You are on page 1of 5

The Brains Blog

CONSCIOUSNESS, DREAMING, JENNIFER WINDT: DREAMING, PSYCHOLOGY

(RE-)MAPPING THE CONCEPT OF DREAMING


JULY 5, 2015 | JENNIFER WINDT | 1 COMMENT

We spend roughly one third of our lives asleep, and research tells us that a considerable portion of this time is spent
dreaming. Yet, most of us rarely remember our dreams, and even when we do, we would be hard-pressed to describe more than a single dream per night. This paucity of spontaneous dream recall stands in marked contrast to
the diverse kinds of dreams and other types of cognitive activity that participants report following timed awakenings
in the sleep laboratory. Scientic sleep and dream research are now producing a steady stream of empirical data,
and it stands to reason that this research will have a profound impact on scientic and philosophical theories of
consciousness and the self. Yet, in order to make sense of these results, a comprehensive framework for describing
conscious experience in sleep and dreams is needed.
Providing the outlines of such a framework is the goal of Dreaming. In this series of blogposts, I will address a number
of questions that I take to be particularly pressing for an empirically informed (and hopefully also empirically informative) philosophical theory of dreaming. I start out by giving a brief and highly selective overview of changing con-

ceptions of sleep and dreaming in scientic research and in philosophy.

The elusiveness of dream recall is paralleled by shifts in scientic and philosophical theorizing about sleep and
dreaming. The most well-known of these are Freudian dream theory, which casts dreaming as a carefully disguised
and censored form of wish-fulllment, and the discovery of REM sleep in the 1950s, which marked the beginning of
the scientic investigation of dreaming, but also of sleep (for an excellent overview, see Kroker 2007). But both before and after these paradigmatic shifts, dream theories, and with them the concepts of sleep and dreaming, underwent various adjustments and renements. While the ancients viewed dreams as messages from the gods, Aristotle,
in his treatise On Dreams, provided the rst strictly naturalistic theory of dreaming: dream imagery was, he thought,
linked to the residual movements of the sensory organs during sleep. Like reections in a pool of water, these movements were clearest in the quiet of deep sleep, which consequently gave rise to the clearest types of dream imagery.
Dreaming was, in a sense, the after-effect of waking perception, and sleep, quite simply, the absence of wakefulness.
This basic idea of sleep and waking as opposites persisted all the way into the 20th century, where sleep was commonly regarded as a uniform period of reduced brain activity, a state in which we are, largely, dead to the world.
In the 1950s, the discovery of a period of sleep characterized by wake-like activation of the EEG, near-complete
muscular paralysis and rapid eye movements (hence the term REM sleep) revolutionized scientic conceptions of
sleep. Sleep was now seen to have a complex architecture, consisting of periodic transitions through different stages
of sleep. It was also thought that dreaming could be assigned its own sleep stage, rather than occurring throughout
sleep. In general, participants in sleep laboratory studies report dreams following almost 80% of awakenings from
REM sleep, but do so much more rarely when awakened from the stages of NREM (or non-REM) sleep (Nielsen
2000). This combination of rich subjective experience and high-levels of brain activity in the absence of behavioral
responsiveness and the outward signs of behavior initially seemed paradoxical (indeed, REM sleep is sometimes also
called paradoxical sleep). It strongly contradicted behaviorist sentiments and seemed to suggest that the occurrence of dreaming could be objectively measured and even predicted based on polysomnographic measurements
obtained during REM sleep (see for instance Dement & Kleitman 1957). This development threatened to dethrone
subjective dream reports, which so far had been the sole arbiter of whether a dream had been experienced or not.
The result was a tug-of-war between philosophical dream theories and the developing eld of scientic dream research. Norman Malcolm (1956, 1959) famously declared that the very attempt to study dreams scientically, independently of and perhaps even in contradiction to subjective dream reports, was a conceptual absurdity: Dreams
occur in sound sleep, and if a person is in any state of consciousness it logically follows that he is not sound asleep
(Malcolm 1956, 21). Others suggested that studying dreams in the laboratory may be the only way to talk sense
about dreams: Couldnt our retrospective impression of having dreamt be profoundly misleading, the product of a
memory insertion produced instantaneously at the moment of awakening (Dennett 1976)? If so, dream reports
would be virtually worthless for the study of dreaming. Today, most reject these radical forms of skepticism about
dreaming and dream reporting. Yet, the exact contribution of dream reports to a science of dreaming continues to
be controversial (for my own take on this, see Windt 2013 and Dreaming, chapters 1 and 4).

There has certainly been important methodological progress. There are well-established methods for scoring the
content of dream reports. Also, while early dream researchers tended to identify dreaming and REM sleep, most
contemporary researchers allow that dreams can occur in all stages of sleep. Neuroimaging paints a differentiated
picture of how the transition from wakefulness via sleep onset and the stages of NREM sleep to REM sleep is accompanied by regional changes in brain activation patterns. These shifts nicely match the phenomenological characteristics of dreamingdreams, for instance, are intensely visual and emotional and often include motor imagery, as
would be predicted from the high activation of the temporo-occipital, motor, and limbic areas in REM sleep (Desseilles 2011). Perhaps, in the future, such data can be used to predict the content of individual dream reports (for a
very rst step in this direction for sleep-onset experiences, see Horikawa et al. 2013). Or perhaps, these insights can
even be used to experimentally manipulate our dreams as they unfold. For instance, Voss et al. (2014; see also Voss
& Hobson 2015) have investigated whether electrical stimulation over the frontal-temporal areas, which are normally deactivated in REM sleep, can induce dream lucidity, or the realization that one is dreaming while one is
dreaming. And nally, the contrast between dreaming and nondreaming within the same sleep stage may extend existing work on the neural correlates of consciousness (Noreika 2009, Siclari 2014).
There has also been theoretical progress. Philosophers of mind now commonly accept that dreams are experiences,
in the sense that dreams are phenomenal states or that it is like something to dream, and they have begun to develop
positive accounts of how exactly dreams can be related to standard and altered wake states. Some, for instance,
liken dreams to virtual realities, suggesting that the sense of presence and immersion targeted by modern virtual reality technology is at best an approximation of nocturnal dreaming (Revonsuo 1995, 2006; Metzinger 2003).
Dreaming, in this view, is a multimodal hallucination that closely mimics the phenomenology of being awake. Others
argue that dreaming should rather be likened to imagining or daydreaming, or question whether dreaming involves
beliefs (McGinn 2004; Ichikawa 2009).
All of this gives rise to important conceptual and methodological questions. Where exactly should the concept of
dreaming dreaming be located on the map of concepts commonly used to describe standard and altered wake
states? What is the relationship between dreaming and dream reporting, and how do dream reports relate to other
types of evidence commonly used for the study of dreaming? And what role does phenomenal selfhood, or the experience of being or having a self, play in different types of dreams?
In Dreaming, I integrate results from scientic sleep and dream research with theoretical-conceptual considerations
from philosophy of mind and cognitive science to work towards a new, comprehensive framework for describing
dreaming. I also consider changing theoretical conceptions of sleep and dreaming throughout the history of philosophy up until the present and investigate how they have inuenced (or have themselves been inuenced by) empirical ndings. Often, these historical bypaths raise important but forgotten questions and highlight the contingencies
of currently popular views. The next post is an introduction to a central theme discussed throughout the book. This
is the claim that the analysis of self-experience in dreams is the key towards a more comprehensive theory of dreaming, but can also inform contemporary theories of self-consciousness.

References
Dement, W. C., & Kleitman, N. (1957). The relation of eye movements during sleep to dream activity: An objective
method for the study of dreaming. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 53, 8997.
Dennett, D. C. (1976). Are dreams experiences? Philosophical Review, 85(2), 151171.
Desseilles, M., Dang-Vu, T. T., Sterpenich, V., & Schwartz, S. (2011). Cognitive and emotional processes during
dreaming: A neuroimaging view. Consciousness and Cognition, 20(4), 9981008.
Horikawa, T., Tamaki, M., Miyawaki, Y., & Kamitani, Y. (2013). Neural decoding of visual imagery during sleep. Science, 340(6132), 639642. doi:10.1126/science.1234330.
Ichikawa, J. (2009). Dreaming and imagination. Mind and Language, 24(1), 103121.
Kroker, K. (2007). The sleep of others and the transformations of sleep research. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Malcolm, N. (1956). Dreaming and skepticism. Philosophical Review, 65(1), 1437.
Malcolm, N. (1959). Dreaming. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
McGinn, C. (2004). Mindsight: Image, dream, meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Metzinger, T. (2003). Being no one: The self-model theory of subjectivity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Nielsen, T. A. (2000). A review of mentation in REM and NREM sleep: Covert REM sleep as a possible reconciliation of two opposing models. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23(6), 851866.
Noreika, V., Valli, K., Lahtela, H., & Revonsuo, A. (2009). Early-night serial awakenings as a new paradigm for studies
on NREM dreaming. International Journal of Psychophysiology, 74(1), 1418.
Revonsuo, A. (1995). Consciousness, dreams, and virtual realities. Philosophical Psychology, 8, 3558.
Revonsuo, A. (2006). Inner presence: Consciousness as a biological phenomenon. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Siclari, F., LaRocque, J. J., Bernardi, G., Postle, B. R., & Tononi, G. (2014). The neural correlates of consciousness in
sleep: A no-task, within-state paradigm. The neural correlates of consciousness in sleep: A no-task, within-state paradigm. bioRxiv, doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1101/012443
Voss, U., & Hobson, J. A. (2015). What is the state-of-the-art on lucid dreaming? Recent advances and questions for

future research. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND. Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.
Voss, U., Holzmann, R., Hobson, A., Paulus, W., Koppehele-Gossel, J., Klimke, A., et al. (2014). Induction of
self-awareness in dreams through frontal low current stimulation of gamma activity. Nature Neuroscience, 17(6),
810812. doi:10.1038/nn.3719.
Windt, J. M. (2013). Reporting dream experience: Why (not) to be skeptical about dream reports. Frontiers in Human
Neuroscience, 7, 708. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2013.00708.

You might also like