PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

This article was downloaded by: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles]
On: 14 March 2011
Access details: Access Details: [subscription number 911796916]
Publisher Routledge
Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-
41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK
Cultural Studies
Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:
http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t713684873
INVOKING AFFECT
Clare Hemmings
To cite this Article Hemmings, Clare(2005) 'INVOKING AFFECT', Cultural Studies, 19: 5, 548 — 567
To link to this Article: DOI: 10.1080/09502380500365473
URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09502380500365473
Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf
This article may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or
systematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or
distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden.
The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents
will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses
should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss,
actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly
or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material.
INVOKING AFFECT
Cultural theory and the ontological
turn
1|.· o.·..!. .»·...c¸o·.· ·|. .c»·.¬¡c.o., .¬..¸.».. c¡ o¡¡..· o· ...·..o! c/¡..· o»1
¡..·¡..·.·. ·|.co¸| «|..| ·c o»1..··o»1 ·|. ·c..o! «c.!1 o»1 co. ¡!o.. «.·|.» .·
i¬¡|o·.·.»¸ ·|. o».·¡..·.1, ·|. ·.»¸o!o. c. ·|. ¸o..|, c·.. ·|. ¸.»..o!!,
o¡¡!..o/!., ·|. ·o.» ·c o¡¡..· /o.!1· c» .¬¡c.·o»· «c.| .» .o!·o.o! ··o1..· c» ·|.
¡.·¡o!!· c¡ «..·.»¸ ·|. /c1, co· c¡ ·|.c., Mc.. .¬¡c.·o»·!, ¡c. ·|.· o.·..!., ·|.
.c»·.¬¡c.o., .»·...·· .» o¡¡..· .·.1.»..· o 1.··o·.·¡o.·.c» «.·| ¡c····.o.·o.o!.··
o¡¡.co.|.· ·c ¡c«.., ¡.o¬.1 o· |.¸.¬c».. .» ·|... ».¸o·.·.·, o»1 .»·.··.».. c¡
·c..o! ··.o.·o..· .o·|.. ·|o» .»·..¡..·c»o! ..!o·.c»·|.¡· o· ¡c.¬o·.·. c¡ ·|. ·o/¡..·
1|. o.·..!. ¡c.o·.· c» ·|. ....»· .c»·../o·.c»· c¡ i.o.» Mo··o¬. o»1 i·. xc·c¡·|,
:.1¸«..| .» ¡o.·..o!o., o»¡o.|.»¸ ·|... ..!./.o·.c» c¡ ·|. 1.¡¡...».. ·|o· o¡¡..·
¬o|.· 1|. oo·|c.’· ...·.¸o. c¡ ·|. o¡¡..·.·. ·o.» ¡c.o·.· c» /c·| ·|. .!!o·.c» c¡
.|c... ·|o· .· c¡¡..· ·|. .o!·o.o! ...·.., o»1 .·· ..«..·.»¸ c¡ ·|. ....»· |.··c., c¡
.o!·o.o! ·|.c., ·c ¡c·.·.c» o¡¡..· o· ‘·|. ».« .o··.»¸ .1¸.’ P|.!. o¡¡..· ¬o,
.c»··.·o·. o ·o!oo/!. ...·..o! ¡c.o· .» .c»·.··, .· ¡..¸o.»·!, .¬..¸.· ·|.co¸| o
....o!o. !c¸.. 1.·.¸».1 ·c ¡..·oo1. ‘¡o.o»c.1 ·|.c..···’ .»·c o ¬c.. ¡.c1o.·.·.
¡.o¬. c¡ ¬.»1 Á ¡c. «|c «co!1 »c· ¡..¡.. o¡¡..·.·. ¡...1c¬ ·c ·c..o! 1.·..¬.».·¬·
1.· .· ..¬o.»· o».!.o. «|o· .c!. o¡¡..· ¬o, |o·. c».. ·|.· .|.·c... |o· «c.|.1 .··
¡..·oo·.·. ¬o¸.. i» o11.·.c», o»1 ¬c.. «c..,.»¸!,, o¡¡..·.·. ..«..·.»¸ ¡!o··.»·
co· ¡c····.o.·o.o!.·· .»¸o.., /, .¸»c..»¸ ·|. .co»·..|.¸.¬c».. .c»·../o·.c»· c¡
¡c··.c!c».o! o»1 ¡.¬.».·· ·|.c..···, c»!, ·|.../, ¡c·.·.c».»¸ o¡¡..· o· ‘·|. o»·«..’
·c .c»·.¬¡c.o., ¡.c/!.¬· c¡ .o!·o.o! ·|.c.,
Keywords affect; cultural theory; epistemology; ontology; feminist
theory; postcolonial theory
There is no denying, or deferring, affects. They are what make up life,
and art . . . Affects are . . . the stuff that goes on beneath, beyond, even
parallel to signification. But what can one say about affects? Indeed, what
Clare Hemmings
Cultural Studies Vol. 19, No. 5 September 2005, pp. 548Á/567
ISSN 0950-2386 print/ISSN 1466-4348 online – 2005 Taylor & Francis
http://www.tandf.co.uk/journals DOI: 10.1080/09502380500365473
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1
needs to be said about them? . . . You cannot read affects, you can only
experience them.
(O’Sullivan 2001, p. 126)
Introduction
In the article from which the above quotation is taken, Simon O’Sullivan
celebrates affects’ capacity to defy deconstruction, and the deconstructionist.
O’Sullivan is writing within the context of art history, where which he claims
that semiotic and deconstructivist approaches have become hegemonic, but he
is far from alone in embracing affect as offering a new critical trajectory for
cultural theory. While not really a school as such, a significant number of
disciplinary and interdisciplinary theorists are currently citing affect as the
privileged ‘way out’ of the perceived impasse in cultural studies. The impasse
needing to be resolved is by now a familiar one, which the attentions of affect
theorists have reshaped into three predominant concerns.
Firstly, post deconstruction we doubt the capacity of constructivist models
of the subject to account fully for our place in the world as individuals or
groups. In a general sense, this concern is indicated by the intensity of current
critical interest in psychoanalytic accounts of the subject, and in particular
Judith Butler’s development of psychoanalysis through her focus on subjection
(1997a). Theorists of affect argue that constructivist models leave out the
residue or excess that is not socially produced, and that constitutes the very
fabric of our being. Thus Brian Massumi (1996) insists that affect is important
to the extent that it is autonomous and outside social signification, and John
Bruns (2000) suggests that affect, and in particular laughter, foregrounds the
unexpected that throws us off balance, that unsettles us into becoming
someone other than who we currently are. Secondly, post deconstruction we
doubt the capacity of both quantitative empirical approaches and textual
analysis to account for the fullest resonance of the social world we wish to
understand. Advocates of affect offer it up as a way of deepening our vision of
the terrain we are studying, of allowing for and prioritizing its ‘texture’, in
Eve Sedgwick’s words (2003, p. 17). This texture refers to our qualitative
experience of the social world, to embodied experience that has the capacity to
transform as well as exceed social subjection. Queer theorists in particular
have taken up Sedgwick and Adam Frank’s (1995) emphasis on the
transformative capacities of ·|o¬., insisting that it should not be something
we strive simply to overcome by turning to its dependent opposite, pride.
Shame itself, as David Halperin (2002), Sally Munt (2000) and Elspeth Probyn
(2000) have all argued, has a resonance well beyond its homophobic
generation, enabling queer subjects both to identify the bodily resonances of
I NVOKI NG AF F ECT 5 4 9
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1
a heterosexual status quo, and to create community through empathy and
shared experience. Thirdly, post deconstruction we doubt that the oppositions
of power/resistance or public/private can fully account for the political
process. In this context, affective ties have been theorized as offering an
alternative model of subject formation. In the work of Adriana Cavarero
(2000), for example, how those we are closest to view us is central to our self-
narration and therefore our way of being in the world. And Michael Hardt
(1999) argues that while affective labour is the hidden centre of capitalist
accumulation, since it remains unremunerated yet is what bestows qualitative
value, it also produces emotional connections that threaten to disrupt that
accumulation. In a similar vein, and following Franz Fanon’s (1952) insistence
that social relations at both the macro and the micro level are based on
o»..o·c»o/!. ties, critical race theorists argue that affect plays a role in both
cementing sexed and raced relations of domination, and in providing the local
investments necessary to counter those relations (e.g. Spivak 1993, Bhabha
1994, Hill Collins 2000).
1
The approaches I have mentioned share an interest in exploring o»o!c¸o.
rather than 1.¸.·o! modes of power and community, which is to say connected
and relational over oppositional modes. They emphasize the unexpected, the
singular, or indeed the quirky, over the generally applicable, where the latter
becomes associated with the pessimism of social determinist perspectives, and
the former with the hope of freedom from social constraint. In making this
move, affect theorists build on the important work within feminist theory and
Sociology on the pitfalls of writing the body out of theory (e.g. Shilling 1993,
Grosz 1994), and offer a different world-view than the rather narrow one
governed by a repressive/subversive dichotomy. The affective critique is not
simply one that highlights omission, however, or one that simply stresses the
devaluing of certain practices and experiences in general paradigms. For affect
theorists, these exclusions matter because of their capacity to transform the
world we live in, and contemporary critical theorists should ignore them at
their peril.
While appreciative of a critical focus on the unusual, which is to say the
non-socially-determined, not as a bid for group rights, but a bid for social
transformation, I remain sceptical of what is often a theoretical celebration of
affect as uniquely situated to achieve this end. This article explores my
scepticism of such affective celebration through close engagement with
Sedgwick’s (2003) and Massumi’s (2002) work on the subject. Both authors
are well-respected contributors to contemporary cultural theory, and both
have recently published monographs invoking affect as ·|. «o, ¡c.«o.1 within
that arena. For both authors it is affect’s difference from social structures that
means it possesses, in itself, the capacity to restructure social meaning. But
both authors are thereby presented with something of a problem. As
prominent cultural theorists, they cannot fail to be aware of the myriad
5 5 0 CULTURAL STUDI ES
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1
ways that affect manifests precisely not as difference, but as a central
mechanism of social reproduction in the most glaring ways. The delights of
consumerism, feelings of belonging attending fundamentalism or fascism, to
suggest just several contexts, are affective responses that strengthen rather than
challenge a dominant social order (Berlant 1997). Sedgwick and Massumi do
both acknowledge this characteristic of affect in their work, but do not pursue
it, interested instead as they both are in that ‘other affect’, the good affect that
undoes the bad. It is difficult to maintain such an affective dichotomy of
course, particularly in light of their own professed irritation with cultural
theorists’ tendency to divide the world up into good and bad, repressive or
subversive and so on, as I discuss in more detail below. But unfortunately
neither author offers any explanation as to the relationship between these ‘two
kinds’ of affect, which means the relationship remains dyadic.
Instead, both authors negotiate a way out of their own uncomfortable
critical position by turning the question of affective freedom back onto the
cultural critic, leaving it up to her or him to decide whether the direction they
wish to pursue is one of the pessimism of social determinism (including bad
affect) or the optimism of affective freedom (good affect). Two points come to
mind at this point. Firstly, this question to the critic is hardly an open one.
‘Wouldn’t you rather be free?’ can hardly elicit a negative response in anyone
but the most hardened cultural theorist, whose hardness is indeed evidenced
by that response. Secondly, as part of persuading the critic that the question is
a valid one, both the ills of cultural theory to date and the restorative power of
affect need to be overstated. My overarching contention in this article, then, is
that while affect may be an interesting and valuable critical focus .» .c»·.·· , it
often emerges as a rhetorical device whose ultimate goal is to persuade
‘paranoid theorists’ into a more productive frame of mind.
Affective territories
I began research for this article as a result of my frustration at seeing affect
mentioned or celebrated but rarely fully explained as either critical tool or
object. So I want to spend some time discussing what is actually meant by
affect. Affect broadly refers to states of being, rather than to their
manifestation or interpretation as emotions. For psychoanalysis affects are
‘the qualitative expression of our drives’ energy and variations’ (Giardini 1999,
p. 150), are what enable drives to be satisfied and what tie us to the world.
Unlike drives, affects can be transferred to a range of objects in order to be
satisfied (love may have many objects, for example), which makes them
adaptable in a way that drives are not. So, affect can enable the satisfaction of a
drive (excitement might prepare the body for the satisfaction of hunger) or
interrupt it (so that disgust might interrupt that satisfaction if you were served
I NVOKI NG AF F ECT 5 5 1
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1
a rotten egg to eat). Discontented by the way affects had been theorized only
in respect to drives, the influential psychologist Silvan Tomkins (1963) was the
first to suggest that they have a singularity that creates its own circuitry. Thus
affects may be autotelic (love being its own reward), or insatiable (where
jealousy or desire for revenge may last minutes or a lifetime). Tomkins’ work
suggests that affects have a complex, self-referential life that gives depth to
human existence through our relations with others and with ourselves.
In terms of our relations with others, Tomkins asked us to think of the
contagious nature of a yawn, smile or blush. It is transferred to others and
doubles back, increasing its original intensity. Affect can thus be said to place
the individual in a ....o.· of feeling and response, rather than opposition to
others. Further, Tomkins argues that we all develop complex o¡¡..· ·|.c...· as a
way of negotiating the social world as unique individuals. An affect theory is all
of our affective experiences to date that are remembered (or better, perhaps,
registered) in the moment of responding to a new situation, such that we keep
‘a trace, within [our] constitution’ of those experiences (Al-Saji 2000, p. 56).
For Tomkins, then, affect connects us to others, and provides the individual
with a way of narrating their own inner life (likes, dislikes, desires and
revulsions) to themselves and others. Thus one of the main reasons affect has
been taken up as the hopeful alternative to social determinism is its positioning
of the individual as possessing a degree of control over their future, rather than
as raw material responding rather passively to cognitive or learned phenomena.
Tomkins is joined by Gilles Deleuze to form an unlikely couple dominating
the contemporary affective imaginary of cultural theory. Deleuze (1997)
proposes affect as distinct from emotion, as bodily meaning that pierces social
interpretation, confounding its logic, and scrambling its expectations. In
contrast to Tomkins, who breaks down affect into a topography of myriad,
distinct parts, Deleuze understands affect as describing the passage from one
state to another, as an .»·.»·.·, characterized by an increase or decrease in
power (1997, p. 181). Deleuze takes two examples from his reading of T. E.
Lawrence’s experiences in the desert to illustrate the body’s capacity to
interrupt social logic. In both examples, he paraphrases Lawrence’s description
of violent events in the desert. The first is the grisly spectacle of ‘the gestures
of the dying, that attempt at raising their hands that makes all the agonizing
Turks ripple together, as if they had practiced the same theatrical gesture,
provoking Lawrence’s mad laughter’ (1997, p. 123). The second is Deleuze’s
account of Lawrence’s experience of being gang raped: ‘in the midst of his
tortures, an erection; even in the state of sludge, there are convulsions that jolt
the body’ (1997: 123). For Deleuze, both instances index the unpredictable
autonomy of the body’s encounter with the event, its shattering ability to go its
own way. In Deleuze’s account, Lawrence does experience shame, but not in
alignment with social prohibition, rather as a judgement on his body’s response
to rape: it is his erection that gives rise to shame. For Deleuze, one cannot do
5 5 2 CULTURAL STUDI ES
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1
justice to Lawrence’s unruly body by reducing it to its social organization. To
do so would be to miss the dramatic significance of the body’s own asocial
trace. Instead, Deleuze proposes a cartographic approach to the body and its
affects where the critical focus is on bodily displacement, the movement
between bodily states that is its intensity (1997, p. 63), its refrain. For many
theorists of affect Deleuze’s approach provides insight into thinking through
the body in a non-essentialist way that remains faithful to many different levels
and modes of bodily experience (e.g. Spinks 2001). As inheritors of this
affective legacy, contemporary critical theorists tend to prefer either Tomkins’
pragmatism or Deleuze’s imaginative flights.
Eve Sedgwick’s new work takes up Tomkins’ suggestion that a focus on
affect sidesteps a myopic attention to structural prohibition. While Tomkins is
concerned with differentiating affect from drives, however, Sedgwick is
interested in using affect theory to challenge what Probyn calls ‘the twinned
problematics of discipline or transgression’ (2000, p. 13), which anchor
poststructuralist critical inquiry. Sedgwick believes that the central problem
facing Theory today is its own critical paranoia, where the project of a
poststructuralist critical imaginary has become reduced to the search for, and
deadening (re)discovery of, prohibition everywhere: prohibition where it
appeared there was freedom, prohibition in a space we had not, until now,
thought to look. Sedgwick argues that such paranoia makes cultural
investigation protectionist instead of expansive, as theorists ward off other
critical imaginaries as duped unless they too come to the same conspiratorial
conclusions, unless they too find violence where there had appeared to be
possibility (2003, pp. 123Á/51). For Sedgwick such a ‘hermeneutics of
suspicion and exposure’ that is at once smug and sour, is not merely an
unattractive trait in a critical theorist, it also makes her or him ill equipped for
analysing contemporary social formations ‘in which visibility itself constitutes
much of the violence’ (2003, p. 140). In current global contexts where
violence is anything but hidden, is disconcertingly proud rather than covert,
Sedgwick asks ‘what use is paranoid theory?’ Part of what makes critical theory
so uninventive for Sedgwick is its privileging of the epistemological, since a
relentless attention to the structures of truth and knowledge obscures our
experience of those structures. She advocates instead a reparative return to the
ontological and intersubjective, to the surprising and enlivening texture of
individuality and community (2003, p. 17). Again following Tomkins,
Sedgwick rather provocatively invites us to consider affect as the key to that
texture, because of its capacity to link us creatively to others. I say
provocatively, because throughout her text, Sedgwick acknowledges that our
learned instinct as cultural theorists is to reject Tomkins for his insistence on
affect as innate. Indeed, this is precisely Sedgwick’s challenge Á/ do cultural
theorists shy away from affect o !o Tomkins for any other reasons than its
essentialism? For Sedgwick, if the answer is ‘no’, as she assumes it is, the
I NVOKI NG AF F ECT 5 5 3
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1
rejection of Tomkins’ model is itself evidence of paranoid cultural theorists’
characteristic disposal of both baby and bathwater.
Brian Massumi similarly intervenes in the contemporary terrain of cultural
theory to propose affect as a new way out of the pernicious reign of
signification that dominates the field. Mirroring Sedgwick, Massumi’s irritation
is chiefly reserved for the cultural theorist whose ability for ‘critical thinking’
has become reduced to identifying points on a stable map of the always already
known (Massumi 2002, p. 12). Interpretation through the overlaying of this
map can only capture certain moments and certain experiences, which will
invariably reflect the framework they are interpreted through. For Massumi,
such critical impoverishment means that cultural theorists consistently miss
both the matter of bodies and, since his framework is Deleuzian rather than
Tomkinsian, the unceasing movement that constitutes the process of
becoming. And without this investment in movement between states and
bodies, Massumi asks, how do we account for let alone encourage, change
(2002, p. 3)? Affect attracts Massumi, then, since it is part of a different order
of experience to the epistemological (as defined by Sedgwick): it is ‘the
unassimilable’ (2002, p. 3). His point is that in order to study the unknowable,
cultural theorists will have to abandon the certainty that has come to
characterize the field.
What is clear then, is that Sedgwick and Massumi emerge as champions of
affect in a more general context of the critique of what is usually understood as
the ‘cultural turn’. The particular form of these arguments is often discipline-
specific, but what all critiques share is a lamenting of the turn to language
represented by poststructuralism. Within the context I am most familiar with,
of feminist debate, this turn to language is usually critiqued for one of two
reasons that are somewhat at odds with one another. The first laments the
increasing theoretical abstraction of feminist writing, associating it with an
increase in professionalization and a concomitant decrease in political
accountability (Gubar 1998, Stanley and Wise 2000, Jackson 2001).
Poststructuralist feminist writing is often aggressively damned for its
inaccessibility, and for its perceived lack of attention to what is often invoked
as ‘the material’. These arguments have been raging within feminist academic
and political contexts for a long time, but cross over into more mainstream
critical terrain through the debates between Judith Butler and Nancy Fraser in
the late 1990s (Butler 1997b, Fraser 1997). In the second critique of the
‘cultural turn’ within feminism, poststructuralism is understood in contrast to
have c·...¬¡|o·...1 power-relations and their framing of both what we do and
who we are, to the extent that there appears to be no hope of liberation. We
are effectively caught in culture. Critics viewing poststructuralism in this way
advocate not a material return but an ontological one, a revaluing of individual
difference and capacity for change over time (Prosser 1998, Mitchell 2000). A
number of theorists Á/ most notably, perhaps, Rosi Braidotti (2002) Á/
5 5 4 CULTURAL STUDI ES
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1
combine these two critiques in their focus on the lived materiality of bodies.
Sedgwick and Massumi’s interest in affect must therefore be seen within the
context of broader challenges to poststructuralist approaches to language,
power and subjectivity, and particularly in line with the second trajectory
detailed here.
Critical chronologies
The critical narrative laid out above is not simply an abstract one; it takes
material form in academic and institutional contexts. In my own institutional
context, where I teach graduate students gender studies, the narrative is
precisely borne out. Each year it seems students grapple with poststructuralist
approaches only to return to the question of how this turn to language is
political. As with both critiques presented above, students identify the political
in an empirically available real world or in the body. Instead of deconstruction,
students are finding themselves drawn to social policy, development theory
and practice, or to psychoanalytic or affective approaches that reframe
questions of sexual and racial difference. What is of interest here, however,
and challenges a simple acceptance of this critical narrative, is that too
frequently such material or ontological judgement is made on the basis of
secondary reading Á/ that rejects poststructuralism as entirely rarefied and
apolitical Á/ not primary reading. This is of course a familiar pattern. As a
masters student in women’s studies in the early 1990s my secondary reading
convinced me of the essentialist ills of early second wave Western feminist
texts, most of which I did not read until much later. That lack of direct textual
engagement did not stop me writing damning critiques of an ‘earlier
generation’ of feminists, however, and nor did it stop that work being
published, because this view was a generally held one. Opinion of what
became crudely termed 1970s feminism has begun to shift, in part because of
an insistence that a decade of proliferating feminist texts and political action
cannot be represented by the handful of theorists most commonly cited as
essentialist (Stacey 1997, Graham .· o! . 2002). But my argument here is not
that these ‘earlier generation’ are beyond critique, or innocent of essentialism
or abstraction in turn, but that a narrative that posits a contemporary critical
break with their characteristics has a vested interest in reading for generality
instead of complexity. In my own, and my students’ cases, such narratives
mitigate against careful critical reading, tend to the dismissive, and celebrate
‘the new’ as untouched by whatever we find ourselves currently transcending.
In the search for ‘the new’ that bears no resemblance to the past, the
identifying features of that past are inevitably overstated, and the claims for
that new embellished in ways that must at the very least fall short of rigorous.
I NVOKI NG AF F ECT 5 5 5
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1
In positing affect as the critical new for the noughts, both Sedgwick and
Massumi invariably overstate the problems of poststructuralism, as well as and
in order to herald affect’s unique capacity to resolve contemporary critical
dilemmas, much as advocates of poststructuralism overstated the ills of the
seventies and early eighties. In 1co.|.»¸ t..!.»¸, the weight of Sedgwick’s
dismissal of poststructuralist epistemology is carried by her reading of only two
texts: Judith Butler’s c.»1.. 1.co/!. and D. A. Miller’s 1|. :c·.! o»1 ·|. tc!....
Published in 1990 and 1988 respectively, despite the fact that both arguments
are ones that their authors have subsequently developed in different directions.
It seems odd to rest the case for needing new theoretical frameworks on texts
that have already prompted just such revisions from their authors, and indeed
that are either side of fifteen years old. Surely if the need for affect is so
urgently felt, the problem could be found in more contemporary texts?
Massumi’s dismissal of cultural theory rests on more slender evidence still. At
no point in to.o/!.· tc. ·|. ¡..·oo! does Massumi engage directly with any of the
theorists responsible for what he insists is theory’s terrible state of critical
affairs, although the scattered but persistent references to ‘performance’ could
be taken as similarly implicating Butler. Instead of critical dialogue, Massumi
persuades his reader of the need for restorative attention to affect by
positioning him or her as a co-conspirator who already knows what the
problems of cultural theory are but just needs a little coaxing. Rather than
tracing the thinking of particular authors, Massumi objectifies critical thinking,
referring to it in the third person throughout. The following passage is typical:
Critical thinking disavows its own inventiveness as much as possible.
Because it sees itself as uncovering something it desires to subtract
from the world, it clings to a basically descriptive and justificatory
modus operandi. However strenuously it might debunk concepts like
‘representation,’ it carries on as if it mirrored something outside of itself
and with which it had no complicity, no unmediated processual
involvement, and thus could justifiably oppose.
(2002, p. 12)
‘Critical thinking’ is unreflexive, childish, stubborn, arrogant and, as
suggested, unauthored. Presumably, the reader can be expected to want to
be an adult, for who among us would want to ‘cling to a . . . descriptive . . .
modus operandi’, let alone ‘disavow[. . . our] own inventiveness’. Our
rejection of such juvenile attachment to the theoretical status quo is in the
end all just part of growing up. As the wise father, Massumi counsels that this
has ‘nothing to do with morals or moralizing. [It is] just pragmatic’ (2002, p.
13). In both Sedgwick and Massumi, I want to stress that these citation issues
are more than simply omission. They construct a critical history at the same
time as they dismiss it. Positing affect as a ‘way out’ ..¸o...· that
5 5 6 CULTURAL STUDI ES
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1
poststructuralist epistemology have ignored embodiment, investment and
emotion, and that the academic reader recognize their own prior complicity
and current boredom with Theory’s straight-jacketing of thought.
If poststructuralist epistemology is the problem, it is perhaps not
enormously surprising that a post-deconstructivist ontology is offered as the
solution. Both Sedgwick and Massumi progress from asserting the absolutely
flawed nature of epistemology to insisting on the unequivocal good of
ontology. For Sedgwick, it is self-evidently horrific that critical thought is
dominated by epistemological approaches that consider ‘the quality of affect
. . . of [no] more consequence than the color of the airplane used to speed a
person to a destination’ (2003, p. 18). This horror underwrites her conviction
that only a turn to ontology can redress the over-emphasis of truth and
knowledge at the expense of individual experience. In Massumi, signification is
(passive) death, and ontology is (active) life. Even where theorists stress
multiplicity of social location, for Massumi (2002, p. 3) this continues to fix
difference: ‘The sites, it is true, are multiple. But aren’t they still
combinatorial permutations on an overarching definitional framework?’ While
all social meaning is already fully known, already ‘[nothing] more than a local
embodiment c¡ ideology’ (2002, p. 3), ontology on the other hand heroically
carries the very difference that ideology, and cultural theory, would minimize
or ignore (2002, p. 5). The epistemological past is grey, flat and predictable,
the ontological future is bright, many-faceted and surprising. That future could
be ours too (again, who would not want it to be?), if . . . and only if . . . we
break free of our paranoid attachment to unfreedom and turn towards the
possibilities offered by feeling. It may seem perverse to resist, but as with the
issues of citation discussed above, the ‘problem of epistemology’ only
materializes in the moment that it is chronologically and intellectually
separated from ontology. Ontology thus resolves the problem its advocates
invent.
Both authors’ chronologies of the past and future of critical theory need to
ignore the range of poststructuralist work that does not follow this pattern;
epistemological work that is neither poststructuralist, nor opposed to
consideration of ontology. As neither theorist can afford to acknowledge,
there is a vast range of epistemological work that attends to emotional
investments, political connectivity and the possibility of change. To briefly
trace one example, feminist standpoint epistemology might be said to
constitute an established body of inquiry into the relationship /.·«..» the
ontological, epistemological and transformative. Feminist standpoint is a useful
example in considering the turn to affect because its genealogical resonances
echo back and forth across the last few decades, countering an affective
chronology whose advocates prioritize grand shifts in ways that promote rather
than caution against generalization. In standpoint, epistemology and ontology
are never separated and opposed, and its key proponents range across Marxist
I NVOKI NG AF F ECT 5 5 7
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1
feminism, critical race theory, sexual difference theory, as well as
poststructuralism (Harding 1986, Haraway 1991, Braidotti 1994, Hartsock
1999, Hill Collins 2000). In addition, all feminist standpoint work, while
enormously divergent, does share the following: firstly, a commitment to
political accountability, community and the importance of positive affect for
both belonging and change. Secondly, against paranoia, all the feminist
standpoint work I can think of posits a different, historical and community
validated standard of evidence for the knowledges that it wishes to produce.
Or, to take a different tack, postcolonial theorists, among others, have
attended to the ways that marginal social location is not simply ‘precoded into
the ideological master structure’ as Massumi (2002, p. 3) suggests. Such
theorists have argued that to be marginal in relation to the dominant is to
inhabit o¬/.·o!.».. , not simply additive or oppositional multiplicity (Fanon
1952, Said 1979, Bhabha 1994, Kandyoti 1994, Spivak 1999). To be ‘other’ is
not only to be the object of another’s gaze within the dominant; it also
precipitates community that is historically resonant, that draws on and creates
alternative signification of the same actions and events. Thus, social difference
is not only opposite, but knowing and inflecting, and the social world is always
crosscut with fissures that have a social and political history that ·.¸».¡..·
c·|..«.·. .
When I first read both Massumi and Sedgwick on affect, I was genuinely
confused. Both theorists are of course familiar with the kind of work on
epistemology or signification that does not reduce experience to a place on a
grid of immutable power relations. Sedgwick herself paradigmatically
complicated questions of knowledge and the subject formed by its perverse
logics in i¡.··.¬c!c¸, c¡ ·|. c!c·.· (1990) and refused to reduce what one could
call queer standpoint to a fixed position on a homophobic map. But in fact this
failure to attend to the fault lines in a chronology charting cultural theory’s
progressive myopia is ..»·.o! to the positioning of affect as panacea for
Theory’s hypochondria. Such broad oversights and lack of citational evidence,
if not deliberate, are a least necessary to both authors’ critical location in their
work on affect. Only through these ‘oversights’ can non-paranoid theory
belong to the future rather than to the present and past. A reader could well
respond that some oversight and generalization is inevitable in the develop-
ment of new critical trajectories, and that if Massumi and Sedgwick are wrong
in some respects, they are also right in others. But what is overlooked in this
particular authorship of history is instructive. It is consistently theory written
from the margins (I just mentioned standpoint and postcolonial theory here)
that refuses both dominant prescription and simple oppositional location, and
values continuity of difference over time. To refuse to cite in order to dismiss,
it is politically invested perspectives of difference, rather than abstract
epistemologists who disappear from the critical record. I would argue then that
affect theorists’ error lies in the evacuation of this theoretical and political
5 5 8 CULTURAL STUDI ES
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1
complexity from critical theory’s development; but this ‘error’ is precisely
what allows complexity to be hijacked for recuperation in the future.
Affective freedoms
As contemporary cultural theorists, both Sedgwick and Massumi know that
they cannot simply propose a return to ontological ...·o.»·, in order to
alleviate the epistemological myopia they identify. For the critical chronology I
have been indicating to remain intact, affect must be both post biological
essentialism and post-epistemology. In this vein, Sedgwick and Massumi use
the notion of affect as free and autonomous respectively, to persuade cultural
theorists of the value of the untrammeled ontological. Sedgwick’s ‘reparative
return’ to the singularity of the ontological hinges on her argument that affect
is free from the constraints of both drives and social meaning. Following
Tomkins, Sedgwick (2003, p. 19) asserts that ‘affects can be, and are, attached
to things, people, ideas, sensations, relations, activities, ambitions, institu-
tions, and any number of other things, including other affects. Thus one can be
excited by anger, disgusted by shame, or surprised by joy’. On the one hand,
then, attention to affect will always be attention to everyday experience rather
than macro abstractions, and even more importantly for Sedgwick, affective
attachments will be o»¡..1..·o/!. . Since affect is a ‘free radical’ that can attach
itself to anything, and since we create associations between feelings and
contexts that are unpredictable, ‘anyone’s character . . . is . . . a record of the
highly individual histories by which . . . fleeting emotion . . . has instituted far
more durable, structured changes’ (2003, p. 62) in the self and in
relationships. Sedgwick’s conclusion is that to collect these records would
be a cure of sorts for critical paranoia, creating both a different archive of
experience as well as a different theoretical paradigm. This freedom of affect
combines with its contagious nature, resulting in what Sedgwick understands as
its capacity to transform the self in relation to others.
It is certainly true that affect attaches all over the place. As Sedgwick
suggests, it is hard to think of an arena of life that is not suffused with affect.
However, there is a slippage here, too. Affect’s freedom of attachment, its
ability to attach to any object, becomes evidence, for Sedgwick, of co. critical
freedom, should we but attend to its unfolding drama. For affective freedom
to equal critical freedom Sedgwick must insist that affect attaches .o»1c¬!, to
any object, despite the fact that even for her guide, Silvan Tomkins, affective
attachment frequently serves to satisfy drives or social norms. Sedgwick’s
argument (2002, p. 19) is that because affect can be surprising in its
attachments, as cultural theorists we have a duty to attend to the patterns and
effects of such surprise, rather than to the social frameworks that we already
know. The critique of Sedgwick’s insistence here takes two directions: firstly,
I NVOKI NG AF F ECT 5 5 9
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1
what might still be gained by a (healthy?) critical paranoia in tracing affect; and
secondly, which critics are able to turn their location into such celebratory
responsibility?
Let us pursue the example of disgustÁ/shame that Sedgwick takes as
exemplary of affective freedom. It attaches itself to many different objects, and
can arise unexpectedly in relation to an object previously favoured. Yet, it is
clear that there are certain things that unquestionably authenticate disgust as
response in human beings in the first place. In a scene from 1|. :.¸o·.·. +¡¡..·· ,
Tomkins suggests that we learn disgust as a primary negative affect when a
parent smells our faeces and reacts with the affect disgust Á/contempt:
It may be that the anal character, whose primary affect is disgust, is an
anal character because humans are innately disgusted by the odor of their
feces. If the human feces were not innately disgusting, however, it would
still be relatively easy to teach the child to be disgusted by his own feces,
by identification with the parent who lifted his lip and drew his head away
from the child’s feces.
(1963, p. 132)
Tomkins continues the story: the child realizes that it is |.¬ that the parent is
disgusted with and through identification with the parent, he becomes ashamed
of himself. So the child finds other objects to be disgusted of, the better to
reduce the likelihood of shame doubling back on him. But the possibility of shit
not being recoiled from if it were not innately disgusting, is only imagined
momentarily in this passage to be summarily dismissed by the insistence that ‘it
would still be relatively easy’ to teach this disgust anyway. Disgust at shit is
thus either innate or inevitable Á/ its randomness resides only in which object
its displacement will settle on. The scene is profoundly homosocial in that it is
the father’s recoil from the son here (all Tomkins’ children are little ‘heroes’)
that forms the pedagogic site. A father teaches his son by example that his
inevitable recoil from shit is natural Indeed Tomkins’ book of negative affect
is bursting with children whose affective responses are bound by the early
contexts in which they learn the codes and practices of gender and sexuality. In
Tomkins’ shame-filled world, boys are instructed specifically not to cry like
girls, mumble, gesticulate when speaking, demonstrate enthusiasm in public or
eat like birds; in ways that suggest that no matter how expansive our capacity
to substitute objects of disgust at a later date, the primary affect these refer to
is either learned Á/ or if innate, reinforced Á/ in heteronormative scenes
(Berlant 1997). My point here is not that Sedgwick misses the heteronormative
regulation of affect, but that her awareness of this inattention is central to
how her affective logic functions. This logic is governed by three phrases: a.
o¡ .co.·. ·|o¬. .o» /. »c.¬o·.·., /o· .· .o» o!·c /. ·.o»·¡c.¬o·.·.; b. :|co!1»’· «.
o··.»1 ·c ·|c·. ·.o»·¡c.¬o·.·. ¡c··./.!.·..· c·.. o»1 o/c·. »c.¬o·.·. c».·· c. i· .·
5 6 0 CULTURAL STUDI ES
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1
·.¬¡!, .|o.!.·| ·c ¬o|. o ¡o·· This grammar only works because of our
prior knowledge of Sedgwick’s work in a central rather than passing way Á/ we
can trust that Sedgwick of all theorists has already factored power into
the equation. Thus in our own expectations, as in the critical chronology
discussed in the previous section, power belongs to the past, to the
already dealt with, allowing the future to emerge as the epoch of individual
difference.
Against this teleology of old power versus new freedom of choice I want to
continue by suggesting that only for certain subjects can affect be thought of as
attaching in an open way; others are so over-associated with affect that they
themselves are the object of affective transfer. In this vein, Jennifer Biddle
(1997, p. 231) insists that in matters of sexuality it is the woman who carries
the shame of gendered impropriety, and marks its limits: ‘It is, after all, the
prostitute who is shameless, but the gentleman, let us not forget, who is
discreet’. Such transferred affective attachments do not only pertain to gender
and sexuality, but also suffuse critical accounts of the process of affective
racialization. I am thinking here of Franz Fanon and Audre Lorde’s often cited
descriptions of c·|.. ¡.c¡!.’· affective response to their blackness. Fanon
remembers:
My body was given to me sprawled out, distorted, recoloured, clad in
mourning in that white winter day. The Negro is an animal, the Negro is
bad, the Negro is mean, the Negro is ugly; look, a nigger, it’s cold, the
nigger is shivering, the nigger is shivering because he is cold, the little boy
is trembling because he is afraid of the nigger, the nigger is shivering with
cold, that cold that goes through your bones, the handsome little boy is
trembling because he thinks that the nigger is quivering with rage, the
little white boy throws himself into his mother’s arms: Mama, the
nigger’s going to eat me up.
(1952, p. 80)
While the white boy’s fear, learned within a racist familial and social order,
can attach to an unknown black object, Fanon’s body is precisely not his own,
but is ‘sprawled out’ and ‘distorted’, presented to him via the white boy’s
affective response. Lorde similarly recalls her realization that it is |.. /c1, that
is disgusting to a white woman sitting next to her on the bus:
When I look up the woman is still staring at me, her nose holes and eyes
huge. And suddenly I realise that there is nothing crawling up the seat
between us; it is me she doesn’t want her coat to touch. The fur brushes
past my face as she stands with a shudder and holds on to a strap in the
speeding train . . . Something’s going on here I do not understand, but I
will never forget it. Her eyes. The flared nostrils. The hate.
(1984, pp. 147Á/8)
I NVOKI NG AF F ECT 5 6 1
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1
In discussing the same passage, Sara Ahmed argues that affect thus places
bodies in spatial relation along racially defined lines (2000, p. 85Á/6). In both
of these examples, it is the black body that carries the weight of, and is
suffused with, racial affect, as it is the female body that carries the burden of
the affects that maintain sexual difference in Biddle’s example above.
Biddle, Fanon and Lorde’s narratives testify to the argument that some
bodies are captured and held by affect’s structured precision. Not only, then,
is affect itself not random, nor is the ability to choose to imagine affect
otherwise. My concerns about the centring of the critic in affective discourse
come full circle. In the first instance, the need for a new theory of the
ontological requires displacing marginal theory and histories from a chronology
of cultural theory. Furthermore, the cultural critic has to evidence their desire
to move away from that imagined chronology by choosing choice. Yet, as I
have suggested, the autonomy of the critic to make such a choice is dependent
upon their being the subject rather than object of affective displacement. The
failure of some critics to ‘choose choice’ paradoxically becomes evidence of
their concomitant failure to relinquish an imagined history that they may
already have been erased from.
Affective autonomy
Placing affective attachment in the context of social narratives and power
relations as I have done above similarly runs counter to Massumi’s claim that
affect is critically useful because of its autonomy. For Massumi, the moment
that we ‘make sense’ of a state of being, or more properly becoming, we
freeze it, evacuating it of the very intensity that offered the capacity for
change. Thus:
Affect is autonomous to the degree to which it escapes confinement in the
particular body whose vitality, or potential for interaction, it is. Formed,
qualified, situated perceptions and cognitions fulfilling functions of actual
connection or blockage, are the capture and closure of affect. Emotion is
the intensest (most contracted) expression of that capture-and of the fact
that something has always and again escaped.
(1996, p. 228)
As for Sedgwick, then, affect is interesting insofar as it resists or runs counter
to the causal linearity through which we make sense of the world. Yet, where
for Sedgwick affective freedom of attachment becomes a mark of the critic’s
freedom, for Massumi the affective autonomy places it outside the reach of
critical interpretation. Affect is thus valuable to the extent that it is not
susceptible to the vagaries of theoretical whim. In Simon O’Sullivan’s words
5 6 2 CULTURAL STUDI ES
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1
that I began this article with, ‘you cannot read affects, you can only experience
them’ (2001, p. 126).
Massumi’s invocation to cultural critics to open themselves up to
something that cannot be read may strike us as odd. While many will concur
with Massumi’s scepticism of quantitative research in its inability to attend to
the particular, we are left with a riddle-like description of affect as something
scientists can detect the loss of (in the anomaly), social scientists and cultural
critics cannot interpret, but philosophers can imagine (2002, p. 17). How then
can we engage affect in light of the critical projects we are engaged in, or are
we to abandon the social sciences entirely? In fact, both Massumi and Sedgwick
are advocating a new academic attitude rather than a new method, an attitude
or faith in something other than the social and cultural, a faith in the wonders
that might emerge if we were not so attached to pragmatic negativity. Massumi
is thus suggesting not that we !cc| ¡c. something outside culture, but that we
·.o·· ·|o· there is something outside culture. This is a useful proposition only if
one’s academic project is to herald the death of the cultural turn, and a return
to the rigour of disciplinarity Á/ the visionary sciences, imaginative philosophy,
but precisely not the miserable social sciences or defeatist cultural studies.
Much seems to rest on Massumi’s understanding of affect as autonomous.
As befits his participation in a critical chronology departing from biological
essentialism in the first instance, Massumi is careful to note that affect ‘.».!o1.·
social elements, but mixes them with elements according to different logic’
(1996, p. 223), taking them up as unfinished ‘·.»1.»...· . . . pastnesses opening
onto a future, but with no present to speak of’ (1996, p. 224). In making this
claim for affect Á/ its movement between past and future, never fixed in the
present Á/ Massumi is extending Deleuze’s chronology of body and mind in
i··o,· c..·..o! o»1 c!.»..o! . Following his description of Lawrence’s unexpected
bodily response to being raped mentioned earlier, Deleuze suggests that we
might therefore conceptualize the relationship between body and mind as
follows:
The mind begins by coldly and curiously regarding what the body does, it
is first of all a witness; then it is affected, it becomes an impassioned
witness, that is, it experiences for itself affects that are not simply effects
of the body, but veritable ...·..o! .»·.·..· that hover over the body and
judge it.
(1997, p. 124)
Body and mind are thus linked but detached, potentially developing in
different directions, differently affected. But the mind is the witness to the
body, thus needing the body, while the reverse is not the case, and it is in that
sense that the body and the affects that it distributes are ‘asocial, but not
presocial’ for Massumi (1996, p. 223).
I NVOKI NG AF F ECT 5 6 3
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1
To conclude this essay on a slightly different note, I want to develop
Deleuze’s description of the relationship between body and mind here, to
argue that extrapolating from its logic that affect is autonomous, as Massumi
does, is a misreading. Deleuze is not critiquing linearity per se, but what we
understand as the components of linearity. If judgement is always secondary to
bodily response, poised above it, but crucially tied to it, the intensity of that
response must also presumably be curtailed or extended by that judgement,
forming an affective cycle in which each element has the capacity to affect
(intensify or diminish) the other. Deleuze has offered us a snapshot of frozen
time, a single moment of judgement, but this is a moment only, and one that
does in fact take place within a larger passage of time. Judgement links the
body and the social and gives both interpretative meaning. The ‘maps of
intensity’ that Deleuze would have us draw up in our desire to understand the
individual are the shifts from one component to the next, one affective cycle to
the next (1997, p. 64). Thus, ‘maps of intensity’ are maps of individual life
and meaning .» ·.¬., perhaps even constituting time. They are certainly not
outside time. To pursue this interpretation of Deleuze further, these affective
cycles form ¡o··..»· that are subject to reflective or political, rather than
momentary or arbitrary judgement. Such affective cycles might be described
not as a series of repeated moments Á/ bodyÁ/affect Á/emotion Á/ a self-
contained phrase repeated in time, but as an ongoing, incrementally altering
chain Á/ bodyÁ/affect Á/emotionÁ/affect Á/body Á/ doubling back upon the body
and influencing the individual’s capacity to act in the world. In this context,
reflective or political judgment provides an alternative to dominant social
norms, but not because of affective autonomy. This reading indicates a return
to Tomkins’ o¡¡..· ·|.c., too, where it is the reinvigoration of previous
affective states and their effects, rather than affective freedom, that allow us to
make our bodies mean something that we recognize and value.
To return to my discussion of Fanon and Lorde, it is clear that racially
marked subject are not simply ‘sprawled out’ and ‘distorted’ (Fanon 1952, p.
80), but have a critical and affective life that resonates differently. So that over
time, Audre Lorde’s critical judgement of the ongoing spiral of smaller cycles
of shame in response to her body and to racism is of such intensity that she is
able to remake the relationship between her body, affect and judgement to
inflect the social world with other meanings. In 1|. co»... jco.»o!· , for
example, a text that is almost definitional in tracing maps of intensity that
fashion the individual other in relation to an other social world (1980), Lorde
does not need to think of affect as asocial in order for her investments in
survival to provide a different affective trajectory than the one that would deny
her subjectivity. Lorde reinvents her body as hers not theirs, a body connected
to other bodies by shared judgements of the social. Those judgements
constitute a political history that reshapes social meaning, creating recognizable
and intelligible alternatives to dominant signification. My critical response to
5 6 4 CULTURAL STUDI ES
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1
Massumi and Sedgwick’s work on affect, then, is not one that rejects the
importance of affect for cultural theory. It is one that rejects the contemporary
fascination with affect as outside social meaning, as providing a break in both
the social and in critics’ engagements with the nature of the social. The
problems in Massumi and Sedgwick discussed in this article do not require a
wholesale rejection of affect’s relevance to cultural theory. Instead, affect
might in fact be valuable precisely to the extent that it is not autonomous.
Note
1 Richard Langston (2005) takes up this capacity of affect to re-embed or
unsettle cultural stereotypes and investments in the context of the foreign
language classroom, to illustrate how affect might usefully be pedagogically
investigated.
References
Ahmed, S. (2000) ‘Embodying strangers’, in ic1, Mo··..· t.¬.».·¬, 1.··oo!.·,,
cc.¡c..o!.·,, eds A. Horner & A. Keane, Manchester University Press,
Manchester, pp. 85Á/96.
Al-Saji, A. (2000) ‘The site of affect in Husserl’s phenomenology’, in ‘Philosophy
in body, culture and time: selected studies in phenomenology and existential
philosophy’, eds W. A. Brogan & M. A. Simons, t|.!c·c¡|, 1c1o,, vol. 26.
Berlant, L. (1997) 1|. ¸o..» c¡ +¬....o cc.· ·c Po·|.»¸·c» c.·, i··o,· c» :.· o»1
c.·...»·|.¡, Duke University Press, Durham.
Bhabha, H. K. (1994) 1|. tc.o·.c» c¡ co!·o.. , Routledge, London.
Biddle, J. (1997) ‘Shame’, +o··.o!.o» t.¬.».·· :·o1..· , vol. 12, no. 26, pp. 227Á/
239.
Braidotti, R. (1994) :c¬o1.. :o/¡..·· i¬/c1.¬.»· o»1 :.·oo! Ð.¡¡...».. .»
cc»·.¬¡c.o., t.¬.».·· 1|.c.,, Columbia University Press, New York.
Braidotti, R. (2002) M.·o¬c.¡|c·.· 1c«o.1· o Mo·...o!.·· 1|.c., c¡ i..c¬.»¸, Polity
Press, Cambridge.
Bruns, J. (2000) ‘Laughter in the aisles: affect and power in contemporary
theoretical and cultural discourse’, :·o1..· .» +¬....o» uo¬c. , vol. 3, no. 7,
pp. 5Á/23.
Butler, J. (1990) c.»1.. 1.co/!. t.¬.».·¬ o»1 ·|. :o/·..·.c» c¡ i1.»·.·,, Routledge,
New York.
Butler, J. (1997a) 1|. t·,.|.. t.¡. c¡ tc«.. 1|.c...· .» :o/¡..·.c», Stanford
University Press, Stanford, CA.
Butler, J. (1997b) ‘Merely cultural’, :c..o! 1.·· , vols 52/53, pp. 265Á/277.
Cavarero, A. (2000) r.!o·.»¸ :o..o·.·.· :·c.,·.!!.»¸ o»1 :.!¡|cc1, trans. P. A.
Kottman, Routledge, London.
Deleuze, G. (1997) i··o,· c..·..o! o»1 c!.»..o!, trans. D. W. Smith & M. A. Greco,
University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.
I NVOKI NG AF F ECT 5 6 5
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1
Fanon, F. (1952) ‘The fact of blackness’, in his (1991) ‘‘i!o.| :|.»·, P|.·. Mo·|· ’’ ,
Pluto Press, London, pp. 77Á/99.
Fraser, N. (1997) ‘Heterosexism, misrecognition, and capitalism: a response to
Judith Butler’, :c..o! 1.·· , vols 52/3, pp. 279Á/289.
Giardini, F. (1999) ‘Public affects: clues towards a political practice of
singularity’, 1|. io.c¡.o» jco.»o! c¡ Pc¬.»’· :·o1..· , vol. 6, no. 2, pp.
149Á/160.
Graham, H., Kaloski, A., Neilson, A. and Robertson, E. (eds) (2002) 1|. t.¬.».··
:.·.»·..· , Raw Nerve Books, York.
Grosz, E. (1994) ¡c!o·.!. ic1..· 1c«o.1 o cc.¡c..o! t.¬.».·¬, Indiana University
Press, Bloomington, IN.
Gubar, S. (1998) ‘What ails feminist criticism?’, c..·..o! i»¸o..,, vol. 24, pp. 878Á/
902.
Halperin, D. (2002) ‘Homosexuality’s closet’, M..|.¸o» ¸oo.·..!, r.·..«, vol. 41,
no. 1, pp. 21Á/54.
Haraway, D. (1991) ‘Situated knowledges: the science question in feminism and
the privilege of the partial perspective’, in her :.¬.o»·, c,/c.¸· o»1 Pc¬.»
·|. r..»·.»·.c» c¡ :o·o.., Routledge, New York, pp. 183Á/201.
Harding, S. (1986) 1|. :...».. ¸o.··.c» .» t.¬.».·¬, Cornell University Press,
Ithaca, NY.
Hardt, M. (1999) ‘Affective labor’, ico»1o., 2, vol. 26, no. 2, pp. 89Á/100.
Hartsock, N. (1999) 1|. t.¬.».·· :·o»1¡c.»· r.·.·.·.1 o»1 o·|.. i··o,· , Westview
Press, Boulder, CO.
Hill Collins, P. (2000) i!o.| t.¬.».·· 1|co¸|· x»c«!.1¸., cc»·..co·».·· o»1 ·|.
tc!.·..· c¡ i¬¡c«..¬.»· , Routledge, New York.
Jackson, S. (2001) ‘Why a materialist feminism is (still) possible and necessary’,
Pc¬.»’· :·o1..· i»·..»o·.c»o! tc.o¬, vol. 24, no. 3Á/4, pp. 283Á/293.
Kandyoti, D. (1994) ‘Identity and its discontents: women and the nation’, in
cc!c».o! Ð.·.co.·. o»1 tc··.c!c».o! 1|.c., o r.o1.. , eds P. Williams & L.
Chrisman, Columbia University Press, New York, pp. 376Á/391.
Langston, R. (2005) ‘Feels like teen spirit: affect, gendered bodies, and teaching
cross-cultural difference at the millennium’, Pc¬.» .» c..¬o» 1.o./cc|,
forthcoming.
Lorde, A. (1980) 1|. co»... jco.»o!· , Aunt Lute Books, San Francisco.
Lorde, A. (1984) ‘Eye to eye: black women, hatred, and anger’, in her :.··..
oo··.1.. i··o,· o»1 :¡...|.· /, +o1.. tc.1., The Crossing Press, Freedom,
CA.
Massumi, B. (1996) ‘The autonomy of affect’, in Ð.!.o.. o c..·..o! r.o1.. , ed. P.
Patton, Blackwell, Oxford, pp. 217Á/239.
Massumi, B. (2002) to.o/!.· ¡c. ·|. ¡..·oo! Mc·.¬.»·, +¡¡..·, :.»·o·.c», Duke
University Press, Durham.
Miller, D. A. (1988) 1|. :c·.! o»1 ·|. tc!..., University of California Press,
Berkeley, CA.
Mitchell, J. (2000) Mo1 M.» o»1 M.1o·o· r..!o.¬.»¸ u,··...o o»1 ·|. i¡¡..·· c¡ :./!.»¸
r.!o·.c»·|.¡ u¡c» ·|. uo¬o» cc»1.·.c», Allen Lane, London.
5 6 6 CULTURAL STUDI ES
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1
Munt, S. (2000) ‘Shame/pride dichotomies in Queer As Folk’, 1.··oo! t.o.·... ,
vol. 14, no. 3, pp. 531Á/546.
O’Sullivan, S. (2001) ‘The aesthetics of affect: thinking art beyond representa-
tion’, +»¸.!o|. , vol. 6, no. 3, pp. 125Á/135.
Probyn, E. (2000) ‘Shaming bodies: dynamics of shame and pride’, ic1, o»1
:c...·,, vol. 6, no. 1, pp. 13Á/28.
Prosser, J. (1998) :..c»1 :|.»· ·|. ic1, :o..o·.·.· c¡ 1.o»··.·oo!.·,, Columbia
University Press, New York.
Said, E. (1979) o...»·o!.·¬, Random House, New York.
Sedgwick, E. K. (1990) i¡.··.¬c!c¸, c¡ ·|. c!c·.· , University of California Press,
Berkeley, CA.
Sedgwick, E. K. (2003) 1co.|.»¸ t..!.»¸ +¡¡..·, t.1o¸c¸,, t..¡c.¬o·.·.·,, Duke
University Press, Durham.
Sedgwick, E. K. & Frank, A. (1995) ‘Shame in the cybernetic fold: reading Silvan
Tomkins’, in their (eds) :|o¬. o»1 i·· :.··..· + :.!·o» 1c¬|.»· r.o1.. , Duke
University Press, Durham, pp. 1Á/28.
Shilling, C. (1993) 1|. ic1, o»1 :c..o! 1|.c.,, Sage, London.
Spinks, L. (2001) ‘Thinking the post-human: literature, affect and the politics of
style’, 1.··oo! t.o.·..., vol. 15, no. 1, pp. 23Á/46.
Spivak, G. C. (1993) ‘Woman in difference’, in her oo··.1. .» ·|. 1.o.|.»¸
Mo.|.». , Routledge, New York, pp. 77Á/95.
Spivak, G. C. (1999) + c..·.¸o. c¡ tc··.c!c».o! r.o·c» 1c«o.1 o u.··c., c¡ ·|.
¡o».·|.»¸ t..·.»· , Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Stacey, J. (1997) ‘Feminist theory: capital F, capital T’, in i»·.c1o..»¸ Pc¬.»’·
:·o1..· t.¬.».·· 1|.c., o»1 t.o.·..., eds V. Robinson & D. Richardson, New
York University Press, New York, pp. 54Á/76.
Stanley, E. & Wise, S. (2000) ‘But the Empress has no clothes! Some awkward
questions about ‘the missing revolution’ in feminist theory’, t.¬.».·· 1|.c.,,
vol. 1, no. 3, pp. 261Á/288.
Tomkins, S. (1963) +¡¡..·, i¬o¸..,, cc»·..co·».·· Á ¡c! ii 1|. :.¸o·.·. +¡¡..·· ,
Springer Publishing, New York.
I NVOKI NG AF F ECT 5 6 7
D
o
w
n
l
o
a
d
e
d

B
y
:

[
I
n
g
e
n
t
a

C
o
n
t
e
n
t

D
i
s
t
r
i
b
u
t
i
o
n

P
s
y

P
r
e
s
s

T
i
t
l
e
s
]

A
t
:

1
7
:
4
7

1
4

M
a
r
c
h

2
0
1
1

Clare Hemmings
INVOKING AFFECT Cultural theory and the ontological turn
Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011

This article interrogates the contemporary emergence of affect as critical object and perspective through which to understand the social world and our place within it. Emphasising the unexpected, the singular or the quirky over the generally applicable, the turn to affect builds on important work in cultural studies on the pitfalls of writing the body out of theory. More importantly for this article, the contemporary interest in affect evidences a dissatisfaction with poststructuralist approaches to power, framed as hegemonic in their negativity and insistence of social structures rather than interpersonal relationships as formative of the subject. The article focuses on the recent contributions of Brain Massumi and Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick in particular, unpacking their celebration of the difference that affect makes. The author’s critique of the affective turn focuses on both the illusion of choice that it offers the cultural critic, and its rewriting of the recent history of cultural theory to position affect as ‘the new cutting edge’. While affect may constitute a valuable critical focus in context, it frequently emerges through a circular logic designed to persuade ‘paranoid theorists’ into a more productive frame of mind Á for who would not prefer affective freedom to social determinism? Yet it remains unclear what role affect may have once this rhetoric has worked its persuasive magic. In addition, and more worryingly, affective rewriting flattens out poststructuralist inquiry by ignoring the counter-hegemonic contributions of postcolonial and feminist theorists, only thereby positioning affect as ‘the answer’ to contemporary problems of cultural theory.
/

Keywords affect; cultural theory; epistemology; ontology; feminist theory; postcolonial theory

There is no denying, or deferring, affects. They are what make up life, and art . . . Affects are . . . the stuff that goes on beneath, beyond, even parallel to signification. But what can one say about affects? Indeed, what
Cultural Studies Vol. 19, No. 5 September 2005, pp. 548 Á/567 ISSN 0950-2386 print/ISSN 1466-4348 online – 2005 Taylor & Francis http://www.tandf.co.uk/journals DOI: 10.1080/09502380500365473

and the deconstructionist. enabling queer subjects both to identify the bodily resonances of Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011 . Advocates of affect offer it up as a way of deepening our vision of the terrain we are studying. You cannot read affects. you can only experience them. O’Sullivan is writing within the context of art history. insisting that it should not be something we strive simply to overcome by turning to its dependent opposite. which the attentions of affect theorists have reshaped into three predominant concerns. that unsettles us into becoming someone other than who we currently are. post deconstruction we doubt the capacity of both quantitative empirical approaches and textual analysis to account for the fullest resonance of the social world we wish to understand. Sally Munt (2000) and Elspeth Probyn (2000) have all argued. foregrounds the unexpected that throws us off balance. pride. (O’Sullivan 2001. Shame itself. p. . 17). While not really a school as such. Thus Brian Massumi (1996) insists that affect is important to the extent that it is autonomous and outside social signification. Queer theorists in particular have taken up Sedgwick and Adam Frank’s (1995) emphasis on the transformative capacities of shame. Simon O’Sullivan celebrates affects’ capacity to defy deconstruction. . of allowing for and prioritizing its ‘texture’. a significant number of disciplinary and interdisciplinary theorists are currently citing affect as the privileged ‘way out’ of the perceived impasse in cultural studies. this concern is indicated by the intensity of current critical interest in psychoanalytic accounts of the subject.INVOKING AFFECT 549 needs to be said about them? . where which he claims that semiotic and deconstructivist approaches have become hegemonic. p. The impasse needing to be resolved is by now a familiar one. to embodied experience that has the capacity to transform as well as exceed social subjection. and that constitutes the very fabric of our being. and in particular Judith Butler’s development of psychoanalysis through her focus on subjection (1997a). 126) Introduction In the article from which the above quotation is taken. and in particular laughter. Theorists of affect argue that constructivist models leave out the residue or excess that is not socially produced. Firstly. In a general sense. but he is far from alone in embracing affect as offering a new critical trajectory for cultural theory. This texture refers to our qualitative experience of the social world. as David Halperin (2002). post deconstruction we doubt the capacity of constructivist models of the subject to account fully for our place in the world as individuals or groups. and John Bruns (2000) suggests that affect. has a resonance well beyond its homophobic generation. in Eve Sedgwick’s words (2003. Secondly.

Grosz 1994). But both authors are thereby presented with something of a problem. Thirdly. affective ties have been theorized as offering an alternative model of subject formation. the singular. I remain sceptical of what is often a theoretical celebration of affect as uniquely situated to achieve this end. for example. critical race theorists argue that affect plays a role in both cementing sexed and raced relations of domination. post deconstruction we doubt that the oppositions of power/resistance or public/private can fully account for the political process. and to create community through empathy and shared experience. these exclusions matter because of their capacity to transform the world we live in. and following Franz Fanon’s (1952) insistence that social relations at both the macro and the micro level are based on unreasonable ties. Shilling 1993. Spivak 1993. This article explores my scepticism of such affective celebration through close engagement with Sedgwick’s (2003) and Massumi’s (2002) work on the subject. And Michael Hardt (1999) argues that while affective labour is the hidden centre of capitalist accumulation. over the generally applicable. however. The affective critique is not simply one that highlights omission. affect theorists build on the important work within feminist theory and Sociology on the pitfalls of writing the body out of theory (e.1 The approaches I have mentioned share an interest in exploring analogue rather than digital modes of power and community. In the work of Adriana Cavarero (2000). In a similar vein. For affect theorists. the capacity to restructure social meaning. Bhabha 1994. it also produces emotional connections that threaten to disrupt that accumulation. Hill Collins 2000). In this context. not as a bid for group rights. In making this move. in itself. and in providing the local investments necessary to counter those relations (e. which is to say the non-socially-determined. and the former with the hope of freedom from social constraint. or one that simply stresses the devaluing of certain practices and experiences in general paradigms.550 C U LT U R A L S T U D I E S a heterosexual status quo. which is to say connected and relational over oppositional modes. or indeed the quirky. For both authors it is affect’s difference from social structures that means it possesses. they cannot fail to be aware of the myriad Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011 . where the latter becomes associated with the pessimism of social determinist perspectives.g. and both have recently published monographs invoking affect as the way forward within that arena. They emphasize the unexpected. and offer a different world-view than the rather narrow one governed by a repressive/subversive dichotomy. As prominent cultural theorists. since it remains unremunerated yet is what bestows qualitative value. Both authors are well-respected contributors to contemporary cultural theory. but a bid for social transformation. While appreciative of a critical focus on the unusual. how those we are closest to view us is central to our selfnarration and therefore our way of being in the world.g. and contemporary critical theorists should ignore them at their peril.

Two points come to mind at this point. whose hardness is indeed evidenced by that response. for example). is that while affect may be an interesting and valuable critical focus in context. Unlike drives. which means the relationship remains dyadic. Firstly. particularly in light of their own professed irritation with cultural theorists’ tendency to divide the world up into good and bad. affects can be transferred to a range of objects in order to be satisfied (love may have many objects.INVOKING AFFECT 551 Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011 ways that affect manifests precisely not as difference. then. interested instead as they both are in that ‘other affect’. Sedgwick and Massumi do both acknowledge this characteristic of affect in their work. affect can enable the satisfaction of a drive (excitement might prepare the body for the satisfaction of hunger) or interrupt it (so that disgust might interrupt that satisfaction if you were served . which makes them adaptable in a way that drives are not. It is difficult to maintain such an affective dichotomy of course. are affective responses that strengthen rather than challenge a dominant social order (Berlant 1997). it often emerges as a rhetorical device whose ultimate goal is to persuade ‘paranoid theorists’ into a more productive frame of mind. but do not pursue it. are what enable drives to be satisfied and what tie us to the world. leaving it up to her or him to decide whether the direction they wish to pursue is one of the pessimism of social determinism (including bad affect) or the optimism of affective freedom (good affect). Secondly. rather than to their manifestation or interpretation as emotions. this question to the critic is hardly an open one. both the ills of cultural theory to date and the restorative power of affect need to be overstated. p. The delights of consumerism. as part of persuading the critic that the question is a valid one. Instead. Affect broadly refers to states of being. So. My overarching contention in this article. For psychoanalysis affects are ‘the qualitative expression of our drives’ energy and variations’ (Giardini 1999. the good affect that undoes the bad. repressive or subversive and so on. But unfortunately neither author offers any explanation as to the relationship between these ‘two kinds’ of affect. to suggest just several contexts. Affective territories I began research for this article as a result of my frustration at seeing affect mentioned or celebrated but rarely fully explained as either critical tool or object. feelings of belonging attending fundamentalism or fascism. So I want to spend some time discussing what is actually meant by affect. 150). both authors negotiate a way out of their own uncomfortable critical position by turning the question of affective freedom back onto the cultural critic. ‘Wouldn’t you rather be free?’ can hardly elicit a negative response in anyone but the most hardened cultural theorist. but as a central mechanism of social reproduction in the most glaring ways. as I discuss in more detail below.

181). 56). In Deleuze’s account.552 C U LT U R A L S T U D I E S a rotten egg to eat). there are convulsions that jolt the body’ (1997: 123). rather than opposition to others. both instances index the unpredictable autonomy of the body’s encounter with the event. and provides the individual with a way of narrating their own inner life (likes. rather as a judgement on his body’s response to rape: it is his erection that gives rise to shame. p. Tomkins’ work suggests that affects have a complex. Tomkins asked us to think of the contagious nature of a yawn. The first is the grisly spectacle of ‘the gestures of the dying. confounding its logic. Deleuze takes two examples from his reading of T. even in the state of sludge. rather than as raw material responding rather passively to cognitive or learned phenomena. Lawrence’s experiences in the desert to illustrate the body’s capacity to interrupt social logic. It is transferred to others and doubles back. In terms of our relations with others. as bodily meaning that pierces social interpretation. registered) in the moment of responding to a new situation. Lawrence does experience shame. provoking Lawrence’s mad laughter’ (1997. perhaps. and scrambling its expectations. In contrast to Tomkins. then. or insatiable (where jealousy or desire for revenge may last minutes or a lifetime). affect connects us to others. such that we keep ‘a trace. that attempt at raising their hands that makes all the agonizing Turks ripple together. who breaks down affect into a topography of myriad. as if they had practiced the same theatrical gesture. within [our] constitution’ of those experiences (Al-Saji 2000. as an intensity characterized by an increase or decrease in power (1997. E. but not in alignment with social prohibition. The second is Deleuze’s account of Lawrence’s experience of being gang raped: ‘in the midst of his tortures. self-referential life that gives depth to human existence through our relations with others and with ourselves. Deleuze understands affect as describing the passage from one state to another. smile or blush. Thus affects may be autotelic (love being its own reward). For Tomkins. its shattering ability to go its own way. p. Discontented by the way affects had been theorized only in respect to drives. dislikes. p. Tomkins is joined by Gilles Deleuze to form an unlikely couple dominating the contemporary affective imaginary of cultural theory. In both examples. An affect theory is all of our affective experiences to date that are remembered (or better. Further. desires and revulsions) to themselves and others. For Deleuze. he paraphrases Lawrence’s description of violent events in the desert. Tomkins argues that we all develop complex affect theories as a way of negotiating the social world as unique individuals. Thus one of the main reasons affect has been taken up as the hopeful alternative to social determinism is its positioning of the individual as possessing a degree of control over their future. increasing its original intensity. one cannot do Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011 . 123). an erection. the influential psychologist Silvan Tomkins (1963) was the first to suggest that they have a singularity that creates its own circuitry. Deleuze (1997) proposes affect as distinct from emotion. Affect can thus be said to place the individual in a circuit of feeling and response. distinct parts. For Deleuze.

contemporary critical theorists tend to prefer either Tomkins’ pragmatism or Deleuze’s imaginative flights. the / / Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011 . I say provocatively. For many theorists of affect Deleuze’s approach provides insight into thinking through the body in a non-essentialist way that remains faithful to many different levels and modes of bodily experience (e. is disconcertingly proud rather than covert. 13). because throughout her text. 17). She advocates instead a reparative return to the ontological and intersubjective. Sedgwick argues that such paranoia makes cultural investigation protectionist instead of expansive. until now. As inheritors of this affective legacy. p. Instead. p. as she assumes it is. p. as theorists ward off other critical imaginaries as duped unless they too come to the same conspiratorial conclusions. To do so would be to miss the dramatic significance of the body’s own asocial trace. Indeed.g. prohibition in a space we had not. For Sedgwick such a ‘hermeneutics of suspicion and exposure’ that is at once smug and sour. is not merely an unattractive trait in a critical theorist. Again following Tomkins. prohibition everywhere: prohibition where it appeared there was freedom. Sedgwick acknowledges that our learned instinct as cultural theorists is to reject Tomkins for his insistence on affect as innate. where the project of a poststructuralist critical imaginary has become reduced to the search for. since a relentless attention to the structures of truth and knowledge obscures our experience of those structures. 123Á 51). this is precisely Sedgwick’s challenge Á do cultural theorists shy away from affect a la Tomkins for any other reasons than its ` essentialism? For Sedgwick. the movement between bodily states that is its intensity (1997. which anchor poststructuralist critical inquiry. thought to look. Eve Sedgwick’s new work takes up Tomkins’ suggestion that a focus on affect sidesteps a myopic attention to structural prohibition. 63). it also makes her or him ill equipped for analysing contemporary social formations ‘in which visibility itself constitutes much of the violence’ (2003. 140). Sedgwick asks ‘what use is paranoid theory?’ Part of what makes critical theory so uninventive for Sedgwick is its privileging of the epistemological. because of its capacity to link us creatively to others. p. Sedgwick is interested in using affect theory to challenge what Probyn calls ‘the twinned problematics of discipline or transgression’ (2000. to the surprising and enlivening texture of individuality and community (2003. unless they too find violence where there had appeared to be possibility (2003. Spinks 2001). however. if the answer is ‘no’.INVOKING AFFECT 553 justice to Lawrence’s unruly body by reducing it to its social organization. Sedgwick rather provocatively invites us to consider affect as the key to that texture. Deleuze proposes a cartographic approach to the body and its affects where the critical focus is on bodily displacement. and deadening (re)discovery of. its refrain. While Tomkins is concerned with differentiating affect from drives. Sedgwick believes that the central problem facing Theory today is its own critical paranoia. In current global contexts where violence is anything but hidden. pp.

which will invariably reflect the framework they are interpreted through. These arguments have been raging within feminist academic and political contexts for a long time. His point is that in order to study the unknowable. Massumi’s irritation is chiefly reserved for the cultural theorist whose ability for ‘critical thinking’ has become reduced to identifying points on a stable map of the always already known (Massumi 2002. to the extent that there appears to be no hope of liberation. Brian Massumi similarly intervenes in the contemporary terrain of cultural theory to propose affect as a new way out of the pernicious reign of signification that dominates the field. cultural theorists will have to abandon the certainty that has come to characterize the field. Rosi Braidotti (2002) Á / / Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011 . Jackson 2001). associating it with an increase in professionalization and a concomitant decrease in political accountability (Gubar 1998. Massumi asks. and for its perceived lack of attention to what is often invoked as ‘the material’. of feminist debate. perhaps. how do we account for let alone encourage. p. since it is part of a different order of experience to the epistemological (as defined by Sedgwick): it is ‘the unassimilable’ (2002. a revaluing of individual difference and capacity for change over time (Prosser 1998. p. but what all critiques share is a lamenting of the turn to language represented by poststructuralism. We are effectively caught in culture. Within the context I am most familiar with.554 C U LT U R A L S T U D I E S rejection of Tomkins’ model is itself evidence of paranoid cultural theorists’ characteristic disposal of both baby and bathwater. Stanley and Wise 2000. is that Sedgwick and Massumi emerge as champions of affect in a more general context of the critique of what is usually understood as the ‘cultural turn’. such critical impoverishment means that cultural theorists consistently miss both the matter of bodies and. Mirroring Sedgwick. A number of theorists Á most notably. the unceasing movement that constitutes the process of becoming. poststructuralism is understood in contrast to have over-emphasized power-relations and their framing of both what we do and who we are. The particular form of these arguments is often disciplinespecific. What is clear then. change (2002. since his framework is Deleuzian rather than Tomkinsian. but cross over into more mainstream critical terrain through the debates between Judith Butler and Nancy Fraser in the late 1990s (Butler 1997b. And without this investment in movement between states and bodies. Interpretation through the overlaying of this map can only capture certain moments and certain experiences. For Massumi. 3). The first laments the increasing theoretical abstraction of feminist writing. p. Poststructuralist feminist writing is often aggressively damned for its inaccessibility. Critics viewing poststructuralism in this way advocate not a material return but an ontological one. then. Fraser 1997). 3)? Affect attracts Massumi. this turn to language is usually critiqued for one of two reasons that are somewhat at odds with one another. 12). Mitchell 2000). In the second critique of the ‘cultural turn’ within feminism.

and particularly in line with the second trajectory detailed here. such narratives mitigate against careful critical reading. in part because of an insistence that a decade of proliferating feminist texts and political action cannot be represented by the handful of theorists most commonly cited as essentialist (Stacey 1997. students identify the political in an empirically available real world or in the body. is that too frequently such material or ontological judgement is made on the basis of secondary reading Á that rejects poststructuralism as entirely rarefied and apolitical Á not primary reading. and celebrate ‘the new’ as untouched by whatever we find ourselves currently transcending. and challenges a simple acceptance of this critical narrative. / / Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011 . In my own. power and subjectivity. and my students’ cases. Graham et al. however. But my argument here is not that these ‘earlier generation’ are beyond critique. tend to the dismissive. the narrative is precisely borne out. 2002). In the search for ‘the new’ that bears no resemblance to the past. it takes material form in academic and institutional contexts. and nor did it stop that work being published. where I teach graduate students gender studies. however. Critical chronologies The critical narrative laid out above is not simply an abstract one. This is of course a familiar pattern. Each year it seems students grapple with poststructuralist approaches only to return to the question of how this turn to language is political. students are finding themselves drawn to social policy. because this view was a generally held one. the identifying features of that past are inevitably overstated. Opinion of what became crudely termed 1970s feminism has begun to shift. and the claims for that new embellished in ways that must at the very least fall short of rigorous. That lack of direct textual engagement did not stop me writing damning critiques of an ‘earlier generation’ of feminists. but that a narrative that posits a contemporary critical break with their characteristics has a vested interest in reading for generality instead of complexity. As a masters student in women’s studies in the early 1990s my secondary reading convinced me of the essentialist ills of early second wave Western feminist texts.INVOKING AFFECT 555 combine these two critiques in their focus on the lived materiality of bodies. Sedgwick and Massumi’s interest in affect must therefore be seen within the context of broader challenges to poststructuralist approaches to language. Instead of deconstruction. As with both critiques presented above. or innocent of essentialism or abstraction in turn. or to psychoanalytic or affective approaches that reframe questions of sexual and racial difference. development theory and practice. What is of interest here. most of which I did not read until much later. In my own institutional context.

In both Sedgwick and Massumi. arrogant and. as suggested. The following passage is typical: Critical thinking disavows its own inventiveness as much as possible. despite the fact that both arguments are ones that their authors have subsequently developed in different directions. Presumably. Massumi counsels that this has ‘nothing to do with morals or moralizing. let alone ‘disavow[. Miller’s The Novel and the Police. Published in 1990 and 1988 respectively. although the scattered but persistent references to ‘performance’ could be taken as similarly implicating Butler. However strenuously it might debunk concepts like ‘representation. and thus could justifiably oppose. It seems odd to rest the case for needing new theoretical frameworks on texts that have already prompted just such revisions from their authors. (2002. both Sedgwick and Massumi invariably overstate the problems of poststructuralism. unauthored. stubborn. Surely if the need for affect is so urgently felt. . As the wise father. 12) ‘Critical thinking’ is unreflexive. modus operandi’. In Touching Feeling. Instead of critical dialogue. the weight of Sedgwick’s dismissal of poststructuralist epistemology is carried by her reading of only two texts: Judith Butler’s Gender Trouble and D. p. descriptive . the reader can be expected to want to be an adult. much as advocates of poststructuralism overstated the ills of the seventies and early eighties. childish. Rather than tracing the thinking of particular authors. I want to stress that these citation issues are more than simply omission. . Positing affect as a ‘way out’ requires that .’ it carries on as if it mirrored something outside of itself and with which it had no complicity. Our rejection of such juvenile attachment to the theoretical status quo is in the end all just part of growing up. . referring to it in the third person throughout. our] own inventiveness’. for who among us would want to ‘cling to a . Massumi objectifies critical thinking. and indeed that are either side of fifteen years old. Massumi persuades his reader of the need for restorative attention to affect by positioning him or her as a co-conspirator who already knows what the problems of cultural theory are but just needs a little coaxing. At no point in Parables For the Virtual does Massumi engage directly with any of the theorists responsible for what he insists is theory’s terrible state of critical affairs. 13). . They construct a critical history at the same time as they dismiss it. .556 C U LT U R A L S T U D I E S Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011 In positing affect as the critical new for the noughts. Because it sees itself as uncovering something it desires to subtract from the world. . no unmediated processual involvement. as well as and in order to herald affect’s unique capacity to resolve contemporary critical dilemmas. p. [It is] just pragmatic’ (2002. it clings to a basically descriptive and justificatory modus operandi. A. the problem could be found in more contemporary texts? Massumi’s dismissal of cultural theory rests on more slender evidence still.

it is perhaps not enormously surprising that a post-deconstructivist ontology is offered as the solution. Both Sedgwick and Massumi progress from asserting the absolutely flawed nature of epistemology to insisting on the unequivocal good of ontology. and only if . we break free of our paranoid attachment to unfreedom and turn towards the possibilities offered by feeling.INVOKING AFFECT 557 poststructuralist epistemology have ignored embodiment. political connectivity and the possibility of change. investment and emotion. . the ‘problem of epistemology’ only materializes in the moment that it is chronologically and intellectually separated from ontology. there is a vast range of epistemological work that attends to emotional investments. 18). It may seem perverse to resist. To briefly trace one example. it is self-evidently horrific that critical thought is dominated by epistemological approaches that consider ‘the quality of affect . are multiple. If poststructuralist epistemology is the problem. p. The epistemological past is grey. As neither theorist can afford to acknowledge. the ontological future is bright. countering an affective chronology whose advocates prioritize grand shifts in ways that promote rather than caution against generalization. . Ontology thus resolves the problem its advocates invent. . of [no] more consequence than the color of the airplane used to speed a person to a destination’ (2003. and that the academic reader recognize their own prior complicity and current boredom with Theory’s straight-jacketing of thought. Feminist standpoint is a useful example in considering the turn to affect because its genealogical resonances echo back and forth across the last few decades. and its key proponents range across Marxist Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011 . nor opposed to consideration of ontology. it is true. epistemological and transformative. Both authors’ chronologies of the past and future of critical theory need to ignore the range of poststructuralist work that does not follow this pattern. many-faceted and surprising. but as with the issues of citation discussed above. p. In Massumi. Even where theorists stress multiplicity of social location. . This horror underwrites her conviction that only a turn to ontology can redress the over-emphasis of truth and knowledge at the expense of individual experience. But aren’t they still combinatorial permutations on an overarching definitional framework?’ While all social meaning is already fully known. p. feminist standpoint epistemology might be said to constitute an established body of inquiry into the relationship between the ontological. epistemological work that is neither poststructuralist. for Massumi (2002. and cultural theory. p. . 3). already ‘[nothing] more than a local embodiment of ideology’ (2002. who would not want it to be?). In standpoint. and ontology is (active) life. For Sedgwick. 3) this continues to fix difference: ‘The sites. if . flat and predictable. epistemology and ontology are never separated and opposed. would minimize or ignore (2002. 5). That future could be ours too (again. ontology on the other hand heroically carries the very difference that ideology. signification is (passive) death. .

But what is overlooked in this particular authorship of history is instructive. Thus. if not deliberate. a commitment to political accountability. Said 1979. it is politically invested perspectives of difference. Only through these ‘oversights’ can non-paranoid theory belong to the future rather than to the present and past. Spivak 1999). 3) suggests. Or. postcolonial theorists. all feminist standpoint work. Kandyoti 1994. and that if Massumi and Sedgwick are wrong in some respects. But in fact this failure to attend to the fault lines in a chronology charting cultural theory’s progressive myopia is central to the positioning of affect as panacea for Theory’s hypochondria. they are also right in others. among others. have attended to the ways that marginal social location is not simply ‘precoded into the ideological master structure’ as Massumi (2002. Such theorists have argued that to be marginal in relation to the dominant is to inhabit ambivalence. A reader could well respond that some oversight and generalization is inevitable in the development of new critical trajectories. In addition. I would argue then that affect theorists’ error lies in the evacuation of this theoretical and political Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011 . and values continuity of difference over time. against paranoia. Both theorists are of course familiar with the kind of work on epistemology or signification that does not reduce experience to a place on a grid of immutable power relations. p. Secondly. critical race theory. Hill Collins 2000). it also precipitates community that is historically resonant. as well as poststructuralism (Harding 1986. that draws on and creates alternative signification of the same actions and events.558 C U LT U R A L S T U D I E S feminism. to take a different tack. Sedgwick herself paradigmatically complicated questions of knowledge and the subject formed by its perverse logics in Epistemology of the Closet (1990) and refused to reduce what one could call queer standpoint to a fixed position on a homophobic map. Bhabha 1994. It is consistently theory written from the margins (I just mentioned standpoint and postcolonial theory here) that refuses both dominant prescription and simple oppositional location. historical and community validated standard of evidence for the knowledges that it wishes to produce. Hartsock 1999. To refuse to cite in order to dismiss. but knowing and inflecting. rather than abstract epistemologists who disappear from the critical record. Braidotti 1994. not simply additive or oppositional multiplicity (Fanon 1952. Such broad oversights and lack of citational evidence. and the social world is always crosscut with fissures that have a social and political history that signifies otherwise. To be ‘other’ is not only to be the object of another’s gaze within the dominant. while enormously divergent. When I first read both Massumi and Sedgwick on affect. does share the following: firstly. all the feminist standpoint work I can think of posits a different. sexual difference theory. I was genuinely confused. Haraway 1991. community and the importance of positive affect for both belonging and change. social difference is not only opposite. are a least necessary to both authors’ critical location in their work on affect.

disgusted by shame. Affect’s freedom of attachment. Sedgwick’s conclusion is that to collect these records would be a cure of sorts for critical paranoia. Sedgwick and Massumi use the notion of affect as free and autonomous respectively. The critique of Sedgwick’s insistence here takes two directions: firstly. including other affects. . becomes evidence. . p. there is a slippage here. For affective freedom to equal critical freedom Sedgwick must insist that affect attaches randomly to any object. 62) in the self and in relationships. and any number of other things. p. . ‘anyone’s character . attached to things. Following Tomkins. should we but attend to its unfolding drama. fleeting emotion . a record of the highly individual histories by which . sensations. then. as cultural theorists we have a duty to attend to the patterns and effects of such surprise. ideas. relations. Affective freedoms As contemporary cultural theorists. On the one hand. people. and even more importantly for Sedgwick. rather than to the social frameworks that we already know. . of our critical freedom. creating both a different archive of experience as well as a different theoretical paradigm. It is certainly true that affect attaches all over the place. This freedom of affect combines with its contagious nature. Sedgwick (2003. Sedgwick’s ‘reparative return’ to the singularity of the ontological hinges on her argument that affect is free from the constraints of both drives and social meaning. . 19) asserts that ‘affects can be. Since affect is a ‘free radical’ that can attach itself to anything.INVOKING AFFECT 559 complexity from critical theory’s development. affective attachment frequently serves to satisfy drives or social norms. affective attachments will be unpredictable. However. . . Silvan Tomkins. to persuade cultural theorists of the value of the untrammeled ontological. p. resulting in what Sedgwick understands as its capacity to transform the self in relation to others. it is hard to think of an arena of life that is not suffused with affect. Thus one can be excited by anger. institutions. In this vein. and since we create associations between feelings and contexts that are unpredictable. its ability to attach to any object. or surprised by joy’. has instituted far more durable. and are. despite the fact that even for her guide. attention to affect will always be attention to everyday experience rather than macro abstractions. . both Sedgwick and Massumi know that they cannot simply propose a return to ontological certainty in order to alleviate the epistemological myopia they identify. too. Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011 . For the critical chronology I have been indicating to remain intact. 19) is that because affect can be surprising in its attachments. for Sedgwick. As Sedgwick suggests. but this ‘error’ is precisely what allows complexity to be hijacked for recuperation in the future. activities. is . structured changes’ (2003. Sedgwick’s argument (2002. ambitions. affect must be both post biological essentialism and post-epistemology.

132) Tomkins continues the story: the child realizes that it is him that the parent is disgusted with and through identification with the parent. whose primary affect is disgust. In a scene from The Negative Affects. but it can also be transformative. This logic is governed by three phrases: a. but that her awareness of this inattention is central to how her affective logic functions. Yet. he becomes ashamed of himself. and can arise unexpectedly in relation to an object previously favoured. Shouldn’t we attend to those transformative possibilities over and above normative ones? c. however. If the human feces were not innately disgusting. My point here is not that Sedgwick misses the heteronormative regulation of affect. p. in ways that suggest that no matter how expansive our capacity to substitute objects of disgust at a later date. b. and secondly. it would still be relatively easy to teach the child to be disgusted by his own feces. A father teaches his son by example that his inevitable recoil from shit is natural. is an anal character because humans are innately disgusted by the odor of their feces. But the possibility of shit not being recoiled from if it were not innately disgusting. In Tomkins’ shame-filled world. mumble. it is clear that there are certain things that unquestionably authenticate disgust as response in human beings in the first place. The scene is profoundly homosocial in that it is the father’s recoil from the son here (all Tomkins’ children are little ‘heroes’) that forms the pedagogic site. by identification with the parent who lifted his lip and drew his head away from the child’s feces. It attaches itself to many different objects. (1963. Of course shame can be normative. It is / / / . which critics are able to turn their location into such celebratory responsibility? Let us pursue the example of disgustÁ shame that Sedgwick takes as exemplary of affective freedom. boys are instructed specifically not to cry like girls. is only imagined momentarily in this passage to be summarily dismissed by the insistence that ‘it would still be relatively easy’ to teach this disgust anyway. Indeed Tomkins’ book of negative affect is bursting with children whose affective responses are bound by the early contexts in which they learn the codes and practices of gender and sexuality.560 C U LT U R A L S T U D I E S Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011 what might still be gained by a (healthy?) critical paranoia in tracing affect. the better to reduce the likelihood of shame doubling back on him. Disgust at shit is thus either innate or inevitable Á its randomness resides only in which object its displacement will settle on. Tomkins suggests that we learn disgust as a primary negative affect when a parent smells our faeces and reacts with the affect disgustÁ contempt: / / It may be that the anal character. gesticulate when speaking. demonstrate enthusiasm in public or eat like birds. the primary affect these refer to is either learned Á or if innate. reinforced Á in heteronormative scenes (Berlant 1997). So the child finds other objects to be disgusted of.

I am thinking here of Franz Fanon and Audre Lorde’s often cited descriptions of other people’s affective response to their blackness. 147Á 8) / . learned within a racist familial and social order. the nigger is shivering because he is cold. but I will never forget it. the nigger’s going to eat me up. clad in mourning in that white winter day. Thus in our own expectations. recoloured. Something’s going on here I do not understand. can attach to an unknown black object. The fur brushes past my face as she stands with a shudder and holds on to a strap in the speeding train . (1952. Lorde similarly recalls her realization that it is her body that is disgusting to a white woman sitting next to her on the bus: When I look up the woman is still staring at me. let us not forget. The Negro is an animal. p. the Negro is ugly. Against this teleology of old power versus new freedom of choice I want to continue by suggesting that only for certain subjects can affect be thought of as attaching in an open way. the Negro is bad. allowing the future to emerge as the epoch of individual difference. the Negro is mean. The flared nostrils. her nose holes and eyes huge. the little boy is trembling because he is afraid of the nigger. the handsome little boy is trembling because he thinks that the nigger is quivering with rage. . to the already dealt with. that cold that goes through your bones. The hate. but is ‘sprawled out’ and ‘distorted’. it is me she doesn’t want her coat to touch.INVOKING AFFECT 561 Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011 simply churlish to make a fuss. and marks its limits: ‘It is. the prostitute who is shameless. power belongs to the past. 231) insists that in matters of sexuality it is the woman who carries the shame of gendered impropriety. 80) While the white boy’s fear. presented to him via the white boy’s affective response. the nigger is shivering with cold. (1984. a nigger. Fanon remembers: / My body was given to me sprawled out. And suddenly I realise that there is nothing crawling up the seat between us. the little white boy throws himself into his mother’s arms: Mama. Jennifer Biddle (1997. This grammar only works because of our prior knowledge of Sedgwick’s work in a central rather than passing way Á we can trust that Sedgwick of all theorists has already factored power into the equation. look. Fanon’s body is precisely not his own. distorted. it’s cold. as in the critical chronology discussed in the previous section. but the gentleman. who is discreet’. others are so over-associated with affect that they themselves are the object of affective transfer. but also suffuse critical accounts of the process of affective racialization. the nigger is shivering. Such transferred affective attachments do not only pertain to gender and sexuality. . after all. Her eyes. p. pp. In this vein.

In both of these examples. For Massumi. we freeze it. Emotion is the intensest (most contracted) expression of that capture-and of the fact that something has always and again escaped. Sara Ahmed argues that affect thus places bodies in spatial relation along racially defined lines (2000. then. Yet. 85Á 6). as it is the female body that carries the burden of the affects that maintain sexual difference in Biddle’s example above. Furthermore. the moment that we ‘make sense’ of a state of being. Formed. Thus: Affect is autonomous to the degree to which it escapes confinement in the particular body whose vitality. Biddle. are the capture and closure of affect. it is. affect is interesting insofar as it resists or runs counter to the causal linearity through which we make sense of the world. situated perceptions and cognitions fulfilling functions of actual connection or blockage. In the first instance. nor is the ability to choose to imagine affect otherwise. it is the black body that carries the weight of. p. p. as I have suggested. or more properly becoming. and is suffused with. the need for a new theory of the ontological requires displacing marginal theory and histories from a chronology of cultural theory. or potential for interaction. racial affect. 228) As for Sedgwick. The failure of some critics to ‘choose choice’ paradoxically becomes evidence of their concomitant failure to relinquish an imagined history that they may already have been erased from. (1996. Yet. Affect is thus valuable to the extent that it is not susceptible to the vagaries of theoretical whim. evacuating it of the very intensity that offered the capacity for change. where for Sedgwick affective freedom of attachment becomes a mark of the critic’s freedom. for Massumi the affective autonomy places it outside the reach of critical interpretation. My concerns about the centring of the critic in affective discourse come full circle. is affect itself not random. In Simon O’Sullivan’s words . then. qualified. the cultural critic has to evidence their desire to move away from that imagined chronology by choosing choice.562 C U LT U R A L S T U D I E S Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011 In discussing the same passage. the autonomy of the critic to make such a choice is dependent upon their being the subject rather than object of affective displacement. Not only. / Affective autonomy Placing affective attachment in the context of social narratives and power relations as I have done above similarly runs counter to Massumi’s claim that affect is critically useful because of its autonomy. Fanon and Lorde’s narratives testify to the argument that some bodies are captured and held by affect’s structured precision.

124) Body and mind are thus linked but detached. p. In making this claim for affect Á its movement between past and future. p. p. potentially developing in different directions. it experiences for itself affects that are not simply effects of the body. Massumi is thus suggesting not that we look for something outside culture. Massumi is careful to note that affect ‘includes social elements. . but philosophers can imagine (2002. an attitude or faith in something other than the social and cultural. 223). ‘you cannot read affects. or are we to abandon the social sciences entirely? In fact. 224). How then can we engage affect in light of the critical projects we are engaged in. you can only experience them’ (2001. p. we are left with a riddle-like description of affect as something scientists can detect the loss of (in the anomaly). it becomes an impassioned witness. differently affected. 17). . As befits his participation in a critical chronology departing from biological essentialism in the first instance. never fixed in the present Á Massumi is extending Deleuze’s chronology of body and mind in Essays Critical and Clinical. But the mind is the witness to the body. p. it is first of all a witness. a faith in the wonders that might emerge if we were not so attached to pragmatic negativity. and it is in that sense that the body and the affects that it distributes are ‘asocial. Much seems to rest on Massumi’s understanding of affect as autonomous. Massumi’s invocation to cultural critics to open themselves up to something that cannot be read may strike us as odd. and a return to the rigour of disciplinarity Á the visionary sciences. but mixes them with elements according to different logic’ (1996. social scientists and cultural critics cannot interpret. While many will concur with Massumi’s scepticism of quantitative research in its inability to attend to the particular. 126). then it is affected. Deleuze suggests that we might therefore conceptualize the relationship between body and mind as follows: / / / The mind begins by coldly and curiously regarding what the body does. taking them up as unfinished ‘tendencies . pastnesses opening onto a future. but with no present to speak of’ (1996. This is a useful proposition only if one’s academic project is to herald the death of the cultural turn. but precisely not the miserable social sciences or defeatist cultural studies. 223). while the reverse is not the case. imaginative philosophy. that is. Following his description of Lawrence’s unexpected bodily response to being raped mentioned earlier. (1997. but veritable critical entities that hover over the body and judge it. . p. both Massumi and Sedgwick are advocating a new academic attitude rather than a new method. thus needing the body. but not presocial’ for Massumi (1996. but that we trust that there is something outside culture.INVOKING AFFECT 563 Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011 that I began this article with.

a body connected to other bodies by shared judgements of the social. So that over time. and one that does in fact take place within a larger passage of time. but have a critical and affective life that resonates differently. Such affective cycles might be described not as a series of repeated moments Á bodyÁ affectÁ emotion Á a selfcontained phrase repeated in time. To return to my discussion of Fanon and Lorde. incrementally altering chain Á bodyÁ affectÁ emotionÁ affectÁ body Á doubling back upon the body and influencing the individual’s capacity to act in the world. My critical response to / / / / / / / / / / Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011 . The ‘maps of intensity’ that Deleuze would have us draw up in our desire to understand the individual are the shifts from one component to the next. but this is a moment only. In The Cancer Journals. Deleuze has offered us a snapshot of frozen time. forming an affective cycle in which each element has the capacity to affect (intensify or diminish) the other. 80). a text that is almost definitional in tracing maps of intensity that fashion the individual other in relation to an other social world (1980). rather than affective freedom. to argue that extrapolating from its logic that affect is autonomous. as Massumi does. Judgement links the body and the social and gives both interpretative meaning. p. that allow us to make our bodies mean something that we recognize and value. one affective cycle to the next (1997. In this context. Audre Lorde’s critical judgement of the ongoing spiral of smaller cycles of shame in response to her body and to racism is of such intensity that she is able to remake the relationship between her body. a single moment of judgement.564 C U LT U R A L S T U D I E S To conclude this essay on a slightly different note. poised above it. Those judgements constitute a political history that reshapes social meaning. Thus. To pursue this interpretation of Deleuze further. This reading indicates a return to Tomkins’ affect theory too. They are certainly not outside time. affect and judgement to inflect the social world with other meanings. If judgement is always secondary to bodily response. but as an ongoing. but what we understand as the components of linearity. it is clear that racially marked subject are not simply ‘sprawled out’ and ‘distorted’ (Fanon 1952. p. I want to develop Deleuze’s description of the relationship between body and mind here. but not because of affective autonomy. the intensity of that response must also presumably be curtailed or extended by that judgement. Lorde does not need to think of affect as asocial in order for her investments in survival to provide a different affective trajectory than the one that would deny her subjectivity. for example. ‘maps of intensity’ are maps of individual life and meaning in time. reflective or political judgment provides an alternative to dominant social norms. creating recognizable and intelligible alternatives to dominant signification. perhaps even constituting time. where it is the reinvigoration of previous affective states and their effects. rather than momentary or arbitrary judgement. but crucially tied to it. Lorde reinvents her body as hers not theirs. 64). is a misreading. these affective cycles form patterns that are subject to reflective or political. Deleuze is not critiquing linearity per se.

Manchester. London. Minneapolis. Stanford University Press. (1997) ‘Shame’. S. CA. Braidotti. Al-Saji. J. 227Á 239. D. H. Brogan & M. References Ahmed. Butler. (1997) The Queen of America Goes to Washington City: Essays on Sex and Citizenship. (1994) Nomadic Subjects: Embodiment and Sexual Difference in Contemporary Feminist Theory. A. 7. Cambridge. Columbia University Press. pp. K. Durham. no. Butler. (1997a) The Psychic Life of Power: Theories in Subjection. pp. to illustrate how affect might usefully be pedagogically investigated. vol. 3. Routledge. A. New York. Smith & M. (2002) Metamorphoses: Towards a Materialist Theory of Becoming. Duke University Press. eds W. eds A. in ‘Philosophy in body. Butler. (1990) Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity. as providing a break in both the social and in critics’ engagements with the nature of the social. Berlant. A. University of Minnesota Press. The problems in Massumi and Sedgwick discussed in this article do not require a wholesale rejection of affect’s relevance to cultural theory. R. R. Manchester University Press. J. J. London. 265Á 277. 12. New York. trans. A. Biddle. culture and time: selected studies in phenomenology and existential philosophy’. A. W. 26. 26. Philosophy Today. pp. / / / / . Corporeality. (1997) Essays Critical and Clinical. Kottman. L. Polity Press. vols 52/53. A. Note Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011 1 Richard Langston (2005) takes up this capacity of affect to re-embed or unsettle cultural stereotypes and investments in the context of the foreign language classroom. Social Text. Textuality. Instead. Australian Feminist Studies. in Body Matters: Feminism. (2000) ‘Laughter in the aisles: affect and power in contemporary theoretical and cultural discourse’. Stanford. (2000) ‘Embodying strangers’. Deleuze. then. vol. Keane. Cavarero. vol. P. Bhabha. Simons. (2000) Relating Narratives: Storytelling and Selfhood. Greco. Braidotti. (1994) The Location of Culture. Routledge. 5Á 23. 85Á 96. Studies in American Humor. affect might in fact be valuable precisely to the extent that it is not autonomous. Routledge. J. (2000) ‘The site of affect in Husserl’s phenomenology’. trans. Horner & A. G. J. (1997b) ‘Merely cultural’. pp. is not one that rejects the importance of affect for cultural theory. Bruns.INVOKING AFFECT 565 Massumi and Sedgwick’s work on affect. no. It is one that rejects the contemporary fascination with affect as outside social meaning.

Pluto Press. 283Á 293. Massumi. Harding. (1999) The Feminist Standpoint Revisited and Other Essays. no. Mitchell. Williams & L. 183Á 201. Blackwell. A. S. no. New York. in his (1991) ‘‘Black Skins. H. 77Á 99. San Francisco. 24. Michigan Quarterly Review. 26. Indiana University Press. and anger’. 217Á 239. pp. pp. Fraser. 6. (2001) ‘Why a materialist feminism is (still) possible and necessary’. New York. Affect. (1980) The Cancer Journals. Critical Inquiry. and Robertson. pp. A. R. (1994) ‘Identity and its discontents: women and the nation’. S. (1991) ‘Situated knowledges: the science question in feminism and the privilege of the partial perspective’. B. Women in German Yearbook. A. gendered bodies. / / / / / / / / / / / Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011 . vol. S. misrecognition. A. (1984) ‘Eye to eye: black women. in her Simians. Halperin. Lorde. Aunt Lute Books. Miller. Routledge. Ithaca. N. Haraway. Kandyoti. Gubar. Bloomington. 41. London. no. and teaching cross-cultural difference at the millennium’. Jackson. J. in her Sister Outsider: Essays and Speeches by Audre Lorde. Consciousness and the Politics of Empowerment. The European Journal of Women’s Studies. The Crossing Press. Duke University Press. New York. (1952) ‘The fact of blackness’. and capitalism: a response to Judith Butler’. Patton. White Masks’’. Hartsock. E. F. Columbia University Press. pp. no. (2002) Parables for the Virtual: Movement. Massumi. (1999) ‘Public affects: clues towards a political practice of singularity’. F. Berkeley. 376Á 391. eds P. Lorde. vols 52/3. CO. (1994) Volatile Bodies: Toward a Corporeal Feminism. (1998) ‘What ails feminist criticism?’. in Colonial Discourse and Postcolonial Theory: a Reader. (1997) ‘Heterosexism. NY. Durham. vol. D. (1999) ‘Affective labor’. 2. Sensation. Hill Collins. D. Westview Press. 149Á 160. Women’s Studies International Forum. 2. P. Cyborgs and Women: the Reinvention of Nature.. vol. 3Á 4. A. ed. London. pp. Neilson. D. Boundary 2. B. vol. Freedom. (eds) (2002) The Feminist Seventies. Langston. (2005) ‘Feels like teen spirit: affect. pp. (1996) ‘The autonomy of affect’. hatred. University of California Press.566 C U LT U R A L S T U D I E S Fanon. York. Raw Nerve Books. (2000) Black Feminist Thought: Knowledge. (1986) The Science Question in Feminism. CA. Kaloski. Cornell University Press. (2002) ‘Homosexuality’s closet’. in Deleuze: a Critical Reader. Hardt. 24. 89Á 100. Social Text. CA. E. M. (1988) The Novel and the Police. Boulder. Oxford. 279Á 289. pp. (2000) Mad Men and Medusas: Reclaiming Hysteria and the Effects of Sibling Relationship Upon the Human Condition.. pp. P. D. N. Graham. Grosz. Chrisman. pp. IN. vol. Allen Lane. 1. 878Á 902. Giardini. Routledge. pp. 21Á 54. forthcoming.

A. (1997) ‘Feminist theory: capital F. Duke University Press. G. (1993) ‘Woman in difference’. no. pp. pp. Cambridge. no. vol. S. & Wise. 13Á 28. New York. Consciousness Á Vol II: The Negative Affects. affect and the politics of style’. (1993) The Body and Social Theory. Performativity. & Frank. Columbia University Press. Probyn. in her Outside in the Teaching Machine. 3. 54Á 76. capital T’. (2001) ‘The aesthetics of affect: thinking art beyond representation’. L. vol. 3. Berkeley. (2000) ‘But the Empress has no clothes! Some awkward questions about ‘the missing revolution’ in feminist theory’. Imagery. New York. pp. Durham. pp. E. (1990) Epistemology of the Closet. Tomkins. New York. no. G. vol. 125Á 135. 6. Spinks. E. S. MA. vol. 1. (2003) Touching Feeling: Affect. S. eds V. J. E. New York University Press. Angelaki. 3. 14. Textual Practice. Richardson. 23Á 46. K. O’Sullivan. (1979) Orientalism. University of California Press. Body and Society. 1. pp. Prosser. K. no. 15. Sedgwick. Sage. Harvard University Press. 77Á 95. 531Á 546. (1998) Second Skins: the Body Narratives of Transsexuality. Shilling.INVOKING AFFECT 567 Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 17:47 14 March 2011 Munt. (2001) ‘Thinking the post-human: literature. Stanley. / / / / / / / / / . Springer Publishing. Pedagogy. no. Random House. Feminist Theory. New York. Durham. (2000) ‘Shaming bodies: dynamics of shame and pride’. pp. Routledge. Spivak. Stacey. London. in Introducing Women’s Studies: Feminist Theory and Practice. J. Sedgwick. Robinson & D. pp. K. (1999) A Critique of Postcolonial Reason: Toward a History of the Vanishing Present. Said. (1995) ‘Shame in the cybernetic fold: reading Silvan Tomkins’. C. C. (2000) ‘Shame/pride dichotomies in Queer As Folk’. E. S. Sedgwick. vol. CA. 6. pp. Spivak. (1963) Affect. E. 1. 261Á 288. New York. 1Á 28. E. Textual Practice. Duke University Press. C. in their (eds) Shame and Its Sisters: A Silvan Tomkins Reader.