You are on page 1of 14

voiUxi 8, No.

¸
x.v zoo8
Reid’s Defense
of Common Sense
P. D. Magnus
University at Albany, SUNY
© zoo8 P. D. Magnus
<www.philosophersimprint.org/oo8oo¸/>
¡. Reid misread
Thomas Reid’s reply to scepticism involves an appeal to common sense.
Since he often claims that no defense of common sense is required, he
is sometimes misread as claiming that no defense could be given. Yet
Reid does defend common sense. This paper explores how he does so.
Before engaging Reid directly, however, I want to consider two other
ways in which Reid is sometimes misread.
First, Norman Daniels (rq;¸) reads Reid as follows: Reid finds com-
mon sense to be trustworthy only because it is given to us by a be-
nevolent God. Trust in common sense thus relies on theological prem-
ises, but these are no more secure than the claims that common sense
is meant to support. Daniels writes, “Reid’s only defense against the
skeptical outcome … that our constitutions might lead us to systemati-
cally false beliefs … is his belief that God would not deceive us.”
l

Second, Philip de Bary (zooz) understands Reid as a reliabilist.
Understood in this way, Reid’s position is that common sense is justi-
fied because it reliably leads to true belief. Common sense would be
justified regardless of whether or why we accepted it, but there is this
further question: Why should we believe that common sense is justi-
fied? It is justified if it will reliably lead us to the truth, but why believe
that? The claim that our natural faculties are reliable is what DeBary
calls the Truth Claim. We can assert the Truth Claim, but we cannot
give a non-circular defense of it.
On both of these readings, the defense of common sense is an ar-
gument from explicit, metaphysical premises. We can then ask for a
defense of the premises, but none can be given. I argue in what follows
that both approaches misunderstand Reid’s defense of common sense.
Admittedly, Reid does think that common sense can be trusted and
that it is given to us by a benevolent deity. Yet, I will argue, he does
r. P. rr;. Another theological reading is given by Brookes who, in his introduc-
tion to Reid (r;6¸), portrays Reid as a ‘Providential Naturalist.’ On Brookes’
view, this appeal to the Almighty is secured by a kind of inference to the
best explanation.
Imprint
Philosophers’
i. i. x.oNUs Reid’s Defense of Common Sense
iniiosoinins’ ixiniN+ – z – voi. 8, No. ¸ (x.v zoo8)
to the truth. His appeals to “the Almighty”
3
may seem like Descartes’
conclusion that we can trust our faculties because we are endowed
with them by a benevolent God the creator. For Descartes, this trust
is the conclusion of an argument meant to escape scepticism. Indeed,
both Reid and Descartes hold that perception is a source of epistemic
authority separate from reason. However, there are several important
diferences. For Reid, trust in our faculties comes at the beginning of
enquiry. If we do not begin by placing some trust in our senses, he
thinks, we will be impotent against the sceptic. Reid insists that reason
and perception are both to be trusted and, moreover, should serve as
correctives for one another.
Clearly with Descartes in mind, Reid says of the sceptic, “[T]hough
in other respects he may be a very good man, as a man may be who
believes he is made of glass; yet, surely he hath a soft place in his
understanding, and hath been hurt by much thinking” (Inq, ch. j §;,
p. 68). He says elsewhere that while the sceptic is in some ways like a
lunatic, in other ways he does not difer from anyone else:
A remarkable deviation from [the principles of common
sense], arising from a disorder in the constitution, is what
we call lunacy; as when a man believes that he is made of
glass. When a man sufers himself to be reasoned out of
the principles of common sense, by metaphysical argu-
ments, we may call this metaphysical lunacy; which difers
from other species of the distemper in this, that it is not
continued, but intermittent: it is apt to seize the patient
in solitary and speculative moments; but, when he enters
into society, Common Sense recovers her authority.
4
(Inq,
ch. ;.¸, p. zrj–6)
¸. (Inq, ch. ;.¸, p. zrj) Also “that almighty Author” (Inq, ch. j §;, p. 68), “the
Author of my being” (ch. 6 §zo, r;o), etc.
¸. Reid’s example of a mad belief — believing that you are made of glass — is
clearly meant to echo Descartes’ First Meditation list of what madmen believe.
Reid also makes the same point elsewhere, in the context of considering
Cartesian doubt explicitly: “Can any man prove that his consciousness may
not think the former because of the latter; that is, he does not think
that trust in common sense is something which we ought to deduce
from the existence of God. Also admittedly, Reid thinks that common
sense is a reliable guide to the truth. Yet he does not think that this is
required as a premise to justify our trust in common sense; quite the
contrary, he thinks we should trust common sense even if it were unre-
liable. In short, I argue that Reid’s defense of common sense is not an
argument from dogmatically held premises — not premises about God,
about our own capacities, or about anything else.
The next two sections explore Reid’s defense of common sense. I
distinguish four arguments: (i) the argument from madness, (ii) the
argument from natural faculties, (iii) the argument from impotence,
and (iv) the argument from practical commitment. One may worry
that there are indefensible premises lurking in these arguments. The
subsequent section makes this worry precise by reconstructing the ar-
guments in contemporary Bayesian terms. “Indefensible premises” can
be formally characterized in the Bayesian framework, allowing us to
see that some of Reid’s arguments do not require them.
2. NaturaI tacuIties
Reid insists that belief in an external world is something he is led to
as “the immediate efect of [his] constitution” (Inq, ch. 6 §zo, p. r68).
2

He explains:
The sceptic asks me, Why do you believe the existence of
the external object which you perceive? This belief, sir, is
none of my manufacture; it came from the mint of Nature;
it bears her image and superscription; and, if it is not right,
the fault is not mine: I even took it upon trust, and with-
out suspicion. (Inq, ch. 6 §zo, p. r68–q)
He trusts in his faculties, trusts that properly applied they will lead
z. In citing Reid, I reference the Inquiry into the Human Mind as (Inq) and the
Essays on the Intellectual Powers as (EIP).
i. i. x.oNUs Reid’s Defense of Common Sense
iniiosoinins’ ixiniN+ – ¸ – voi. 8, No. ¸ (x.v zoo8)
Reid uses the phrase ‘common sense’ to mean these faculties other
than reason — our senses, our memory, and so on.
5
Reid writes that
“original and natural judgements … serve to direct us in common life,
where our reasoning faculty would leave us in the dark. They are a part
of our constitution, and all the discoveries of our reason are grounded
upon them. They make up what is called the common sense of man-
kind …” (Inq, ch. ;.¸, p. zrj). By reason, for example, we believe the
consequent of a conditional, given the conditional and its antecedent.
By common sense, we believe that there are men in the street when
we see them emerge from a coach. Each warrants beliefs in a certain
way, and neither can do the work of the other.
We can call this Reid’s argument from natural faculties. It is sometimes
reconstructed as a trilemma. We can trust either (a) all of our facul-
ties, (b) none of our faculties, or (c) some but not all of our faculties.
Consider these options in turn:
a. If we trust all of our faculties, then we trust percep-
tion as providing prima facie warrant for believing
in the things that we seem to perceive. So too for
memory and things remembered. Radical scepti-
cism is swept away.
b. If we trust none of our faculties, then we have no
warrant to believe anything. Just as much, we have
no ground for doubting anything. So scepticism
would be unmotivated and presumptive.
c. If we trust some but not all of our faculties, then
which ones should we trust? The sceptic rejects
the senses because they can be fooled. Yet, as Reid
notes,
[Our faculties] are all limited and imperfect ….
j. The fact that Reid thinks of reason as something distinct from common sense
is suggested by his rhetoric throughout — e. g., that he aims to “reconcile rea-
son to common sense” (Inq, ch. ; §;, p. 6q).
We may call this the argument from madness. Schematically, it proceeds
in this way:
r. Believing P would be mad.
z. Therefore (one should believe) ¬ P.
One may object: ‘Madness’ is familiar in a pejorative use, applied
to views that we find uncongenial — views that we judge are not to be
believed. As such, insofar as the argument is valid, the “one should be-
lieve” in the conclusion is more about social acceptability than about
epistemic justification. It is more like “One should not chew with one’s
mouth open” than “One should not believe a contradiction.” Even if
we could make out the argument as one we would want to endorse,
the sceptic is free to reject its conclusion. He need not pay any great
price to deny inferences of this form. If the sceptic lives without incur-
ring sanction from the community, then his is a benign form of mad-
ness and this argument would be insumcient to shake him from it.
There is another important strand of Reid’s argument. He argues
that by accepting the authority of reason, the sceptic accepts the au-
thority of our natural faculties. If one is in the business of accepting
the authority of natural faculties, and if one concedes that perception
is one of the natural faculties, then it makes no sense to attempt radical
doubt with respect to the perceivable world.
Reasoning in the Cartesian way allows us to formulate sceptical
arguments that discredit sense perception, but reason is one of our
faculties just as perception is. Reason and perception are both ways in
which we naturally form beliefs. Why should we trust the faculty of rea-
son if we refuse to trust the faculty of perception? Reason cannot prove
the reliability of our senses, but neither can the senses observe the
reliability of reason. If we are to trust either, we ought to trust both.
not deceive him? No man can: nor can we give a better reason for trusting it,
than that every man, while his mind is sound, is determined, by the constitu-
tion of his nature, to give implicit belief to it, and to laugh at or pity the man
who doubts its testimony” (Inq, ch. r §¸, p. r;).
i. i. x.oNUs Reid’s Defense of Common Sense
iniiosoinins’ ixiniN+ – ¸ – voi. 8, No. ¸ (x.v zoo8)
if we trust our reason, but that does not show that we should trust our
reason. Reid does in fact trust both, but admits that there is no proof
that we should trust either. It is odd even to ask for a proof if we begin
distrusting reason.
Reid escapes doubt, perhaps, but does so by trusting his faculties.
Trust in a particular perception is not a dogmatically held premise.
Common sense allows room for criticism. Our senses have a positive
presumption, in that seeing is grounds for believing, but the presump-
tion is defeasible.
Moreover, Reid does have more to say against the sceptic. In the
next section, I concentrate on a rich section of the Inquiry in which
Reid gives three further replies to the sceptic.
3. 1hree turther repIies to the sceptic
As we have seen, Reid’s appeal to Common Sense — construed either
as an argument from madness or as an argument from natural fac-
ulties — is not a direct answer to the determined sceptic. The deter-
mined sceptic might still reject reason and the senses both. Reid rarely
addresses even the possibility of such an indomitable sceptic, but he
explicitly concedes: “Perhaps the sceptic will agree to distrust reason,
rather than give any credit to perception” (Inq, ch. 6 §zo, p. r6q). After
acknowledging this possibility, Reid ofers three reasons why he and
“the sober part of mankind” would not follow the indomitable sceptic.
I will first uncritically recount all three reasons and then consider each
at greater length.
First, Reid insists that he is unable to disbelieve all that he per-
ceives. Even the sceptic “may struggle hard to disbelieve the informa-
tions of his senses, as a man does to swim against a torrent: but, ah!
it is in vain …. For, after all, when his strength is spent in the fruitless
attempt, he will be carried down the torrent with the common herd of
believers” (Inq, ch. 6 §zo, p. r6q). It is no use for the sceptic to insist we
should doubt everything if it is impossible to do so.
Second, Reid suggests that actually doubting the world, were such
a thing possible, would only lead to disaster. Suppose, Reid says, “I
We are liable to error and wrong judgment in the
use of them all; but as little in the informations of
sense as in the deductions of reasoning. And the
errors we fall into with regard to objects of sense
are not corrected by reason, but by more accurate
attention to the informations we may receive by
our senses themselves. (EIP, ess. z ch. zz, p. zjz)
All of our faculties are fallible. We make errors in reasoning, we misre-
member, and so on. Fallibility will not privilege reason. Absent some
motivation for trusting reason that is not also a motivation for trusting
in the senses, scepticism would be capricious.
6

We have no reason to accept either (b) or (c); they would presume
scepticism rather than establish it. The sceptic can reply that (a) is no
better established. We might presume (a), of course, but — the sceptic
may say — such presumption would be no less capricious than pre-
suming (b) or (c).
We must admit to the sceptic that the argument from natural facul-
ties does not yield an unconditional conclusion. It is not a direct proof
and it lacks deductive certainty. Although Reid would not have put it
this way, we can think of it as being like a relative consistency proof.
Mathematicians can prove that the axiom of choice is consistent with
Zermelo-Frankel (zi) set theory, provided that zi is consistent. They
can also prove it consistent relative to some other set of axioms, but no
proof shows that zic is consistent tout court. Most mathematicians do
in fact believe that zi is consistent, but there can be no direct proof of
its consistency.
7
Similarly, Reid argues that we should trust our senses
6. The argument from natural faculties is sometimes read as a reductio of the
system of ideas, e. g., by de Bary (zooz). Cuneo (zoo¸) maintains, as I do, that
the argument applies more generally. The system of ideas does not enter as
a premise of the argument. The conclusion is that we should place prima
facie trust in our natural faculties, including perception. If the argument goes
through, scepticism about the external world is defeated.
;. Any consistency proof must suppose some axioms and — by Gödel’s incom-
pleteness theorem — any sumciently powerful, consistent system of axioms
cannot be used to prove its own consistency.
i. i. x.oNUs Reid’s Defense of Common Sense
iniiosoinins’ ixiniN+ – j – voi. 8, No. ¸ (x.v zoo8)
research into it. Not only will this reason convince me, it is reasonable
for me to be convinced.
The existence of the external world may be thought of similarly.
The fact that I cannot help but believe in an external world provides
me with a reason not to attempt withholding assent. That said, it re-
mains to be explained how I can know which beliefs I cannot help
but accept. Some people claim to be able to withhold assent from the
belief in an external world. Perhaps such gifted sceptics are diferent
from the rest of us, but how could we know? Other people at other
times have claimed that they could not but believe other, more contro-
versial things. The devout interlocutor may say that it is impossible not
to believe in God, the mathematically retrograde interlocutor may say
that it is impossible to deny the truth of the parallel postulate, and so
on. Not only would I insist that it is in my power to doubt these things, I
would suggest that their assessment of their own abilities reflects only
a lack of imagination or determination. It is open to the sceptic to give
the same reply, insisting that Reid’s belief that he cannot doubt the
existence of the world reflects only his lack of imagination.
The argument from impotence fails, then, not for a lack of rhetori-
cal or justificatory force. Instead, the problem is that it turns on a prem-
ise about some matter of fact. Worse, people are often mistaken about
this kind of premise, as the examples of God and the parallel postulate
show. Any interlocutor may respond to the argument from impotence
merely by denying the premise, and after they have done so there is
little more to be said.
Reid’s second argument is that “it would not be prudent” to be a
sceptic (Inq, ch. 6 §zo, p. r6q). We could read this merely as a fallacy old
and notorious enough to have a Latin name, an argumentum ad bacu-
lum. With even a modicum of charity, however, it is a richer argument.
Peter Baumann (rqqq, zoo¸) interprets Reid’s argument here as a
bit of implicit decision theory. Epistemically, Baumann suggests, there
is no fair way to decide whether we should embrace common sense or
embrace scepticism. If there is an external world roughly like the one
that we seem to be in, then we would be right to do the former but
wrong to do the latter. Otherwise, we would be wrong to do the former
resolve not to believe my senses. I break my nose against a post that
comes in my way; I step into a dirty kennel; and, after twenty such
wise and rational actions, I am taken up and clapt in a madhouse” (Inq,
ch. 6 §zo, p. r;o). There is a commitment in practice to the existence
of an external world that contains many of the snares and pitfalls in
which realists believe.
Third, Reid notes that scepticism about the world can only arise
after many years of living in the world; the doubt is only possible af-
ter a long history of trust. He puts the point this way: “I gave implicit
belief to the informations of Nature by my senses, for a considerable
part of my life, before I had learned so much logic as to be able to start
a doubt concerning them” (Inq, ch. 6 §zo, p. r;o). The track record of
perception has been good, and without perception we would never
have come so far as to be able to entertain the possibility of doubt.
Before taking up the question of scepticism, we have already put trust
in our faculties. It is too late to call our whole life into doubt. We are
already trusting a great deal.
If the sceptic persists in doubting after such reasons, Reid thinks
that there is no ultimate argument with which to force assent. Let’s
consider each of these arguments in turn.
In the first of the three further replies, Reid alleges that scepticism
is in some sense impossible. This argument from impotence turns on a
psychological claim. Suppose Reid is right that I am utterly incapable
of denying the existence of an external world. This does not show that
my belief in it is justified. Nevertheless, it does give me a reason to
accept that belief.
Consider a parallel case: The fact that perpetual motion is impos-
sible does not show that I ought not build a perpetual motion machine,
in the sense that it would be wrong for me to do so. It seems plau-
sible to say that neither right nor wrong attach to building such a ma-
chine. Nevertheless, this fact convinces me that I should not spend
time attempting to invent perpetual motion machines, even though
they would be very useful if only they were possible. The force of
this ‘ought’ is both rhetorical and rational. If I come to be convinced
that perpetual motion is impossible, I will also come to give up any
i. i. x.oNUs Reid’s Defense of Common Sense
iniiosoinins’ ixiniN+ – 6 – voi. 8, No. ¸ (x.v zoo8)
Furthermore, Baumann’s interpretation fails to reflect Reid’s actual
argument. Reid does not argue that scepticism would lead to disaster
conditional on there being a world. Quite the opposite. He considers
the scenario in which there is no world and in which Nature has de-
signs to deceive us. Even were that so, it would be imprudent to be a
sceptic. Quoting Reid at greater length:
If Nature intended to deceive me, and impose upon me
false appearances, and I by my great cunning and pro-
found logic, have discovered the imposture; prudence
would dictate me in this case … to … not call her an im-
postor to her face, lest she should be even with me in an-
other way. For what do I gain by resenting this injury?
You ought at least not believe what she says. This indeed
seems reasonable, if she intends to impose upon me. But
what is the consequence? I resolve not to believe my
senses. I break my nose against a post that comes in my
way …. (Inq, ch. 6 §zo, p. r6q–r;o)
Reid is quite clear that scepticism would end in disaster, even condi-
tional on the assumption that Nature deceives us.
Reid grants arguendo that common sense deceives us. Even given
such deception, he argues, we should trust common sense. This pas-
sage does more than undercut Baumann’s decision-theoretic recon-
struction; it also undercuts readings of Reid as a reliabilist (e. g., de Bary
(zooz)). Reid is so far from dogmatically asserting the Truth Claim that
he says we would be justified in trusting common sense even if the
Truth Claim were false. He is not recommending common sense just
insofar as it will lead to the truth, but even on the assumption that it
mires us in falsehood.
Baumann’s version of the argument might be revised by changing
the payof matrix. Regardless, the sceptic has a ready answer to any
decision theoretic argument: Methodological doubt is about belief but
same value. Yet there is no determinate value; it is rather as if we fill in both
of them with a number divided by o.
but right to do the latter. This symmetry means that neither common
sense nor scepticism wins out, absent dogmatic question-begging.
Practically, the situation is diferent. Baumann constructs a payof
matrix for the choice between common sense and skepticism (see
figure r).
There is an external world No external world
We follow common sense few broken noses nothing really
We become sceptics many broken noses nothing really
iioUni ¡: Baumann’s payof matrix
As Baumann explains, “The outcomes of common sense are always at
least as good as those of scepticism and they are better under at least
one circumstance” (zoo¸, p. ;j). In the language of decision theory:
Given that we prefer few broken noses to many broken noses, follow-
ing common sense weakly dominates becoming a sceptic. There are
worries about dominance reasoning in decision theory, but I do not
think any of them are relevant here. Baumann is right to say that we
ought to accept common sense if this is the correct payo matrix.
Baumann suggests that the matrix is unproblematic. He writes that
it involves only “conditional judgments [that] are not controversial
between sceptics and non-sceptics” (zoo¸, p. ;j). I find this puzzling.
The left-hand column of the payof matrix seems uncontroversial, but
I do not see how to arrive at values in the right-hand column. I am un-
certain what the consequences of any of my actions would be if there
were no external world. Without some specification of what there is
instead, absent a world, there is no well defined utility for doing any-
thing. Baumann’s argument requires that ‘nothing really’ means we are
indiferent between the two right-hand outcomes. Yet ‘nothing really’
is uncontroversial only if we treat it not as indiference but as com-
plete inability to say how satisfactory or unsatisfactory the outcome
would be.
S

8. If we were to fill in the cells with numerical values for expected utility,
Baumann’s argument succeeds if we fill in the two right-hand cells with the
i. i. x.oNUs Reid’s Defense of Common Sense
iniiosoinins’ ixiniN+ – ; – voi. 8, No. ¸ (x.v zoo8)
is a world. This issues in a conditional conclusion. The sceptic may
challenge the form of the inference, of course, by arguing that behav-
ing much as common folk do does not entail believing as common
folk do. Perhaps some sense could be made out of a sceptical lifestyle
that does not presuppose an implicit belief in the external world.
ll
If
this cannot be done, then the sceptic must concede that her practice
implies certain beliefs. She is left with a choice of abstaining from her
practice or accepting the beliefs. The argument from practical commit-
ment cannot force her choice, but it makes her pay a higher price if she
remains a sceptic.
In the last of the three further replies, Reid observes that he gave
his senses “implicit belief” before he developed enough sophistication
to even entertain scepticism (Inq, ch. 6 §zo, p. r;o, quoted above). De
Bary (zooz) reads this as a track-record argument, of the sort discussed
by Alston (rq86). On de Bary’s reading, the argument infers from the
faculties’ having led us to the truth in the past to the conclusion that
they can be relied on to do so in the future. Such an argument is circular,
because it relies on the natural faculties in collecting evidence that the
natural faculties are reliable. The debate then becomes whether this
circularity is fatal to the argument. I want to suggest a diferent reading
of the passage. Reid observes that he lived as ordinary folk for many
years and that scepticism could only be motivated in light of things
he had learned in the course of ordinary life. He need not claim that
his natural faculties have previously given him the truth. Rather, the
argument relies on the mere fact that any would-be sceptic has — un-
til now — relied on her natural faculties. The very observations which
motivate scepticism come from trusting memory and the senses.
For instance, Descartes says that he has dreamt of such and so. The
dream argument yields doubts about his present sensation because
he accepts those memories. It fails as an argument for scepticism tout
rr. Although even Descartes would not allow for such a possibility, the possibil-
ity of such a lifestyle is a central issue in evaluating Phyrronism; cf. Burnyeat
and Frede (rqq;).
not about action. In the First Meditation, Descartes claims that he “can-
not possibly go too far in [his] distrustful attitude. This is because the
task now in hand does not involve action but merely the acquisition
of knowledge” (AT zz).
º
Descartes’ method would have us navigate
the world just as believers do even while we pretend to doubt. Reid
anticipates such a reply, however, insisting that anyone who navigates
the world just as believers do is a believer, regardless of their written
protestations to the contrary. Reid puts the point this way: “If a man
pretends to be a sceptic with regard to the informations of sense, and
yet prudently keeps out of harm’s way as other men do, he must ex-
cuse my suspicion, that he either acts the hypocrite, or imposes upon
himself” (Inq, ch. 6 §zo, p. r;o). It is easy to misread this passage. In
contemporary English, “he imposes upon himself” is awkward at best.
When I impose on my relatives, I make their lives dimcult; so when
the sceptic imposes on himself, one might think, he makes his own
life dimcult. On this reading, the argument does seem to be about con-
sequences. Yet Reid uses ‘impose’ in an older sense to mean that the
sceptic is self-deceived.
l0

In the Discourse on Method, Descartes makes a similar point when
discussing how he should decide what his countrymen believe: “[I]n
order to discover what opinions they really held I had to attend to what
they did rather than what they said…. [M]any people do not know
what they believe …”(AT z¸). We should judge people by their actions,
Descartes says, because their actions most reveal what they believe.
Call this the argument from practical commitment: The ordinary prac-
tices of people who are able to navigate the world indicate that they
know their way around in the world and that they believe that there
q. Citations to Descartes are from the translation by Cottingham et al. (rq8j);
pagination follows their marginal numbering, the pagination of the Adam
and Tannery edition (AT).
ro. Jonathan Bennett treats the passage as I do in his “translation” of the Inquiry.
Wolterstorf (zoor) gives a similar reading of the argument but treats it mere-
ly as “an extra fillip” that Reid adds to (what I’ve called) the argument from
impotence.
i. i. x.oNUs Reid’s Defense of Common Sense
iniiosoinins’ ixiniN+ – 8 – voi. 8, No. ¸ (x.v zoo8)
seen. He attempts to show that scepticism would have consequences,
and demands that would-be sceptics face up to them. A first princi-
ple is connected to other principles, he insists: “It draws many others
along with it in a chain that cannot be broken. He that takes it up must
bear the burden of all its consequences; and if it is too heavy for him to
bear; he must not pretend to take it up” (EIP, ess. 6 ch. ¸, p. ¸6¸).
Nevertheless, there is an important diference between the argu-
ments in the Inquiry and those in the Essays. The latter are about first
principles, principles that are explicitly propositional, “axioms” which
enter into inference as self-evident premises (cf. EIP, ess. 6 ch. ¸, p. ¸jz).
On the face of it, this is incompatible with my reading of the Inquiry. If
Reid answers the sceptic by appealing to principles of common sense,
and if these principles are premises, then Reid is relying on explicit
premises rather than trusting in his faculties. It is possible that Reid’s
thinking on the issue shifted, but I want to argue instead that the de-
fense of first principles — on a more careful reading — reflects the same
argumentative strategies as the earlier Inquiry.
Reid suggests several ways in which first principles might be iden-
tified and defended. First among these is the “argument ad hominem”
in which it is shown that “a first principle a man rejects, stands on the
same footing with others which he admits” (EIP, ess. 6 ch. ¸, p. ¸6¸).
Importantly, Reid does not argue that a sceptic can be answered just
by noting that scepticism is at odds with some first principle. Rather, a
principle that the sceptic does accept (that reason is reliable, for exam-
ple) “stands on the same footing” as other principles that the sceptic
denies (that the senses are reliable). This is what I’ve called the argu-
ment from natural faculties. Reid’s immediately goes on to give a nice
summary of the argument:
[T]he faculties of consciousness, of memory, of external
sense, and of reason, are all equally the gifts of Nature. No
good reason can be assigned for receiving the testimony
of one of them, which is not of equal force with regard
to the others. The greatest Sceptics admit the testimony
court. But without such an argument, we trust perception as prima fa-
cie warrant to believe in the things perceived.
l2
In appealing to our past
experience of dreams, Descartes implicitly asks us to trust our memory
and senses; but our belief as to whether we are awake or dreaming
will only be underdetermined if we give up trusting our senses once
the rival hypotheses are spelled out.
This is a variant of the argument from natural faculties. In terms of
the trilemma discussed above, the sceptic accepts (a) when collecting
evidence but switches to (c) when evaluating the evidence. The would-
be sceptic has, as a matter of fact, trusted natural faculties like reason,
perception, and memory. Any justification for doubting them must
rely on evidence obtained by trusting them. So the sceptic is in the
unstable position of advocating scepticism and throwing out the moti-
vation for scepticism. Perhaps there is no explicit contradiction in this,
but it reveals that the price of consistent scepticism is rather high.
l3

4. Reid´s Iater work
The previous section considered primarily Reid’s response to scepti-
cism in the Inquiry. In the later Essays on the Intellectual Powers, we see
similar arguments, especially in the sections concerning first principles.
Reid maintains that there are no direct arguments for first principles.
Nevertheless, the principles can be defended. Reid explains: “[I]t is
contradictory to the nature of first principles to admit of direct or apod-
ictical proof; yet there are certain ways of reasoning even about them,
by which those that are just and solid may be confirmed …” (EIP, ess.
6 ch. ¸, p. ¸6¸). His argumentative strategy is similar to what we have
rz. One might instead think that for Descartes methodological scepticism is
presumed. The sceptical scenarios serve as exercises to help us shake of our
obdurate belief in an external world, rather than as arguments to convince
us that we should shake it of. Regardless of what Descartes’ intention might
have been, Reid and many later commentators read the sceptical scenarios as
arguments for scepticism.
r¸. Wolterstorf (zoor) gives a reading of the argument somewhat between mine
and de Bary’s. He argues, in efect, that perception is presupposed by a track-
record argument.
i. i. x.oNUs Reid’s Defense of Common Sense
iniiosoinins’ ixiniN+ – q – voi. 8, No. ¸ (x.v zoo8)
If a sceptic should build his scepticism upon this foun-
dation, that all our reasoning and judging powers are
fallacious in their nature, or should resolve at least to
with-hold assent until it be proved that they are not; it
would be impossible by argument to beat him out of this
stronghold, and he must even be left to enjoy his scepti-
cism. (EIP, ess. 6 ch. j.;, p. ¸8o)
Although Reid sometimes says that scepticism is impossible, that is not
the point here. Scepticism (according to Reid) is a natural consequence
of the project of doubting everything, whether or not we are constitu-
tionally capable of carrying out that project. If we could execute such
a project, then we would refuse to believe anything — but the project
presumes an unreasonable standard of evidence.
When we reason to a conclusion that we have no other grounds to
reject, we accept the argument. When we see a cat sitting on a table
and have no reason to suspect dreams or animatronics, we accept that
there is a cat. If indeed these are our natural faculties, this is an ob-
vious standard. We trust our faculties. How could we do otherwise?
How else would we form beliefs other than the ways in which we
form beliefs?
Rather than being merely psychological or practical, this is funda-
mentally rational. It involves a claim about how one should respon-
sibly apportion belief and doubt; that is to say, it involves a theory of
evidence. As Reid admits, it is always possible for a sceptic to insist on
the strictest standard. In such a case, it will not be possible to dislodge
the sceptic with rational arguments alone: What counts as reason-
able is just one of the things in dispute! By appealing to the sceptic’s
own commitments, both practical and cognitive, we can try to show
that the sceptic ought not accept such a strict standard. The commit-
ments serve as an arational starting point, but — given these commit-
ments — the force of the argument is rational. It might be nice to make
a stronger reply than this, since the sceptic is always free to struggle in
an efort to throw of these prior commitments. What would a stronger
reply be like? We could argue that the sceptic’s struggle is doomed to
failure, but this is a claim about the sceptic’s incapacities. This claim
of consciousness, and allow, that what it testifies is to be
held as a first principle. If therefore they reject the imme-
diate testimony of sense, or of memory, they are guilty of
an inconsistency. (EIP, ess. 6 ch. ¸, p. ¸6¸)
It is important to note that the sceptic is not urged to accept the plati-
tude that the senses are reliable, but rather to admit the testimony of
the senses. What our natural faculties testify is to be believed as a first
principle, which is just to say that the faculties are to be trusted.
Reid also ofers, in passing, a version of the argument from practi-
cal commitment. He writes, “Our ordinary conduct in life is built upon
first principles … and every motive to action supposes some belief”
(EIP, ess. 6 ch. ¸, p. ¸6¸). To say that beliefs are implicit in our actions
cannot be an appeal to explicit premises. Rather, our practice provides
an indirect argument for ways of arriving at explicit beliefs.
There is certainly more to be written about the relation between
Reid’s early and later works. I only mean to have argued that the inter-
pretation of Inquiry §zz that I defended above can be maintained when
considering the later Essay 6.
5. 1om Reid meets 1om ßayes
We have seen so far that Reid does ofer arguments as to why we should
trust common sense: I have called these the argument from madness,
the argument from natural faculties, the argument from impotence,
and the argument from practical commitment. Not all of these are
good arguments, but some of them are. They give us some reason to
put prima facie trust in our reason, perception, and memory.
As Greco (zoo¸) argues, Reid’s replies to the sceptic rely on a theory
of evidence. Roughly, the standard of evidence is this: Beliefs formed
on the basis of natural faculties such as reason, perception, memory,
and so on should be given a positive presumption of truth. Indeed,
this is already our standard of evidence; we are committed to counting
perception and memory as sources of evidence. Reid’s arguments will
not be an irrefragable answer to a determined sceptic who is willing
and able to consistently renounce these commitments. Reid puts the
point this way:
i. i. x.oNUs Reid’s Defense of Common Sense
iniiosoinins’ ixiniN+ – ro – voi. 8, No. ¸ (x.v zoo8)
sentences, where degrees of belief are real num-
bers. As a matter of notation, we denote an agent’s
degree of belief in P as Pr (P).
z. An agent’s degrees of belief should accord with
axioms of the probability calculus. For example,
Pr (P) + Pr (¬ P) = r.
¸. After an agent learns something, the agent’s de-
grees of belief should change so that the new de-
grees of belief (the posterior probabilities) equal
the prior probabilities conditional on the evidence.
When the agent learns E, Pr
posterior
(P) = Pr
prior
(P | E)
for all P. This is called “conditionalizing on E.”
The formula known as Bayes’ rule follows from this constraint, along
with the theorem that

Pr (P | E) =

Pr (E | P) Pr (P)
Pr (E)
Within this framework, there is no objective constraint on agents’ pri-
or degrees of belief. Nevertheless, convergence theorems are taken to
show that diferences “wash out” in the limit of enquiry. Given a suf-
ficient number of sunrises, for example, any two agents will eventually
agree that the sun will rise tomorrow. There is still a sense in which
their agreement depends on their prior degrees of belief. Suppose that
two specific agents agree after one thousand sunrises. If a third agent
had assigned a lower prior to the sun rising tomorrow, then he would
not agree with them yet. He would require more sunrises in order to
be convinced — perhaps one thousand more, perhaps one million. If
his priors are sumciently eccentric, the time-to-agreement can be ar-
bitrarily long.
l6

There is something wrong with a belief if it depends merely on
prior probabilities, i. e., if arbitrary agents would not agree on it in
r6. Earman (rqqz) provides a useful, critical summary of convergence theorems.
itself relies on a matter of fact about which it is possible to be scepti-
cal. We could instead argue that the sceptic should in some binding
sense accept these commitments, but that proof will itself suppose a
standard of proof. Not only are Reid’s arguments workable tools, then,
but we would be hard-pressed to find better ones.
For all that, one might worry that these arational starting points
are just dogmas in fancy dress. Yet they escape the worry, voiced by
Daniels, that common sense must bottom out in theism. They also
escape de Bary’s worry that we must explicitly know a Truth Claim
about how our natural faculties will track the truth. They rely just on
a standard of evidence that is woven into our cognitive and practical
lives.
l4
Yet one may worry that there is some illicit premise in these
arguments. In the remainder of the paper, I want to argue against this
possibility by considering parallel arguments that can be made within
Bayesian epistemology.
My approach here becomes somewhat ahistorical. Although Reid
was a contemporary of Thomas Bayes and was probably aware of
Bayes’ work on probability, I do not know of any place in the Reid cor-
pus where it is explicitly discussed. Reid mentions Bayes once, but in
the context of natural theology. In the published edition of Reid’s r;8o
lectures on natural theology, there is a reference to Divine Benevolence,
a pamphlet by “Boyce” (Duncan rq8r, p. q8). Elmer Duncan (personal
communication) informs me that this was mistranscribed and that the
original refers to Bayes.
Regardless, I want to consider what Earman (rqqz) has called
Modern Bayesianism.
l5
It consists of the following claims:
r. An agent’s beliefs can be represented as assign-
ments of degrees of belief to propositions or
r¸. Like Van Cleve (rq86), I understand Reid to be providing principles of evi-
dence rather than principles of truth.
rj. Jefrey (zoo¸, p. xi) provides a concise summary of the position, which he
calls “basic probability theory from a thoroughly ‘subjective’ point of view.”
Reid surely did not have anything like it in mind; on the connection between
Bayes’ original work and recent Bayesianism, see Earman (rqqz).
i. i. x.oNUs Reid’s Defense of Common Sense
iniiosoinins’ ixiniN+ – rr – voi. 8, No. ¸ (x.v zoo8)
¸. Therefore, Pr (I believe that P) is high.
Construed in this way, the argument is a disaster. An agent who ac-
cepts the argument is not thereby led to a high degree of belief in P.
Rather, the agent has a high degree of belief in ‘I believe that P ’. This
yields a belief in P only if the agent has a high degree of belief in the
further premise Pr (P | I believe that P). There is no requirement that
Bayesian agents accept premises of this kind.
l7

This formulation conditionalizes on ‘I act in that way’ and thus re-
lies on a rational constraint to establish the reliability of the senses. Yet,
according to Reid, reason cannot justify perception. So this formula-
tion fails to capture what Reid had in mind. It over-intellectualizes the
appeal to practice.
Reid’s argument is not ofered as a straightforward argument that
P. Rather, it is ofered as a tool for dislodging ersatz sceptics from their
feigned scepticism. It makes use of a connection between belief and
action. This connection is not merely a matter of prior probabilities in
the Bayesian framework but instead is built into the framework itself.
Take a step back and ask what, for the Bayesian, connects practice
to belief. Rational constraints on degrees of belief are often justified
by Dutch Book arguments. If an agent violates constraints of rational-
ity — for instance by assigning Pr (P) + Pr (¬ P) > r — then it is possible
to construct a Dutch Book: a series of bets that the agent would judge
to be fair but that would result in the agent’s losing money regardless
of what the world is like. Such arguments make sense only if we think
that an agent’s behavior will reflect their degrees of belief. More pre-
cisely, what count as an agent’s degrees of belief are determined by the
way that the agent would make risky decisions.
lS

The argument from practical commitment can be understood in
this way: The sceptic pretends to assign a low value to Pr (P). Yet when
r;. One might try to argue for such a requirement. The premise Pr (P | Pr (P) = r) = r
is an instance of the Reflection Principle; but the Reflection Principle is con-
troversial. Failure to assign a high degree of belief to this premise would lead
to Moore’s paradox; but Moore’s paradox is not a logical contradiction. In any
case, the argument so construed is not Reid’s argument.
r8. Although such discussions typically resolve around betting behavior, an
agent has degrees of belief even if they refuse to take overt bets.
the arbitrarily long run. So we have a precise way of saying, within the
Bayesian framework, whether an argument relies on dogmatic prem-
ises: It does so if it requires specifying a prior probability of o or r for a
contingent proposition, or if it requires specifying priors in a way that
will not be washed out by convergence. Within the Bayesian frame-
work, our question of whether Reid’s arguments depend on dogmatic
premises takes on this form: Do Reid’s anti-sceptical arguments de-
pend on prior probabilities in such a way? We need to consider each in
turn, but the short answer is that some of them do and some of them
do not.
First, consider the argument from madness. If we suppose that P is
a claim of common sense, then the argument is that ¬ P is mad — it is so
outré that a rational agent would never adopt it. Within the Bayesian
framework, the only way to make a belief so taboo is to assign it a
prior probability of o. Since Pr (¬ P) = o, Pr (¬ P | E) = o for all possible
evidence E. One could never rationally come to assign a higher prob-
ability to ¬ P. This relies entirely on the value of the prior Pr (¬ P). If an
agent were to assign any non-extreme degree of belief to the claim of
common sense, then there might be evidence that would lead to an
upward or downward revision of that degree of belief.
Second, consider the argument from impotence. Suppose that an
agent is unable to resist a belief in P. If the agent assigns a prior prob-
ability between o and r and yet is still utterly incapable of shaking the
belief regardless of the evidence, then the incapacity is irrational. This
would fail to capture Reid’s argument. Reid thinks that common sense
cannot be established by reason but does not think that it overtly con-
tradicts reason; it is arational but not irrational.
So suppose instead the incapacity is rational. Within the Bayesian
framework, the prior probability of P must be r. Again, the argument
depends entirely on this prior probability.
Third, consider the argument from practical commitment. We might
naïvely reconstruct the argument in this way:
r. Pr (I believe that P | I act in a certain way) is high.
z. I act in that way.
i. i. x.oNUs Reid’s Defense of Common Sense
iniiosoinins’ ixiniN+ – rz – voi. 8, No. ¸ (x.v zoo8)
P by conditionalizing on some evidence E or if P is itself evidence.
Otherwise, they are presumed to maintain a constant Pr (P). That is,
Bayesian agents remember their degrees of belief. A faculty of memo-
ry is thus a presumption of the Bayesian framework. It is crucial to note
that this is not a belief presumed by Bayesian agents themselves. They
do not observe “I seem to remember that P ” and conditionalize with
Pr (P | I seem to remember that P). Rather, Bayesian agents are constituted
so as to accurately remember their degrees of belief. This, like percep-
tion, is distinct from reason. Bayesian agents with no memory would
exogenously change all their beliefs from moment to moment. This
would be logically consistent, but nonetheless epistemically bankrupt.
In Reid’s idiom, memory is a crucial natural faculty.
Unfortunately, this captures only declarative memory. Reid does
not treat memory as primary declarative. Remembering that P is, for
Reid, merely knowing that P. Genuine memory, as Reid thinks of it, is
episodic. I remember a conference in Waco because I can recall having
been there and not merely because I know facts about it. (Copenhaver
(zoo6) provides further discussion of Reid on this point.) I do not see
any straightforward way to represent episodic memory in the Bayesian
framework.
Second, testimony. Reid thinks that the argument from natural fac-
ulties justifies trust in the testimony of others. Not so for the Bayesian.
It is natural to treat testimony, as Earman (zooo) does, as evidence
that somebody A says E. The resulting degree of belief in E is the poste-
rior Pr (E), which is equal to the prior Pr (E | A says E). This conditional
probability need not be high, so — for the Bayesian — a priori trust in
testimony requires specific values for prior probabilities; that is, it re-
quires unjustified premises.
Note that these caveats about memory and testimony apply only to
the argument from natural faculties, not to the argument from practi-
cal commitment.
In this section, I have treated Bayesianism as including a com-
mitment to conditionalization. Although defenses of conditionaliza-
tion are problematic, it is often presumed in applications of Bayesian
performing actions to which P is relevant, the agent acts as if P. The
agent is thus self-deceived in denying the degrees of belief that are
apparent from his actions.
Fourth, consider the argument from natural faculties. Providing a
Bayesian explication of the argument from practice required asking
how practice is reflected implicitly in the Bayesian framework. Similarly,
explicating the argument from natural faculties requires asking how
perception, memory, and testimony are construed in the framework.
When an agent observes E, she conditionalizes and sets Pr (P) to
the prior value of Pr (P | E). The new value for Pr (E) is directly set at r.
The new value of Pr (E) is not determined by any rational constraint.
E’s counting as evidence is a necessary precondition for conditional-
izing. As Reid might say, the Bayesian agent trusts perception.
One might object that this is too quick. The Bayesian framework
presupposes that there are exogenous changes of belief (ones not
prompted by conditionalization). Calling some propositions ‘evidence’
is suggestive, but the account gives no guidance as to which proposi-
tions those ought to be. These might be deliverances of natural facul-
ties, but they might be any other propositions whatsoever.
It seems to me that this just underscores the parallel with Reid. As
Reid would have it, rationality must be supplemented with trust in our
senses. There is no ultimate principle that can stop us from becom-
ing sceptics and refusing to accept the evidence of our senses. It is no
accident, however, that typical Bayesian models describe agents who
conditionalize on propositions that we would count as evidence. We
do trust our natural faculties, and we build this into the models.
With respect to perception, the Bayesian reconstruction of Reid’s
argument from natural faculties does not depend on prior probabili-
ties. A fortiori, it does not rely on degrees of belief in the existence
of God or in the reliability of our natural faculties. Yet Reid aims to
defend more than just perception with the argument. Consider two
further faculties.
First, memory. It appears in the Bayesian framework only im-
plicitly. Bayesian agents may change their degrees of belief in some
i. i. x.oNUs Reid’s Defense of Common Sense
iniiosoinins’ ixiniN+ – r¸ – voi. 8, No. ¸ (x.v zoo8)
Reterences
William P. Alston (rq86). “Epistemic circularity”. Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, ¸;(r): r–¸o.
Peter Baumann (rqqq). “The Scottish pragmatist?” Reid Studies, z(z):
¸;–j;.
Peter Baumann (zoo¸). “On the subtleties of Reidian pragmatism: A
reply to Magnus”. Journal of Scottish Philosophy, z(r): ;¸–;;.
Jonathan F. Bennett. Some texts from early modern philosophy. http://
www.earlymoderntexts.com/.
Myles Burnyeat and Michael Frede, editors (rqq;). The Original Sceptics:
A Controversy. Hackett, Indianapolis.
Rebecca Copenhaver (zoo6). “Thomas Reid’s theory of memory”.
History of Philosophy Quarterly, z¸(z): r;r–8q.
Terence Cuneo (zoo¸). “Critical notice: Philip de Bary’s Thomas Reid and
Skepticism: His Reliabilist Response”. The Journal of Scottish Philosophy,
z(z): rq¸–rqq.
Norman Daniels, editor (rq;¸). Thomas Reid’s Inquiry. Burt Franklin &
Co, New York.
Philip de Bary (zooz). Thomas Reid and scepticism: his reliabilist response.
Routledge, London, zooz.
René Descartes (rq8j). The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. Cambridge
University Press. Translated by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothof,
and Dugald Murdoch.
Elmer H. Duncan, editor (rq8r). Thomas Reid’s Lectures on Natural
Theology (). University Press of America, Washington, DC.
John Earman (rqqz). Bayes or Bust? MIT Press, Cambridge,
Massachusetts.
John Earman (zooo). Hume’s Abject Failure: The Argument Against
Miracles. Oxford University Press.
John Greco (zoo¸). “Reid’s reply to the skeptic”. In Terence Cuneo and
René Van Woudenberg, editors, The Cambridge Companion to Thomas
Reid, r¸¸–rjj. Cambridge University Press.
Richard Jefrey (zoo¸). Subjective Probability: The Real Thing. Cambridge
University Press.
confirmation theory. Moreover, as Earman puts it, “Bayesianism
without a rule of conditionalization is hamstrung …” (rqqz, p. r6r).
Without it, Bayesianism has no account of inference — the change of
belief over time. I have been considering strict conditionalization (in
which evidence is assigned probability r) but nothing depends on this.
The points I have made about Reid’s argument apply given the general
probability kinematics (so-called Jefrey conditionalization, in which
evidence is given a probability between o and r). In fact, this accords
better with Reid’s insistence that our beliefs are defeasible; if I see a cat,
then my degree of belief that there is a cat becomes rather high, but it
does not become an unassailable probability r.


6. ConcIusion
As we have seen, Reid does give arguments in defense of common
sense. Admittedly, they are not answers to the determined global
sceptic. They are meant to dislodge the partial sceptics (who doubt
their senses but accept reason, for example) or the would-be sceptics
(who think for some reason that perhaps they ought to be sceptics).
Still, they do not rely on some indefensible premise like the existence
of God or the reliability of our natural faculties. I have tried to make
this explicit by considering Bayesian analogues of Reid’s arguments.
The arguments— some of them, anyway — do not rely on agents’ prior
probability assignments; which is to say that they do not rely on agents
having prior beliefs of any specified kind.
20
rq. In so far as it can be rendered in the Bayesian framework, Reid’s epistemology
is a variety of what Jefrey (zoo¸) calls “softcore empiricism”.
zo. Parts of this paper are descended from material in Magnus (zoo¸) and (zoo¸)
and an earlier draft was presented at the “Hume and his Critics” conference in
April zooj. I would like to thank Stephen Boulter, Becko Copenhaver, Elmer
Duncan, Gordon Graham, Ryan Nichols, Susan Purviance, and Ken Westphal
for helpful discussion at the conference; Todd Buras and Margaret Tate at
Baylor University for organizing the conference; and anonymous referees for
helpful comments on the penultimate draft.
i. i. x.oNUs Reid’s Defense of Common Sense
iniiosoinins’ ixiniN+ – r¸ – voi. 8, No. ¸ (x.v zoo8)
P. D. Magnus (zoo¸). Underdetermination and the Claims of Science. PhD
thesis, University of California, San Diego.
P. D. Magnus (zoo¸). “Reid’s dilemma and the uses of pragmatism”. The
Journal of Scottish Philosophy, z(r): 6q–;z.
Thomas Reid (r;6¸). An Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles
of Common Sense, edited by Derek R. Brookes. Pennsylvania State
University Press, University Park, Pennsylvania, rqq;.
Thomas Reid (r;8j). Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, edited by
Derek R. Brookes. Pennsylvania State University Press, University
Park, Pennsylvania, zooz.
James van Cleve (rq86). “Reid on the first principles of contingent
truths”. Reid Studies, ¸(r): ¸–zq.
Nicholas Wolterstorf (zoor). Thomas Reid and the story of epistemology.
Cambridge University Press.

he thinks we should trust common sense even if it were unreliable. One may worry that there are indefensible premises lurking in these arguments. we may call this metaphysical lunacy. that is. he thinks. Reid insists that reason and perception are both to be trusted and. Reid’s example of a mad belief — believing that you are made of glass — is clearly meant to echo Descartes’ First Meditation list of what madmen believe. . p. The subsequent section makes this worry precise by reconstructing the arguments in contemporary Bayesian terms. Common Sense recovers her authority. ) Also “that almighty Author” (Inq. The next two sections explore Reid’s defense of common sense. . should serve as correctives for one another. (Inq. arising from a disorder in the constitution. it came from the mint of Nature. p. . ). “the Author of my being” (ch.. p.  §.  ( ) . ch. as a man may be who believes he is made of glass. –) . ch. For Reid. the fault is not mine: I even took it upon trust.  §.. (ii) the argument from natural faculties. –) He trusts in his faculties. is none of my manufacture. but intermittent: it is apt to seize the patient in solitary and speculative moments. trusts that properly applied they will lead . He explains: The sceptic asks me. both Reid and Descartes hold that perception is a source of epistemic authority separate from reason. ch. as when a man believes that he is made of glass. and hath been hurt by much thinking” (Inq. Yet he does not think that this is required as a premise to justify our trust in common sense. in the context of considering Cartesian doubt explicitly: “Can any man prove that his consciousness may Reid insists that belief in an external world is something he is led to as “the immediate eect of [his] constitution” (Inq.  §. I reference the Inquiry into the Human Mind as (Inq) and the Essays on the Intellectual Powers as (EIP). p.  not think the former because of the latter. ).  §. “Indefensible premises” can be formally characterized in the Bayesian framework. If we do not begin by placing some trust in our senses. Reid also makes the same point elsewhere. this trust is the conclusion of an argument meant to escape scepticism. In citing Reid. etc. Clearly with Descartes in mind. it bears her image and superscription. However. yet. ch. He says elsewhere that while the sceptic is in some ways like a lunatic.  §. “[T]hough in other respects he may be a very good man. (Inq. surely he hath a soft place in his understanding. In short. allowing us to see that some of Reid’s arguments do not require them. and (iv) the argument from practical commitment. moreover. (Inq. . (iii) the argument from impotence. Reid says of the sceptic. quite the contrary. trust in our faculties comes at the beginning of enquiry. p. but. sir. if it is not right. that it is not continued. Indeed. by metaphysical arguments. ch. His appeals to “the Almighty” may seem like Descartes’ conclusion that we can trust our faculties because we are endowed with them by a benevolent God the creator. which diers from other species of the distemper in this. in other ways he does not dier from anyone else: A remarkable deviation from [the principles of common sense]. . For Descartes. I argue that Reid’s defense of common sense is not an argument from dogmatically held premises — not premises about God. there are several important dierences. we will be impotent against the sceptic. Also admittedly. and without suspicion. ). p. Why do you believe the existence of the external object which you perceive? This belief. ’  –– . he does not think that trust in common sense is something which we ought to deduce from the existence of God. Reid thinks that common sense is a reliable guide to the truth. ch. and. . or about anything else.. is what we call lunacy. When a man suers himself to be reasoned out of the principles of common sense. ). about our own capacities. Reid’s Defense of Common Sense to the truth. when he enters into society. I distinguish four arguments: (i) the argument from madness.

p. Believing P would be mad. it proceeds in this way: . where our reasoning faculty would leave us in the dark... then which ones should we trust? The sceptic rejects the senses because they can be fooled. ch. . Yet. If the sceptic lives without incurring sanction from the community. The fact that Reid thinks of reason as something distinct from common sense is suggested by his rhetoric throughout — e. Why should we trust the faculty of reason if we refuse to trust the faculty of perception? Reason cannot prove the reliability of our senses. then we have no warrant to believe anything. Consider these options in turn: a. by the constitution of his nature. He need not pay any great price to deny inferences of this form. than that every man. is determined. . If we are to trust either. Just as much.  §. ). b. . p. By common sense. while his mind is sound. c. we have no ground for doubting anything. It is sometimes reconstructed as a trilemma. By reason. our memory. One may object: ‘Madness’ is familiar in a pejorative use. [Our faculties] are all limited and imperfect …. They are a part of our constitution. Reid’s Defense of Common Sense Reid uses the phrase ‘common sense’ to mean these faculties other than reason — our senses. They make up what is called the common sense of mankind …” (Inq. Schematically. We can call this Reid’s argument from natural faculties. g. . If we trust some but not all of our faculties. So scepticism would be unmotivated and presumptive. So too for memory and things remembered. insofar as the argument is valid.  §. then we trust perception as providing prima facie warrant for believing in the things that we seem to perceive. ch. . If one is in the business of accepting the authority of natural faculties.  We may call this the argument from madness. given the conditional and its antecedent. to give implicit belief to it. Reason and perception are both ways in which we naturally form beliefs. ). the sceptic accepts the authority of our natural faculties.” Even if we could make out the argument as one we would want to endorse. Radical scepticism is swept away. then his is a benign form of madness and this argument would be insucient to shake him from it. It is more like “One should not chew with one’s mouth open” than “One should not believe a contradiction.. There is another important strand of Reid’s argument. As such. that he aims to “reconcile reason to common sense” (Inq. We can trust either (a) all of our faculties. and all the discoveries of our reason are grounded upon them. but neither can the senses observe the reliability of reason. ch. and to laugh at or pity the man who doubts its testimony” (Inq. Each warrants beliefs in a certain way. the sceptic is free to reject its conclusion. and if one concedes that perception is one of the natural faculties. Reasoning in the Cartesian way allows us to formulate sceptical arguments that discredit sense perception. then it makes no sense to attempt radical doubt with respect to the perceivable world. Therefore (one should believe) ¬ P. as Reid notes. If we trust all of our faculties.  ( ) . we believe that there are men in the street when we see them emerge from a coach. . not deceive him? No man can: nor can we give a better reason for trusting it. but reason is one of our faculties just as perception is. we ought to trust both. the “one should believe” in the conclusion is more about social acceptability than about epistemic justification. He argues that by accepting the authority of reason. (b) none of our faculties. ). applied to views that we find uncongenial — views that we judge are not to be believed. and neither can do the work of the other. or (c) some but not all of our faculties. we believe the consequent of a conditional. Reid writes that “original and natural judgements … serve to direct us in common life. and so on. for example. p. ’  –– . If we trust none of our faculties.

I concentrate on a rich section of the Inquiry in which Reid gives three further replies to the sceptic. It is no use for the sceptic to insist we should doubt everything if it is impossible to do so. including perception. Similarly. scepticism would be capricious. If the argument goes through. After acknowledging this possibility.  §. consistent system of axioms cannot be used to prove its own consistency. Reid does in fact trust both. They can also prove it consistent relative to some other set of axioms.. In the next section. p. would only lead to disaster.. It is odd even to ask for a proof if we begin distrusting reason. Reid does have more to say against the sceptic. in that seeing is grounds for believing. scepticism about the external world is defeated. but does so by trusting his faculties. but as little in the informations of sense as in the deductions of reasoning. were such a thing possible. but by more accurate attention to the informations we may receive by our senses themselves. ). ch. but no proof shows that  is consistent tout court. . that the argument applies more generally. Reid’s Defense of Common Sense if we trust our reason. Mathematicians can prove that the axiom of choice is consistent with Zermelo-Frankel () set theory. provided that  is consistent. we misremember. We might presume (a).  ( ) . p. We have no reason to accept either (b) or (c). after all. Reid escapes doubt. Moreover. Fallibility will not privilege reason. . . but admits that there is no proof that we should trust either. Although Reid would not have put it this way. Absent some motivation for trusting reason that is not also a motivation for trusting in the senses. We must admit to the sceptic that the argument from natural faculties does not yield an unconditional conclusion. Cuneo () maintains.  ch. as I do. Reid says. Reid’s appeal to Common Sense — construed either as an argument from madness or as an argument from natural faculties — is not a direct answer to the determined sceptic. g. e. As we have seen. ch. For. “I ’  –– . Common sense allows room for criticism. Suppose. (EIP. ) All of our faculties are fallible. The argument from natural faculties is sometimes read as a reductio of the system of ideas. The conclusion is that we should place prima facie trust in our natural faculties. Reid argues that we should trust our senses . Reid oers three reasons why he and “the sober part of mankind” would not follow the indomitable sceptic.  §. but there can be no direct proof of its consistency. ess. but the presumption is defeasible. Reid suggests that actually doubting the world. . Trust in a particular perception is not a dogmatically held premise. they would presume scepticism rather than establish it. ah! it is in vain …. Most mathematicians do in fact believe that  is consistent. Second. p. but that does not show that we should trust our reason. And the errors we fall into with regard to objects of sense are not corrected by reason. perhaps. by de Bary (). It is not a direct proof and it lacks deductive certainty. The sceptic can reply that (a) is no better established. he will be carried down the torrent with the common herd of believers” (Inq. Reid rarely addresses even the possibility of such an indomitable sceptic. Any consistency proof must suppose some axioms and — by Gödel’s incompleteness theorem — any suciently powerful. ). Reid insists that he is unable to disbelieve all that he perceives. Our senses have a positive presumption. when his strength is spent in the fruitless attempt. The determined sceptic might still reject reason and the senses both. of course. as a man does to swim against a torrent: but. but — the sceptic may say — such presumption would be no less capricious than presuming (b) or (c). Even the sceptic “may struggle hard to disbelieve the informations of his senses. I will first uncritically recount all three reasons and then consider each at greater length. We make errors in reasoning. we can think of it as being like a relative consistency proof. The system of ideas does not enter as a premise of the argument.  We are liable to error and wrong judgment in the use of them all. and so on. rather than give any credit to perception” (Inq. First. . but he explicitly concedes: “Perhaps the sceptic will agree to distrust reason.

). it is a richer argument. after twenty such wise and rational actions. It seems plausible to say that neither right nor wrong attach to building such a machine. It is open to the sceptic to give the same reply. not for a lack of rhetorical or justificatory force. and without perception we would never have come so far as to be able to entertain the possibility of doubt. Reid’s second argument is that “it would not be prudent” to be a sceptic (Inq. ). even though they would be very useful if only they were possible. the mathematically retrograde interlocutor may say that it is impossible to deny the truth of the parallel postulate. the doubt is only possible after a long history of trust. and after they have done so there is little more to be said. Let’s consider each of these arguments in turn. and. . ) interprets Reid’s argument here as a bit of implicit decision theory. Not only will this reason convince me. ch. as the examples of God and the parallel postulate show. it remains to be explained how I can know which beliefs I cannot help but accept. more controversial things. Baumann suggests. ch. Worse. an argumentum ad baculum. then we would be right to do the former but wrong to do the latter. ). Instead. There is a commitment in practice to the existence of an external world that contains many of the snares and pitfalls in which realists believe. Third. it does give me a reason to accept that belief. This does not show that my belief in it is justified. p. This argument from impotence turns on a psychological claim. there is no fair way to decide whether we should embrace common sense or embrace scepticism. The fact that I cannot help but believe in an external world provides me with a reason not to attempt withholding assent. . Consider a parallel case: The fact that perpetual motion is impossible does not show that I ought not build a perpetual motion machine. I would suggest that their assessment of their own abilities reflects only a lack of imagination or determination. and so on. Nevertheless. p. however. With even a modicum of charity. Suppose Reid is right that I am utterly incapable of denying the existence of an external world. The argument from impotence fails. The track record of perception has been good. . It is too late to call our whole life into doubt. p. but how could we know? Other people at other times have claimed that they could not but believe other.  ( ) . If I come to be convinced that perpetual motion is impossible. we would be wrong to do the former ’  –– . That said. I am taken up and clapt in a madhouse” (Inq. Nevertheless. The existence of the external world may be thought of similarly. Perhaps such gifted sceptics are dierent from the rest of us. Reid notes that scepticism about the world can only arise after many years of living in the world. Otherwise. Not only would I insist that it is in my power to doubt these things. We are already trusting a great deal. He puts the point this way: “I gave implicit belief to the informations of Nature by my senses. the problem is that it turns on a premise about some matter of fact. this fact convinces me that I should not spend time attempting to invent perpetual motion machines. insisting that Reid’s belief that he cannot doubt the existence of the world reflects only his lack of imagination.. in the sense that it would be wrong for me to do so. If the sceptic persists in doubting after such reasons. Peter Baumann (. we have already put trust in our faculties. Before taking up the question of scepticism. Reid alleges that scepticism is in some sense impossible.  §. Epistemically. for a considerable part of my life. then. Some people claim to be able to withhold assent from the belief in an external world. people are often mistaken about this kind of premise. it is reasonable for me to be convinced. Reid thinks that there is no ultimate argument with which to force assent.  §. The force of this ‘ought’ is both rhetorical and rational. Any interlocutor may respond to the argument from impotence merely by denying the premise. In the first of the three further replies. If there is an external world roughly like the one that we seem to be in. We could read this merely as a fallacy old and notorious enough to have a Latin name. I will also come to give up any Reid’s Defense of Common Sense research into it.  §. The devout interlocutor may say that it is impossible not to believe in God. I step into a dirty kennel. ch. before I had learned so much logic as to be able to start a doubt concerning them” (Inq.  resolve not to believe my senses. I break my nose against a post that comes in my way.

the situation is dierent. Baumann’s argument requires that ‘nothing really’ means we are indierent between the two right-hand outcomes. )... This passage does more than undercut Baumann’s decision-theoretic reconstruction. de Bary ()). have discovered the imposture. g. it also undercuts readings of Reid as a reliabilist (e. even conditional on the assumption that Nature deceives us. Quite the opposite. Baumann is right to say that we ought to accept common sense if this is the correct payo matrix. This symmetry means that neither common sense nor scepticism wins out. . p. Quoting Reid at greater length: If Nature intended to deceive me. following common sense weakly dominates becoming a sceptic. but I do not think any of them are relevant here. and impose upon me false appearances.  ( ) . Practically. Even given such deception. There is an external world We follow common sense We become sceptics few broken noses many broken noses No external world nothing really nothing really Reid’s Defense of Common Sense Furthermore. He is not recommending common sense just insofar as it will lead to the truth. it is rather as if we fill in both of them with a number divided by . and I by my great cunning and profound logic. Reid grants arguendo that common sense deceives us. I break my nose against a post that comes in my way …. ch. Regardless. He writes that it involves only “conditional judgments [that] are not controversial between sceptics and non-sceptics” (. absent a world. but I do not see how to arrive at values in the right-hand column.  but right to do the latter. absent dogmatic question-begging. (Inq. Baumann constructs a payo matrix for the choice between common sense and skepticism (see figure ). There are worries about dominance reasoning in decision theory. Yet there is no determinate value. Baumann’s version of the argument might be revised by changing the payo matrix. Baumann’s interpretation fails to reflect Reid’s actual argument. This indeed seems reasonable. it would be imprudent to be a sceptic.  §. the sceptic has a ready answer to any decision theoretic argument: Methodological doubt is about belief but same value. there is no well defined utility for doing anything. Even were that so. –) Reid is quite clear that scepticism would end in disaster. In the language of decision theory: Given that we prefer few broken noses to many broken noses. ). Without some specification of what there is instead. . prudence would dictate me in this case … to … not call her an impostor to her face. if she intends to impose upon me. Yet ‘nothing really’ is uncontroversial only if we treat it not as indierence but as complete inability to say how satisfactory or unsatisfactory the outcome would be. p.  : Baumann’s payo matrix As Baumann explains. For what do I gain by resenting this injury? You ought at least not believe what she says. But what is the consequence? I resolve not to believe my senses. we should trust common sense. . but even on the assumption that it mires us in falsehood. lest she should be even with me in another way. Reid is so far from dogmatically asserting the Truth Claim that he says we would be justified in trusting common sense even if the Truth Claim were false. Baumann suggests that the matrix is unproblematic. “The outcomes of common sense are always at least as good as those of scepticism and they are better under at least one circumstance” (. If we were to fill in the cells with numerical values for expected utility. He considers the scenario in which there is no world and in which Nature has designs to deceive us. he argues. Reid does not argue that scepticism would lead to disaster conditional on there being a world. . I am uncertain what the consequences of any of my actions would be if there were no external world. The left-hand column of the payo matrix seems uncontroversial. p. I find this puzzling. Baumann’s argument succeeds if we fill in the two right-hand cells with the ’  –– .

because their actions most reveal what they believe. Reid puts the point this way: “If a man pretends to be a sceptic with regard to the informations of sense. In contemporary English. Descartes claims that he “cannot possibly go too far in [his] distrustful attitude. because it relies on the natural faculties in collecting evidence that the natural faculties are reliable. ). Burnyeat and Frede (). insisting that anyone who navigates the world just as believers do is a believer. I want to suggest a dierent reading of the passage. The dream argument yields doubts about his present sensation because he accepts those memories. Descartes says that he has dreamt of such and so. the argument does seem to be about consequences.  §. the possibility of such a lifestyle is a central issue in evaluating Phyrronism. The argument from practical commitment cannot force her choice. one might think. by arguing that behaving much as common folk do does not entail believing as common folk do. Reid anticipates such a reply. . then the sceptic must concede that her practice implies certain beliefs. In the last of the three further replies. Reid observes that he gave his senses “implicit belief” before he developed enough sophistication to even entertain scepticism (Inq. . The debate then becomes whether this circularity is fatal to the argument. When I impose on my relatives. p. He need not claim that his natural faculties have previously given him the truth. . On de Bary’s reading. This issues in a conditional conclusion.. In the First Meditation.  §. p. but it makes her pay a higher price if she remains a sceptic. The very observations which motivate scepticism come from trusting memory and the senses. The sceptic may challenge the form of the inference. Wolterstor () gives a similar reading of the argument but treats it merely as “an extra fillip” that Reid adds to (what I’ve called) the argument from impotence. the argument relies on the mere fact that any would-be sceptic has — until now — relied on her natural faculties. In the Discourse on Method. Call this the argument from practical commitment: The ordinary practices of people who are able to navigate the world indicate that they know their way around in the world and that they believe that there . It is easy to misread this passage. he makes his own life dicult. This is because the task now in hand does not involve action but merely the acquisition of knowledge” (AT ). the pagination of the Adam and Tannery edition (AT). . On this reading. If this cannot be done. (). I make their lives dicult. and yet prudently keeps out of harm’s way as other men do. She is left with a choice of abstaining from her practice or accepting the beliefs. cf. ch. Rather. Reid’s Defense of Common Sense is a world. of the sort discussed by Alston (). so when the sceptic imposes on himself. pagination follows their marginal numbering. De Bary () reads this as a track-record argument. Descartes makes a similar point when discussing how he should decide what his countrymen believe: “[I]n order to discover what opinions they really held I had to attend to what they did rather than what they said….  ( ) . Reid observes that he lived as ordinary folk for many years and that scepticism could only be motivated in light of things he had learned in the course of ordinary life. Jonathan Bennett treats the passage as I do in his “translation” of the Inquiry. Citations to Descartes are from the translation by Cottingham et al. Perhaps some sense could be made out of a sceptical lifestyle that does not presuppose an implicit belief in the external world. Yet Reid uses ‘impose’ in an older sense to mean that the sceptic is self-deceived.  not about action. regardless of their written protestations to the contrary. ch. ’  –– . quoted above). “he imposes upon himself” is awkward at best. It fails as an argument for scepticism tout . however. . Descartes says. We should judge people by their actions. For instance. Such an argument is circular. that he either acts the hypocrite. he must excuse my suspicion. Although even Descartes would not allow for such a possibility. [M]any people do not know what they believe …”(AT ). or imposes upon himself” (Inq. of course. Descartes’ method would have us navigate the world just as believers do even while we pretend to doubt. the argument infers from the faculties’ having led us to the truth in the past to the conclusion that they can be relied on to do so in the future.

). Nevertheless. . In the later Essays on the Intellectual Powers. .  ch. Reid does not argue that a sceptic can be answered just by noting that scepticism is at odds with some first principle. First among these is the “argument ad hominem” in which it is shown that “a first principle a man rejects. The sceptical scenarios serve as exercises to help us shake o our obdurate belief in an external world. Importantly. ). trusted natural faculties like reason. His argumentative strategy is similar to what we have . stands on the same footing with others which he admits” (EIP. a principle that the sceptic does accept (that reason is reliable. we trust perception as prima facie warrant to believe in the things perceived. ess. ess. . In terms of the trilemma discussed above. p. . “axioms” which enter into inference as self-evident premises (cf.  ( ) . and memory. he must not pretend to take it up” (EIP.  ch. This is what I’ve called the argument from natural faculties. p. ess. that perception is presupposed by a trackrecord argument. . So the sceptic is in the unstable position of advocating scepticism and throwing out the motivation for scepticism. This is a variant of the argument from natural faculties. and if these principles are premises. The greatest Sceptics admit the testimony The previous section considered primarily Reid’s response to scepticism in the Inquiry. The latter are about first principles. . The wouldbe sceptic has. then Reid is relying on explicit premises rather than trusting in his faculties. this is incompatible with my reading of the Inquiry. we see similar arguments. are all equally the gifts of Nature.  ch. He argues. Reid suggests several ways in which first principles might be identified and defended. It is possible that Reid’s thinking on the issue shifted. there is an important dierence between the arguments in the Inquiry and those in the Essays. . A first principle is connected to other principles. If Reid answers the sceptic by appealing to principles of common sense. He attempts to show that scepticism would have consequences. Reid explains: “[I]t is contradictory to the nature of first principles to admit of direct or apodictical proof. He that takes it up must bear the burden of all its consequences.  ch. ). But without such an argument. Wolterstor () gives a reading of the argument somewhat between mine and de Bary’s. of memory. No good reason can be assigned for receiving the testimony of one of them. Reid’s immediately goes on to give a nice summary of the argument: [T]he faculties of consciousness. the sceptic accepts (a) when collecting evidence but switches to (c) when evaluating the evidence. Regardless of what Descartes’ intention might have been. and of reason. p. in eect. which is not of equal force with regard to the others. and if it is too heavy for him to bear. In appealing to our past experience of dreams. On the face of it. One might instead think that for Descartes methodological scepticism is presumed.. ). Reid’s Defense of Common Sense seen. ’  –– . Rather. principles that are explicitly propositional. and demands that would-be sceptics face up to them. Nevertheless. EIP. p. Reid maintains that there are no direct arguments for first principles. by which those that are just and solid may be confirmed …” (EIP. rather than as arguments to convince us that we should shake it o. but our belief as to whether we are awake or dreaming will only be underdetermined if we give up trusting our senses once the rival hypotheses are spelled out. he insists: “It draws many others along with it in a chain that cannot be broken. Descartes implicitly asks us to trust our memory and senses.  court. perception. of external sense. especially in the sections concerning first principles. ess. Any justification for doubting them must rely on evidence obtained by trusting them. . for example) “stands on the same footing” as other principles that the sceptic denies (that the senses are reliable). but it reveals that the price of consistent scepticism is rather high. Reid and many later commentators read the sceptical scenarios as arguments for scepticism. as a matter of fact. Perhaps there is no explicit contradiction in this. yet there are certain ways of reasoning even about them. but I want to argue instead that the defense of first principles — on a more careful reading — reflects the same argumentative strategies as the earlier Inquiry. the principles can be defended.

) It is important to note that the sceptic is not urged to accept the platitude that the senses are reliable. in passing.. . Rather. we accept that there is a cat. Scepticism (according to Reid) is a natural consequence of the project of doubting everything. They give us some reason to put prima facie trust in our reason. . ess. Reid also oers. As Greco () argues. We trust our faculties. He writes. If we could execute such a project. both practical and cognitive. p.  ch. but — given these commitments — the force of the argument is rational. What would a stronger reply be like? We could argue that the sceptic’s struggle is doomed to failure. or should resolve at least to with-hold assent until it be proved that they are not. As Reid admits.  ch. Roughly. “Our ordinary conduct in life is built upon first principles … and every motive to action supposes some belief” (EIP.  of consciousness. that is not the point here. memory. Reid puts the point this way: ’  –– . . whether or not we are constitutionally capable of carrying out that project. How could we do otherwise? How else would we form beliefs other than the ways in which we form beliefs? Rather than being merely psychological or practical.  ch. then we would refuse to believe anything — but the project presumes an unreasonable standard of evidence. . (EIP. Reid’s arguments will not be an irrefragable answer to a determined sceptic who is willing and able to consistently renounce these commitments. Reid’s replies to the sceptic rely on a theory of evidence. that what it testifies is to be held as a first principle. ). and so on should be given a positive presumption of truth. that is to say. In such a case. . they are guilty of an inconsistency. it will not be possible to dislodge the sceptic with rational arguments alone: What counts as reasonable is just one of the things in dispute! By appealing to the sceptic’s own commitments. perception. When we see a cat sitting on a table and have no reason to suspect dreams or animatronics. the standard of evidence is this: Beliefs formed on the basis of natural faculties such as reason. ) Although Reid sometimes says that scepticism is impossible. There is certainly more to be written about the relation between Reid’s early and later works. (EIP. perception.. and allow. Not all of these are good arguments. and memory. Reid’s Defense of Common Sense If a sceptic should build his scepticism upon this foundation. this is already our standard of evidence. our practice provides an indirect argument for ways of arriving at explicit beliefs. or of memory. It involves a claim about how one should responsibly apportion belief and doubt. this is fundamentally rational. ess. If indeed these are our natural faculties. ess. since the sceptic is always free to struggle in an eort to throw o these prior commitments. and the argument from practical commitment. p. p. It might be nice to make a stronger reply than this. we are committed to counting perception and memory as sources of evidence. we accept the argument. we can try to show that the sceptic ought not accept such a strict standard. the argument from impotence. it would be impossible by argument to beat him out of this stronghold. The commitments serve as an arational starting point. a version of the argument from practical commitment. which is just to say that the faculties are to be trusted. but rather to admit the testimony of the senses. When we reason to a conclusion that we have no other grounds to reject.  ( ) . This claim We have seen so far that Reid does oer arguments as to why we should trust common sense: I have called these the argument from madness. but this is a claim about the sceptic’s incapacities. this is an obvious standard. but some of them are. What our natural faculties testify is to be believed as a first principle. the argument from natural faculties. If therefore they reject the immediate testimony of sense. and he must even be left to enjoy his scepticism. . that all our reasoning and judging powers are fallacious in their nature. it is always possible for a sceptic to insist on the strictest standard. To say that beliefs are implicit in our actions cannot be an appeal to explicit premises. Indeed. it involves a theory of evidence. I only mean to have argued that the interpretation of Inquiry § that I defended above can be maintained when considering the later Essay .

My approach here becomes somewhat ahistorical. We could instead argue that the sceptic should in some binding sense accept these commitments.  ( ) . For example. There is still a sense in which their agreement depends on their prior degrees of belief. I do not know of any place in the Reid corpus where it is explicitly discussed. Nevertheless. Jerey (. Pr (P) + Pr (¬ P) = . Yet they escape the worry. For all that. but that proof will itself suppose a standard of proof. In the remainder of the paper. This is called “conditionalizing on E. Like Van Cleve (). An agent’s degrees of belief should accord with axioms of the probability calculus. perhaps one million. Although Reid was a contemporary of Thomas Bayes and was probably aware of Bayes’ work on probability. Suppose that two specific agents agree after one thousand sunrises. voiced by Daniels. Given a sufficient number of sunrises. It consists of the following claims: . where degrees of belief are real numbers. ’  –  – . then he would not agree with them yet. then. I want to argue against this possibility by considering parallel arguments that can be made within Bayesian epistemology. If his priors are suciently eccentric. there is no objective constraint on agents’ prior degrees of belief. Yet one may worry that there is some illicit premise in these arguments.” The formula known as Bayes’ rule follows from this constraint.  itself relies on a matter of fact about which it is possible to be sceptical. the time-to-agreement can be arbitrarily long. if arbitrary agents would not agree on it in . An agent’s beliefs can be represented as assignments of degrees of belief to propositions or . there is a reference to Divine Benevolence. Elmer Duncan (personal communication) informs me that this was mistranscribed and that the original refers to Bayes. In the published edition of Reid’s  lectures on natural theology. but in the context of natural theology. They also escape de Bary’s worry that we must explicitly know a Truth Claim about how our natural faculties will track the truth. Earman () provides a useful. p.” Reid surely did not have anything like it in mind.. I understand Reid to be providing principles of evidence rather than principles of truth. .. we denote an agent’s degree of belief in P as Pr (P). a pamphlet by “Boyce” (Duncan . convergence theorems are taken to show that dierences “wash out” in the limit of enquiry. but we would be hard-pressed to find better ones. As a matter of notation. When the agent learns E. . which he calls “basic probability theory from a thoroughly ‘subjective’ point of view. After an agent learns something. xi) provides a concise summary of the position. one might worry that these arational starting points are just dogmas in fancy dress. Reid’s Defense of Common Sense sentences. see Earman (). on the connection between Bayes’ original work and recent Bayesianism. . . He would require more sunrises in order to be convinced — perhaps one thousand more. . critical summary of convergence theorems. any two agents will eventually agree that the sun will rise tomorrow. for example. Prposterior (P) = Prprior (P | E) for all P. . If a third agent had assigned a lower prior to the sun rising tomorrow. Not only are Reid’s arguments workable tools. p. along with the theorem that Pr (P | E) = Pr (E | P) Pr (P) Pr (E) Within this framework. i. There is something wrong with a belief if it depends merely on prior probabilities. ). that common sense must bottom out in theism. Reid mentions Bayes once. the agent’s degrees of belief should change so that the new degrees of belief (the posterior probabilities) equal the prior probabilities conditional on the evidence. e. I want to consider what Earman () has called Modern Bayesianism. Regardless. They rely just on a standard of evidence that is woven into our cognitive and practical lives.

We might naïvely reconstruct the argument in this way: . . Failure to assign a high degree of belief to this premise would lead to Moore’s paradox. Construed in this way. reason cannot justify perception. the only way to make a belief so taboo is to assign it a prior probability of . the argument depends entirely on this prior probability. then there might be evidence that would lead to an upward or downward revision of that degree of belief. the agent has a high degree of belief in ‘I believe that P ’. Such arguments make sense only if we think that an agent’s behavior will reflect their degrees of belief. This relies entirely on the value of the prior Pr (¬ P). Second. So suppose instead the incapacity is rational. whether an argument relies on dogmatic premises: It does so if it requires specifying a prior probability of  or  for a contingent proposition. Although such discussions typically resolve around betting behavior. Suppose that an agent is unable to resist a belief in P. The argument from practical commitment can be understood in this way: The sceptic pretends to assign a low value to Pr (P). . This would fail to capture Reid’s argument. what count as an agent’s degrees of belief are determined by the way that the agent would make risky decisions. but Moore’s paradox is not a logical contradiction. Third. it is arational but not irrational.  ( ) . ’  –  – . If we suppose that P is a claim of common sense. then the incapacity is irrational. . . Again. Take a step back and ask what. consider the argument from practical commitment. consider the argument from impotence. More precisely.. One could never rationally come to assign a higher probability to ¬ P. In any case. Pr (I believe that P | I act in a certain way) is high. Within the Bayesian framework. . This formulation conditionalizes on ‘I act in that way’ and thus relies on a rational constraint to establish the reliability of the senses. So we have a precise way of saying. according to Reid. It makes use of a connection between belief and action. Since Pr (¬ P) = . our question of whether Reid’s arguments depend on dogmatic premises takes on this form: Do Reid’s anti-sceptical arguments depend on prior probabilities in such a way? We need to consider each in turn. One might try to argue for such a requirement. Rather. This yields a belief in P only if the agent has a high degree of belief in the further premise Pr (P | I believe that P). If an agent were to assign any non-extreme degree of belief to the claim of common sense. An agent who accepts the argument is not thereby led to a high degree of belief in P.  the arbitrarily long run. Within the Bayesian framework. Reid’s Defense of Common Sense . Rather. within the Bayesian framework. The premise Pr (P | Pr (P) = ) =  is an instance of the Reflection Principle. First. It over-intellectualizes the appeal to practice. Rational constraints on degrees of belief are often justified by Dutch Book arguments. Reid’s argument is not oered as a straightforward argument that P. Pr (¬ P | E) =  for all possible evidence E. it is oered as a tool for dislodging ersatz sceptics from their feigned scepticism. Yet. an agent has degrees of belief even if they refuse to take overt bets. the prior probability of P must be . consider the argument from madness. or if it requires specifying priors in a way that will not be washed out by convergence. but the Reflection Principle is controversial. There is no requirement that Bayesian agents accept premises of this kind. So this formulation fails to capture what Reid had in mind. but the short answer is that some of them do and some of them do not. the argument so construed is not Reid’s argument. I act in that way. the argument is a disaster. Reid thinks that common sense cannot be established by reason but does not think that it overtly contradicts reason. connects practice to belief. then the argument is that ¬ P is mad — it is so outré that a rational agent would never adopt it. Within the Bayesian framework. Therefore. This connection is not merely a matter of prior probabilities in the Bayesian framework but instead is built into the framework itself. If the agent assigns a prior probability between  and  and yet is still utterly incapable of shaking the belief regardless of the evidence. If an agent violates constraints of rationality — for instance by assigning Pr (P) + Pr (¬ P) >  — then it is possible to construct a Dutch Book: a series of bets that the agent would judge to be fair but that would result in the agent’s losing money regardless of what the world is like. for the Bayesian. Pr (I believe that P) is high. Yet when .

We do trust our natural faculties. Bayesian agents with no memory would exogenously change all their beliefs from moment to moment. With respect to perception. which is equal to the prior Pr (E | A says E). however. they are presumed to maintain a constant Pr (P). and testimony are construed in the framework. They do not observe “I seem to remember that P ” and conditionalize with Pr (P | I seem to remember that P). . consider the argument from natural faculties. this captures only declarative memory. but nonetheless epistemically bankrupt. As Reid would have it. for Reid.) I do not see any straightforward way to represent episodic memory in the Bayesian framework. In this section. The resulting degree of belief in E is the posterior Pr (E). As Reid might say. that typical Bayesian models describe agents who conditionalize on propositions that we would count as evidence. so — for the Bayesian — a priori trust in testimony requires specific values for prior probabilities. that is. Note that these caveats about memory and testimony apply only to the argument from natural faculties. First. E’s counting as evidence is a necessary precondition for conditionalizing. . memory. This. The Bayesian framework presupposes that there are exogenous changes of belief (ones not prompted by conditionalization).. I remember a conference in Waco because I can recall having been there and not merely because I know facts about it. That is. not to the argument from practical commitment. it requires unjustified premises. I have treated Bayesianism as including a commitment to conditionalization. she conditionalizes and sets Pr (P) to the prior value of Pr (P | E). It is natural to treat testimony. Yet Reid aims to defend more than just perception with the argument. It seems to me that this just underscores the parallel with Reid. but they might be any other propositions whatsoever. but the account gives no guidance as to which propositions those ought to be. Calling some propositions ‘evidence’ is suggestive. . testimony. These might be deliverances of natural faculties. merely knowing that P. Although defenses of conditionalization are problematic. as evidence that somebody A says E. In Reid’s idiom. Remembering that P is. The agent is thus self-deceived in denying the degrees of belief that are apparent from his actions. memory is a crucial natural faculty. A faculty of memory is thus a presumption of the Bayesian framework. like perception. (Copenhaver () provides further discussion of Reid on this point. explicating the argument from natural faculties requires asking how perception. is episodic. is distinct from reason. There is no ultimate principle that can stop us from becoming sceptics and refusing to accept the evidence of our senses. It is no accident. Providing a Bayesian explication of the argument from practice required asking how practice is reflected implicitly in the Bayesian framework. It is crucial to note that this is not a belief presumed by Bayesian agents themselves. This conditional probability need not be high. Rather. A fortiori. the Bayesian agent trusts perception. Similarly. Reid does not treat memory as primary declarative. This would be logically consistent. Second. Bayesian agents are constituted so as to accurately remember their degrees of belief. rationality must be supplemented with trust in our senses. as Earman () does. When an agent observes E. Consider two further faculties. Not so for the Bayesian. It appears in the Bayesian framework only implicitly. Bayesian agents remember their degrees of belief. the agent acts as if P. Fourth. Reid thinks that the argument from natural faculties justifies trust in the testimony of others. The new value for Pr (E) is directly set at . Bayesian agents may change their degrees of belief in some Reid’s Defense of Common Sense P by conditionalizing on some evidence E or if P is itself evidence. as Reid thinks of it. it does not rely on degrees of belief in the existence of God or in the reliability of our natural faculties.  ( ) . the Bayesian reconstruction of Reid’s argument from natural faculties does not depend on prior probabilities. The new value of Pr (E) is not determined by any rational constraint. memory. Unfortunately. Genuine memory.  performing actions to which P is relevant. One might object that this is too quick. it is often presumed in applications of Bayesian ’  –  – . Otherwise. and we build this into the models.

for example) or the would-be sceptics (who think for some reason that perhaps they ought to be sceptics). but it does not become an unassailable probability . p. The points I have made about Reid’s argument apply given the general probability kinematics (so-called Jerey conditionalization. Bayesianism has no account of inference — the change of belief over time. (): –. if I see a cat. Cambridge University Press. Burt Franklin & Co. History of Philosophy Quarterly. Terence Cuneo (). Hackett. The Cambridge Companion to Thomas Reid. Thomas Reid and scepticism: his reliabilist response. they are not answers to the determined global sceptic. Norman Daniels. Without it. “The Scottish pragmatist?” Reid Studies. “Critical notice: Philip de Bary’s Thomas Reid and Skepticism: His Reliabilist Response”. Elmer Duncan. Todd Buras and Margaret Tate at Baylor University for organizing the conference. Indianapolis. in which evidence is given a probability between  and ). John Earman (). (): –. Richard Jerey (). “Bayesianism without a rule of conditionalization is hamstrung …” (. Becko Copenhaver. Thomas Reid’s Lectures on Natural Theology (). editors. Alston (). editor (). . . DC. In so far as it can be rendered in the Bayesian framework. (): –. Journal of Scottish Philosophy. John Earman (). Ryan Nichols. Subjective Probability: The Real Thing. The Journal of Scottish Philosophy. “Reid’s reply to the skeptic”. and anonymous referees for helpful comments on the penultimate draft.com/. Reid’s epistemology is a variety of what Jerey () calls “softcore empiricism”. Still. “Epistemic circularity”. William P. Cambridge University Press. They are meant to dislodge the partial sceptics (who doubt their senses but accept reason. In fact.earlymoderntexts. and Dugald Murdoch. then my degree of belief that there is a cat becomes rather high. University Press of America. Reid does give arguments in defense of common sense. http:// www. I have been considering strict conditionalization (in which evidence is assigned probability ) but nothing depends on this.. Admittedly. Reid’s Defense of Common Sense As we have seen. this accords better with Reid’s insistence that our beliefs are defeasible. Myles Burnyeat and Michael Frede. Susan Purviance. (): –. –. Routledge. they do not rely on some indefensible premise like the existence of God or the reliability of our natural faculties. (): –. Cambridge. Peter Baumann (). I have tried to make this explicit by considering Bayesian analogues of Reid’s arguments. René Descartes (). . ). The Original Sceptics: A Controversy. editors (). which is to say that they do not rely on agents having prior beliefs of any specified kind. Elmer H.  confirmation theory. Bayes or Bust? MIT Press. . John Greco (). Moreover. Translated by John Cottingham. Philip de Bary (). Cambridge University Press. In Terence Cuneo and René Van Woudenberg. Jonathan F. “Thomas Reid’s theory of memory”. New York. Peter Baumann (). Bennett. as Earman puts it. and Ken Westphal for helpful discussion at the conference. Duncan. Gordon Graham. I would like to thank Stephen Boulter. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Massachusetts. Parts of this paper are descended from material in Magnus () and () and an earlier draft was presented at the “Hume and his Critics” conference in April .  ( ) . anyway — do not rely on agents’ prior probability assignments. Washington. . ’  –  – . Thomas Reid’s Inquiry. Hume’s Abject Failure: The Argument Against Miracles. Robert Stootho. London. The arguments— some of them. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. “On the subtleties of Reidian pragmatism: A reply to Magnus”. editor (). Some texts from early modern philosophy. Oxford University Press. . Rebecca Copenhaver ().

Pennsylvania State University Press.  P. D. University Park. “Reid on the first principles of contingent truths”. (): –. . Underdetermination and the Claims of Science. Brookes. Magnus (). edited by Derek R. Brookes. Thomas Reid and the story of epistemology. Cambridge University Press. Magnus (). PhD thesis. “Reid’s dilemma and the uses of pragmatism”. James van Cleve ().  ( ) . The Journal of Scottish Philosophy. Pennsylvania State University Press. . Thomas Reid ().. Reid Studies. University Park. Reid’s Defense of Common Sense ’  –  – . edited by Derek R. . Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man. . University of California. (): –. Pennsylvania. D. An Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense. Pennsylvania. Thomas Reid (). . Nicholas Wolterstor (). San Diego. P.