You are on page 1of 38

50 Ellen

Journal Meiksins
of Agrarian Change, Wood
Vol. 2 No. 1, January 2002, pp. 50 –87.

SYMPOSIUM†

The Question of Market Dependence

ELLEN MEIKSINS WOOD

Capitalism is a system of social-property relations in which survival and social


reproduction are dependent on the market; a system that is, therefore, driven
by the imperatives of competition and a relentless drive to improve the forces
of production. This article explores the nature of that market dependence and
the specific historical conditions in which it emerged. In debate with Robert
Brenner’s recent article in this journal (vol. 1, no. 2) about the early develop-
ment of capitalism in the Low Countries, it is suggested that, while the Dutch
Republic was a highly developed commercial society, it seems to have lacked
the specific conditions that made market dependence a basic property relation,
as it was in early modern English agrarian capitalism. The differences between
Dutch and English patterns of economic development reflect some fundamental
differences between commercial and capitalist societies.
Keywords: capitalism, market, commerce, Dutch Republic, England

In a recent issue of this journal, Robert Brenner (2001) made a powerful case for
the early development of capitalism in parts of the Low Countries. Building on
his groundbreaking work on England, he argued that, for different reasons and in
different ways, agricultural producers in the maritime Northern Netherlands were
subjected to economic imperatives that impelled their development in a capitalist
direction. The argument has major implications for our understanding of capital-
ism in general, and that is the basis on which I want to respond to it here. If, as
Brenner has argued, the differentia specifica of capitalism is the market dependence
of economic actors, much depends on exactly what market dependence means.

†Robert Brenner will respond to the following articles in a forthcoming issue of the journal.

Ellen Meiksins Wood, Department of Political Science, York University, 4700 Keele Street, Toronto,
Canada, M3J 1PR. e-mail: ewood@yorku.ca
I want to thank George Comninel for his, as usual, extremely helpful comments and suggestions,
and for innumerable fruitful discussions about these and related issues. Thanks also to Terry Byres for
his very useful and thought-provoking observations. As always, I am also grateful to Neal Wood, for
his comments and encouragement. But I owe special thanks to Bob Brenner, with whom I have been
discussing this essay from the start. The final product is the result of an ongoing debate between us,
after he read the original draft, and he intends to respond to it in print. Our objective is to conduct
not the customary academic slanging match, but a constructive conversation between basically like-
minded friends, in the hope of clarifying things for ourselves and anyone else who might be interested.

© Blackwell Publishers Ltd, Henry Bernstein and Terence J. Byres 2002.


The Question of Market Dependence 51

In his discussion of the Low Countries, Brenner was again elaborating the
fundamental principle that was also at the heart of his recent important analysis
of the global economy. Capitalism, he wrote in that controversial text, is a system
characterized by ‘relentless and systematic development of the productive forces’,
because it is ‘a system of social-property relations in which economic units –
unlike those in previous historical epochs – must depend on the market for
everything they need and are unable to secure income by extra-economic coercion
. . .’ (Brenner 1998, 10).
In his historical work, Brenner has shown how the systemic pressures deriv-
ing from market dependence, the imperatives that have driven the development
of capitalism, operated before, and as a precondition for, the proletarianization of
the workforce. Economic units could be market dependent – that is, separated
from non-market access to the means of their self-reproduction – without being
completely propertyless and even without employing propertyless wage labourers.
This early form of market dependence, which subjected producers to the im-
peratives of competition and profit-maximization, set in train the development
of capitalism, and with it mass dispossession and the mature relation between
capital and labour. In his earlier work, Brenner explained the nature of market
dependence in English agrarian capitalism, and he has now offered an account of
a different path to market dependence in the Low Countries.
One implication of Brenner’s argument on the nature of market dependence
as in a sense independent of, and prior to, the class relation between capital and
labour has been his emphasis, especially in his recent account of the contemporary
global economy, on imperatives and contradictions rooted in the ‘horizontal’
relations among capitals, the relations of competition. This emphasis has aroused
much hostility among other Marxists. More particularly, Brenner’s critics have
reacted strongly against a conception of capitalism that, in their view, displaces
the class relation between capital and labour as the defining feature of the system,
giving pride of place to ‘horizontal’ relations.
This seems to me a complete misreading of what Brenner is about, for many
reasons that I cannot elaborate here.1 For our purposes here, it is enough to
emphasize two points: first, that Brenner shows how the market itself can con-
stitute a social-property relation (a point to which I shall return); and second,
that the class relation between capital and labour is what it is – and unique among
class systems – precisely because its constitutive units are market dependent and
because the relation between capital and labour, unlike any other system of class
exploitation, is mediated by the market. Because the market here is not simply
a mechanism of circulation but the medium of basic social-property relations, it
carries with it the imperatives of competition, profit-maximization and increasing
labour productivity.
It is not my intention to retreat from my strong support for Brenner’s basic
argument about market dependence. On the contrary, the questions I intend to
raise here have to do with following that concept to its logical conclusions. If

1
For more on this, see my ‘Horizontal Relations: A Note on Brenner’s Heresy’ (Wood 1999).
52 Ellen Meiksins Wood

anything, these questions may suggest that, in his analysis of economic develop-
ment in the Low Countries, he has perhaps departed from, or at least not ela-
borated enough, his own insights on the nature and consequences of market
dependence as a social-property relation.

BRENNER ON MARKET DEPENDENCE IN THE NETHERLANDS


We may start with a brief summary of Brenner’s argument on the Low Coun-
tries, or specifically on the maritime Northern Netherlands, which apparently
underwent some kind of early capitalist development.
Brenner is clearly working backwards from what appear to be some funda-
mental similarities between this region of the Low Countries and England in the
late seventeenth century. By that time, both were experiencing, he suggests,
a process of economic development in which, among other things, a differentiation
was taking place between producers who successfully competed in the market by
specializing, and less successful farmers who lost their land and were obliged to
seek non-agricultural employment.
It is, argues Brenner, an indication of how deeply ingrained capitalist practices
were in the early modern period that, in the general European crisis of the
seventeenth century, when agricultural prices collapsed, Dutch landlords reacted
in much the same way as their English counterparts – and differently from
landlords elsewhere, notably in France – subsidizing their tenants by lowering rents
and/or accepting arrears and undertaking capital investments, instead of expelling
them in favour of land-hungry peasants. The subsequent differences between the
two cases – the halt in Dutch development while England continued in its pro-
cess of self-sustaining growth, giving rise to industrial capitalism – were not a
consequence of any fundamental differences in the internal dynamics of the two
economies but rather a result of Dutch dependence on an external market, a Euro-
pean market operating on different, non-capitalist principles and subject to the
limits of a fundamentally feudal economy.
Brenner sets out to explain how apparently similar processes of capitalist
development could have been generated in substantially different ways, how the
maritime Northern Netherlands, coming from a different starting point, was,
before hitting the buffers, approaching the same destination as English agrarian
capitalism. He describes a situation in which producers were unable to produce
their own means of survival because of their region’s ecological degradation.
They therefore had to depend on the market for food grain. In other words, they
were dependent on the market for their ‘inputs’, or for the most basic conditions,
indeed for the ‘full costs’, of their own reproduction.
In order to obtain the means of acquiring grain in the market, they were obliged
to produce other commodities for exchange and, to a substantial degree, to
produce them for export. They therefore had ‘to find products that they could
successfully sell on the market’. Switching from grain production to cattle breeding
and dairy farming, they did find a market for their output, especially in large towns
in nearby Brabant and Flanders, as well as supplying summer grains for the
The Question of Market Dependence 53

nascent domestic market for beer. ‘From the very beginning,’ writes Brenner,
‘Dutch commercial farmers were not only reliant upon their domestic market,
but heavily dependent as well upon the European feudal “world market” ’. Farmers
in the region were therefore, he argues, compelled to produce competitively, ‘to
compete or go under’, which meant they were obliged to produce in such a way
as ‘to hold their own in price-cost maximization’.
At first, levels of productivity were too low to permit the producers to rely
completely on specialization, and they supplemented their livelihoods with some,
also commercially oriented, diversification. They enjoyed competitive advantages
in trade largely because of their relatively low labour costs and because of the
relatively low price of grain in the maritime Northern Netherlands as compared to
elsewhere in Europe, as merchants from the Netherlands expanded the Baltic grain
trade in response to increasing demand. But eventually, the countryside, under the
pressures of competitive production, and in the context of expanding markets and
growing demand, experienced a process of ‘real economic development’, driven
by specialization, investment and an increasingly productive agriculture.
I will, in what follows, have occasion to question part of Brenner’s account
of what happened in the Netherlands, especially during the seventeenth-century
crisis. I have some doubts, in particular, about whether the Dutch pattern of
development really does display a capitalist logic. But my main purpose is to
explore the foundations of the argument – what it tells us about the nature of
market dependence and about capitalism. I wonder not only whether the kind
of ‘market-dependence’ he attributes to the Dutch could set off a process of
capitalist development, but also, and more particularly, whether the rise and
decline of the Dutch economy, even as Brenner describes it himself, can be
adequately accounted for by the explanation he offers, or whether there might
be an alternative account perhaps more consistent with the pattern of Dutch
development, which does not require us to assume a capitalist logic of process.
My questions have to do, first, with the conditions in which producers can be
regarded as market dependent, in such a way as to make their economic strategies
essentially different from any other agricultural producers, including peasants who
enter the market to obtain basic necessities; second, with the nature of markets
themselves – whether and when they are competitive and capable of imposing
the requirements of competition on the methods and costs of production; and
finally, with the conditions in which appropriating classes, not only direct pro-
ducers, are market dependent. The issue here is whether the presence or absence
of such conditions made a critical difference between the patterns of development
in England and the Dutch Republic, and whether the kind of market dependence
Brenner attributes to the Dutch set in motion a pattern of development we can
reasonably call capitalist.

MARKET-DEPENDENT PRODUCERS
In his analysis of the Low Countries, Brenner’s first premise is that market
dependence, of a kind that sets in train the process of capitalist development, can
54 Ellen Meiksins Wood

be created simply by the producers’ need to obtain basic ‘inputs’ from the market
(not necessarily, it seems, the factors of production, but the basic condition of
survival, namely food), and to produce other commodities for the market in
order to obtain those basic inputs. The corollary is that the production of these
commodities must be adapted to meet the requirements of competition and its
price-cost pressures. So let us explore whether, or in what specific conditions,
the need to exchange the outputs of production for basic inputs, and notably
food, will generate the kinds of imperatives that Brenner is talking about.
There is no mystery, especially for readers of a journal such as this, about the
fact that throughout history there have existed many kinds of markets and that
agricultural producers have entered them in diverse ways, with various different
purposes and consequences. There is presumably no need here to spell out, for
instance, the differences between, on the one hand, a ‘market system’, in which
virtually all commodities are produced for the market and where all factors of
production, including land and labour, are treated as commodities and, on the
other hand, peasant markets in which producers who own, or securely possess,
the means of production – in particular, land – sell their surpluses as an adjunct
or supplement to their own production for subsistence.
But even this relatively clear distinction raises questions about the point at
which reliance on the market becomes vital to subsistence or, in Brenner’s terms,
the point at which, short of complete separation from the means of production,
a loss of non-market access to the means of subsistence becomes decisive in
establishing market dependence, setting in train a process of economic develop-
ment. This question is particularly difficult to answer in the case of the Northern
Netherlands, even more than in the English case.
In the latter, the critical factor, convincingly explained by Brenner in his earlier
work, was the loss of non-market access to the land itself. In what has long seemed
to me his most important historical insight, he demonstrated how this kind
of market dependence could exist well short of complete dispossession. Non-
market access to the means of production was lost well before the complete
commodification of labour, in the form of tenancies that operated on ‘economic’
principles. The pivotal point of his argument was the relation between tenant
producers who held their land (de jure or de facto) on ‘economic’ leases and paid
‘economic’ rents, and landlords who, lacking extra-economic powers of surplus
extraction, the powers of direct coercion to squeeze more surplus from producers,
instead depended for their wealth on the productivity, competitiveness and profit-
ability of their tenants. In other words, both producers and appropriators depended
on the market for access to the conditions of their self-reproduction, and the
relation between them was mediated by the market. Brenner’s argument may
not have been uncontroversial, but in his explanatory framework the dividing
line between market dependence and its absence was relatively clear, determined
by the logic of the property relations he described rather than by some elusive
quantitative measure.
By contrast, in the Netherlands the decisive factor is not some kind of
market-mediated property relations or market access to the land itself. Instead,
The Question of Market Dependence 55

Brenner invokes the ecologically determined inadequacy of the land which made
its possessors – outright owners no less than tenants – unable to supply their own
subsistence needs, specifically their need for food grain, without entering the mar-
ket. Producers here were market dependent simply in the sense that they were
obliged to sell commodities they produced in order to obtain basic necessities
they were unable to produce.
In such a case, it seems much harder to avoid confronting the quantitative
question: to what extent must people rely on the market to purchase the means
of survival before they become market dependent? At what point does the loss
of non-market access to subsistence goods become market dependence? Does
it require dependence on the market for the full costs of self-reproduction, or
would something short of the full costs still constitute market dependence in the
relevant sense? Why, for instance, is the case of Dutch farmers – who presum-
ably consume some of their own dairy products and meat, vegetables from their
own kitchen gardens and eggs from their own chickens – differ fundamentally
from peasants elsewhere who produce much or most of their own food but still
require exchange to obtain certain basic necessities? At what point does a quant-
itative difference become a qualitative one? For that matter, precisely how does
the economic logic of the Dutch farmer differ from that of craft producers, even
more dependent on the market for their basic food needs, in a commercial centre
like Renaissance Florence?
But let us accept that there is a critical difference between, on the one hand,
producers who generally produce their own food but enter the market to supple-
ment their ‘subsistence/safety first strategies’, even if these ventures into the
market are for the purpose of acquiring necessary goods, and, on the other hand,
producers who must produce for the market even to gain access to their most basic
food requirements, particularly grain. The question still remains whether, or in
what conditions, the need to produce and sell commodities (of whatever kind) in
order, in turn, to buy food on the market creates a pressure to produce competit-
ively and maximize profit in the capitalist manner. Or, to put it another way, the
essential question is this: in what specific conditions do competitive production
and profit-maximization themselves become survival strategies, the basic condition
of subsistence itself ?
Strategies for survival are identical with strategies for maximizing profit, at least
for producers, only in capitalism. The conditions of capitalist competition require
‘maximizing’ strategies because capitalists have no guarantee of ‘realization’ in
advance. They cannot know whether their commodities will sell, or even what
conditions and production costs would ensure sale at all, let alone profit. Lacking
the capacity to control prices in a competitive market, they must adopt strategies
that will optimize the price/cost ratio, and their only available strategy is to reduce
costs by enhancing labour productivity, to achieve the maximization of surplus value.
But such competitive conditions cannot simply be assumed even in the pres-
ence of well-developed markets and trading networks, so we need to know more
about market dependence and how it engenders imperatives of competition.
Brenner seems to suggest that the decisive factor is the degree of specialization,
56 Ellen Meiksins Wood

which, if not a cause is at least an index for him of market dependence and
capitalist development. Needless to say, the more specialized producers become,
the more they must look elsewhere, particularly to the market, to obtain the
necessary goods they do not themselves produce. But there have been many
cases of specialization that has not been directed at ‘efficient’ – i.e. ‘competitive’
– production. So specialization for purposes of ‘efficiency’ in the interests of
profit in a competitive market requires further explanation.
It is important to recognize that specialization, which for Brenner is a critical
index of capitalist development, may have no connection whatever with ‘effi-
ciency’. Specialization has existed in non-capitalist economies not driven by the
imperatives of competition. In such cases, the object, far from generating max-
imum profit, or indeed profit at all, has been to supply the community’s needs
by means of division of labour and exchange, and methods of production as well
as opportunities for profit have been limited by all kinds of mutual expectations,
obligations and customs.
Take the example of so-called ‘sectional’ markets in which specialization is the
dominant principle of economic organization.2 Here, traditional, even heredit-
ary, communities of geographically separated monopolistic specialized producers
regularly meet each other in the marketplace to supply their various needs. Yet,
despite variation not only in the quality but in the price of goods on offer from
various producers of the same commodity, unless these markets are integrated
into an already capitalist economy, there is no intrinsic reason why these markets
should be competitive in the capitalist sense; and their effects on the methods and
costs of production – which may still be deeply rooted in the traditions of the
peasant community and the communal solidarities that are their basic conditions
of survival – may be minimal or even non-existent.
The opportunities of export trade in precapitalist societies could also encour-
age specialization, without transforming social-property relations or methods of
production. This was the case, for instance, in France. Even in the Middle Ages,
at a time when French agriculture in general was striving for self-sufficiency in
grain production, some rural communities were, where possible, already com-
pletely given over to viticulture, because wine was a distinctively valuable and
uniquely exportable commodity. Later, with the resumption and growth of trade,
that specialization increased, yet this labour-intensive agricultural craft, far from
signalling a movement toward capitalist property relations, has even been credited
with preserving the traditional French peasantry.3
We cannot even assume the producers’ desire for profit-maximization in
exchange on the grounds that it would give them the best return for their labour
and other inputs. We cannot presume the kind of calculation of returns to fac-
tors specific to capitalism, which may be quite alien to non-capitalist peasant

2
On sectional markets, see Wolf (1966, 40 –1).
3
See, for example, Fernand Braudel (1986, 316), where he even suggests that ‘it was chiefly through
the spread of the vine’ that France acquired its distinctive character as a nation of small landowners
and independent peasants.
The Question of Market Dependence 57

economies, where all kinds of other considerations enter into the calculation of
the ‘value’ of labour and land. But even when peasants do respond to the market
with some kind of ‘economic rationality’, it may be in ways very different from
capitalist responses to market imperatives.
For instance, farmers may respond to rising prices for their particular
commodities – typically in cases of growing demand – by increasing their output
of those commodities as much as possible, perhaps by bringing more land under
cultivation or even by employing more (cheap) labour, in order to take advantage
of the opportunities for increased profits. The typical response to falling prices
would, in such cases, be to reduce or withdraw from production. In that sense,
these producers are indeed price-sensitive. But this kind of motivation is very
different from the cost-sensitivity of a capitalist producer who strives for increas-
ing labour productivity at lower cost, especially by transforming the methods of
production, in a competitive market with many producers.
The latter kind of market response presupposes conditions that have not
prevailed in most societies, throughout most of human history. There must,
of course, be the material possibility of systematic innovation in the methods
of production, which is seldom present in peasant communities with limited
resources. But we cannot simply assume that peasants would so respond if only
they could systematically improve the forces of production and that nothing but
their poverty prevents them from doing so. There are also social constraints, the
requirements and regulations of the peasant community, which may themselves
be essential to survival.
Yet even these communal constraints, with or without the material limits
of peasant property, are not enough to account for the absence of systematic
development of productive forces of the kind we associate with capitalism. In
fact, it is, on the whole, a mistake to think in terms of blockages. The self-
sustaining development unique to capitalism requires not just the removal of
obstacles to development but a positive compulsion to transform the forces of
production, and this comes only in competitive conditions, where economic
actors are both free to move in response to those conditions and obliged to
do so. No one has taught us more than Brenner about the specificity of such
conditions.
Nor has anyone demonstrated more effectively that even the need to produce
surpluses for exploiting classes or states has not, throughout most of history, by
itself transformed the methods of production in that way, even production for
exchange. Where exploiters – whether rent-taking landlords or tax-hungry states
– have had at their disposal the extra-economic means of surplus extraction,
the direct military, political and judicial powers of coercion to squeeze more
surpluses from peasants, there has been no systematic compulsion to enhance
labour productivity. Indeed, the effect of exploitation has typically been to
impede such transformations of productive forces. Coercive ‘extra-economic’
modes of surplus extraction have both lacked the incentive to promote the
development of productive forces and positively hindered it by draining the
resources of direct producers. What capitalist development requires is a mode
58 Ellen Meiksins Wood

of appropriation that must extract maximum surplus from direct producers but
can do so only by encouraging or compelling producers to increase their labour
productivity and by enhancing rather than impeding the development of product-
ive forces. That kind of appropriation is a rare and contradictory formation, with
very specific and stringent conditions of existence.
We shall return to the question of appropriation. But for now, the question
remains why, and in what highly unusual conditions, people would abandon their
old survival strategies, which were not based on profit-maximization by means
of ‘efficient’ production, and begin pursuing a strategy that did take this form.
We need to know more to explain how survival strategies came to be united with
profit-maximizing strategies, and even how profit-maximization and ‘efficiency’
were joined, or, for that matter, specialization and efficiency.
When farmers in the maritime Northern Netherlands switched to dairy pro-
duction, for instance, in response to a huge and growing demand especially
in the cities of neighbouring Brabant and Flanders, they may have had more
freedom to alter production in response to market conditions than has been
typical of peasants throughout history constrained by communal requirements.
But they seem, at first glance, to have been responding according to a logic not
fundamentally different from the strategies of peasants in many other times and
places, reacting to a seller’s market in conditions of rising demand (and probably
rising prices). There seems to be nothing in their behaviour to suggest that they
were doing anything but increasing output to meet increasing demand. Of course,
switching from one commodity to another to meet an unfilled need, or even
specializing in order to take advantage of growing demand for a particular com-
modity, is different from merely increasing already existing production to meet
a growing need. But these strategies surely have more in common with each
other than either has in common with adjustment of production to meet the
constraints of a competitive market where supply always threatens to exceed
demand, with a downward pressure on prices.
It may be possible to argue that these farmers – dependent as they were on
buying in their basic food requirements – would have had no, or little, option to
limit production in a tight market, and even less option to withdraw altogether.
They would therefore have had no choice but to reduce their costs of produc-
tion in order to stay in contention. But there is nothing in Brenner’s account
to suggest that they were operating in a market of that kind. On the contrary,
every indication is that they enjoyed the dual advantage of a growing market and
a dominant commercial apparatus.
The ‘competition’ that certainly took place in European trading networks
was principally among merchants and commercial centres, the mercantile
interests of the Netherlands, say, against the Hanse, and later, even within the
Dutch Republic, between Amsterdam and rival commercial cities. Here, it was,
in general, less a question of price competition among producers of particular
commodities than a contest among merchants or whole commercial cities for
control of markets. Even when this kind of competition (rivalry might be a
better and less question-begging word) was intended to corner a larger share of
The Question of Market Dependence 59

the market for domestic producers, it was an essentially ‘extra-economic’ contest.


It had less to do with the methods and costs of production than with either
politically enforced restrictions and privileges or with superiority in the instru-
ments, methods and range of commercial activity, to say nothing of superiority
in shipping and navigation, and military might.
The question, then, is whether the markets so skilfully negotiated by the
Dutch were already operating according to different principles. The Dutch
situation described by Brenner’s principal source, de Vries and van der Woude
(1997), seems to be one in which the growth of commercial agriculture involved
increasing production for growing demand, but not necessarily the kinds of
competitive pressures that would systematically drive uncompetitive producers
off the land. In a sense – and this is a point to which we shall return – the Dutch
Golden Age was a period of growing market opportunities for more total output
with more or less guaranteed sale, rather than a period of market imperatives
requiring the systematic improvement of labour productivity to meet the demands
of competition.
Not even the technical advances pioneered by Dutch farmers, nor the massive
reclamation projects which extended cultivable land, by themselves argue for the
need to ‘compete or go under’, as distinct from expanding production to meet
expanding demand. This is not to deny that the Dutch did pioneer certain advances
in productivity, not least in agriculture. But it is not at all clear (as I shall argue
in what follows) that the success of the Dutch economy, or the survival of
individual producers, depended on these advances in productivity more than
on ‘extra-economic’ advantages in commercial rivalries. Dutch investment in
production could signal not so much the emergence of a capitalist dynamic as a
precapitalist logic taken to its absolute limits.
To be sure, Brenner’s argument, here and elsewhere, is precisely that capitalism
emerged as an unintended consequence of precapitalist strategies, when, for one
reason or another, non-capitalist economic actors had exhausted their capacity for
self-reproduction as they were. But it seems to me that more needs to be said in
the Dutch case about how one thing led to another. If, by the seventeenth century,
farmers in the Northern Netherlands had reached the limits of a precapitalist
economic logic and brought about a capitalist transformation, it still remains
unclear how and why this came about, or, indeed, whether it happened at all.

THE CYCLES OF MARKET DEPENDENCE


The final and, for Brenner, apparently decisive argument in favour of capitalist
development in the Northern Netherlands is its end result: he maintains that
Dutch landlords in the late seventeenth century, when agricultural prices in Europe
collapsed, behaved like English landlords more than French. I shall return to
the seventeenth-century crisis and how Dutch appropriating classes in general
responded to it. Their response, it seems to me, was very different from the
English, in ways that go directly to the distinction between the dynamics of
capitalist development and a rather different, non-capitalist economic logic. For
60 Ellen Meiksins Wood

the moment, it is enough to raise a few questions about landlords and tenants
in the Dutch Republic.
Let us leave aside the question of numbers and whether landlord/tenant rela-
tions of any kind ever played a role in the Republic comparable to their centrality
in England. We can infer from Brenner’s argument itself that, while the landlord/
tenant relation did play a part in Dutch economic development, it never dominated
the agricultural scene as it did in England. The distinctive systemic logic of the
Dutch economy, as against the specific logic of the English case, seems in Brenner’s
account to be determined above all by the market dependence of owner/occupiers.
What can we nonetheless deduce from the behaviour, during and after the
seventeenth-century crisis, of landlords in the Dutch Republic?
It must be said that the picture painted by de Vries and van der Woude is
rather different from what Brenner suggests. First, it is not at all clear from
their account that competitive pressures, in the sense intended by Brenner, drove
people off the land in the period leading up to and during the Golden Age. In
the early stages, ecological conditions made certain kinds of agriculture more
difficult, if not impossible, while alternatives became available in the towns, as
the Dutch exploited new commercial opportunities and the Republic became
a major link in the larger European division of labour. This account of Dutch
development would also, incidentally, explain a differentiation among Dutch
farmers, between successful proprietors who could increase their holdings and
those who gave up their land, without signalling the kind of competitive economy
Brenner has in mind.
The main point emphasized by de Vries and van der Woude is that ‘Dutch
society from the sixteenth century was dominated by its cities’, and this domin-
ance shaped the rural economy (1997, 507). Urbanization, fuelled by the Republic’s
role in international trade, transformed the rural economy in at least two major
ways. The urban population swelled to service the Republic’s growing domin-
ance in shipping, trade, and eventually finance. In turn, the growing urban sector
provided new markets for agricultural goods. At the same time, it provided new
sources of capital to exploit new opportunities for profit, and urban investors in
agriculture became a major feature of the rural scene.
This was, in fact, a, if not the, critical factor in transforming the Dutch rural
economy, especially by means of speculative urban investment in land reclama-
tion. Agricultural productivity seems to have been improved not in response
to competition so much as in response to growing demand, in an economy with
a unique imbalance between urban consumers and rural producers, and the
growing opportunities for commercial profit this entailed. More particularly, the
productive capacities of relatively small farmers were disproportionately enhanced
by urban investment responding to growing commercial opportunities.
But perhaps most revealing is de Vries and van der Woude’s account of what
happened at the very moment Brenner finds most telling, the seventeenth-
century crisis. We should, of course, keep in mind that the Republic’s prosperity
always depended disproportionately on the role of the Dutch in international
trade as commercial mediators, as distinct from producers. Their great wealth
The Question of Market Dependence 61

would have been impossible without their preeminence in long-distance trade,


circulating throughout Europe commodities produced far afield. But against that
background, we can simply look at what happened to domestic production in
the period of decline.
While there had been considerable capital investment in agriculture during
the Golden Age of the Republic, the period of crisis and thereafter was, according
to de Vries and van der Woude, a period of disinvestment. At this stage, there
was indeed some concentration of land in the hands of the ‘relatively strong’, but
Dutch investors typically abandoned land altogether. At the same time, the
behaviour of landlords who remained seems hardly different from what non-
capitalist landlords sometimes did even in France. Some did indeed lower
rents and/or accept arrears, but so did many French landlords, when conditions
obliged them to retrench and share the costs of economic decline with their
tenants – especially where, as in Burgundy or the Paris Basin, there were larger
tenancies, which landlords were compelled to preserve by making concessions
on rents.
The main point, however, is that, while investment in cost-reducing tech-
nologies was ‘not altogether lacking’ in Dutch agriculture during the crisis and
thereafter, this was far from being the preferred strategy (de Vries and van der
Woude 1997, 676). Dutch farmers responded in various ways, and ‘the Republic’s
producers manoeuvred as best they could in a structure of high costs and limited
markets’, but while ‘[l]ethargy and routine did not characterize their conduct . . .
neither did decisive cost-reducing investments’ (de Vries and van der Woude
1997, 677). Perhaps even more significantly, much of the investment of com-
mercial wealth that had driven the remarkable development of domestic produc-
tion in the earlier period dried up. Instead, as we shall see, Dutch elites reverted
to more classically non-capitalist modes of appropriation by extra-economic
means, notably office-holding, as well as rentier wealth, and commercial ventures
unrelated to domestic production, agricultural or industrial. This was in sharp
contrast to England, where the period of declining agricultural prices spurred an
increase in investment, not least by landlords, to enhance labour productivity
and cost-effectiveness.4
We shall return to the differences in the patterns of development between
England and the Dutch Republic, but we already have reasons to expect some

4
See, for instance, Coleman (1977, 124). It should, however, be emphasized that the attitude
of these English landowners was a symptom rather than a cause of England’s capitalist development.
As Brenner stresses in ‘The Low Countries’, while landlords depended on their tenants’ competitive
success and therefore helped their tenants improve production, especially to get through bad years,
‘landlord’s decisive contribution to the rise of capitalism in the English countryside was certainly not
. . . to be found in their investment and innovation in agriculture, which they very often eschewed
. . . It was found, rather, in their seeing to the separation of the direct producers from the means
of subsistence in English agriculture and thus their subordination as tenants to the competitive
constraint . . .’ (199, n. 12.). Again, the difference in the attitude of Dutch investors is symptomatic
of different social-property relations. To put it crudely, while English landlords helping their tenants
improve production in bad times is a symptom of subjection to market imperatives, the imperatives
of competition, the Dutch elite’s investment in agricultural production in good times and withdrawal
in bad is a symptom of responsiveness to market opportunities.
62 Ellen Meiksins Wood

fundamental divergences. The main point is this: in the English case, we can
understand why, even in a period of rising demand and growing economic
opportunities, unproductive tenants were dispossessed by competitive pressures.
It is not so difficult to see how, in the early phases of development, England’s
property relations, with its system of competitive rents, compelled producers not
simply to stay in the market but to ‘maximize’ and, even in conditions of rising
demand and prices, to ‘compete or go under’. We can also understand why in a
time of falling prices landlords encouraged their tenants to improve productivity
instead of driving them off the land. It is not so difficult to understand why, in
a declining market, the same social-property relations that made both producers
and appropriators dependent on competitive production required the enhance-
ment of productive forces. It is rather more difficult to see why or how the
Dutch were subject to the same compulsions – and their pattern of development
suggests that they were not.

A DIFFERENT KIND OF MARKET DEPENDENCE?


The question, then, is whether, in the early modern period and before the
seventeenth-century crisis, the basic need of Dutch producers to sell in order to
buy was compelling enough and distinctive enough to become a driving force
for a historically rare kind of ‘real’, or transformative, economic development,
which was thwarted only by conditions external to the Dutch economy. Perhaps
their reliance on the market for their most basic ‘inputs’ is enough to distinguish
them from peasants whose ventures into the market have not generated such
developmental processes. There can be little doubt that these farmers were obliged
to sell in order to buy, and that they were obliged to buy to obtain certain basic
‘inputs’. What is not quite so clear is whether that really did mean that they were
forced to maximize profits or even that they were obliged to ‘compete or go under’.
Where producers depend on the market not in the sense that their possession
of land is directly market dependent but rather in the sense that they must sell
what they produce in order to buy what they cannot, they have (within the limits
of their productive capacities) a certain room for manoeuvre. They can adjust
production not only to changing commercial demand but to their own con-
sumption (which can itself be adjusted) in ways and degrees ruled out by capitalist
competition, where profit-maximization is a condition of survival – and also
ruled out by the relation between English landlords and their tenants. Their room
for manoeuvre is that much greater if they are not subject to surplus extraction
by landlords or states.
It is a truism that peasant proprietors will continue cultivating land in condi-
tions that would make no sense for capitalist producers. They will push themselves
and their families to the utmost limit if necessary to maintain subsistence, and
reduce their consumption to a bare minimum. It is also true that, even in the
context of a capitalist economy, small independent farmers will typically proceed
in this way, even when their own subsistence depends on selling their commod-
ities at market-regulated prices. Marx pointed out a long time ago that ‘For the
The Question of Market Dependence 63

peasant parcel holder to cultivate land, or to buy land for cultivation, it is therefore
not necessary, as under the normal capitalist mode of production, that the market-
price of the agricultural products rise high enough to afford him the average
profit, and still less a fixed excess above this average profit in the form of rent. It
is not necessary, therefore, that the market-price rise, either up to the value or
the production of his product’ (Marx 1962, 786). In this sense, the farmer even in
capitalism may, up to a point, stand outside the ‘normal’ capitalist economy and
its price/cost logic, to the extent that only his bare subsistence, and not the
compulsions of profit or rent, represent his absolute limit.
To be sure, in an advanced capitalist economy, in which all economic
relations are thoroughly commodified and every commodity is subject to the
conditions of a competitive market, even the independent farmer’s room for
manoeuvre is more limited than it was in Marx’s nineteenth century, let alone in
the seventeenth. But the early modern Dutch owner/occupier was operating in a
non-capitalist European economy and, in any case, he seems to have had the best
of both worlds.
Like Marx’s ‘self-managing proprietor’, he was not obliged to adapt produc-
tion to any average rate of profit or to attain some kind of cost/price optimum.
At the same time, as de Vries and van der Woude point out, Dutch agricultural pro-
ducers, as they ‘came under the influence of the low cost production centers’ that
were their source of grain, had a more or less unique ‘margin of advantage’. Their
privileged access to cheap grain – deriving from their extra-economic dominance
in shipping and trade – was set against the prices of the ‘relative luxuries’ they
themselves produced (de Vries and van der Woude 1997, 199). Dutch farmers
originally shifted from grain to dairy production under the influence of cheap im-
ported grain from the Baltic, because they were obtaining increasingly more grain
for every pound of butter (as well as beef and cowhide) that they sold. Importing
cheap grain lowered the costs of producing other, higher priced commodities at
home. In other words, if Dutch grain production was replaced by lower cost
‘competitors’, that ‘competition’ had the effect not of creating price/cost pres-
sures or lowering profit margins in Dutch agriculture but, on the contrary,
encouraging the production of higher priced and more profitable commodities.
So the Dutch dairy farmer not only had the freedom of the independent
producer but also, unlike most small producers such as those Marx had in mind
(who work ‘in the least favourable conditions’, like grain producers in the Baltic),
a freedom from indigence, enjoying the input-cost benefits of unusually cheap
imported grain bought in a low cost market, and the output-price benefits of
his own semi-luxury commodities sold in a large and prosperous market with
a relatively high price ceiling. In those conditions (and with generally limited
productive capacities in the face of growing demand), it is hard to see what
systematic price/cost compulsions were operating on the Dutch dairy farmer. If
Dutch producers ‘came under the influence’ of cheap production and low prices
in relation to their input costs rather than their output prices, they were enjoying
the benefits of something like the opposite of the price/cost pressures that drive
competitive production in a capitalist economy.
64 Ellen Meiksins Wood

But more particularly, we must surely distinguish between the need to sell
even in order to survive and the need to attain an average rate of profit in order
to survive, irrespective of one’s own consumption needs. The English tenant
may not have been compelled to attain an average rate of profit in the manner of
a modern capitalist producer, but his particular relation to the landlord already
made production for profit beyond his own subsistence needs a presupposition of
production for his own subsistence. In that sense, he was subject to price/cost
pressures in a wholly new way.
When a farmer in the Northern Netherlands switched from grain to dairy
production, and supplemented his income by producing summer grains for beer,
he was doing so to meet his own consumption needs and those of his household,
even if he did so by means of exchange, consumption needs that were, within
reason, under their own control. When English land-use was switched from arable
to sheep pasture, driving many producers off the land, and when later, in conditions
where rents for arable were rising again, landlords derived their rents from pro-
ductive agriculture, the driving force was something very different from the con-
sumption needs of the producer. The requirements of the surplus-appropriating
landlord were imposed on production from the start, and the requirements of
that landlord were different from the pressures exerted by landlords or states that
could rely on extra-economic coercion.
We begin to see in the English case something more like a capitalist dynamic,
in which the immediate object of production is not consumption, or even ex-
change, but profit; and perhaps for the first time in history, production was directly
subjected to the requirements of profit-maximization, which became a condition
of self-reproduction. It is certainly true that Dutch farmers, even independent
owner-occupiers, were subject to the requirements of appropriators, notably the
state, in the form of taxation. But, again, on its own, this kind of surplus
extraction, in the absence of capitalist property relations, does not compel com-
petitive production. Perhaps the point can be made simply by considering the
conditions in which agricultural producers were in danger of losing their access
to land. To be sure, even owner-occupiers in non-capitalist societies may not
only suffer poverty but, in extreme cases, may even be forced to give up their land,
if the exigencies of inadequate land, together with burdens of rent or taxation,
make survival impossible. But it takes something other than the pressures of
inadequacy to make possession dependent on competitive production. The pres-
sures of a capitalist economy are such that even a prosperous farmer, like the
English yeoman-tenant, is subject to them, making his continuing possession of
good land dependent on his cost-effective production.
At any rate, if Dutch commercial farmers in the earlier phases of development
were simply responding to a new market or an absolute rise in demand, it is not
even clear whether or to what extent they were confronted by rival producers
aiming for the same consumers, let alone competitors in a specifically capitalist
sense – that is, producers always driven to lower their costs of production, and
not only in times of economic decline, in order to maintain their positions in
an integrated market where there is always a threat of overcapacity. At the very
The Question of Market Dependence 65

least, we need to know a great deal more to determine whether, or how, they
were subjected to pressures that obliged them to produce competitively – or
whether, even if there existed the productive potential for more supply than
demand, they were simply availing themselves of the ‘extra-economic’ advantages
enjoyed by their compatriot merchants, such as the command of trade routes and
trading networks or outright monopolies, superior shipping, and so on.
One major test of a transformative market dependence is the need to compete
not in a period of declining prices and demand but in times of readily available
and even growing demand. Brenner himself, in his analysis of contemporary cap-
italism, has demonstrated with devastating effect that this apparent anomaly is a
constitutive contradiction of the capitalist system, causing crises of overcapacity
and ultimately systematic economic downturns. His historical work on English
agrarian capitalism has traced this contradictory imperative of competition to its
earliest source. But it is not so clear why, or even whether, such a contradiction
was at work in the Netherlands.
It is, however, clear that the English and the Dutch behaved differently in
the downward cycle, in ways that may shed light on the economic logic of the
Republic’s previous Golden Age. I have already alluded to the shift by Dutch
elites, during and after the crisis, from investment in production to investment in
‘extra-economic’ means of appropriation, and I shall say more about this later.
But we may already have to ask whether self-sustaining development in the
Republic was really blocked only by conditions external to the Dutch economy,
or whether there were limits inherent in its own essential nature.
De Vries and van der Woude have argued that the decline of the Dutch
economy after its Golden Age was nothing more than the kind of secular decline
that affects all ‘modern’ economies. Brenner, by contrast, has insisted that
the crisis was not a ‘modern’ one but fundamentally feudal, and that the Dutch
economy, for all its apparently capitalist development, was implicated in that
feudal crisis because it was irreducibly integrated into that feudal economy. Perhaps
it would be useful to take the argument just one step further and show how its
involvement in a feudal economy was not external to but constitutive of its own
internal logic from the start.
The Dutch Republic flourished in the Golden Age (as de Vries and van der
Woude have argued) because domestic production was linked to commercial
expansion, with a transformation of production in tandem with expanding trade.
‘When these interactions weakened,’ they continue, ‘the whole of the Dutch
economy became something less than the sum of its parts’ (de Vries and van
der Woude 1997, 502). We need to consider, then, whether this weakening was
simply the result of a cyclical downturn, or a strategic error, or whether the
limits of this kind of linkage between production and commerce, its ultimate
weakness and eventual rupture, were inherent in it from the outset – in contrast
to the kind of organic link that joined production and commerce in the English
case.
It is, as Brenner points out, a striking fact that the Dutch were able to survive
a long-term decline and to stagnate for a long time at an unusually high level. He
66 Ellen Meiksins Wood

suggests that this was possible because of the economy’s capitalist dynamic,
which later enabled the economy to regenerate itself on a new basis. But there is,
first, no reason to attribute the later success of the Dutch to some long-standing
prior capitalist development. After all, the French and the Germans were able to
develop their industrial capitalisms without – on Brenner’s own reading – such a
prior advantage, and having suffered no less than the Dutch from the European
crisis. Once British capitalism, especially in its industrial form, became a serious
challenge to Britain’s European rivals, a geopolitical and military threat no less
than a commercial one, capitalist imperatives imposed themselves on the other
economies even without any prior domestic capitalism.
It may, however, be more difficult to explain how the Dutch economy could
tread water for so long, without either advancing or sinking further. It is perhaps
even harder to explain if we assume that it was operating according to a capitalist
logic. The imperatives of the capitalist market are generally not so permissive.
By contrast, it is not so difficult to imagine that the Dutch could stagnate at a
relatively high level precisely because they were able to fall back on their old
commercial strengths without depending on competitive production. It is
tempting to argue (though I shall resist taking this too far) that the precapitalist
commercial strengths of the Dutch made them less, rather than more, vulnerable
to the kinds of pressures that cause typically capitalist patterns of stagnation and
downturn.
My intention here is not so much to question the general explanation of the
Dutch decline as caused by its insertion in and dependence on the larger Euro-
pean economy. This might have thwarted Dutch development even if the
Republic’s economy had indeed been driven by capitalist imperatives in the
century or more before the crisis. But even if there was little the Dutch could
have done to avoid being drawn into the European crisis, it is surely worth
considering whether the ways in which they responded to the crisis gives us
some indication of the economic forces that were driving it before the fall.
At the very least we have to consider the difference between, on the one hand,
the kind of market dependence that derives simply from a need to obtain subsist-
ence goods by means of exchange, and, on the other hand, the kind that derives
from market-mediated property relations in the English manner. It cannot be
emphasized enough that market dependence in English agrarian capitalism did
not derive simply from a need to exchange, not even to exchange in order to
obtain the basic means of subsistence.
I have long been insisting on the importance of distinguishing between the
market as an opportunity and the market as an imperative. There is a sense in which
the Dutch case represents an opportunity-driven commercial economy taken to
its utmost limits. But I am now suggesting that we may also have to distinguish
among different kinds of market compulsions. Both the English and the Dutch
certainly had the means, including the productive capacities, to avail themselves
of market opportunities. There is also a sense in which both were responding to
the compulsions of the market, at least a need to enter the market to guarantee
the conditions of their own reproduction. But it is equally significant that the
The Question of Market Dependence 67

compulsions were different in their source, in their nature and, apparently, in


their consequences.

COMPETITIVE MARKETS
We cannot fully understand the difference between these divergent forms of
market dependence without exploring more closely the market dependence of
appropriating classes no less than that of the direct producers. First, however, let
us consider the relevant markets themselves.
Let us look first, in very general outline, at the logic of precapitalist trade.
The simple logic of trade is ‘the exchange of reciprocal requirements’. This can
take place within a single community or among adjacent communities, and this
simple logic can still obtain where the direct exchange of products is replaced by
circulation of commodities mediated by money. It does not by itself generate the
need to maximize profit and, even less, to produce competitively.
Beyond such simple acts of exchange, there are more complex transactions
between separate markets, involving commercial profit-taking (buying cheap in
one market and selling dear in another) in the process of conveyance from one
market to another or arbitrage between them. This kind of trade may have a
logic different from the simple exchange of reciprocal requirements, at least to
the extent that requirements of commercial profit intervene. But here too there
is no inherent compulsion to transform production.
Even in pre-capitalist societies, there are, of course, always people for whom
profit-making (profit-taking might be a better term) is indeed a survival strategy,
people who make a living by trade. But the logic of non-capitalist production,
even specialized production, does not change simply because profit-seeking
middlemen, even highly developed merchant classes, intervene. Their strategies
need have nothing to do with transforming production in the sense required by
capitalist competition. Profit by means of carrying trade or arbitrage between
markets has strategies of its own. These do not depend on transforming produc-
tion, nor do they promote the development of the kind of integrated market that
imposes competitive imperatives. On the contrary, they thrive on fragmented
markets and movement between them, rather than competition within a single
market, and the links between production and exchange may be very tenuous.
The trading networks of medieval and early modern Europe, for instance,
depended on a degree of local or regional specialization that allowed merchants
to profit by carrying goods from one locale where they were produced to others
where they were not. But here as elsewhere in the non-capitalist world, though
profit-seeking strategies may indeed have been survival strategies, profit-seeking
was separate from, if not actually opposed to, ‘efficient’ production.
What, then, constitutes a competitive market? I want to emphasize again that
the ultimate issue here is the conditions in which the market constitutes a system
of social-property relations. But let me leave aside for now my suggestion that
there is a fundamental difference between the situation Brenner describes, in
which producers must exchange in order to obtain basic goods, and a system of
68 Ellen Meiksins Wood

social-property relations that makes profit, and not just exchange, the immediate
object of production. Are there any irreducible conditions without which there
can be no competitive market?
Certain simple conditions must surely prevail. The simplest requirement is
that buyers must have ready access to alternative suppliers. This means not only
that productive capacities must be sufficient to meet and, at least potentially, to
exceed demand but also that supply and demand are reasonably accessible to
one another, even if by means of middlemen. But that is only a necessary and far
from sufficient condition. The relation among various producers must be such
that they can affect each other’s costs of production. Price competition presupposes
various suppliers responding to the same or similar conditions, some common
standard of measure – not only some common standard of monetary exchange
but, more particularly, some compelling social average of labour costs and the
‘socially necessary labour time’ that underlies it.
It can, of course, happen that producers in social conditions that yield low
labour costs, even without productivity-enhancing technologies or methods of
production, can drive down the price of a commodity in ways that affect pro-
ducers of the same commodity in other, higher-cost social environments, com-
pelling them to lower their costs by increasing labour productivity. This is,
needless to say, a familiar situation in the modern global economy, though
throughout most of human history it has probably been uncommon to find
the same commodities produced in very different social environments regularly
competing for the same market. At any rate, even when the same commodity is
available from different sources with substantially different costs of production,
very specific conditions, both technological and social, must be present to permit
the costs and methods of production in one locale systematically to affect
those in another, distant one, not to mention modern means of transport and
communication – conditions very rare until quite late in history.
The link between production and consumption must also be such that, while
production and consumption are separate and mediated by the market, there is a
relation between them that creates price/cost pressures and generates the need for
cost-effective production. We need not get embroiled in fruitless calculations of the
relation between ‘value’ and ‘price’ in order to recognize that competition – the
kind of competition that entails price/cost pressures and compels cost-effective
production – presupposes a relation between costs at the point of production
and price at the point of consumption. Various factors may weaken that relation:
for instance, there may be a great distance between production and consumption,
with one relatively inaccessible to the other; social conditions at the poles of
production and consumption may be so different that a commodity bought by
merchants in a ‘cheap’ environment can easily be sold relatively ‘dear’ in another
more affluent one without straining the buyers’ resources; there may be complex
and multiple interventions by merchants whose relative advantages are determined
by extra-economic factors; and so on. The more mediated the relation between
production and consumption, the less direct will be the effect of commerce on
the process of production.
The Question of Market Dependence 69

Consider, for instance, the process of exchange in the Northern Netherlands


described by Brenner. It was, on the face of it, a highly mediated process. To be
sure, the European economy was sufficiently ‘integrated’ to allow, for instance,
the price of grain produced in the Baltic region to affect economic trends else-
where, but the nature of its effects is telling in itself. Baltic grain, produced at
costs determined by conditions in the region of origin, and especially in poorer
locales, was, as we have seen, bought and conveyed by Dutch merchants who
enjoyed a clear dominance in the Baltic trade. That dominance had nothing to do
with the costs of producing the traded commodity. Their profits were derived
from buying it cheap in one locale and selling it (relatively) dear in another.
Dutch consumers, including farmers, in a richer economy whose wealth and social
conditions of production were entirely different, were able to buy that grain
with the proceeds of trade in other commodities, the production of which had
nothing to do, in cost or in price, with the cost and price of grain, except in the
sense that Dutch farmers benefited from the low cost of imported grain, which
they enjoyed thanks to the commercial dominance of Dutch traders. In any case,
what was ‘dear’ in relation to the costs of production was ‘cheap’ in relation to
prevailing conditions at the point of final sale, and Dutch merchants could easily
buy cheap (from their own vantage point, if not from that of Baltic producers)
and sell dear in Dutch markets – that is, dear in relation to the original purchase
price, yet cheap for the ultimate buyer.
At the same time, Dutch producers of dairy products were, of course, in no
way competing with Baltic producers of grain. If the costs of producing grain in
the Baltic had any effect on the costs of dairy production in the Netherlands, the
relatively low price of grain, as an ‘input’ for Dutch farmers, would have made
it less, rather than more, necessary to reduce their production costs in other
ways. Nor is it clear that Dutch dairy producers were competing with each
other, if the demand for their products was ample and growing. If they were in
principle competing with dairy producers elsewhere, their advantages seem to
have derived in large part from the dominance of Dutch merchants, both in the
export of their goods and in the import of cheap grain. So there was no obvious
need for competitive production, let alone for the maximization of profit as the
immediate object of production; and, again, the reverse of a price/cost squeeze
was at work.
If Dutch prosperity depended on a link between production and commerce,
it was perhaps always a tenuous connection, and certainly a very mediated one,
which may always have been vulnerable to rupture. To be sure, the Golden Age
of the Republic saw Dutch producers adapting themselves with considerable
flexibility to changing conditions and transforming production to meet expand-
ing commercial opportunities; and Dutch farmers continued to be remarkably
flexible in their responses to economic change (see Mastboom 1996, 2000). In
their relative freedom to adapt production in this way they may indeed have been
very different from peasant producers in other societies whose survival strategies
have necessarily involved constraints on changes in production imposed by limited
resources, or by customary practices, communal needs and regulations. But much
70 Ellen Meiksins Wood

of their success depended on the commercial role of the Republic and its mer-
chants, whose connection with domestic production was, so to speak, always at
one remove. Given the series of detachments between commerce and production
in the Dutch case, is it really possible to say that the eventual weakening of the
link was accidental, a failure of policy, or even just a cyclical trend?
De Vries and van der Woude (1997, 502) have argued that ‘[f ]oreign trade rarely
acts as the engine of growth of an economy’, and that once the link between
domestic production and international commerce was weakened, and the Dutch
began to rely on their ‘commercial sophistication’ without a linkage to domestic
production, the economy was bound to cease growing and become ‘less than the
sum of its parts’. But perhaps the reliance on commercial sophistication, as distinct
from competitive production, was always essential to the Dutch economy. The
commercial interests that dominated the economy were always, in a sense, semi-
detached from domestic production and ready to shift their investments into
other, often non-productive fields. Their vocation was, to put it simply, circula-
tion, not production, and profit was generated by that means.
This may have distinguished the Republic from England, which, while always
seeking to compete with the Dutch and other commercial rivals by traditional
extra-economic means, never quite achieved commercial dominance until its
domestic economy had been transformed by internal competitive pressures. The
logic of the English domestic economy created a new commercial system in
which advantage really did depend on competitive production. Even Britain’s
growing ‘extra-economic’ dominance, especially in the form of its navy, presup-
posed this new economic order and the wealth it generated.

MARKET-DEPENDENT APPROPRIATORS
Throughout this discussion, we have repeatedly been drawn back to one critical
point: in the one unambiguous case of self-sustaining capitalist development,
in England, where the imperatives of competition, profit-maximization and the
improvement of productive forces operated systematically in both rising and
declining markets, market dependence was not simply a need for exchange in
order to obtain basic necessities but a social-property relation. Both producers
and appropriators depended on the market for their self-reproduction. Just as
producers depended on the market for access to the means of production – land
– so was the power of appropriation dependent on the market, and the relation
between appropriators and producers was mediated by the market.
In his account of capitalist development in England, Brenner himself has
emphasized, as we have repeatedly noted, both sides of the relation between
English landlords and tenants. The specific pattern of self-sustaining economic
development in England was driven not only by the market dependence of the
direct producers but by their relation to a class of appropriators who could no
longer rely on extra-economic powers of appropriation, or politically constituted
property, and were increasingly dependent on rents deriving from the profits
of market-dependent tenants. Those tenants, in turn, depended on cost-effective
The Question of Market Dependence 71

production in a competitive market. We can now draw some larger implications


from the specificity of this relation.
When I first read Brenner’s analysis of the transition to capitalism many
years ago, I was persuaded by his forceful argument about England’s distinctive
appropriating class, a ruling class of landowners whose capacity to extract surplus
labour from direct producers was mediated by the market. I was persuaded that
this distinctive feature, as much as any other, accounted for England’s very specific
pattern of development, and hence the development of capitalism. What made
the argument even more persuasive was the contrast he drew between the course
of English development and the very different pattern in France.
In the French case, Brenner argued, production was dominated by peasant
owner/occupiers, while appropriation took the classic precapitalist form of
politically constituted property, eventually giving rise not to capitalism but to the
‘tax/office’ structure of absolutism. Here, centralized forms of extra-economic
exploitation competed with and increasingly supplanted older forms of seigneur-
ial extraction. Office became a major means of extracting surplus labour from
direct producers, in the form of tax; and the state, which became a source of great
private wealth, co-opted and incorporated growing numbers of appropriators
from among the old nobility as well as newer ‘bourgeois’ officeholders.
In other words, as in other precapitalist systems, wealth in absolutist France
depended less on the improvement of productive forces than on the enhancement
of appropriative powers, the extra-economic powers of military and political
coercion. The effect of this system of social-property relations, according to
Brenner, ‘was to prove disastrous to economic development’ (1985, 290). In its
efforts to preserve its tax-producing base, the absolutist state strengthened old
forms of peasant possession, and the new system of surplus extraction ‘was
oriented even more single-mindedly to conspicuous consumption and war’. This
system was more effective than the old in squeezing surplus out of the direct
producers, which meant not only that it was even more of a drain on the
productive forces of the peasantry, but also that there was little incentive for
the appropriators to encourage labour productivity and the development of
productive forces.
The contrast between England and France, then, stands out in sharp relief.
It is not so difficult to discern the difference between the presence of market
dependence in the former and its absence in the latter, for both producers and
appropriators, despite the existence of a well-developed commercial system in
France and its active participation in international trade. A more difficult case is
presented by the other major model of European development, the wealthy
commercial centres that emerged, for instance, in Northern Italy and the Nether-
lands. No one could deny that the wealth of the dominant classes here rested on
commerce, and that the appropriation of surpluses from direct producers did not
here take the classic form of feudal rent. Nevertheless, here too, it can be argued,
great wealth still depended on politically constituted property; and here too this
form of appropriation shaped the particular and self-limiting course of economic
development.
72 Ellen Meiksins Wood

Urban patriciates or merchant elites in commercial centres in medieval and


early modern Europe often extracted great wealth from commercial activities,
but they relied in large part on the privileges and powers associated with their
status in the city. The success of these commercial centres was dependent less on
competitive production than on ‘extra-economic’ factors such as monopoly priv-
ileges, sophisticated commercial methods and instruments, elaborate commercial
networks, and far-flung trading posts, or military superiority, superior shipping
and command of trade routes. Ruling elites in these centres depended on their
civic status not only for privileged access to such commercial advantages but
typically also, as officeholders, for exploitation of domestic producers by means
of direct extra-economic surplus extraction in the form of dues and taxes of one
kind or another, so much so that cities of this kind have been described as
collective lordships.
This is true even in cases like Florence, whose commercial wealth was based
not only on trade in foreign goods but on its own domestic products. In relation
to the surrounding countryside, the city of Florence was certainly a collective
lordship, extracting rent in the form of tax according to a logic not so very
different from the absolutist state in France. At the same time, the success of
its trade in its own manufactured commodities continued to depend on extra-
economic factors, on monopoly privileges, or on especially sophisticated com-
mercial and financial practices, which facilitated a commerce in goods whose
success in a luxury market in any case had less to do with cost-effective produc-
tion than with the skills of craftsmanship. Not the least significant trait of the
Florentine economy was that its greatest merchant families, even those whose
fortunes had begun in trade, moved into more lucrative non-productive enter-
prises, such as financial services for monarchs and popes, or public office, up to
and including dynastic rule of the city-state itself – as most famously in the case
of the Medici.
As successful as these commercial centres were for a time, and as great as the
wealth they amassed, their economic development was self-limiting. It is self-
evidently true that the market played a central role in their development, but it
seems just as clear that here it really did function more as an opportunity than as
an imperative. At least, the market did not operate here in such a way as to create
the relentless capitalist drive to maximize profit by developing the forces of
production. Where the necessary productive capacities were present and the
market, especially for luxury goods, was available, the dominant classes were
willing and able to encourage and exploit not only commerce but production.
Merchants even organized and invested in production. Yet, the appropriation of
great wealth still depended on extra-economic powers and privileges, and far less
on developing productive forces than on refining and extending the forces of
appropriation. A system of this kind would inevitably respond to declining
market opportunities not by enhancing labour productivity and improving cost-
effectiveness but by squeezing producers harder or by withdrawing altogether
from production in favour of more ‘extra-economic’ powers of appropriation.
It may be possible to argue (as I would be inclined to do) that the non-
capitalist character of such commercial economies was as much their strength as
The Question of Market Dependence 73

their weakness, and that, for instance, the Italian Renaissance, which flourished
in the environment of commercial city-states in northern Italy like Florence,
would not have achieved its great heights under the pressures of capitalist
imperatives. The same may be true of the Dutch Republic, which enjoyed its
own spectacular cultural boom during the ‘Golden Age’ of its commercial
supremacy. But that is another story. The point here is simply that, in the
absence of those capitalist imperatives, the pattern of economic development was
bound to be different than it would be in capitalism.
The Dutch case is no doubt the most complex. It seems to have been the most
highly commercialized society in history, before the advent of capitalism. It was,
as Brenner has shown, unusually dependent on trade to provide the most basic
conditions of subsistence even for direct producers. More particularly, even its
agricultural producers seem to have depended on trade to an unprecedented
degree for basic subsistence needs. Nor can there be any doubt that the great
wealth of the Republic was founded on commerce, or that Dutch elites, as
Brenner emphasizes, invested in domestic production – notably in agriculture –
in unprecedented ways and degrees. Yet, quite apart from the questions that can
be raised about the nature and degree of market dependence in production, the
market dependence of appropriation is also open to question.
One of the most striking features of the Dutch social structure, as de Vries
and van der Woude stress, was the predominance of public office as a source
of private wealth. The decentralized organization of the Republic created a
particularly fertile field for public service occupations, so the proportion of such
occupations in the population of Dutch cities was very high. But more than the
sheer numbers of offices, the most striking thing is the wealth associated with
them. To be sure, it required substantial wealth from real property or finance
to enter the urban patriciate, since to be part of the governing elite increasingly
required abandoning private economic activities, but this wealth was vastly
supplemented by the large salaries attached to high office.
Lucrative offices were always an important resource for the Dutch ruling
classes, and even in the Golden Age of the Republic’s commercial dominance,
a wealthy landowner or financier would often choose to use his wealth for access
to such offices. In the seventeenth century, ‘the financial and social advantages
of participation in town government became fully evident’ (de Vries and van der
Woude 1997, 588). After 1660, when economic conditions declined, the value of
this source of wealth became even more evident and highly prized. In Holland,
for instance, the urban patriciate that comprised the governing elite enjoyed
‘incomes (and wealth!) that exceeded that of all other groups, bar none’ (de Vries
and van der Woude 1997, 586). In the Republic as a whole in the eighteenth
century (at a time when Britain was dominated by the wealth of capitalist
landlords), while the largest total income was held by rentiers (a significant fact
in itself ), ‘no less than nine of the fifteen occupations with the highest average
incomes were located in the public sector’, including the top six occupations (de
Vries and van der Woude 1997, 596).
We shall return in a moment to the pattern of development disclosed by these
statistics. But the first point that suggests itself here is that the Dutch Republic
74 Ellen Meiksins Wood

bears the unmistakeable marks of a ‘tax/office’ structure. Before the late


eighteenth century, taxation in the Republic ‘stood at a far higher level than in
surrounding countries; it was then nearly twice as high as in Britain’ (de Vries
and van der Woude 1997, 111). The scale of taxation, however, is less significant
in revealing the logic of the Dutch economy than are the uses to which taxes
were put, not least in subsidizing the structure of public office as a means of
private appropriation.
The particular nature of taxation may also reveal much about the logic of the
Dutch economy. While the French taxed their peasants, and the English landed
classes, especially in the late seventeenth century and thereafter, taxed themselves
(after extracting their wealth directly from direct producers by means of increas-
ingly market-dependent private appropriation), the Dutch preferred the excise tax.
In these simple contrasts there is a wealth of information about their respective
social structures and economic patterns.
If the English mode of taxation bespeaks agrarian capitalism, the French is the
mark of a tax/office structure that rests on the backs of the peasantry. The Dutch
have in common with the French a system of wealth derived from public office
resting on a base of taxation. But the excise, while certainly hard on poorer
consumers, taxed consumption (or, effectively, commerce) rather than production,
and in this respect, at least while commercial conditions were good, was less of
a drain on productive capacities. So, for a time, the Dutch were able to sustain
a tax/office structure, on the basis of their vast commercial wealth, without
suppressing productivity. In fact, while the Golden Age lasted, a significant part
of that wealth was ploughed into production, invested, for instance, in major
projects of land reclamation. What happened thereafter is another story, to which
we shall return in a moment.
The role of taxation in sustaining a structure of lucrative public offices was
not the only signal of a precapitalist logic. The Republic reached its commercial
peak in large part by devoting much of its tax revenues to military ventures that
secured its ‘extra-economic’ advantages in international trade. ‘Military expend-
iture formed the largest category of expenses of the young Republic’ (de Vries
and van der Woude 1997, 100); and military aggression remained an essential
part of the Republic’s economic strategy throughout the Golden Age and there-
after. Even while the Republic’s massive resources were being used to sustain
production, a major part of its revenues were still expended on the ‘extra-
economic’ pursuit of commercial interests by means of military aggression for the
sole purpose of enhancing commercial opportunities. These included not only
aggressive trade wars but such ventures as their notorious seizure, in 1602, of a
Portuguese ship containing an enormously valuable cargo of unprecedented pro-
portions, large enough to affect the future course of Dutch economic development;
or the famous ‘Amboina massacre’ of English merchants in 1623.
But the most telling development is what happened, even to production in
the Republic, as the European economy went into decline. The Dutch response
reveals an economic logic that, contrary to de Vries and van der Woude, even on
their own evidence, does not simply correspond to the cyclical pattern of a
The Question of Market Dependence 75

‘modern’ (i.e. capitalist) economy, but suggests something rather different. During
and after the seventeenth-century crisis, there is, to begin with, a process of
disinvestment in land. More significantly, ‘with the onset of agrarian depression,
the interest in public office was intensified’, because investment in office was
more lucrative than investment in land (de Vries and van der Woude 1997, 535).
There was, as a result, an ‘oligarchization’ of public office. Even the exception
proves the rule: Friesland was the only region that saw a renewed interest in
landownership – simply because here it was a requirement for voting rights, and
hence access to office, so people bought land ‘in the hope that what the economy
had taken away, political office might restore’ (de Vries and van der Woude
1997, 218).
While investment in technologies to enhance labour productivity was ‘not
altogether lacking’, it was far from being the preferred response to declining
market opportunities. More attractive to the wealthy elites were ‘extra-economic’
strategies and investment in politically constituted property, notably office, but
also such attempts to revive monopoly privileges as the reestablishment of the
West India Company or one company’s monopoly on navigational charts (de
Vries and van der Woude 1997, 676).
We have already seen how this pattern was reflected in the distribution of
wealth in the Republic, with the concentration of wealth in the hands of
officeholders. There are other telling features too. The fact which, as de Vries
and van der Woude emphasize, more than any other ‘gave the eighteenth-
century economic its distinctive shape’ was a fiscal system supporting an enormous
debt, which concentrated wealth in the hands of a small layer of bondholders (de
Vries and van der Woude 1997, 681). At the same time, ‘the most prominent and
dynamic of eighteenth-century growth sectors were finance and trade in colonial
goods’. Finally, there is what de Vries and van der Woude regard as the fatal
‘separation of the shipping, trading, financing, insuring, and producing sectors’,
the integration of which had been ‘the hallmark of the Golden Age’. The classic
commercial interests of merchants whose profits derived from circulation rather
than production asserted themselves in various ways, if not in their abandonment
of commerce for office, then their abandonment of domestic production for more
lucrative means of trading in goods produced elsewhere.
Nor did the Dutch neglect the military dimension of their commercial strategy
as the European economy was sinking into crisis. Perhaps the most striking
example is the Dutch role in England’s so-called ‘Glorious Revolution’ in 1688.
Here is a particularly interesting reversion to precapitalist modes of investment,
in which the massive financial resources of the Republic were directed not at
improving production, as they had been during the Golden Age by investment
in major projects like land reclamation, but at achieving extra-economic com-
mercial advantage by military means.
The province of Holland in particular depended on the profitability of
commerce and therefore was especially affected by the incursions of French
mercantilism in the late seventeenth century, its interference with Dutch ships
and its draconian tariffs. The only solution to this problem of commercial
76 Ellen Meiksins Wood

profitability was to defeat French mercantilism, and that required an alliance


with England, which seemed possible only with a friend on the English throne.
The Dutch Republic therefore committed its resources to supporting William of
Orange’s bid for the English monarchy, in ‘a risky investment to use the one
resource the Republic had in abundance – money – to re-establish an international
environment in which the economy could once again prosper’ (de Vries and van
der Woude 1997, 680). The Revolution may, to the English, seem ‘glorious’ and
largely bloodless. But from the Dutch point of view it was an invasion, involving
the occupation of London by Dutch troops, in full expectation of a war involving
the English and also the French. Not only the state but also the Amsterdam stock
exchange invested in this ultimate use of extra-economic power in pursuit of
commercial profit.
In short, during the crisis there seems to be a consistent pattern of reversion
to, or intensification of, non-capitalist forms of commerce or even ‘extra-economic’
appropriation, rentier wealth and officeholding. This is not, on the face of it,
consistent with a capitalist pattern of development. But we can make sense of
the Dutch pattern, both the rise and the decline of the Dutch economy, if we
acknowledge that its fate rested not on the successes or failures of competitive
capitalist producers but on the interests of commercial profit-takers and the
beneficiaries of office.
It was suggested earlier that one important test of competitive imperatives is
the degree to which they operate in a rising market with increasing demand. But
the ultimate test of market imperatives such as those that drive the capitalist
system may be what happens in the face of declining market opportunities. No
one would deny that capitalists will withdraw from unprofitable ventures, but
the mark of capitalist imperatives may be the extent to which they preclude
disinvestment in the face of competition (as Brenner himself has famously shown
in his explanation of overcapacity in the contemporary global economy). A
decrease of production is one possible response for capitalist producers in the face
of declining markets, but to the extent that their profits derive from production,
it is hard to detach themselves from it, and from their capital investments in
specific sectors of production. It is easier for commercial profit-takers whose
connection to production is not so direct.
The most striking index of the difference between the Dutch and English
cases is that in England, falling prices in the European crisis of the late
seventeenth century, instead of promoting withdrawal of capital from agricul-
tural production, led to more capital investment to promote improvement and
lower costs. This fact alone brings into sharp relief the difference between an
economy driven by market imperatives, the imperatives of competition and
profit-maximization by means of increasing labour productivity, and an economy
which, while certainly subject to certain commercial ‘imperatives’, is more re-
sponsive to market opportunities.
The Dutch economy certainly flourished in its Golden Age beyond any other
commercial society, but its subsequent trajectory suggests that there remains a
fundamental difference between market opportunities and market imperatives,
The Question of Market Dependence 77

or between commercialization and capitalism. While British agrarian capitalism


entrenched itself more firmly during the seventeenth-century crisis, followed by
the golden age of ‘improvement’, with its great landed wealth in the eighteenth
century and industrial capitalism thereafter, the Dutch economy played to its
own great strengths, its ‘commercial sophistication’, together with the tax/office
structure that fed on it. That pattern of Dutch economic development followed
the logic not of competitive capitalist production but of profit-taking commercial
circulation.
More than any other historian, Brenner has alerted us to the flaws in the
‘commercialization model’ of capitalist development. He has persuasively demon-
strated that all those attempts, from Adam Smith onward, to explain the rise of
capitalism as little more than the quantitative growth of markets and trade have
simply begged the question, assuming the prior existence of capitalism, with its
distinctive imperatives, in order to explain its coming into being. More than
anyone else, he has insisted on the specificity of capitalism. To make his vastly
important argument even more powerful, it seems indispensable to follow through
on it by explaining and theorizing the economic logic of commercial development,
and in particular the very specific form of commercialization that took place in
certain parts of Western Europe, in the late medieval and early modern period,
without setting in motion the self-sustaining and constantly expanding imperatives
of capitalist development.

MARKET DEPENDENCE AND TRADE IN BASIC NECESSITIES


Let me, then, try to sum up and elaborate what I take to be specific about the
English form of market dependence. We can certainly start from the premise that
market dependence has something to do, in the first instance, with the produc-
tion and exchange of basic necessities, notably food. But if market dependence
means a compulsion to ‘compete or go under’, with all that entails, it may not be
enough to say that producers become market dependent when they must sell
some other commodity in order to buy their basic necessities.
The distinctiveness of market dependence in England is evident in the emerg-
ence, in the early modern period, of a novel commercial system based on com-
merce in the means of survival and self-reproduction for a growing mass market,
a commercial system in which the trade in basic necessities played a historically
unprecedented role, different in its ‘logic of process’ from other commerce in
food, including the massive European grain trade.
To say that the English domestic market was a novelty in this respect is not,
of course, to deny either that trade in basic necessities was a major feature of
other commercial systems, in Europe and elsewhere, or that England, like other
European commercial powers, was involved in the luxury trade. The grain
trade was certainly an essential characteristic of commerce in medieval and early
modern Europe, while England, like other European countries, saw the growth
of a market at home, and increasingly among prosperous urban classes, for a vast
array of luxury goods. But the English domestic market generated something
78 Ellen Meiksins Wood

different from either the luxury trade, or the precapitalist trade in basic necessities,
or the specific interaction between the two that marked the European trading
system.
Consider first, in very broad outline, the nature of the commercial system
in medieval and early modern Europe. It is certainly true that a growing urban
population in parts of Europe, and especially in the major commercial centres,
created not only a growing market for luxury goods, supplied increasingly by
long-distance trade, but also a market for very basic subsistence needs which
their own domestic agriculture was unable to meet. These needs were supplied
above all by imported grain, increasingly from the Baltic region.
But as essential as the grain trade was, it cannot be regarded as the motor of
the European trading system. Imported grain was certainly an essential condition
of commercial success in the major European trading powers, but the grain trade
was not itself the driving force of a commercial system whose fortunes were
always dependent on the fate of the luxury trade and the wealth of the prosperous
consumers that impelled it. It is even possible to argue that the need for a massive
trade in grain was determined by the luxurious consumption patterns of the
wealthier classes, in the sense that the (grain-consuming) urban population of
Europe was swelled by people servicing the opulent living and ‘conspicuous
consumption’ of richer consumers.5
In the Middle Ages, trade was driven by the wealth of the landed aristocracy,
whose consumption patterns – their hunger for luxuries, as well as for the instru-
ments of ‘extra-economic’ coercion on which their economic power depended –
dictated the logic of the commercial system. ‘The landed aristocracy,’ writes
Rodney Hilton, ‘whether lay or ecclesiastical, constituted at all times the principal
market for a range of products, mainly luxuries, which entered into international
trade . . . International trade, of course, dealt also in bulk commodities like grain
and timber, but the demand for these was mainly urban and probably depended
ultimately on the health of the international trade in luxuries’ (1985, 127).
Even later, with the growth of towns and prosperous burgher classes,
the same fundamental logic prevailed. Many more people, many of them poor,
came to depend for their subsistence on cheap imported grain. But the interna-
tional trading system of pre-capitalist Europe continued to be driven by the
wealth and wants of prosperous consumers, as well as the needs of the state,
not by the consumer needs and powers of those who entered the market
above all to acquire the basic means of survival and self-reproduction, whether
food or other commodities of everyday life, from inexpensive textiles to cheap
cooking pots.
The point can be illustrated by considering the disjunction between com-
mercial power in Europe and the trade in grain. The production and export of
grain, as essential as it was to European subsistence, was not (until Britain
broke the pattern) an index of wealth and economic power. It was even (as Marx
once put it – 1973, 277) the function of those ‘left behind’ in Europe’s economic

5
I owe the latter point to George Comninel.
The Question of Market Dependence 79

development. A division of labour developed between Europe’s, often poorer,


grain-exporting regions and its richest trading powers, such as the Dutch Republic.
But this division of labour was never a simple exchange of necessities between
specialized regions – grain from the Baltic for, say, the dairy products of the
Low Countries. While the Dutch role in the Baltic grain trade was certainly
paramount, commercial power such as theirs derived not simply from commerce
in basic necessities but from trade in luxuries or ‘relative luxuries’, consumed
disproportionately by other rich commercial powers as distinct from grain-
exporting countries.
The commercial system of pre-capitalist Europe, then, was characterized by a
series of disjunctions: the geographic separation between the production of grain
and its consumption by countries whose wealth derived from trade in other
commodities – not even necessarily from the production of those commodities but
also, sometimes even more, from the conveyance, transhipment and arbitrage of
commodities produced elsewhere and revenues from entrepots – together with
an imbalance between the production of basic necessities and economic power
derived from trade in luxuries. These disjunctions and imbalances were, needless
to say, reinforced by the basic practicalities of transport and communication.
The whole system, indeed, was based on the fragmentation of markets, detach-
ment of one market from another, the distance between sites of production and
sites of consumption, the geographic separation of supply and demand. Mercantile
wealth depended precisely on the relative inaccessibility of markets and the pos-
sibility of profiting from an endless process of arbitrage between fragmented
markets (Kerridge 1988, 6).
These disjunctions constituted a fundamental separation between consumption
and production. The social conditions in which grain was produced in exporting
regions had very little to do with the conditions in which it was consumed in the
rich commercial centres. This meant, among other things, that grain was cheap
by the economic standards of the consuming powers, without the enhancement
of productive forces in the producing regions. Nor did low costs in the grain-
producing regions impose competitive pressures on the consuming economies
that benefited from cheap imports. At any rate, the trading advantages of the
commercial leaders did not depend primarily on competitive production.
This was true even of the Dutch, who differed from other Europeans in the
degree to which even their farmers depended on buying food grains; for whom
the grain trade was an absolute necessity; whose commerce in food was essential
to their economic success; and who certainly pioneered many advances in pro-
ductivity, not least in agriculture. Here, the influence of low-cost grain producing
regions, which benefited the Dutch even more than other economies, if anything
reduced competitive pressures by lowering the costs of basic inputs. To the extent
that the Dutch exchanged their own products, including agricultural commodities,
for goods produced elsewhere, there was certainly a linkage between produc-
tion and commerce; and the Golden Age of the Republic was no doubt, as de
Vries and van der Woude have argued, a period in which this link was close
and fruitful (followed by a period of decline when the linkage was weakened).
80 Ellen Meiksins Wood

Nevertheless, the link was mediated by the disjunctions characteristic of the Euro-
pean market in general, and the Dutch constructed their commercial empire on
the strength of other advantages outside the sphere of production. Like other com-
mercial leaders in Europe (before the commercial dominance of capitalist Britain),
the Dutch typically relied, for their successes in international trade, on extra-
economic superiority in negotiating separate markets, rather than on competitive
production in a single market: on dominance in shipping and command of trade
routes, on monopolies and trading privileges, on an elaborate network of far-
flung trading posts and settlements, on the development of sophisticated financial
practices and instruments, and so on.
At the same time, there was in the Dutch Republic a disproportionately large
domestic market for luxury goods. These were consumed not only by large urban
populations, in which the proportion of prosperous burghers was unusually large
in relation to the impoverished and dispossessed. There was also an unusually
substantial market for luxury goods among prosperous peasants. In this sense,
too, the logic of commerce in the Republic was driven less by the needs of poor
consumers than by the wants of the well-to-do, and, it might be said, by the
market dependence of consumers (including consumers of grain) more than of
producers.
These disjunctions certainly meant that, while a rich commercial nation like
the Dutch Republic was dependent on the grain trade for the means of survival,
the cost of the most basic survival needs was disproportionately low in relation
to the wealth derived from commerce in less necessary goods. But the same
disjunctions also meant that the commercial centres whose wealth depended on
them were vulnerable to the fragilities of the international trade in superfluous
goods. Not only their great wealth but even their supply of cheap and basic
necessities could suffer from declines in the luxury trade. The Dutch, like other
European economies, came up against the barriers of the old commercial system
in the crisis of the seventeenth century. For all their agricultural success, and for
all their trade in basic commodities, they always belonged to an economy – both
externally and, I would argue, internally – still subject to the constraints of
the precapitalist market, not least its disproportionate dependence on luxury
consumption by the wealthy few at home or abroad.

THE SPECIFICITY OF BRITISH MARKET DEPENDENCE


The British, and more particularly the English, created a new kind of commer-
cial system, driven by different needs and answering to a logic different from any
other in history. To be sure, they participated in the old commercial system, and
they certainly experienced a consumer boom in luxury goods. Nor, of course,
can it be denied that the wealth of prosperous classes continued to play – as, by
definition, it must, in any grossly unequal society, including, and especially,
capitalism – an economic role disproportionate to their numbers in all forms of
trade. But alongside the more traditional forms of trade, there emerged, in Eng-
land’s domestic market, a novel system with a logic of its own, which eventually
The Question of Market Dependence 81

extended its reach beyond Britain’s national boundaries, to create a new system
of international trade.
First, the English domestic market was, already by the seventeenth century,
something like a unified national market, without the disjunctions that had char-
acterized international trade (disjunctions that, indeed, have yet to be entirely
overcome even by today’s ‘globalization’), and without the internal trade barriers
that still affected domestic economies elsewhere, not just fragmented city-states
but even a centralized kingdom like France. This national economy was also
increasingly distinctive in the sheer size and the particular composition of the
market for basic necessities, as well as for simple, cheap commodities of every-
day life, like iron cooking pots. The decline of the English peasantry may have
taken longer than has sometimes been suggested, extending well into the nine-
teenth century. But as the early market dependence of English tenant farmers,
already visible in the sixteenth century in the form of competitive rents, acceler-
ated the dispossession of those unable to survive in increasingly competitive
conditions, market dependence increasingly took the more complete form of
commodified labour power and the reliance on a wage for access to the means of
subsistence.
The European grain trade had traditionally been directed largely to urban
populations, which, of course, grew substantially in the relevant period. The
proportion of urban to rural populations in England increased more than most,
and London became the largest city in Europe, a uniquely huge consumer of
basic necessities. But this demographic pattern alone was not enough to account
for the uniqueness of England’s domestic market. After all, the urban population
of England in the early modern period never reached the proportions of the
Dutch Republic at its peak.6 Yet even here there is a telling contrast. The urban
population in the Dutch Golden Age was swelled not simply by the poor and
dispossessed unable to sustain themselves on agricultural production, but to an
unusual degree by those who benefited from or serviced the Republic’s great
commercial wealth. By contrast, the English city, London in particular, was
disproportionately enlarged by the poor dispossessed by agrarian capitalism. In
any case, what made the English market for basic goods distinctive was not
simply the demographic distribution between town and country but the growing
proportion of the population, whether urban or rural, that was dispossessed and
reliant on wages for survival, together with the more direct relation of production
to consumption of this kind.
Historians have in recent years devoted much attention to the growth of a
‘consumer society’ in Britain (as well as elsewhere, notably in the Netherlands).7
There can be little doubt that, particularly in the eighteenth century and especially

6
By the late seventeenth century, the urban population of the Republic as a whole may have been
as high as 45 per cent (the province of Holland was well above that national average), with some
decline thereafter, making it the most highly urbanized country in Europe. See de Vries and van der
Woude (1997, 59–61).
7
For discussions of these ‘consumer societies’, see, for example, Thirsk (1978), McKendrick et al.
(1983) and Schama (1988).
82 Ellen Meiksins Wood

with the growth of prosperous urban classes, there was a burgeoning market for
all kinds of goods, beyond the basic necessities, from fine apparel to works of
art. But the ‘consumer society’ in England, however new it may have been in the
size of the market and the range of its goods, was not qualitatively different from
bourgeois markets elsewhere in Europe. Nor were such consumer markets
fundamentally discontinuous from Europe’s medieval burgher culture, and their
sheer quantitative growth was not enough to distinguish them fundamentally
from the luxury trade of earlier periods. To identify what was truly new and
distinctive, representing a major qualitative break from old economic patterns
and the operation of a new systemic logic, we have to look elsewhere.
It can be misleading to define the specific character of the new economy in
Britain by stressing the growing wealth of the ‘middle classes’ or the numbers of
consumers who were able to buy a wide range of goods to enhance their comfort,
pleasure, aesthetic enjoyment or status. More distinctive was the growth of the
numbers compelled to buy – not the superfluities of life but the most basic com-
modities and the implements of daily subsistence and self-reproduction. Need-
less to say, the growth of such a market presupposed the ability to buy no less
than the compulsion. In the historical moment between agrarian and industrial
capitalism, the purchasing power of labourers may indeed have been unusually
substantial; and no doubt the definition of necessity was becoming ever more
elastic, increasingly embracing manufactured instruments of daily life such as
industrially produced kitchenware and eating utensils. But compulsion lies at the
heart of the new economic dynamic, and, in this kind of market, even the ability
to buy was defined by its strict limitations. It was certainly a novelty that so
many working people were now consumers, but the specific logic of this novel
market depended as much on the poverty of its consumers as the luxury trade
depended on wealth.
It is not, however, enough to say that first England and then Britain saw
the emergence of a historically unprecedented mass market for cheap everyday
commodities. What finally distinguishes this market from earlier markets in basic
necessities is the fact that the consumption needs of relatively poor consumers
became the driving force of a new kind of market also in the sense that this
market affected production in wholly new ways. The new patterns of consump-
tion reacted directly on production as never before, in the context of an already
integrated and increasingly competitive national market. English agricultural
production substantially supplied its own domestic market for food, and
England was, for a time, even a net exporter of grain. At the same time, the
development of productive forces in the countryside was the corollary of trans-
formations in social-property relations that eventually also created the mass
of wage-earning consumers. English agriculture was sufficiently productive by
itself – not only, like the Dutch, by means of exchange, dependent on a super-
abundance of purely commercial wealth – to sustain a large population no longer
engaged in agricultural production, while British industry developed on the
strength of cheap basic goods, like cotton cloth, and their accessibility to that
growing mass market.
The Question of Market Dependence 83

The development of a mass proletariat employed by capital represented the


ultimate development of the direct relationship between production and con-
sumption. (It also, of course, represented a fundamental contradiction: the same
conditions that brought about the integration of production and consumption,
the same forces that overcame the disjunctions of the old commercial system,
the same imperatives of competition and capital accumulation, with their sys-
tematic tendency to overcapacity, also ensured a regular imbalance between
production and consumption, a new and systematic disjunction between supply
and demand. In the old commercial system, with its spatial and structural dis-
connections between production and consumption, between supply and demand,
there could certainly be imbalances; but they were, so to speak, contingent,
arising by default rather than by compulsion. The absence of the imperatives
of competition meant that there were no systemic mechanisms that compelled
the regular recurrence of such imbalances, least of all the imbalances of over-
capacity.) The proletariat constituted both a force of production and a mass
consumer market, and the condition of the proletariat in both its aspects shaped
the development of productive forces. In a competitive environment with sys-
temic imperatives to increase labour productivity, the general commodifica-
tion of labour power in the form of wage-labour compelled capital, already
driven by competitive pressures, to extract the maximum surplus value from
workers in the limited time during which it controlled the labour power of
juridically free workers. At the same time, these propertyless wage labourers,
dependent on the market for all their material needs, determined the nature of
production not only by their own productive activity but also by their powers of
consumption.
This kind of consumption constituted a market uniquely broad and inclusive,
but also uniquely limited in its resources. As a class entirely dependent on
exchanging a money-wage for the most basic means of subsistence, the pro-
letariat represented a larger market in a more or less unified geographic space,
and in a more or less integrated economy, than had ever existed before. But it
was also a market whose consumers had restricted powers of consumption. That
distinctive combination naturally engendered its own pressures for cost-effective
production. Production for this market required making up in numbers what
consumers lacked in wealth, and this created pressures to produce cheaply, pres-
sures that reinforced the cost-sensitivity imposed by already existing imperatives
of competition. This was, in other words, the first economic system in history
in which the limitations of the market impelled instead of inhibited the forces of
production.
Until the production of the means of survival and self-reproduction is market
dependent, there is no capitalist mode of production. With the advent of industrial
capitalism, market dependence had truly penetrated to the depths of the
social order. But its precondition was an already well-established and deeply
rooted market dependence, reaching back to the early days of English agrarian
capitalism, when the production of food became subject to the imperatives of
competition. This was a unique social form in which the main economic actors,
84 Ellen Meiksins Wood

both appropriators and producers, were market dependent in historically unpre-


cedented ways.8
No doubt other societies, especially England’s commercial rivals, relied on
trade to supply certain basic conditions of subsistence. But in none of them was
production subject to the pressures of market dependence in the same way. More
particularly, in none of them was access to the very means of agricultural pro-
duction, to land, market dependent as it was in the conditions of English property
relations; and in none of them was appropriation market dependent in the way
that it was for English propertied classes already from the early modern period.
This, as has been argued here, distinguishes the English even from the Dutch,
whose market dependence was of a different kind.
The effect of the English system was not only to make agricultural producers
uniquely subject to market imperatives and the requirements of competitive
production, but also to propel the mass dispossession that created both the
labour force and the market for wholly new forms of industrial production. The
end result was a system of production, with mutually reinforcing agrarian and
industrial sectors, uniquely capable of imposing its competitive imperatives on
other parts of the world; and with it came a new commercial system. Thereafter,
and especially with the advent of British industrial capitalism, economic develop-
ment elsewhere, from Britain’s European neighbours to the farthest corners of
the colonial world, would be determined by the new imperatives of capitalism.

CONCLUSION
It is, then, worth considering the implications of the differences between England
and the ‘capitalist’ Netherlands. It is worth considering whether the divergence of
the Dutch from the English pattern of development was simply rooted in a factor
external to its own systemic logic or whether that divergence was already inherent
in their different starting points. One striking difference is that England’s early
market dependence, unlike that of the maritime Northern Netherlands, had nothing
to do with filling the gaps in existing productive capacities, or the inability of its
agriculture to supply its own subsistence needs. The market dependence of English
farmers was based on something altogether different, not simply the need to ex-
change in order to live, but the particular relation between ‘economic’ tenants and
landlords devoid of extra-economic powers. Even the capacity for self-sufficiency
in agricultural production would not make producers in England less market de-
pendent. Theirs was a particularly stringent, all-or-nothing mode of market depend-
ence, which was in no way alleviated by more than adequate productive capacities.
8
The market dependence at the heart of this unique formation was reflected in various conceptual
and ideological developments, not least in the concept of value. Already in the sixteenth century,
English land surveyors were explicitly measuring the actual customary rents of a specific tenancy
against its putative ‘real’ value in a competitive market. Later developments in political economy can,
I would argue, be traced to these early, very practical manifestations of the mentality associated with
English market dependence, which can be sharply contrasted to developments elsewhere in Europe.
But that is another story, which I hope to pursue another time, though I discuss this point to some
extent in the forthcoming revised and expanded edition of The Origin of Capitalism (Wood 2002).
The Question of Market Dependence 85

The English situation, then, was distinctive in several related ways. The
producer’s access to land itself was directly determined by the market, and the
degree of market success required in order to retain possession was not determined
by the producer himself, by the needs of his family or by their own consumption
patterns – nor, for that matter, by their own hunger for profit. Possession of
good and ample land did not obviate or even reduce dependence on the market.
On the contrary, dependence on the market – by means of economic leases – was
a condition for access to that kind of land; and more successful farmers were
likely to have more access to more land. So producers who had the possibility to
compete and maximize profit were likely to be those who were most subject
to the need to do so. That compulsion derived in the first instance from their
relation to appropriators who themselves lacked non-market access to the means
of appropriation. In that way, profit – not direct consumption or exchange –
became the immediate object of production; and for the first time in history,
there developed a mode of exploitation that systematically impelled the develop-
ment of productive forces.
So what does this all mean? I have suggested, here and elsewhere, that
Brenner’s Marxist critics are wrong about the implications of his focus on the
‘horizontal’ relations of capitalism. I now want to add that much of their
misreading has to do with a tendency to see the market as just the ‘sphere of cir-
culation’. Marx, they remind us, looked beneath the appearances of exchange and
the circulation of commodities to the underlying reality of the social-property
relations between capital and labour. It is, they insist, a mistake to focus on the
market in the way that Brenner does. Yet Brenner’s great strength has been
precisely to uncover the realities of the market itself as a social-property relation.
The questions I have raised about his analysis of capitalist development in the
Low Countries may come down to this: there is a difference between the market
as a mechanism of exchange or an instrument of circulation, and the market as
a social-property relation. The specificity of capitalism is that the relations of
producers to the means of production, and of appropriators to the means of
appropriation, as well as their relation to each other, is mediated, indeed consti-
tuted, by the market. It follows from this that there may, again, be two different
kinds of market dependence, one that entails a need to exchange in order to sur-
vive, and another that makes profit-maximization, not consumption or exchange,
the immediate object of production.
It would not, as I have already suggested, be unreasonable to identify the
Dutch case – like other precapitalist commercial powers – as an opportunity-
driven economy, responding to rises and declines in market opportunities more
than to market imperatives of the capitalist kind. But perhaps we should dis-
tinguish not only between the market as an opportunity and the market as an
imperative but also between two different kinds of market dependence. The
latter difference is not just conceptual but historical. There have existed societies
that relied for their self-reproduction on the market as a means of circulation but
not as a fundamental property relation, and this distinction may help to charac-
terize the differences between the Northern Netherlands and England. If we are
86 Ellen Meiksins Wood

to understand capital itself as a specific social form, we surely have to recognize


the specificity of the market as a social-property relation.
This is not to say that market dependence of the Dutch variety could never
have produced capitalist development of the English kind, that a need to enter
the market for most or all material needs could not have set in train the kind of
development that did take place where the market from the start constituted
basic property relations. But what ‘actually happened’ was something else: the
market as simply a means of exchange and circulation, and even market depend-
ence as a need to exchange in order to live, did not, in Europe or anywhere else,
become a medium of continuous capitalist development until market dependence
in the English sense, with its inherent drive to competitive production and profit-
maximization, imposed a need on Britain’s rivals to produce competitively.
From then on, and especially once the first capitalism assumed its industrial
form, the market as a means of exchange and circulation did indeed become
a transmission belt for capitalist competitive pressures. From then on, market
dependence of any kind would indeed entail the imperatives of competitive pro-
duction and profit-maximization. Economies inserted in the international trading
system and depending on it for their material needs, whatever their prevailing
social-property relations, would henceforth be subject to capitalist imperatives.
Although the origin of capitalism depended on the social relation between
market-dependent producers and appropriators, once commodification and com-
petition became a virtually universal form of social reproduction, producers even
in the absence of class exploitation were subject to market imperatives. This was
true of independent farmers and would have been no less true of independent
workers’ industrial collectives. Those imperatives, in turn, would carry in their
wake strong pressures to transform social-property relations, to reproduce the
class relation between capital and labour; and as the process of capitalist develop-
ment took its course, with mass dispossession and the general commodification
of labour power, there developed wholly new and even more inescapable imper-
atives of competition and capital accumulation.

REFERENCES
Aston, T.H. and C.H.E. Philpin, eds, 1985. The Brenner Debate: Agrarian Class Structure and
Economic Development in Pre-Industrial Europe. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Braudel, Fernand, 1986. The Identity of France: Volume Two: People and Production, trans.
Sian Reynolds. New York: Harper Collins.
Brenner, Robert P., 1985. ‘The Agrarian Roots of European Capitalism’. In The Brenner
Debate: Agrarian Class Structure and Economic Development in Pre-Industrial Europe, eds
T.H. Aston and C.H.E. Philpin, 213–327. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Brenner, Robert P., 1998. ‘The Economics of Global Turbulence’. New Left Review, 229
(May/June): 1–262.
Brenner, Robert P., 2001. ‘The Low Countries in the Transition to Capitalism’. Journal of
Agrarian Change, 1 (2): 169–241.
Coleman, D.C., 1977. The Economy of England, 1450–1750. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
The Question of Market Dependence 87

de Vries, Jan and A. van der Woude, 1997. The First Modern Economy: Success, Failure, and
Perseverance of the Dutch Economy, 1500–1815. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hilton, R.H., 1985. ‘A Crisis of Feudalism’. In The Brenner Debate: Agrarian Class Structure
and Economic Development in Pre-Industrial Europe, eds T.H. Aston and C.H.E. Philpin,
119–37. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kerridge, Eric, 1988. Trade and Banking in Early Modern England. Manchester: Manchester
University Press.
Marx, Karl, 1962. Capital. Volume 3. Moscow: Foreign Languages Publishing House.
Marx, Karl, 1973. Grundrisse. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Mastboom, Joyce, 1996. ‘Protoindustrialization and Agriculture in the Eastern Netherlands’.
Social Science History, 20 (2): 235–58.
Mastboom, Joyce, 2000. ‘On Their Own Terms: Peasant Households’ Response to Cap-
italist Development’. History of Political Thought, XXI (3): 391–403.
McKendrick, Neil, John Brewer and J.H. Plumb, 1983. The Birth of a Consumer Society:
the Commercialization of Eighteenth Century England. London: Hutchinson.
Schama, Simon, 1988. The Embarrassment of Riches: An Interpretation of Dutch Culture in the
Golden Age. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Thirsk, Joan, 1978. Economic Policy and Projects: The Development of a Consumer Society in
Early Modern England. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wolf, Eric R., 1966. Peasants. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Wood, Ellen Meiksins, 1999. ‘Horizontal Relations: A Note on Brenner’s Heresy’.
Historical Materialism, 4: 171–9.
Wood, Ellen Meiksins, 2002. The Origin of Capitalism: A Longer View. London: Verso.

You might also like