You are on page 1of 7

American Economic Association

Negative Time Preference


Author(s): George Loewenstein and Drazen Prelec
Source: The American Economic Review, Vol. 81, No. 2, Papers and Proceedings of the
Hundred and Third Annual Meeting of the American Economic Association (May, 1991), pp.
347-352
Published by: American Economic Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2006883 .
Accessed: 22/07/2011 12:37

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at .
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=aea. .

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

American Economic Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The
American Economic Review.

http://www.jstor.org
Negative Time Preference

By GEORGE LOEWENSTEIN AND DRAZEN PRELEC*

The man who lives within his income reached at the end. Thus a declining series
is naturally contented with his situa- of consumption levels ought to be prefer-
tion, which, by continual, though small able to an increasing series, holding total
accumulations, is growing better and consumption constant.
better every day. He is enabled gradu- In this paper, we present a short selection
ally to relax, both in the rigour of his of findings (reported more fully in our 1990
parsimony and in the severity of his
application; and he feels with double paper) that sharply contradict the normative
satisfaction this gradual increase of sequencing rule just described. To most per-
ease and enjoyment, from having felt sons, a deteriorating series of utility levels is
before the hardship which attended a rather close approximation to the least
the want of them. attractive of all possible patterns, regardless
Adam Smith of the nature of events that are being or-
The Theoryof Moral Sentiments dered. As a secondary violation of the dis-
counted utility model, the preferences of
Planning for the future invariably re- many people are not additive. Such additiv-
quires one to choose among alternative se- ity violations often reflect a concern for
quences of outcomes. Even simple short- spreading utility levels evenly over time that
term scheduling decisions about work, play, is not attributable to diminishing marginal
chores, vacations, etc., involve choosing be- utility within periods.
tween sequences, because events that take
up time cannot be rescheduled without I. Sequences vs. Simple Outcomes
changing the timing of other activities.
Most economic analyses of preferences Several recent studies have documented
between temporally spaced sequences rely an apparently negative rate of time prefer-
on the discounted utility model, along with ence for choices among outcome sequences.
the assumption of positive time preference Loewenstein and N. Sicherman (1991) found
and diminishing marginal utility.1 Barring that a majority of museum visitors preferred
any preferential interactions across different increasing wage profiles over those that are
time periods, the predictions of this model flat or decline over time (holding total value
for determining the optimal sequencing of a constant). Pointing out that the flat and
given set of events are simple: Place the declining wage profile could produce a
best event at the start, then proceed in dominating consumption stream through a
descending order until the worst event is suitable savings program, did not have much
impact on preference. C. Varey and D.
Kahneman (1990) found that subjects
strongly preferred brief sequences of de-
*Department of Social and Decision Sciences, creasing discomfort, even at the cost of ex-
Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh, PA 15215, and periencing overall greater discomfort, while
Harvard Graduate School of Business Administration,
Boston, MA 02136, respectively. W. T. Ross and I. Simonson (1990) showed
1The applications of this model have been remark- that people prefer sequences that end on a
ably diverse, ranging from savings behavior, educa- good note.
tional investment, labor supply, bargaining, to crimi- Preference for improvement is an over-
nal behavior and addiction. In recent years, however,
its descriptive validity has come under challenge (see
determined phenomenon, driven in part
our forthcoming article, and Loewenstein and Richard by anticipatory savoring and dread (Loew-
Thaler, 1990). enstein, 1987), and in part by loss aver-

347
348 AEA PAPERS AND PROCEEDINGS MAY1991

sion (A. Tversky and Kahneman, 1990) and We anticipated that more people would de-
habit forming changes in the adaptation lay the fancy French dinner when it was
level (J. Duesenberry, 1949). Savoring and combined in a sequence with the Greek
dread contribute to the preference for im- dinner than when it was expressed as a
provement because, for gains, improving se- single outcome prospect. This is indeed what
quences allow decision makers to savor the happened. Of the 86 percent of subjects
best until the end of the sequence. With who preferred the fancy French dinner, 80
losses, getting the worst outcomes over with percent preferred a more immediate dinner
quickly eliminates dread. Adaptation and (option C) over a more delayed dinner (op-
loss aversion induce preference for im- tion D). However, when the French dinner
provement because, over time, people tend was composed into a sequence with the
to assimilate to ongoing stimuli and to eval- Greek dinner, a slight majority (57 percent)
uate new stimuli relative to their assimila- preferred to have the better dinner come
tion level. Thus, changes in, rather than later. Even with single-outcome events there
levels of, consumption are the carriers of is some motivation to defer the French din-
value. Improving sequences afford a contin- ner-witness the 20 percent of subjects who
ual series of positive departures (gains) from opted for the longer delay. However, this
one's adaptation level; declining sequences tendency is stronger for sequences than for
provide a series of relative losses. individual items.
Savoring and dread apply to single out- A similar pattern is observed when "Di-
comes as well as to sequences, but assimila- nner at home" is substituted for the Greek
tion and loss aversion apply only to se- dinner. Since most people eat dinner at
quences. The fact that two motives operate home on most nights anyway, embedding
for sequences but only one for simple out- the French dinner in an explicit binary se-
comes suggests that the tendency to defer quence does not introduce any real modifi-
desirable outcomes will be stronger when cation of the problem, but the subject is
those outcomes are embedded in sequences. reminded that the choice is "really" be-
Such a pattern is illustrated by a survey tween complete sequences. Like other fram-
conducted with undergraduates at Harvard ing effects, such reminders cause prefer-
University, who were asked the following ences to shift, in this case in favor of the
three questions: improving sequence.
1. Which would you prefer if both were
free? II. WhatIs a Sequence?
A. Dinner at a fancy French restau-
rant (86%) If impatience and the desire for improve-
B. Dinner at a local Greek restau- ment are simultaneously present within a
rant (14%) single individual, what determines the pre-
For those who prefer French: potent motive on a given occasion? A rea-
2. Which would you prefer? sonable conjecture is that the desire for
C. Dinner at the French restaurant improvement depends on the "integrity" of
on Friday in 1 month (80%) the sequence-the extent to which the
D. Dinner at the French restaurant events that comprise it are of a similar type,
on Friday in 2 months (20%) are regularly spaced, and are not stretched
3. Which would you prefer? too far apart.
E. Dinner at the French restaurant The following example illustrates how the
on Friday in 1 month and dinner integrity of sequence can be reduced in a
at the Greek restaurant on Fri- predictable way. Visitors to a science mu-
day in 2 months (43%) seum were asked to choose between alter-
F. Dinner at the Greek restaurant native scheduling of two visits to a city where
on Friday in 1 month and dinner the respondent once lived, one to be spent
at the French restaurant on Fri- with "an irritating, abrasive, aunt who is a
day in 2 months (57%) horrendous cook," the other with "former
VOL. 81 NO. 2 INTERTEMPORALCHOICE 349

work associates whom you like a lot." Each sequence, while a pair of weekends sepa-
subject made three choices, as described rated by 6 months does not.
below. Response frequencies are reported The saliency of particular intervals is not
in parentheses. an objective matter, but depends rather on
perceptual framing. By deliberately manipu-
This Next lating the subjective frame, it is possible to
weekend weekend induce normatively peculiar patterns of
A. friends aunt (10%) choices, as the following example shows.
B. aunt friends (90%) Subjects were asked to indicate their pre-
ferred times to eat two free dinners at the
This 26 weeks restaurant of their choice. One group was
weekend from now given no time constraint concerning when
they could eat the dinners. A second, con-
C. friends aunt (48%) strained group was told that the dinners
D. aunt friends (52%) must be consumed within the next 2 years.
We anticipated that constrained subjects
26 weeks 27 weeks would prefer to delay the dinners more than
from now from now unconstrained subjects, because the intro-
E. friends aunt (17%) duction of an explicit planning interval re-
F. aunt friends (83%) minds the subjects that, by selecting a par-
ticular pair of dates, they are also choosing
Observe that it is not possible to interpret not to consume the meals on all of the other
the three modal choice patterns as the re- dates. As predicted, the mean preferred
sult of a single time preference function, delay for the first dinner was 3.3 weeks for
denominated in absolute time. Responses to the unconstrained group and 7.7 for the
the first and third questions suggest a nega- constrained. Mean preferred delay times for
tive rate of time preference over a 1-week the second dinner were 13.1 and 31.1 weeks.
interval, irrespective of whether the week is These results are inconsistent with the
close or far. By interpolation, one may con- axiom of revealed preference. The imposi-
clude that the aunt would be scheduled in tion of a time constraint on an initially
the earlier of any consecutive 2 weekends. unconstrained population should only affect
Yet, for many subjects, the negative time the responses of that fraction of the popula-
preference over adjacent weekends does not tion whose preferred delays are longer than
compound into a negative time preference permitted by the constraint. The population
for the complete 6-month interval, as shown averages should, therefore, be longer in the
by responses to the second question. unconstrained condition.
Applied uniformly to all choices, negative
time preference would require harsh reduc- III. Nonadditive Preferences
tions in present consumption in favor of the
future. The fact that one does not observe Aside from a preference for improve-
such sacrifices, even given the additional ment, choices between sequences also re-
inducements of a positive interest rate, is veal a sensitivity to certain global or
normally taken as evidence for positive time "ggestalt"properties, having to do with how
preference (M. Olson and M. J. Bailey, evenly the good and bad outcomes are ar-
1981). ranged over the total time interval. Con-
We propose a different interpretation: sider the following problem presented to 37
Negative time preference is applied selec- Yale University undergraduates (from
tively, to those events that are seen as part Loewenstein, 1987). Subjects were first given
of a meaningful sequence, having a well- a choice between A and B, then between C
defined starting and ending point. As the and D. Percentages choosing each of the
previous example shows, a pair of adjacent options are presented in the right-hand col-
weekends defines a minimal but coherent umn.
350 AEA PAPERS AND PROCEEDINGS MAY1991

Alter- filler weekends should reduce adaptation,


native Weekend 1 Weekend 2 Weekend 3 Choices
A Fancy French
and altogether eliminate differential inter-
Eat at home Eat at home 16
B Eat at home Fancy French Eat at home 84 actions between adjacent periods, they
should attenuate the separability violations.
C Fancy French
D Eat at home
Eat at home
Fancy French
Fancy Lobster
Fancy Lobster
54
46
The results with the 5-weekend version of
the problem were essentially equivalent,
however: Only 11 percent of respondents
In the first problem, the majority of subjects opted for option A over B, while 49 percent
preferred to postpone the fancy dinner to preferred C over D.
weekend 2, in keeping with the improve- The problem here is that habit forma-
ment principle. However, in the second tion/loss aversion models do not well cap-
problem, the insertion of the common lob- ture the global properties that people find
ster dinner in weekend 3 caused preference attractive in sequences. The relative advan-
to shift slightly in favor of having the French tage of sequences B and C is due to the fact
dinner right away. This is a violation of that they both "cover" the 3-week interval
additive separability, which implies that an better than their respective alternatives. In
individual preferring sequence A over B other words, they interleave the good and
should continue to prefer A over B if any indifferent events in a more nearly uniform
elements shared by the two sequences are manner.
altered in the same way. We have developed a theoretical model
Intertemporal additivity has never been that measures both the degree of improve-
viewed as normatively compelling, since ment and spreading of any sequence in
there are many situations in which it is terms of cumulative utility sequences (see
reasonable for consumption at one point in our 1990 paper). The model defines im-
time to influence the marginal utility of provement over time as the sum of devia-
consumption at another. Models of the tions of the cumulative sequence that would
"habit formation" type (Duesenberry; R. A. be obtained by spreading total utility evenly
Pollack, 1970; G. M. Constantinedes, 1990) over time from the cumulative utility stream
assume that instantaneous utility depends of the sequence being evaluated. Evenness
negatively on past consumption. Other of spread is represented by the sum of the
models incorporate the rate of consumption absolute value of these deviations.
change into the utility function (R. Frank, The derivation of our notions of improve-
1989), or a preference/aversion for utility ment and uniformity is depicted in Table 1,
variation between adjacent periods, as in I. using the last illustrative example on the
Gilboa's elegant formulation (1989). assumption that the "Eat at home" event
Can the separability violation described has utility zero, and the "Fancy French"
above be reasonably attributed to some sort and "Fancy Lobster" events have utility one.
of loss aversion, following an adaptation to Note that a simple preference for improve-
a reference point? An aversion to utility ment would lead to a preference for B over
reductions from one period to the next A and D over C, while discounting alone
would seem to work in favor of alternative would produce the opposite pattern. The
D over C, while leaving preferences be- desire for spreading outcomes over time,
tween A and B unchanged (to a first ap- however, designated in the row marked
proximation). Hence it would predict the Spread (lower numbers signify more even
opposite violation pattern to the one actu- spreading of outcomes), can explain the
ally observed. preference for B over A and for C over D.
Furthermore, we have observed the same In several longer surveys (see our 1990
preference pattern when common "Eat at paper), we have systematically mapped out
home" weekends are inserted between the preferences over multiple period sequences.
original weekends 1 and 2, and 2 and 3, in The judgments of the average person could
all four alternatives (thereby creating 5- be briefly described as follows: There is a
weekend sequences). Because the neutral strong liking for improving sequences, mod-
VOL. 81 NO. 2 INTERTEMPORALCHOICE 351

TABLE 1-DERIVATION OF IMPROVEMENT than people who are given no time frameat
AND SPREAD MEASURES
all. Apparently,as soon as the relevantin-
Alternative terval is specified, a person becomes con-
A B C D cerned with shiftingthe good events out to
Sequence 1,0,0 0,1,0 1,0,1 0,1,1 the end. This result has implicationsfor life
Cumulative 1,1,1
Flat
0,1,1 1,1,2 0,1,2 cycle choices; for example, it suggests the
Seq. .33,33,33 .33,33,33 .66,66,66 .66,66,66 possibility that some individuals would
Flat
Cumul. .33,.66,1 .33,.66,1 .66,1.33,2 .66,1.33,2
choose an earlier retirementin the absence
Difference -.66,-.33,0 .33,-.33,0 -.33, .33,0 .66, .33,0 of a mandatedretirementpoint.
Improve- -1 0
The sensitivityof time preference to the
0 1
ment sequence "frame" casts new light on the
Spread 1 .66 .66 1 often-repeatedchargethat certaingroupsof
people (consumers,managers,membersof a
particularnation or culture)have an exces-
sively steep rate of time preference.Such a
eratedby a penaltyfor deviationfromglobal claim is a psychologicallyimprecise defini-
uniformness,and a small premiumfor se- tion of the problem,at best. The differences
quences that startwell. that do prevail should instead perhaps be
traced to different styles of mental book-
IV. Conclusion keeping, which will alone produce different
degrees of impatienceeven with a common
Previouspsychologicalworkon time pref- underlyingrate of time preference.Any op-
erence has focused almost entirely on the eration, custom, or habit that causes the
tradeoff that arises when two outcomes of stream of purposeful activity to fragment
differentdates and differentvalues are com- into a series of isolatedchoices, each involv-
pared. The tacit premise was that such ing a simple intertemporal tradeoff, and
judgmentswill reveal an individual's"raw" each unrelatedto a largerplan, encourages
time preference,from which one can then impatientchoices. Whereas the integralse-
synthesize preferences over more complex quence frame,by fusingevents into a coher-
objects-retirement plants, intertemporal ent sequence, promotesconcernfor the fu-
income profiles,and such. This view we feel ture, thereby creating an appearance of
is fundamentallyincorrect:As soon as an negativetime preference.
intertemporaltradeoff is embedded in the
context of two alternativesequencesof out- REFERENCES
comes, the psychological perspective, or
"frame"shifts,and individualsbecomemore Constantinides,G. M., "Habit Formation: A
farsighted,usuallywishing to postpone the Resolution of the Equity Premium Puz-
better outcome to the end. The same per- zle," Journal of Political Economy, June
son who prefersa good dinnersoonerrather 1990, 98, 519-43.
than later, if given a choice between two Duesenberry,J., Income, Saving, and the
explicitlyformulatedsequences,one consist- Theory of Consumer Behavior, Cam-
ing of a good dinner followed by an indif- bridge: Harvard University Press, 1949.
ferent one, the other of the indifferentdin- Frank, R., "Frames of Reference and the
ner followed by the good one, may well Quality of Life," American Economic Re-
prefer the latter alternative.Sequences of view Proceedings, May 1989, 79, 80-85.
outcomes that decline in value are greatly Gilboa, I., "Expectation and Variation in
disliked, indicatinga negative rate of time Multi-Period Decisions," Econometrica,
preference. September 1989, 57, 1153-69.
A byproduct of the sequence frame is Loewenstein,G., "Anticipation and the Valu-
that subjectswho are given a time interval, ation of Delayed Consumption," Eco-
within which to schedule some enjoyable nomic Journal, September 1987, 97,
activity, may schedule it later on average 666-84.
352 AEA PAPERS AND PROCEEDINGS MAY1991

and Prelec, D., "Anomalies in In- 745-63.


tertemporal Choice: Evidence and an In- Olson, M. and Bailey, M. J., "Positive Time
terpretation," Quarterly Journal of Eco- Preference," Journal of Political Econ-
nomics, forthcoming. omy, February 1981, 89, 1-25.
and , "Preferences over Out- Ross, W. T., Jr. and Simonson, I., "Consumers'
come Sequences," Harvard Business Evaluation of Purchase and Consumption
School Working Paper, 1990. Experiences: A Preference for Happy
and Sicherman, N., "Do Workers Pre- Endings," unpublished manuscript, 1990.
fer Increasing Wage Profiles?," Journal of Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D., "Reference
Labor Economics, January 1991, 9. Theory of Choice and Exchange," unpub-
and Thaler, R., "Anomalies: In- lished working paper, 1990.
tertemporal Choice," Journal of Eco- Varey,C. and Kahneman,D., "The Integration
nomic Perspectives, Fall 1989, 3, 181-93. of Aversive Experiences Over Time: Nor-
Pollak, R. A., "Habit Formation and Dy- mative Considerations and Lay Intu-
namic Demand Functions," Journal of itions," working paper, University of Cali-
Political Economy, July/August 1970, 78, fornia-Berkeley, 1990.

You might also like