Citation:
Alpana Roy, Intellectual Property Rights: A Western
Tale, 16 Asia Pac. L. Rev. 219 (2008)
Copyright Information
Alpana Roy
Abstract
Even today, when the development and expansion of intellectual property
protections is justified or criticised, the Western philosophical tradition is
generally evoked. Appeals to natural rights, Lockean labour theories of property
and Kantian or Hegelian theories of personality abound. Alternatively, economic
principles and utilitarian rationales are drawn upon to rationalise or question
intellectual property laws as incentive structures that produce a socially optimal
supply of intellectual creations. In both these moral and utilitarian arguments,
scholars address intellectual property laws purely abstractly, as promoting reified
rights in unremarkable and indistinguishable intangibles.'
1. Introduction
Lecturer, Faculty of Law, University of Technology, Sydney. BA (UTS), LLB (Hons) (Syd),
MA (Journalism) (UTS), DipLegPrac (College of Law), PhD (Syd), GCHETL (UTS),
Barrister of the Supreme Court of NSW and the High Court of Australia.
Rosemary J Coombe, The CulturalLife ofIntellectual Properties:Authorship,Appropriation,
and the Law (Duke University Press, Durham and London, 1998) p 7.
Ibid.
219
220 ALPANA ROY
liberalism, have been embodied into the substance of this area of law. And
concepts which are integral to a liberal understanding of intellectual property
law (such as 'private property', 'authorship', and 'possessive individualism') are
Western and modern constructs, as opposed to universal ones. Indeed, the law
in this area has taken for granted certain basic categories and constructions the
foundations of which are uncontested, and which through colonialism have now
gained the status of universal truths. By illustrating that categories we consider
as 'natural' have actually been culturally produced in hierarchies and structures
of difference, a major aim of this article is also to trace the ideological operations
of intellectual property law.
Coombe notes above that the laws of intellectual property are usually
addressed by scholars 'purely abstractly'. 3 As the history of Western intellectual
property law is far from a universal experience, this is clearly an area which could
benefit from further contextual analysis. Christopher May observes that legal
scholars are generally rather parochial in their analysis of intellectual property
rights, and tend to focus on the specifics of intellectual property law rather
than the broader global political context in which these rights are situated.' In
this way, legal scholars are unlike their non-legal counterparts, who are often
aware of both the legal and non-legal debates surrounding intellectual property
rights.' A contextual analysis of intellectual property is important, as it furthers
our understanding on how discourses (such as law) are internally categorised,
and epistemologically and ontologically structured. As Peter Drahos suggests,
'[t]he law's own internal taxonomic structures may help us to understand the
character of intellectual property rights, especially if this legal character is itself
based on some pre-existing philosophical idea or influence.' As the Western
idea of intellectual property is not universal, it is important to be sensitive to the
particular world view(s) which continue to motivate intellectual property rights
' Ibid.
4 Christopher May, 'Why IPRs are a Global Political Issue', 25(1) European Intellectual
Property Review 1-5, 1 (January 2003). Although, Bently and Maniatis assert that while
intellectual property discourse has traditionally been fairly doctrinal and dry in its
approach, there has recently been a burgeoning of interdisciplinary studies in intellectual
property, in areas such as cultural studies and history. See Lionel Bently and Spyros
M Maniatis, 'Introduction' in Lionel Bently and Spyros M Maniatis (eds), Intellectual
PropertyandEthics (Sweet & Maxwell, London, 1998), vii-xi, vii. Ostergard also suggests
that the increasingly global and interdependent nature of these rights have placed them
firmly within the domain of politics and economics, and not just in the narrower sphere
of the law. See Robert L Jr Ostergard, The Development Dilemma: the PoliticalEconomy
of IntellectualProperty Rights in the InternationalSystem (LFB Scholarly Publishing LLC,
New York, 2003) pp 1-2.
SMay, Ibid, p 1.-
6 Peter Drahos, A Philosophy of Intellectual Property (Dartmouth, Brookfield USA, 1996)
p 14.
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS: A WESTERN TALE 221
on a global scale, and also be wary of the status that these laws have assumed for
themselves through international agreements such as TRIPS.
The purpose of this article is two-fold. Firstly, as intellectual property is
far from a global experience, I wish to excavate its essentially Westcentric
genealogies and foundations (as I am uneasy by its claims of apparent
universality). Secondly, due to the proliferation, and indeed, globalisation of
intellectual property rights, the purpose of this article is also to trace the Western
philosophical theories which have traditionally been used to both justify and
criticise expanding rights in intellectual property. Indeed, both the justifications
and the criticisms of expanding rights in intellectual property form part of the
same Western dialectic. In doing so, I hope that this article will contribute
towards scholarship which encourages a more contextual and expanded
understanding of the concept of intellectual property law.
10 Ibid, p 5.
" Sam Ricketson and Megan Richardson, Intellectual Property: Cases, Materials and
Commentary (LexisNexis Butterworths, Sydney, 2005), pp 5-6. See further Ostergard,
op cit note 4, p 12.
12 See A Bogsch, Brief History of the First 25 Years of the World Intellectual Property
Organization (Geneva: WIPO, 1992) p 8. See also Georges Koumantos, 'Reflections
on the Concept of Intellectual Property' in Jan JC Kabel and Gerard JHM Mom (eds),
IntellectualPropertyand Information Law: Essays in Honour of Herman Cohen Jehoram (The
Hague: Kluwer Law International 1998), 39-45, 39.
13 WIPO was established in 1967, and is one of the intergovernmental organisations
administered under the UN. For further information, see World InternationalProperty
Organization:http://www.wipo.int/portal/index.html.en (retrieved 9 September 2007).
1 The full text of the TRIPS Agreement is available online. See note 7 above.
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS: A WESTERN TALE 223
15 Ibid.
16 Ibid.
17 Ibid.
1 Ibid.
19 For example, see Peter Drahos' philosophical analysis of intellectual property using both
Hegelian and Marxist approaches, op cit note 6, pp 73-117.
20 For example, Alford suggests that intellectual property issues can be traced back to the
Chinese Zhou dynasty (1122 BC) where issues of commodity identification arose. See
William P Alford, To Steal a Book is an Elegant Offense: Intellectual Property Law in
Chinese Civilization (Stanford University Press, Standford, 1995).
224 ALPANA ROY
21 See Drahos, op cit note 6, pp 41-72. See further Edwin C Hettinger, 'Justifying
Intellectual Property' (1989), 18 Philosophy and Public Affairs, pp 31-52; Justin Hughes,
'The Philosophy of Intellectual Property' (1988) 77 Georgetown Law journal, pp 287-
366.
22 John Locke, Two Treatises of Government (Everyman, London, 1993). For commentaries
on Locke, see Richard Ashcraft (ed), John Locke: CriticalAssessments (Routledge, London
and New York, 1991) (Volume 3 contains the discussion on Locke's property theory).
3 For a very readable overview of natural law, see Margaret Davies, Asking the Law
Question: the Dissolution ofLegal Theory (Lawbook Company, Sydney, 2002), pp 73-90.
Staniforth Ricketson, The Law of IntellectualProperty: Copyright, Designs ' Confidential
Information (LBC Information Services, Sydney, 1999) (loose-leaf service) Vol 1,
p 14 (accessed 13 July 2004). Although Ricketson (at 15) also suggests that natural
law justifications for intellectual property have not been 'fashionable' in common law
jurisdictions, where the focus of the debate has been more on the public benefits of
intellectual property rights.
25 The impact of natural law is clearly evident in the famous English case on literary
property: Millar v Taylor (1769) 4 Burr 2303; 98 ER 201. For a discussion on this case,
see Drahos, op cit note 6, pp 24-25, 27-28.
26 See Drahos, op cit note 6, pp 42-43.
27 Locke, op cit note 22; the Second Treatise, section 27.
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS: A WESTERN TALE 225
(b) Utilitarianism
In Western discourses, the concept of 'utilitarianism' is most commonly
associated with the work of the British philosopher Jeremy Bentham (1748-
1832).33 The central premise of utilitarianism is very well known: in sum, the
doctrine proposes that all action should be directed towards achieving the
greatest happiness for the greatest number of people.
The utilitarian argument of incentives is most commonly used for the
justification of granting intellectual property rights: these rights are necessary as
they provide incentives to produce new intellectual objects, the benefits of which
: Ibid.
29 Ibid, chapter 5, section 40.
30 Ibid, chapter 5, section 27.
3 Ibid, chapter 5, section 31.
32 See Drahos, op cit note 6, p 47.
3 The British philosophers James Mill (1773-1836) and John Stuart Mill (1806-1873) are
also widely acknowledged for their scholarly work on the doctrine of utilitarianism.
226 ALPANA ROY
3 See, eg, Joseph Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy (Unwin Paperbacks,
London and Boston, 1987) .
3 Sol Picciotto, 'Defending the Public Interest in TRIPS and the WTO' in Peter Drahos
and Ruth Mayne (eds), Global Intellectual Property Rights: Knowledge, Access and
Development (Palgrave Macmillan, Hampshire (GB) and New York, 2002), pp 224-243,
225.
36 Carlos M Correa, 'Pro-competitive Measures under TRIPS to Promote Technology
Diffusion in Developing Countries' in Drahos and Mayne (eds), ibid, pp 40-57. In this
paper, I will use the geographical indicator 'North' to refer to Western states (or the
former colonial powers), and countries commonly categorised as 'First World'nations.
Due to its status as a leading industrial nation, I will also include Japan within my
definition of Northern countries - even though it is idiosyncratically non-Western.
The term 'South' will refer to the former colonies, and countries commonly categorised
as 'developing' or 'Third World'. I will generally avoid using the term 'Third World' as
it has been heavily criticised for its negative associations with poverty, disease, famine,
debt, and conflict; and its 'third' place in the hierarchy of the First and Second worlds.
Moreover, the categorisation and division of the world into 'three worlds' is anachronistic
and inappropriate in this post-Cold War era (communist states were previously referred
to as the 'Second World'). The 'three worlds' vocabulary is also inappropriate to describe
the situation of Indigenous groups residing in the 'First World', although arguably in
'Fourth World' conditions. Please note that while I utilise the fairly commonly used
terms 'North' and 'South', others have used alternative indicators. For example, Young
employs the term 'three continents' (ie Asia, South America and Africa), or 'tricontinental'.
See Robert JC Young, Postcolonialism: an HistoricalIntroduction (Blackwell Publishing,
Oxford, 2001) 5.
17 Drahos and Mayne (eds), ibid.
38 Hettinger, op cit note 21, p 48.
3 See David Vaver, 'Some Agnostic Observations on Intellectual Property', 6 Intellectual
PropertyJournal125-153 (June 1991).
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS: A WESTERN TALE 227~
traditions have given rise to the idea of 'art' and 'culture' as commodities, where
the European Romantic view of the artist was transformed from an independent
creator to a perty commodity producer. Critics such as Coombe rightly point
out that the 19th century European art/culture system - which continues to
inform Western intellectual property laws - is no longer appropriate in post-
colonial contexts." These essentiallv Western traditions have also infused the
idea of intellectual property rights on a global scale, where these laws have
proven to be fundamentally inconsistent with the value-system of several non-
Western cultures: discussed further in Part 5. The following section follows
some of the key arguments in another Western dialectic on intellectual property:
proprietarianism and instrumentalism.
As noted above, both the justifications and criticisms of these expanding rights
in intellectual property are generally based in Western philosophical traditions.
The values underlying both the justifications and criticisms also generally stem
from WVestern individualistic notions of property, ownership, and community.
In Western jurisprudence, there have generally been two approaches taken
to the scope of intellectual property protection: the instrumentalist and the
proprietarian. While the instrumentalist approach is generally more concerned
with using intellectual property for desirable social ends, the proprietarian
approach focuses less on societal considerations and more on the individual
rights of the creator. Further discussion on these two perspectives follow.
Terry Eagleton explores the tension berween the Romantic view of the artist (aesthete),
and the harsh economic reality of the artist turned into a petty commodity producer. See
Terry Eagleton. The Ideology of the Aesthetic (Basil Blackwell, Oxford. 1990), pp 42-43.
56-:9. 64-65.
Coombe, op cit note 1, p 215.
Picciotto. op cit note 35, p 224.
228 ALPANA ROY
a Ibid. Vaver also suggests that allocating property rights to knowledge makes ideas less
valuable from a social viewpoint, as those ideas are less frequently used; see Vaver, op cit
note 39, p 151.
45 Vaver, ibid,p 126.
16 Ibid p 127.
Macaulay's speech in the House of Common Debates, 5 February 1842, p 350; cited in
Ricketson, op cit note 24, p 12 (accessed 13 July 2004).
4 Ibid.
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS: A WESTERN TALE 229
and development, and indeed for the attainment of true beliefs. These values
continue to form part of the cornerstone on which modern democracies are
based, particularly in the West. Proponents of the instrumentalist approach
also suggest that excessive intellectual property protection causes restrictions on
the free flow of information, which not only stifles individual growth, but also
actively disrupts human knowledge and technological innovation on a societal
level.
4 For example, Article I, s 8 of the US Constitution states that the Congress shall have
the power: 'To promote the Progress of Science and useful Arts, by securing for limited
Times to Authors and Inventors the exclusive Right to their respective Writings and
Discoveries'. The US Constitution is available online at the National Archives (US):
http://www.archives.gov/national-archives-experience/charters/constitution-transcript.
html (retrieved 9 December 2005).
For example, in the case of copyright, Kase asserts that this approach: 'sees the
foundation of the rights of an author in the very nature of things.. .These rights are
not created by the laws because they have always existed in the legal conscience of
men. Copyright is thus a natural right growing out of natural lawx See Francis J Kase,
Copyright Thought in Continental Europe: its Development, Legal Theories, and Philosophy
(South Hackensack, NJ: Rothman, 1967) p 8.
51 See Ricketson (note 24 above).
51 (1769) 4 Burr 2303; 98 ER 201. Although note that Ricketson critiques this notion of
'fairness' used to justify intellectual property, and argues that concepts such as 'justice'
and 'fairness' are exceedingly difficult to apply in practice. See Ricketson, op cit note 24,
p 16 (accessed 13 July 2004).
230 ALPANA ROY
52 Willem Pretorius, 'TRIPS and Developing Countries: How Level is the Playing Field?' in
Drahos and Mayne (eds), op cit note 35, pp 183-197, 184, 196.
5 Indeed, intellectual property is recognised as a human right in both the Universal
Declaration of Human Rights (1948) in Article 27, and also in the International
Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966) in Article 15. Article 27(2)
of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights states: 'Everyone has the right to the
protection of the moral and material interests resulting from any scientific, literary, or
artistic production of which he is the author.' The Universal Declaration of Human
Rights is available online: http://www.unhchr.ch/udhr/lang/eng.htm (retrieved 27
December 2005). Commentators such as Ostergard suggest that the status of intellectual
property as a universal human right is highly problematic, as fundamental needs (such as
food, shelter and medicine) must take priority over the guarantee of intellectual propery.
According to Ostergard, Article 27 clearly reflects the economic interests of Northern
states and the West-centric view of intellectual property as a commodity. Moreover, the
Declaration does not recognise the hierarchy of global interests in intellectual property:
a registered trademark for a multinational is given the same status as a patent for a life-
threatening disease. Ostergard argues that Article 27 directly conflicts with the UN's
other important goals, such as the improvement of health, welfare, and education for
countries of the South. See Ostergard, op cit note 4, pp 12, 28-31. See generally Francois
Dessemontet, 'Copyright and Human Rights' in Jan J C Kabel and Gerard J H M Mom
(eds), Intellectual Property and Information Law: Essays in Honour of Herman Cohen
Jehoram (Kluwer Law International, The Hague, 1998), pp 113-120.
5 As Dworkin suggests: 'some sovereignty over a range of personal possessions [is] essential
to dignity.' See Ronald M Dworkin, 'Liberalism', in Stuart Hampshire (ed), Public and
PrivateMorality (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1978), pp 113-143, 139.
" Hettinger, op cit note 21, pp 45-46. Vaver also rejects the notion that copyright and
patent laws are designed to protect authors and inventors. Instead, he suggests that (even
historically), these laws have not been used to benefit their individual creators/inventors,
but the firms which employ them. See Vaver, op cit note 39, pp 129-136.
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS: A WESTERN TALE 231
intellectual property rights are not necessary for achieving these type of goals in
the same way that other property rights may be, such as owning one's home.56
Drahos suggests that there is a strong move attitudinally towards
proprietarianism in intellectual property.' He asserts that the ideology
which infuses intellectual property globally is the 'proprietarian creed', which
proposes 'that the possessor should take all, that ownership privileges should
trump community interests and that the world and its contents are open
to ownership'. 8 It is the ideology of proprietarianism which underlies the
global expansion of intellectual property rights. Indeed, an underlying theme
common to several Western philosophical traditions, such as natural law
and utilitarianism, is the omnipotent status of property which prevails over
all other interests." For centuries, these traditions have been dominated by
discussions on the necessity of private property, and the importance of private
property rights.o Significantly, as will be discussed below, these theories have
proven to be fundamentally inconsistent with understandings of 'property',
including 'intellectual property', in several non-Western cultures. However,
before outlining some of these incompatibilities, how the very Western idea of
intellectual property became a universal story will be briefly plotted below.
56 Hettinger explains further that the right to exclude others from copying one's work is
not essential for one's sovereignty and security, although excluding others from rights in
one's home might be. Hettinger, op cit note 21, p 45.
5' Drahos, op cit note 6.
58 Ibid pp 200-203.
5 Indeed, Becker suggests that there have been too many justifications for private property;
see Lawrence C Becker, 'Too Much Property', 21(2) Philosophy and Public Affairs 196-
206 (1992).
60 As noted by Epstein, '[t]he desirability of private property has been endlessly debated
across the disciplines'. See Richard A Epstein, 'On the Optimal Mix of Private and
Common Property'. 11(2) SocialPhilosophy andPolicy 17-41, 17 (1994).
232 ALPANA ROY
6 Although it is worthwhile to note that there have been a few exceptions to this general
trend. For example, prior to Vietnam's economic liberalisation in 1986, its intellectual
property laws were modelled on those of the former Soviet Union. See Peter Drahos,
'Negotiating Intellectual Property Rights: Between Coercion and Dialogue' in Drahos
and Mayne (eds), op cit note 35, pp 161-182, 164.
62 See Janice Wickeri, 'Copyright in the Chinese Context' in Philip G Altbach (ed),
Copyright and Development: Inequality in the Information Age (Bellagio Publishing
Network Research and Information Center; Chestnut Hill, Massachusetts; 1995), pp 73-
91, 88.
63 See Amir U Khan and Bibek Debroy, IntellectualProperty Rights Beyond 2005: An Indian
Perspective on the Debate on IPR Protection and the WTO (DC School Press; Kottayam,
India; 2004), p 142.
6 See Khaw Lake Tee, Copyright Law in Malaysia (Butterworths Asia, Kuala Lumpur,
1994).
65 See Christoph Antons, 'Indonesian Copyright Law after TRIPs: between Dutch
Tradition and Anglo-American Influences' in Jan JC Kabel and Gerard JHM Mom (eds),
Intellectual Property and Information Law: Essays in Honour of Herman Cohen Jehoram
(Kluwer Law International, The Hague, 1998), pp 79-86, 79.
6 See Drahos, op cit note 61, p 164.
67 See Enrico B Astudillo, 'Intellectual Property Regime of the Philippines' in Arthur
Wineburg (ed), Intellectual Property Protection in Asia (Lexis Law Publishing;
Charlottesville, Virginia; 1999); cited in ibid.
68 Drahos, op cit note 61, p 164. Interestingly, South Korea was actually
one of the first
countries to have its intellectual property laws targeted under US trade laws in the 1980s.
See Susan K Sell, 'Intellectual Property Protection and Antitrust in the Developing
World: Crisis, Coercion, and Choice', 49(2) International Organization 315-349, 321
(1995).
69 See Khan and Debroy, op cit note 63, p 116.
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS: A WESTERN TALE 233
During the era of decolonisation after the Second World War, several
formerly colonised nations reviewed the intellectual property systems that had
been left to them by their former colonial powers. For example, India's patent
system was reviewed after independence;7 7 and in the 1970s Brazil, Argentina,
Mexico, and the Andean Pact also re-evaluated their patent laws." Several of
these postcolonial nations subsequently passed laws which resulted in weaker
patent regimes.7 1 Part of the decolonisation process also involved postcolonial
nations critiquing the Westcentric focus of major treaties, such as the Paris
Convention (1883) and Berne Convention (1886), and although reform was
sought in both the international copyright" and patent regimes," they were
largely unsuccessful. More recently, there has been intense criticism of the TRIPS
Agreement as a neo-colonial instrument heavily biased towards the intellectual
property owners, or Western nations.8 2 As products of Western legal cultures,
these international treaties have (not surprisingly) championed Western legal
norms as the acceptable standard for the rest of the world. Nevertheless, it is
important to remain conscious of the epistemological foundations underpinning
intellectual property as discourse, and remind ourselves that its 'story' has not
been constructed from a neutral place.
Two expert committees reviewed India's patent laws, and concluded that they had
failed to 'stimulate inventions among Indians and to encourage the development and
exploitation of new inventions'. It is interesting to note that India did not choose to
discard patent law as a regulatory tool, but instead chose to reconstruct its patent laws
to suit its own national postcolonial circumstances. India's new patent law was passed in
1970. The Act did not permit the patenting of substances used as food or medicine, or
substances produced by chemical processes. See Khan and Debroy, op citnote 63, pp 116-
117. Vandana Shiva suggests that one of India's greatest achievements since independence
was the patent law, as human welfare and development goals (particularly in the areas of
food and health) took precedence over profits; cited in Madeleine Bunting, 'Intellectual
Property Rights: the New Colonialism', The Guardian (London), 13 February 2001,
available online: http://lists.essential.org/pipermail/upd-discuss/2001ql/000132.html
(retrieved 10 August 2004).
' Drahos, op cit note 61, p 165.
79 Ibid.
80 See Alan Story, 'Don't Ignore Copyright, the 'Sleeping Giant' on the TRIPS and
International Educational Agenda' in Drahos and Mayne (eds), op cit note 35, pp 125-
143, 137-138.
See Duncan Matthews, GlobalisingIntellectual Property Rights: the TRIPs Agreement
(Routledge, London and New York, 2002), pp 11-12; Drahos, op cit note 61, p 166;
Gary Lea, 'Digital Millennium or Digital Dominion? The effect of IPRs in Software on
Developing Countries' in Drahos and Mayne (eds), ibid, pp 144-158, 150.
82 See, eg, Drahos and Mayne, op cit note 35.
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS: A WESTERN TALE 235
At every level the claims of aboriginal peoples to cultural rights fall outside
the parameters of Western legal discourse. As neither state actors, nor
individuals, their claims can be heard neither in the international regimes
governing cultural property, nor in the domestic regimes governing
intellectual property.
8 By the term 'indigenous' I mean the disparate cultures in the West who share a historical,
pre-colonial (or 'pre-invasion') continuity with the land, and consider themselves
as distinct from the other dominant cultural groups which arrived as a result of
colonisation.
* Coombe, op cit note 1, p 229.
* Amanda Pask, 'Cultural appropriation and the law: an analysis of the legal regimes
concerning culture', 8 IntellectualPropertyJournal57-86, 64 (1993).
236 ALPANA ROY
On this point, Gana argues that those societies whose intellectual and creative
endeavours have not been formed around Gutenberg's press, nor restricted
to the printed expression, completely fall outside the domain of copyright.
Significantly, the notion that knowledge is 'owned' as a commodity is also a
thoroughly Western idea, as opposed to a universal one. As Vaver suggests,
'Western capitalist societies are highly property-oriented' where entrenched
ideas of ownership and property affect all areas of civil society." Indeed, what
has generally become apparent around the globe is the inadequacy of Western
intellectual property regimes to 'fit' within indigenous understandings of
intangible property. However, given that the laws of a society essentially reflect
its underlying values, this is hardly surprising. As Shelley Wright asserts, as ideas
about culture and property in the West are 'thoroughly Eurocentric', they are
'therefore, almost certainly inappropriate in most Aboriginal cultural contexts'.
Richard Handler suggests that in the West, the rationale of possessive
individualism - which was initially formulated in Locke's labor theory of value
on the connection between the individual to property - increasingly dictates
the language and philosophy of legal claims to cultural property and political
claims to cultural autonomy." However, it is clear that indigenous concepts
of ownership and property are far wider than the exclusivity of the possessive
individualism of traditional European categories. Loretta Todd suggests that
indigenous concepts of property recognise the interdependence of communities,
families and nations.90 Moreover, indigenous groups and individuals 'created
songs, dances, rituals, objects, and stories that were considered to be property,
but not property as understood by the Europeans'. 9 ' In the Australian context,
6. Conclusion
The purpose of this article was to discuss the concept of intellectual property
as essentially a Western idea, and to excavate its Eurocentric (as opposed to
universal) foundations. Too often, the law in this area is presented as some kind
of collective human experience when its core values are actually strongly based
in Western ideological traditions. As discussed, the established view in Anglo-
American jurisprudence has been that intellectual property laws are a necessary
prerequisite for producing intellectual products. However, the principles
underlying this stem from Western capitalist notions of property, ownership, and
commodification - and, indeed, are far from global values. Significantly, these
Western capitalist principles have now been linked on an international scale to
economic development, growth, and prosperity.
Ultimately, this article presents itself as simply an act of criticism, a
disapproval, an interpellation, a gentle reminder, as the law in this area has
taken for granted some primary categories and presumptions, the foundations
of which are unquestioned and indeed, which through colonialism have now
gained the status of eternal truths. I hope that this critical reading of intellectual
property law will provoke a certain wariness toward generalisations which
transcend the boundaries of culture and region, and by doing so encourage a
reconceptualisation of intellectual properties.
Much more than documents.
Discover everything Scribd has to offer, including books and audiobooks from major publishers.
Cancel anytime.