You are on page 1of 523

The Cambridge Handbook of

Situated Cognition

Since its inception some fifty years ago, cognitive science has undergone a number of sea
changes. Perhaps the best known is the development of connectionist models of cognition
as alternatives to classical, symbol-based approaches. A more recent - and increasingly influ-
ential - trend is that of dynamical-systems-based, ecologically oriented models of the mind.
Researchers suggest that a full understanding of the mind will require systematic study of the
dynamics of interaction among mind, body, and world. Some argue that this new orientation
calls for a revolutionary new metaphysics of mind, according to which mental states and
processes, and even persons, literally extend into the environment.
The Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition is a state-of-the-art guide to this new move-
ment in cognitive science. Each chapter tackles either a specific area of empirical research or
a specific sector of the conceptual foundations underlying this research. The chapter authors
are leading figures in the emerging interdisciplinary field of situated cognition, including
representatives from philosophy, psychology, neuroscience, linguistics, and anthropology.

Philip Robbins received his A.B. from Harvard University and his Ph.D. from the University
of Chicago. Before coming to the University of Missouri, he taught at the University of
Vermont and Washington University in St. Louis.

Murat Aydede received his B.A. from Bogazi^i University in Istanbul and his Ph.D. from the
University of Maryland at College Park. Before coming to the University of British Columbia,
he taught at the University of Chicago and the University of Florida.
The Cambridge Handbook of
Situated Cognition

Edited by
PHILIP ROBBINS
University of Missouri-Columbia

MURAT AYDEDE
University of British Columbia

CAMBRIDGE
UNIVERSITY PRESS
CAMBRIDGE UWVÉRSITY PRESS

Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, Sfto Paulo, Delhi

Cambridge University Press

p. Avenue of the Americas, New York, NY 10013-2473, USA

w w * .Cambridge org

Information on this tide: www.cambridge.org/97805z1612869

C Cambridge University Press 2009


Tins publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception
and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements,
no reproduction of any part may take place without the written
permission of Cambridge University Press.

First published 2009

Printed in the United States of America

A catalog record for this publication is available from the British Library.

Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data


The Cambridge handbook of situated cognition / edited by Philip Robbins,
Murat Aydede,
p. cm.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 978-0-521-84S32-9 (hardback) - ISBN 978-0-521-61286-9 (pbk.) 1. Cognition.
I. Robbins, Philip, 1963- II. Aydede, Murat III. Title.
BF3U.C19 2009
!53~dc22 2008017805
ISBN 978-0-521-84832-9 hardback
ISBN 978-0-521-61286-9 paperback
Canbridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or
accuracy of URLs for external or third-party Internet Web sites referred to in
this publication and does not guarantee that any content on such Web sites is,
or will remain, accurate or appropriate. Information regarding prices, travel
timetables, and other factual information given in this work are correct at
the time of first printing, but Cambridge University Press does not guarantee
the accuracy of such information thereafter.
Contents

page vii
Acknowledgments
ix
Contributors
l
p a r t I: B a c k d r o p

1 A Short Primer on Situated Cognition 3


Philip Robbins and Murat Aydede
2 Scientific Antecedents of Situated Cognition
William J. Clancey
3 Philosophical Antecedents of Situated Cognition 35
Shaun Gallagher

partII: Conceptual Foundations 53

4 How to Situate Cognition: Letting Nature Take Its Course 55


Robert A. Wilson and Andy Clark
5 Why the Mind Is Still in the Head
Fred Adams and Kenneth Aizawa
6 Innateness and the Situated Mind 96
Robert Rupert
7 Situated Representation 117
Mark Rowlands
8 Dynamics, Control, and Cognition 134
Chris Eliasmith
CONTENTS

9 Explanation: Mechanism, Modularity, and Situated Cognition 155


William Bechtel
10 Embedded Rationality 171
Km
Part III: Empirical Developments 183
11 Situated Perception and Sensation in Vision and Other Modalities:
A Sensorimotor Approach 185
Erik Myin and J. Kevin O 'Regan
12 Spatial Cognition: Embodied and Situated 207
Barbara Tversky
13 Remembering 217
John Sutton
14 Situating Concepts 236
Laurence W. Barsalou
15 Problem Solving and Situated Cognition 264
David Kirsh
16 The Dynamic Interactions between Situations and Decisions 307
Jerome R Busemeyer, Ryan K. Jessup, and Eric Dimperio
17 Situating Rationality: Ecologically Rational Decision Making with
Simple Heuristics 322
Henry Britfiton and Peter M. Todd
18 Situativity and Learning 347
R. Keith Sawyer and James G. Greeno
19 Language in the Brain, Body, and World 368
Rolf A. Zwaan and Michael P. Kaschak
20 Language Processing Embodied and Embedded 382
Michael Spivey and Daniel Richardson
21 Situated Semantics 401
Vatvl Alarum
22 Is Consciousness Embodied? 4J9
Jesse Prinz
23 Emotions in the Wild: The Situated Perspective on Emotion 437
Paul Griffiths and Andrea Scarantino
24 The Social Context of Cognition 454
Eliot R. Smith and Frederica R. Conrey
25 Cognition for Culture 467
Felix Warneken and Michael TomaseUo
26 Neuroethology: From Morphological Computation to Planning 480
Malcolm A. Maclver
Index 505
Acknowledgments

This volume has been a long time in the On the business end, Phil Laughlin,
making, and we have gotten a lot of help formerly of Cambridge University Press,
from á lot of people. Accordingly, we have encouraged us to take on the project and
a long list of people to thank. supervised its initial development. His assis-
At the top of the list are our contrib- tant, Armi Macaballug, provided solid sup-
utors, every one of whom did top-notch port throughout. After Phil left the Press,
work for us. Among them, the four mem- Eric Schwartz and his assistant, April Poten-
bers of our advisory board - Larry Barsalou, ciano, took over supervision of the project
Bill Bechtel, David Kirsh, and Rob Wilson - and saw it through the home stretch. During
also assisted us with recruitment and other the production phase, Shana Meyer oversaw
editorial matters. A number of other peo- the project from start to finish, guiding us
ple, including several contributors, extended skillfully through the maze. Katherine Fay-
our editorial reach still further by reviewing dash copyedited the manuscript, and Kate
individual chapters: Pascal Boyer, Philippe Mertes made the index for the book. Both
Chuard, Bill Clancey, Carl Craver, Chris of them did fine work.
Eliasmith, Shaun Gallagher, Kent Johnson, Finally, our nearest and dearest - Sara
Hilary Kornblith, Alan Lambert, Edouard and Judah, and Sema and Derya - helped
Machery, Eric Margolis, Pascale Michelon, immeasurably by just being there.
Michael Wheeler, Wayne Wright, and Jeff Hearty thanks to all.
Zacks. In the final phase, Chris Kahn came
to our rescue by agreeing to format the Philip Robbins
entire manuscript for production, a task that Murat Aydede
he performed with admirable skill and care.
Contributors

FRED ADAMS WILLIAM BECHTEL*


Department of Linguistics and Cognitive Department of Philosophy
Science University of California, San Diego
University of Delaware USA
USA
HENRY BRIGHTON
KENNETH AIZAWA Center for Adaptive Behavior and
Department of Philosophy Cognition
Centenary College of Louisiana Max Planck Institute for Human
USA Development
Germany
VAROL AKMAN
Departments of Computer Engineering and JEROME R. BUSEMEYER
Philosophy Department of Psychological and Brain
Bilkent University Sciences
Turkey Indiana University
USA
MURAT A Y D E D E
Department of Philosophy WILLIAM J . CLANCEY
University of British Columbia NASA/Ames Research Center
Canada USA

LAWRENCE W . BARSALOU* A N D Y CLARK


Department of Psychology Department of Philosophy
Emory University University of Edinburgh
USA Scotland

'Member of the editorial advisory board.


CONTRIBUTORS

FkEDERICA R. CONREY MALCOLM A . MACIVER


Department of Psychological and Brain Department of Biomedical Engineering
Sciences Northwestern University
Indiana University USA
USA
RUTH MILLIKAN
ERIC DIMPERIO Department of Philosophy
Department of Psychological and Brain University of Connecticut
Sciences USA
Indiana University
USA ERIK MYIN
Department of Philosophy
CHRIS ELIASMITH University of Antwerp
Departments of Philosophy and Systems Belgium
Design Engineering
University of Waterloo J . KEVIN O ' R E G A N
Canada Laboratory of Experimental Psychology
Centre National de la Recherche
SHAUN GALLAGHER Scientifique (CNRS)
Department of Philosophy and Cognitive France
Sciences Program
University of Central Florida JESSE PRINZ
USA Department of Philosophy
University of North Carolina at
JAMES G. GREENO Chapel Hill
School of Education USA
University of Pittsburgh
USA DANIEL RICHARDSON
Department of Psychology
PAUL GRIFFITHS University of Reading
Department of Philosophy England
University of Sydney
Australia PHILIP ROBBINS
Department of Philosophy
RYAN K. JESSUP University of Missouri-Columbia
Department of Psychological and USA
Brain Sciences
Indiana University MARK ROWLANDS
USA Department of Philosophy
University of Miami
MICHAEL P. KASCHAK USA
Department of Psychology
Florida State University ROBERT RUPERT
USA Department of Philosophy
University of Colorado at Boulder
D A V I D KIRSH* USA
Department of Cognitive Science
University of California, San Diego R. KEITH SAWYER
USA Department of Education
CONTRIBUTORS xi

Washington University in St. Louis MICHAEL TOMASELLO


USA Department of Developmental and
Comparative Psychology
A N D R E A SCARANTINO Max Planck Institute for Evolutionary
Department of Philosophy Anthropology
Georgia State University Germany
USA
BARBARA T V E R S K Y
E L I O T R . SMITH Department of Psychology
Department of Psychological and Brain Stanford University
Sciences USA
Indiana University
USA FELIX WARNEKEN
Department of Developmental and
M I C H A E L SPIVEY Comparative Psychology
Department of Psychology Max Planck Institute for Evolutionary
Cornell University Anthropology
USA Germany

JOHN SUTTON ROBERT A . W I L S O N *


Macquarie Centre for Cognitive Science Department of Philosophy
Macquarie University University of Alberta
Australia Canada

PETER M . T O D D ROLF A. ZWAAN


Department of Psychological and Brain Department of Biological and Cognitive
Sciences Psychology
Indiana University Erasmus University
USA The Netherlands
Part I

BACKDROP
CHAPTER 1

A Short Primer on Situated Cognition

Philip Robbins and Murat Aydede

In recent years there has been a lot of buzz it seems to us as good as any (for compet-
about a new trend in cognitive science. The ing proposals, see Anderson, 2003; Clancey,
trend is associated with terms like embodi- 1997; Wilson, 2002).
ment, enactivism, distributed cognition, and In this brief introductory chapter, we
the extended mind. The ideas expressed using present a bird's-eye view of the concep-
these terms are a diverse and sundry lot, tual landscape of situated cognition as seen
but three of them stand out as especially from each of the three angles noted previ-
central. First, cognition depends not just on ously: embodiment, embedding, and exten-
the brain but also on the body (the embodi- sion. Our aim is to orient the reader, if
ment thesis). Second, cognitive activity rou- only in a rough and preliminary way, to the
tinely exploits structure in the natural and sprawling territory of this handbook.
social environment (the embedding thesis).
Third, the boundaries of cognition extend
beyond the boundaries of individual organ- 1. The Embodied Mind
isms (the extension thesis). Each of these
theses contributes to a picture of mental Interest in embodiment - in "how the body
activity as dependent on the situation or shapes the mind," as the title of Gallagher
context in which it occurs, whether that sit- (2005) neatly puts it - has multiple sources.
uation or context is relatively local (as in the Chief among them is a concern about the
case of embodiment) or relatively global (as basis of mental representation. From a foun-
in the case of embedding and extension). It is dational perspective, the concept of em-
this picture of the mind that lies at the heart bodiment matters because it offers help
of research on situated cognition. According with the notorious "symbol-grounding prob-
to our usage, then, situated cognition is the lem," that is, the problem of explaining how
genus, and embodied, enactive, embedded, representations acquire meaning (Anderson,
and distributed cognition and their ilk are 2003; Hamad, 1990; Niedenthal, Barsalou,
species. This usage is not standard, though Winkielman, Krauth-Gruber, & Ric, 2005).

3
4 PHILIP ROBBINS AND Ml'RAT AYDF.DE

Has is a pressing problem for cognitive sci- the high-level central systems responsible
ence. Theories of cognition are awash in for thinking, and central processing oper-
representations, and the explanatory value ates over amodal representations. On the
of those representations depends on their embodied view, the classical picture of the
meaningfulness, in real-world terms, for mind is fundamentally flawed. In particu-
the agents that deploy them. A natural lar, that view is belied by two important
way to underwrite that meaningfulness is facts about the architecture of cognition:
by grounding representations in an agent's first, that modality-specific representations
capacities for sensing the world and acting not amodal representations, are the stuff
in it: out of which thoughts are made; second
that perception, thought, and action are co-
Grounding the symbol far 'chair', fin- constituted, that is, not just causally but also
instance, involves both the reliable detec- constitutively interdependent (more on this
tion of chairs, and also the appropriate distinction follows).
reactions to them The agent must know Supposing, however, that the sandwich
what sitting is and be able to systemati-
model is retired and replaced by a model in
cally relate thatknowledge to the per&ived
which cognition is sensorimotor to the core,
scene, and thereby see what things (even if
non-standardly) afford sitting. In the nor- it does not follow that cognition is embod-
mal course of things, such knowledge is ied in the sense of requiring a body for its
gained by mastering the skill of sitting (not realization. For it could be that the sensori-
to mention the related skills of walking, motor basis of cognition resides solely at the
standing up, and moving between sitting central neural level, in sensory and motor
and standing), including refining one's per- areas of the brain. To see why, consider that
ceptual judgments as to what objects invite sensorimotor skills can be exercised either
or allow these behaviors; grounding 'chair', on-line or off-line (Wilson, 2002). On-line
that is to say, involves a very specific set of sensorimotor processing occurs when we
physical skills and experiences. (Anderson,
actively engage with the current task envi-
2003, pp. 102-103)
ronment, taking in sensory input and pro-
This approach to the symbol-grounding ducing motor output. Off-line processing
problem makes it natural for us to attend to occurs when we disengage from the envi-
the role of the body in cognition. After all, ronment to plan, reminisce, speculate, day-
our sensory and motor capacities depend on dream, or otherwise think beyond the con-
more than just the workings of the brain and fines of the here and now. The distinction is
spinal cord; they also depend on the work- important, because only in the on-line case
ings of other parts of the body, such as the is it plausible that sensorimotor capacities
sensory organs, the musculoskeletal system, are body dependent. For off-line function-
and relevant parts of the peripheral nervous ing, presumably all one needs is a working
system (e.g., sensory and motor nerves). brain.
Without the cooperation of the body, there Accordingly, we should distinguish two
can be no sensory inputs from the environ- ways in which cognition can be embodied:
ment and no motor outputs from the agent- on-line and off-line (Niedenthal et al., 2005;
hence, no sensing or acting. And without Wilson, 2002). The idea of on-line embodi-
sensing and acting to ground it, thought is ment refers to the dependence of cogni-
empty. tion - that is, not just perceiving and acting
This focus on the sensorimotor basis of but also thinking - on dynamic interactions
cognition puts pressure on a traditional con- between the sensorimotor brain and rele-
ception of cognitive architecture. According vant parts of the body: sense organs, limbs,
to what Hurley (1998) calls the "sandwich sensory and motor nerves, and the like.
model," processing in the low-level periph- This is embodiment in a strict and literal
eral systems responsible for sensing and act- sense, as it implicates the body directly. Off-
ing is strictly segregated from processing in line embodiment refers to the dependence
A SHORT PRIMER ON SITUATED COGNITION

of cognitive function on sensorimotor areas (approach), and thinking about something


of the brain even in the absence of sen- negative, like hate, involves negative motor
sory input and motor output. This type of imagery (avoidance). This result exempli-
embodiment implicates the body only indi- fies off-line embodiment, insofar as it sug-
rectly, by way of brain areas that process gests that ostensibly extramotor capacities
body-specific information (e.g., sensory and like lexical comprehension depend to some
motor representations). extent on motor brain function - a mainstay
To illustrate this distinction, let us con- of embodied approaches to concepts and
sider a couple of examples of embodiment categorization (Glenberg & Kaschak, 2002;
effects in social psychology (Niedenthal Lakoff & Johnson, 1999).
et al., 2005). First, it appears that bodily The distinction between on-line and off-
postures and motor behavior influence eval- line embodiment effects makes clear that
uative attitudes toward novel objects. In not all forms of embodiment involve bodily
one study, monolingual English speakers dependence in a strict and literal sense.
were asked to rate the attractiveness of Indeed, most current research on embodi-
Chinese ideographs after viewing the latter ment focuses on the idea that cognition
while performing different attitude-relevant depends on the sensorimotor brain, with
motor behaviors (Cacioppo, Priester, & or without direct bodily involvement. (In
Bernston, 1993). Subjects rated those ideo- that sense, embodied cognition is something
graphs they saw while performing a posi- of a misnomer, at least as far as the bulk
tively valenced action (pushing upward on of research that falls under this heading is
a table from below) more positively than concerned.) Relatively few researchers in
ideographs they saw either while performing the area highlight the bodily component of
a negatively valenced action (pushing down- embodied cognition. A notable exception is
ward on the tabletop) or while performing Gallagher's (2005) account of the distinc-
no action at all. This looks to be an effect tion between body image and body schema.
of on-line embodiment, as it suggests that In Gallagher's account, a body image is a
actual motor behaviors, not just activity in "system of perceptions, attitudes, and beliefs
motor areas of the brain, can influence atti- pertaining to one's own body" (p. 24), a
tude formation. complex representational capacity that is
Contrast this case with another study of realized by structures in the brain. A body
attitude processing. Subjects were presented schema, on the other hand, involves "motor
with positively and negatively valenced capacities, abilities, and habits that both
words, such as love and hate, and asked enable and constrain movement and the
to indicate when a word appeared either maintenance of posture" (p. 24), much of
by pulling a lever toward themselves or by which is neither representational in charac-
pushing it away (Chen & Bargh, 1999). In ter nor reducible to brain function. A body
each trial, the subject's reaction time was schema, unlike a body image, is "a dynamic,
recorded. As predicted, subjects responded operative performance of the body, rather
more quickly when the valence of word than a consciousness, image, or conceptual
and response behavior matched, pulling the model of it" (p. 32). As such, only the
lever more quickly in response to posi- body schema resides in the body proper;
tive words and pushing the lever away the body image is wholly a product of the
more quickly in response to negative words. brain. But if Gallagher is right, both body
Embodiment theorists cite this finding as image and body schema have a shaping influ-
evidence that just thinking about some- ence on cognitive performance in a variety
thing — that is, thinking about something of domains, from object perception to lan-
in the absence of the thing itself - involves guage to social cognition.
activity in motor areas of the brain. In par- So far, in speaking of the dependence
ticular, thinking about something positive, of cognition on the sensorimotor brain and
like love, involves positive motor imagery body, we have been speaking of the idea that
6 PHILIP ROBB1NS AND Ml'RAT AYDEDE

certain cognitive capacities depend on the boost efficiency and extend one's epistemic
structure of either the sensorimotor brain or reach.
die body, or both, far their physical real- One of the best articulations of the idea
ization. But dependence of this strong con- of cognitive off-loading involves the concept
stitutive sort is a metaphysically demand- of epistemic action (Kirsh & Maglio, 1994)
ing relation. It should not be confused with An epistemic action is an action designed
causal dependence, a weaker relation that to advance the problem solver's cause by
is easier to satisfy (Adams & Aizawa, 2008; revealing information about the task that
Block, 2005). Correlatively, we can distin- is difficult to compute mentally. T h e best-
guish between two grades of bodily involve- known example of epistemic action involves
ment in mental affairs: one that requires the computer game Tetris, the goal of which
the constitutive dependence of cognition on is to orient falling blocks (called "zoids") so
the sensorimotor brain and body, and one they form a maximally compact layer at the
that requires only causal dependence. This bottom of the screen. As the rate of fall
distinction crosscuts the one mooted ear- accelerates, the player has less and less time
lier, between on-line and off-line embodi- to decide how to orient each block b e f o r e it
ment. Although the causal/constitutive dis- reaches the bottom. To cope better with this
tinction is less entrenched than the on-line/ constraint, skilled players use actual physical
off-line distinction, especially outside of phi- movements on the keyboard to manipulate
losophy circles, it seems no less funda- the blocks on the screen - a m o r e efficient
mental to an adequate understanding of strategy than the "in-the-head" alternative
the concept of embodiment. To see why, of mentally rotating the blocks prior to ori-
note that the studies described previously enting them on the screen with keystrokes.
do not show that cognition constitutively A roughly analogous strategy of cognitive
depends on either the motor brain or the off-loading facilitates more m u n d a n e tasks
body. The most these studies show is some like grocery packing (Kirsh, 1995). T h e prob-
sort of causal dependence, in one or both lem here is to arrange things so that h e a v y
directions. But causal dependencies are rel- items go on the bottom, fragile items on top,
atively cheap, metaphysically speaking. For and intermediate items in between. As the
this reason, among others, it may turn out groceries continue to move along t h e con-
that the import of embodiment for foun- veyor belt, decisions about which items go
dational debates in cognitive science is less where need to be made swiftly, to avoid pile-
revolutionary than is sometimes advertised ups and clutter. As items come o f f the con-
(Adams & Aizawa, 2008). veyor belt and enter the work space, skilled
grocery packers often rapidly sort t h e m by
category (heavy, fragile, intermediate) into
2. The Embedded Mind distinct spatial zones prior to placing each
item in a bag. This procedure significantly
It seems natural to think of cognition as an decreases load on working m e m o r y relative
interaction effect: the result, at least in part, to the alternative of mentally calculating t h e
of causal processes that span the boundary optimal placement of each item as it enters
separating the individual organism from the the work space, without the benefit of exter-
natural, social, and cultural environment. To nal spatial cues.
understand how cognitive work gets done, Both of these examples of epistemic
then, it is not enough to look at what goes action point to the importance of m i n i m i z -
on within individual organisms; we need ing load on internal memory, on w o r k i n g
to consider also the complex transactions memory in particular. This echoes the t w i n
between embodied minds and the embed- themes of Brooks's (1991) "world as its o w n
ding world. One type of such a transaction is model" (p. 140) and O'Regan's (1992) " w o r l d
the use of strategies for off-loading cognitive as an outside memory" (p. 461). T h e c o m -
work onto the environment, a useful way to mon idea here is that, instead of building
A SHORT PRIMER ON SITUATED C O G N I T I O N

up detailed internal models of the world and world (Hutchins, 1995). The scope of
that require continuous and costly updat- this ecological perspective on the mind is
ing, it pays to look up relevant informa- very broad indeed. Having expanded far
tion from the world on an as-needed basis. beyond Gibson's (1979) work on vision, it
In other words, "rather than attempt to informs research programs in virtually every
mentally store and manipulate all the rele- area of psychology, from spatial naviga-
vant details about a situation, we physically tion to language acquisition to social cog-
store and manipulate those details out in the nition. It is nicely illustrated by theories
world, in the very situation itself' (Wilson, of social rationality, which try to explain
2002, p. 629). The suggestion that intelligent human judgment and decision making in
agents do best when they travel informa- terms of the structure of the social envi-
tionally light, keeping internal representa- ronment (Gigerenzer, 2000). Somewhat fur-
tion and processing to a minimum, informs ther afield, the ecological view has begun to
a wide spectrum of research on cognition in show up with increasing frequency in the
the situated tradition (Clark, 1997). Vision literature on phenomenal consciousness,
science affords a nice example of this trend that is, consciousness in the "what-it's-like"
in the form of research on change blind- sense popularized by Nagel (1974). It is
ness. This is a phenomenon in which viewers implicit, for example, in the enactivist idea
fail to register dramatic changes in a visual that the felt quality of visual awareness is
scene - a phenomenon that some interpret a by-product of ongoing agent-environment
as evidence that the visual system creates interaction (Noe, 2004). It also informs con-
only sparse models of the world, giving rise structivist conceptions of consciousness,
to representational blind spots (O'Regan, such as the idea that an individual's con-
1992). scious mental life tends to mirror that of
The embedding thesis, then, goes hand in socially salient others (Robbins, 2008). Both
hand with what Clark (1989) calls the "007 of these suggestions about the nature of phe-
principle." nomenal consciousness — arguably the last
bastion of Cartesian internalism - reflect a
In general, evolved creatures will neither newly invigorated ecological perspective on
store nor process information in costly ways the mind.
when they can use the structure of the envi-
ronment and their operations upon it as
a convenient stand-in for the information-
processing operations concerned. That is,
3. The Extended Mind
know only as much as you need to know to
get the job done. (p. 6 4 J Assigning an important explanatory role to
brain-body and agent-environment interac-
Embedding, in turn, goes hand in hand with tions does not constitute a sharp break from
embodiment, as off-loading cognitive work classical cognitive science. Both the embodi-
depends heavily on sensorimotor capacities ment thesis and the embedding thesis can be
such as visual lookup, pattern recognition, seen as relatively modest proposals, given
and object manipulation. Epistemic actions, that they can be accommodated by rela-
for instance, typically require embodiment tively minor adjustments to the classical pic-
in a strict and literal sense, as they involve ture, such as the acknowledgment that "not
real-time dynamic interaction with the local all representations are enduring, not all are
physical environment. symbolic, not all are amodal, and not all are
The theoretical and methodological independent of the sensory and effector sys-
import of embedding, however, is much tems of the agent" (Markman & Dietrich,
wider. It points to the importance, in gen- 2000, p. 474; see also Vera & Simon, 1993)
eral, of studying cognition "in the wild," The same cannot be so easily said, however
with careful attention to the complex inter- of the claim that cognition is extended
play of processes spanning mind, body, the claim that the boundaries of cognitiv
s PHILIP ROBBINS AND Ml'RAT AYDEDE

systems lie outside the envelope of individ- to the conclusion that cognition is extended
ual organisms, encompassing features of the as well. Or so the reasoning goes.
physical and social environment (Clark & Another part of the motivation behind
Chalmers, 1 9 9 8 ; Wilson, 2 0 0 4 ) . In this view, the extension thesis traces back to a fic-
the mind leaks out into the world, and cog- tional (but realistic) scenario that Clark and
nitive activity is distributed across individ- Chalmers (1998) describe. T h e y introduce
uals and situations. This is not your grand- a pair of characters named Otto and Inga.
mother's metaphysics of mind; this is a brave Otto is an Alzheimer's patient w h o supple-
new world. Why should anyone believe ments his deteriorating memory by carry-
in it? ing around a notebook stocked with use-
One part of the answer lies in the promise ful information. Unable to recall the address
of dynamical systems theory - the intel- of a museum he wishes to visit, Otto pulls
lectual offspring of dassical control theory, out his trusty notebook, flips to the rele-
or cybernetics (Ashby, 1956; Wiener, 1948; vant page, looks up the address, and pro-
Young, 1964) - as an approach to model- ceeds on his way. Neurotypical Inga, in con-
ing cognition (Beer, 1995; Thelen & Smith, trast, has an intact memory and no need for
1994; van Gelder, 1 9 9 5 ) . Using the tools of such contrivances. When she decides to visit
dynamical systems theory, one can describe the museum, she simply recalls the address
in a mathematically precise way how various and sets off. Now, there are clear differences
states of a cognitive system change in rela- between the case of Otto and the case of
tion to one another over time. Because those Inga; Otto stores the information externally
state changes depend as much on changes in (on paper), whereas Inga stores it internally
the external environment as on changes in (in neurons); Otto retrieves the information
the internal one, it becomes as important by visual lookup, whereas Inga uses some-
for cognitive modeling to track causal pro- thing like introspective recall; and so on.
cesses that cross the boundary of the indi- But according to Clark and Chalmers, these
vidual organism as it is to track those that differences are relatively superficial. What
lie within that boundary. In short, insofar as is most salient about the cases of Otto and
the mind is a dynamical system, it is natu- of Inga, viewed through a functionalist lens,
ral to think of it as extending not just into are the similarities. Once these similarities
the body but also into the world. The result are given their due, the moral of the story
is a radical challenge to traditional ways of becomes clear: "When it comes to belief,
thinking about the mind, Cartesian intemal- there is nothing sacred about skull and skin.
ism in particular: What makes some information count as a
belief is the role it plays, and there is no rea-
The Cartesian tradition is mistaken in sup- son why the relevant role can be played only
posing that the mind is an inner entity from inside the body" (Clark & Chalmers,
of any kind, whether mind-stuff, brain 1998, p. 14). As for the fact that this con-
states, or whatever. Ontologically, mind ception of mind runs afoul of folk intu-
is much more a matter of what we do
itions, well, so much the worse for those
within environmental and social possibil-
intuitions.
ities and bounds. Twentieth-century anti-
This conclusion is not forced on us, how-
Cartesianism thus draws much of mind
out, and in particular outside the skull, ever, and a number of theorists have urged
(van Gelder, J 9 9 5 , p. 3 8 0 ) that we resist it. For example, Rupert ( 2 0 0 4 )
argues that generalizing memory to include
Implicit in this passage is a kind of slippery cases like Otto's would have the untoward
slope argument premised on a broad theo- effect of voiding the most basic lawlike gen-
retical assumption. Grant that cognition is eralizations uncovered by traditional m e m -
embodied and embedded - something that ory research, such as primacy, recency, and
the dynamical systems approach takes more interference effects - and without furnishing
or less as a given - and it is a short distance anything comparably robust to substitute in
A SHORT PRIMER ON SITUATED COGNITION 9

their place. In short, insofar as the goal of Block, N. (2005). Review of Alva Nog's Action
scientific inquiry is to carve nature at its in Perception. Journal of Philosophy, 102, 259-
joints, and lawlike regularities are the best 272.
guide to the location of those joints, it is Brooks, R. (1991). Intelligence without represen-
not clear that a f r u i t f u l science of extended tation. Artificial Intelligence, 47,139-159.
m e m o r y is possible, even in principle. More Cacioppo, J. T., Priester, J. R., & Bemston, C. G.
generally, A d a m s and A i z a w a (2008) con- (1993). Rudimentary determination of atti-
tend that the standard argument for pushing tudes: II. Arm flexion and extension have dif-
ferential effects on attitudes. Journal of Person-
the boundary of cognition beyond the indi-
ality and Social Psychology, 65, 5-17.
vidual organism rests on conflating the meta-
Chen, S., & Bargh, J. A. (1999). Consequences
physically important distinction between
of automatic evaluation: Immediate behavior
causation and constitution. As they point dispositions to approach or avoid the stimulus.
out, it is one thing to say that cognitive Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,
activity involves systematic causal interac- 215-224.
tion with things outside the head, and it is Clancey, W. J. (1997). Situated cognition. Cam-
quite another to say that those things instan- bridge: Cambridge University Press.
tiate cognitive properties or undergo cogni- Clark, A. (1989). Microcognition. Cambridge, MA:
tive processes. Bridging this conceptual gap MIT Press.
remains a m a j o r challenge for defenders of Clark, A. (1997). Being there. Cambridge, MA:
the extended mind. MIT Press.
Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended
mind. Analysis, 58,10-23.
Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the
4. C o d a
mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to
Situated cognition is a many-splendored visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
enterprise, spanning a w i d e range of projects Gigerenzer, G. (2000). Adaptive thinking. Oxford:
in philosophy, psychology, neuroscience, Oxford University Press.
anthropology, robotics, and other fields. In Glenberg, A. M„ & Kaschak, M. P. (2002).
this chapter we have touched on a f e w of the Grounding language in action. Psychonomic
themes running through this research, in an Bulletin and Review, 9, 558-565.
e f f o r t to convey some sense of w h a t situ- Harnad, S. (1990). The symbol grounding prob-
ated cognition is and w h a t the excitement is lem. Physica D, 42, 335-346.
about. T h e twenty-five chapters that follow Hurley, S. L. (1998). Consciousness in action.
it develop these themes, and other themes Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
in the vicinity, in depth. Both individually Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cam-
bridge, MA: MIT Press.
and collectively, these chapters reveal what
Kirsh, D. (1995). The intelligent use of space. j4rti-
"getting situated" means to cognitive sci-
ficial Intelligence, 7, 31-68.
ence, and w h y it matters.
Kirsh, D., & Maglio, P. (1994). On distinguish-
ing epistemic from pragmatic action. Cognitive
Science, 18, 513-549.
References Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy in
the flesh. New York: Basic Books.
Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of Markman, A. B., 8c Dietrich, E. (2000). Extending
cognition. Oxford: Blackwell. the classical view of representation. Trends in
Anderson, M. L. (2003). Embodied cognition: Cognitive Sciences, 4, 470-475.
A field guide. Artificial Intelligence, 149, 91- Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Phil-
130. osophical Review, 82, 435-450.
Ashby, W. R. (1956). Introduction to cybernetics. Niedenthal, P. M., Barsalou, L. W., Winkiel-
New York: Wiley. man, P., Krauth-Gruber, S., & Ric, F. (2005).
Beer, R. D. (1995). A dynamical systems perspec- Embodiment in attitudes, social perception,
tive on agent-environment interaction. Artifi- and emotion. Personality and Social Psychology
cial Intelligence, 72,173-215. Review, 9,184-211.
10 PHILIP ROBBINS AND MURAT AYDF.0F.

Nof. A. (1004). Action in perception. Cambridge, van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be,
if not computation? Journal of Philosophy, 91-
MA: MIT Press.
O 'Regan. J. K (1992). Solving the "real" mysteries 345-3®1-
Vera, A. H., & Simon, H. A. (1993). Situated
of visual perception: The world as an outside
action: A symbolic interpretation. Cognitive
memory. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 46,
Science, 17, 7-48.
461-4SS.
Wiener, N. (1948). Cybernetics; or, Control and
Robbins, P. (aoo8). Consciousness and the social
communication in the animal and the machine.
mind. Cognitive Systems Research, 9, 15- New York: Wiley.
Rupert, R. (2004)- Challenging the hypothesis of Wilson, M. (2002). Six views of embodied cogni-
extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy, 101, tion. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 9, 625-
636.
Thelen, E„ & Smith, L. B. (1994). ^ dynamic Wilson, R. A. (2004). Boundaries of the mind.
systems approach to the development of cog- Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
nition and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Young, J. Z. (1964). A model of the brain. Oxford:
Press. Oxford University Press.
CHAPTER 2

Scientific Antecedents of Situated


Cognition

William J. Clartcey

Introduction provides a broad historical review of the


scientific antecedents of situated cognition;
In the late 1980s, an artificial intelligence Gallagher (this volume) details philosophi-
(AI) researcher trying to untangle controver- cal aspects. 1
sies about the nature of knowledge, mem- What idea could be so general that it
ory, and behavior would have been sur- applies to every scientific discipline? A n d
rounded by perplexed computer science and why was this idea so controversial in the
psychology colleagues who viewed situated AI community? What aspect of cognition
cognition ideas as fool's gold — or even sug- relates the social sciences, linguistics, ped-
gested that those ideas threatened the foun- agogy, animal cognition, and evolutionary
dations of science itself. But scholars knew biology to neural theories of perception,
the concepts and methods of situated cogni- learning, and memory? W h a t problematic
tion from a much broader and deeper back- aspects of cognition in AI research foreshad-
ground, one that embraced Dewey's (1896) owed the development of a situated episte-
early objections to stimulus-response the- mology? These are the topics I discuss in
ory, Wittgenstein's (1953/1958) notions of this chapter. In large part, the story cen-
family resemblances and language games, ters on particular scientists, but I present the
Gibson's (1966) affordances, Bateson's (1972) central ideas as crosscutting themes. These
ecology of mind, Polanyi's (1966) tacit themes reveal that human cognitive pro-
knowledge, von Bertalanffy's (1968) general cesses are inherently social, interactive, per-
systems theory, and so on, in the work of sonal, biological, and neurological, which is
dozens of well-known figures in philosophy, to say that a variety of systems develop and
psychology, linguistics, ethology, biology, depend on one another in complex ways.
and anthropology. Indeed, throughout sci- Many stories can be told about these interre-
ence, including AI itself during the 1960s lations. T h e concepts, perspectives, and the-
and 1970s, one finds at least the seeds for oretical frameworks that influenced the sit-
a situated theory of cognition. This chapter uated cognition of the 1980s are still alive in

11
12
WILLIAM I. CLANCEY

and so on.1 A system is viewed as a dynamic


potential for thoughtful reconsideration in
and complex whole, an organization (e.g., a
tomorrow's cognitive research.
cell, a community) located within an envi-
The kev concept across the sciences that
ronment. We look at the inputs, processes,
in the realm of Al and cognitive science
outputs, feedback, and controls to identify
manifested as situated cognition is today
bidirectional relationships that affect and
often called "systems thinking" (von Berta-
constitute a system.
lanffy, 1968). This idea is manifested in
different forms as general systems theory, In identifying parts and wholes, systems
complex systems theory (or simply "com- thinking does not reject the value of reduc-
plexity"; Gell-Mann, 1995; Waldrop, 1992), tionist compartmentalization and compo-
system dynamics, chaos theory (Gleick, nential analysis; rather, systems thinking
198-; Prigogine, 1984), complex adaptive sys- strives for a "both-and" perspective (Wilden,
tems (Holland, 1995), and so on. These are 1987) that shows how the whole makes the
modeling approaches with a broadly shared parts what they are and vice versa. For exam-
perspective on how causality operates in ple, in conceptual systems, metonymic rela-
many natural systems and in some designed tions (tropes or figures of speech) may have
systems (Altman & Rogoff, 1987). For exam- a both-and meaning. Consider how the Syd-
ple, systems thinking views human exper- ney Opera House, derided at first as "a pack
tise as occurring within and developing as of French nuns playing football" (Godwin,
a system involving an economic market, a 1988, p. 75), became a symbol for Australia -
community of practice, facilities, represen- and thus changed the national identity, what
tational tools, reasoning, and perceptual- Australia meant to the Australians and the
motor coordination (Lave, 1988). world. The radical and captivating archi-
The following section provides an intro- tecture, built for a high-culture purpose,
duction to systems thinking and its applica- marked Australia as a modem, preeminent
tion in systems theory. The section is fol- society, occupying a unique position in the
lowed by a review of the historical context
world (as does the building on the harbor's
in which a non-systems-thinking perspec-
edge) and representing a force for change.
tive developed in the study of intelligence,
Thus, the meaning of the nation (the whole)
particularly in Al research. I then briefly
and the meaning of the building (a part)
review how systems thinking relates to and
reaffirmed each other. The building is both
is manifested in the study of cognition. The
contained in the country and a symbol for
core of this chapter then summarizes cross-
cutting themes that constitute the scientific the country as a whole.
antecedents of situated cognition. Finally, In situated cognition, one of the funda-
I consider recent and continuing dilemmas mental concepts is that cognitive processes
that foreshadowed the acceptance of situ- are causally both social and neural. A per-
ated cognition in the fields of Al and psy- son is obviously part of society, but causal
chology and suggest prospects for the next effects in learning processes may be under-
scientific advances. stood as bidirectional (Roschelle & Clancey,
1992).
Systems thinking also views the parts
from different disciplinary viewpoints. For
Overview of Systems Thinking
example, when building a highway, one can
consider it within a broader transportation
Systems thinking involves studying things
system, an economic system, a city and
in a holistic way - understanding the caus-
regional plan, the environmental ecology,
al dependencies and emergent processes
and so on (Schon, 1987). Thus, different
among the elements that comprise the
categories and relationships from different
whole system, whether it be artificial (e.g., viewpoints frame the design of the high-
a computer program), naturally occurring way system, producing different ontologies
(e.g., living systems), cultural, conceptual, of parts and causal processes; the constraints
scientific antecedents of situated cognition n

between these perspectives are the basis for appropriate formulation of systemic struc-
defining trade-offs of costs and benefits. tures and processes. However, computer sci-
Such a multidisciplinary view of prob- entists and psychologists who found situated
lem solving both extends and challenges cognition perplexing around 1990 did not
the disciplinary notion of expertise that recognize its roots in the work of von Neu-
assumed an objective ontology (i.e., truth mann and Burks (1966), cybernetics (von
about the world), which was inherent in Foerster, 1970), or parallel developments
most knowledge-acquisition theories and in general semantics (Korzybski, 1934/1994).
methods (Hayes-Roth, Lenat, & Waterman, Each of these theoretical developments con-
1983) . For example, in the 1970s, it was com- tradicted the tenets of knowledge-base the-
mon to build a medical expert system for a ories of intelligence (Clancey, 1997). These
clinic by working only with physicians in a tenets include a temporally linear process
particular subject area, omitting the nurses, model relating perception, conception, and
hospital managers, computer system admin- action; stored propositional memory; identi-
istrators, insurance companies, family doc- fication of scientific models and knowledge;
tors, and others. and a single-disciplinary view of problem
By adopting a systems perspective, new formulation.
insights may be gained into what prob- In contrast, the development of con-
lems actually occur in a given setting and nectionism in AI (McClelland, Rumelhart,
why; what opportunities technology may 8c PDP Research Group, 1986) promoted
offer; and how changes in tools, processes, theories and models characterized as com-
roles, and facilities may interact in unex- plex adaptive systems (Gell-Mann, 1995;
pected ways (Greenbaum & Kyng, 1991). Morowitz, 2002; Holland, 1995; van Gelder,
These ideas were becoming current in busi- 1991). This distributed-processing, emergent
ness management (e.g., Jaworski & Flowers, organization approach is also manifest in
1996; Senge, 1990) just as situated cognition multi-agent systems modeling, which brings
came onto the scene in AI and cognitive sci- the ideas of cellular automata and systems
ence. theory back to the computational model-
ing of human behavior (Clancey, Sachs,
Sierhuis, 8c van Hoof, 1998; Hewitt, 1977).
Systems Theory

Systems theory is an application of sys- Features of C o m p l e x Systems


tems thinking, closely related to cybernet-
ics (Wiener, 1948) and what is now called In systems theory, the term complex system
"complex systems."' Systems theory was (Center for the Study of Complex Systems,
founded by von Bertalanffy (1968), Ashby n.d.; Gallagher & Appenzeller, 1999; N e w
(1956), and others between the 1940s and the England Complex Systems Institute, n.d.;
1970s on principles from physics, biology, Waldrop, 1992) refers to a system whose
and engineering. Systems theory was espe- properties are not fully explained by linear
cially influential in social and behavioral sci- interactions of component parts. 4 Although
ences, including organizational theory, fam- this idea was well known by the mid-
ily psychotherapy, and economics. Systems 1980s to many AI scientists in the technical
theory emphasizes dynamics involving cir- areas of artificial life and genetic algo-
cular, interdependent, and sometimes time- rithms, its applicability to the study of cog-
delayed relationships. nition proper (e.g., the nature of concep-
Early systems theorists aimed for a gen- tual systems, how memory directly relates
eral systems theory that could explain all sys- perception and action) was not gener-
tems in all fields of science. Wolfram (2002) ally recognized. In particular, applications
argued that a computational approach based to education (situated learning; Lave 8c
on cellular automata begins to provide an Wenger, 1991) and expert system design
M WILLIAM J. CLANCEY

(communities of practice; Wenger, 1998) example, an economy is made up of


were difficult for proponents to articulate - organizations, which are made up of
and for others to understand - because the people.
epistemological foundation of knowledge-
based systems was at question.
The following features of complex sys- Historical Context of the
tems are useful to consider when analyzing Stored-Program Theory of Mind
human behavior, a social system, an organi-
zational design, and so on: Having now presented the seeds of the ref-
ormation (systems thinking and complex
Emergence: In a complex system (ver- systems), I now return to the context of
sus a complicated one), some behav- the reactionary - the cognitive theories that
iors and patterns result from interac- conflict with situated cognition. This brief
tions among elements, and the effects synopsis provides a background for recog-
are nonlinear. nizing the novelty and usefulness of the
Feedback loops: Both negative (damp- crosscutting themes of sociology, language,
ing) and positive (amplifying) feed- biology, and others, which are presented
back relations are found in complex subsequently.
systems. For example, in cognition, First, one must recognize that the
causal couplings occur subconsciously founders of AI in the 1950s were themselves
within processes of conceptualization reforming psychology and even the nature
and perception, consciously as the per- of science. Newell and Simon (1972, p. 9)
son reflects on alternative interpre- explicitly contrast their reductionist process
tations and actions, and serially as theory with behaviorism, which sought to
the physical world and other people explain behavior without reference to unob-
are changed by and respond to the servable internal states. Minsky (1985) refers
person's action. Situated cognition re- to gestalt theories as halting the analysis
veals nonconceptual and nonlinguis- of cognition into interacting components.
tic aspects of these feedback relations Thus, the founders of AI were biased to
while highlighting conceptual aspects view cognition as fully explained by inputs
that pertain to identity and hence and internal processes that could be bro-
social relations. ken down into structure states and func-
Open, observer-defined boundaries: tional transformations. Consequently, situ-
What constitutes the system being ated cognition claims that aspects of the
studied depends on the questions at mechanism of cognition were outside the
head can be interpreted as a fruitless return
issue and the purposes of knowing.
to "the great debates about the empty organ-
For example, is the boundary of a
ism, behaviorism, intervening variables, and
person his or her body? Are clothes
hypothetical constructs" (Newell & Simon,
part of the person? If you stand
1972, pp. 9-10; cf. Vera & Simon, 1993).
uncomfortably close to someone, have
you crossed an emotional boundary? Artificial intelligence research was strong-
Complex systems have a history: How ly shaped by the stored-program von Neu-
the parts have interacted in the past mann computer architecture, consisting of
has changed the parts and what con- a processor that executes instructions sepa-
stitutes their system environment (i.e., rated from a memory containing data and
"the response function depends on a programs (Agrawala & Noh, 1992). The
history of transactions" [Clancey, 1997, derivative information-processing metaphor
p. 280]; Shaw & Todd, 1980). of the mind tended to equate data (i.e.,
Compositional networks: The compo- inputs) with information, models (repre-
nents of the system are often them- sented in the stored programs) with knowl-
selves complex adaptive systems. For edge, logical deduction with reasoning, word
scientific antecedents of situated c o g n i t i o n n

networks with conceptual systems, and knowledge consists of enumerable discrete


problem solving with all human activity elements (e.g., propositions, terms, rela-
(Clancey, 1997, 2002). tions, procedures). The folk distinction be-
The success of the computational meta- tween skills and factual knowledge was well
phor led to the view that a cognitive the- known, but the computational metaphor
ory is not well formed or useful unless suggested that skills were simply com-
it is implemented as a computer program piled from previously known facts and rules
(Vera & Simon, 1993): "the model captures (e.g., Anderson, 1983), which reinforced the
the theory-relevant properties of a domain stored-program memory metaphor. Systems
of study" (Kosslyn, 1980, p. 119). Thus, in thinking may have seemed incompatible
the study of intelligence, most researchers or irrelevant to AI researchers because it
assumed that having a useful, functional threatened the grammar-based theories (see,
understanding (i.e., knowledge) required e.g., Winston & Shellard, 1990) that had
a model (derived from theoretical under- been so successful in facilitating the under-
standing). Questioning this relation threat- standing of aspects of speech recognition,
ened the notion that progress in psychol- text comprehension, scene and object recog-
ogy (and hence AI) depended on explicating nition, and problem solving.
knowledge as propositions, rules, and func- As in other fields, the seeds of situated
tional procedures (e.g., the idea that cognition were probably always present in
commonsense knowledge should be exhaus- the AI community. Connectionism might
tively captured in a knowledge base; Lenat be viewed as the clearest outgrowth of
& Guha, 1990). systems thinking in AI, suggesting a the-
During the three decades starting in the ory of memory compatible with situated
mid-1950s, AI was largely separated from cognition (e.g., Clancey, 1997, pp. 69-75,
sociology and anthropology, and the seeds of chaps. 4 and 7; Clancey, 1999). Connec-
situated cognition in ethology were largely tionism has direct origins in early neural
ignored. 5 During this time, the knowledge- network modeling (e.g., the work of War-
based paradigm took hold, and AI research ren McCulloch) that inspired the founders
shifted dramatically from "blocks world" of AI. Indeed, by 1950, Minsky had begun
games (specifically, stacking children's play- developing "a multiagent learning machine."
ing blocks, but also chess, cryptarithmetic However, "low-level distributed-connection
puzzles, and so on) to the specialized exper- learning machines" were too limited (Min-
tise of professionals in medicine, science, sky, 1985, p. 323; Minsky & Papert, 1969),
and engineering. With the focus on individ- so Minsky focused instead on common-
ual experts (reinforced by the professional sense reasoning. Minsky (1998) expressed
view of textbook knowledge; Schon, 1987), this continuing theoretical concern with
the idea of distributed cognition was not in examples such as knowing that "you can
vogue until the late 1980s, and, if considered push things with a straight stick but not pull
at all, culture was viewed as a collection of them."
common knowledge (rather than as a com- Minsky's (1985) encompassing Society of
plex system of diverse artifacts, skills, and Mind combined the original notion of a net-
practices; Lave, 1988). work of agents with nearly three decades
In trying to identify persistent internal of work on vision and simple problem solv-
structures that cause intelligent behavior, ing, arguing (to paraphrase Winston & Shel-
AI was philosophically grounded in objec- lard, 1990, p. 244) that intelligence emerges
tivism (e.g., scientifically defined universal from contributions of a heterogeneous orga-
ontologies). Failing to recognize different nization of agents. Society of Mind does
disciplinary frameworks for modeling real- not mention systems theory, but it does
ity for different purposes (e.g., the road credit cybernetics with enabling psychology
design example cited previously), AI explic- to use the concept of goal (p. 318). Minsky
itly embraced a reductionist theory that includes internal regulation and feedback in
t6 WILLIAM J. CLANCEY

his framework, which is clearly based on bio- with some individuals questioning what the
logical theory. majority of their colleagues take for granted.
But like Newell and Simon (1972), hav- Even for well-established areas of study, the
ing conceived cognitivism as antibehavior- book is never entirely closed. For example
ist, Minsky (1985) had difficulty relating Kamin's (1969) research on simple animal
his theories of agent interaction to systems cognition questioned whether even classi-
thinking. He stated that emergence was a cal conditioning could be explained with-
"pseudo-explanation" (p. 328), merely label- out delving into cognitive theory. Society of
ing phenomena that could be explained by Mind is indeed a broad exploration that goes
taking into account the interactions of parts, well beyond what could be implemented in
in defining gestah, for example, he says, a computer model when it was formalized
"'holistic' views tend to become scientific from about 1975 to 1985. The formation of
handicaps," and that "there do not appear the Cognitive Science Society in 1980 can
to be any important principles common to itself be viewed as a recognition of the need
the phenomena that have been considered, to regroup and identify the perspectives
from time to time, to be 'emergent'" (p. 328). to be reconciled. Nevertheless, the strong
Although Minsky was right to press for the reaction to situated cognition research from
study of parts and interactions, he appeared about 1985 to the mid-1990s demonstrates
to deny the distinction between complex that something new and conceptually diffi-
and complicated systems. cult to assimilate was being introduced. The
next section outlines the leap to systems
In contrast, at this time, Papert, Minsky's
thinking that an understanding of situated
Perceptrvns collaborator, pursued systems-
cognition requires.
thinking ideas in the realm of education,
building on the work of Piaget to explicitly
teach "administrative ways to use what one
already knows" ("Papert's Principle," Min- Manifestation of Systems Thinking
sky, 1985, p. 102), which Papert realized as in Situated Cognition
a form of constructivism (see section "Con-
structivismi: Philosophy + Cognition"). For psychologists in particular, systems
Also at the same time, Hewitt (1977), thinking reveals contextual effects that can-
a student of Papert and Minsky, had pro- not be viewed simply as environmental or as
moted a decentralized procedural model of input. Thus, one studies authentic, naturally
knowledge. His ideas were picked up in occurring behaviors, with the awareness that
the blackboard architecture of AI programs, inputs and outputs defined by an experi-
which harkened back to 1940s neurobio- menter (e.g., lists of words to be sorted)
logical models. The blackboard approach may set up situations unrelated to the per-
was successful in the 1970s because it pro- son's problematic situations and problem-
vided an efficient functional decomposition solving methods in practice (Lave, 1988).
of a complex process: heterogeneous knowl- In particular, determining what constitutes
edge sources (also called "actors," "beings," information ("the difference that makes a
or "demons") operate in parallel to access difference"; Bateson, 1972, p. 453) is part
and modify a symbolic construction (e.g., an of the cognitive process itself (versus being
interpretation of a speech utterance) repre- predefined by the experimenter) and often
sented at different levels of abstraction (e.g., involves causal feedback with physical trans-
phonemes, words). The relation of this com- formations of materials, such that look-
putational architecture to complex, open ing, perceiving, conceiving, reasoning, and
systems in nature and society was not gen- changing the world are in dynamic relation
erally acknowledged until the 1990s (but see (Dewey, 1938).
Hewitt, 1985).
One way to understand a dynamic pro-
We must recognize that every field cess is that the system that is operating -
has its own controversies and antinomies, the processes being studied, modeled,
SCIENTIFIC ANTECEDENTS OF SITUATED COGNITION 17

controlled, and/or designed - cannot be individuals and groups in processes of assim-


understood in its development or function ilation that are inevitably adapted and inter-
as strictly localized within one level of preted from unique perspectives (impro-
analysis (e.g., Gould, 1987). That is, cog- vised in action, not simply transferred and
nitive processes are not strictly attributable applied).
(reducible) to neurological mechanisms, nor Articulating the situated view of knowl-
are they purely conceptual (e.g., driven by edge has been and remains difficult because,
knowledge), characteristics of a person, or to some people, it has suggested the cul-
properties of the physical world. But rather, tural relativism of science (Bruner, 1990;
what a person experiences and what an Slezak, 1989). Indeed, the debate appears
observer views - for example, of organ- on the public scene in the issue of h o w
isms, mental performance, individuals, orga- U.S. Supreme Court judges are to interpret
nizations, populations, ecologies - is the the U.S. Constitution. 6 But ironically, fears
ongoing product of a coupled causal rela-
of arbitrariness (stemming from the view
tion, such that the entity being studied and
that if an understanding is not objective it
its context (whether neurological, concep-
must be arbitrary) assume that either sci-
tual, physical-artifactual, interpersonal, or
entific or legal activities might occur in a
ecological) shape each other in a complex
vacuum, apart from a complex system of
system. Thus, scientific insights of systems
social-historical-physical constraints - as if,
thinking (read "situated thinking") in areas
for example, a science that ignored phys-
of study ranging from neurology to environ-
ical realities of how sensors operate could
mentalism are often framed as blended disci-
accomplish anything at all, or that checks
plines: genetic epistemology, the biology of
and balances in the legal system would allow
cognition, the sociology of knowledge, neu-
ropsychology, evolutionary biology, social a judge's ruling that ignored precedent to
cognition, and so on. stand. Wilden (1987) refers to these confused
debates (e.g., objective versus arbitrary)
as "a switch between imaginary opposites"
Claims, Challenges, and Contributions (p. 125). Thus, some objections to situated
cognition arose because of a reactionary con-
In summary, situated can be understood as cern that open systems could be arbitrary,
emphasizing the contextual, dynamic, sys- and that control must be imposed f r o m out-
temic, nonlocalized aspects of the mind, side to keep complex systems organized (see
mental operations, identity, organizational Clancey, 2005; Lakoff, 2002 [analysis of polit-
behavior, and so on. Across the sciences of ical metaphors]).
psychology, anthropology, sociology, ethol- In summary, situated cognition devel-
ogy, biology, and neurology, and their spe- oped not as a discipline (or a movement)
cialized investigations of knowledge, lan- within AI or psychology or educational tech-
guage, and learning, the systemic, holistic nology but as a way of thinking proclaimed
view strives to explain behavior within by some of the best-known scientists of the
a developmental and evolutionary frame- twentieth century in psychology, biology,
work. Specifically, situated cognition views ethology, sociology, psychiatry, and phi-
human knowledge not as final objective facts losophy. Granting that the threads of the
but as (1) arising conceptually (e.g., dynam- argument were known since D e w e y (1896)
ically constructed, remembered, reinter- at least, what did the proponents of situ-
preted) and articulated within a social con- ated cognition of the 1980s and 1990s add
text (i.e., a context conceived with respect to our understanding of systems, causality,
to social roles and norms); (2) varying within and mental operations? T h e contributions
a population in specialized niches (areas include:
of expertise); (3) socially reproduced (e.g.,
learning in communities of practice; Lave I Better scientific models and modeling
81 Wenger, 1991); and (4) transformed by
techniques (e.g., models of m e m o r y and
WILLIAM J. CLANCEY

learning, such as Edelman's 1987 neuronal its manifestations in different settings. From
group selection) a psychological perspective, the fundamen-
• Relating explanatory models on different tal issues often boil down to how we
levels (e.g., symbolic and neural models; should properly relate memory, percep-
Clancey, 1999) tion, problem solving, and learning. For
• Improved theories and practices in learn- many AI researchers and cognitive psy-
ing and instruction (e.g., Koschmann, in chologists, such a theory must be inher-
press), as well as in software engineering ently expressed as a mechanism, in partic-
(e.g., Clancey, 2006; Greenbaum & Kyng, ular a computer program that implements
1991), arising through extensive multi- the theory of memory and mental process-
disciplinary collaborations between social ing. But systems thinkers argued that cog-
and computer scientists nitive processes are not like conventional
• The extension of cognitive theory beyond computer programs. Wilden (1987), a com-
games and expert problem solving to munication theorist, contrasted a mech-
include the nature of consciousness and anism (meaning something like a clock
emotion (e.g., autism, dreaming, dys- made of gears, a "machineism") with an
functions). organicism (essentially an open system).
Further, Bateson (1972), an anthropologist-
But perhaps most visibly and germane to philosopher, explored whether "mental"
the original objectives of AI, situated was a phenomenon that could be localized
robotics flourished as dynamic cognition as a process inside the brain (as opposed
theories - based on feedback, interaction, to being a person-environment interactive
and emergence - inspired new approaches process).
to navigation, perceptual categorization, and Telling this multidimensional, histori-
language learning (Clancey, 1997, chap. 5). cal development is challenging, for it was
never known to anyone at any time in all
of its threads and perspectives. Moreover,
Disciplinary Perspectives because of its complex form, we cannot find
a viewpoint for grasping it, as if it were a
In relating cognitive studies to other sci- landscape, from a single, all-encompassing
ences, it is apparent that no single disci- perspective. Post hoc we can trace themes,
pline has all the answers. All have had par- such as epistemology and the theory of
allel developments that were contrary to memory, and make causal links among indi-
situated cognition and even within their viduals, publications, institutions, and even
own discipline were viewed as lacking an pivotal academic meetings. Even a litany
appropriate contextual aspect. For example, of concepts or issues is perspectival, articu-
some anthropologists might be critical of lated, and exploited within a particular com-
ethnoscience (a development within cogni- munity's interests and problems. It helps to
recognize the many dimensions of analysis
tive anthropology) because the study of how
at play and to attempt to identify issues that
people perceive their environment through
pertain to different concerns, such as the
their use of language may use phonemic
examples that follow:
analysis too narrowly, thereby reifying lin-
guistic categories as if they had a reality apart
from their existence within conceptual and Academic disciplines: Philosophy, psy-
cultural systems. chology, sociology, education, man-
Arguably, epistemology underlies all of agement, anthropology, biology, com-
situated cognition, and thus one might say puter science, neural science
that all cognitive research in sociology, Cross-disciplines: Philosophy of mind/
anthropology, education, psychology, and science, cybernetics, social psychol-
even neurology is aimed at developing an ogy, cognitive anthropology, cogni-
appropriate epistemology and articulating tive science, AI, neuropsychology,
scientific antecedents of situated c o g n i t i o n

evolutionary/genetic epistemology, evo- same time the neural sciences adapted an


lutionary biology AI computational modeling method to for-
Applications: Robotics, instruction and mulate the theory of connectionism? Strik-
training, process control automation ingly, each 1980s thread relating to learning,
Methodologies: Sociotechnical systems, animal cognition, and neurology was firmly
ethnomethodology, knowledge acqui- grounded in well-known (including Nobel
sition, cognitive task analysis Prize-winning) research forty to one hun-
Modeling/representational frameworks: dred years earlier. Indeed, one would have
Theory of computation, cybernetics, to view the development of scientific ideas
semantic networks, heuristic classifica- relating to situated cognition as a complex
tion, qualitative causal modeling, neu- system itself - nonlinear, historical, emer-
ral networks (connectionist models), gent, nested, networked, with open bound-
genetic programming aries and feedback loops, and so on.
Cognitive functions: Representation, In particular, and crucially, no discipline
memory, knowledge, learning or focus of study is more fundamental or
Cognitive elements: Percepts, concepts, "inside" another: a computational theory
relations, procedures, beliefs, goals, will not "explain" psychology any more than
desires, theories, activities, motives, situated learning can explain culture. Also,
skills insights do not accumulate monotonically;
Cognitive behavior: Language, classifica- insights from D e w e y or 1950s cybernetics
tion, problem solving, navigation might be stomped on by today's c o m m u -
Systemic concepts: Dynamics, feedback, nication theory (Radford, 1994).
self-regulation, emergence, chaos, N o t only the history of situated cognition
interactionism, constructivism, con- but also the systems comprising cognition
textualism, ecology, ethnomethodol- are in principle complexly related. Physio-
ogy, self/identity logical, conceptual, and organizational sys-
tems are mutually constraining — not caus-
In teaching a course about situated cog- ally nested - in what Wilden (1987, p. 74)
nition from a historical perspective, the piv- calls a "dependent hierarchy" of environ-
otal scientific areas of study are the nature mental contexts. Culture is the most diverse
of learning (e.g., as social, psychological, and complex system, but it lies at the bot-
neurological), animal cognition, and neurol- tom of the dependent hierarchy. Like any
ogy (i.e., how the brain accomplishes cogni- open system, culture depends for its exis-
tive functions). Indeed, although symbolic tence on the systems that contain it environ-
AI and problem-solving research in cogni- mentally - society, organic (biological), and
tive science fell behind the systems think- inorganic nature (at the top). Diversity and
ing developed in other sciences in the 1970s, complexity increase descending the depen-
it is apparent that systems thinking itself dent hierarchy; constraints become more
was changing dramatically, as it was reartic- general ascending. An individual organism is
ulated in a communication theory that com- a complex of the two higher orders of com-
bined physics and philosophy by cyberneti- plexity (organic plus inorganic), and "a per-
cists (von Foerster, 1970, 2003), and then son . . . is a complex of 'both-and' relation-
developed into chaos and complexity theory ships between all four orders of complexity"
in the 1980s (Prigogine, 1984; Waldrop, 1992) (culture, society, organic, and inorganic),
and into what Wolfram (2002) calls "a new and so cannot be logically fitted within this
kind of science" based on cellular automata hierarchy (Wilden 1987, p. 74).
(pp. 12-14). At best, in writing a scientific history
Is it a coincidence that the term situ- one can hope to mention most of the
ated learning was introduced in the 1980s names and ideas that other stakeholders
not long after animal cognition became a (e.g., researchers in education, psychology,
mainstream topic for ethology, or at the anthropology) would cite, providing not as
william j. g l a n c e v

much a chronological tale but a coherent James, and John Dewey (see Gallagher, this
relation of people and concepts that fit to tell volume). This perspective emphasized that
a coherent, useful story. Especially, the best knowledge was not merely transferred but
motivation might be the question, What that a transformation developed within and
should any student know about the work through the person's action. Most simply,
that came before, particularly, what might this means that people can be instructed
be fruitfully read again, in the original, for and are not simply learning habits (rote
inspiration? This is my criterion for select- learning). Importantly, "being instructed"
ing the scientific ideas that follow; I empha- means that what is learned is subjectively
size primary sources that future researchers interpreted and assimilated. The subjective
should read and interpret for themselves. aspect emphasizes both that knowledge can-
not be identified with the curriculum -
which Dewey (1902/1981) called a "map for
Crosscutting Themes of Cognition learning" - and that the learner is consciously
reflecting on and making sense of instruc-
I organize scientific work related to situated tive situations and materials in actively look-
cognition according to what discipline or ing and touching while doing things. Two
field of study the advocates were grounded constructivist principles suggested by von
in - philosophy, education, sociology, lin- Glasersfeld (1984, 1989) build on Piaget's
guistics, biology, neurology, anthropology - work and philosophical realism (Berkeley,
and then group related work by themes that 1710/1963; Vico, 1710/1858): (1) knowledge is
were developed by studying cognition from not passively received but actively built up
the given perspective. This is different from by the cognizing subject, and (2) the func-
a cognitive-element perspective, insofar as tion of cognition is adaptive and serves the
research on memory, for example, appears organization of the experiential world, not
both in the "language + cognition" category the discovery of ontological reality.
as well as in the "neurology + cognition"
category. My aim is to show fundamental
relations between ideas, not what aspects of Constructivism2: Education +
mind were derived from the studies. The Cognition
themes are research topics embodying a sit-
uated perspective. Space allows for only a Constructivist epistemology combined with
brief mention of each person's work 1 for developmental psychology to greatly influ-
elaboration, please see the references cited. ence pedagogical designs in the twenti-
eth century (Dewey, 1902/1981, 1934, 1938;
Piaget, 1932, 1970, 1970/1971). Research
Constructivism,: Philosophy + emphasizes the development of individ-
Cognition uals to understand the learner's active
cognitive operations (e.g., Dewey's [1938]
Constructivism is a theory of learning notion of inquiry) strategies, stages of
according to which people create knowledge conceptual development, and the nature
from the interaction between their exist- of experiential processes of assimilation
ing knowledge or beliefs and the new ideas and accommodation. Learning interactions
or situations they encounter.7 Constructivist can be analyzed in many dimensions,
pedagogy tends to stress the importance of including perception, conception, repre-
both teacher/environmental guidance and sentation, skills, actions, material interac-
learner activity. One thread of construc- tion, and transformation (e.g., interpret-
tivist thinking developed in the philoso- ing instructions, arranging objects into a
phy of psychology, in the late-nineteenth- design). Perception-conception and action
century American pragmatism (Konvitz & are understood to mutually interact (which
Kennedy, i960) of Charles Peirce, William Dewey [1896] called "coordination").
scientific antecedents of situated c o g n i t i o n 21

Constructivism,: Sociology + the emergence of mind and self out of


Cognition the social process of significant communi-
cation, which become the foundation of the
More broadly, a social perspective empha- symbolic-interactionist school of sociology
sizes that the environment includes (often and social psychology (Cronk, 2005). S y m -
physically but always conceptually) other bolic interaction focuses on the construction
people with w h o m the learner participates of personal identity through interactions
in activity systems (Leont'ev, 1979; Vygot- of individuals, especially through linguistic
sky, 1978; Wertsch, 1979, 19.8:5, 1991). T h e communication (i.e., symbolic interaction).
individual and society are mutually inter- Meanings are thus socially constructed and
acting: " c u l t u r e . . . is the capacity for con- interrelate with actions. Other noted sym-
stantly expanding the range and accuracy of bolic interactionists are Blumer (1969) and
one's perception of meanings" (Dewey, 1916, G o f f m a n (1959). Polanyi (1966) developed
p. 123). A social-cognitive analysis empha- these antipositivist theories further in his
sizes interpersonal communication; mutual, elucidation of the nature of tacit knowledge.
dependent action in a group (e.g., as in play- By the 1970s, sociology ideas stemming
ing hide-and-seek); action by a group (e.g., from turn of the century w e r e reformu-
involving specialized and coordinate roles, as lated in the sociology of knowledge (Berger
in a team playing soccer); and identity (the & Luckmann, 1966), a constructivist theory
conscious concept of self as a person engag- that emphasized the learning of individuals
ing in normative, participatory activity). in their social lives, as actively making sense
D e w e y and Bentley (1949) describe this of and thus forming a social reality (e.g.,
system in which learning occurs as "trans- Shibutani, 1966). T h e anthropologist Hall's
actional," emphasizing mutual, historical The Silent Language (1959/1973) provides a
development across levels; between individ- virtuoso exposition of the nature of culture,
uals; and through comprehending and doing in a theory of communication that relates
(Clancey, in press). C o l e (1996) and C o l e formal, informal (e.g., spatial-temporal lay-
and Wertsch (1996, p. 251) emphasize this out, gestures), and technical conceptual sys-
co-construction aspect: both the child and tems. Latour (1999) has applied the social
the environment are active, and culture is construction perspective to science itself,
"the m e d i u m within which the t w o active leading to the side debate that situated
parties to development interact." cognition was undermining the integrity
Both the social and perceptual-motor of science (Slezak, 1989). Stemming f r o m
coordination perspectives suggest that the the early w o r k by D u r k h e i m (1912/1947),
phenomenon of knowing (or mind) can- the philosophy of science here intersects
not be localized as a system existing wholly with the epistemological study of c o m m o n
within a person's brain. As explained, this sense, namely that scientists and ordinary
was seriously at odds with arguments against folk use different tools to develop theories
behaviorism and gestalt theory, and thus of their world but are still constrained by
appeared to turn away again f r o m decom- (and actively changing) a social-historical
posing the brain's structures and processes. environment of language, instruments, and
Constructivism was not denying the role of values.
the brain but emphasizing that it was not the
locus of control in determining behavior -
nor w a s the individual the locus of control - Remembering, Storytelling,
and in no case was h u m a n behavior simply a Theorizing: Language 4- Cognition
linear process of logical transformation f r o m
stimulus to decision to action.
Philosophy, pedagogy, and sociology defined
A l t h o u g h not o f t e n cited in situated broad constraints for a c o m p l e x system the-
cognition research by psychologists, M e a d ory of mind, but it remained f o r m o r e
(1934), a sociologist, developed a theory of specific studies of cognitive processes to
22 william j. c l a n c e y

elucidate what the processes were and how (see Shapiro, 1992, pp. 1427-1443). Ironically,
they were distributed and temporally devel- Bartlett's theory of memory is based not on
oped. In particular, a focus on language in storage of schemata but rather on active
its manifestations of remembering, story- processes that are always adaptively con-
telling (narrative), and theorizing revealed structed within action, biased through pre-
a dynamic, constructive aspect that fit the vious ways of working together, and when
pragmatists' and interactionists' views that engaged "actively doing something all the
behavior itself was transformative and not time" (Bartlett, 1932/1977, p. 201). Thus, he
merely an applicative result (an output) argued for a process memory, not a descrip-
from the "real" cognitive workings of infor- tive memory of processes or a preconfigured
mation input, matching, retrieval, deduc- memory of stored procedures (see Clancey,
tion, and action-plan configuration. Instead, 1997, chap. 3).
we have the notions of dynamic mem- Bartlett developed his theory by ana-
ory, reconstructive memory, representing lyzing story recollection, showing how
as an observable behavior (e.g., speaking details, fragmentary ideas, and narrative
as representing), and thinking as including were remembered and reconstructed. Lof-
nonverbal conceptualizing (versus purely tus (1979/1996) applied these ideas to reveal
linguistic deduction). In this shift - from the improvisational aspects of memory in
information as stimuli extracted from the legal testimony. Bransford et al. (1977) and
environment and responses as stored pro- Jenkins (1974) demonstrated in experimen-
grams to a theory of remembering-in-action tal settings how linguistic-narrative memory
(a process memory) - situated cognition blended phrases, roles, and themes in ways
more radically turns from behaviorism than people did not realize. All of this suggested
information processing was able. that remembering was not merely retriev-
The language-related foundations of situ- ing but actively reconstructing and reactivat-
ated cognition were well established before ing ways of thinking - and seeing, hearing,
AI research on comprehension and dis- doing.
course by the pragmatists (see especially Schank's (1982) Dynamic Memory high-
Dewey's [1939/1989, p. 534] response to Rus- lighted how past experience, such as previ-
sell, Wittgenstein's [1953/1958] break with ous encounters in a restaurant, shapes how
positivism in his analysis of the language we interpret and act in situations we con-
game, Ryle's [1949] distinction between ceive to be similar. He suggested that fail-
"knowing how" and "knowing that," Langer's ure of expectation was particularly impor-
[1942/1958] distinction between discursive tant in constructing new concepts. Although
and presentational representation, Austin's formalized by Schank's research group in
[1962] view of language as speech acts, a network of stored descriptions, this work
and the general semantics of Korzybski emphasized the historical nature of knowl-
[1934/1994]). edge. Learning and behaving are insepa-
rable, with learning occurring in behavior
itself, in contrast with the view that learning
Remembering
occurs only in reflective reconstruction after
A situated theory of human memory is a problem-solving episode is complete. Fur-
like an arch keystone that relates neural, thermore, normative (social) behavior can
symbolic information processing and social be described by scripts (Schank & Abelson,
views of cognition. Bartlett's (1932/1977) 1977), which are learned patterns of behav-
notion of schemata was of course influential ior based on the sequence of experience,
in qualitative modeling applications, rang- not compiled from theoretical models about
ing from visual processing (e.g., Minsky's restaurants, and so on (for further relation
[1985] frames) to expert (knowledge-based) of scripts to situated cognition, see Clancey,
problem solving and case-based reasoning 2002).
scientific antecedents of situated c o g n i t i o n

Conceptual Structure these relationships w e r e v i e w e d as e n u m e r -


able, definable, and in s o m e respects admit-
Focusing on aspects of storytelling, ting to f u r t h e r d e c o m p o s i t i o n . S u c h descrip-
metaphor, and comprehension, researchers tions ignore the d y n a m i c relations across
explored how concepts are related in perception and motor systems, the concep-
h u m a n understanding, h o w these relations tual organization of physical skills (espe-
develop, and how they are manifest in cially in t h e d y n a m i c s of a n d a m o n g ges-
linguistic behavior. This work tended to ture, sound, and vision), and h o w social
underscore that knowledge is more than n o r m s (e.g., conceptualization of activity)
c o n c e p t u a l n e t w o r k s w i t h n o d e s and links develop through interactions. In particular,
representing words and their attributes. c u e s a n d t i m i n g (as in a d a n c e or c o m p l e x
Instead, conceptual understanding is not group conversation) cannot be easily p r e -
separate f r o m sensory and gestural ( e m b o d - described or linearly s e q u e n c e d as f r a m e s
ied) e x p e r i e n c e ( L a k o f f , 1987); relations can or schemata in a k n o w l e d g e base. R a t h e r ,
be m u t u a l l y defining (e.g., W i l d e n ' s [1987] the m e n t a l constructs are b e h a v i o r patterns
exposition of dialectics); and a linguist's that are activated and adaptively impro-
reduction of speaking to grammatical f o r m vised through ongoing tacit reflection (e.g.,
and definitions "alienates language f r o m the Schon's [1987] knowing-in-action). T h i s is
s e l f (Tyler, 1978, p. 17). Similarly, B r u n e r not to say that t h e grammatical descrip-
(1990) highlighted t h e role of narrative in tions of observable patterns are n o t accu-
the construction of t h e self. Narrative is rate or useful theoretical tools b u t to ques-
a representational form that transcends tion w h e t h e r such models can be identified

individual concepts through "tropes" of with the neural structures that participate in

agents, scenes, goals, and so on, that h a v e t h e described b e h a v i o r (see C l a n c e y , 1997,

interpretive value, but not logical "truth c h a p . 1).

conditions" (pp. 59-60). T h u s understand-


ing t h e genre, development, and function Learning by Doing and Inquiry
of narrative requires systems thinking.
These theoretical perspectives each As previously noted, the philosophical, psy-
sought in their o w n w a y to avoid the pit- chological, a n d social d e v e l o p m e n t of t h e
falls of a n a r r o w structuralism, w h i c h t e n d e d systems view of cognition w a s often based
to localize behavior, knowledge, or meaning on or directly influenced educational theory
in o n e b o x of a m e n t a l process (e.g., c o n - and designs. T h i s is m o s t o b v i o u s in t h e w o r k
ceptual m e m o r y , g r a m m a r ) w h i l e ignoring of D e w e y (who started his own school),
t h e d y n a m i c relations b e t w e e n s y s t e m s (e.g., Piaget, Bruner, and Papert, and t h e n m a n i -
perception-conception-action, experience- fest in the analyses by Bamberger and S c h o n
self-participation). (1983) o f learning i n t h e arts, s u c h a s m u s i c
Structuralism, attributed to Titchener (Bamberger, 1991) and architectural design
(Plucker, 2003), sought to explain behavior (Schon, 1987). Each explored an aspect
through the interaction of component men- of constructionism (Papert & Harel, 1991),
tal structures, in t h e m a n n e r of a c h e m i s t which claimed that making and experiment-
explaining reactions in terms of atomic and ing w i t h physical objects (including d r a w -
molecular interactions. In his core-context ings and notations) facilitates t h e learning of
theory of meaning, Titchener suggested a abstract concepts, as well as the generation
complex system, by which "a new mental of n e w insights that p r o m o t e abstract think-
p r o c e s s ( t h e c o r e ) a c q u i r e d its m e a n i n g f r o m ing. T h e theoretical claims w e r e b a s e d o n
the context of other mental processes within constructivism, but can be read as respond-
w h i c h it occurs" (Plucker, 2003). H o w e v e r , ing t o A I ' s m o d e l s of knowledge acquisi-
in m o s t m o d e l s of language until the mid- tion: (1) learning is an active, w i l l f u l p r o c e s s ,
1980s (predating neural network models), not a passive comprehension and storage of
517 WILLIAM J. CLANCEY

tacts and procedures to be later applied, (2) already well established in biology, as scien-
understanding requires experience, whether tists came to realize that neither the cell nor
physical or in the imagination, such that the organism could be isolated for under-
multiple modalities of thought are coor- standing the sustenance, development, or
dinated, and (3} conceptual understanding evolution of life. Systems thinking, involv-
relies on perceptual-motor experience and ing notions of dynamic and emergent inter-
simpler ideas, such that learning can be actions, was necessary to relate the interac-
viewed and usefully guided in stages, which tions of inherited phenotype, environmental
themselves require time and exploration to factors, and the effect of learning. Indeed,
develop. Most important, this dynamic sys- in reviewing the literature, one is struck by
tems perspective does not deny the central how ethologists (studying natural behavior
role of formal representations (e.g., musi- of animals), neurologists (focusing on neu-
cal notation) but rather seeks to explain ral and cell assemblies), and cyberneticists
how representations are created and acquire (forming cross-disciplinary theories of sys-
meaning in practice. tems and information) were meeting and
Schón (1979,1987) combined these ideas writing about similar aspects of life and cog-
quite practically in his reinterpretation of nition. Yet, with a more narrow focus on
Dewey's (1938) theory of inquiry (Clancey, intelligence, and then expertise, the rele-
1997, pp. 207-213). For example, his anal- vance of these broad theories to AI and cog-
ysis of architectural design revealed how nitive science was not recognized for several
decades. Thus, even though one can easily
conceiving, articulating, drawing, perceiv-
see cybernetics as kin to situated cognition,
ing, and interpreting/reflecting were dynam-
cybernetics was not presented in AI text-
ically influencing one another in nested and
books as a necessary background for study-
parallel processes. Within the Al commu-
ing the nature of intelligence.
nity, these ideas were first developed most
visibly in the idea of cognitive appren-
ticeship (Brown, Collins, & Duguid, 1989;
Collins, Brown, & Newman, 1989), which Cybernetics
produced a lively debate (Bredo, 1994; The intersection of neurology, electronic
Greeno, 1997; see also Clancey's [1992] network theory, and logic modeling around
response to Sandberg & Wielinga, 1991). World War II was popularized by Nor-
In related naturalistic studies, Gardner bert Wiener (1948), who defined cybernet-
(1985) examined the varieties of intelligence, ics as the study of teleological mechanisms,
emphasizing skills in different modalities exemplified by the feedback mechanisms in
that people exhibited or combined in dif- biological and social systems. As we have
ferent ways. This work had the dual effect seen throughout, the notions of memory
of highlighting what schoolwork and tests and localization were central. Von Foerster
ignored and how the verbal emphasis of (1973) wrote: "The response of a nerve cell
problem-solving research over the previous does not encode the physical nature of the
two decades had ignored physical, visual, agents that caused its response. Encoded is
and even interpersonal forms of knowledge. only 'how much' at this point on my body,
but not 'what'" (pp. 214-215). That is, the
observer's described world of objects, prop-
Animal Cognition, Evolution, and erties, and events is not represented at this
Ecology Feedback: Biology + level in the nervous system; rather, what
Cognition is registered or encoded is a difference or
change as the body interacts with its envi-
In many respects, the application of sys- ronment.
tems thinking that was so confusing and Similarly, Maturana and Varela's notion
indeed threatening to psychologists and AI of organizational closure views information
researchers in the 1970s and 1980s was ("in-formation") as a dynamic relation and
SCIENTIFIC ANTECEDENTS OF SITUATED COGNITION 25

not something that flows into the organ- cognitivist perspective (see especially Shaw
ism as instructions or objectively meaningful & Todd, 1980; elucidated by Clancey, 1997,
packets. Maturana and Varela's (Maturana, pp. 280-283). psychology this alternative
1975; 1978, 1983; Maturana & Varela, 1980, view was also called "contextualism" (Hoff-
1987) theoretical framework of the biology man & Nead, 1983).
of cognition also formalizes the complex-
systems concepts of structural coupling
Ethology
(mutual causal relations between organism
and environment) and autopoiesis (self- From a historical perspective, perhaps the
creating) (see Capra, 1996; Clancey, 1997, oddest disconnection in the science of cog-
pp. 85-92). Von Glasersfeld (1974) called this nition is the study of intelligence by early
"radical constructivism" (see also Riegler, Al and cognitive scientists without refer-
2001). ence to animal research. In part, this could
Bateson (1972, 1988, 1991) was a cen- reflect perhaps a resistance to attribute cog-
tral figure in the inquiry relating cybernet- nition per se to animals, as animal cognition
ics, biology, and cognition. His reach was only flourished on the scientific scene in the
especially broad, including cultural anthro- 1980s (e.g., Gould, 1986; Griffin, 1992; Roit-
pology, ethology, and family therapy. For blat, Bever, & Terrace, 1984). And certainly
example, his theory of the double bind the Skinnerian behaviorist psychology of the
in schizophrenia claimed that contradic- 1950s and 1960s appeared to be more about
tory messages (e.g., a verbal command and rote animal training than about problem
an incommensurate gesture) could disrupt solving. Nevertheless, the work of Konrad
conceptual coordination. Thus, in under- Lorenz, Karl von Frisch, and Nikolaas Tin-
standing schizophrenia as not only an inter- bergen, winners of the Nobel Prize in 1973,
nal mental-biological dysfunction but also a was well known through the 1950s. In the
confused interpersonal dynamic - a disor- autobiography accompanying his Nobel lec-
ganized relation between person and envi- ture, Lorenz (1973) says he early on believed
ronment - Bateson brought a dialectic, that his responsibility ("chief life task") was
ecological notion of information and com- to develop an evolutionary theory of ani-
munication to understanding development mal psychology, based on the comparative
in biology and social science. study of behavior. He was influenced by Karl
Biihler and Egon Brunswick to consider a
psychology of perception tied to epistemol-
Ecological Psychology ogy; similarly, he found in Erich von Hoist "a
Gibson (1979), a psychologist, developed a biologically oriented psychologist who was,
systems theory of cognition that explained at the same time, interested in theory of
behavior as a relation that develops in knowledge."
located action. For example, rather than say- Frisch's analysis of the "waggle dance" of
ing that a person can jump over a stream, honeybees, The Bee's Language (published
one might say that a given stream affords in German in 1923), is an exemplary study
jumping when a person is running as he or of situated animal behavior in groups (com-
she approaches (Turvey & Shaw, 1995). Such pare this study over time and across loca-
an affordance is a dynamic relation between tions with feeding pellets to pigeons in a cage
a moving person and the environment, not apparatus). Tinbergen's (1953) The Herring
located in the person or in the stream. Tur- Gull's World teased apart the stimuli orga-
vey and Shaw further developed this the- nizing social behavior patterns.
ory relating perception and motion, char- The study of animal navigation and
acterizing the organism-in-environment as a social behavior is especially profound for
reciprocal relation, seeking a biologically rel- Al and cognitive science because it reveals
evant information theory (see Clancey, 1997, what simpler mechanisms - fixed pro-
chap. n). They explicitly argued against the grams with perhaps limited learning during
26 WILLIAM J. CLANCEY

maturation - can accomplish. Studying ani- Lashley, 1951) and predated computational
mals forces the scientist to acknowledge that modeling of problem solving. Rosenfield
an observer's descriptive world maps and (1988, 2000), Edelman (1987), and Freeman
principled rule descriptions of behavior (as (1991) directly addressed and often critiqued
might be found in an expert system), though cognitive theories, showing that they were
useful to model animal behavior, could not incoherent from the perspective of com-
be the generative mechanism in creatures plex systems theory and were biologically
lacking a language for modeling the world implausible.
and behavior. This realization, pioneered by Similarly, Sacks (1987), a neurologist,
Brooks (1991), produced in the late 1980s a used case studies of how patients survive
wide variety of animal-inspired mechanisms and adapt to reveal how neural processes,
in the field of situated robotics (Clancey, the environment, and issues such as self-
1997, Part 2). The formulation of a theory of hood interact to inhibit or enable men-
dynamic (complex) systems (termed chaos tal experience. Sacks was especially adept
systems) by Prigogine (1984) helped explain, at showing how conventional neurology's
for example, ant organization around a tests and dysfunctional categories veritably
food source. In particular, the complex sys- "decomposed" the patient by an inventory
tems concept of dissipative structures (in of deficits, while instead the patient's expe-
which decreased energy becomes a source rience developed as a compensatory reor-
of increased order) inspired Steels's (1990) ganizing process of preserving and reestab-
designs of self-organizing robotic systems. lishing identity (persona). Notice how the
Related work in artificial life (Resnick, idea of a person - involving personal projects
1997) in the 1980s sought to explain the (Sacks, 1995), temperament, friendships,
development of systemic organization and cherished experiences, and so on - is very
emergent properties through the same cellu- different from the typical antiseptic refer-
lar automata mechanisms that inspired Min- ence to humans as subjects of study, in
sky in 1950. Kaufmann (1993) moved this which it becomes all too easy to then ignore
investigation to molecular biology, interest- issues of identity and consciousness.
ingly combining the strings-of-symbols idea
from information processing with the notion
of self-organizing feedback systems. He sug- Contemporary Theories of K n o w l e d g e
gested the applicability of this approach to and Learning: Anthropology +
understanding economics, conceptual sys- Cognition
tems, and cultural organization - hence "the
new kind of science" (Wolfram, 2002). At this point in the story, the history of
science by the late 1980s becomes the con-
temporary development of situated cogni-
Neurology and Neuropsychology: tion in Al and cognitive science (Clancey,
Neurology + Cognition 1997). Some social scientists were shift-
ing from third-world sites to business and
Neuroscience, inspired by mechanisms of school settings in the United States, Europe,
computational connectionism and grounded and South America, focusing especially on
in magnetic resonance imaging and related learning (e.g., Lave 81 Wenger, 1991). These
methods for inspecting brain processes, researchers were especially influenced by
raced ahead in the 1990s with new models Dewey, Vygotsky, Piaget (e.g., Cole &
of categorization learning, visual processing, Wertsch, 1996), Bateson, Gibson, Hall, and
sensory memory, and theories relating emo- Mead (e.g., Suchman, 1987). Often anthro-
tion to cognition (Damasio, 1994). pology provided an organizing theoreti-
As previously related, connectionism cal and methodological perspective (Green-
derived from early work in neural network baum & Kyng, 1991). Studies of learning
modeling (e.g., Head, 1920; Hebb, 1949; and instructional design were transformed
SCIENTIFIC ANTECEDENTS OF SITUATED COGNITION

to relate information and participatory pro- tic network of concepts and relations - sup-
cesses in activity systems (Greeno, 2006). posedly modified in long-term memory and
Drawn in perhaps by the formation processed by a central processing unit that
of the Cognitive Science Society in 1980, was by assumption identical in every human
some social scientists and psychologists brain.
reacted especially to the theory that all Nevertheless, some cognitive phenomena
problem-solving behavior was generated stood out as requiring consideration: com-
from a preformulated plan derived from monsense knowledge (nobody needs physics
verbally defined goals and deductive infer- calculations to know whether a spilled liq-
ence about problem-solving methods (Agre, uid is likely to reach the end of a table), the
1997; Schon, 1987). For example, Lave (1988) relation of imagery and discursive thought
questioned whether human expertise could (Langer, 1942/1958), the subjective nature
be inventoried and indeed stored in a of meaning versus the idea that knowl-
knowledge base. Situated action and situ- edge consisted of stored proposition mod-
ated learning sought to expose how peo- els of facts and rules (highlighted by the
ple actually behaved, what they knew, and philosophical analysis of Winograd & Flo-
how they learned during work. Some of res, 1986), language learning (how does a
the earliest proponents were Scribner and child learn so much grammar from so few
Cole (1973), Rogoff and Lave (1984), and examples?), ill-structured problems (Simon,
Suchman (1987). The previously mentioned 1973), musical creation and performance
ideas of cognitive apprenticeship devel- (e.g., Smoliar, 1973), how symbols in a cog-
oped in this academic community of prac- nitive system are grounded (Hamad, 1990),
tice, which resided predominantly at the and so on.
University of California's Irvine and San Reflecting on the problems scientists had
Diego campuses, Xerox-PARC, Pittsburgh's in bringing a complex-systems perspective
Learning Research and Development Cen- to Al and cognitive science, Clancey (1997,
ter ( L R D C ) , the Massachusetts Institute of pp. 345-364) formulated a set of heuristics
Technology's Media Lab, and the Institute for scientists: Beware an either-or mental-
for Research on Learning. ity (e.g., knowledge is either objective or
arbitrary). Try both narrow and broad inter-
pretations of terms. Given a dichotomy,
Foreshadowed Dilemmas in Cognitive ask what both positions assume. Beware
Psychology and Al imposing spatial metaphors. Beware locat-
ing relations. Try viewing independent lev-
Artificial intelligence and cognitive scientists els as codetermined. Don't equate a descrip-
were aware of gaps and oddities in main- tive model with the causal process being
stream theories of intelligence through the described. Recognize that first approxima-
1960s and 1970s. However, any science must tions may be overstatements. Be aware
exclude certain phenomena (one is tempted that words sometimes mean their opposites.
to say, "certain complexities"). Thus, it is no Enduring dilemmas are possibly important
surprise that although engaging invited talks clues. Periodically revisit what you have
and textbook final chapters (e.g., Neisser, chosen to ignore. Beware of building your
1976) might mention autism, dreaming, and theory into the data. Locate your work
emotion, there was no coherent theory of within historical debates and trends. "It's not
consciousness. (Indeed, the new reputabil- new" does not refute a hypothesis. Beware
ity of the topic of consciousness in cognitive of errors of logical typing. Recognize con-
science during the 1990s was somewhat like ceptual barriers to change. To understand
the admission of cognition into talk about an incomprehensible position, start with
animals in the 1980s.) Psychiatric disorders, what the person is against. Recognize that
for example, were difficult to make sensi- the bom-again mentality conceives sharp
ble from the perspective of a single seman- contrasts. Recognize how other disciplines
28
WILLIAM I. CLANCEY

study and use as tools different aspects of inhibited; prone to ennui and powerless anx-
intelligence. Recognize the different mental iety, yet in joy of nature and companionship
styles of tout colleagues. always situated.
Can we summarize the meaning of situ-
ated cognition itself, as seen through all the
scientific disciplines over the past century? Acknowledgments
As stated, an all-encompassing generaliza-
tion is the perspective of complex systems. My understanding of situated cognition has been
strongly influenced by courses at Rice University
From an investigative standpoint, the one
in 1971-1973 taught by Fred Gamst (Sociocultural
essential theoretical move is contextualiza-
Anthropology); Konstantin Kolenda (Philosophy
tion (perhaps stated as "antilocalization," in of Knowledge; Philosophy of Literature); Ken
terms of what must be rooted out): we can- Leiter, then visiting from University of Cali-
not locate meaning in the text, life in the fornia, Irvine (Ethnomethodology: The Radical
cell, the person in the body, knowledge in Sociology of Knowledge); and Stephen Tyler
the brain, a memory in a neuron. Rather, (Language, Thought, and Culture). Conversa-
these are all active, dynamic processes, exist- tions with my colleagues at IRL (1987-1997),
ing only in interactive behaviors of cultural, particularly John Seely Brown, Jim Greeno,
social, biological, and physical environment Gitti Jordan, Jean Lave, Charlotte Linde, Jeremy
systems. Meaning, life, people, knowledge, Roschelle, Susan Stucky, and Etienne Wenger,
provided insights and motivation for putting
and so on, are not arbitrary, wholly sub-
these ideas together. I am grateful to Alex
jective, culturally relative, or totally impro-
Riegler, Mike Shafto, Jim Greeno, and an anony-
vised. Rather, behaviors, conceptions, and mous reviewer for their comments on this chap-
emotional experiences are constrained by ter. My writing has been supported in part
historically developed structural relations by NASA's Computing, Communications, and
among parts and subprocesses in different Information Technology Program.
kinds of memories - neural, artifactual, rep-
resentational, and organizational - and are
dynamically constrained in action across sys- Notes
tem levels.
Many difficult problems remain in under- 1 This is a story about the conceptual founda-
standing learning, language, creativity, and tions of situated cognition; for how the par-
consciousness. From a computer scientist's ticular theories of situativity and learning in
the 1980s and 1990s developed, see Sawyer
standpoint, looking out over the vast land-
and Greeno (this volume).
scape of more than a century of exploration,
2 Definitions in this section are adapted from
the nature of memory and development
the Wikipedia discussion (retrieved June
still appears pivotal. Almost certainly, elu-
7, 2005, from http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/
cidating the emergent structures and regu- Systems_Thinking). For an introduction, see
latory processes of genetic biology (Carroll, also New England Complex Systems Institute (n.d.)
2005) will inspire more complex computa-
tional theories and machines with perhaps 3 Definitions in this section are adapted from
reconstructive procedures and hierarchies. the Wikipedia discussion (retrieved June 7,
The nature of conceptualization and hence 2005, from http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/
consciousness will gradually be articulated, Systems_theory).
comprising a complex order of molecular, 4 Definitions in this section are adapted
physiological, neural, coordination memory, from the Wikipedia discussion (retrieved
and activity systems. The nature of the June 7, 2005, from http://en.wikipedia.org/
self - unfolding, self-organized, and willfully wiki/Complex_system).
determined - will be revealed as the essential ; As a graduate student in the 1970s, I read
cognitive dialectic: controlling, yet biased by a Natural History article about the dance of
ideas; open to change, yet inconsistent and the bees and wondered, How did insect nav-
igation relate to expert reasoning? Could we
SCIENTIFIC ANTECEDENTS OF SITUATED COGNITION

model the bee's knowledge as rules? Brooks Bateson, G. (1972). Steps to an ecology of mind.
(1091) provided an alternative theory. New York: Ballantine Books.
6 For a discussion of the dichotomy between Bateson, G. (1988). Mind and nature: A necessary
the living constitution (arbitrariness) and unity. New York: Bantam Books.
strict interpretation (objectivity) - indeed Bateson, G. (1991). Sacred unity. New York: Cor-
an argument against either-or thinking - see nelia & Michael Bessie.
Antonin Scalia's remarks at the Woodrow Berger, P., & Luckmann, T. (1966). The social
Wilson International Center for Scholars in construction of reality: A treatise in the
Washington, DC, on March 14, 2005 (re- sociology of knowledge. New York: Anchor
trieved July 20, 2005, from http://www. Books.
cfif. org/htdocs/freedomline/current/guest_ Berkeley, G. (1963). A treatise concerning the prin-
commentary/scalia-constitutional-speech. ciples of human knowledge. La Salle, IL: Open
htm). Court. (Originally published 1710)
7 "Constructivism." In Webster's Third New Blumer, H. (1969). Symbolic interactionism: Per-
International Dictionary, Unabridged (re- spective and method. Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
trieved July 26, 2005, from http://unabridged. Prentice Hall.
merriam-webster.com). Bransford, J. D., McCarrell, N. S., Franks, J. J.,
8l Nitsch, K. E. (1977). Toward unexplaining
memory. In R. E. Shaw & J. D. Bransford
References (Eds.), Perceiving, acting, and knowing: Toward
an ecological psychology (pp. 431-466). Hills-
Agrawala, A. K., & Noh, S. H. (1992). Computer dale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
systems. In S. C. Shapiro (Ed.), Encyclopedia of Bredo, E. (1994). Reconstructing educational psy-
artificial intelligence (pp. 241-248). New York: chology: Situated cognition and Deweyan
John Wiley &. Sons. pragmatism. Educational Psychologist, 29(1),
2
Agre, P. E. (1997). Computation and human 3~35-
experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Brooks, R. A. (1991). How to build complete
Press. creatures rather than isolated cognitive sim-
Altman, I., 81 Rogoff, B. (1987). World views in ulators. In K. VanLehn (Ed.), Architectures for
psychology: Trait, interactional, organismic, intelligence: The 22nd Carnegie Mellon Sympo-
and transactional perspectives. In D. Stokols sium on Cognition (pp. 225-240). Hillsdale, NJ:
8t I. Altman (Eds.), Handbook of environmental Lawrence Erlbaum.
psychology (pp. 7-40). New York: John Wiley Brown, J. S., Collins, A., & Duguid, P.
& Sons. (1989). Situated cognition and the culture
Anderson, J. R. (1983). The architecture of cog- of learning. Educational Researcher, 18(1), 32-
nition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University 42-
Press. Bruner, J. (1990). Acts of meaning. Cambridge,
Ashby, W. R. (1956). An introduction to cybernet- MA: Harvard University Press.
ics. London: Chapman 81 Hall. Capra, F. (1996). The web of life. New York:
Austin, J. L. (1962). How to do things with words. Anchor Books.
Oxford: Oxford University Press. Carroll, S. B. (2005). Endless forms most beautiful:
Bamberger, J. (1991). The mind behind the musi- The new science of Evo Devo and the making of
cal ear. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University the animal kingdom. New York: W. W. Nor-
Press. ton.
Bamberger, J., 8c Schon, D. A. (1983). Learning as Center for the Study of Complex Systems, (n.d.).
reflective conversation with materials: Notes Retrieved June 7, 2006, from http://www.
from work in progress. Art Education, 36, 68- cscs.umich.edu/
73- Clancey, W. J. (1992). Representations of know-
Barker, R. G. (1968). Ecological psychology. Stan- ing: In defense of cognitive apprenticeship.
ford, CA: Stanford University Press. Journal of Al Education, 3(2), 139-168.
Bartlett, F. C. (1977). Remembering: A study in Clancey, W. J. (1993). Situated action: A neu-
experimental and social psychology. Cambridge: ropsychological interpretation (Response to
Cambridge University Press. (Original work Vera and Simon). Cognitive Science, 17(1), 87-
published 1932) 116.
WILLIAM J. CLANCEY

Ckneey, W. J. (1997). Situated cognition: On Dewey, J. (1934). Art as experience. N e w York-


human knowledge and computer represento- Minton, Balch.
rsns. New York: Cambridge University Press. Dewey, J. (1938). Logic: The theory of inquiry. New
Clancev, W. J. (1999). Conceptual coordination: York: Henry Holt.
How the mind orders experience in lime. Hills- Dewey, J. (1981). The child and the curriculum
dale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (Origi-
Clancev, W. J. (2002). Simulating activities: nal work published 1902)
Relating motives, deliberation, and attentive Dewey, J. (1989). Experience, knowledge and
coordination. Cognitive Systems Research, 3(3), value: A rejoinder. In P. A. Schilpp, & L. E
471-499. Hahn (Eds.), Philosophy of John Dewey (3rd
Clancev, W. J. (2005). Folk theory of the so- ed.). La Salle, IL: Open Court. (Original work
cial mind: Policies, principles, and foun- published 1939)
dational metaphors. In Proceedings of the Dewey, J., & Bendey, A. F. (1949). Knowing and
:~th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science the known. Boston: Beacon Press.
Society Retrieved May 14, 2008, from http:// Durkheim, E. (1947). The elementary forms of
www.cogsci.rpi.edu/CSJarchive/Proceedings/ religious experience. Glencoe, IL: Free Press.
2005/d0cs/p46;.pdf (Original work published 1912)
Clancey, W. J. (2006). Observation of work prac- Edelman, G. M. (1987). Neural Darwinism: The
tices in natural settings. In A. Ericsson, N. theory of neuronal group selection. N e w York:
Chamess, P. Feltovich, & R. Hoffman (Eds.), Basic Books.
The Cambridge handbook on expertise and Freeman, W. J. (1991). The physiology of percep-
expert performance (pp. 127-145). New York: tion. Scientific American, 264(2), 78-87.
Cambridge University Press. Gallagher, R., & Appenzeller, T. (1999, April 2).
Clancey, W. J. (in press). A transactional perspec- Complex systems [Special issue]. Science,
tive on the practice-based science of teaching 79-
and learning. In T. Koschmann (Ed.), Theoriz- Gardner, H. (1985). Frames of mind: The the-
ing learning practice. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence ory of multiple intelligences. N e w York: Basic
Erlbaum. Books.
Clancey, W. J., Sachs, P., Sierhuis, M., & van Gell-Mann, M. (1995). The quark and the jaguar:
Hoof, R. (1998). Brahms: Simulating practice Adventures in the simple and complex. N e w
for work systems design. International Journal York: W. H. Freeman.
of Human-Computer Studies, 49, 831-865. Gibson, J. J. (1966). The senses considered as per-
Cole, M. (1996). Culture in mind. Cambridge, ceptual systems. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
MA: Harvard University Press. Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to
Cole, M., & Wertsch, J. V. (1996). Beyond the visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
individual-social antimony in discussions of Gleick, J. (1987). Chaos: Making a new science.
Piaget and Vygotsky. Human Development, 39, New York: Viking.
250-256. Glenberg, A. M. (1997). What memory is for.
Collins, A., Brown, J. S., & Newman, S. (1989). Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 20(1), 1-55.
Cognitive apprenticeship: Teaching the craft Godwin, J. (1988). Australia on $25 a day. Upper
of reading, writing, and mathematics. In L. Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Resnick (Ed.), Knowing, learning, and instruc- Goffman, E. (1959). The presentation of self in
tion: Essays in honor of Robert Glaser (pp. 453- everyday life. Garden Q t y , N Y : Double-
494). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. day/Anchor.
Cronk, G. (2005). Mead. The Internet encyclope- Gould, J. L. (1986). The locale map of honey
dia of philosophy. Retrieved July 1, 2005, from bees: Do insects have cognitive maps? Science,
http://www.iep.utm.edu/rn/mead.htm 232(4752), 861-863.
Damasio, A. (1994), Descartes' error: Emotion, rea-
Gould, S. J. (1987). An urchin in the storm. N e w
son, and the human brain. New York: Putnam. York: W. W. Norton.
Dewey, J. (1896). The reflex arc concept in Greenbaum, J., & Kyng, M. (Eds.). (1991)- Design
psychology. Psychological Review, 3(4), 357- at work: Cooperative design of computer systems.
37°- Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Dewey, J. (1916). Democracy and education: An Greeno, J. G. (1997). On claims that answer the
introduction to the philosophy of education. New wrong questions. Educational Researcher, 26,
York: Macmillan. 5~»7-
SCIENTIFIC ANTECEDENTS OP SITUATED COGNITION
V
Greeno, J. G. (2006). Learning in activity. In R. Lakoff, G. (1987). Women, fire, and dangerous
Keith Sawyer (Ed.), The Cambridge handbook things: What categories reveal about the mind.
of the learning sciences (pp. 79-96). Cambridge: Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Cambridge University Press. Lakoff, G. (2002). Moral politics: How liberals and
Griffin, D. R. (1992). Animal minds. Chicago: conservatives think (2nd ed.). Chicago: Univer-
University of Chicago Press. sity of Chicago Press.
Hall, E. T. (1973). Silent language. New York: Langer, S. (1958). Philosophy in a new key: A study
Anchor Press. (Original work published 1959) in the symbolism of reason, rite, and art. New
Harnad, S. (1990). The symbol grounding prob- York: Mentor Books. (Original work pub-
lem. Physica D, 42, 335-346. lished 1942)
Hayes-Roth, F., Lenat, D. B., & Waterman, D. A. Lashley, K. S. (1951). The problem of serial order
(1983). Building expert systems. Reading, MA: in behavior. In L. A. Jeffress (Ed.), Cerebral
Addison-Wesley. mechanisms in behavior (pp. 112-136). New
Head, H. (1920). Studies in neurology. London: York: Wiley.
Oxford University Press. Latour, B. (1999). Pandora's hope: Essays on the
Hebb, D. O. (1949). The organization of behavior. reality of science studies. Cambridge, MA: Har-
New York: Wiley. vard University Press.
Hewitt, C. (1977). Viewing control structures as Lave, J. (1988). Cognition in practice. Cambridge,
patterns of passing messages. Artificial Intelli- MA: Cambridge University Press.
gence, 8(3), 323-364. Lave, J., & Wenger, E. (1991). Situated learning:
Hewitt, C. (1985). The challenge of open systems. Legitimate peripheral participation. Cambridge,
Byte Magazine, 10(4), 223-244. MA: Cambridge University Press.
Hoffman, R., 81 Nead, J. (1983). General con- Leiter, K. (1980). A primer on ethnomethodology.
textualism, ecological science and cognitive New York: Oxford University Press.
research. Journal of Mind and Behavior, 4(4), Lenat, D. B., & Guha, R. V. (1990). Building
507-560. large knowledge-based systems. Reading, MA:
Holland, J. H. (1995). Hidden order: How adapta- Addison-Wesley.
tion builds complexity. Reading, MA: Addison- Leont'ev, A. N. (1979). The problem of activ-
Wesley. ity in psychology. In J. V. Wertsch (Ed.),
Jaworski, J., & Flowers, B. (1996). Synchronicity: The concept of activity in Soviet psychology
The inner path of leadership. San Francisco: (pp. 37-71). Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe.
Berrett-Koehler. Loftus, E. (1996). Eyewitness testimony. Cam-
Jenkins, J. J. (1974). Remember that old theory bridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Orig-
of memory? Well, forget it! American Psychol- inal work published 1979)
ogist, 29(11), 785-795. Lorenz, K. (1973). Autobiography. Retrieved July
Kamin, L. J. (1969). Predictability, surprise, atten- 1, 2005, from http://nobelprize.org/medicine/
tion, and conditioning. In R. Church & B. laureates/1973/lorenz-autobio.html
Campbell (Eds.), Punishment and aversive Luria, A. R. (1928). The problem of the cultural
behavior (pp. 279-296). New York: Appleton- development of the child. Journal of Genetic
Century-Crofts. Psychology, 35, 493-506.
Kauffinan, S. A. (1993). The origins of order: Self- Luria, A. R. (1979). The making of mind. Cam-
organization and selection in evolution. New bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
York: Oxford University Press. Maturana, H. (1975). The organization of the liv-
Konvitz, M. R., & Kennedy, G. (Eds.). (1960)- ing: A theory of the living organization. Inter-
The American pragmatists. New York: World. national Journal of Man-Machine Studies, 7,
Korzybski, A. (1994). Science and sanity: An intro- 313—332-
duction to non-Aristotelian systems and general Maturana, H. (1978). Biology of language: The
semantics (5th ed.). Englewood, NJ: Institute epistemology of reality. In G. A. Miller & E.
of General Semantics. (Original work pub- Lenneberg (Eds.), Psychology and biology of
lished 1934) language and thought: Essays in honor of Eric
Koschmann, T. (Ed.). (In press). Theorizing Lenneberg (pp. 27-64). New York: Academic
learning practice. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Press.
Erlbaum. Maturana, H. R. (1983). What is it to see? Que
Kosslyn, S. M. (1980). Image and mind. Cam- es ver? Archivos de Biologia y Medicina Exper-
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press. imental, 16, 255-269.
william j . c l a n c e y

Miturana, H. R., & Varela, F. J. (19S0). Auto- Radford, G. P. (1994). Overcoming Dewey's
poiesis and cognition: The realization of the liv- "false psychology": Reclaiming communica-
ing. Dordrecht: Reidel. tion for communication studies. Presented
Maturana, H., & Varela, F. J. (1987). The tree of at the 80th Annual Meeting of the Speech
knowledge: The biological roots of human under- Communication Association, New Orleans
standing. Boston: New Science Library. November 19-22. Retrieved August 5, 2005,
McClelland, J. L„ Rumelhart D. E., & PDP from http://alpha.fdu.edu/~gradford/dewey.
Research Group. (1986). Parallel distributed html
processing: Explorations in the microstruc- Resnick, M. (1997). Turtles, termites, and traf-
ture of cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT fic jams: Explorations in massively parallel
Press. micrvworlds. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Mead, G. H. (1934). Mind, self, a"d society. Riegler, A. (2001). Towards a radical construc-
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. tivist understanding of science. Foundations of
Minsk)', M. (1985). The society of mind. New York: Science, 6(1-3),
Simon & Schuster. Rogoff, B., & Lave, J. (Eds.). (1984). Everyday cog-
Minsky, M. (1998). "The mind, artificial intelli- nition: Its development in social context. Cam-
gence and emotions: Interview with Marvin bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Minsky," conducted by Renato M. E. Sabba- Roitblat, H. L., Bever, T. G., & Terrace, H. S.
tini (Associate Editor, Brain & Mind Maga- (Eds.). (1984). Animal cognition. Hillsdale, NJ:
zine). Retrieved July 1,2005; from http./Avww. Lawrence Erlbaum.
cerebromente.org.br/no7/opiniao/minsky/ Roschelle, J., & Clancey, W. J. (1992). Learning
minsky_i.htm as social and neural. Educational Psychobgist,
Minsky, M., & Papert, S. A. (1969). Percep- 27(4). 435-453-
trtms: An introduction to computational geom- Rosenfield, I. (1988). The invention of memory: A
etry. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. new view of the brain. New York: Basic Books.
Morowitz, H. J. (2002). The emergence of every- Rosenfield, I. (2000). Freud's megalomania. New
thing: How the world became complex. Oxford: York: W. W. Norton.
Oxford University Press. Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. New York:
Nasser, U. (1976). Cognition and reality: Principles Barnes & Noble.
and implications of cognitive psychology. New Sacks, O. (1987). The man who mistook his wife for
York: W. H. Freeman. a hat. New York: Harper & Row.
Newell, A., & Simon, H. A. (1972). Human prob- Sacks, O. (1995). An anthropologist on Mars: Seven
lem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice paradoxical tales. New York: Knopf.
Hall. Sandberg, J. A. C., & Wielinga, B. J. (1991).
New England Complex Systems Institute, (n.d.). How situated is cognition? In Proceedings of the
Home page. Retrieved June 7, 2006, from 12th International Conference on Artificial Intel-
http://www.necsi.org/ ligence (pp. 341-346). San Mateo, CA: Morgan
Papert, S., & Harel, I. (1991). Constructionism. Kaufinann.
Norwood, NJ: Ablex. Schank, R. C. (1982). Dynamic memory: A the-
Piaget, J. (1932). The moral judgment of the child. ory of reminding and learning in computers and
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. people. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Piaget, J. (1970). Structuralism. New York: Basic Schank, R., & Abelson, R. P. (1977). Scripts,
Books. plans, goals, and understanding. Hillsdale, NJ:
Piaget, J. (1971). Genetic epistemology. New York: Lawrence Erlbaum.
W. W. Norton. (Original work published Schon, D. A. (1979). Generative metaphor:
1970) A perspective on problem-setting in social
Plucker, J. A. (Ed.). (2003). Human intelligence: polity. In A. Ortony (Ed.), Metaphor and
Historical influences, controversies, teaching thought (pp. 254-283). Cambridge: Cambridge
resources. Retrieved July 1, 2005, from http:// University Press.
www.indiana.edu/~intell/titchener.shtml Schon, D. A. (1987). Educating the reflective prac-
Polyani, M. (1966). The tacit dimension. New titioner. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
York: Doubleday/Anchor Book. Scribner, S., & Cole, M. (1973). Cognitive con-
Prigogine, I. (1984). Order out of chaos. New York: sequences of formal and informal education.
Bantam Books. Science, 182(4112), 553-559.
SCIENTIFIC ANTECEDENTS OF SITUATED COGNITION

Senge, P. M. (1990). The fifth discipline: The an von Bertalanffy, L. ( 1 9 6 8 ) . General system theory:
and practice of the learning organization. New Foundations, development, applications. New
York: Doubleday/Currency. York: George Braziller.
Shapiro, S. C. (Ed.). (1992). Encyclopedia of arti- von Foerster, H. ( 1 9 7 0 ) . Thoughts and notes on
ficial intelligence (2nd ed.). New York: Wiley- cognition. In P. L. Garvin (Ed.), Cognition: A
Interscience. multiple view (pp. 25—48). N e w York: Spartan
Shaw, R. E., & Todd, J. (1980). Abstract machine Books.
theory and direct perception [Commentary von Foerster, H. ( 2 0 0 3 ) . Understanding under-
on "Against Direct Perception" by Shimon standing. New York: Springer-Verlag.
Ullman]. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, von Glasersfeld, E. ( 1 9 7 4 ) . Piaget and the radical
400-401. constructivist epistemology. In C. D. Smock
Shibutani, T. (1966). Improvised news: A soci- 8c E. von Glasersfeld (Eds.), Epistemology and
ological study of rumor. Indianapolis: Bobbs- education (pp. 1 - 2 4 ) . Athens, G A : Follow
Merrill. Through Publications,
Simon, H. A. (1973). The structure of ill- von Glasersfeld, E. ( 1 9 8 4 ) . An introduction
structured problems. Artificial Intelligence, to radical constructivism. In P. Watzlawick
4(3), 181-202. (Ed.), The invented reality (pp. 1 7 - 4 0 ) . N e w
Slezak, P. (1989). Scientific discovery by com- York: W. W. Norton,
puter as refutation of the strong programme. von Glasersfeld, E. ( 1 9 8 9 ) . Facts and the self from
Social Studies of Science, 19(4), 563-600. a constructivist point of view. Poetics, 18(4—5),
Smoliar, S. (1971). A parallel processing model of 435-448.
musical structures (Tech. Rep. No. AITR-242). von Neumann, J., 8c Burks, A. W. ( 1 9 6 6 ) . Theory
Cambridge, M A : Artificial Intelligence Labo- of self-reproducing automata. Urbana: Univer-
ratory, MIT. sity of Illinois Press.
Steels, L. (1990). Cooperation between dis- Vygotsky, L. S. ( 1 9 6 2 ) . Thought and language.
tributed agents through self-organisation. In Cambridge, M A : MIT Press. (Original work
Y. Demazeau & J. P. Muller (Eds.), Decen- published 1 9 3 4 )
tralized Al (pp. 175-196). Amsterdam: North- Vygotsky, L. S. ( 1 9 7 8 ) . Mind in society:
Holland. The development of higher psychological pro-
Suchman, L. A. (1987). Plans and situated actions: cesses. Cambridge, M A : Harvard University
The problem of human-machine communication. Press.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Waldrop, M. M. ( 1 9 9 2 ) . Complexity: The emerg-
Tinbergen, N. (1953). The herring gull's world. ing science at the edge of order and chaos. N e w
London: Collins. York: Simon 8c Schuster.
Turvey, M. T., & Shaw, R. E. (1995). Toward an Wenger, E. ( 1 9 9 8 ) . Communities of practice:
ecological physics and a physical psychology. Learning, meaning, and identity. N e w York:
In R. L. Solso 81 D. W. Massaro (Eds.), The Cambridge University Press.
science of the mind (pp. 144-172). N e w York: Wertsch, J. V. (Ed.). ( 1 9 7 9 ) . The concept of activ-
Oxford University Press. ity in Soviet psychology. Armonk, N Y : M. E.
Tyler, S. (1978). The said and the unsaid: Mind, Sharpe.
meaning and culture. N e w York: Academic Wertsch, J. V. ( 1 9 8 5 ) . Vygotsky and the social
Press. formation of mind. Cambridge, M A : Harvard
van Gelder, T. (1991). Connectionism and dynam- University Press.
ical explanation. In Proceedings of the 13th Wertsch, J. V. ( 1 9 9 1 ) . Voices of the mind: A socio-
Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Soci- cultural approach to mediated action. C a m -
ety (pp. 499-503). Hillsdale, N J : Lawrence Erl- bridge, M A : Harvard University Press.
baum. Wiener, N. ( 1 9 4 8 ) . Cybernetics: Or control and
Vera, A., & Simon, H. (1993). Situated action: communication in the animal and the machine.
Reply to William Clancey. Cognitive Science, Cambridge, M A : M I T Press.
Wilden, A. ( 1 9 8 7 ) . The rules are no game: The strat-
'7(0/ "7-135- egy of communication. London: Routledge 8c
Vico, G. (1858). De antiquissima Italorum sapi- Kegan Paul.
entia. Translated by F. S. Pomodoro, Naples:
Winograd, T., 8c Flores, F. ( 1 9 8 6 ) . Under-
Stamperia de' Classici Latini. (Originally pub-
standing computers and cognition: A new
lished 1710)
WILLIAM J. C L A N C E Y

foundation for design, Norwood. NJ: Ablex. Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical investiga-
Winston, P. H., with Shellard, S. A. (Eds). tions. New York: Macmillan. (Original work
(1990). Artificial intelligence at MIT: Expand published 1953)
ing frontiers (Vol. i). Cambridge, MA: MIT Wolfram, S. (2002). A new kind of science. Cham-
Pres. paign, IL: Wolfram Media.
CHAPTER 3

Philosophical Antecedents
of Situated Cognition

Shaun Gallagher

In this chapter I plan to situate the concept sky to Gibson} and biologists (from von
of situated cognition within the framework Uexkiill to Varela), many of whom have had
of antecedent philosophical work. My inten- a significant impact on how we think of cog-
tion, however, is not to provide a simple nition as complexly embodied and situated. 2
historical guide but to suggest that there are I think that it is right to say that most con-
still some untapped resources in these past temporary philosophers who champion the
philosophers that may serve to enrich cur- idea of situated cognition have been posi-
rent accounts of situated cognition. tively influenced by this work in psychol-
I will include embodied cognition as part ogy and neurobiology. For the philosophers
of the concept of situated cognition. One with whom we will be concerned, how-
often encounters these terms used together - ever, the psychology and biology of their
embodied cognition and situated cognition - time had less of a positive effect, and in
and it is clear that situated cognition can- some cases defined precisely what these
not be disembodied, although some authors philosophers were reacting against. What is
emphasize one over the other or provide even clearer is that these philosophers were
principled distinctions between them. 1 Phi- reacting against a long philosophical tradi-
losophical thought experiments notwith- tion that simply ignored the importance of
standing, however, the often-encountered body and situation in favor of the isolated
brain in a vat is, to say the least, in a very mind. This tradition included, of course,
odd and artificial situation. Given what Descartes, but also Locke, Hume, and Kant,
seems to be an essential connection between and almost every other modern philosopher
embodiment and situation, I will take the one can name. To ignore embodiment and
more inclusive and holistic route and view situation was the overwhelming tendency of
them accordingly. the philosophical tradition up to and includ-
The large landscape of sources for the ing many twentieth-century philosophers.
concept of situated cognition is populated Before the twentieth century it is dif-
with important psychologists (from Vygot- ficult, though not impossible, to find

35
36
shaun g a u . a g h e r

philosophers who could count as propo- many others, such as William James, George
nents of situated cognition. There is, how- Herbert Mead, Hans-Georg G a d a m e r , Aron
ever, a long tradition that emphasized prac- Gurwitsch, Hans Jonas, H u b e r t Dreyfus
tical reason, especially in discussions of or more recendy, A n d y Clark, Mark John-
ethics and politics, and in these discourses son (writing with G e o r g e L a k o f f ) , and Evan
the idea of situated reasoning is not absent. Thompson (writing with Francisco Varela)
One could mention here Aristotle's notion
of phnmesis (practical wisdom), which is
a form of knowing or epistemic capacity Organism-Environment
that is highly dependent on the particular
and practical (moral) situation in which it Situated cognition has b e c o m e an impor-
must be practiced. In the case of phnme- tant concept in educational theory, and one
sis, one does not know in general, or by of the most frequently cited philosophers
appeal to a set of rules, so much as one in this context is John D e w e y (see, e.g.,
decides case by case - with special atten- Bredo, 1994; Brown, Collins, & Duguid, 1989;
tion to the details of each case - what one Clancey, 1997; Lave, 1988; L a v e & Wenger,
must do. The Stoics also regarded the situ- 1991). Curiously, just as m u c h as D e w e y is
ation, defined in its most determined and cited in discussions of situated learning, he
concrete terms, as an important factor in is almost entirely ignored in the philosophy-
knowing what one can and cannot do. These of-mind discussion of situated cognition.*
traditions, however, were not carried over But Dewey was clearly the D e n n e t t of his
into the realm of theoretical knowledge, time, at least in terms of his enthusiasm
or what philosophy has considered cogni- for the science of mind and his rejection
tion per se (something closer to mathe- of Cartesianism. As early as 1884 D e w e y
matics than to phnmesis), which was most reviewed the significance of the n e w phys-
frequently thought to be independent of iological psychology, and he points to the
situation. Even moral deliberation was importance of certain biological concepts of
frequently modeled on context-free or organism and environment:
mathematical thinking (think of Kant's cat-
egorical imperative or Bentham's utilitarian The influence of biological science in general
calculus). There may be a number of excep- upon psychology has been very great... .To
tions to this general view (I think Nietzsche biology is due the conception of organ-
would count as an exception, for example),' ism In psychology this conception has
led to the recognition of mental life as an
but nothing like a folly developed concept
organic unitary process developing accord-
of situated cognition is to be found prior to
ing to the laws of all life, and not a
the twentieth century.
theatre for the exhibition of independent
In general, then, if the roots of the idea of autonomous faculties, or a rendezvous
situated cognition extend back into the his- in which isolated, atomic sensations and
tory of philosophy, they remained undevel- ideas may gather, hold external converse,
oped and well covered by the ground from and then forever part. Along with this
which the Enlightenment grew, not even to recognition of the solidarity of mental life
be unearthed in all the digging for episte- has come that of the relation in which it
mological foundations. But in the twenti- stands to other lives organized in society.
eth century this idea did break the surface, The idea of environment is a necessity to
and it started to grow in certain philoso- the idea of organism, and with the con-
phers who were reacting critically against ception of environment comes the impos-
the modern philosophies of Descartes, Kant, sibility of considering psychical life as an
individual, isolated thing developing in a
and numerous others. I focus on four such
vacuum. (Dewey, 1884, p. 280)
philosophers: Dewey, Heidegger, Merleau-
Ponty, and Wittgenstein. These are four
Dewey thus criticized conceptions of cogni-
philosophers among a list that could include
tive experience that construe it as narrowly
philosophical antecedents of situated c o g n i t i o n 37

individual, ideational, and passive. Experi- the situation.5 For Dewey, ideas, as well
ence is not something that happens in an as gestures and speech acts, are themselves
isolated mind; rather, experience is biologi- tools for this kind of interaction. Further-
cal, insofar as it involves an organism in an more, whether we are moving things about
environment, and social, insofar as that envi- or reconstructing meaning, cognition is pri-
ronment is intersubjective. Cognition, then, marily a social event and is often accom-
emerges in the transactional relations that plished in a joint effort. Cognition and such
characterize organisms and the physical and communicative processes are measurable in
social environment with which they engage. terms of their pragmatic success. A good
Experience is thus situated. "In actual expe- idea consists of a set of practices that resolves
rience, there is never any such isolated sin- the problem.
gular object or event; an object or event is Dewey was thus criticizing a strict Carte-
always a special part, phase, or aspect, of an sian division of labor between mind and
environing experienced world - a situation" body - a division of labor that was not simply
theoretical and a problem for philosophers
(Dewey, 1938a, p. 67).
but that was finding its way into the prag-
Dewey uses the notion of a problematic
matics of everyday life. Consider the fol-
situation to describe how cognition involves
lowing description of management practices
coping with unfamiliar circumstances. Situ-
from Taylor's 1911 textbook Scientific Man-
ations are problematic if there is some ele- agement:
ment of confusion, disturbance, uncertainty,
or incompleteness that needs to be resolved Thus all of the planning which under the
and there is no clear direction that would old system was done by the workman, as
lead to resolution. In such cases, cognition is a result of his personal experience, must
a form of inquiry, and this is understood as of necessity under the new system be done
a hands-on practical activity through which by the management in accordance with the
we transform the situation into one that is laws of the science... .It is also clear that
in most cases one type of man is needed to
less confused and more comprehensible, and
plan ahead and an entirely different type
in which ideas for successful action start to
to execute the work. The man in the plan-
emerge. An idea is not primarily an intel- ning room, whose specialty under scientific
lectual entity in the head but "an organic management is planning ahead, invariably
anticipation of what will happen when cer- finds that the work can be done better
tain operations are executed under and with and more economically by a subdivision
respect to observed conditions" (Dewey, of the labour; each act of each mechanic,
1938a, p. 109). Cognitive inquiry is not a for example, should be preceded by vari-
purely mental phenomenon but involves an ous preparatory acts done by other men.
interaction between organism and environ- (Taylor, 1911/1967, p. 3 j)
ment to produce real changes in the causal
The separation of mental experience
couplings that characterize the situation.
from hands-on physical manipulation of the
We should add the important point that the
environment was, for Dewey, both a philo-
situation should be defined as inclusive of
sophical and a social problem. 6 For him, cog-
the inquirer. It is not I as cognitive inquirer
nition is a form of action and not a relation
confronting a situation; the situation sur-
between a thinking that goes on in the mind
rounds and includes me.
and a behavior that goes on in the world.
Dewey was influenced by Peirce in his
The basic unit of experience is the organism-
thinking that, in the process of coping with
environment rather than a Cartesian cogito
a problematic situation, we use not only
ideas but also tools - physical ones like ham- or Kantian pure ego:
mers with which we can physically reshape
We see that man is somewhat more than
the environment, but also linguistic ones, a neatly dovetailed psychical machine who
which in communicative contexts may do may be taken as an isolated individual....
just as well in reshaping the dynamics of We know that his life is bound up with
38
shaun g a l l a g h e r

rhf life of society...we know that he is and perceive their intentions, but that such
dosefy connected with all the past by the interaction helps to shape our perception
lines of education, tradition, and hered- and understanding of things.
ity We know that our mental life is
not a syllogistic sorites, but an enthymeme
most of whose members art suppressed;
Being in the W o r l d
that large tracts neiw ame into conscious-
ness; that those which do get into am-
Dewey's pragmatism acknowledges the
sctousnes, are vague and transitory, with
a meaning hard to catch and read;... that importance of situation for the biologi-
mind is no compartment box nor bureau cal organism, and as such, his position is
of departmental powers. (Dewey, 1884, deep in the traditions of naturalism and
p . 278) psychologism.8 These views contend, for
example, that the rules of logic are not abso-
Dewey's concept of cognition is not far lute or independent of the biological or psy-
removed from what today is called "enactive chological makeup of the organism. One
cognition," which is the idea that perception reaction to the relativism implied in such
and thinking are fully integrated with motor views is to make the Fregean move to the
action. Yet one thing that Dewey clearly logic of pure concepts and to understand
emphasizes and that is all but missing in conceptual meaning and truth to be inde-
some discussions of the enactive approach pendent of context. Another involves the
(e.g., Noe, 2004; Noe & O'Regan, 2002; Husserlian move to a transcendental con-
O'Regan & Noe, 2001) is the fact that cog- sciousness that is distinct from the particu-
nition is always socially situated. Through- larities of any individual's psychological con-
out Noe's (2004) analysis of enactive per- stitution. Both moves are clearly away from
ception, for example, we find elements like the situatedness of experience and consti-
central nervous systems, sensory organs, tute a seeming retreat into a Cartesian, if
skin, muscles, limbs, movements, actions, not Platonic, mind. Heidegger recognized
and plenty of physical and pragmatic situa- the ontological limitations of pursuing these
tions to deal with. But there is no considera- lines of thought. In his questioning about
tion given to the role that others (and our the nature of the kind of entity that would
social or intersubjective interactions with be capable of such decontextualized think-
them) play in the shaping of perceptual ing, he implies that human existence is spe-
cifically not that kind of entity. He finds an
processes. For Noe (2004), "the key to [the
important clue to the nature of human exis-
enactive theory] is the idea that perception
tence and cognition in the notion of inten-
depends on the possession and exercise of a
tionality as it is developed in the work of
certain kind of practical knowledge" (p. 33).
Brentano and Husserl. Intentionality, the
The mind is "shaped by a complicated hier-
idea that all consciousness is consciousness
archy of practical skills" (p. 31). If we ask,
of something or about something, signifies
How do we get this practical know-how?
an unavoidable connection with the world.
his answer is embodied practice and action.
For Heidegger (1968), the kind of being that
Dewey would not deny this, but he would
is capable of having an intentional relation
certainly proffer the idea that we also get
to the world is a being that is already in the
it from others - watching them act, com-
world in a more basic, ontological way. This
municating with them, and learning from
is what he sets out to show in Being and
them through processes like imitation, and
Time, published in 1927.
indeed from the very start of life when we
are completely dependent on others.7 What From Heidegger's existential-phenome-
is important in this context is to recognize nological perspective, claims made by
not simply that others populate our environ- Dewey about the organism's embeddedness
ment, or even that we interact with them in the environment are claims informed by
philosophical antecedents of situated cognition 39

c o m m o n sense ( w h a t H u s s e r l c a l l e d t h e o u r p e r c e p t i o n s a n d actions. " T h e k i n d o f


"natural a t t i t u d e " ) a n d natural science, and dealing w h i c h is closest to us i s . . . n o t a b a r e
are thus m a d e f r o m a n o b j e c t i v e (external p e r c e p t u a l cognition, b u t rather t h a t k i n d o f
or o b s e r v a t i o n a l ) p e r s p e c t i v e . H e i d e g g e r ' s c o n c e r n w h i c h m a n i p u l a t e s things a n d p u t s
p r o j e c t is to dig d e e p e r into a q u e s t i o n t h a t t h e m t o use; a n d this has its o w n k i n d o f
still has t h e ring of a certain kind of tran- ' k n o w l e d g e ' " ( H e i d e g g e r , 1968, p. 95). If, f o r
s c e n d e n t a l i s m a b o u t it: w h a t k i n d o f exis- e x a m p l e , I w a l k into m y o f f i c e , m y p r i m a r y
tence does the h u m a n being have such that relation to this setting is n o t as a c o l l e c t i o n
it is necessarily s i t u a t e d or e m b e d d e d in t h e of o b j e c t s — desk, chairs, b o o k c a s e s , c o m -
w o r l d ? H i s r e s p o n s e can b e p u t into D e w e y ' s p u t e r , a n d so on. I do n o t think a b o u t t h e
language 9 : t h e o r g a n i s m d o e s n o t s i m p l y f i n d o f f i c e d o o r - 1 o p e n it. I d o n o t c o n t e m p l a t e
itself d e e p l y s i t u a t e d in an e n v i r o n m e n t as my desk or chair, I sit, a b s e n t m i n d e d l y , a n d
o n e possibility rather t h a n another. R a t h e r , start t o w o r k , w i t h m y attention o n a p r o b -
l e m to s o l v e or a p i e c e of c o r r e s p o n d e n c e to
it is p a r t of t h e v e r y n a t u r e of h u m a n exis-
w r i t e . T o use G i b s o n ' s t e r m , t h e affordances
tence that being in the environment and
o f f e r e d b y door, desk, chair, c o m p u t e r , a n d
being w i t h o t h e r s are necessary, existential
so on, are i m p l i c i t in t h e w a y t h a t I inter-
characteristics. D e w e y c o m e s v e r y close t o
act w i t h t h e m — t h e y are r e a d y - t o - h a n d , as
saying p r e c i s e l y this:
H e i d e g g e r (1968) says:
The statement that individuals live in a
world means, in the concrete, that they The kind of Being which belongs to these
live in a series of situations. The meaning entities is readiness-to-hand. But this char-
of the word "in" is different from its mean- acteristic is not to be understood as merely a
ing when it is said that pennies are "in" way of [perceptually or cognitively] taking
a pocket or paint is "in" a can. It means... them, as if we were talking such 'aspects'
that interaction is going on between indi- into the 'entities' which we proximally
viduals and objects and other persons. The encounter, (p. 101)
conceptions of situation and of interaction
are inseparable from each other. (Dewey, T h a t is, i n t h e m a j o r i t y o f o u r e v e r y d a y
1938b, p. 43; dealings, w e d o n o t f i r s t e n c o u n t e r o b j e c t s
cognitively, a n d t h e n d e c i d e w h a t t h e y are
In H e i d e g g e r ' s w o r d s , Dasein ( h u m a n exis-
and w h a t t h e y can b e u s e d f o r . C o g n i t i o n
tence) is in t h e w o r l d , not in t h e sense
is "a f o u n d e d m o d e " of B e i n g - i n - t h e - w o r l d
that w e are s i m p l y g e o g r a p h i c a l l y p l a c e d
that d e p e n d s o n o u r p r i m a r y , p r a g m a t i c
in t h e e n v i r o n m e n t , b u t in t h e sense that
interaction w i t h things ( H e i d e g g e r , 1968,
a m e a n i n g f u l w o r l d constitutes p a r t of o u r
p . 86). B y t h e t i m e w e t h i n k a b o u t things,
existence. T o b e situated, f o r H e i d e g g e r , i s
o r explicitly p e r c e i v e t h e m a s w h a t t h e y
not s i m p l y s o m e t h i n g that h a p p e n s t o t h e
are, w e h a v e already b e e n i m m e r s e d i n their
h u m a n being, b u t it is part of t h e b e i n g -
pragmatic meaning.
structure of b e i n g h u m a n , a n d as s u c h per-
m e a t e s e v e r y a s p e c t o f o u r cognitive a n d T o b e pragmatically i m m e r s e d i n w o r l d l y
pragmatic activities a n d o u r social relations. c o n t e x t s is to h a v e a certain k n o w i n g rela-
tion to t h e w o r l d , w h i c h H e i d e g g e r calls "cir-
T h e w o r l d , in this sense, is not a collec-
c u m s p e c t i o n " (Umsicht) a n d distinguishes
tion o f objects t o b e o b s e r v e d o r c o n t e m -
f r o m theoretical k n o w l e d g e . T h e latter takes
plated by t h e m i n d . R a t h e r , in a p r i m a r y
things i n t h e w o r l d a s m e r e objects that w e
w a y , w e h a v e o u r hands i n it. T h e w o r l d
e n c o u n t e r in an observer m o d e ( H e i d e g g e r
is "at h a n d " in an almost-literal sense ( H e i -
refers to such objects as having a Vorhanden
degger uses t h e t e r m Zuhandensein - being-
[present-to-hand] m o d e o f being):
to-hand). T h i n g s are not only available f o r
our m a n i p u l a t i o n — we find ourselves already "Practical" behaviour is not "atheoretical"
i m m e r s e d in such m a n i p u l a t i o n s or dealings, in the sense of "sightlessness." The way it
and the possibilities of such dealings s h a p e differs from theoretical behaviour does not
40
shaun g a l l a g h e r

lie simply in the fact that in theoretical catch sight of the very situatedness that nor-
behaviour one observes, while in practical mally characterizes our existence. In such
behaviour one acts, and that action must instances, we do not escape being situated'
employ theoretical cognition if it is not to rather, the situation simply shifts around us
remain blind; for the fact that observation as different things become ready-to-hand for
is a kind of concern is just as primordial purposes of addressing the problem. But in
as die fact that action has its own kind of
this process the situation of always being
sight. Theoretical behaviour is just looking,
in a situation announces itself and tells us
without circumspection. [Heidegger, 1968,
something not simply about the world (or
P 99)
what Heidegger calls the "worldhood of the
Heidegger points out that Cartesian phi- world") but about our own existence (i.e.
losophy and philosophical conceptions of that we are always situated, that we are in
science tend to overlook this basic ontologi- the world in such a radical way that we are
cal situatedness of the cognitive agent.10 Sci- never able to step outside of it). One can
ence begins as something that is already a never get a "view from nowhere," as Nagel
cognitive, theoretical project. Nature "itself (1986) puts it. The situated view (which in
can be discovered and defined simply in its other terms Heidegger calls the "hermeneu-
pure presence-at-hand. But when this hap- tic situation") is something that qualifies all
pens, the Nature which 'stirs and strives', theoretical knowledge and all third-person
which assails us and enthralls us as land- scientific accounts. Moreover, being situated
scape, remains hidden" (1968, p. 100). Hei- is something that in its inconspicuousness
degger claims that something poetic that is tends to escape our attention, but not sim-
tied to our situatedness is lost in the third- ply because we overlook it, in the way that
person objective observations of science. Of we might overlook something in the envi-
course it is important to point out that even ronment. Rather, it is part of what it means
our most theoretical contemplations are sit- to be situated that the fact of being situated
uated as well, and it is questionable whether commonly goes unnoticed.
it is ever possible to capture something in its This inconspicuousness of being situated
pure presence-at-hand. Theoretical behav- leads Heidegger to a number of interest-
ior is never just looking without circumspec- ing existential observations, for example, the
tion, even if it is sometimes conceived as idea that we are thrown into the world,
such. that our familiarity and fascination with the
Heidegger's analysis raises important world generally leads to our being lost to
questions about the very nature of the sit- ourselves, a form of inauthenticity. To the
uatedness of cognition as we try to under- extent that being situated commonly goes
stand it in the varied contexts of education, unnoticed, our sense of our own existence is
psychiatry, artificial intelligence, and so on. curiously incomplete and likely misguided -
Can situatedness be properly characterized something that gets cashed out in terms of
in third-person accounts, or does it require the problems encountered by classical cogni-
an existential analysis of the sort provided tive science and strong artificial intelligence
by Heidegger? In this sort of analysis, we (see Wheeler, 2005). At the same time, such
catch sight of what it means to be situ- incompleteness is part of what our exis-
ated in an environment, what readiness-to- tence means and is tied to the finitude of
hand itself means, primarily when readiness- our understanding. Heidegger also suggests
to-hand breaks down - for example, when some caution about any philosophy of the
something we intend to use is discovered to world that starts with an understanding of
be unusable, or when something we need the world as a res externa - Descartes' notion
is missing, or when something we need to of an extended, spatial thing - or any philos-
get around stands obstinately in the way. ophy of mind that starts with an understand-
In such cases, things are no longer there ing of the mind as a res cogitans, the idea
ready-to-hand, and just in that instance we that the mind is a substance or thing that
41
philosophical antecedents of situated cognition

thinks. What the Cartesian ontology over- includes being-with; being situated already
looks is exactly the kind of situatedness that involves being situated with others."
Heidegger describes. For Descartes, a thing Heidegger also presents an analysis of spa-
(whether extended or thinking) is a sub- tiality that is tied to our situated condi-
stance, which, Heidegger explains, is a form tion. Space is objective only derivatively; it
of being that is present at hand and precisely is first of all related to the kinds of activ-
not that form of being through which we are ities in which we are engaged. Thus, "a
always situated (the ready-to-hand). Indeed, pathway which is long 'Objectively' can be
for Descartes, as for metaphysics generally much shorter than one which is 'Objec-
and for natural science, the kind of being tively' shorter still but which is perhaps
attributed to things, including the entity of 'hard going' and comes before us as inter-
the human being, is the kind of being that we minably long" (1968, p. 141). Far and close
access in an explicit (third-person) observa- are determined by our pragmatic relations.
tional attitude and the kind of being that Five miles is a long distance to go to buy
is open to analysis by cognition, "inteUec- a newspaper but not so long if you intend
tio in the sense of the kind of knowledge to purchase a new home. Far and close also
we get in mathematics and physics" (Hei- become metaphors that inform our evalua-
degger, 1968, p. 128). Heidegger's existential tion of situations. I may feel closer to a per-
analysis is meant to show that human exis- son who lives a thousand miles away than to
tence is precisely not something present-at- the person standing next to me (1968, p. 141).
hand, an object among other objects, but Heidegger's discussion of embodiment is
is in-the-world, that is, always situated in minimal and is found mostly in the context
a way that the world is primarily ready-to- of his analysis of spatiality. Closeness, he
hand. maintains, is not definable as an objective
Within our everyday situated projects, we distance from one's body. Even the "here"
also encounter entities with a being that is not defined in terms of bodily location,
is different from the things that are sim- but relative to a "there" that is defined prag-
ply ready-to-hand. These are other humans, matically. How do I reach the thing that is
that is, other entities who are in-the-world there; how do I move myself over there?
in the way that we are in-the-world. For Hei- Only in relation to such concerns do I start
degger, others appear within the pragmatic to consider my "here." In this sense, in my
contexts that characterize our life. Along situation, I am always "there," or at least
with the activities that we are engaged in, directed to the "there," and in that light my
"we encounter not only entities ready-to- "here" is defined as too far (from the "there"
hand but also entities with Dasein's kind of where I need to be), or too awkwardly posi-
Being - entities for which, in their concern, tioned, and so on. Heidegger even suggests
the product [e.g., that we may be engaged in that right and left emerge in such prag-
producing] becomes ready-to-hand" (1968, matic relations, and that our spatialization
p. 100). Likely as not, our own activities "in its 'bodily nature' is likewise marked out
often require others to play some role. I in accordance with these directions" (1968,
am never an isolated I without others (1968, p. 143). According to Heidegger, however,
pp. 147-163). Moreover, I do not encounter our embodied sense of right and left play no
others primarily as those who are in opposi- role in these determinations.
tion to me but as those from whom I do not Heidegger's accounts of both inter subjec-
distinguish myself. That is, in regard to other tivity and spatiality remain closely tied to
persons, I do not first or in a primary way his analysis of the pragmatic or instrumen-
encounter strangers; rather, I find myself tal situation. Our encounters with others
already included with others. According to are always situated in pragmatic contexts -
Heidegger, this with is to be understood as he often uses the example of work-related
part of the very structure of human exis- projects. As such, we encounter others not
tence. That is, being-in-the-world already directly but across our dealings with things.
42
shaljn g a l l a g h e r

Others "show themselves in the world in Bergson, too, had provided a rich concept
their special environmental Being, and do of embodied cognition. In Matter and Mem-
so in terms of what is ready-to-hand in that ory (1911). he understands memory to accu-
world" (1968, p. 160), That is, others appear mulate in the body as a set of responses to a
as engaged in pragmatic contexts similar to complex set of solicitations from the world
(or different from) our own. This analysis The body retains
leaves little room for more direct and per-
from the past only the intelligently co-
sonal relations such as those based on emo- ordinated movements which represent the
tional or even biological attraction. Without accumulated efforts of the past; and it
doubt, such personal relations may also be recovers those past efforts, not in the
situated in instrumental contexts, but it is memory-images which recall them, but in
also possible to find such relations in what the definite order and systematic charac-
are closer to purely social or communica- ter with which the actual movements take
tive contexts. Likewise, spatiality is cast in place. In truth, it no longer represents our
purely instrumental terms with little role pasts to us, it acts it; and if it still deserves
the name memory, it is not because it con-
for embodied processes. Heidegger does not
serves bygone images, but because it pro-
deny that our existence is embodied, but he
longs their useful effect into the present
does not say very much about it moment. (Bergson, 1 9 1 1 , p. 9 3 J

Merleau-Ponty supplements these philo-


Embodiment and Beyond sophical sources with his own study of psy-
chology and neurology. He borrows the con-
Merleau-Ponty, working in the same phe- cept of body schema from Head and Holmes
nomenological tradition, takes both embodi- (1911-1912). Consistent with Bergson's con-
ment and intersubjectivity as more central cept of embodied memory, Head's (1920)
to the way that experience works. His anti- body schema dynamically organizes senso-
Cartesian view of the active body derives rimotor feedback in such a way that the
from his study of Bergson and what were final sensation of position is "charged with
Husserl's unpublished manuscripts (espe- a relation to something that has happened
cially Husserl, 1952). Husserl had outlined a before" (p. 606). Head uses the metaphor
concept of embodiment that distinguished of a taximeter, which computes and reg-
Descartes' concept of the objective body isters movement as it goes. Merleau-Ponty
(the body as an object extended in space, relates this metaphor to Husserl's analysis
or as studied by biological science) and the of time-consciousness, which shows that we
lived body [Leib], which is the body that I should think of experience not as momen-
experience and with which I act. It is the tary but as a temporally extended yet cohe-
lived body that gears into the affordances of sive flow structured to enable retentions
the world, and that, according to Husserl, (of the just past) and protentions (of the
is lived as an "I can." I approach the world just about to be). For Merleau-Ponty (1968),
with all of the possibilities for movement action is also temporally extended and orga-
and action that are of my body. 1 experience nized according to the "time of the body,
the world in an egocentric spatial frame- taximeter time of the corporeal schema"
work that is determined by my body. In (p. 173). And this includes a retentional
this regard, "my body appears to me as an component, as well as anticipatory aspects:
attitude directed towards a certain existing "At each successive instant of a move-
or possible task. And indeed its spatiality is ment, the preceding instant is not lost sight
not, like that of external objects or like that of. It is, as it were, dovetailed into the
of spatial sensations', a spatiality of position, present... [Movement draws] together,
but a spatiality of situation" (Merleau-Ponty, on the basis of one's present position, the
1 9 6 2 , p. 1 0 0 ) . succession of previous positions, which
43
philosophical antecedents of situated cognition

envelop each other" (Merleau-Ponty, 1962, that I represent the day as measurable by the
p. 140). clock;
This temporality is essential to the struc-
ture of our situated experiences and actions. / do not form a mental picture of my day,
We are situated not only spatially but also in it weigfts upon me with all its weight, it
is still there, and though I may not recall
time, and more generally in history. Indeed,
any detail of it, 1 have the impending power
Merleau-Ponty suggests that the experience to do so, I still 'have it in hand.'... Our
of meaning or our ability to make sense future is not made up exclusively of guess-
of things within the space of the envi- work and daydreams. Ahead of what I see
ronment is only possible if our experience and perceive... my world is carried for-
is structured in this temporal (retentional- ward by lines of intentionality which trace
protentional) way. Imagine if every expe- out in advance at least the style of what is
rience we had completely fell away into a to come. (1962, p. 416)
past that remained inaccessible to us. If our
Thus, Merleau-Ponty suggests, I feel time on
perception or thought were a strictly syn-
my shoulders and in my fatigued muscles; I
chronic experience, there could be no mean-
get physically tired from my work; I see how
ingful structure to it; it would lack context
much more I have to do. Time is measured
and connection with anything else that we
out first of all in my embodied actions as I
experience. But, Merleau-Ponty warns, we
"reckon with an environment" in which "I
should not think that the problem is solved
seek support in my tools, and am at my task
on a purely physiological or purely psycho-
rather than confronting it" (p. 416). Accord-
logical level. That is, as Bergson had shown,
ingly, my sense of time emerges out of my
the temporality of experience that is a nec-
situated actions: "What, in fact, do we mean
essary condition for us to be in a situation
when we say that there is no world without
is not explainable as a physical trace within
a being in the world? Not indeed that the
an objective body or brain, as such traces
world is constituted by consciousness, but
would be purely present and not sufficient
on the contrary that consciousness always
to explain the past. But, Merleau-Ponty sug-
finds itself already at work in the world"
gests, for the same reason neither is some
(p. 432).
unconscious or psychical trace sufficient. A
What finds itself already at work in the
present representation of the past or any
world is not the Cartesian cogito, which,
present content of consciousness remains
Merleau-Ponty suggests, thought has to
present; it cannot explain why we might
strain to discover. Rather, "my body, in a
take it as representing the past. Rather, he
familiar surrounding, finds its orientation
proposes that we have a direct but incom-
and makes its way among objects without
pletely constituted "contact with the past in
my needing to have them expressly in mind"
its own domain" (1962, p. 413), but not in the
(1962, p. 369). It is not a matter of an "I"
form of an object of knowledge. Temporal-
standing back as an observer of the things
ity is in some way a "dimension of our being"
around me; "rather it is that my conscious-
(p. 415). More specifically, it is a dimension
ness takes flight from itself and, in them, is
of our situated existence. Merleau-Ponty
unaware of itself' (p. 369), and it does this
explains this along the lines of the Heideg-
in perception as in action. Merleau-Ponty
gerian analysis of being-in-the-world. It is
means that there is no explicit or concep-
in my everyday dealings with things that
tual or reflective awareness of myself, or of
the horizon of the day gets defined: it is in
my body, when I am engaged in my everyday
"this moment I spend working, with, behind
projects. It is not that, as if by some inner
it, the horizon of the day that has elapsed,
power, I conceive of a space through which I
and in front of it, the evening and night -
need to guide my hand as it reaches to grasp
that I make contact with time, and learn
something; the shape of my grasp is not a
to know its course" (pp. 415-416). It is not
44 shaun g a l l a g h e r

representation of the object that I intend to them, in the first place, as other persons
grasp. How could anything like this be pos- rather than as, for example, other, albeit
sible, Merleau-Ponty asks, if my hand was peculiar, instruments, or how we escape a
"not already situated on a path" of action kind of philosophical autism. Rather, one
(p. 570}? The situation, then, is not laid out needs to understand this problem in terms
before me, as an object of consciousness; it of embodiment and to recognize that "the
is a trrgp -1 am in it and it is affecting me very first of all cultural objects, and the one
before 1 know it. Merleau-Ponty brings this by which all the rest exist, is the body of
afièctivity into focus as an important com- the other person as the vehicle of a form of
ponent of situated cognition in a way that behavior" (1962, p. 348). My access to the
the theorists of enactive perception some- other is not by way of inference or analogy,
times lose sight of. using the other's body as a means to pro-
In agreement with such theorists, ject myself into his or her mind. Rather,
Merleau-Ponty would say that vision or, there is a direct interrelation between my
more generally, perception is a form of body and the other's body at the level of per-
action (1962, p. 377)° Merleau-Ponty, how- ception (see Gallagher, 2001, 2005, chap. 9).
ever, would balance this claim with the idea Merleau-Ponty suggests what developmen-
that the world, the situation we find our- tal psychology has only recently shown;
selves in, also shapes our vision, and there namely, even young infants are capable of
is an element of passivity, or more properly perceiving the intentions of others (1962, p.
affectivity, that is built into our way of being 352; see, e.g., Baldwin & Baird, 2001; Bald-
in the world. Moreover, this is not simply win, Baird, Saylor, & Clark, 2001; Meltzoff,
the case for perception but extends to the 1995). But, more than this, there is a direct
full cognitive-emotional-linguistic life of an resonance between my bodily behavior and
individual and can easily have a normative the bodily behavior of the other.
significance: This concept of intercorporeality finds
good support in recent research on mir-
Children and many groum people are ror neurons and neuronal resonance systems
under the sway of situational values', (e.g., Decety & Sommerville, 2003; Jean-
which conceal from them their actual feel- nerod, 2001; Rizzolatti, Fadiga, Gallese, &
ings - they are pleased because they have Fogassi, 1996; Rizzolatti, Fadiga, Matelli,
been given a present, sad because they et al., 1996), although these phenomena
are at a funeral, gay or sad according to
would not have led Merleau-Ponty in the
the countryside around them, and, on the
direction of simulation theory, as we find
hither side of any such emotions, indiffer-
ent and neutral Our natural attitude in many authors (e.g., Gallese & Goldman,
is not to experience our own feelings or to 1998; Jeannerod & Pacherie, 2004). If by sim-
adhere to our own pleasures, but to live in ulation one means the use of a model to
accordance with the emotional categories of understand something that cannot be under-
the environment. (1962, pp. 379-380J stood directly (e.g., the other's mind), a
routine in which I manipulate a set of first-
This kind of affectivity is obviously in- person as-if intentions - and this is the con-
volved in intersubjectivity, which Merleau- cept of simulation as it is defined by simu-
Ponty analyzes in terms of what he calls lation theory - then this is clearly not what
"intercorporeality." Although Merleau- is going on in the activation of mirror neu-
Ponty acknowledges the kind of analysis rons. The activation of resonance systems
that Heidegger provided (i.e., that we en- is automatic and subpersonal; that is, it is
counter others across the various instrumen- not 1 who do it but rather a process in
tal contexts involved in everyday life; see the perceiver's brain that is elicited by the
Merleau-Ponty, 1962, pp. 347-348), this is perception of the other's action. It is not
not a sufficient account because it does not something the subject decides to do, or does
answer precisely how we come to recognize actively, and therefore it is not a simulation
philosophical antecedents of situated cognition
45

in that sense. If activation of the mirror sys- simultaneously and ambiguously my action
tem looks like a first-person pretense, it does and something that language does to me.
so only to an external observer, not to the
subject or system itself. Neurons do not fire
as if they were generating action; they just Language in the Context
fire.'5 If intercorporeality is about action, it is of Everyday Life
not entirely about my action in response to
others but must include the effect that the It is also the case that language use is a
other's action has on my system. It is not that socially constrained practice. According to
I simulate the action of the other; it is rather Wittgenstein (1953), our use of language is
that the other's action elicits the resonant similar to playing a game that has a particu-
responses in my system. In this affectivity lar set of rules. Each use of language, how-
we find ourselves pulled into a situation that ever, involves a different language game,
is already intersubjective. Just as Merleau- where the various games are run accord-
Ponty (1962) suggests that "the theory of ing to different sets of rules, and there are
the body is already a theory of perception" no universal rules. The games are played,
(p. 203), we could suggest that the theory we might say, in the world, and linguistic
of the body is already a theory of inter- meaning is determined by the circumstances
subjectivity. in which any particular game is played. On
A similar affectivity can be found in lan- this view, a private language - a language
guage, which in some sense may be a tool spoken by a person who somehow grasps a
that we use for communicative action with conceptual truth about the world and then
others - "I learn [language] as I learn to simply expresses that truth in words that
use a tool, by seeing it used in the context receive their meaning from what goes on in
of a certain situation" (Merleau-Ponty, 1962, his or her isolated mind — is not intelligi-
p. 403) - but in another sense is not some- ble to, or learnable by, anyone other than
thing that we totally control in our speech the speaker, because a language consists of
acts; rather, it is something that contributes a communicative system that exists only
to the constitution of the situation in which between agents who are in social interac-
we find ourselves immersed. Thus, tion. Linguistic meaning is generated in that
kind of contextualized communication:
language takes on a meaning for the
child when it establishes a situation for Language games are the forms of language
him.... The power possessed by language with which a child begins to make use
of bringing the thing expressed into exis- of words.... When we look at the simple
tence, of opening up to thought new ways, forms of language the mental mist which
new dimensions and new landscapes, is, in seems to enshroud our ordinary use of lan-
the last analysis, as obscure for the adult guage disappears. We see activities, reac-
as for the child. (Merleau-Ponty, 1962, tions, which are clear-cut and transparent.
p. 401) (Wittgenstein, 1969, p. 1 y)

For Merleau-Ponty, language has this effect Language is grounded on acting in partic-
on us; in the speech act, the subject does ular contexts, and in the immediate reac-
not first represent the words to him- or her- tions we have to others. T h e meanings of
self; the subject "plunges into speech," and words are not the products of the linguistic
in so doing "reveals a motor presence of the system nor derived f r o m a one-to-one cor-
word which is not the knowledge of the respondence to items in the world; rather,
word" (1962, p. 403). My speech involves they are generated in the activities in which
both my action and a passive affectivity: it is they are used. In this sense the use of a
"a certain use made of my phonatory equip- term does not presuppose having a concept
ment, a certain modulation of my body as stored in one's head. Rather, language is
a being in the world" (1962, p. 403) that is generated in the experience of the various
shaun g a l l a g h e r

contexts, practices, and activities that gen- erating on a project in which meanings
erate meaning. 1 do not think first in abstrac- are created by ostensive reference precisely
tion and then put a word to the concept (see, because the context is narrowly circum-
e.g., Gauker, 2003,2005; Travis, 1989). There scribed so as to define a shared communica-
are no abstract principles or universal rules tive situation. The tasks that compose this
that would allow me to do that. I am first in- project are context specific and require skills
volved in some project in a specific set- that are not only about material construction
ting - for example, a science lab, an operat- but also about conceptual construction. A
ing room, an airport - and in a specific kind language and a set of concepts are created
of discourse or conceptual practice that oth- by the particular purposes involved in the
ers share just in such settings, in the same situation. The vocabulary involved in this
way that they share certain instruments and context consists of four words - block, pillar
technologies. slab, beam - names of the f o u r items that the
Wittgenstein is thus committed to some builders use to build. Grammatically, the
form of extemalism, the idea that the mean- utterance of one word is, in this context, a
ing of a word or statement depends on the sentence. Moreover, when the builder utters
linguistic community in which the word is the word slab, something gets accomplish-
used or on what exists or happens in the ed - the assistant passes on a slab. Thus, in
environment (for a discussion, see Over- contrast to traditional approaches that make
gaard, 2004). To know what something concept use a matter of detached and delib-
means is not equivalent to simply being in erative judgment, Wittgenstein maintains
a certain psychological state (Putnam, 197;). that concept use is more like a practical skill.
Following a rule in a language game does not Proponents of situated cognition have
involve a metacognitive interpretation of a argued both for and against the idea that this
rule that we somehow hold in our head. It kind of skill is nonrepresentational, an issue
is rather an ability that consists in nothing that is taken up in other chapters of this
more or less than a practice, the mastery of volume.^ Here it may be h e l p f u l to men-
which has been fine-tuned in particular set- tion how Wittgenstein fits into this debate.
tings (Wittgenstein, 1953, §201). If the notion A radical situationist can argue that because
of situated cognition emphasizes the con- we are already in the world, we do not need
textual dimensions of such practices, where to replicate the world in our head; an inter-
the meaning of a concept and the signif- nal representation would be no better than
icance of verbal and gestural actions are the access we have to the w o r l d itself (see,
inseparable from the setting of action, or e.g., Noe, 2004, p. 219). T h a t is, we do not
from a form of life, then Wittgenstein is need a representation of the w o r l d if, in fact,
clearly describing situated cognition. In a the world is there for our having. W h e n the
well-defined situation, a practice can be well builder says "slab," the assistant does not
defined not by the existence of a rule book need to form a mental image of a slab; the
that is consulted, or by an explicit under- slab is perceptually and handily available.' 5
standing of the rules, but by the physical and His concept of slab - its meaning - is equiv-
socially defined situation itself. The mean- alent to what he can do with it. At t h e very
ing of a concept is not fixed or universal, least we can say that a representation in the
as it is dependent on its use in specific con- form of a mental image is not necessary for
texts, which are subject to temporal and his- the successful use of language. Rowlands
torical change. What determines our con- (2007), however, argues that t h e Wittgen-
cepts, Wittgenstein asserts, is "the whole steinian appeal to practice, u n d e r s t o o d as a
hurly-burly of human actions, the back- form of intentional action, is not sufficient
ground against which we see any action" to rid cognitive systems of representations.
(1967. §567). Wittgenstein, famously, d e v e l o p e d a par-
Wittgenstein (1953, §§2-21) describes the adox concerning the possibility of rule fol-
practices of a builder and his assistant coop- lowing. Many commentators h a v e thought
philosophical antecedents of situated c o g n i t i o n 47

that the key to solving this paradox lies descriptive of the different pragmatic con-
in Wittgenstein's (1953) appeal to practice: texts. T h e argument between representa-
"And hence also 'obeying a rule' is a prac- tionalists and nonrepresentationalists, the
tice. A n d to think one is obeying a rule is Wittgensteinian might suggest, is compli-
not to obey a rule. Hence it is not possible cated by the use of multiple language games
to obey a rule 'privately': otherwise thinking that differ f r o m one discourse to another,
one was obeying a rule w o u l d be the same from phenomenology and philosophy to
thing as obeying" (§202; see also Rowlands, psychology and neuroscience. T h e term rep-
2007). resentation does not have a meaning out-
That is, in our ordinary practice in every- side of its particular uses in these differ-
day contexts, we do not explicitly consult ent language games. Is it better to use
a set of rules to guide our practice; indeed, the w o r d representation than to not use
consulting the rules w o u l d itself be a prac- it? Better for what? Assuming that in cer-
tice different f r o m the worldly practice that tain contexts we agree on the concepts
we are trying to guide. But Rowlands argues of intentional state and intentional con-
that the appeal to practice cannot explain tent, Rowlands's insistence on the notion
away representations because, at least in of representation may be correct f o r those
the traditional view, practice involves inten- contexts.
tional action, and this presupposes some This brings us to the possibility that
form of representational content. "A prac- theories of situated cognition are t h e m -
tice is what we do. H o w e v e r , doing, it seems, selves differently situated, within d i f f e r e n t
is a f o r m of acting and, as such, is essen- disciplines or discourses, shaped by spe-
tially connected to intentional states. But cific debates and specialized vocabularies.
intentional states are individuated by their In any case, it is generally understood that
Wittgenstein offers significant resources in
c o n t e n t . . . . A n d content arises through rep-
support of the notion of situated cognition
resentation" (Rowlands, 2007). To defeat
and against both Cartesian dualist m e t a -
representationalism once and for all, R o w -
physics and m o r e recent computationalist
lands argues, one needs a different concept
views. 1 7 For Wittgenstein, cognition can-
of action than the one Wittgenstein w a s
not be reduced to propositional k n o w l e d g e
working with.
tightly organized in a w e l l - f o r m e d mind;
It is not clear, h o w e v e r , that Wittgenstein
cognition is really a collection of skills
was working w i t h one concept of action
and practices that rely on c o m m o n s e n s e
or one concept of representation. It w o u l d
k n o w - h o w and context-specific k n o w l e d g e .
seem to be a Wittgensteinian principle that
T h e contexts of cognitive practices are also
there is no one correct answer to the ques-
always social, so that w h a t we call our b e l i e f s
tion of w h e t h e r a representational concept
have meaning only in virtue of their role in
of skill, or action, or mind is better than
the social contexts in w h i c h we participate
a nonrepresentational one. In the cognitive (see, e.g., Brandom, 1994).
sciences, f o r e x a m p l e , there are in f a c t many
different meanings to the term representation
(sometimes the t e r m is used in discussing
mental images, s o m e t i m e s in discussing ref- Conclusion
erence, and other times in describing neu-
ronal firing patterns), and w h e t h e r we are D e w e y , Heidegger, M e r l e a u - P o n t y , and
willing to accept the implications carried by Wittgenstein provide continuing resources
the term m a y d e p e n d on the particular the- f o r approaches to cognition that r e c o g n i z e
oretical c o n t e x t in w h i c h it is used. Like- its situated nature. 1 h a v e suggested t h a t
wise, in regard to the question of everyday these thinkers are n o t just part of t h e his-
practice, it m a y be the case that s o m e torical background, b u t that w e can learn b y
practices are representational and s o m e are thinking f u r t h e r a b o u t their contributions.
not, depending o n h o w the t e r m m i g h t b e T h e y r e m i n d us that cognition is n o t
shaun g a l l a g h e r

only pragmatically situated but also always VI say 'lightning flashes,' I have posited
socially situated, not simply in the sense the flash once as an activity and a sec-
that die world is populated with others ond time as a subject, and thus added
with whom we communicate but also in to the event a being that is not one with
the event but is rather fixed, is, and does
the sense that this communication and inter-
not 'become.' - To regard an event as an
action shape our cognitive abilities from
'effecting,' and this as being, that is the
the very beginning. They push us to real-
double error, of interpretation, of which
ize that cognition not only is enactive but we are guilty, (p. 289)
also elicited by our physical and social envi-
ronment; that it not only involves a deeply To conceive of the mind as a Cartesian think-
embodied and temporally structured action ing thing is to posit something over and above
but also is formed in an affective resonance the situation in which thinking occurs. Think-
generated by our surroundings and by others ing is not something that happens in a mind
with whom we interact These thinkers also as an attribute or quality that belongs to a
challenge us to consider what it means to subject who is isolated from the world; it is
an activity or event in the world.
think of cognition as situated, what it means
4 One clear exception to this is Johnson (2007),
to do die science of situated cognition, and
who borrows extensively from Dewey to sup-
what it means if we end up with more than
port his conception of embodied, situated
one conception of what situated cognition
cognition.
means.
5 David Kirsh (2004) summarizes Peirce's view
that "thought is not just expressed in work, it
is executed in work":
Notes
C. S. Peirce, in his prescient way, was
1 Clark (1997) provides one of the best analyses fond of saying that a chemist as much
of embodied and situated cognition. Ander- thinks with test tube and beaker as with
son (2003), for example, provides the follow- his brain. His insight was that the activ-
ing principled distinction: ity of manipulating tools - in Peirce's
case, manipulating representation rich
In my view, it is the centrality of the tools and structures such as measuring
physical grounding project that differ- devices, controllable flames, the lines in
entiates research in embodied cogni- diagrams, written words - this activity
tion from research in situated cognition, is part of the overall process of thought.
although it is obvious that these two There is not the inner component, the true
research programs are complementary locus of thought, and its outer expres-
and closely related Although related sion. The outer activity is a constituent
to and continuous with situated cog- of the thought process, though for Peirce
nition, [embodied cognition] takes the it had to be continually re-interpreted to
physical grounding project as its cen- be meaningful. (Kirsh, 2004, p. 206)
tral research focus. This project calls for
detailing die myriad ways in which cogni- 6 We cannot help but be reminded of Marx's
tion depends upon - is grounded in-the thoughts along this same line. He maintains
physical characteristics, inherited abili- that there is a close connection between con-
ties, practical activity, and environment sciousness, which is a social product, and
of thinking agents, (pp. 92,126) labor - a connection that is ruined in alienated
forms of labor (Marx, 1974; Marx & Engels,
For further discussion of this distinction, see 1964).
Prinz (this volume). 7 In this regard, the work of Hurley (2006),
2 For a review of the psychological sources, see who considers the importance of imitation,
Clancey (this volume). has a closer affinity to Dewey. Thompson
3 If 1 say, The mind thinks," Nietzsche (1967) and Varela (2001) also emphasize the impor-
responds in the following way: tance of "cycles of intersubjective interaction,
philosophical antecedents of situated cognition 49

involving the recognition of t h e intentional Sripada (2005). They define a minimal sense
meaning of actions and linguistic communi- of simulation that does not involve subjective
cation (in humans)" (p. 424). These authors control or the generation of pretend states.
never mention Dewey, however. How a minimal concept of simulation differs
8 On Dewey's naturalism, see Santayana from perception on an enactive model is not
0939) • clear, however.
9 Notably, in the early 1930s, Dewey expressed 14 See chapters in this volume by Adams and
interest in Heidegger's project, "particularly Aizawa, Clark, Eliasmith, Millikan, and Row-
in his conception of the human situation" lands. See also Anderson (2003), Brooks
(Spiegelberg, 1976, p. 272). (1999), Clancey (1997), Hutto (2005), Kirsh
10 For an extended discussion of Heidegger (2004), Noe (2004), Rowlands (2007), and the
in contrast to Cartesian psychology, see special issue of Phenomenology and the Cogni-
Wheeler (2005). tive Sciences (vol. 1, no. 4, 2002) on Dreyfus's
11 Heidegger points out that this is the case even antirepresentationalism.
if one is alone. The claim that our existence is 15 This may run against situated approaches
characterized as being-with "must be under- to language comprehension and concept use
stood as an existential statement as to its that emphasize the role of simulation. For
essence. Even if the particular factical Dasein discussion, see chapters in this volume by
does not turn to Others, and supposes that it Zwaan and Kaschak, and by Barsalou.
has no need of them or manages to get along 16 For a discussion of content and practice in
without them, it is in the way of Being-with" Wittgenstein, see Hurley (1998, chap. 6).
(1968, p. 160). 17 Even if some philosophers still think that
12 See Noe (2004, pp. 1, 73), who cites Merleau- Turing wins out over Wittgenstein, current
Ponty in this context: "You aren't given the theorists of artificial intelligence and robotics
visual world all at once. You are in the are not so sure. Dennett (2003, p. 3) writes:
world, and through skillful visual probing - "What Turing saw, and Wittgenstein did not,
what Merleau-Ponty called 'palpation with was the importance of the fact that a com-
the eyes' - you bring yourself into contact puter doesn't need to understand rules to
with i t . . . . Like touch, vision is active" (Noe, follow them. W h o 'won'? Turing comes off
2004, p. 73). The idea of enactive perception as somewhat flatfooted and naive, but he
recently put forward by Varela, Thompson, left us the computer, while Wittgenstein left
and Rosch (1991), Hurley (1999), O'Regan and u s . . . Wittgenstein." Rodney Brooks (1999),
Noe (2001), and others, often with references in his work on robotics, clearly takes Turing's
to Merleau-Ponty, has been discussed at least gift but works with it in a Wittgensteinian
since the end of the nineteenth century. Noe situated framework.
could just as easily have cited Dewey's state-
ment from his 1896 essay "The Reflex Arc
Concept in Psychology": References
not with a sensory stimulus, but with
a sensori-motor coordination.. .it is the Anderson, M. L. (2003). Embodied cognition:
movement which is primary, and the sen- A field guide. Artificial Intelligence, 149, 9 1 -
sation which is secondary, the movement 130.
of body, head and eye muscles deter- Baldwin, D. A., & Baird, J. A. (2001). Discerning
mining the quality of what is experi- intentions in dynamic human action. Trends
enced. ... [In audition] the sound is not a in Cognitive Sciences, 5,171-178.
mere stimulus, or mere sensation; it again Baldwin, D. A., Baird, J. A., Saylor, M. M., &
is an act.... It is just as true to say that Clark, M. A. (2001). Infants parse dynamic
the sensation of sound arises from a motor action. Child Development, 72, 708-717.
response as that the running away is a Bergson, H. (1911). Matter and memory (N. M.
response to the sound, (p. 358) Paul & W. S. Palmer, Trans.). London: George
Allen & Unwin.
13 See Gallagher (2007) for a critique of implicit Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit: Reasoning,
simulation theory. I thank Philip Robbins for representing, and discursive commitment. C a m -
alerting me to an article by Goldman and bridge, M A : Harvard University Press.
SHAlJN GALLAGHER

Bredo, E. (1994). Reconstructing educational psy- Goldman, A. L, 81 Sripada, C. S. (2005). Simula-


chology: Situated cognition and Deweyan tionist models of face-based emotion recogni-
pragmatism. Educational Psychologist, 29, 23- tion. Cognition, 94,193-213.
V>- Head, H. (1920). Studies in neurology (Vol. 2)
Brooks, R. (1999). Cambrian intelligence: The early London: Oxford University Press.
history of the new AI. Cambridge, MA: MIT Head, H ., & Holmes, G. (1911-1912). Sensory dis-
Press. turbances from cerebral lesions. Brain, 34, i03;_
Brown, J. S., Collins, A., & Duguid, P. (1989). H5-
Situated cognition and the culture of learning. Heidegger, M. (1968). Being and time (J. Macquar-
Educational Researcher, 18,32-42. rie & E. Robinson, Trans.). New York: Harper
Claneey, W. J. (1997). Situated cognition: On & Row.
human knowledge and computer represen- Hurley, S. (1998). Consciousness in action. Cam-
tation. Cambridge: Cambridge University bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Press. Hurley, S. (2006). Active perception and perceiv-
dark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, ing action: The shared circuits hypothesis. In
and world together again. Cambridge, MA: T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual
MIT Press. experience (pp. 205-259). New York: Oxford
Decety, J., & Sommerville, J. A. (2003). Shared University Press.
representations between self and other: A Husserl, E. (1952). Ideen zu einer reinen
social cognitive neurostience view. Trends in phdnomenologie und phanomenologischen
Cognitive Sciences, 7(12), 527-533. philosophie. Zweites Buch. (M. Biemel,
Dennett, D. (2003). Ludwig Wittgenstein. Ed.), Husserliana IV. The Hague: Martinus
The Time too. Retrieved May 9, 2008, from Nijhoff.
httpV/www .time.com/time/timeioo/stientist/ Hutto, D. (2005). Knowing what? Radical versus
profile/wittgenstein.html. conservative enactivism. Phenomenology and
Dewey, J. (1884). The new psychology. Andover the Cognitive Sciences, 4(4), 389-405.
Review, 2, 278-289. Retrieved May 9, 2008, Jeannerod, M. (2001). Neural simulation of
from http://psychdassics.yorku.ca/Dewey/ action: A unifying mechanism for motor cog-
newpsych.htm. nition. Neurvlmage, 14,103-109.
Dewey, J. (1896). The reflex arc concept in Jeannerod, M., & Pacherie, E. (2004). Agency,
psychology. Psychological Review, 3, 357- simulation, and self-identification. Mind Si
370. Retrieved May 9, 2008, from http:// Language, 19(2), 113-146.
psychdassics.yorku.ca/Dewey/reflex.htm. Johnson, M. (2007). The meaning of the body.
Dewey, J. (1938a). Logic: The theory of inquiry. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston. Kirsh, D. (2004). Metacognition, distributed cog-
Dewey, J. (1938b). Experience and education. New nition and visual design. In P. Gardenfors &
York: Macmillan. P. Johansson (Eds.), Cognition, education, and
Gallagher, S. (2001). The practice of mind. Jour- communication technology (pp. 147-180). Mah-
nal of Consciousness Studies, 8(5-7), 83-107. wah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the Lave, J. (1988). Cognition in practice: Mind, mathe-
mind. Oxford. Oxford University Press. matics, and culture in everyday life. Cambridge:
Gallagher, S. (2007). Logical and phenomenolog- Cambridge University Press.
ical arguments against simulation theory. In Lave, J., & Wenger, E. (1991). Situated learning:
D. Hutto & M. Ratdiffe (Eds.), Minding our Legitimate peripheral participation. Cambridge:
practice: Folk psychology re-assessed (pp. 63- Cambridge University Press.
78). Dordrecht, the Netherlands: Springer. Marx, K. (1974). Economic and philosophical
Gallese, V. L., & Goldman, A. (1998). Mirror manuscripts of 1844. Moscow: Progress.
neurons and the simulation theory of mind- Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1964). The German
reading. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 2, 493— ideology (S. Ryazanskaya, Trans.). Moscow:
50L Progress.
Gauker, C. (2003). Words without meaning. Cam- Meltzoff, A. N. (1995). Understanding the inten-
bridge, MA: MIT Press. tions of others: Re-enactment of intended acts
Gauker, C. (2005). On the evidence for prelin- by 18-month-old children. Developmental Psy-
guistic concepts. Theoria, 54,287-297. chology, 31, 838-850.
PHILOSOPHICAL ANTECEDENTS OP SITUATED COGNITION 51

Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of per- humans by PET: 1. Observation com-


ception (C. Smith, Trans.). London: Routledge pared with imagination. Experimental Brain
& Kegan Paul. Research, 111, 246-252.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968). The visible and the Rowlands, M. (2007). Understanding the 'active'
invisible (A. Lingis, Trans.). Evanston, IL: in 'enactive.' Phenomenology and the Cognitive
Northwestern University Press. Sciences, 6(4), 427-443.
Nagel, T. (1986). The view from nowhere. Oxford: Santayana, G. (1939). Dewey's naturalistic meta-
Oxford University Press. physics. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philoso-
Nietzsche, F. W. (1967). The will to power (R. phy of John Dewey (pp. 245-261). Evanston, IL:
Hollingdale & W. Kaufmann, Trans.). New Northwestern University Press.
York: Random House. Spiegelberg, H. (1976). The phenomenological tra-
Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, dition. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
MA: MIT Press. Taylor, F. W. (1967). The principles of scientific
Noë, A., & O'Regan, J. K. (2002). On the brain management. New York: Harper & Brothers,
basis of perceptual consciousness. In A. Noë & W. W. Norton & Company. (Original work
E. Thompson (Eds.), Vision and mind: Selected published 1911)
readings in the philosophy of perception (pp. Thompson, E., & Varela, F. (2001). Radical
567-598). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. embodiment: Neural dynamics and conscious-
O'Regan, J. K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor ness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5(10), 418-
approach to vision and visual consciousness. 425.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24(5), 939-973. Travis, C. (1989). The uses of sense: Wittgenstein's
Overgaard, S. (2004). The private language argu- philosophy of language. Oxford, UK: Claren-
ment and externalism. Danish Yearbook of Phi- don.
losophy, 39, 17-48. Varela, F., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The
Putnam, H. (1975). Mind, language, and real- embodied mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
ity: Philosophical papers (Vol. 2). Cambridge: Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the cognitive
Cambridge University Press. world. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., Gallese, V., 8c Fogassi, Wittgenstein, L. (1953)- Philosophical investiga-
L. (1996). Premotor cortex and the recognition tions (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford,
of motor actions. Cognitive Brain Research, 3, UK: Blackwell.
131-141. Wittgenstein, L. (1967). Zettel. Oxford, UK:
Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., Matelli, M., Bettinardi, Blackwell.
V., Paulesu, E., Perani, D., & Fazio, G. (1996). Wittgenstein, L. (1969). On certainty. New York:
Localization of grasp representations in Harper 81 Row.
Part II

CONCEPTUAL
FOUNDATIONS
CHAPTER 4

How to Situate Cognition


Letting Nature Take Its Course

Robert A. Wilson and Andy Clark

i. T h e Situation in Cognition related but underexplicated notions, such


as embodiment, embeddedness, and exter-
The situated cognition movement in the nalism. Importantly, researchers who self-
cognitive sciences, like those sciences them- identify with the situated movement in
selves, is a loose-knit family of approaches the cognitive sciences have not been para-
to understanding the mind and cognition. lyzed by a relative lack of attention to the
Although it has both philosophical and psy- conceptual articulation of their paradigm.
chological antecedents in thought stretch- They have instead gotten on with the task
ing back over the past century (see Clancey, of showing how the situated perspective
this volume; Gallagher, this volume), it has leads to interesting and novel approaches
developed primarily since the late 1970s to understanding particular cognitive abili-
as an alternative to, or a modification of, ties.
the then-predominant paradigms for explor- In this chapter we do some conceptual
ing the mind in the cognitive sciences. For stocktaking. We propose a way of thinking
this reason it has been common to charac- of situated cognition that captures at least
terize situated cognition in terms of what one important historical strand to the situ-
it is not - a cluster of anti-isms. Situ- ated cognition movement but, more impor-
ated cognition has thus been described as tant, also provides the field with some nor-
opposed to Platonism, Cartesianism, indi- mative direction. In a nutshell, the basic idea
vidualism, representationalism, and even is that we should think of situated cogni-
computationalism about the mind. A clus- tion as a form of cognitive extension, or
ter of positive characterizations of the sit- rather as a variety of forms that such cog-
uated cognition movement has also been nitive extension can take. Our aim is not to
given, both in terms of adjectival descrip- specify the essence of situated cognition (a
tions based on the approach of one or misplaced goal here, as in many places in
more figures of influence (e.g., Gibsonian, philosophical theorizing) nor to do justice
Heideggerian) and in terms of a medley of to all of the work that has, at various times,

55
ROBERT A. WILSON AND ANDY CI.ARK

been referred to under the heading "situated just the kinds of cognitive extension that w
cognition" (or one of its many noms de articulate here.
plume; see section 2). Rather, it is to
provide a way of conceptualizing situated
cognition that helps both to focus and to 2. Situated Cognition: A Potted
reorient the study of cognition as a situated Recent History
phenomenon.
The chief innovation of the chapter thus Cognition, it is widely agreed, both stems
lies in a preliminary articulation of the vari- from and generates the activities of physi-
ety of forms that cognitive extension can cal individuals located in particular kinds of
take. This articulation involves two main environments. But despite this general con-
dimensions, one tracking the nature of the sensus, the views of cognition and the mind
augmentative resource and the other track- that constituted a kind of status quo in the
ing the durability and reliability of the aug- field by the end of the 1970s took a partic-
mentation. The resulting matrix captures ular view of the relationship among cogni-
many forms of cognitive extension that seem tion (or the mind), individuals, and environ-
almost trivial and that most parties to the ments - a view that was typically understood
debate over the nature of cognition can take to have fairly direct implications for how to
for granted. But it also accommodates a vari- study cognition and the mind. According
ety of forms that cognitive extension can to this view, the cognitive sciences were to
take that challenge us to reassess what cogni- embrace what Jerry Fodor (following Hilary
tion is, who we (as cognizers) are, and what Putnam) called "methodological solipsism"
the future holds for the study of cognition. and were, in effect, to bracket off the world
In addition, once we provide such a nuanced beyond the individual in characterizing and
framework for thinking about the varieties individuating cognitive states and structures.
of cognitive extension, we are better able to We will follow common practice and refer
respond to several important recent objec- to this as the individualistic conception of
tions to the conception of situated cognition the mind and cognition (Wilson, 1995, 2003,
as cognitive extension. 2004a, 2004b).

To set the scene, we begin with some On one of the strongest such individ-
potted history, in the form of a brief tour ualistic conceptions, cognition takes place
through some of the anti-isms and positive inside the head, wedged between percep-
characterizations of situated cognition. One tion (on the input side) and action (on
caveat, however, before we get going. An the output side), constituting what Susan
important strand to the situated cognition Hurley (1998) has called a kind of cog-
movement that we are unable to discuss here nitive sandwich. It involves the computa-
directly concerns the ways in which cogni- tional processing of mental representations,
tion is embodied. There is a range of discus- where these are language-like both in their
sion of this idea elsewhere in the volume, constituents (concepts as words) and in
as well as in our own previous work (Clark, their structural composition (mental rep-
1997, 2003; Wilson, 2004a), but it remains resentations as generated by, and decom-
a separate project to relate the embodi- posable in terms of, an underlying men-
ment of cognition to the idea of cogni- tal syntax). Such processing relies purely
tive extension that we are concentrating on on formal or syntactic features of the sym-
here (but see Maclver, this volume; see also bols themselves and the rules by which they
Gallagher, 2005). Suffice it to say that we are manipulated, rather than on broader
think that taking seriously the embodiment features of the individuals who instanti-
of cognition will reinforce the perspective ate them and the environments in which
that we are developing, primarily because they operate. On the version of this view
many forms of embodied cognition, prop- most influential among philosophers of
erly understood, will turn out to involve mind, much of this cognitive architecture
HOW T O SITUATE C O G N I T I O N 57

is universal across the species and innately and artificial intelligence. Exemplars include
specified. The task of developmental and Zenon Pylyshyn's Computation and Cogni-
cognitive psychologists is to uncover these tion (1984), and Allen Newell and Herb
innate structures and to understand how it is Simon's physical symbol system hypothesis
that they eventually gave rise to the diversity (see Newell, 1980; Newell & Simon, 1976)
that we appear to see in everyday cognitive according to which cognition is the algo-
activity. rithmic manipulation of symbol structures.
Even though cognition takes place inside Perhaps the best-known large-scale project
the head, on this view, cognition is not sim- in artificial intelligence that steadfastly
ply to be given a neural description. For adopts a classic, individualistic perspective is
cognition is taken to be, in an important the C Y C project, an ongoing, twenty-year
sense, substrate neutral: it is not what you project to create a general-purpose, com-
are made of but how you are functionally monsense reasoner (see http://www.cyc.
organized that matters for cognition. This com).
view, functionalism, has sometimes been Philosophical doubts about individualism
presented as reflecting the old blues adage were first raised in the now-classic argu-
that "it ain't the meat, it's the motion" that ments of Hilary Putnam (1975) and Tyler
matters (e.g., Clark, 1989, p. 21) - in this Burge (1979), both turning on the question
case, for mind. In truth, however, within of whether individualistic views of the mind
the individualistic paradigm for the study and cognition could adequately account for
of cognition that we are sketching there meaning or mental content. These origi-
was not so much attention to motion as nal challenges to individualism were cast in
to relatively static functional structure and terms of whether psychological states, par-
organization. That is why researchers con- ticularly intentional states, should be indi-
structing computer programs (and some- viduated or taxonomized in accord with the
times program-driven robots) could view constraint of individualism. For this reason
themselves as contributing not simply to one of us has elsewhere called the result-
the study of cognition through simulation ing forms of extemalism taxonomic external-
but also to the enterprise of creating gen- ism (Wilson, 2000, 2004a); it has also been
uinely cognitive beasts, with creating arti- called "traditional extemalism" and "philo-
ficial intelligence. A n d that is at least one sophical extemalism." The general idea was
reason why the neurosciences were often to continue to view intentional or content-
viewed, at least until the 1980s, as a kind laden mental states as some kind of inter-
of junior partner in the venture to under- nal state of the individual but to argue that,
stand and explain cognition. Thus, although nonetheless, because of their content, they
the neurosciences could tell us much about did not supervene on, or were not metaphys-
the realization of cognitive processes and ically determined by, what fell within the
structures in certain kinds of cognizers, their physical boundary of that individual. Hence
findings were explanatorily secondary to the debates over whether folk psychology
the investigations of psychologists, linguists, was individualistic (Burge, 1979; Fodor, 1982;
and computer scientists who were explor- Loar, 1988), over whether the notion of con-
ing the functional structure of the mind as tent used in David Marr's celebrated com-
such. putational theory of vision is internalist or
Fodor's The Language of Thought (1975) externalist (Burge, 1986a; Egan, 1992; Segal,
and The Modularity of Mind (1983) are par- 1989; Shapiro, 1997), and over the relation-
ticularly striking expressions of this kind of ship between individualism and the norma-
view in philosophy, with Fodor taking much tivity of the mental (Burge, 1986b; Ebbs,
of his cue from Noam Chomsky's work 1998; Pettit, 1993).
in linguistics. But this view of cognition More radical forms of extemalism about
was manifest across the cognitive sciences the mind abound and go by a variety of
more generally, including in psychology labels. These include locational extemalism
ROBERT Ai WILSON AND ANDY CLARK

(Wilson. 2000, 2004a), emrironmentalism Extensions in Biology, C o m p u t a t i o n


(Rowlands, 1999), vehicle extemalism (Hur- and Cognition
ley, 199S), and the extended mind (Clark &
Chalmers, 1998). One way or another, all Cognitive extensions, like house extensions
these locutions aim to suggest that the mind come in a surprising variety of forms. Some
and the cognitive processes that constitute are truly, massively, staggeringly transfor-
it extend beyond the boundary of the skin mative, and others are content to project a
of the individual agent. The extended mind previously existing theme. Some are seam-
thesis very explicidy identifies cognitive sys- less and elegant, and others expose a barely
tems themselves as reaching beyond individ- connected hodgepodge of warring materials.
uals into their physical and social environ- Some are visibly permanent, built to per-
ments. Such theses challenge individualism sist as long as the main structure does, and
direcdy by implying that an individualistic others are more temporary, apt for rapid
psychology, at best, can tell only part of the dissolution or replacement. Some appear
story about cognitive processing: the inside homely, and others can seem alien (some
story. An early gesture at such a view was find them monstrous). And the very idea
wide computationalism (Wilson, 1994), the of cognitive extension, just like its bricks-
view that the computational systems that and-mortar cousin, can be apt to provoke
make up the mind can extend into, and objection and outcry. In this section and the
include as parts of themselves, aspects of an next we present what seem to us to be the
organism's environment, a view that we will main varieties of possible cognitive exten-
discuss further herein. sion. Distinguishing these varieties is, we
Locational extemalism, environmental- believe, the crucial first step toward reveal-
ism, and the extended mind thesis are rad- ing the attractions of extemalism, allaying
ical forms of extemalism that do not rest the fears of critics, and generally restoring
on claims and intuitions about whether the peace to the neighborhood that proponents
content of a pair of states of two individuals and critics of extemalism share.
in different environments (or one individ- We should go further, however, and not
ual in two such environments over time) simply think of cognitive and house exten-
is the same or different, or on questions sions as alike but as instances of the very
about how particular intentional states are same kind of activity: the activity of modify-
taxonomized, or on questions concerning ing one's environment from the situation in
the role of the physical or social environ- which one find's oneself in ways that melio-
ments in individuating such states. Instead, rate that situation. Thinking is a kind of
they appeal to the nature of psychological building, a kind of intellectual niche con-
processing, to the arbitrariness of the head struction that appropriates and integrates
(or the skin) for bounding cognitive sys- material resources around one into preexist-
tems, and to the structure of real-life, on- ing cognitive structures. In cognition, agents
line cognitive activity in the world. Thus, if modify or augment the capacities that those
the extended mind thesis is true, it is true preexisting structures enable. Part of the
in virtue of something implementationally point of suggesting that we m o v e beyond
deep about cognition, rather than follow- the "minds are like houses" metaphor and
ing directly from any traditionally external- view cognition itself as a kind of building
ist view of mental content. activity is to introduce a deeper analogy for
understanding the idea of cognitive exten-
We thus arrive at the basic idea of this
sion, one anchored in recent thinking about
chapter: work in situated cognition is best
genetics, development, and evolution. Sev-
viewed as an ongoing series of investiga-
eral recent paradigms in the biological sci-
tions into cognitive extensions, extensions
ences - in particular, niche construction the-
of the mind into the physical and social
ory, developmental systems theory, and the
world.
HOW TO SITUATE COGNITION

idea of an e x t e n d e d physiology - advocate velopmental systems t h e o r y is rooted in


a m o v e b e y o n d the boundary of the organ- skepticism about t h e e m p h a s i s p l a c e d on
ism and an accompanying reconceptualiza- the role of genes in accounts of d e v e l o p -
tion of s o m e of the processes at the core of m e n t and evolution that arose in t h e w a k e of
biology. T h e idea of cognitive extension can Richard D a w k i n s ' s The Selfish Gene (1976)
be fruitfully a p p r o a c h e d by means of these and the d e v e l o p m e n t of sociobiology in
examples (see also Wilson, 2004b, 2005). the mid-1970s. Proponents o f D S T argue
N i c h e construction theory has been artic- that genes are b u t o n e (albeit i m p o r t a n t )
ulated by J o h n O d l i n g - S m e e and his col- developmental resource, and t h a t t h e basic
leagues over the past t w e n t y years and unit of d e v e l o p m e n t is t h e d e v e l o p m e n t a l
receives its m o s t elaborate, synthetic e x p o - system that (typically) contains genes as
sition in O d l i n g - S m e e , Laland, and Feld- components. G e n e t i c systems t h u s d o n o t
man's Niche Construction: The Neglected Pro- exhaust t h e kinds of d e v e l o p m e n t a l sys-
cess in Evolution (2003). N i c h e construction, tems there are w i t h o t h e r d e v e l o p m e n t a l
they say, "occurs w h e n an organism m o d - systems, such as t h e c h r o m a t i n - m a r k i n g sys-
ifies the . . . relationship b e t w e e n itself and tem, being epigenetic, w h e r e a s others, s u c h
its environment by actively changing one as those f o r the transmission of b e h a v i o r
or more of the factors in its environment" and culture, stretch not s i m p l y b e y o n d t h e
boundary o f t h e nucleus o f t h e cell b u t
(2003, p. 41). N i c h e construction (see also
b e y o n d the organism into t h e e n v i r o n m e n t
discussion in Clark, 2005b) is a w i d e s p r e a d
(see J a b l o n k a & L a m b , 2005). T h e s e w i d e or
process in t h e natural world, encompassing
e x t e n d e d d e v e l o p m e n t a l systems h a v e p r e -
not only the construction of nests and bur-
viously (and problematically) b e e n c o n c e p -
rows in m a m m a l s , birds, and insects, b u t also
tualized quite independently from i n d i v i d u -
the manipulation of existing social struc-
alistic d e v e l o p m e n t a l systems, separated by
tures, the off-loading of physiological f u n c -
t h e divide b e t w e e n culture a n d biology, o r
tions to environmental resources, and t h e
that b e t w e e n learning a n d inheritance, or
appropriation and adaptation of environ-
b e t w e e n environment and genes.
mental resources as biological and cultural
tools. B u t although niche construction has Finally, t h e ecological physiologist J.
long been recognized as an important pro- Scott T u r n e r has recently p r e s e n t e d a range
cess in certain contexts, O d l i n g - S m e e et al. of e x a m p l e s , including coral r e e f s (consisting
place it center stage in t h e biological sci- of polyps, calcite deposits, a n d p r o t o z o a n
ences, viewing it as introducing a missing flagellates), t e r m i t e m o u n d s ( c o m p l e t e w i t h
dynamic aspect to t h e theory of evolution their o w n interspecies c o m m u n i t i e s ) , a n d
that has radical implications f o r the bio- mole-cricket b u r r o w s in w h i c h , as T u r n e r
logical sciences. N i c h e construction, on this (2000) says of t h e first of t h e s e e x a m p l e s ,
view, provides t h e k e y to integrating ecology an "important c o m p o n e n t of t h e physiolog-
and genetics via an e x t e n d e d notion of inher- ical process takes place outside t h e animal"
itance - ecological inheritance (inheritance (p. 24). T u r n e r aims to s h o w , by a series of
via genetic and nongenetic — e.g., cultural, detailed e x a m p l e s , that t h e notion of p h y s -
artifactual - means). A n d , t h e y h a v e argued, iological organ, given its role in biological
the pervasive character of niche construc- and evolutionary explanation, o u g h t t o b e
understood so as to include k e y n o n b i o -
tion and its contrast w i t h natural selection
logical structures such as t h e "singing b u r -
make it "nothing less than a second selective
r o w " that amplifies t h e song o f t h e m o l e
process in evolution" (2003, p. 178).
cricket (for discussion of this e x a m p l e , s e e
D e v e l o p m e n t a l systems theory ( D S T )
Clark, 2005a). T u r n e r takes his inspiration
derives from Susan O y a m a ' s The Ontogeny
from Richard D a w k i n s ' s (1982) idea of t h e
of Information (1985) and has its flagship pre-
e x t e n d e d p h e n o t y p e , according t o w h i c h
sentation in O y a m a , G r i f f i t h s , and G r a y ' s
key survival-relevant genetic e f f e c t s s h o u l d
collection Cycles of Contingency (2001). D e -
6b ROBERT A. WILSON AND ANDY CLARK

not always be sought solely within the organ- But (see Hurley, 1998, pp. 335-336) why
ismic skin bag. In a similar vein, Turner think that the skull constitutes a magic
argues that physiological processes, such as boundary beyond which cognitively rele
metabolism, energy transfer, and homeosta- vant computation ends and mere causation
sis, extend beyond the boundary of the begins? We are creatures embedded in infer-
organism, and that this provides grounds (nationally rich and complex environments
for thinking of the physiology of organisms The computations that occur inside the head
themselves as extending beyond their own are an important but nonexhaustive part of
outer membranes, whether it be skin, shell, the corresponding computational systems. A
or soft tissue. wide or extended computational perspec-
These recent emphases on niche con- tive opens up the possibility of exploring
struction, developmental systems, and ex- computational units that include the brain
tended physiology in the biological sciences together with aspects of the brain's beyond-
suggest blind spots in past biological thought the-head environment. Wide computational
and fruitful directions for future research. systems thus literally extend beyond the
And the new suggestions all share a premise confines of the skull into the world.
central to our idea of situated cognition as The first point we want to make is that
cognitive extension: the individual organ- the idea of extended computation is entirely
ism is an arbitrary stopping point for the noncontroversial in noncognitive contexts.
scientific study of at least a range of rele- Indeed, it is presumed in a large variety of
vant processes in the corresponding domain. contexts in which computational techniques
In the domain of cognition, no one is an are brought to bear on understanding causal
island. mechanisms and processes. Computational
Time, then, to get a little closer to cogni- processes occur within discrete entities -
tion itself. Central to much cognitive science whether they be biological cells, computer
is the assumption that cognition is compu- chips, or larger entities comprised of these
tational, an assumption manifest in general units - but they can also occur between such
appeals to the metaphor of the mind as com- units. Typically, such extended computa-
puter, in the construction of computational tional processes constitute a larger compu-
models for particular problem-solving pro- tational system, but that should not obscure
cesses, and in the claims of so-called strong the fact that, with respect to those discrete,
artificial intelligence that appropriately pro- metal-shell bounded units, genuine compu-
grammed machines are (or would be, if we tational processes physically extend beyond
could only construct them) cognizers. At the the boundaries of those same units. There is
start of this chapter we mentioned computa- nothing ersatz, for example, about the com-
tionalism in the list of isms that have some- putations that flow across a grid system or a
times been thought to be challenged by the local area network.
idea of situated cognition. We think, how- The second point is that there are at least
ever, that any such inference is mistaken. It some cognitive contexts in which the idea
is mistaken because computation itself can of extended computation should be just as
be an extended process in just the sense in uncontroversial. As an example, and to illus-
which we are suggesting that cognition can trate how extended computationalism mod-
be an extended process. ifies the traditional view of cognition as com-
This is the view that one of us has called putation, consider Figures 4.1 and 4.2, which
"wide computationalism" (Wilson, 1994, depict two ways in which one might multi-
199;, chap. 3), and the basic idea behind it ply two three-digit numbers.
is simple. Traditionally, the sorts of com- On the traditional computationalist view,
putation that govern cognition have been the first step in the process of multiplication
thought to begin and end at the skull. Com- is to code some form of input (e.g., visual or
putationalism has thus been viewed as en- auditory input) from the world into inter-
tailing an individualistic view of cognition. nal symbols. The computations involved
HOW TO SITUATE COGNITION 61

(e.g., Ballard et al., 1997), and cognitive


anthropology (e.g., Hutchins, 1995). It is not
a distinct, novel, or ersatz kind of computa-
tion but simply an extension of the standard
view of computationalism, just as the three
examples that we began this section with -
that of niche construction, developmen-
tal systems, and extended physiology - are
extensions of quite standard corresponding
views in the biological sciences.
Wide computationalism (or extended
computation) thus provides the basis for
one direct argument for extended cogni-
tion. Suppose that we grant the assumption
Figure 4.1. Traditional computationalism: of computationalism that has structured
Multiplying with only internal symbols. much of the work in cognitive science. If the
Computational system ends at the skull. kinds of computation that at least parts of
Computation must be entirely in the head:
cognition involve are extended, then those
(1) code external world, (2) model computations
parts of or aspects to cognition will also
between internal representations only,
be extended. This is to reject the tradi-
(3) explain behavior on the basis of outputs
from step 2. tional individualistic understanding of com-
putationalism, of course, but we have sug-
gested that doing so does not require a
novel or nonstandard view of computation
in multiplication then take place entirely itself. Rather, it is to sift the wheat of
between these internal symbols; computa- computation from the chaff of individual-
tion ends at the skull. Contrast this with an ism. Thus, far from being incompatible with
extended computational view of multiplica-
tion, which involves some kind of internal
symbol manipulation or computation, but
which also involves the active manipulation
of symbols - such as those on a piece of
paper - that are not in the head, as depicted
in Figure 4.2.
On the extended computationalist view,
multiplication begins as a causal process
between external and internal symbols, but
that initial relationship is then incorpo-
rated as part of the computational process
itself. The resultant computational system
itself is not restricted to what is inside the
head but includes both internal and exter-
nal symbols. This allows one to understand
the entire activity of multiplication as it is
typically performed as a dynamic series of Computational systems can extend beyond the
skin into the world. Computation may not be
perception-action cycles that are computa-
entirely in the head: (1) identify representational
tional in nature. or informational forms - whether in the head or
It is this conception of extended compu- not - that constitute the relevant computational
tation, we claim, that is invoked in much system, (2) model computations between these
of the recent work in situated robotics (e.g., representations, (3) behavior itself may be part
Brooks, 1991a, 1991b, 1999), animate vision of the wide computational system.
ROBERT A.WILSON AND ANDY CLARK

computationalism, situated cognition as cally and functionally changes the relevant


extended cognition follows rather directly capacities of hermit crabs, it is plausible
from it. and relatively uncontroversial to see the crab
But whether or not one accepts compu- together with its appropriated shell as a uni-
tationalism. and the claims we have made fied entity, one with capacities and abilities
about it here, there remain a variety of forms due in part to the shell that a shell-less crab
that extended cognition can take. We turn alone does not possess.
now to examine two major dimensions that As in this example, one should expect
structure much of this variety. to find natural extended systems for cogni-
tive functions just when there has been suf-
ficient world-mind constancy for organisms
4. Articulating the Idea to reliably exploit that constancy to lighten
of Cognitive Extension their internal cognitive load. Such exploita-
tion manifests what one of us (Clark, 1989)
The first dimension concerns the nature of has dubbed the 007 principle: know only as
the nonneural resources that are incorpo- much as you need to know to get the job
rated into extended cognitive behaviors, dis- done. As Clark said in articulating this prin-
positions, and activities. Such resources may ciple, in general, "evolved creatures will nei-
be natural, technological, or sociocultural in ther store nor process information in costly
nature, and each of these determines dis- ways when they can use the structure of the
tinct kinds of cognitive systems. The second environment and their operations upon it as
dimension concerns the durability and reli- a convenient stand-in for the information-
ability of the larger (extended) system. The processing operations concerned" (1989,
system may be a temporary and one-off con- p. 64). Perception is one prima facie likely
struct, a temporary but repeatable one, or domain in which this is true. O n e of us
something more permanent. Let's take the has previously argued (Wilson, 1994, 1995,
two dimensions in turn. chap. 3) that it is here that some of the best
Natural extended cognitive systems are candidates for wide computational systems
those cognitive systems containing natural can be found and (Wilson, 2004a, chap. 7)
resources from the cognizer's environment that Dana Ballard's animate-vision paradigm
that have been functionally integrated into also exemplifies the 007 principle and posits
the cognitive repertoire of that cognizer. A natural extended cognitive systems for
natural resource for a creature is any feature perception.
of its natural world that it draws on for some A second kind of extended cognitive sys-
aspect of its continued functioning. Oxygen tem appropriates not natural but techno-
is a natural resource for respiration, and fruit logical resources. In contrast with natural
(for humans and other primates) is a natural resources, technological resources are artifi-
resource for nutrition. But some organisms cial in the sense of being made or developed
also require cognitive resources, and many by human agents. But like natural resources,
of these form part of the natural world of they encompass a diverse range of resources,
those organisms. Natural resources, includ- from those that are used in a novel, one-
ing cognitive resources, can simply be used off manner, such as a book that you use on
by organisms, but sometimes this use does the spur of the moment to jam open a win-
not merely fuel a preexisting system - as in dow, to those that represent permanent fea-
the previously mentioned cases of the respi- tures of our everyday life, such as prosthetic
ratory and digestive systems - but also aug- limbs. In the cognitive domain, technolog-
ments the system itself and the capacities ical resources include dedicated cognitive
that it possesses. artifacts, such as instruments for the mea-
To take a noncognitive example, empty surement and recording of data, and those
shells are a resource that hermit crabs use that extend our sensory abilities; make-do
for protection. Because this use both physi- procedures, such as scribbling sticky notes
h o w t o situate cognition

as reminders and guiding one's immediate in which the resulting system serves radically
behavior by reference to improvised lists; different purposes - but as with well-crafted
and devices with m o r e general functions, devices generally, we think that cognitive
such as cell phones and other t e l e c o m m u n i - extension tends to be stepwise, building on
cations e q u i p m e n t that can be used f o r cog- the solid achievements of systems that h a v e
nitive augmentation (see Clark, 2003). Like already earned their keep in some particular
natural extended cognitive resources, such domain.
technological resources can serve merely as A third kind of extended cognitive system
inputs to a skin-bound cognitive system, is also worth distinguishing, though it m i g h t
but there is a range of cases in w h i c h they be thought subsumable under either t h e nat-
do more than this and b e c o m e functionally ural or the technological (or both). T h e s e
integrated into a larger cognitive system. are sociocultural systems, which are f o r m e d
An electronics engineer usually has a w h e n there is stable reliance by an individual
pretty clear sense of w h a t is m e r e input to in his or her cognitive activity on social struc-
a system and w h a t is an integrated addition tures, other individuals, and their cultural
that alters the system itself. T h e distinction products. T h e s e structures and products
here is intuitive enough, even if it is one that serve as resources f o r a range of cognitive
has been surprisingly hard to pin d o w n (for activities. Perhaps the most striking e x a m -
a classic attempt, see Haugeland, 1995/1998; ples of sociocultural cognitive resources
for a slightly different treatment, see Clark, involve writing systems, broadly construed,
2007). M u c h obviously turns on degree and which have constituted a relatively durable,
complexity of integration. B u t m u c h also public cognitive resource crucial to edu-
turns on h o w one conceives the goal or pur- cation, training, regimentation, c o m m e r c e ,
pose of the system at hand. T h e purpose and military conquest in the Western w o r l d
of the radio being to receive, decode, and f o r millennia. But there are m a n y others,
play contents borne by radio signals, any- including those that derive f r o m practices
thing locally added that helps it do so (e.g., of distributing cognitive labor b e t w e e n indi-
a better transistor at s o m e key point, a signal viduals, f r o m the parental transmission of
amplifier) looks like an augmentation of the information to children to the establishment
system rather than a m e r e input. This is so of ritual, musical, and ceremonial orderings.
whether the additional transistor or ampli- For many individuals, such sociocultural
fier falls inside the preexisting boundaries of resources are like natural cognitive resources
the radio or lies b e y o n d them. in that they can be taken f o r granted as part
In most cases w h e n we are t e m p t e d to of the normal conditions under which their
speak of cognitive augmentation, the same cognitive abilities develop, they acquire spe-
rule of thumb seems to apply: we find cogni- cific skills, and they learn particular facts.
tive augmentation w h e r e n e w resources help Sociocultural resources are a kind of cog-
accomplish a recognizable cognitive task in nitive oxygen, simply given as part of the
an intuitively appropriate manner, such as natural world in which at least m u c h cogni-
by enabling the faster or m o r e reliable pro- tion takes place. On the other hand, socio-
cessing of information that s o m e goal or cultural resources and the cognitive systems
project requires. T h e n e w resource need not that they partially constitute are not biolog-
bear any close mechanical or functional sim- ically - genetically, physically, or evolution-
ilarity to the rest of the system. Rather, it arily - givens, as they have been created and
needs to achieve functional integrity w h e n modified by the activities of past generations
operating together with the rest of some cog- of people. So sociocultural resources are
nitive system that serves the kinds of pur- distinguished by their origin. B u t they are
poses that that cognitive system has served: worth highlighting in reflecting on e x t e n d e d
to perceive, to decide, to remember, to cognition because, we claim, they consti-
behave. M o r e radical cases of cognitive aug- tute a crucial part of some of those cogni-
mentation m a y be possible - such as those tive abilities and activities that distinguish
ROBERT A. WILSON A N D A N D Y C L A R K

human cognition from its nearest neighbors. in new forms of intelligent problem solv-
There may be animal cultures, but it is only ing. Sometimes these larger problem-solving
in Homo sapiens that we find diverse cultures ensembles are transient creations, geared
of cognition, social structures, and products toward a specific purpose (e.g., doing the
that, whatever their own origins, now signif- accounts, writing a play, locating a star
icandy augment the cognitive capacities of in the night sky), and combine core neu-
individuals who are embedded in them. ral resources with temporary add-ons (e.g.,
pen, paper, diagrams, instruments). At other
As we saw with extended cognitive sys-
times, they involve more stable and perma-
tems that are either natural or technolog-
nent relationships between biological agents
ical, sociocultural extended cognitive sys-
and extended cognitive resources. We first
tems exist when the appropriate type of
consider the more transient varieties.
resource is not simply used by an agent
but becomes functionally integrated into the Consider, by way of a staging analogy,
cognitive functioning of that agent (see also the idea of a task-specific device (TSD) dis-
Clark, 2007). We think that the kinds of cussed by Bingham (1988). The notion of a
sociocultural resources that we have men- TSD was introduced as a theoretical tool
tioned often meet this additional criterion. to help tackle the problem of understand-
Writing systems, for example, are not sim- ing the organization of human action. In
ply used by agents with given cognitive abil- brief, a TSD is a temporary but highly inte-
ities but significantly augment the cognitive grated assembly created to accomplish some
abilities that those agents possess, such as kind of goal. In the motor arena, a T S D is
the capacity for short- and long-term mem- a soft-assembled (i.e., temporary and easily
ory, the ability to keep track of the rela- dissoluble) whole that meshes the dynam-
tionship between abstract propositions as is ics that are inherent in the human action
often required in reasoning, and the ability system and the so-called incidental dynam-
to systematically fix and then critique our ics contributed by various extraorganismic
own ideas (see Clark, 1998; cf. Goody, 1977). factors and forces. That is to say, T S D s
Similarly, mathematical notation does not are "assembled over properties of both the
simply feed existing mathematical abilities - organism and the environment" (Bingham,
although it does that, to be sure - but 1988, p. 250). In each specific case, the bio-
also builds on those abdities to produce an logical action-system will need to recruit
agent with significandy greater mathemati- some complex, nonlinear combination of
cal capacities. The difference between the contributions from its four chief subsys-
ability to multiply using Arabic numerals tems - the link-segment system, the mus-
versus that using Roman numerals serves as culoskeletal system, the circulatory system,
a reminder of how much specific forms of and the nervous system - and do so in a
writing can contribute to particular abilities way expressly tailored to accommodate and
here. exploit the incidental task dynamics intro-
So much for the first dimension to duced by, for example, a handle on a paint
extended cognition, whether the cognitive pot, a bouncing ball, or a windsurfing rig out
resources it incorporates are natural, techno- on the open sea. These examples span the
logical, or sociocultural. The second dimen- three main kinds of incidental task dynam-
sion concerns the durability and reliabdity of ics identified by Bingham - namely, those
the extended cognitive system that results tasks that simply introduce inertial and dis-
from the functional integration of such sipative properties or mechanical constraints
resources. Extended cognition, we have so (as when we carry the paint pot by the han-
far proposed, occurs when internal and dle); those that involve absorbing, storing,
external resources become fluently tuned and/or returning energy (as when bounc-
and integrated so as to enable the larger ing a ball); and those that involve coupling
system - the biological agent plus specific with systems that have their own indepen-
items of cognitive scaffolding - to engage dent energy sources (the windsurfing rig
h o w t o situate cognition

powered by the wind and w a v e s of the open We have described this strategy in a little
sea). detail because many of the key ideas apply
Why study such T S D s ? O n e reason, the directly, it seems to us, to the case of those
most obvious one, is that it is these very extended systems that involve temporary,
ensembles that are locally at w o r k in many of transient forms of cognitive augmentation.
the most distinctive cases of human action. Let us label these "transient extended cog-
We alone on the planet seem capable of nitive systems" ( T E C S ) .
creating and exploiting such a wide vari- A T E C S is a soft-assembled whole that
ety of action amplifiers, ranging f r o m ham- meshes the problem-solving contributions
mers and screwdrivers to archery bows and of the human brain and central nervous sys-
bagpipes, to planes, trains, and automobiles. tem with those of the (rest of the) body
But a second reason, far less obvious, is and various elements of local cognitive scaf-
that working backward f r o m the analysis folding. To further probe the structure of
of these complex wholes m a y itself con- the space of possible T E C S , we might dis-
tribute important insights concerning the tinguish cases according to the durability
contributions and functioning of the biolog- and reliability of the relationship between
ical human action system itself. Although agent and resource. Thus we might want to
a natural first thought w o u l d be to try to distinguish temporary, one-off relationships
understand each of the four main biolog- from those that, though transient, are reg-
ical subsystems in isolation, then perhaps ularly repeated. To solve a new brainteaser,
to look at their coupled interactions, then an agent may generate a brand-new, one-
finally to add in the incidental dynamics, it off kind of T E C S . A practiced crossword-
turns out that this simple stepwise approach puzzle solver, by contrast, when confronted
may be doomed to failure. T h e reason is with a new puzzle (and as usual armed with
that the potential behaviors of the whole pen and paper), may rapidly generate a well-
biological action system are determined by understood, often-repeated form of T E C S .
staggeringly complex nonlinear interactions An intermediate case, for many, might be
between the four main subsystems and when working on the popular and strangely
the incidental dynamics. T h e good news, satisfying Sudoku puzzles that have cropped
up in newspapers all over the world. We
though, is that in a typical T S D the degrees
could repeat this kind of exercise in fill-
of freedom of this large and unwieldy sys-
ing out the details of many other exam-
tem are dramatically reduced. T h e whole
ples of T E C S . A seasoned journalist, armed
point, in fact, of soft-assembling a T S D is to
with a word processor and a bunch of notes,
reduce the initially high-dimensional avail-
may rapidly cycle through a whole range of
able dynamics to a m u c h lower dimensional
T E C S , some one-off and others repeated;
structure and thus to establish an effectively
ditto for the mountaineer equipped with
controllable resource (see, e.g., Fowler &
compass, map, and altimeter, and so on.
Turvey, 1978; Salzman & Kelso, 1987). As
a result: Now, there is no doubt that, in each spe-
cific case involving a T E C S , the biological
The challenge is to work backwards from brain is (currently) an especially active play-
a description of the reduced dynamics er, recruiting some complex, nonlinear com-
to an understanding of the manner in bination of contributions from various types
which subsystem dynamics couple and of onboard neural circuit and resources,
co-constrain one another to produce the
and doing so in a way expressly tailored
observed dynamical system. Because infor-
to accommodate and exploit the additional
mation about both task-specific dynamics
and the individuated resource dynamics is representational and computational poten-
required, the strategy unites the efforts of tials introduced by, for example, the com-
behavioral scientists and physiologists in pass, the pen and paper, or the word-
an integrated and coherent effort. (Bing- processing package. These examples are,
ham., 1988, p. 237) incidentally, the rough cognitive equivalents
66 ROBERT A. WILSON AND ANDY C L A R K

of the three main kinds of incidental task internal and the external (Scaife & Rogers,
dynamics identified by Bingham - namely, 1996; Rogers & Scaife, 1997; see also Nor-
those that simply introduce useful infor- man, 1993)., and its practice involves seeking
mation or constraints (the compass), those to understand the different properties of the
that support the off-loading and returning internal and external structures and the way
of information (the pen and paper), and they fit together in specific problem-solving
those that introduce new active sources of contexts. Sustained attention to the prop-
information processing and representation- erties of, and varieties of, T E C S may thus
transformation (the word-processing soft- yield a good deal of indirect information
ware). But despite this crucial role for the concerning what the biological subsystems
biological brain, there is much to be gained are and are not good at, and the forms of
from the complementary study of TECS in representation and computation on which
their own right. they most likely depend. One key advan-
As before, the most obvious, and highly tage is, of course, that in the case of the
motivating, reason to do so is that it is these external props and aids themselves, we are
very ensembles that are locally at work in able (as Hutchins [1995] nicely notes) to
many of the most distinctive cases of human inspect directly the various forms of repre-
reasoning and problem solving. Here too, we sentation, and to observe directly many of
alone on the planet seem capable of creating the key information-processing moves and
and exploiting such a wide variety of cogni- representational transformations.
tion amplifiers, ranging from maps and com- Much more contentious sounding to
passes to pen and paper, to software pack- some than the notion of a T E C S is the notion
ages and digital music laboratories. But once of an extended mind (Clark & Chalmers,
again, a second and perhaps less obvious 1998). Yet in terms of our two-dimensional
motivation is that working backward from taxonomy, the notion of an extended mind
the analysis of these complex wholes may is nothing more than the notion of a cogni-
itself contribute important insights into the tive extension, of any one of our three kinds,
contributions and functioning of the biolog- that scores rather higher on the second
ical brain itself. For here, too, the various dimension of durability and reliability. The
internal neural contributions interact in a extended-mind idea thus simply takes the
complex, nonlinear fashion, and here, too, kinds of observation that already motivate
we may hope to gain valuable leverage on interest in TECS and asks what would hap-
this forbidding internal complexity by ana- pen if some such organization were made
lyzing cases in which some of the many more permanently available. Thus, Clark
degrees of freedom are deliberately (and and Chalmers (1998) imagined an agent,
profitably, relative to some specific goal) Otto, so thoroughly fluent in the use of
reduced by the use of external props and a relatively permanent cognitive augmenta-
aids. For example, work on diagrammatic tion - a notebook, containing addresses and
reasoning is beginning to track the various other such information - that the resource
ways in which different kinds of diagram was deployed without conscious thought or
impose constraints on reasoning and action intention, its operation and contents typi-
that (when the diagram is effective) echo cally trusted, and the information it made
those of some target domain (Stenning & available poised to affect conscious reason
Oberlander, 1995; see also Zhang & Norman, and deliberate action in very broadly the
J994)- same way as might the same information
The more general project known as exter- were it stored in biological memory. In
nal cognition explicitly aims to track and such a case, they argued, we should treat
understand the complex and often unobvi- the nonbiological augmentation as part of
ous relationship between internal and exter- the material supervenience base for some
nal forms of representation. Its guiding idea of Otto's long-term, nonoccurrent, disposi-
is that cognition is a function of both the tional beliefs (e.g., about the location of an
HOW TO SITUATE COGNITION 67

art museum). The notebook and the phys- as it may initially appear, especially once
ical traces therein should be treated as the one recognizes the many grades along the
physical vehicles of some of Otto's own non- continuum from the fleeting to the perma-
conscious mental states. nent, and further articulates the trichotomy
Or consider, very briefly, another exam- among one-off, repeated, and permanent
ple that one of us has discussed previously relationships uniting individuals and cog-
in presenting the idea of extended cogni- nitive resources, as introduced previously.
tion (Wilson, 2004a, chap. 8). Kanzi is a As we see it, an extended mind is what
human-raised bonobo (pygmy chimpanzee) you get, given the more basic acceptance of
who has been thoroughly embedded from the possibility of temporary, soft-assembled
an early age in human-centered environ- extended cognitive systems, if and when cer-
ments located in the research laboratories tain additional coupling conditions are met
and grounds of Sue Savage-Rumbaugh (see (for much further discussion, see Clark, in
Savage-Rumbaugh & Lewin, 1994; Savage- press). Such coupling conditions are meant
Rumbaugh, Shanker, 8t Taylor, 1998). As to ensure that the capacities of the hybrid
part of that enculturation process, Kanzi system - the biological organism plus aug-
has learned how to use a 256-symbol, mentation - are plausibly seen as the capac-
portable keyboard to communicate with ities of a specific individual (e.g., Otto). We
people around him. Kanzi's actual develop- properly expect our individual agents to be
mental trajectory has taken him from using mobile, more or less reliable, bundles of
a technological resource designed by human stored knowledge and computational, emo-
agents, initially in temporary interactions tional, and inferential capacities. So we need
then in repeated cycles of interaction, to to be persuaded that the new capacities
becoming a distinctive agent whose persist- enabled by the addition of the notebook
ing cognitive system has come to function- are likewise sufficiently robust and endur-
ally integrate a much richer set of sociocul- ing as to contribute to the persisting cogni-
tural resources into its purview. The system tive profile we identify as Otto the agent.
that Kanzi plus his keyboard constitute The bulk of Clark and Chalmers' (1998)
forms a cognitive system with memory work was an attempt to isolate and defend
and other cognitive capacities that seem a specific account of the conditions under
qualitatively distinctive from that of other, which we would be justified in identifying
unaugmented bonobos, capacities that are such an extended mind. These amounted,
somewhere between those of humans and in the end, to a set of conditions that (1)
other apes. It is not simply that Kanzi's established the reliable presence of the new
enriched learning environment has restruc- capacities as and when needed, and then (2)
tured his neural wiring (although it has made sure that the mode of deployment of
almost certainly done that, too), but that the resource (automatic, trusted) made it
his cognitive restructuring has proceeded more like a proper part of the agent and less
through a potent cognitive extension involv- like a perceptually consulted independent
ing these stable symbolic structures in his oracle.
environment. Otto and keyboard-Kanzi are
These conditions turned out to be fairly
thus both cases where a relatively endur-
stringent, and it is unlikely that any actual
ing augmentation, suggesting deep func-
notebook currently carried by a human
tional integration, plausibly results in a cog-
agent will meet the demands. In the con-
nitively reconfigured agent, an agent with an
text of near-future technologies, however,
extended mind.
it may be that reliable, more permanent
There has been much recent debate over forms of personal cognitive augmentation
such radical-sounding claims, and we do not will become relatively commonplace. Two
plan to repeat very much of it here. Instead, interlocking key developments (see Clark,
we simply note that the step from TECS 2003) likely to support such a transition are,
to the extended mind is not really as large first, the increasing use of portable (perhaps.
68 ROBERT A. WILSON AND ANDY CLARK

though not necessarily, implanted) electron- fact, earthbound cognitive processes are cur-
ics, and second, the spread of ubiquitous rently (at least as far as we know) restricted
and pervasive computing, infusing much of to the head - better, the neural circuitry and
the routinely available material world with central nervous system - of biological organ-
accessible information and added computa- isms. They thus reject the extended-mind
tional potential. thesis as described previously and assert
The point of choosing the simple, tech- instead that nothing that is, properly speak-
nologically unsophisticated notebook, how- ing, cognitive goes on outside the bounds of
ever, was both to dramatize the importance skin and skull.
of the reliability and coupling conditions and One key failure of the arguments sup-
to highlight the relative unimportance of the porting the extended-mind story, they sug-
intrinsic nature of the resource itself. For a gest (this volume), is the failure of those
simple notebook, plainly, is quite unlike bio- arguments to distinguish mere causal influ-
logical memory in its representational for- ence from constitution. Now merely cou-
mat, computational activity, and (for what pling a resource to an agent does not, of
it is worth) material structure. Indeed, as course, make it part of the agent. But this
critics seldom tire of pointing out, such dif- does not show the nature and degree of
ferences obtain between most of our exter- intercomponential coupling to be irrelevant
nal props and aids and the inner biological to the question of constitution. What makes
engine whose cognitive capacities they aug- my hippocampus part of my cognitive sys-
ment in significant ways. But such dispari- tem, it seems fair to say, has a great deal to
ties, far from being a problem, are (we will do with how it is informationally integrated
now argue) the source of much of the power with the rest of my cognitive system. We can
and interest of cognitive extension. imagine a case in which, despite being firmly
located in my head, there is zero integration
and hence the onboard hippocampus fails
5. Are Some Resources Intrinsically to form part of my active cognitive system.
Noncognitive? Contrariwise, we can imagine a hippocam-
pus in a distant vat whose activity is so well
We said at the outset that our articulation of integrated as to unproblematically count as
the very idea of cognitive extension would part of my cognitive apparatus (see, e.g.,
help to reveal shortcomings with some of the Dennett, 1978 - a classic treatment titled
most prominent objections to the view of "Where Am I?"). Coupling, we conclude,
situated cognition as extended cognition. In does not in and of itself render a tool or
this section and the next we concentrate on resource part of the agent's cognitive appa-
two recent critiques that we regard as pos- ratus. But the right kind of coupling (one
ing some of the most challenging objections resulting in deep functional integration) is a
to this view of situated cognition, those of major part of what determines the scope and
Adams and Aizawa (2001, 2008, in press, this bounds of an agent's cognitive apparatus. As
volume) and Rupert (2004, in press). In both one of us (Clark, in press) has addressed
cases, we aim to respond to their critiques these issues at some length, we shall not
in part by pointing to the diverse forms that repeat the exercise here.
extended cognition can take, and in part In addition to the worry about coupling,
(and perhaps more interestingly) by uncov- Adams and Aizawa (2001, this volume)
ering some deeper assumptions on which worry that certain kinds of nonbiological
their critiques turn. We think that such structures may be in some sense fundamen-
assumptions are thrown into doubt by the tally inappropriate as elements in extended
framework that we have introduced here. cognitive wholes. Thus at one point they
Adams and Aizawa have argued for what write, "If the fact that an object or process
they term contingent intracranialism, accord- X is coupled to a cognitive agent does not
ing to which, as a matter of empirical entail that X is part of the cognitive agent's
HOW TO SITUATE COCNITION

cognitive apparatus, what does? The nature can be part of the supervenience base of
ofX of course" (Adams & Aizawa, in press, 3; something's having property P without itself
our italics). We find this revealing. It allows having property P. To take a simple parallel
us to draw attention to what seems to be suggested by David Chalmers, someone can
a crucial underlying belief or dogma with- be a leader by virtue of his or her relation
out which Adams and Aizawa's larger vision to other people, without those other people
would not go through. We shall call this the being leaders or having intrinsic leadership.
"dogma of intrinsic unsuitability." The dogma of intrinsic unsuitability is
just that: a dogma. Moreover, it is one that,
we suggest, ultimately stands in some ten-
The Dogma of Intrinsic Unsuitability sion with a robust faith in one of the cen-
Certain kinds of encoding or processing are tral tenets of computationally inspired cog-
intrinsically unsuitable to act as parts of nitive science. This is the idea that pretty
the material/computational substrate of any much anything, including any kind of pro-
genuinely cognitive state or process. cessing or encoding, provided that it is prop-
In the work of Adams and Aizawa (2001), erly located in some ongoing web of com-
the dogma emerges as the claim that cer- putational activity, can contribute to the
tain neural states, and no extraneural ones, nature and unfolding of the cognitively rel-
exhibit "intrinsic intentionality," conjoined evant computations, and hence emerge as a
with the assertion that no proper part of a proper part of the material substrate of some
truly cognitive process can trade solely in target cognitive process or activity. Call
representations lacking such intrinsic con- this the "tenet of computational promis-
tent, such as the conventionally couched cuity." Given that we have defended the
encodings in Otto's notebook (on intention- idea that cognition can be extended because
ality and extended cognition, see Wilson, the computations it involves are extended,
unpublished). The upshot of this is that the this tenet leads directly to the view of sit-
notebook (or Kanzi's keyboard) is deemed uated cognition as extended cognition that
unsuitable as an element in any puta- we have been defending. When computa-
tively cognitive process (see, e.g., Adams & tional promiscuity meets intrinsic unsuit-
Aizawa, 2001, p. 53). The dogma is also at ability, something surely has to give. We
work in their later suggestion that cognitive think what has to give is clearly the notion
psychology, in discovering pervasive fea- of intrinsic unsuitability.
tures of human biological systems of mem- The pressure on the dogma of intrinsic
ory and perception, is discovering features unsuitability here, however, does not stem
that may be the signatures of the kinds of solely from accepting the idea of extended
causal process essentially required to sup- computation. This is because the tenet of
port cognition. As a result, the absence of computational promiscuity is an instance of
these signatures in the case of certain aug- the broader functionalist insight that causal
mentations and add-ons is presented as a or functional networks of certain kinds are
reason to doubt that the augmentations and what are crucial to cognitive capacities,
add-ons contribute to cognitive processing rather than anything about the particular
properly understood (see, e.g., Adams & stuff in which those networks are realized.
Aizawa, 2001, pp. 52, 61). To be sure, we should require that func-
The biggest flaw in both of these argu- tional networks provide more than a shallow
ments concerns the relations between puta- behavioral mimicry of indisputably cogni-
tively essential properties of a whole and tive creatures (see Block, 1978; Searle, 1980).
essential properties of the parts. For even if But the kind of view that we have developed
we grant that every cognitive system needs here, which begins with indisputably cogni-
to trade in intrinsic contents, it does not tive creatures and then argues that their cog-
follow that each part of every such system nitive systems are, in fact, extended, avoids
needs do so (see Clark, in press). Something this kind of problem at the outset.
70 ROBERT A. WILSON AND ANDY CLARK

Computational promiscuity is, it is im- mentary processes, some cognitive, some


portant to note, fully compatible with the not. Robert Rupert (2004, in press) offers
thought that certain kinds of computational just such a challenge for the kind of
structure may be necessary for fluid, real- approach we have been describing. T h e
world intelligence. It is even compatible challenge comes in two parts. The first con-
with the thought that such necessary com- cerns what Rupert sees as the severe costs
putational structures (if such there be) may of seriously adopting an extended cogni-
all be located, at present at least, inside the tive systems perspective. The second con-
heads of biological agents. It asserts only cerns what Rupert depicts as the lack of
that once any such necessary structuring added value provided by the adoption of an
conditions have been met, there is then no extended perspective. To offset the severe
limit on the kinds of additional resource that costs, he argues, the added value would have
may then be co-opted as proper parts of an to be very great indeed. But in fact, the com-
extended cognitive process. bined effect, he fears, is just the opposite.
Once any such core systems are in place, The large costs are offset by no correspond-
many other kinds of representational and ingly large gains, and so the project of study-
computational resource may come to act ing cognition as an extended phenomenon is
either temporarily or permanently as proper one that both philosophy and cognitive sci-
parts of more complex, hybrid, distributed, ence would be wise to reject.
cognitive wholes. In such cases, it is often Rupert distinguishes two projects that he
the very fact that these additional elements sees as competing proposals for understand-
trade in modes of representation and pro- ing situated cognition. The first is the one
cessing that are different from those of the we defend here. It embraces a vision of
cognitive core that makes the hybrid orga- cognitive processing itself as (sometimes)
nization worthwhile. We think that tracing quite literally extending into the extra-
and understanding such deep complemen- organismic environment. Rupert dubs this
tarity is the single most important task con- the hypothesis of extended cognition (HEC)
fronting the study of situated cognition. The and depicts it as a radical hypothesis apt, if
previously mentioned example of Kanzi is true, to transform cognitive scientific the-
a case in point. There can be little doubt ory and practice and to affect our concep-
that, were it not for a wealth of pattern- tions of agency and persons. But it needs
recognizing know-how, Kanzi would not to be assessed, he argues, alongside a more
have been able to learn to use and deploy conservative (though still interesting and
the symbol board. Yet there can also be lit- important) competitor perspective. This is
tle doubt that keyboard-Kanzi - the larger the perspective dubbed the hypothesis of
cognitive whole that results from the fluent embedded cognition (HEMC), according to
coupling between bio-Kanzi and the new which: "Cognitive processes depend very
resource - is a fundamentally different kind heavily, in hitherto unexpected ways, on
of cognizing entity from his unaugmented organismically external props and devices
cousins. Keyboard-Kanzi is not simply a cog- and on the structure of the external envi-
nitive core with an add-on symbol board. He ronment in which cognition takes place"
is a new kind of hybrid thinking device. ( R u p e r t , 2004, p. 393).
Why prefer HEMC over HEC? Rupert
starts with an appeal to common sense.
6. Is Cognition Extended Common sense, he suggests, rebels at the
or Only Embedded? vision of extended cognition, so we need
sound theoretical reasons to endorse it. By
Perhaps, though, we can carry out this contrast, HEMC is much more compatible
project without buying into the idea of with common sense.
literal cognitive extensions. Perhaps it is Two main worries are then raised for
enough, indeed, to speak merely of comple- HEC. The first worry, similar to one raised
HOW TO SITUATE COGNITION 71

by Adams and Aizawa, concerns the pro- framework of HEMC, there can be no com-
found differences that appear to distinguish pelling reason to adopt HEC.
the inner and outer contributions. Thus, These are good questions to raise, and we
for example, we read that "the external find Rupert a thoughtful and engaging critic.
portions of extended 'memory' states (pro- Nonetheless, we think that Rupert's wor-
cesses) differ so greatly from internal memo- ries, including the very idea of a stark, all-or-
ries (the process of remembering) that they nothing contrast between HEC and HEMC,
should be treated as distinct kinds" (Rupert, are misplaced, and for two quite deep rea-
2004, p. 407). Given these differences, there sons.
is no immediate pressure to conceive the The first is that no part of the arguments
internal and the external contribution in for extended cognition tum on, or other-
the same terms. But worse still, there is wise require, the similarity of the inner and
(allegedly) a significant cost. The cost is one outer contributions. This point also deflects
that appears briefly in Rupert (2004) and is a related concern that Adams and Aizawa
greatly expanded in Rupert (in press). For express. They say that, because the causal
taking all kinds of external props and aids as arrangements whereby external stuff con-
proper parts of human cognitive processing tributes to action seem very different from
robs us, he fears, of the standard object of those in place when internal stuff does
cognitive scientific theorizing, namely, the so, there can be no unified science of the
stable persisting individual. Even in cases extended mind. Thus, they note (Adams &
of developmental theorizing, where what is Aizawa, 2001, p. 61) that biological memory
at issue is not so much stability as change, systems display a number of effects (e.g.,
Rupert argues, one still needs to find an iden- recency, priming) that are not currently fea-
tifiable, though developing, core. Treating tures of external modes of storage, such as
the temporary coupled wholes comprising Otto's notebook. True enough. Such differ-
organism and props as our target cognitive ences, however, in no way compromise the
case for extended cognition. For that case
systems is thus a recipe for chaos:
depends not on fine-grained functional iden-
tity but on the deep complementarity of
The radical approach offers developmental inner and outer contributions whose joint
psychologists no more reason to be inter- effect (e.g., effective remembering) seems
ested in, for example, the series of temporal apt for the solution of a cognitive task, intu-
segments we normally associate with Sally itively identified.
from ages two-to-six rather than to be inter-
ested in, say, Sally, aged two, together with In the case of Adams and Aizawa, part
a ball she was bouncing on some particu- of the confusion hereabouts may be due to
lar day, Johnny, aged five, together with a persistent misreading (one unfortunately
the book he was reading on some particu- invited by certain phrasings elsewhere in
lar afternoon, and Terry, aged seven, plus the original text) of what is sometimes now
the stimulus item he has just been shown known as the "parity claim," originally intro-
by the experimenter. (Rupert, in press, p. 9)
duced by Clark and Chalmers (1998). This
was the claim that if, as we confront some
More generally then, Rupert worries that task, a part of the world functions as a pro-
cognitive science and cognitive psychology cess that, were it to go on in the head, we
would lose their grip on their subject matter, would have no hesitation in accepting as part
and with it whatever progress has been made of the cognitive process, then that part of the
so far, were they to identify human cognitive world is (for that time) part of the cognitive
processing with the activity of these "short- process. Far from requiring any deep similar-
lived coupled systems" (in press, p. 7). Given ity between inner and outer processes, the
this very high cost, and given that all the gen- parity claim was specifically meant to under-
uine insights of HEC, so Rupert claims, can mine any tendency to think that the shape
be accommodated in the more conservative of the (present-day, human) inner processes
72 ROBERT A.WILSON AND ANDY CLARK

sets some bar (as, e.g., Adams & Aizawa, Biomemory thus meets the requirement as it
2001, suggest) on what ought to count as falls under the laws and explanatory frame-
part of a genuinely cognitive process. (For works of a successful science — cognitive
the same kind of move, see Hurley, 1998, psychology or cognitive science more gener-
pp. 190-193.) ally. But (the argument continues) extended
The parity probe is thus meant to act as memory does not fit the profile of m e m o r y
a kind of veil of metabolic ignorance, invit- as described by successful science and hence
ing us to ask what our attitude would be should not be subsumed under the heading
if currently external means of storage and of "memory" at all.
transformation were, contrary to the pre- Our response to this is twofold. First, it is
sumed facts, found in biology. Thus were by no means clear that acceptable forms of
Martian biomemory systems found not to unification require that all the systemic ele-
involve priming or recency effects, no one ments behave according to the same laws.
would (we suppose) treat that as a reason for For example, human biomemory systems
not treating them as part of the Martian cog- may, as Rupert notes, themselves form a
nitive apparatus. Likewise, were such novel kind of family resemblance grouping that
systems found inside human heads, no one tolerates substantial variation in fine-grained
would demur at their forming part of the nature. But second, and most important, the
human cognitive apparatus. This means that study of extended cognitive systems is just
such systems pass the parity test (merely beginning, and it is no wonder that our best
a rule of thumb or heuristic) as Clark and current unified understandings target the
Chalmers intended it to be deployed. Notice inner elements alone; that is where science
then that the parity is not about the outer has been looking, after all. It is the empiri-
performing just like the (human-specific) cal bet of the extended systems theorist that
inner. Rather, it is about avoiding a rush the larger wholes, comprising biological and
to judgment based on spatial location alone. nonbiological elements, will indeed prove
(This, by the way, is very much how Turner to be the proper objects of sustained scien-
approaches the idea of an extended physiol- tific study, exhibiting features and answer-
ogy, which we discussed in section 3.) The ing to constraints characteristic of (different
parity principle thus appeals to our rough kinds of) extended problem-solving wholes.
sense of what we might intuitively judge to Examples of the payoff of that bet include
belong to the domain of cognition - rather Zhang and Norman's 1994 work on repre-
than, say, that of digestion - but attempts to sentations in distributed cognitive tasks, and
do so without the pervasive distractions of Gray and Fu's 2004 systematic studies tar-
skin and skull. geting the principles that govern the rapid
Rupert's worry, though closely related, recruitment of least-effort problem-solving
turns not on the misplaced requirement of packages that sometimes, but not always,
fine-grained functional identity of contribu- incorporate neural, bodily, and environmen-
tion but on the issue (also raised by Adams tal resources.
and Aizawa) of natural or explanatory kinds. Contrary to any requirement of fine-
Rupert thus seeks to question the idea, cer- grained similarity, then, what the friends
tainly present in Clark and Chalmers's orig- of extended cognition actually expect, and
inal treatment, that treating the organism- (as we saw in section 4) study, are hybrid
notebook system as the supervenience base processes in which the inner and the outer
for some of Otto's dispositional beliefs was contributions are typically highly distinct in
to be recommended on grounds of explana- nature, yet deeply integrated and comple-
tory unity and power. The argument (and mentary. As an epistemic aside, this com-
thanks to Rob Rupert for clarifying input plementarity is probably most evident if
here) took as a premise the idea that a your vision of the inner realm departs fun-
kind is natural if it is adverted to by the damentally from that of classical cognitive
laws or explanations of a successful science. science, as the stability, compactness, and
HOW TO SITUATE COGNITION

arbitrariness of linguistic symbols and en- and results from a failure to appreciate the
codings contrasts dramatically with the two independent dimensions that jointly
fluid, distributed, context-sensitive repre- construct the space of cognitive extensions.
sentations developed by a connectionist or With this framework in mind, we see that
dynamical engine. there is no need, in taking cognitive exten-
A second reason to resist the easy assim- sions perfectly seriously, to lose our grip
ilation of HEC into HEMC concerns the on the more or less stable, more or less
nature of the interactions between the inter- persisting biological bundle that lies at the
nal and the external resources themselves. heart of each episode of soft assembly lead-
Such interactions, it is important to note, ing to a TECS. Occasionally, of course, we
may be highly complex, nested, and non- may confront genuine (permanent, reliable)
linear. As a result, there may be no viable extensions of that more or less persisting
means of understanding the behavior and core. Otto's notebook and Kanzi's symbol
potential of the extended cognitive ensem- board are, we think, gestures at examples
bles by piecemeal decomposition and addi- of this kind: cases in which the persisting,
tive reassembly. To understand the inte- mobile resource bundle is augmented in a
grated operation of the extended-thinking robustly reliable manner. But in most other
system created, for example, by combining cases, we confront the cognitive equivalent
pen, paper, graphics programs, and a trained of Bingham's TSDs: soft-assembled, tem-
mathematical brain, it may be quite insuf- porary medleys of information-processing
ficient to attempt to understand and then resources comprising a dovetailed subset of
combine (1) the properties of pens, graph- neural activity and environmentally routed
ics programs, paper, and brains. This may augmentations. The costs of not accepting
be insufficient for just the same kinds of HEC are thus great indeed. For as cogni-
reasons advanced by Bingham in the case tive extensions these are, quite literally, the
of the human action system, or, within soft-assembled circuitry of a great deal of
neuroscience itself, as reasons to study not practical human thought and reason. We
ignore or downplay the importance of these
just the various major neural substructures
ensembles, treating them as merely ersatz
and their capacities but also the com-
cognitive circuitry, at our theoretical peril.
plex (often-transient) larger-scale activities
For the bulk of real-world problem solving,
in which they combine.
especially of the kinds apparently unique to
The larger explanatory targets here are
our species, may be nothing but the play of
whole processing cycles, involving soft- representation and computation across these
assembled coalitions of neural resources spectacularly transformative mixes of organ-
recruited for some specific problem-solving ismic and extraorganismic resources.
purpose. Such soft-assembled neural pack-
ages involve the temporally evolving, often Overall, Rupert's strategy of argument
highly reentrant activity of multiple pop- rests on the claim that any benefits accruing
ulations of neurons spanning a variety of to the expanded perspective can be as eas-
brain areas. Why, then, suppose that the ily accommodated by the more conservative
soft assemblies most relevant to human cog- reading, according to which all the cognizing
nitive achievements are essentially bounded goes on in the biological elements, with the
by skin and skull? Why shouldn't the process rest just a temporarily recruited set of input
of recruitment, and the skills of dovetailing devices, props, and supports. In this respect,
the various contributions, yield, at least in it is similar to the claims of behaviorists in
our artifact-rich world, a succession of sim- the first half of the twentieth-century that
ilarly complex hybrid ensembles spanning they could account for all so-called cognitive
brain, body, and world? phenomena solely in terms of behavior. Sim-
What, finally, of the allegedly intolera- ilarly, Griffiths and Scarantino (this volume)
ble costs of such an enlarged perspective? think the debate concerning the extended
mind merely semantic and effectively opt
In one sense, the worry is simply misplaced
74 r o b e r t a., w i l s o n a n d a n d y c l a r k

for H E M C on grounds of minimal disrup- least a preliminary sense of its diversity in


tion. the preceding sections. For s o m e cognitive
But we should treat such conservative performances, it m a y very w e l l be that the
claims with great caution. Consider the fol- smallest systems that are apt f o r t h e s u p p o r t
lowing caricature: of the target behavior turn out to involve
multiple looping processes that span brain,
Look, there's all this new exciting talk body, and aspects of the social or physical
about how the brain is the causal basis for environment. T h e question, in e a c h case, is
cognitive processing. Call this the hypothe- where it is that we find f u n c t i o n a l l y inte-
sis of in-brain cognition (HIC). Poppycock1. grated systems that allow their bearers to
For there is a more conservative hypothe- perform cognitive tasks. We think t h a t s o m e
sis available, the hypothesis of in-neuron
of these are found solely in t h e h e a d , and
cognition fHINC): for any particular cog-
that some of them cross t h e cranial b o u n d -
nitive ability, there is a given neuron, N,
ary and incorporate cognitive resources in
that is the real causal basis for that ability.
an individual's environment. T h a t is nature's
Cognitive processes depend very heavily,
in hitherto unexpected ways, on the rest way.
of the brain, but it is only a given indi-
vidual neuron that is ever genuinely cogni-
tive. Any useful accounts you may develop 7. Conclusion: Letting Nature
using HIC can, in any case, be fully accom-
Take Its Course
modated by HINC, and HINC is signif-
icantly less radical than HIC in that it
Human agents exhibit b o t h a m e t a b o l i c
requires only that we take into account how
N exploits information coming from the rest and a cognitive organization. B u t w h e r e a s
of the brain and how N, in turn, transmits the former depends heavily on e x p e n s i v e l y
other information to yet other parts of the maintained and policed organismic b o u n d -
brain. Hence, HINC is to be preferred to aries, the latter looks p r o n e to r e p e a t e d
HIC. bouts of seepage in w h i c h c o g n i t i v e pro-
cesses productively loop through surround-
What makes this a caricature, of course, is ing environmental structures. T h e s e struc-
the fact that as far as cognition goes, H I N C tures may be natural, sociocultural, or
lacks the explanatory successes of HIC. And technological, or any combination t h e r e o f .
this, presumably, is because the smallest sys- And the resultant wholes m a y be one- o f f ,
tems that seem apt for the support of gen- repeated, or relatively permanent. T h i s t w o -
uinely cognitive behavior have turned out dimensional matrix limns t h e s p a c e and
to be larger than single neurons. Our best structure of cognitive extensions. T h e study
empirical research tells us that intuitively of situated cognition, we h a v e argued, is the
cognitive acts often involve lots of neurons study of the many forms of cognitive e x t e n -
spread throughout the brain. HIC is then a sion that appear in this c o m p l e x space. To
sort of shorthand that signals this. In fact, study such systems is not perversely to f o c u s
our best research has helped us to identify on some strange mishmash of t h e cognitive
not the brain but specific (sometimes tem- and the noncognitive, study that p u r s u e s the
porarily assembled) complexes of neural sys- mind into some place it is not. It is, rather,
tems as the causal basis for particular cogni- to corral cognition in its den: to track nature
tive acts and capacities.
taking its cognitive course.
If this kind of substantive justification (of
our actual preference for HIC over HINC)
is at all on track, then Rupert's claim that Acknowledgments
HEMC is preferable to H E C should seem
suspect. For there is already much research This project was completed thanks to teaching
that already fruitfully explores extended relief provided to Andy Clark under the A H R C
cognitive systems, and we have provided at Research Leave Scheme (Project: "On the Proper
h o w t o situate cognition

Treatment of Embodiment"), and with the sup- Burge, T. (1986a). Individualism and psychology.
port of individual three-year grant 410-2005-1629 Philosophical Review, 95, 3—45,
from the Social Sciences and Humanities Re- Burge, T. (1986b). Intellectual norms and founda-
search Council of Canada to Robert A. Wilson. tions of mind. Journal of Philosophy, 83, 697—
Thanks to Andrew Wilson for the pointer to Bing- 720.
ham's work on task-specific devices; and to Mark Clark, A. (1989). Microcognition: Philosophy, cog-
Rowlands, John Sutton, Michael Wheeler, Philip nitive science and parallel distributed processing.
Robbins, Susan Hurley, Robert Rupert, Fred Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Adams, and Ken Aizawa for useful comments Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body,
and discussions concerning many of the topics. and world together again. Cambridge, M A :
The authors can be contacted at rob.wilson@ MIT Press.
ualberta.ca and andy.clark@ed.ac.uk. Clark, A. (1998). Magic words: How language
augments human computation. In P. Car-
ruthers & J. Boucher (Eds.), Language and
References thought: Interdisciplinary themes (pp. 162-183).
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Clark, A. (2003). Natural-born cyborgs: Minds,
Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2001). The bounds
technologies, and the future of human intelli-
of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 14, 43-
gence. New York: Oxford University Press.
64.
Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of Clark, A. (2005a). Beyond the flesh: Some lessons
cognition. Oxford: Blackwell. from a mole cricket. Artificial Life, 11, 233-244.
Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (in press). Defending Clark, A. (2005b). Word, niche and super-niche:
the bounds of cognition. In R. Menary (Ed.), How language makes minds matter more.
The extended mind. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate. Theoria, 20, 255-268.
Ballard, D., Hayhoe, M. M., Pook, P. K., & Rao, Clark, A. (2007). Re-inventing ourselves: The
R. P. N. (1997). Deictic codes for the embodi- plasticity of embodiment, sensing, and mind.
ment of cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sci- Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 32(3), 263—
ences, 20, 723-767. 282.
Bingham, G. (1988). Task-specific devices and the Clark, A. (in press). Coupling, constitution and
perceptual bottleneck. Human Movement Sci- the cognitive kind: A reply to Adams and
ence, 7, 225-264. Aizawa. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended
Block, N. (1978). Troubles with functionalism. In mind. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.
N. Block (Ed.), Readings in the philosophy of Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended
psychology (Vol. 1, pp. 268-305). Cambridge, mind. Analysis, 58,10-23.
MA: Harvard University Press. Dawkins, R. (1976). The selfish gene. Oxford:
Brooks, R. A. (1991a). Intelligence without rea- Oxford University Press.
son. In J. Myopoulos 8c R. Reiter (Eds.), Pro- Dawkins, R. (1982). The extended phenotype.
ceedings of the 12th International Joint Con- Oxford: Oxford University Press.
ference on Artificial Intelligence (IJCAI-gi) Dennett, D. C. (1978). Where am I? In D. C. Den-
(pp. 569-595). San Mateo, CA: Morgan Kauf- nett (Ed.), Brainstorms (pp. 311-323). Cam-
mann. bridge, MA: Bradford Books, MIT Press.
Brooks, R. A. (1991b). Intelligence without rep- Ebbs, G. (1998). Rule-following and realism. Cam-
resentation. Artificial Intelligence, 47, 139-160. bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
(Modified version reprinted in J. Haugeland Egan, F. (1992). Individualism, computation, and
[Ed.], Mind design II: Philosophy, psychology, perceptual content. Mind, 101, 443-459.
artificial intelligence [pp. 395-420]. Cambridge, Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought. Cam-
MA: MIT Press, 1997.) bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Brooks, R. A. (1999). Cambrian intelligence: The Fodor, J. A. (1982). Cognitive science and the
early history of the new AI. Cambridge, MA: twin-earth problem. Notre Dame Journal of
MIT Press. Formal Logic, 23, 98-118.
Burge, T. (1979). Individualism and the mental. Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cam-
In P. French, T. Uehling Jr., 8c H. Wettstein bridge, MA: MIT Press.
(Eds.), Midwest studies in philosophy (Vol. 4, Fowler, C., 8c Turvey, M. T. (1978). Skill acqui-
pp. 73-121). Minneapolis: University of Min- sition: An event approach with special ref-
nesota Press. erence to searching for the optimum of a
76
ROBERT A. WILSON AND ANDY CLARK

function of several variables. In G. Stelmach knowledge (pp. 131-193). Minneapolis: Univer-


(Ed.), Information processing tn motor control sity of Minnesota Press.
and learning (pp. 1-40). New York: Academic Pylyshyn, Z. (1984). Computation and cognition.
Press. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gallagher. S. (2005). How the body shapes the Rogers, Y., & Scaife, M. (1997). Distributed cog-
mind. New York: Oxford University Press. nition. Retrieved May 13, 2008, from http://
Goody, J. (1977). TV domestication of the sav- www.irit.fr/ACTIVrTES/GRIC/cotcos/pjs/
age mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University TheoreticalApproaches/DistributedCog/Dist
Press CognitionpaperRogers.htm.
Gray, W. D., & Fu, W.-T. (2004). Soft constraints Rowlands, M. (1999). The body in mind. New
in interactive behavior: The case of ignoring York: Cambridge University Press.
perfect knowledge in-the-world for imperfect Rupert, R. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis
knowledge in-the-head. Cognitive Science, 28, of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy,
359-3^2. 101, 389-428.
Haugeland, J. (1998). Mind embodied and Rupert, R. (in press). Representation in extended
embedded. In J. Haugeland (Ed.), Having cognitive systems: Does the scaffolding of lan-
thought: Essays in the metaphysics of mind. guage extend the mind? In R. Menary (Ed.),
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. The extended mind. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.
(Reprinted from Acta Philosophica Fennica, 58, Salzman, E., | Kelso, J. A. S. (1987). Skilled
[1995], 233-267.) actions: A task dynamic approach. Psychologi-
Hurley, S. (1998). Consciousness in action. Cam- cal Review, 94, 84-106.
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Savage-Rumbaugh, S., & Lewin, R. (1994). Kami:
Hutchins, E. (199.5). Cognition in the wild. Cam- The ape at the brink of the human mind. New
bridge, MA: MIT Press. York: Wiley and Sons.
Jablonka, E., & Lamb, M. (2005). Evolution in four Savage-Rumbaugh, S., Shanker, S. G., & Taylor,
dimensions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. T. J. (1998). Apes, language, and the human
Loar, 6. (1988). Social content and psychologi- mind. New York: Oxford University Press.
cal content. In R. Grimm & D. Merrill (Eds.), Scaife, M., 8c Rogers, Y. (1996). External cogni-
Contents of thought (pp. 99-110). Tucson: Uni- tion: How do graphical representations work?
versity of Arizona Press. International Journal of Human-Computer
Newell, A (1980). Physical symbol systems. Cog- Studies, 45,185-213.
nitive Science, 4,135-183. Searle, J. (1980). Minds, brains, and programs.
Newell, A., & Simon, H. (1976). Computer sci- Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 417-424.
ence as empirical enquiry. In J. Haugeland Segal, G. (1989). Seeing what is not there. Philo-
(Ed.), Mind design (pp. 35-66). Cambridge, sophical Review, 98,189-214.
MA: MIT Press. Shapiro, L. (1997). A clearer vision. Philosophy of
Norman, D. (1993). Cognition in the head and in Science, 64,131-153.
the world. Cognitive Science, 17,1-6. Stenning, K, & Oberlander, J. (1995). A cognitive
Odling-Smee, J., Laland, K., & Feldman, M. theory of graphical and linguistic reasoning:
(2003). Niche construction: The neglected process Logic and implementation. Cognitive Science,
in evolution. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univer- 19, 97-140.
sity Press. Turner, J. S. (2000). The extended organism:
Oyama, S. (1985). The ontogeny of information (2nd The physiology of animal-built structures. Cam-
ed.). Durham, NC: Duke University Press, bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
2000. Wilson, R. A. (1994). Wide computationalism.
Oyama, S., Griffiths, P. E., & Gray, R. D. (Eds.). Mind, 10t, 351-372.
(2001). Cycles of contingency: Developmental Wilson, R. A. (1995). Cartesian psychology and
systems and evolution. Cambridge, MA: MIT physical minds: Individualism and the sciences
Press. of the mind. New York: Cambridge University
Pettit, P. (1993). The common mind: An essay Press.
on psychology, society, and politics. New York: Wilson, R. A. (2000). The mind beyond itself.
Oxford University Press. In D. Sperber (Ed.), Misrepresentations: A
Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of "meaning." multidisäplinary perspective (pp. 31-52). New
In K Gunderson (Ed.), Language, mind and York: Oxford University Press.
HOW TO SITUATE COGNITION

Wilson, R. A. (2003). Individualism. In S. sciences. Biology and Philosophy, 19, 397-423.


Stich & T. A. Warfield (Eds.), The Blackwell Wilson, R. A. (2005). Genes and the agents of life:
companion to philosophy of mind (pp. 256-287). The individual in the fragjle sciences: Biology.
New York: Blackwell. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Wilson, R. A. (2004a). Boundaries of the mind: Wilson, R. A. (unpublished). Meaning making
The individual in the fragile sciences: Cognition. and the mind of the externalist.
New York: Cambridge University Press. Zhang, J., & Norman, D. A. (1994). Representa-
Wilson, R. A. (2004b). Recent work in individu- tions in distributed cognitive tasks. Cognitive
alism in the social, behavioural and biological Science, 18, 87-122.
CHAPTER 5

Why the Mind Is Still in the Head

Fred Adams and Kenneth Aizawa

Philosophical interest in situated cognition computers, watches, telescopes, and hear-


has been focused most intensely on the claim ing aids are all properly understood as cases
that human cognitive processes extend from in which cognitive processes interact with
the brain into the tools humans use. As we noncognitive processes. Although the tools
see it, this radical hypothesis is sustained we are familiar with are like this, not all
by two kinds of mistakes, the confusion of tools are necessarily like this. Perhaps one
coupling relations with constitutive relations day it will be possible to replace the rods
and an inattention to the mark of the cogni- and cones in the human retina with syn-
tive. Here we wish to draw attention to these thetic rods and cones. These synthetic cells -
mistakes and show just how pervasive they these microtools - might have the same
are. That is, for all that the radical philoso- size and shape as naturally occurring human
phers have said, the mind is still in the rods and cones. They might have the same
head.1 neurotransmitter-handling properties. They
might have the same response properties
to light. On the supposition that percep-
1. The Issue tual processes are cognitive and that they
begin at the retina, it would turn out that in
In Adams and Aizawa (2001), we defended the future just described, there might well
a commonsense and scientifically standard be individuals whose cognitive processes
view of the locus of cognition we called extend beyond their organismal boundaries,
"contingent intracranialism." According to giving them transorganismal cognition. 1 Be
this view, as a matter of contingent empir- the future what it may, our view is that these
ical fact, human tool use is typically a possible cases of tool use are unlike at least
matter of intracranially localized cognitive the vast majority of our contemporary cases
processes interacting with extracranial bio- of tool use.
logical, chemical, and physical processes. In the face of both common sense and
Current human use of pencils and paper, much contemporary science, an increasing

78
WHY THE MIND IS STILL IN THE HEAD 79

number of philosophers and psychologists cognition that a properly organized configu-


have found themselves attracted to con- ration of processes can simultaneously cross
tingent transcranialism.' This is the view the boundaries of the brain and constitute
that, in ordinary tool use, we have instances cognition. Another thesis is Ron McClam-
in which cognitive processes span the cra- rock's (1995) claim that "the information
nial boundary and extend into extracranial available to us in deciding what to do . . . is
space. As Dennett (2000) puts it, "minds are not so clearly circumscribed at the boundary
composed of tools for thinking that we not only of the physical organism" (p. 89). Although
obtain from the wider (social) world, but McClamrock appears to think this is contro-
largely leave in the world, instead of clut- versial, it seems to us quite clear that infor-
tering up our brains with them" (p. 21, ital- mation beyond the boundary of our bodies
ics in original). This is the view that when a makes a difference to our decisions. Written
student takes notes in class, the student liter- material often contains useful information.
ally commits information to memory. When That is why reading it is so often helpful in
someone uses pencil and paper to compute decision making. Another tangential issue is
large sums, cognitive processes extend to the Clark and Chalmers's (1998) claim that
pencil and paper themselves. In these cases,
the processes involving the pencil and paper i f , as we confront some task, a part of the
constitute cognitive processes. Not all trans- world functions as a process which, were
cranialists make as sweeping a proposal as it done in the head, we would have no
does Dennett. Some transcranialists think hesitation in recognizing as part of a cogni-
that only certain types of tool use bring tive process, then that part of the world is
(so we claim) part of the cognitive process.
about the extension of the cognitive into
(P-8)
the extracranial world. Some transcranialists
think that only special brain-tool couplings We agree with this, because it seems to us
will let the cognitive enter the artifactual. 4 to say nothing other than that the difference
Be these refinements as they may, all trans- between being in the head and being outside
cranialists we know of have enthusiastically of the head does not constitute a mark of
embraced what they recognize to be a radi- the cognitive. Yet another tangential issue is
cal departure from orthodoxy. the thesis that cognitive psychology should
So described, intracranialists and trans- attend to the interactions between organ-
cranialists are concerned with the manner isms and their environments, or between
in which processes are subdivided. When a minds and their environments. Insofar as
person uses pencil and paper to compute a this thesis requires only that one attend to
sum, the intracranialist maintains that there the interactions of cognitive processes with
is a natural kind of process (recognizably noncognitive environmental processes, the
cognitive) that happens to occur within the intracranialist can accept it.7 Finally, we are
brain, where the transcranialist maintains not concerned with whether the concept
that there is a natural kind of process (rec- of cognition requires that cognition only be
ognizably cognitive) that extends from the found in the brain.8 We do not think it
brain to the pencil and paper. The radical does, but we also do not think that this
transcranialist thesis that concerns us here is all that interesting a question. It is no
must be distinguished from many less rad- more interesting than whether our concept
ical but related theses with which it might of water requires that it be found only on
be confused. One thesis is that it is possi- earth or whether our concept of a pen-
ble for cognitive processes to extend beyond guin requires that it be found only in the
the boundaries of the brain. Susan Hur- Antarctic. The transcranialist thesis we care
ley (1998), for example, and Andy Clark about maintains that organism-environment
(2005, in press) are quite interested in this interactions are to be understood as entirely
possibility. 5 We are not, because we think it cognitive processes rather than merely par-
is part of the standard functionalist view of tially cognitive and partially noncognitive
80 FRED ADAMS A N D KENNETH AIZAWA

processes Another way to put the matter What is at issue are the bounds of cogni-
is to say that the current issue is whether tion. What regions of space-time contain
tool use is typically a matter of cognitive cognitive processing? Clark and Chalmers's
processes interacting with portions of the account is inadequate on another score.
noncognitive environment (the contingent Grant, for the moment, their unsubstanti-
intracranialist view) or is typically a mat- ated claim that intracranialism and trans-
ter of cognitive processing throughout (the cranialism lead to different scientific
transcranialist view). methodologies. This seems to us an insuffi-
cient basis to block the charge of this debate
In this debate, a recurring worry for trans-
being a terminological dispute. Make up
cranialists is, or at least should be, that the
some terminological shift. Consider using
«conceptualization they urge will degener-
cognitive to mean avian. Surely such a termi-
ate into a mere terminological dispute over
nological shift will have dramatic method-
how to use the word cognitive and related
ological implications for the new cognitive
descriptors.9 It is not enough for trans-
science. So, as we said, there is reason to be
cranialists to argue that something extends
dissatisfied with the solution that Clark and
beyond brain boundaries.10 It is not enough
Chalmers propose.
that there be some scientific taxonomy that
groups the intracranial and the transcranial It is not clear that the charge of termi-
under one set of kinds or processes. Physics, nological quibbling can be entirely avoided
biology, and chemistry might well do that. in favor of what all parties are interested
The transcranialists need to maintain that in, namely, an understanding of brain-world
cognition extends beyond the brain. So, they interactions. Yet, here is our attempt. We
cannot simply propose to use cognitive and maintain that there is something distinctive
its kin to describe any old scientific kind. about the brain. There are natural kinds
There must be some appropriate theoretical of processes that happen to occur only
affinity between what they call "cognitive" within the brain. These processes differ from
and what has traditionally gone under the neurophysiological processes insofar as they
name cognitive. Clark and Chalmers (1998) consist of (in general, poorly understood)
try to address this problem by saying that causal operations on nonderived represen-
tations (representations whose content does
in seeing cognition as extended one is not not depend on other previously existing con-
merely making a terminological decision; tent). These processes also differ, we sup-
it makes a significant difference to the pose, from typical processes that extend
methodology of scientific investigation. In into the world from brains and from pro-
effect, explanatory methods that might once cesses found in typical machines. In other
have been thought appropriate only for the words, we hypothesize that there are within
analysis of inner processes are now being
the brain natural laws that are not identi-
adapted for the study of the outer, and there
cal to physical, chemical, biological, or neu-
is promise that our understanding of cogni-
rophysiological covering laws spanning the
tion will become richer for it. (p. 10)
cranium." We are not offering a stipula-
tive definition of the cognitive but some
This seems to us inadequate for two rea-
hypotheses about the nature of cognition. In
sons. The first stems from the distinc-
taking this line, we suppose that it is recog-
tion made in the previous paragraph. Intra-
nition of the distinct type of information-
cranialists can perfectly well accept the idea
processing capacities of the brain, rather
that brain-tool interactions and brain-world
than mere prejudice, that has inclined ortho-
interactions are worthy of scientific inves-
dox cognitive science to the view that cog-
tigation. The study of human factors - the
nitive processing is, in all actual cases, an
way in which humans interact with prod-
intracranial affair.13
ucts, tools, and procedures - is fine by the
intracranialist. Vision science is also a per- Reviewing the literature on this issue,
fecdy legitimate area of scientific research. one finds that there are two principal
w h y t h e mind is st1li, in t h e h e a d 87

mistakes that sustain transcranialism. First, examples. Consider the bimetallic strip in
transcranialists are insensitive to the dif- an ordinary thermostat. T h e expansion and
ference between cognitive processes being contraction of this strip is closely coupled to
causally connected to environmental pro- the ambient temperature of a room and the
cesses and cognitive processes being, in part, air-conditioning apparatus for that room.
constituted by environmental processes. Nevertheless, this gives us no reason to say
Second, transcranialists are insufficiently that the expansion and contraction of the
sensitive to the problem of distinguish- strip extends beyond the limits of the strip
ing the cognitive f r o m the noncognitive. and into the room or air conditioner. T h e
In this chapter, we wish to show h o w Watt governor provides another example.
these two mistakes run through m u c h of T h e combustion of fuel in the governed
the philosophical literature defending trans- engine is tightly coupled to the rotation of
cranialism. the weighted arms, yet the process of com-
bustion does not extend beyond the bounds
of the engine.' 4 This is the generic form of
2. The Coupling A r g u m e n t s a coupling argument, but we find a range of
specific variations in the literature.
Coupling arguments are far and away the
primary sort of argument given in support
2.1. The Simple Coupling Argument
of transcranialism. W h a t is c o m m o n to these
arguments is a tacit m o v e f r o m the observa- In what we call the "simple coupling argu-
tion that process X is in some w a y causally ment," all that is invoked in arguing for an
connected (coupled) to a cognitive process Y extended cognitive process is a causal con-
to the conclusion that X is part of the cog- nection or looping between the cognizing
nitive process Y. T h e pattern of reasoning organism and its environment. T h e infer-
here involves moving f r o m the observation ence is most commonly made in the sug-
that process X is in some w a y causally con- gestion that in the use of pencil and paper
nected (coupled) to a process Y of type 4> to compute large sums one's cognitive pro-
to the conclusion that X is part of a pro- cesses include the pencil and paper. But
cess of type <j>. In attributing this pattern other examples are invoked as well.
of reasoning to advocates of transcranialism, In chapter 8 of his book Boundaries of the
we do not mean that they consciously and Mind, Robert Wilson (2004) suggests that
deliberately draw a distinction between the he plans to make a case for transcranialism
coupling claim and the constitution claim, (pp. 188-193). He then proceeds to describe a
and then explicitly assert that coupling is children's puzzle game, Rush Hour, wherein
sufficient for constitution. Far f r o m it. W h a t one moves wooden rectangles around in a
typically happens is that writers just casu- wooden frame. Then following the presenta-
ally slip between one and the other. W h e n tion of the example, Wilson writes, "[when
presented with this analysis, defenders of solving the puzzle] the mind extends itself
transcranialism typically deny that they rea- beyond the purely internal capacities of
son in this way. W h a t we are offering is a the brain by engaging with, exploiting, and
reconstruction of what appears to be going manipulating parts of its structured environ-
on in many cases. To m a k e this analysis ment" (p. 195). In this context, it is plausible
stick, while being as sympathetic as possible to read the inference from coupling to con-
to transcranialists, we adopt the inelegant stitution into the following passage:
practice of quoting extensively f r o m the
transcranialists.
We solve the problem by continually look-
In our view, the coupling arguments are ing back to the board and trying to fig-
fallacious.1' They commit w h a t we call the ure out sequences of moves that will get
"coupling-constitution fallacy." We can see us closer to our goal, all the time exploiting
that it is in fact a fallacy by considering some the structure of the environment through
Hi FRED ADAMS AND KENNETH AIZAWA

continual interaction with it. We look, we calculations that we can perform, the pen-
think, we move. But the thinking, the cog- cil and paper are necessary. If the pencil
nitive part of solving the problem, is not and paper are necessary for the calculation,
squirreled away inside us, wedged between why not view them as part of the necessary
the looking and the moving, but developed
substrate for the calculating activity?" (Noe,
and made possible through these interac-
tions with the board. (Wilson, 2004, p. 194J 2004, p. 220). This, too, might or might not
be a claim about constitution. Perhaps Noe
is not in these passages guilty of committing
What one might expect that Wilson means the coupling-constitution fallacy, because
in the foregoing passage is that, in this case, he does not specifically draw the consti-
cognitive processing is not squirreled away tution conclusion. Avoiding the fallacy by
in the brain but extends into the inter- discussing only the substrate of cognition,
actions with the board. Now, if this is however, becomes more difficult when Noe
what he means, although he does not lit- describes, with apparent approval, an idea
erally say it, then he appears to be guilty of he attributes to Clark and Chalmers (1998):
the coupling-constitution fallacy. Of course,
According to active extemalism, the envi-
Wilson might not really mean this. He might ronment can drive and so partially con-
mean only that, in this case, cognitive pro- stitute cognitive processes. Where does the
cessing is developed and made possible by mind stop and the rest of the world begin ?
interactions with the board. But then the If active extemalism is right, then the
contrast implied in the first part of the final boundary cannot be drawn at the skull.
sentence comes out infelicitous and Wilson The mind reaches - or at least can reach,
turns out not to be providing an argument sometimes - beyond the limits of the body
out into the world. (Noe, 2004, p. 221)
for transcranialism after all. Wilson perhaps
has enough wiggle room to avoid the charge
We think Noe's discussion here nicely illus-
of committing the coupling-constitution fal-
trates our view that advocates of trans-
lacy, but recognizing the fallacy is important
cranialism are largely insensitive to the dis-
in the recognition that Wilson is providing
tinction between coupling and constitution
no argument for transcranial cognition.
and just casually slip between one and the
Alva Noe (2004) provides a nice illus-
other.'6
tration of the casual shift between causa-
Raymond Gibbs (2001) provides another
tion and constitution. He begins by describ-
case in point. He runs the simple coupling
ing perceptual experiences as external in
argument on intentions by appeal to what is
the sense that they depend on causal
involved in windsurfing:
interactions between the animal and the
5
environment.' He then frames a slightly The windsurfer continually affects and
different question that might be taken to is affected by the set of the rig, so the
bear more closely on the constitution issue; behavioral intention to successfully wind-
namely, What is the causal substrate of an surf emerges as a result of the interac-
experience? As an answer, he writes, "per- tion between the person and environment.
haps the only way - or the only biological Focusing on the agent alone, or on how the
way - to produce just the flavor sensations agent responds to the environment, fails
one enjoys when one sips wine is by rolling to capture the complex nuances of wind-
a liquid across one's tongue. In that case, surfing behavior. Just as it is important to
understand the significance of paper and
the liquid, the tongue, and the rolling action
pencil when one does long division, where
would be part of the physical substrate for
the cognition of doing long division is in
the experience's occurrence" (Noe, 2004,
part "offloaded" into the environment, the
p. 220). This could be a claim about con- intentionality in windsurfing is best under-
stitution. Discussing the use of pencil and stood as a distributed cognitive behavior
paper in complex calculations, Noe makes involving a person, a device, and the envi-
a similar move: "Indeed, for a great many ronment. (Gibbs, 2001, pp. 117-118)
w h y t h e mind is st1li, in t h e head 85

In this passage, G i b b s urges t w o separate system which solves the problem.... The
claims. One is the m e t h o d o l o g i c a l the- intelligent process just is the spatially and
sis that we should not study intentions temporally extended one which zig-zags
between brain, body, and world. (Clark,
without keeping an e y e on t h e interaction
2001, p. 132; cf. Clark, 2002, pp. 23-24)
between the organism and the environment.
Gibbs evidently refers to this issue w h e n
H e r e the intracranialist can agree w i t h
he describes the putative c o n s e q u e n c e s of
everything up until that last sentence. H e r e
focusing on the agent alone. As indicated
we find a familiar pattern, a long description
previously, we think t h e charge that cog-
of the causal connections b e t w e e n the brain
nitive science does not attend to environ-
and environment f o l l o w e d by the m o v e to
mental interactions is o v e r b l o w n b u t in any
the v i e w that these causal loops constitute
case should not be c o n f u s e d w i t h the issue
part of the cognitive process. This is the sim-
we care about here, n a m e l y , the b o u n d -
ple coupling-constitution fallacy.' 8 W e can
ary of the cognitive. T h e other claim in the
note as w e l l that it is c o m m o n ground that
foregoing passage is the ontological issue of
the brain and the tools are jointly respon-
the bounds on cognition, h o w t h e processes
sible for the product, the journal article.' 9
involved in windsurfing m i g h t be divided
This, however, does not require that b o t h
into the cognitive and the noncognitive.
the brain and tools constitute a single cog-
Gibbs at least c o m e s close to t h e ontolog-
nitive process. It is the interaction of the
ical issue w h e n he claims that the inten-
spinning bowling ball w i t h the surface of
tionality in windsurfing is best understood
the alley that leads to all the pins falling.
as a distributed cognitive b e h a v i o r involv-
Still, the process of the ball's spinning does
ing a person, a device, and t h e environment.
not extend into the surface of the alley or
Unfortunately, he gives no reason to think
the pins. T h e r e is no extended bowling ball
this is so. In describing t h e w i n d s u r f e r case,
that meshes with the alley, nor do we see
Gibbs apparently assumes that, in virtue of
any particular intimacy b e t w e e n a b o w l i n g
a causal coupling, the w i n d s u r f e r and his or
ball and the alley. 2 0 Moreover, t h e contin-
her environment should be analyzed as a sin-
gent intracranialist has no objection to say-
gle cognitive/intentional w h o l e .
ing that operation of the tools and the brain
Clark (2001) gives us another e x a m p l e provide the basis for hypothesizing a sin-
that is strikingly similar to the ones we have gle causal process. T h e p r o b l e m is that this
just seen, a case of writing an academic provides no reason to think that the tools
paper' 7 : and the brain constitute a single "cognitive"
process.
Confronted, at last, with the shiny finished
product the good materialist may find her-
self congratulating her brain on its good
work. But this is misleading. It is mislead- 2.2. The System Version of the Coupling
ing not simply because (as usual) most of Argument
the ideas were not our own anyway, but
because the structure, form and flow of the In an early presentation of this version of the
final product often depends heavily on the argument, we find T i m van G e l d e r (1995)
complex ways the brain cooperates with, claiming the following:
and leans upon, various special features of
the media and technologies with which it In this vision, the cognitive system is not
continually interacts.... The brain's role is just the encapsulated brain; rather, since
crucial and special. But it is not the whole the nervous system, body, and environment
story. In fact, the true (fast and frugal!) are all constantly changing and simulta-
power and beauty of the brain's role is that neously influencing each other, the true
it acts as a mediating factor in a variety of cognitive system is a single unified system
complex and iterated processes which con- embracing all three. The cognitive system
tinually loop between brain, body and tech- does not interact with the body and the
nological environment. And it is this larger external world by means of the occasional
$4 FRED ADAMS AND KENNETH AIZAWA

stalic symbolic inputs and outputs; rather, linguistic communication through a 256-
interaction between the inner and the outer symbol keyboard that he can carry with
is best thought of as a matter of coupling, him. Given Kanzi's actual developmen-
such that both sets of processes continually tal environment, Kanzi plus a 256-symbol
influencing [sic] each other's direction of keyboard forms a cognitive system with
change, (p. 373) memory and other cognitive capacities that
far exceed those of just Kanzi. (Much the
In this passage, van Gelder only claims same holds true of Alex, Irene Pepper-
berg's African grey parrot.) My point here
that the brain, body, and environment con-
is not the trivial one that enriched environ-
stitute a cognitive system. Only later in the
ments can causally produce smarter crit-
paper does he go further to claim that cogni- ters; rather, it is that what metaphysically
tion extends outside the brain: "The Carte- determines the smartness of at least some
sian tradition is mistaken in supposing that critters is their being part of wide cognitive
mind is an inner entity of any kind, whether systems. (Wilson, 2004, p. 195; cf. Wilson
mind-stuff, brain states, or whatever. Onto- & Clark, this volume)
logically, mind is much more a matter of
what we do within environmental and social
possibilities and bounds" (van Gelder, 1995, In the system version of the coupling-
p. 380). Subsequendy, Clark and Chalmers constitution fallacy, the argument begins
(1998) ran a version of the coupling argu- with the observation of important causal
ment inserting the idea that humans and connections (couplings) among the brain
their tools form a cognitive system." They and body and the environment, then infers
write: that these causal connections warrant the
conclusion that the brain, body, and envi-
In these cases [of external tool use], the ronment form a cognitive system. From
human organism is linked with an external there, there is the tacit move to the conclu-
entity in a two-way interaction, creating a sion that cognition extends from the brain
coupled system that can be seen as a cog- into the body and environment. T h e system
nitive system in its own right. All the com-
version of the coupling-constitution fallacy,
ponents in the system play an active causal
thus, differs from the simple version because
role, and they jointly govern behavior in
of the intermediate inference concerning a
the same sort of way that cognition usu-
ally does. If we remove the external compo- system.
nents the system's behavioral competence We can grant for the sake of argument
will drop, just as it would if we removed that the combination of a human being with
part of its brain. Our thesis is that this sort pencil and paper constitutes a system, that
of coupled process counts equally well as a a person with a laptop computer constitutes
cognitive process, whether or not it is wholly a system, that a person with a notebook
in the head. (Clark &! Chalmers, 1998,
constitutes a system, and so forth. We can
PP H)
also concede that humans and their tools
constitute cognitive systems. Still, this does
More recendy, Clark (2003) developed the
not establish transcranialism. It does not fol-
system version of the argument by claim-
low from the fact that one has an X sys-
ing that humans are hybrid artifact-organism
tem that every component of the system
systems, or cyborgs." Robert Wilson also
runs a system version of the coupling argu- does X. Obviously there are systems that
ment with a different example: consist of many types of components and
involve a multiplicity of process types. An
Consider Kanzi, the human-raised bonobo air-conditioning system, for example, can
that has been central to both the life and involve a thermostat, a compressor, an evap-
research of the primatologist Sue Savage- oration coil, a fan, and so forth. Perhaps
Rumbaugh. Kanzi has been thoroughly we can say that the process of the air cool-
enculturated, and engages in sophisticated ing as it passes over the evaporation coils
w h y t h e mind is st1li, in t h e h e a d

is the process of conditioning the air, but One of Gibbs's arguments is based on a
surely the liquefaction of Freon and the dialogue he observed in a bar. The dialogue
electrical processes within the thermostat begins after John spills a beer:
and the opening and closing of the circuit
in the thermostat are not air-conditioning. John: I wonder if there is a towel behind
Surely nothing forces us to lump all of these the bar.
processes under a single descriptor, "air- Nicole (goes over to the bar and grabs a
conditioning." Another example is a per- towel): Here you go.
sonal computer, a computing system. Sup- John: Oh thanks! I wasn't actually ask-
pose, for the sake of argument, that we don't ing you to get a towel for me. I
limit the notion of computing to what the just was thinking aloud about whether
central processing unit (CPU) does. Sup- there might be a towel that I could
pose that we understand computing broadly get from the bartender. But thanks.
so as to cover many sorts of information (Gibbs, 2001, p. 109)
processing. Thus, we might count the pro-
Gibbs begins his analysis of this dialogue by
cess of reading a floppy disk, reading a
saying, "John intends his utterance with a
compact disc (CD), and turning the com-
particular meaning, but changes his mind
puter on as kinds of information process-
and accepts Nicole's interpretation of what
ing, hence as kinds of computing. Even on
he said" (ibid.). We think that Gibbs's treat-
this very broad understanding of computing,
ment of this case is flawed in many ways, so
it is still not the case that every process in
it will take a while to work through these
this computing system is a computing pro-
problems before we can ultimately relate it
cess. There is the production of heat by the
to the other coupling arguments. So, first
CPU, the circulation of air caused by the
off, we think that Gibbs simply misunder-
fan, the transmission of electrons in the com-
stands John's comment. John is not changing
puter's cathode-ray tube, and the discharge
his mind about anything. He is not adopt-
of the computer's internal battery. Think of
ing Nicole's interpretation of what he said;
a sound system. Not every component pro-
in fact, he is explicitly rejecting it. John
duces sounds. The speakers do, but lasers in
says, "I wasn't actually asking you to get a
CD players, amplifiers, volume controls, and
towel for me," which is an explicit rejec-
tone controls do not. Again, not every com-
tion of what he thinks Nicole thinks (or
ponent of an X system does X. So, an appeal
might think) he intends. When he says, "But
to the notion of a system does not help the
thanks," he means that, even though he did
transcranialist.
not intend for Nicole to get him a towel, he
is thankful that she did it anyway. It looks as
though John's initial intention remains con-
2.3. Gibbs's Interpersonal Coupling stant throughout the whole episode.
Argument
Not to rest our argument too much on
Gibbs (2001) claims that "intentions are, in what Gibbs might take to be our idiosyn-
many cases, emergent products of inter- cratic understanding of the foregoing dia-
actions between individuals, and between logue, we might try to develop an imag-
individuals and the environment, and that inary scenario in which John does change
therefore they exist in a distributed manner his initial intention. How would the sce-
across individuals" (p. 106). Clearly, Gibbs is nario have to be different for John to have
a transcranialist about at least some inten- really changed his original intention? Let's
tions and, as we have seen, is prone to com- say that at to he had the intention merely
mit the simple coupling-constitution fallacy. to wonder out loud and so he proceeded
In addition, however, he advances some to utter, "I wonder if there is a towel behind
more complicated versions of the fallacy. the bar." Nicole then goes and gets the towel
We will consider just one. and says, "Here you go." Now at t, let John
Eg FRED ADAMS AND KENNETH AIZAWA

s a y . "Thanks. I'm glad you discerned what mental flaw in coupling arguments; namely,
I intended." Now at least Nicole's actions the fact that events at one time causally
have provoked a kind of conflict between influence cognitive events at another time
the intention John had at to and the inten- does not make it the case that those first
tion he implies (at t,) he had at This, events constitute part of a single cognitive
however, is still not an instance of the process that includes the cognitive events.
actions at t, changing John's intentions at More concretely, the fact that Nicole's and
to. Indeed, the mechanics of this exchange John's actions made some cognitive differ-
are that of a comic scene with Inspec- ence to John's intention at to is not enough to
tor Clouseau. Clouseau clearly intends one establish that Nicole's and John's actions are
thing, has something unexpected arise, but part of the same cognitive process or state as
then tries to play off the surprise as what John's intention at to.
he intended all along. What reason is there Further evidence that Gibbs is guilty of
to think that John changed the intention he confusing constitution relations and causal
had at to rather than that he changed his relations in the analysis of this case is sup-
interpretation of the intention he had at to? ported by his claims following another
It could be that John suffers from a failure sample dialogue. He notes that "speakers'
of memory or self-deception. It must surely intentions also clearly shift as a result of con-
be admitted that self-deception or failures versation and may at times not be viewed as
of memory can lead to distorted interpre- solely a product of an individual speaker's
tations or assessments of the intentions one mind" (Gibbs, 2001, p. 111). It is surely com-
had in the past. So, why not in these types mon ground that intentions change over the
of cases? Gibbs provides no reason to pre- course of a conversation. I ask you to pass
fer the view that John changed his inten- the salt. That, against a backdrop of other
tions at to to the view that John merely factors, might cause you to form the inten-
changed his assessment of his intentions at tion to pass the salt. And, of course, in such a
to. Worse, Gibbs appears to be insensitive to case, there is a perfectly good sense in which
this distinction. Nowhere is this more evi- your intention is not solely a product of your
dent than when he writes: "The fact that mind; namely, your intention is not caused
John altered what he believed to be his origi- exclusively by events within your own mind.
nal intention shows that Nicole's interpreta- Yet such an admission does nothing to chal-
tion of his intention actually shaped John's lenge the intracranialist position. For all that
own conception of what that intention may has been conceded, the intracranialist can
be" (Gibbs, 2001, p. 110, emphasis added). still maintain that your intention to pass the
What Gibbs says here can be conceded by salt is entirely constituted by events and pro-
the intracranialist. What Gibbs is hoping for, cesses within your cranium. So, even under
but has provided no argument for, is much quite generous concessions, Gibbs has not
stronger; namely, that John's intentions at to produced an argument for transcranialism.
were changed. Having surveyed a wide range of ways
But suppose we set aside the infelicity of committing the coupling-constitution fal-
of Gibbs's original example wherein John lacy, it should be clear how pervasive it
says, "I wasn't actually asking you to get a is. What would help transcranialists at this
towel for me." Further suppose that at t, point is a plausible theory that demarcates
John really is able to do something to alter the cognitive from the noncognitive. Yet, as
the intention he had at to- In particular, let we will now argue, they do not have one.
us suppose that there are no problems with
backward causation, that there is nothing
wrong with events at t, causally influenc- 3. The Mark of the Cognitive
ing temporally prior events at to- (We think
we are being especially generous here.) Still, When we claim that transcranialists have
Gibbs must come to grips with the funda- paid inadequate attention to the problem of
WHY THE MIND IS STILL IN THE HEAD

the mark of the cognitive, we do not mean Because we have already twice defended our
to imply that they have entirely ignored original articulation of this view, which is in
the issue. For example, Clark and Chalmers any case a common view in cognitive sci-
(1998) consider the idea that consciousness ence, we will not here belabor our positive
is the mark of the cognitive: account. 1 '
Inattention to the mark of the cognitive
Some find this sort of externalism unpalat- figures into the debate over intracranialism
able. One reason may be that many iden- and transcranialism as follows. If one views
tify the cognitive with the conscious, and it
the world simply in terms of causal pro-
seems far from plausible that consciousness
cesses, then one will likely miss the differ-
extends outside the head in these cases.
But not every cognitive process, at least on ence between what goes on inside the brain
standard usage, is a conscious process. It is and what goes on outside. After all, causal
widely accepted that all sorts of processes processes are transcranial. Alternatively, if
beyond the borders of consciousness play a one is only interested in a science of the arti-
crucial role in cognitive processing: in the ficial, rather than cognitive science, one is
retrieval of memories, linguistic processes, likely to be drawn to transcranialism. Alter-
and skill acquisition, for example. So, the natively, if one is only interested in finding
mere fact that external processes are exter- systems, or cognitive systems, one is liable
nal where consciousness is internal is no to miss the point at which cognitive pro-
reason to deny that those processes are cog-
cesses leave off and noncognitive processes
nitive. (Clark & Chalmers, 1998, p. 10)
begin. Consider, now, some of the others
Clark and Chalmers clearly deserve credit more subtle ways in which theories of the
for broaching the issue. Further, they mark of the cognitive abet transcranialism.
deserve credit for providing reasonable argu-
ments against this theory of the cognitive.
3.1. Cognition as Information Processing
Yet their paper comes up short in its fail-
ure to specify what they believe does dis- Clark (in Wilson & Clark, this volume) and
tinguish the cognitive from the noncogni- Rowlands (1999) suggest that cognition is
tive. Further, Clark and Chalmers, like all information processing. 24 We have consid-
the other transcranialists we have read, do erable sympathy for this as a part of a theory
not address any version of the rules-and- of the cognitive, but we think that cogni-
representations conception of cognition 1 tive processing is only a narrow subspecies of
arguably the received view of the nature information processing. Not all information
of cognition. Adams and Aizawa (2001) processing is cognitive processing. Compact
drew attention to this conception by ven- disc players, D V D players, FM radios, digital
turing two hypotheses concerning how the computers, cell phones, and so forth, are all
cognitive would turn out to be different information processors, but none of them is
from the noncognitive. T h e first hypothesis a cognitive processor. Any theory of the cog-
was that cognitive processing involves non- nitive that does not notice the difference is
derived content, that is, that cognitive states clearly missing something relevant to cogni-
have the content they do in virtue of the tive psychology. This difference is presum-
satisfaction of certain naturalistic conditions ably part of the difference between a sci-
that do not depend on the existence of other entifically interesting cognitive psychology
content-bearing, representational, or inten- and a scientifically uninteresting consumer
tional states. The second was that cognitive electronics.
processes are to be distinguished by certain
sorts of principles that are found to operate
'n the brain but not elsewhere. As examples, 3.2. The Cognitive as the Computational
we noted the existence of certain laws of Similar in spirit to the idea that cognition
memory formation and retention and certain is information processing simpliciter, there
psychophysical laws, such as Weber's law. is the idea that cognition is computation
ss FRED ADAMS AND KENNETH AIZAWA

ampliciter This appears to be how Edwin ful is more inclusive. As Haugeland (1998)
Hutchins motivates the view that, in the tells it:
navigation of a ship by a team of sailors,
cognition is extended throughout the team A hammer, for instance, is significant
in a kind of supermind over and above the beyond itself in terms of what it's for: driv-
minds of the individual sailors: ing nails into wood, by being wielded in a
certain way, in order to build something,
Hating taken ship navigation as it is per- and so on. The nails, the wood, the proj-
formed by a team on the bridge of a ship as ect, and the carpenter him or herself, are
the unit of cognitive analysis, I will attempt likewise caught up in this "web of signifi-
to apply the principal metaphor of cognitive cance", in their respective ways. These are
science - cognition as computation - to the the meaningful objects that are the world
operation 6f this system. In so doing I do itself; and none of them is a representation.
not make any special commitments to the (P- 233)
nature of the computations that are going
on inside individuals except to say that So, we may now ask, "What kind of signifi-
whatever happens there is part of a larger cance constitutes the cognitive?"26 Were we
computational system. But 1 do believe that to review Haugeland's arguments in favor
the computation observed in the activity of using the broader notion of the mean-
of the larger system can be described in ingful in cognitive science, we would find
the way cognition has traditionally been that they are simply the system versions of
described - that is, as computation real- the coupling argument, an argument form
ized through the creation, transformation,
we have found inconclusive. Note as well,
and propagation of representational states.
however, that even if there were a science
(Hutchins, 1995, p. 49)
of the meaningful, this would not necessar-
If cognition is just any sort of computation, ily constitute a cognitive psychology. Surely,
then by this relatively broad theory of the the vast differences between hammers and
mark of the cognitive, then it should not be saws, on the one hand, and cognition, on the
so surprising that cognition is found in hith- other, are part of what interests cognitive
erto unsuspected places, such as spanning psychologists.27 Surely a cognitive psychol-
the boundary of brains, bodies, and environ- ogy that ignores such differences is ignoring
ment of a group of sailors. But, then again, something important.
by this standard, we would have cognition
in personal computers. As we understand
3.4. Operationalizing the Cognitive
it, the orthodox computational theory of
the mind maintains not that any compu- Another way that transcranialists attempt to
tation is a kind of cognition, but that only provide a mark of the cognitive is by a tacit
some specific forms of computation (yet to operationalism. They may well reject this
be discovered and characterized) constitute characterization of their project, but one can
cognition.1* see it in their tacit assumption that whatever
process or mechanism accomplishes a given
task must be a cognitive process or mech-
3.3. The Cognitive as the Meaningful
anism. In the closing pages of his paper on
Haugeland (1998) urges another theory of embodied and embedded cognition, Hauge-
the cognitive, or of human intelligence. land invites us to consider the ability to go
Haugeland contrasts the representational to San Jose. He observes that there are many
and the meaningful. Representations are ways one might accomplish this task, such
symbolic markers that denote things; they as retaining a horse that is trained to go to
are the data structures of computational the- San Jose or picking a road that leads to San
ories of mind. The meaningful, however, is a Jose. And, of course, he is right that there are
broader kind. Representations have one kind many ways of getting to San Jose. Further,
of meaning or significance, but the meaning- he is right that not all of these ways involve
WHY THE MIND IS STILL IN THE HEAD
89

representation of the sort postulated in the definition of cognition. He proposes that


familiar rules-and-representations kind of cognitive tasks involve the acquisition and
cognitive science. But it also appears that employment of information, information
not all of the ways to get to San Jose involve in the sense of a nomological dependence
cognitive processing. A train on rails has the between event types. Further, he suggests
ability to go to San Jose from a point out of that a cognitive process is one that is essen-
sight. A cloud can blow to San Jose from tial to the accomplishment of some cog-
a point out of sight. An intercontinental nitive task and that involves operations on
ballistic missile has the ability to go to San information-bearing structures.28 As we see
Jose from a point out of sight. These abilities things, this is a species of operationalism and
require no intelligence, no cognition. There is fundamentally misguided.
are lots of combinations of cognitive abilities Here is a task: make sure that when the
that one might deploy to get to San Jose, but electric garage-door opener lowers the door,
not every way of getting to San Jose involves the door does not close on anyone. This
cognition. Once one abandons the idea that task apparently requires that the garage-
the ability to move to a point out of sight is a door opener have some more or less reliable
criterion for the cognitive, these possibilities mechanism for detecting the presence of a
should be clear. person beneath the door. In other words,
In truth, a more famous case of tacitly the opener must acquire and use informa-
operationalizing the cognitive is in Rodney tion regarding the presence or absence of
Brooks's discussion of his robot Herbert. a person beneath the closing door. So, by
Brooks (1997) reports that Herbert has the Rowlands's account, this task is a cognitive
task of finding soda cans in offices at MIT, task. The most common way electric garage-
picking them up, and bringing them back door openers gather this information these
to a start point. Brooks tacitly presupposes days is by passing a light beam from a source
that this task requires intelligence, that any on one side of the entrance of the garage to
device that can accomplish this task must be a detector on the other side. If some object,
intelligent. So, if one adds to this the view such as a person, breaks the beam, the door
that Herbert lacks representations of the sort opener will raise the door. The system is not
postulated by rules-and-representations the- perfectly reliable, however. A person posi-
ories of cognition, one can infer that intel- tioned in just the right way beneath the door
ligence without representation is possible. need not break the beam. It is also pos-
Yet suppose we challenge the idea that any sible to have other sorts of objects break
device that can collect soda cans in the the beam, resulting in false-positives for the
offices at MIT must be intelligent or must presence of a person. Presumably, the light
be a cognitive agent. In that case, a differ- source, detector, and accompanying wiring
ent analysis becomes available. That is, one are essential to the accomplishment of the
is free to suppose that, although the soda- task and use information about the pres-
can collection task can be accomplished in ence of objects in the light path. Thus, by
the way humans do it, namely, by deploy- Rowlands's account, the light source, detec-
ing cognitive processes, other devices can tor, and its accompanying wiring constitute
also accomplish the task through chains of a cognitive processor.
simple noncognitive mechanisms. To decide Contrast the foregoing method of ensur-
between these two analyses of what Herbert ing that the door does not close on any-
is doing, we need a substantive theory of one with a more old-fashioned way. Not
what constitutes the cognitive. so many years ago, whenever a garage door
The most extensive example of trans- was to be closed, a person would position
cranialists operationalizing the cognitive is him- or herself so as to have a clear view
found in Rowlands (1999). When he begins of the space where the door will close,
his discussion of perception, he claims that then start the garage-door opener when he
he is not presupposing any controversial or she could see that the path is clear.
FRED ADAMS AND KENNETH AIZAWA

Clearly there is some difference between sight of it during the course of an evolu-
the new way and the old way of operat- tionary argument for transcranialism. At the
ing an electric garage-door opener. A very least detailed level, Rowlands's evolution-
reasonable empirical hypothesis is that the ary argument might be viewed as having the
process by which the electric eye works to form of modus ponens:
detect objects beneath the door is different
from the process by which the human eye 1. Development of our cognitive capaci-
and visual system detects objects beneath ties has followed the most efficient evo-
the door. It also seems very reasonable to us lutionary path.
to suppose that figuring out what is going 2 If development of our cognitive capac-
on in the human eye and visual system is ities has followed the most efficient
part of what has interested cognitive scien- evolutionary path, then cognitive pro-
tists who have studied vision in recent years. cesses are an essentially hybrid combi-
It is this difference that makes the study of nation of internal and external processes
the human eye and visual system intellec- (cf. Rowlands, 1999, p. 25).
tually challenging, where the electric eye is 3. Therefore, cognitive processes are an
a boring piece of hardware you can buy at essentially hybrid combination of inter-
Sears. So, even if Rowlands were given the nal and external processes.
term cognitive to use as he pleases, there still
appears to be a natural kind of process, at
Matters would have been simpler had Row-
least reasonably construed as cognitive, that
lands just presented this argument and stood
is worthy of scientific investigation.
by it. At least this argument has the virtue
Now Rowlands will say that both the new of having a conclusion that is inconsistent
way and the old way of avoiding accidents with intracranialism. Unfortunately, vari-
with electric garage-door openers involves ous reasons move Rowlands to depart from
information processing, hence that both are this. In running the argument, Rowlands
cognitive. As we saw, however, the prob- wants to mark the conclusion as a defea-
lem with Rowlands's approach is that even sible inference. Thus, in his version of the
if we accept his conception of the cognitive consequent and the conclusion, we are told
as essentially information processing, there that we should expect our cognitive pro-
remains a scientific natural kind of process- cesses to be an essentially hybrid combina-
ing that appears to be worthy of scientific tion of internal and external processes. Yet
investigation in its own right, a scientific, the conclusion of this argument is logically
natural kind of processing that traditional consistent with intracranialism, and so tech-
intracranialist cognitive scientists have been nically irrelevant. So, we should probably
investigating. Perhaps the human brain is interpret what Rowlands writes to make its
an information processor in just the sense relevance clearer, namely, in the way pre-
in which a CD player, a DVD player, a sented previously. Second, in a desire not
television, a cash register, and an automo- to rely too heavily on empirical assumptions
bile gas gauge are information processors. about evolutionary history, Rowlands wants
But it is presumably the specific differ- to assert only something like the second
ences between the brain and these other premise. Yet premise 2 is logically consistent
devices that have engaged intracranialists.
with intracranialism, and so not particularly
What interests cognitive psychologists, in
germane to the debate. Third, it should be
part, are the specific ways in which the brain
noted that essentially all of Rowlands's dis-
processes information.
cussion in chapter 4 of his book is directed
toward the exposition and defense of some-
3.5. Rowlands's Evolutionary Argument thing like premise | where nothing at all is
said in defense of premise 2. Reading Row-
Although Rowlands has a theory of the lands as interested only in premise 2 is, in this
mark of the cognitive, he seems to lose regard, a distortion of the argumentation of
w h y t h e mind is st1li, in t h e h e a d 91

his book. We propose not to be a part of it that the process of extending the lower leg
and instead hold Rowlands to the preceding involves subprocesses of distinct kinds inter-
argument. nal to the leg. There is the stretching of the
So, what are we to m a k e of the foregoing proprioceptive cells in the tendon, the fir-
argument? Aside f r o m the fact that R o w - ing of the proprioceptive cells, the propa-
lands provides no evidence or argument for gation of the action potentials to the spinal
premise 2, we think this premise is clearly cord, the release of neurotransmitters in the
spinal cord, the firing of motor neurons
false.19 In general, an inference of this form
in the spinal cord, the propagation of the
is no good, because the second premise is
action potentials to the sundry muscles of
false:
the thigh, the release of neurotransmitters
1 Development of our capacities f o r X has at the neuromuscular junction, and the con-
followed the most efficient evolutionary tractions of the muscles, just to name a f e w .
path. N o n e of these processes extends into the
environment, despite their interaction with
2. If development of our capacities for X
the environment. Take the isomerization of
has followed the most efficient evolu-
rhodopsin in the retina on absorption of
tionary path, then processes for X are an
light. Presumably this chemical change has
essentially hybrid combination of inter-
been selected for, but there is no temptation
nal and external processes (cf. R o w -
to suppose that the chemical change extends
lands, 1999, p. 25).
into the environment. Consider dilation of
3. Therefore, processes f o r X are an essen-
the pupil in response to low light. T h e pro-
tially hybrid combination of internal and
cess of dilation is causally linked to environ-
external processes.
mental stimuli and the explanation of w h y a
pupil dilates on a given occasion may make
Consider human spermatogenesis. Even if some reference to the level of ambient light-
this were a capacity that had followed the ing, but, all the same, the process of dilation
most efficient evolutionary path, it is evi- takes place within the eye.
dently not a process that extends into the
external world. Consider the phosphory- Rowlands may well wish to say that these
lation of A D P to f o r m A T P . Even if the counterexamples merely clarify what he had
phylogenetic development of this capacity already conceded, namely, that the infer-
had followed the most efficient evolution- ence he is making is defeasible. His idea is
ary pathway, it is pretty clearly an intra- really that, if the development of a capacity
cellular process if anything is. Consider the has followed the most efficient evolutionary
transcription of D N A into R N A , meiosis, path, then this gives us some defeasible rea-
the phases of mitosis (prophase, metaphase, son to think that the process is a hybrid com-
anaphase, and telophase), the secretion of bination of internal and external processes.
bile, filtration of the blood in the kidneys, This, however, misses what should be the
and pumping of blood. A l l are intraorgan- moral of the counterexamples. T h e point is
ismal processes. W h a t does it matter h o w that there is no reason to link the property
efficiently they evolved? of being a product of natural selection with
Nor are counterexamples to the preced- the property of extending into the environ-
ing form of argument limited to processes ment. They appear to be entirely orthogonal
that are clearly internal to the body's func- concerns.
tions. Even processes that have presum- Here is another way to make the fore-
ably been selected for their role in aiding going point. Rowlands spends the bulk of
an organism in responding to its environ- chapter 4 of The Body in Mind making a
ment have their easily recognized inter- kind of plausibility argument for the view
nal subprocesses.' 0 Presumably the patel- that using tools makes for greater fitness
lar reflex was selected for to prevent injury than not using tools. We concede, just for
to the patellar tendon. Still, we recognize the sake of running another argument more
9* FRED ADAMS AND KENNETH AIZAWA

simply, that this is so. Our objection to Row- attention to ordinary language tends to
lands'* evolutionary argument is that, even efface these differences. We also think that
if organisms that use tools are more fit than the existence of these processes, rather than
organisms that do not, this has nothing to do mere prejudice or tradition, explains why
with how we discriminate among types of the orthodox position in cognitive science
processes and their subcomponents. Surely, is intracranial.'1 Finally, we think that these
the most reasonable thing to expect evolu- differences explain why even transcranialists
tionary theory to do is provide a theoretical maintain that cognition extends from brains
taxonomy of processes based on evolution- into the extraorganismal world rather than
ary theory, not a theoretical taxonomy of from the extraorganismal world into brains.
processes based on cognitive theory. Evolu-
tionary theory parses the world up into units
that are significant in terms of evolution, Notes
not in terms of cognition. So, one should
expect that appeals to evolutionary theory 1 Ideas in this chapter are precursors to those
are entirely orthogonal to the intracranial- we have developed in more detail in our
transcranial debate. Here again, we think recent book (Adams & Aizawa, 2008).
that, were consideration of the mark of the 2 Although there is a difference between the
intracranial and the intraorganismal, it is not a
cognitive brought to die fore, this sort of
difference we propose to trouble about here.
misdirected argument might be avoided.
3 Among philosophers we count van Gelder
(199;); Dennett (1996); Clark and Chalmers
(1998); Haugeland (1998); perhaps Hurley
4. Conclusion
(1998); Rowlands (1999, 2003); Noe (2004);
and Sutton (200;). Among psychologists we
In this chapter we have drawn attention count Donald (1991); O'Regan (1992); The-
to what appear to us to be the two prin- len and Smith (1994); Hutchins (1995); and
cipal weaknesses in current developments Gibbs (2001). An interesting early advocate
of transcranialism. They are that trans- of extended cognition is the anthropologist
cranialism is regularly backed by some form Bateson (1972). Following this rising tide in
of coupling-constitution fallacy and that it support of extended cognition are voices of
does not have an adequate account of the resistance. These include Adams and Aizawa
difference between the cognitive and the (2001, in press); Wilson (2002); Susi, Lind-
noncognitive. A more nagging worry, how- blom, and Ziemke (2003); Rupert (2004);
Sterelny (2004); Block (2005); Rupert (in
ever, is the motivation for transcranialism.
press, this volume); and Aizawa (2007).
What reason is there to make this proposed
Actually, some extracranialists sometimes
conceptual shift? Why parse up causal pro-
wish to maintain that cognitive processes
cesses in the transcranialist way rather than
are essentially extended into the external
in the intracranialist way? We have tried world. Insofar as we are successful in argu-
to motivate the intracranialist approach by ing that cognitive processes are typically not
drawing attention to the existence of distinc- extended, it will follow that they are not
tive causal processes that take place intra- essentially extended. We do not, however,
cranially. For example, the human visual sys- maintain that cognitive processes are essen-
tem appears to have information-processing tially internal.
channels for such things as color, motion, 4 Haugeland (1998), Clark and Chalmers
and form, where digital camcorders do not. (1998), and Clark (in press), for example, are
Further, human memory appears to show fairly explicit about the kinds of couplings
primacy and recency effects unlike those they have in mind.
that occur in computer hard drives or pen 5 Cf. Hurley (1998, pp. 2-4); Clark (2005, p. 1);
and paper. We think that greater attention and Clark (in press).
6 Cf., e.g., McClamrock (1995, pp. 3-4); Hauge-
to cognitive psychology textbooks helps to
land (1998, pp. 209-210); Rowlands (1999,
highlight these differences, where greater pp. 106-113); and Gibbs (2001, pp. 117-118).
WHY THF. MIND IS STILL IN THE HEAD 93

7 In fact, contemporary intracranialist cogni- constitution and can be viewed as a defense


tive science appears to do this already. The of the view that cognition is constituted, in
interaction between organism and environ- part, by one's body. In his chapter i, No?
ment is at the heart of the lively empiricist- defends the view that perceptual abilities are
nativist debates. Insofar as contemporary constituted, in part, by sensorimotor skills.
ethology is intracranialist, it too studies Given the assumption that the exercise of
organism-environment interactions, namely, perceptual abilities are cognitive processes
the interactions of organisms with their nat- and that sensorimotor skills are constituted
ural environments. And where would the in part by muscles and peripheral nerves, one
study of sensation and perception be if it did has the view that cognitive processing is con-
not study the interaction between organism stituted, in part, by bodily processes, in this
and environment? chapter, Noe is pretty explicit in favoring
8 In correspondence, Dan Dennett indicated the constitutive claim over the causal claim.
that what he was concerned to point out is Aizawa (2007) provides a detailed critique of
that our concept of cognition does not require this case for extended cognition.
that it be found in the brain. 17 Actually, the example first appears in the
9 Cf., e.g., Clark and Chalmers (1998, p. 10) and work of Clark (1997), but its use to support
Rowlands (1999, pp. 115-116). Rowlands (1999, extracranialism is less marked there.
pp. 115-116) tries to put the burden of avoiding 18 This jointly responsible idea figures more
a terminological dispute on the intracranial- prominently in the version presented in
ist. Susi, Lindblom, and Ziemke (2003) also Clark (1997). Haugeland (1998) runs the same
raise this concern. "jointly responsible" line about navigating to
10 Clark (in press) sometimes appears not to San Jose. By driving the interstate, one relies
appreciate this. on the structure of the interstate and on one's
11 One might make the case that psychology cognitive abilities in dealing with roads. Thus,
should be understood in terms of mecha- the road and the brain are between them
nisms, rather than ceteris paribus laws, some- responsible for successfully navigating to San
thing along the lines suggested by Machamer, Jose and they constitute a single causal pro-
Darden, and Craver (2000). Perhaps this is cess. Still, that does not make the interactions
so, but we do not see that debate between between the road and the brain a single cog-
intracranialists and transcranialists depends nitive process. Establishing the latter stronger
on this. In addition, one might make the case claim is what the extracranialist needs.
that psychological explanations should be 19 This jointly responsible idea figures more
understood in terms of functional analysis (cf. prominently in the version presented in
Cummins, 1983). Perhaps so, in which case Clark (1997). Haugeland (1998) runs the same
we might reformulate our approach within jointly responsible line about navigating to
this framework. For the sake of simplicity of San Jose. By driving the interstate, one relies
exposition, however, we forbear here. on the structure of the interstate and on one's
12 Here we find ourselves at odds with Hauge- cognitive abilities in dealing with roads. Thus,
land (1998); Rowlands (1999, 2003); Clark and the road and the brain are between them
Chalmers (1998); and Clark (2005), who sug- responsible for successfully navigating to San
gest that it is mere prejudice that sustains the Jose and they constitute a single causal pro-
orthodox intracranialist position in cognitive cess. Still, that does not make the interactions
science. between the road and the brain a single cog-
13 This is a line of criticism we broached in nitive process. Establishing the latter stronger
Adams and Aizawa (2001). The same kind of claim is what the extracranialist needs.
argument has recently been applied by Block 20 Cf. Haugeland (1998): "If. . . there is a con-
(2005) in a critique of Noe's (2004) theory stant close coupling between the ant and the
of enactive perception. See also Rupert (in details of the beach surface, and if this cou-
press). pling is crucial in determining the actual path,
14 For other examples, see Adams and Aizawa then, for purposes of understanding the path,
(2001, in press). the ant and beach must be regarded more as
15 Who since about Leibniz has doubted this? an integrated unit than as a pair of distinct
16 Chapter 1 of Noe (2004) is much more explicit components. This is the simplest archetype of
about the distinction between causation and what I mean by intimacy" (p. 217). Substitute
FRED ADAMS AND KENNETH AIZAWA

bowtingbal] for out and alley for beach and you 30 Rowlands (1999) adds another small wrinkle
are well on your way to committing Hauge- to his argument:
land to something rather wild.
In fact, one can pick up a reference to a sys- If we have adopted the most efficient
tem in the passage from Clark (2001), cited strategy for accomplishing tasks, then the
previously. Much of Haugeland (1998) can cognitive mechanisms we have evolved
be viewed as an elaborate case of the sys- should be designed to function in con-
tem version of the coupling-constitution fal- junction with environmental structures.
lacy: "The strategy will be to bring some well- Then, the cognitive processes realized
known principles of systems analysis to bear by these mechanisms would have to be
on the mind-body-world 'system' in a way understood as straddling both internal
that refbcuses questions of division and unity" processes and those external processes
(pp. 108-209). whereby the organism interacts with these
¿2 Doesn't the cyborg example play into the environmental structures, [p. 25)
intracranialist's hand? After all, cyborgs are The consequent in the second sentence moti-
hybrids of organism and artifact rather than vates the present paragraph. Note as well that
simply organisms. So, shouldn't humans with it is the move from the second sentence to the
tools be hybrids of cognizers and artifacts third in this passage that constitutes for us the
rather than simply cognizers?
non sequitur.
23 Aizawa and Adams (200;) and Adams and 31 Rupert (2004) provides a nice elaboration
Aizawa (in press). of this kind of consideration, which we
24 Clark (in press); Wilson and Clark (this vol- broached in Adams and Aizawa (2001).
ume); and Rowlands (1999, pp. 26, 115, 119,
122).
25 Incidently, if one hypothesized that cognitive
processing is just the evolution of a dynam- References
ical system, then it will of course turn out
that cognitive processing extends into the Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2001). The bounds of
body and environment. Of course, on such cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 14, 43-64.
a lax theory of the mark of the cognitive, Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of
there will be cognition in Watt governors, cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.
the pendulums in grandfather clocks, and Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (in press). Defending
so on. the bounds of cognition. In R. Menary (Ed.),
26 Haugeland (1998, p. 233) puts the mat- The extended mind. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.
ter this way: "The real question is: Which Aizawa, K. (2007). Understanding the embodi-
sense matters in the context of understand- ment of perception. Journal of Philosophy, 104,
ing human intelligence?" This way of for- 5p|
mulating the issue risks inserting controversy Aizawa, K., & Adams, F. (2005). Defending non-
over exactly what constitutes "understanding derived content. Philosophical Psychology, 18,
human intelligence." We wish to avoid this 661-669.
tangential issue here. Bateson, G. (1972). Steps to an ecology of mind.
27 Adams and Aizawa (2001) provide reason to New York: Ballantine Books.
be skeptical of the possibility of a science of Block, N. (2005). Review of Alva Noe's Action in
the artificial. perception. Journal of Philosophy, 102, 259-272.
28 This seems to be Rowlands's "official" the- Brooks, R. (1997). Intelligence without represen-
ory of the mark of the cognitive, where tation. In J. Haugeland (Ed.), Mind design 11
the idea that cognition is simply informa- (pp. 121-145). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
tion processing is merely a view suggested Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body,
by stylistic variations in Rowlands's writing. and world together again. Cambridge, MA:
Cf., e.g., Rowlands (1999, pp. 102-103, "6, MIT Press.
>37) Clark, A. (2001). Reasons, robots, and the
29 Clearly the truth value of premise 2 is a pri- extended mind. Mind & Language, 16,121-145-
mary concern whether Rowlands wants to Clark, A. (2002). Towards a science of the bio-
assert just premise 2 or run the whole modus technological mind. International Journal of
ponens sketched previously. Cognition and Technology, 1, 21-33.
WHY THF. MIND IS STILL IN THF. HEAD 95

Clark, A. (2003). Natural-bom cyborgs. Oxford: memory. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 46,
Oxford University Press. 461-488.
Clark, A. (2005). Intrinsic content, active memory Rowlands, M. (1999). The body in mind. Cam-
and the extended mind. Analysis, 65,1-11. bridge: Cambridge University Press.
Clark, A. (in press). Memento's revenge: The Rowlands, M. (2003). Extemalism: Putting mind
extended mind, extended. In R. Menary (Ed.), and world back together again. Montreal:
The extended mind. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate. McGill-Queen's University Press.
Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended Rupert, R. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis
mind. Analysis, 58, 7-19. of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy,
Cummins, R. (1983). The nature of psychological 101, 389-428.
explanation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Rupert, R. (in press). Representation in extended
Dennett, D. C. (1996). Kinds of minds. New York: cognitive systems: Does the scaffolding of lan-
Basic Books. guage extend the mind? In R. Menary (Ed.),
Dennett, D. C. (2000). Making tools for think- The extended mind. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.
ing. In D. Sperber (Ed.), Metarepresenta- Schlatter, M., & Aizawa, K. (2008). Walter Pitts
tions: A multidisciplinary perspective (pp. 17- and "A logical calculus." Synthese, 162, 232-
29). Oxford: Oxford University Press. 250.
Donald, M. (1991). Origins of the modern mind. Sterelny, K. (2004). Extemalism, epistemic arti-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. facts, and the extended mind (pp. 239-254).
Gibbs, R. J. (2001). Intentions as emergent prod- In R. Schantz (Ed.), The externalist challenge.
ucts of social interactions. In B. F. Malle, L. J. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.
Moses, & D. A. Baldwin (Eds.), Intentions and Susi, T., Lindblom, J., & Ziemke, T. (2003).
intentionality (pp. 105-122). Cambridge, MA: Beyond the bounds of cognition. In K. Forbus,
MIT Press. D. Centner, 8c T. Regier (Eds.), Proceeding?
Haugeland, J. (1998). Mind embodied and of the 25th Annual Conference of the Cognitive
embedded. In J. Haugeland (Ed.), Having Science Society (pp. 1305-1310). Mahwah, NJ:
thought (pp. 207-237). Cambridge, MA: Har- Lawrence Erlbaum.
vard University Press. Sutton, J. (2005). Memory and the extended
Hurley, S. L. (1998). Vehicles, contents, concep- mind: Embodiment, cognition, and culture.
tual structure, and externalism. Analysis, 58, Cognitive Processing, 6(4), 223-226.
1-6. Thelen, E., & Smith, L. (1994). A dynamical sys-
Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cam- tems approach to the development of cognition
bridge, MA: MIT Press. and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Machamer, P., Darden, L., 81 Craver, C. (2000). van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be,
Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Sci- if not computation? Journal of Philosophy, 91,
ence, 67,1-25. 345-381-
McClamrock, R. (1995). Existential cognition. Wilson, M. (2002). Six views of embodied cogni-
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. tion. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 9, 625-
Noe, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, 636.
MA: MIT Press. Wilson, R. (2004). Boundaries of the mind: The
O'Regan, J. K. (1992). Solving the "real" mysteries individual in the fragile sciences. Cambridge:
of visual perception: The world as an outside Cambridge University Press.
CHAPTER 6

Innateness and the Situated Mind

Robert Rupert

Many advocates of situated approaches to also argue for the nonnativist interpreta-
the study of cognition (e.g., Griffiths & tion of certain cognitive phenomena; never-
Stotz, 2000; Thelen & Smith, 1994) explicitly theless, these antinativist recommendations
take exception to cognitive science's pro- come heavily hedged - in some cases, at the
nounced nativist turn. 1 Other proponents expense of a robust reading of the situated
of situated models seek to mitigate strong program or one of its subdivisions.
nativist claims by, for example, finding ways
to acknowledge innate contributions to cog-
nitive processing while at the same time 1. Extended Cognition and Nativism
downplaying those contributions (Wilson,
2004, chap. 3). Still others leave implicit Consider first the view that cognitive pro-
their apparent opposition to nativism: they cesses extend beyond the boundary of the
emphasize the environment's contribution organism. The intimacy of the human organ-
to cognition so strongly as to suggest anti- ism's interaction with its environment dur-
nativist views but do not take up the issue ing cognitive processing suggests that those
explicitly (Clark, 1997; Varela, Thompson, & cognitive processes literally comprise ele-
Rosch, 1991), 2 Thus, situated theorists have ments of the environment beyond the
reached something approximating an anti- boundary of the human organism (Clark &
nativist consensus. In this chapter, I argue Chalmers, 1998). I shall refer to this view as
that they should not embrace the anti- the "hypothesis of extended cognition," or
nativist view so readily. To this end, I divide HEC. As I understand it, H E C entails that
the situated approach into two species, the human mind is extended. Accordingly,
extended and embedded views of cognition, the subject matter of H E C (i.e., the kind
arguing that each version of the situated of cognition at issue) had better be the sort
view admits of a plausible nativist interpre- that bears on the location of the mind. This
tation with respect to at least some impor- seems fair enough. The explananda of cog-
tant cognitive phenomena. In contrast, I nitive science are various mental capacities

96
INNATENESS AND THE SITUATED MIND
97
broadly pertaining to belief formation, such extended cognitive systems, it would seem
as the capacities to reason, perceive, remem- that not even the entire set of biological
ber, construct theories, and use language. resources internal to the organism can spec-
Thus, whatever model of cognition we ulti- ify what will become part of the resultant
mately adopt will be a model of the mind's extended cognitive system.
activities or capacities; and if the activities This antinativist argument from HEC
of a mind take place at a particular spa- seems quite powerful. What, in contrast,
tiotemporal location, that mind is at least might motivate a nativist reading of HEC?
partly at that location. 5 On this view, a Consider two widely discussed measures of a
given mind has a location in space-time and, trait's or a capacity's innate status: canaliza-
according to HEC, this location includes tion (Ariew, 1999) and generative entrench-
points outside the skin bag, as Andy Clark ment (Wimsatt, 1999). The canalization-
(2003) has colorfully dubbed the boundary based approach to nativism holds that a trait
of the human organism. Thus we arrive is innate to the extent that it resists pertur-
at the division mentioned previously. A bation across changes in the environment.
view is extended if it holds that, in some As an account of innateness, this allows a
cases, a system composed of a human organ- trait to be more or less innate, depending on
ism together with material (possibly includ- the breadth of environments in which the
ing other organisms) existing beyond that trait appears.
organism's boundaries instantiates cognitive Now consider some systems typically
properties relevant to the location of a mind; claimed to involve extended cognition: a
views that merely emphasize the human human together with a map (Hutchins,
organism's heavy dependence on, and fre- 1995); a human together with a pencil and
quent interaction with, the environment paper on which she performs mathemat-
during cognitive processing are embedded ical calculations (Clark, 1997); a human
views, discussion of which is deferred to sub- together with auditory patterns of spoken
sequent sections. language (Clark, 1997; Rowlands, 1999); a
If extended systems are the proper human together with the visible objects
objects of study in cognitive science, anti- in his immediate environment (O'Regan,
nativism seems to follow, particularly if one 1992); and a human together with gross
accepts the common notion that a trait is physical structures in her environment, for
innate if and only if it is specified by the instance, a human and a roadway that he is
genome (Block, 1981, pp. 280-281; Elman et following (Haugeland, 1995).
al., 1996, p. 22). The advocate of extended At least some traits of such systems ex-
cognition urges us to focus on the traits hibit a high degree of canalization. Take, for
of extended systems, and it is difficult to example, a human using external symbols -
see how genes could encode such traits, for say, self-directed speech 1 to guide herself
genes would seem to affect directly only through a complicated task (Clark, 1997,
the organism itself. Extended theorists typ- 1998). Humans typically live in groups and
ically hold that cognitive systems include use language, and thus the typical human
such external components as hard drives; subject is likely to engage in some kind of
notebooks; text messages; and, in the case self-directed symbol use across a wide range
of vision, whatever the subject happens to of environments. Furthermore, even in the
be visually engaged with. How, one might absence of a clear channel of learning from
wonder, could genes specify anything about conspecifics, humans tend to create linguis-
such external resources? These extended tic or quasi-linguistic symbol systems
elements are disconnected from the organic (Bloom, 2000, chap. 10; Goldin-Meadow &
milieu of the genome and thus beyond Zheng, 1998). To the extent that subjects
the genome's direct causal or informational developing in abnormal environments use
purview. Given the great variability in the partly externalized, self-devised systems to
external resources alleged to become part of guide their own thought and behavior, the
Si8 ROBERT RUPERT

self-directed use of a symbolic system passes those underlying feats of engineering and
the deprivation test for canalization (Anew, commerce (cf. Wimsatt's [1999, p. 143] dis-
1999): deprived of a species-typical environ- cussion of generative entrenchment and cul-
ment, the trait emerges nonetheless. The tural evolution).
use of the environment as visual memory is, The antinativist advocate of H E C might
perhaps, even more broadly canalized; this respond directly, attempting to show that
trait appears in all but the most extreme when properly applied, considerations of
environments, such as those involving phys- canalization and generative entrenchment
ical damage to the visual system or restric- do not support a nativist reading of HEC's
tion to dark environments. Once we have favored examples. It is, however, difficult
placed extended cognitive systems on par to execute this strategy without relegat-
with organismic systems, the canalization ing external resources to second-class sta-
theory of innateness delivers a nativist vision tus, which crosses purposes with HEC; for
of many of the former systems' traits.4 the most promising antinativist response
Move now to William Wimsatt's (1999) invokes asymmetries in the contribution of
theory of generative entrenchment5 Ac- the organism to the apparent canalization
cording to this view, a cognitive capac- and generative entrenchment. It is not a trait
ity or trait is innate to the extent that its of the extended system that is, for exam-
appearance is a prerequisite for the appear- ple, canalized, so much as the ability of
ance of traits emerging later in develop- the human organism to enter into certain
ment. Some important and prima facie relations with external resources (cf. Clark,
cognitive characteristics of extended sys- 2003); the appearance of alleged extended
tems seem to satisfy the criterion of gen- systems depends on the latter ability. Fur-
erative entrenchment. Consider, for exam- thermore, this dependence is asymmetric:
ple, the human organism's spoken-out, rote the intentions, desires, and purposes of
learning of times tables. This is a prereq- the organism provide impetus missing from
uisite for the acquisition of many later- external resources (I discuss this point in
emerging traits of the extended cognitive more detail herein). This asymmetry implies
system. Typically, when learning the times that the organismic portions of extended
tables, subjects intentionally create exter- systems are deeply privileged, to an extent
nal sound (or print) structures to facili- that should unsettle the advocate of H E C
tate learning. For many subjects, either the (cf. Rupert, 2004). The antinativist H E C the-
continued vocalization of basic facts about orist might do better, then, to advocate a
multiplication or the internal representa- distinct biological perspective on innateness.
tion of such verbalization proves invalu- Of most promise would seem to be devel-
able in the solving of more complex prob-
opmental systems theory, or DST, which
lems (compare the intentionally created,
appears not only to preserve HEC's anti-
linguistic means of external control dis-
nativist credentials but also to support
cussed by Clark, 1997, pp. 195-196, 1998,
directly the HEC-style individuation of cog-
pp. 173, 181). At the very least, one would
nitive systems.
think that, for any given subject, there must
have been a time when the extended trait Developmental systems theory is often
appeared; it is difficult to learn the times seen as an antidote to twentieth-century
tables without verbalizing them (or writ- biology's overemphasis on the gene. For
ing them out - another extended process). many years, textbook presentations charac-
The ability to solve problems involving the terized genes as the codes for and the deter-
multiplication of large numbers depends minants of phenotypic traits of living things;
on the memorization of the times tables, these encodings were selected for because
and the ability to solve problems involv- they determined the presence of phenotypic
ing the multiplication of large numbers traits that confer reproductive advantage on
grounds many further abilities, for example, their bearers. In contrast, the advocates of
DST point to the wide range of contextual
INNATENESS AND THE SITUATED MIND

factors affecting gene expression and, more innateness presuppose an important distinc-
generally, the development of phenotypic tion between the organism (or the mind)
traits. The most uncontroversial of these and its environment; nativists claim that, in
contextual factors reside in the organism some substantive sense, internal structures
itself. Developmental systems theorists go (beliefs, theories, concepts) arise indepen-
one further, however, to argue that deter- dently of the environment (or of what is
mination involves the entire host of factors external to the mind) and are innate for just
shaping the phenotype (i.e., the entire host that reason. According to DST, evolution-
of factors that create a life cycle), which, ary processes select for traits determined by
in many cases, includes factors in the envi- more than the organism itself. On the tradi-
ronment beyond the organism's boundary tional view of innateness, then, where there
(Griffiths & Gray, 2004). is extraorganismic determination of pheno-
Developmental systems theory empha- typic traits, the traits in question are not
sizes the ways in which organismic resources innate. Similarly, in the case of cognitive
contribute to the shaping of environments systems: if a cognitive system includes the
(e.g., in niche construction) that confer environment in nontrivial ways — ways that
reproductive advantage on the very organ- pertain directly to the cognitive capacities
ismic resources that help to create those or structures in question - this precludes
environments. As a result, those environ- a nativist account of those structures; for
ments are more likely to be re-created surely the cognitive capacities in question
or maintained. Thus, environmental factors are not sufficiently independent of the envi-
can themselves exhibit the dynamics of se- ronment to be innate.7
lection as it is thought to operate on genetic Both appeals to D S T fail the H E C the-
resources: the environmental resources ex- orist. Take first the nonnativist interpreta-
hibit traits that, given the context, increase tion of D S T and, derived from it, the non-
their own fitness. In fact, the environments nativist interpretation of HEC. If there is
are selected for along with the selection for any single overarching idea driving nativist
organisms that create those environments. thought throughout the centuries, it is the
Because reproduction of the two systems - equation of innateness with what follows
organismic resources and external ones - from the internal properties or states of
rely on each other for success, selection is for a system. If, however, the relevant system
the composite package of resources, internal is extended, the internal-external boundary
and external: the entire developmental sys- shifts accordingly: it separates what is inter-
tem, organism-and-environment, is selected nal to that extended system, including its
for.6 organismic and extraorganismic parts, from
Developmental systems theory thus what falls outside that extended system. It
appears to support H E C in a fairly straight- follows from HEC, then, that traits arising
forward way. According to DST, evolution- exclusively or largely from what is inter-
ary forces often operate on transorganismic, nal to the entire developmental system are
or extended, systems. Assuming that cogni- innate to that system: they are determined
tive traits were selected for, it is no surprise by the resources internal to it. Both Wilson
that transorganismic systems should exhibit (1999, pp. 363-364) and Wimsatt (1999, p.
such traits. The H E C theorist simply takes 160) entertain this view, or something close
the systems instantiating cognitive proper- to it, though neither embraces it. It is a chal-
ties to be, or to at least be similar in scope lenge, though, to see where precisely it goes
to, the systems of fundamental importance wrong.
with respect to the biological processes that It might fall to eliminativism. The advo-
give rise to cognitive phenomena. cate of H E C might argue either that innate-
What is more, D S T seems to ground a ness, in general, is too fractured a concept to
nonnativist account of the cognitive traits be of any use (Griffiths, 2002) or that the par-
of extended systems. Traditional notions of ticular conception of innateness currently
loo robert rupert

at issue floats too far from the traditional biology. There are alternatives, however. If
one to merit the title. Such qualms miss the one focuses on selection for individual traits,
mark, though, by failing to appreciate the one can, in many cases, interpret the selec-
fundamental role of the internalist view in tion process in either of two ways: as the
historical and contemporary thinking about selection for extended biological systems or
innateness. According to Plato, knowledge as selection for traits of individual organisms
is innate because it is already in the mind, as that occurs within a particular environment
a result of the soul's experiences prior to (which might, for example, include the pres-
earthly embodiment. On Leibniz's view, ence of other organisms with the same or a
knowledge is present in the mind like veins complementary trait; Sterelny & Griffiths,
in marble and thus is innate - similarly for 1999, p p . 1 6 6 - 1 7 2 ) .
most contemporary views. The idea that To distinguish cases, Sterelny and Grif-
what is innate is what is genetically deter- fiths propose a common-fate criterion (1999,
mined expresses the internalist view: genes pp. 161, 172-177). Say that we encounter
constitute the relevant material internal to what appears to be an extended system, one
the system; therefore, whatever they create that includes something more than a sin-
is innate. Various other views, for example, gle organism. We can ask to what degree
that what is innate is canalized, universal,
the various components of that system are
or typical to the species, arguably constitute
subject to the same selection pressure, that
diagnostic measures of the organism's inter-
is, to what extent the reproductive fate of
nal contribution - the contribution of what
the components is shared. In the extreme
is internal to all members of a given species
case, every part of a system reproduces
and in virtue of which they are members of
together or not at all; there is no indepen-
that species. At the very least, the internal-
dent reproduction or survival of parts. 8 In
ist conception constrains theories of innate-
such cases, a trait exhibited by the entire
ness: any conception of innateness that rules
system is possessed by that system as a bio-
a trait to be noninnate when the system's
logical individual. In other cases, though,
internal properties are primarily responsible
for that trait's appearance thereby faces a the organism interacts with its environment
serious objection. It is not credible, then, to in reproduction-enhancing ways, without
dismiss the internalist concept of innateness shared fate. In these cases, traits are selected
as unprincipled, fractured, or deviant. Thus, for because of their bearers' interactions
DST does not secure a nonnativist reading with components of some larger system; it
of HEC. is only in the context of those interactions
that the trait confers its selectional advan-
Moreover, closer examination of DST's tage. Still, the bearers in question can and
implications regarding systems individua- sometimes do go it alone: they can survive
tion undermines HEC's appeal to DST as and reproduce in the absence of the other
a general source of support. One of the pri- components on which the utility of some
mary problems currently faced by DST is of their own individual traits depends. In
the problem of systems individuation in the such cases, although an extended system
theory of selection (Griffiths & Gray, 2004, might seem to exhibit a single trait, the
pp. 423-424). Advocates of DST have made components of that system are reproduc-
a strong case that external resources con- tively independent; and thus the traits on
tribute significantly to the traits on which which selectional forces operate are traits of
selection operates. Nevertheless, this does the components. In these cases, componen-
not settle the issue of what are, properly tial explanation - that is, explanation given
speaking, biological individuals; if we were in terms of selection pressures operating on
to accept that anything causally relevant to the traits of the components as biological
the development of a trait becomes part individuals - is to be preferred; and in this
of a biological individual, we would saddle way, we avoid profligate metaphysics. Many
ourselves with a profligate metaphysics for selection-based explanations depend on
INNATENESS AND THE SITUATED MIND 101

distinguishing parts of the system. Once a form that the artist would not have envi-
such smaller individuals have been admitted sioned without the use of the sketch pad as
into our ontology, there is no reason to add a tool. Nevertheless, if the organismic sub-
an extended system; analysis in terms of the ject had not been interested in drawing, the
smaller individuals situated in their environ- organism would not have taken up a sketch
ments suffices to explain whatever effects pad; that is, the extended system in ques-
the trait in question has, including effects tion would never have come into existence.
that change how selectional forces operate Asymmetrically, the sketch pad's interests,
on the trait.9 goals, or other internal processes provide; lit-
Thus, although DST might lay firm bio- tle impetus for the creation of the system
logical ground for some extended cogni- in question. (Artists might describe their
tive systems, significant limitations apply: sketch pads as calling to them, but they
extended systems exist only where the parts would, I take it, be speaking figuratively of
of the extended system share a common their internal states.)
fate; only in those cases do facts about Admittedly, there is some bare counter-
extended trait selection bear on cognitive factual sense in which the sketch pad causes
systems individuation because only in those the existence of the extended system: in the
cases do facts about extended trait selection nearest possible world in which the sketch
bear on the individuation of biological sys- pad does not exist, the particular extended
tems. The problem is that most of the sys- system in question does not come into exis-
tems of interest to HEC theorists do not tence. Despite this causal contribution on
satisfy the shared-fate criterion; these sys- the part of the sketch pad, the asymme-
tems exhibit significant asymmetries among try is genuine. Keep in mind how lopsided
their components, analogous to asymmetries are the relative contributions of the organ-
resulting in reproductive independence in ismic and extraorganismic portions of the
the biological context. In lieu of some other extended system. Consider what happens if
more convincing criterion for the individua- a particular sketch pad or a particular artist
tion of biological systems, these asymmetries is deleted from history. The human, wish-
undermine the DST-based case for HEC. ing to draw, is likely to find or make a dif-
Consider the genesis of extended cogni- ferent sketch pad if the particular one she
tive systems. The volition of the organism, would otherwise have gotten is destroyed.
its intention to take up tools, and its abilities The sketch pad seems less likely to find or
to do so are asymmetrically responsible for make a different human if her user has been
the creation of extended cognitive systems.10 removed. This may be partly a contingent
For example, an organism with no need to statistical factor - at any given time, the
solve complex mathematical problems does proportion of artists who want to sketch
not create a system of written numerals, the who find sketch pads is much greater than
manipulation of which facilitates the solving the proportion of sketch pads ready for use
of those problems. I would like to pursue that in fact get used 1 but behind it lies the
this concern about asymmetry, but in the point about impetus made previously: the
interest of variety, I shall do so in the con- human who wants to sketch will go out of
text of a different example, one presented her way to find or make a sketch pad; the
by Clark (2003, pp. 76-77]: the artist using a sketch pad instantiates no internal processes
sketch pad who creates drawings via a feed- that home in on or actively create users.
back loop. The artist begins a sketch by mak- Now consider a slightly different kind of
ing preliminary figures. The results of these counterfactual variation: type-level obliter-
early strokes impinge on the organism, caus- ation. Wipe the sketch pads from history
ing her to "see" the artistic possibilities in a and human organisms still exist. Wipe the
new light and thus to make different, often humans from history, and there will be no
more sophisticated sets of new strokes; the sketch pads. Finally, take a special case of
cycle repeats, with the final art object taking the preceding point, a world in which no
102 ROBERT RUPERT

sketch pads exist or ever have existed. It science is interested in abilities that can be
is likely that human organisms will create exercised flexibly across a wide range of
sketch pads, but the converse will not hap- environments, danger of mismatch looms
pen: no sketch pad will bring a human into large. These concerns about mismatch,
being. So, there appears to be an asymmet- together with the nativist results of com-
ric relation between the causal processes bining DST and HEC, suggest that the anti-
responsible for the existence of the compo- nativist HEC theorist should try a different
nents of the extended system." tack: to set aside entirely the appeal to biol-
Return now to the question of whether ogy - DST and all the rest - and look instead
DST, qualified by the shared-fate criterion, to psychological criteria of innateness.
supports HEC. In light of the preceding
discussion of asymmetries, it seems clear
that the human organism is reproductively 2. Extended Systems, Nativism,
independent of the sketch pad and thus and Psychology
that the composite system of sketch pad
plus human does not satisfy the shared-fate Before turning to psychological criteria of
criterion. Does this concern carry over to innateness, we should address the prior
other examples? It would appear that the question: are there extended systems that
standard examples of extended systems - might plausibly serve as bearers of innate
those involving language, mathematics, psychological capacities or traits? If there are
external memory storage, and nautical arti- no such systems, it is moot whether psycho-
facts - manifest most or all of the asym- logical criteria would pronounce their cog-
metries discussed previously. Furthermore, nitive traits to be innate. To prosecute this
although the development of these tools question, it is helpful to take up more gen-
surely affected humans' rate of reproduc- eral issues pertaining to the explananda of
tion, human organisms are reproductively cognitive psychology, its investigative meth-
independent of all such resources (having ods, and the relation of both to HEC.
reproduced without them for millennia). Humans categorize, perceive, remember,
In the end, then, two systems-based con- use language, reason, and make sense of the
cerns threaten the marriage of DST and actions of others - these and more are abil-
HEC. First, a plausible DST validates only ities of persisting systems. In contrast, most
a narrow range of genuinely extended bio- actual extended systems are short-lived:
logical individuals; the shared-fate criterion they involve the human organism's short-
severely limits the number of such extended term use of or interaction with some kind
systems. Second, no matter how things turn of external resource. The importance of sys-
out with respect to biology, we cannot tems that persist and cohere, even through
ignore the potential for mismatch between change, is especially clear in developmental
the extended individuals established by DST psychology: we want to know how that sys-
and those systems claimed by HEC to be tem - a single developing human - came to
extended cognitive systems. Clearly these be the way it is and how a similar course
two worries operate together: given the of development happens, on average, for
broad range of extended cognitive systems, the relatively homogeneous multitude of
the narrowness of the range of extended bio- such persisting human systems. We want
logical systems dims the prospects for cross- to understand how and why the capacities
disciplinary fit. It may well be that natural and abilities of individual persisting systems
forces sometimes select for extended sys- change over time and eventually take a sta-
tems, but such systems might not be the ble form. If the systems to be investigated
ones of interest to psychology (Rupert, 2004, were relatively short-lived systems - the
1122; Wilson, 1999, p. 363).12 If, for exam- organism together with its immediate lin-
ple, extended selection requires a stable guistic environment, for example - develop-
environmental contribution, yet cognitive mental inquiry would seem incoherent. We
INNATENESS AND THE SITUATED MIND
m
want to be able to explain why, for example, use, for example, normally presuppose that
the child categorizes on the basis of appear- the subjects of investigation are individual
ance at age two but pays more attention to persisting systems. Some such studies are
insides at age five (Carey, 1995; Keil, 1989; explicitly longitudinal (Bahrick, 1979, 1 9 % )
Markman, 1989). How can this question be and thus much like developmental psychol-
sensibly posed - and in such a way that it ogy in the relevant respects. Beyond these
might motivate a research program - if all cases, psychologists and linguists frequently
that exists are ephemeral systems, lacking in study contextual effects. It is striking that
the continuity that makes the child at five the same person behaves in one way in
the same system as the child at two?' 3 one context - say, when not primed - and
In response, the advocate of H E C might behaves differently in another slightly differ-
remind us of the aim to reconceptualize ent context, when, in contrast, he or she has
cognitive systems. Such reconceptualization been primed. There is an enormous body
founders on a dilemma, however: either we of fascinating literature filled with exper-
pursue genuine reconceptualization of cog- iments interpreted in just this way; their
nitive systems as relatively short-lived sys- explananda are taken to be persisting indi-
tems, at great cost to cognitive psychology, viduals with various capacities or abilities
or we can jury-rig a method of cognitive- that they exercise in different ways in dif-
systems individuation that preserves the suc- ferent contexts.
cesses of cognitive psychology and is consis- A focus on the persisting individual is
tent with a viable investigative method - but also evident in research on perception. We
unmotivated and unnecessarily complex. would like to know why, for example,
Consider what is lost if the H E C theorist the subject perceives certain features under
pursues the former tack. T h e typical exper- some conditions - say, against a particular
iment in cognitive psychology yields use- background - but does not perceive those
ful and coherent results by assuming such same features under other conditions (see,
privileged grouping of various short-lived e.g., various results surveyed in Treisman,
systems (i.e., the typical experiment pre- 1998). The experimenter asks a single sys-
supposes that subjects are persisting, organ- tem to perform various visual tasks, and
ismically bound cognitive systems). 14 Think the outcome sheds light on the process by
of the multitude of within-subject analyses which that system sees. Perhaps, as is some-
of results on short series of experiments, all times emphasized, the subject does some-
data lost, absent privileged groupings. Rad- thing as a way to get information visually
ical reconceptualization, however, offers (Churchland, Ramachandran, & Sejnowski,
developmental psychologists no more rea- 1994). Still, such results reveal something
son to be interested in, for example, the about the ability of a single persisting sys-
series of temporal segments we normally tem: they reveal how that system gets visual
associate with Sally from ages two to six than information.' 5
it offers to be interested in, say, Sally, at age The preceding argument against ex-
two, together with a ball she was bounc- tended individuation might seem to have
ing on some particular day; Johnny, age five, ignored an important aspect of standard
together with the book he was reading on methodology: researchers frequently assign
some particular afternoon; and Terry, age experimental subjects to different groups; in
seven, plus the stimulus item he has just a typical experiment, these consist of a con-
been shown by an experimenter. It is sim- trol group and an experimental group. In
ply not clear how one should proceed after such experiments, researchers do not appear
giving up the traditional method of systems to be investigating the capacities of individ-
individuation. ually persisting systems as they change over
These problems are not limited to time or as they exercise their capacities in
developmental psychology. Investigations of varying circumstances. This rejoinder mis-
adult capacities, for memory and language interprets standard methodology, however.
104 ROBERT RUPERT

Researchers assign subjects to different (that they are extended beyond the organ-
groups on the assumption that the set of ismic boundary) for the cost of unneces-
members of each group represents a stan- sary complications, without any substantive
dard distribution of cognitive skills and departure from standard individuating
capacities across a population of members practice.
of the same kind. By statistical analysis of We should not pronounce in advance
the results, we think we discover some- what a completed cognitive psychology will
thing about the way the standard persist- bring. Nevertheless, insofar as we can make
ing human system reacts under different out a genuinely extended-systems-based al-
conditions. ternative to existing methodology, it faces
The HEC theorist might, in response, deep problems. It introduces a profligate
point out that data is sometimes analyzed set of distinct cognitive systems the rich-
simply by condition or by question. This ness of which confounds standard method-
rejoinder, however, takes too narrow a ology, with no productive replacement in
view of the ways in which analysis by ques- sight. In contrast, it is open to the H E C
tion is used. Normally, researchers com- theorist to partition extended systems into
pare the results of analysis by condition to useful subgroups, but this amounts to lit-
the results of a similar analysis of results tle more than a co-opting of the success of
in conditions - the point being to see how standard methodology. On measures of sim-
systems of the same kind behave under dif- plicity and conservatism, then, this strategy
ferent conditions. Such comparative analy- clearly loses out to the traditional approach
sis presupposes that the individuals involved (and to an embedded approach). Of course,
in both (or the many) conditions are rep- costiy revisions in theoretical frameworks
resentative of the human population; thus, are justified when they offer sufficient gains
we are, once again, comparing the responses along other dimensions (e.g., in explanatory
of a single (kind of) system under different power or accuracy). The shift under consid-
conditions. eration does not, however, do so. The range
of provocative and fruitful results in con-
Of course, sometimes we naturally and
temporary cognitive science can reasonably
legitimately group together temporally dis-
and manageably be cast in terms of organis-
joint systems. Consider the practice of medi-
mically bounded cognitive systems that fre-
cal doctors, who talk about the same patient
quentiy interact intimately with their envi-
over time, even though, at the biological
ronments.
level, that patient changes his or her con-
stitution (cells die; new ones form). This, Where does this leave us with respect
however, only emphasizes the need for to HEC and nativism? Previously I rec-
a principle of organization to ground the ommended that HEC abandon biology-
groupings. Organismic integrity and the way based theorizing about innateness and draw
it physically grounds health and disease rec- instead from sciences closer in subject mat-
ommend treating a person over time as a sin- ter to HEC's own domain. Before conclud-
gle patient returning for visits. Insofar as an ing this section, let us briefly consider a
organizing principle motivates the groupings pair of widely discussed psychological crite-
of alleged cognitive systems into privileged ria of innateness. First, take the primitivist
sets (and legitimates the chosen groupings), view (Cowie, 1999; Fodor, 1981; Samuels,
this principle is similarly organism based - 2002). According to this view, a psycholog-
which is, of course, just how traditional cog- ical trait is primitive if and only if there is
nitive science identifies its systems of inter- no psychological account of its appearance. 16
est. This moderate position - the second The asymmetries discussed herein suggest
horn of the dilemma mentioned previously - that, in most cases, the appearance of an
is not worth its price. The HEC theorist buys extended cognitive trait has a psychological
a highly counterintuitive claim about minds explanation: extended systems, and thus
INNATENESS AND THE SITUATED MIND 105

their traits, originate in the psychology of 3. Embedded Cognition and


the organism and thus would not count as Context-Specific Representations
innate by the primitivist criterion.' 7 Appli-
cation of a second commonly used psycho- Many embedded views appeal to context-
logical measure of innateness, domain speci- specific representations, the contents of
ficity (Cowie, 1999; Keil, 1990), yields similar which seem best understood in nonnativist
results. The basic idea is that if a cognitive terms. These context-specific representa-
capacity can be exercised only with respect tions amount to little more than mental
to a proprietary set of inputs or tasks, it is demonstratives, internal placeholders that
innately dedicated to those inputs or to that take ephemeral values relative to the task
task domain, and the capacity in question being performed (Ballard, Hayhoe, Pook, &
is thus innate. Many of the relevant capac- Rao, 1997); as such, their contents depend
ities of extended systems are not domain heavily on the contribution of the environ-
specific. Pen and paper are used to draw ment. The embedded view's deep reliance
diagrams, to solve math problems, and to on context-specific representation promises
make sketches, and thus, they are not cate- to provide the situated program with an
gorized as innate by this criterion. Surpris- importantly nonnativist aspect, for represen-
ingly, this might even hold in the case of tations play a central role in many embedded
extended visual systems. Keep in mind that models, and questions about representation,
the organism together with what it visu- concepts, and content stand at the center
ally perceives constitutes the relevant sys- of many debates about nativism (Cowie,
tem; so, even if the organism's visual sys- 1999; Fodor, 1981; Rupert, 2001). If embed-
tem is domain dedicated, it is not clear ded cognition avoids nativism along this
what the domain-specific restrictions are rel- dimension of the debate, embedded cogni-
ative to the entire extended system (i.e., the tion is nonnativist in at least one substan-
visual apparatus taken together with what is tive respect. Nevertheless, although there is
seen). a fairly robust sense in which the content
of context-specific representations is not
Thus, the antinativist H E C theorist wins
innately determined, the theory of content
a Pyrrhic victory. The psychological crite-
best suited to such representations entails a
ria of primitiveness and domain specificity
significant nativist contribution to their con-
plausibly categorize at least some of the rele-
tent — or so I argue in this section.
vant cognitive capacities in a way consistent
with the nonnativist leanings of many sit- Generally speaking, the embedded ap-
uated theorists. Consequently, if extended proach aims to minimize the amount of
systems were the right sort of thing to which internal representation used to model the
to attribute psychological properties, the human performance of cognitive tasks (Bal-
advocate of HEC would have found anti- lard et al., 1997; Clark, 1997, chap. 8; Mc-
nativist support in the application of these Clamrock, 1995, chap. 6). 18 To appreciate
psychological criteria for innateness. Cog- the kind of minimization at issue, let us
nitive science, however, takes as its ex- first consider a contrasting approach. On
plananda cognitive capacities of persisting a more traditional understanding of cogni-
systems; it is wrongheaded to attribute tion, the subject performs a complex anal-
innate capacities to systems that are short- ysis of a problem before acting: in the
lived relative to the capacities in question, case of action or inference based on visual
largely because the capacities of the short- perception, such complex analysis involves
lived systems are not the proper objects of the construction of a detailed internal
inquiry in cognitive science. Thus, I con- representation of the immediate environ-
clude that there are few or no innate capac- ment; in the case of abstract planning (e.g.,
ities of extended systems - but for reasons the choice of which college to attend), the
HEC theorists cannot embrace. subject might explicidy represent the costs
106 ROBERT RUPERT

and benefits of each of a range of options, some of these other facts at some time dur-
as well as the likelihood of success of each ing the visit; but on entering the store and
option and the maximum cost the subject is beginning to look for the photo counter, he
willing to pay to achieve his or her goal. On can ignore these other matters.
an embedded view of the former case, the A more general idea binds these three
subject uses context-specific correlations to principles to the embedded theorist's mini-
act on the basis of visual perception in a way malist approach to representation: as much
that requires substantially less in the way as possible, let the environment do the cog-
of representational resources than would be nitive work (Brooks, 1991; Clark, 1989,
required to build a detailed internal repre- p. 64). Perhaps surprisingly, all of these prin-
sentation of the relevant environment. To ciples - from the overarching idea of let-
illustrate, consider Clark's (1995) example ting the world do the work to the more
of finding the photo-development counter specific tactical principles particularly to do
at a supermarket. Given the market domi- with representation - apply also to the case
nance of Kodak, the area above or around of decision making, in which many of the
the photo-development counter is normally points about visual engagement with the
splashed with yellow. This suggests a sim- world might seem to have little applica-
ple strategy to the consumer in search of the tion. The general strategy of letting the
photo counter: enter the supermarket and world do the work could be applied in the
swivel one's head about to look for a large following way: the agent sets a maximum
patch of yellow. acceptable cost of achieving her goal as well
At work in this example are three tactical as a minimum probability of success, then
principles by which embedded models mini- accepts the first satisfactory option offered
mize the subject's use of internal representa- by the environment. This requires some
tional resources. First, the subject need not internal calculation on the subject's part and
explicidy represent - in working memory thus some internal representation, but it is
or any other sort of cognitive work space - much less demanding than an optimizing
any very elaborate theory or conception of comparison of a good number of options.
photo counters. She needs only to activate Thus, this approach remains in step with the
a routine that exploits the local, contingent embedded emphasis on minimizing inter-
correlation between patches of yellow and nal representational resources. Furthermore,
the location of photo counters. Second, the the three principles listed in connection
subject represents what might be called a with the example of visual cognition
"coarse-grained" property: the subject looks are at work, at least to some extent. In
for a large patch of yellow, not one of any many actual environments, there is a contin-
particular size. Third, the subject collects gent correlation between being an option that
only the information she needs. Mind you, presents itself and beinga satisfactory option.19
the requisite representational resources far Of course, if there were only a weak cor-
exceed nil. The subject must, for example, relation or none at all, the subject might
represent in some way the project or plan spend a lot of time performing a series of
she is engaged in: a person should not wan- quick and dirty analyses of the many possi-
der through life looking for yellow patches. bilities that present themselves, determin-
Once the goal has been determined, though ing serially that none will do. It is often
(e.g., to get one's photos developed) and observed, though, that humans structure
the subject has found and entered the store, their environments, institutions, and social
the amount of information needed, at that interactions in such a way as to strengthen
moment, is fairly small. The subject need the kind of correlation at issue - so that,
not know the general layout of the building, for example, if the subject decides on the
the location of the restrooms, the number first college she comes across that meets
of cashiers on duty, or which cashier lines her minimum standards, she will probably
are open. The subject might need access to achieve her related goals (e.g., to become
INNATENESS AND THE SITUATED MIND 107

reasonably well educated). Also, given that view, then, representational content clearly
the subject makes no detailed comparison depends on the contribution of the sub-
of options, she can represent coarse-grained ject's immediate local environment, some-
properties - such as being a fairly prestigious thing that, having set aside H E C and DST,
school - in place of any attempt to make we can assume is not innate to the subject.
a fine-grained determination of, for exam- Let us pursue this approach to represen-
ple, relative degree of prestige of a range tation, to see whether one can reasonably
of alternatives. Imagine a case where two expect it to deliver a robustly nonnativist
or more options fall in roughly the same understanding of mental content.
ball park in terms of costs and benefits; if It might be too demanding to insist that
the subject's charge is to figure out which the embedded theorist have in pocket a fully
is better overall, she cannot coarse grain 9 worked-out theory of content for context-
coarse graining leads to a tie. Decision mak- specific representations. Furthermore, limi-
ing under such conditions required fine- tations of space prevent a sustained attempt
grained comparison. If, however, the subject to determine here which, among the various
considers the first opportunity that presents leading theories of mental content, correctly
itself, sees that it offers sufficient promise of characterizes the kind of content carried by
success while falling at or below the max- context-specific representations.20 Of extant
imum acceptable cost, then she is off to theories, Robert Cummins's (1996) combi-
the races. The discussion of coarse grain- nation of intenders and isomorphism can
ing makes clear that embedded accounts be most naturally applied to the embed-
of decision making embody the last of the ded approach. On Cummins's view, the
three representation-minimizing principles cognitive system consists largely of func-
discussed in connection with visual percep- tionally discrete components - intenders -
tion: collect only the information needed. each of which aims at a particular kind
The amount of information one needs to of target, for example, the spatial layout
gather to determine that a single school is of the immediate environment. Each
fairly prestigious falls far short of the amount intender employs a set of representational
the subject would need to gather to deter- primitives that can be activated in complex
mine which of a number of fairly presti- arrangements. The representational value
gious schools beats all the others in the of each arrangement is determined by iso-
group. morphism alone, leaving each arrangement
wildly ambiguous. Nevertheless, a mental
The drive to minimize the use of inter-
state - a belief, for example - can be deter-
nal representational resources seems to
minate^ correct because the function of
recommend heavy reliance on ad hoc,
an intender in which the representation
context-specific representations. Such rep-
appears limits that representation's contri-
resentations do not persist content intact,
bution to something from the appropriate
hut rather depend for their content on the
range of targets (i.e., targets appropriate to
immediate and typically short-lived contri-
the intender in which the representing struc-
bution of their environment. The embedded
ture is activated)."
approach would thus seem to suggest a cog-
nitive system that does as much as possible How does any of this bear on the ques-
with only a standing collection of mental tion of innateness? It depends partly on how
demonstratives (e.g., pointers instantiated we resolve a question that Cummins him-
>n visual cortex) that take different values self leaves open, the question of how the
depending on their short-lived relationships intenders acquire their functions. On the
to environmental factors; or perhaps in the one hand, Cummins considers the approach
extreme, the subject might construct new he helped to found, that of homuncular or
pointers in new situations, so that even indi- systemic decomposition. According to this
viduated nonsemantically, the pointers have view, the contribution of a component to
little integrity over time. On the embedded the performance of its containing system
108
ROBERT RUPERT

determines that component's function. If accurate visual detection. There is no case


intender Ii contributes what - in the con- to be made that accurate berry detection
text of the system's overall behavior - is on Tuesdays led to reproductive advantage,
best construed as perceptual uptake, then partly because there is no relevant aspect of
li has some particular aspect of the immedi- the organism's physiology connected nom-
ate environment as its target (which aspect ically to the property being eaten on a
depends on what kind of perceptual uptake Tuesday. But - and here is the punch line -
Ii is best understood as contributing to the if embedded cognition relies on the teleo-
overall performance of the system). Cum- semantic version of Cummins's theory of
mins also considers a Millikan-style teleo- content, content is innate in one very impor-
functional view (Millikan, 1984). On this tant respect. Any given representing struc-
approach, evolutionary selection determines ture is isomorphic to a great number of
an in tender's function (Cummins, 1996, external structures; the intender plays an
chap. 8). essential disambiguating role by determin-
The former approach is problematic, for ing which of a representation's many values
reasons parallel to those Cummins (1996, that representation contributes to the con-
pp. 41-51) wields against functionalist (or tent of the mental state in question. The
conceptual role) theories of content. In con- representational content of that mental state
flict with a fundamental constraint on any rests immediately and synchronically on the
theory of mental content, functionalist the- function of the intender in which the repre-
ories do not seem to allow for error. Take a sentation appears, and the function of that
case in which we think a subject has made intender is determined innately.
a representation-based error. Recall that One might think that causal contact with
the functions at issue are computational- the environment minimizes nativist com-
mathematical functions; thus, it will always mitments: after all, in the typical embed-
be possible to locate some other function - ded model, the subject causally interacts
that is, some function other than the one we with the portion of the world to which
thought the system was computing - rela- his or her context-specific representations
tive to which the system's computation was are bound. Even here, however, innate con-
accurate. Similarly, though, this strategy of tributions play a prominent role. In one
alternative interpretation applies to any case of Ballard et al.'s (1997) examples, a sin-
of what we might think of as erroneous rep- gle pointer gets bound to the color of a
resentation within an intender. If, for exam- block in a visual display, but that block
ple, it seems that h contributes information has texture as well as shape and other visu-
about spatial layout to the functioning of ally detectable properties. What determines
its containing system, but on some particu- that the pointer is bound to the color of
lar occasion its output causes the containing the block? Presumably, the pointer's content
system to trip over a table, we can reinter- depends on the function of that pointer in a
pret Ii's function as representing the spatial routine, which is partly determined by the
layout of the room adjusted in such and such intender(s) involved, in Cummins's view.
a way (e.g., Ii is supposed to represent spa- This routine can have complex structure,
tial layout excepting tables on Tuesdays, if for example, in terms of the way it uses
that is when the trip occurred). the bound information, and this structure
The teleofunctionalist view fares better determines to what the pointer is bound."
because, presumably, it is a matter of fact To the extent that this complex structure of
what a particular functional component was the routine arises from its teleofunction, its
selected for (assuming it was selected for the contribution to the content of the relevant
performance of a function!). If a component cognitive state is innately determined to a
kept its owners alive longer because it con- significant extent.
ferred the ability to see berries, then this Of course, there is also a significant
component had better have the function of sense in which embedded models remain
INNATENESS AND THE SITUATED MIND

empiricist: the world contributes specific perceptual systems or modules. Call the
content (e.g., green or yellow) to the pointer. representations employed at this level
Here Wilson's (2004) two-dimensional anal- "peripheral representations." These include
ysis of the nativism-empiricism debate may such representations as the visual image of a
be useful. Put simply, there are two dimen- tree currently in the subject's view; typically
sions of complexity, the internal and the the context-specific representations posited
external. If the internal mechanisms driving by embedded models fall into this cate-
some cognitive process are rich and complex gory. The second layer is what some the-
and largely independent of environmen- orists call "central processing" (Fodor, 1983).
tal control, but the external contribution Let us dub the representations appearing
is minimal, we rightly label that pro- at this level "central representations." The-
cess "innate." If, in contrast, the internal oretical, abstract, and nonsensory concepts,
mechanism driving a cognitive process is such concepts as PROTON, JUSTICE, and
simple in structure, but the external con- CHAIR (as a general kind) fall into this
tribution is rich and complex, an empiri- category.
cist conclusion is warranted. In mixed It might appear that central representa-
cases, such as the present one, the two- tions come into no special contact with the
dimensional analysis fails to deliver a par- embedded program. I propose a contrast-
ticular judgment - innate or not. Thus, Wil- ing view: peripheral representations mediate
son's two-dimensional analysis explains our the causal relations that fix the content of
discomfort in issuing either a firmly nativist many central representations; furthermore,
or firmly empiricist judgment about the con- one of the most commonly cited exam-
tent of context-specific representations. ples of embedded representational activ-
ity - the active use of language - con-
tributes significantly to the fixation of the
4. Nativism and Persisting content of central representations, by help-
Representations ing to bring them into the causal relations
that determine what they represent. This
view does not require that central represen-
Theories of cognition must make some
tations inherit their content directly from
allowance for persisting, internal represen-
some selection of peripheral representations
tations. Children employ amodal represen-
or from external symbols; nor does it require
tations from early on; concepts are used in
that peripheral representations or exter-
abstract thought, when one is, for exam-
nal symbols define central representations.
ple, alone in the study; theorists conceptu-
Thus, the current proposal is not empiricist
alize, reason, design experiments, and write
in the traditional sense: central representa-
papers (about, for example, embedded cog-
tions can and typically do have content that
nition); and what is more, embedded mod-
outruns the content of the subject's sensory
els themselves appeal to standing routines,
representations or logical constructions from
intentions, or programs in ways touched those sensory representations.2'
on previously. I do not offer this observa-
tion in argument against embedded mod- In what sense, then, is the current pro-
els. Rather, the present section fleshes out posal empiricist? Because atomic central
a sense in which embedded models help to representations are stable, reappearing units,
explain - in an empiricist way, no less - how it seems likely that their content can be fixed
the content of persisting representations is without the contribution of an intender
fixed. that determines the target of the repre-
Think of the human cognitive system as sentation on particular occasions of use.
two layered; this is surely an oversimplifica- Moreover, application of the primitivist cri-
tion, but it allows us to focus on the rele- terion suggests that the content of central
representations is not innate; peripheral rep-
vant issues without, I think, distorting the
resentations and external symbols mediate
conclusions reached. One layer consists of
uo ROBERT RUPERT

content fixation, which typically involves a sentation with that kind as its content - see
fairly detailed psychological explanation of Fodor, 19988)
the fixation of the content of central rep- Granted, the contents of peripheral or
resentations (cf. Co we, 1999). This non- organismically external representations do
nativist implication of the primitivist cri- not exhaust the contents of the central rep-
terion follows from a central commitment resentations in question, and thus the organ-
of the embedded approach. A recurring ism must make some internal contribution
theme in the embedded literature has been to the fixation of content for the latter repre-
the extent to which humans simplify their sentations. For Fodor (1975, 1981), this con-
cognitive tasks by structuring their external tribution - together with the absence of a
environment in ways that facilitate the per- hypothesis-testing explanation of the acqui-
formance of those tasks (Clark, 1997; Den- sition of central representations - secures
nett, 1996; McClamrock, 1995). Some such the innateness of those representations. To
simplification can be effected through the a certain extent, I think Fodor is right.
use of language and the assignment of a priv-Even with a set of mediating mechanisms
ileged role to certain observations. Straight- in place, including peripheral representa-
forward examples involve the construction tions, the organism must at least be disposed
of written descriptions or visual diagrams to come into the appropriate content-fixing
meant to convey a new concept to others, causal relation to one external kind or prop-
that is, to get their central representations erty rather than another. Thus, there is some
causally connected to the correct properties innate contribution to the content of cen-
or kinds. In another sort of case, the individ- tral representations. All the same, there is a
ual formulates his or her own observation- rich and complex psychological explanation
based heuristic, for example, of the form, of how mediating mechanisms contribute
"When I see such and such, it means there to the fixation of content for central repre-
is a C present," where C is a central repre- sentations, while the nonpsychological story
sentation. In all of these cases, a peripheral is very thin. Furthermore, both the nature
representation comes to mediate the activa- of the environment and the causal prop-
tion of a newly created central representa- erties of the material available to instanti-
tion or a central representation to which the ate peripheral representations in the human
peripheral representation had not previously brain substantially limit the innate, internal
been connected. In the initial case, where contribution. There is a limited number of
the subject coins a new central representa- genuine properties and kinds present in the
tion that representation might not carry any subject's environment. Moreover, the mech-
determinate content or at least not the con- anisms that mediate the tokening of the cen-
tent it will ultimately carry (Margolis, 1998; tral representations in question themselves
Rupert, 1996, chap. 4,1998,2001). As various have limited causal properties: the visual
peripheral representations become causally cortex may be capable only of relaying reli-
connected to the newly coined central repre- able signals to central processing about cer-
sentation, the latter can come into a content- tain available properties among that lim-
determining causal relation to an external ited set present in the environment. Thus,
property, kind, or individual. Adverting to it may be that the human mind develops a
the human habit of actively structuring her representation of, for example, electron in a
environment so that she has certain sensory given set of circumstances not because a cen-
experiences constitutes a powerful psycho- tral representation has electron as its innate
logical explanation of how a human comes content but rather because the contingent
into the right causal position to have a cen- facts about the environment the human is
tral representation with the content electron. thrown into and the physical substance its
(In fact, in the case of some kinds, for exam- perceptual mechanisms are made of do not
ple, electron, this process seems the only allow the central representation in ques-
plausible way for a human to get a repre- tion to be attached in the proper fashion
INNATENESS AND THE SITUATED MIND 111

to any kind other than electron. It is plau- lowship for College Teachers. My thanks to the
sible that the physical mechanisms realiz- NEH. I would also like to thank Edward Averill
ing sensations were selected because of the and Robert Wilson for comments on an earlier
way they respond causally to certain phys- draft.
ical features of the subject's environment.
In contrast, the physical material that real-
izes central processing was selected for its Notes
relative flexibility, not its physical ability to
carry information about any specific aspects 1 For a substantial list of references to influ-
ential nativist work, see Elman et al. (1996,
of the environment. Thus, central processing
pp. 107-108).
contributes very little to the content of such
2 Although Clark (1997, chap. 2) discusses
concepts as E L E C T R O N that is innately Thelen and Smith's (1994) developmental
keyed specifically to their content. work in some detail, he avoids the ques-
In the end, we might try grafting Wilson's tion of nativism (but see Clark & Thornton,
two-dimensional view to the primitivist the- 1997, p. 63, where antinativist leanings are
ory of innateness — the two dimensions made a bit more explicit). Similarly, Varela,
becoming psychological and nonpsychologi- Thompson, and Rosch (1991, chap. 9) address
cal contributions to the development of the biological issues of genetic determination -
trait (acquisition of the concept) in question. advocating positions that are often taken to
support antinativist views - without address-
In the present case, this approach yields a
ing the question of nativism head on. Note
fairly strong judgment on the empiricist end that I use antinativist, nonnativist, and their
of the spectrum. The psychological story of cognates as umbrella terms to cover all man-
content fixation is quite rich, whereas the ner of empiricist and eliminativist views,
nonpsychological internal contribution con- where an eliminativist view holds that the
sists only in a disposition to be causally con- empiricist-nativist distinction is incoherent
nected in one way rather than another given or for some other reason should be ex-
a certain complex psychological and physi- cluded from theoretical discourse (Griffiths,
cal environment.24 2002).
3 For a contrasting view, see McGinn (1989,
pp. 24-26, 46,116, 210).
4 I do not wish to oversell this point, how-
5. Conclusion
ever. Kim Sterelny has rightly emphasized
the prevalence of cases in which traits alleged
Much of this chapter has been an explo- to be exhibited by extended cognitive sys-
ration of possibilities, an attempt to show tems - mathematical abilities involving the
that the situated program does not reside use of external media, for example - emerge
squarely in either the empiricist or the only with great difficulty and often do not
nativist camp. Along the way, I have argued appear at all in the extended systems in ques-
that, on various plausible assumptions, some tion, even after extensive tutelage (Sterelny,
2004). Note, though, that the HEC theorist
situated models are subject to a clear nativist
incurs a cost by pursuing this response to the
gloss, contrary to the leanings of many sit-
nativist charge. He must be prepared to assert
uated theorists. As development of situated that in cases where, for example, a student
program proceeds, we should keep in mind cannot seem to acquire the relevant math-
the wide range of theoretical possibilities ematical skill, an extended cognitive system
open with respect to nativism and the sit- exists nonetheless, so that the system's fail-
uated modeling of cognition. ure to develop the ability in question counts
against the canalization of that ability in the
kind of system in question. This creates some
tension when conjoined with the examples
Acknowledgments typically used to motivate HEC, for such
examples almost invariably involve success-
Work on this chapter was supported by a ful activity: showing that an extended system
National Endowment for the Humanities Fel-
112 ROBERT RUPERT

successfully performs the tasks we associate of the individuals enhances the fitness of each
with human cognitive capacities is meant to of the individuals in the group. (The idea
show that the extended system has cognitive is that sometimes the presence of a trait
capacities, that is, that it is an extended cog- enhances the fitness of an individual, even
nitive system. The organism's bare disposi- where that individual does not possess the
tion to try to use pencil and paper to solve trait in question but rather benefits from
math problems does not sufficiently moti- other individuals' possession of it.) A given
vate HEC, although antinativist HEC theo- individual, however, can be a member of
rists must count this system as an extended many trait groups, the members of which
cognitive system to avail themselves of the vary significandy. Thus, to avoid a Byzantine
antinativist defense bruited previously, network of partially overlapping, composite
s Keep in mind, however, that Wimsatt some- biological individuals (and to ensure that our
times leans toward eliminativism, describing account of composite, biological individual
generative entrenchment as a successor con- tracks only the theoretically important indi-
cept to innateness (1999, p. 139; see also viduals - see Griffiths & Gray, 2004, p. 423),
pp. 162-163 and 1122). we might lay down the following necessary
6 Developmental systems theory has played an condition: for two individuals to be mem-
important role in discussions of group selec- bers of the same composite biological organ-
tion (Sterelny & Griffiths, 1999), where con- ism, both should be members of all, or nearly
specifics or their traits constitute the relevant all, of the same trait groups. A given per-
environment. Throughout the discussion of son's brain and heart, for instance, are part
DST and HEC, I focus instead on systems of the same composite biological individual
that comprise individual organisms together because the brain's and the heart's probabili-
with nonorganismic aspects of the environ- ties of contributing to the appearance of oth-
ment. ers of their own kind are enhanced by the
7 Griffiths and Stotz (2000) present their
same (or very nearly same) group of traits,
account of extended inheritance in this way;
establishing what is, extensionally, the same
see pp. 34-9 for a juxtaposition of the ex-
trait group relative to the many traits that
tended view of selection and their anti-
affect the brain's and heart's fitness. Any
nativist reading of it. See also Griffiths and
composite biological individual satisfying this
Gray (2004, p. 425) for the view that extended
criterion is such that its component individ-
inheritance is inimical to nativism. Griffiths
uals have a very high probability of a shared
and Stotz (Griffiths, 2002; Griffiths & Stotz,
fate; they will not reproduce independently
2000) object to the association of innateness
of each other.
with human nature (or species nature), and
10 Cf. Wilson's locus-of-control argument for
this motivates some of their resistance to the
nativist characterization of extended inheri- the privilege of the organismic system (2004,
tance. In the present case, however, it seems pp. 197-198; for a similar argument, see But-
that extended systems do have a nature: if ler, 1998).
there are mechanisms - both internal and 11 Compare Clark's (2003) sustained argument
external to the organism - in place to reli- that humans are, by their nature, tool users.
ably reproduce extended systems, then the Clark may well be correct about human
requirements for the entire system's being a nature, and there is at least a clear sense to
natural kind seem to have been met. I am, his claim. It is a bit difficult to understand
however, getting ahead of myself. the converse claim - that it is the nature
of external resources that they be used by
8 The form of independence I have in mind humans; insofar as it does have clear meaning,
is not full-blown probabilistic independence it seems obviously false: it is not the nature
but rather the more intuitive idea of there of iron ore that it be wrought by humans
being a nonnegligible probability of one
into automobile parts or anything else. (Note
thing's reproducing successfully when the
that Clark sometimes wields his argument
other does not.
about human nature and tool use to a dif-
9 This point might be articulated in terms of ferent end: to support H E C . So far as I can
trait groups. A trait group with respect to tell, the argument faces serious difficulties,
trait F is a collection of individuals such that partly because it highlights significant asym-
instantiation of F by some sufficient number metries between the contributions of various
INNATENESS AND THE SITUATED MIND

portions of allegedly extended cognitive sys- leads to a kind of idealism that should give us
tems. Given the asymmetric contribution of pause: on this view, humans do not, on the
human organisms to the formation of such basis of perception, interact with the object*
systems, I take Clark's argument to support perceived; rather, certain parts of the human
the embedded approach rather than HEC.) mind interact with other parts of the human
See also Sterelny (2004), where he argues for mind!
other substantial asymmetries, both episte- 16 I do not claim that the primitivist view
mic and representational. is without problems. Many authors reject
12 With regard to biology alone, different inter- Fodor's radical concept of nativism because it
ests might lead to different principles of sys- counts too many concepts among the innate -
tems individuation (Griffiths & Gray, 2004, in Samuels's terms, it overgeneralizes (2002,
pp. 419-420), as well as to different standards pp. 256-259). Samuels responds to problems
of innateness: Ariew (1999, p. 120) argues that of this kind by adding the following con-
within biology itself, different research pro- dition to primitivism: a psychological abil-
grams have made use of conflicting concep- ity, capacity, or state that is primitive, yet
tions of innateness. arises only in nonstandard environments, is
13 Clark and Chalmers's (1998, p. 10) discus- not innate. But consider the case of cognitive
sion of portability as a criterion for cognitive deficits resulting from childhood lead poison-
states seems partly motivated by a concern for ing. There was a time when exposure to lead
persisting systemic integrity. There is a gap, threatened to become part of the developing
however, between the various hypothetical child's normal environment - species wide -
systems discussed by Clark and Chalmers - yet, even if the threat had been fully real-
systems that may well qualify as cognitive sys- ized, having impaired cognitive functions of
tems with persisting abilities - and systems the relevant kind (e.g., lowered IQ) would
subject to cognitive scientific inquiry; I am not have been innate. And notice, this is not a
concerned with the latter systems. far-out thought experiment; only by political
14 Even those researchers who focus on short- action and policy changes was the problem
lived, extended dynamical systems must take mitigated in technologically developed coun-
the traditional approach in certain respects. tries. Even today, in many regions and cities
For example, Thelen and Smith (1994, of the world, exposure to unhealthy levels of
pp. 288-289) attempt to explain children's lead is so common as to count, from a sta-
performance on specific A-not-B trials by tistical standpoint, as a normal condition of
adverting to characteristics of a short-lived childhood development.
dynamical system; but insofar as Thelen and 17 But, as argued previously, such asymme-
Smith's dynamical approach can explain the tries also cut against HEC's plausibility; see
child's developmental trajectory - how com- note 11.
petency changes over time - they must appeal 18 Note that embedded views minimize internal
to changes in the capacities of the persisting representation via a different strategy than
organismic system; after all, the toys and the the one often employed by HEC theorists:
wells need not change at all. What changes the extended approach lends itself to the
is the cognitive capacity of the organism. In external placement of the vehicles or bear-
Thelen and Smith's terms, what changes is ers of representational content (Houghton,
the child's ability to enter into dynamic rela- 1997; Hurley, 1998; Wilson, 2004), whereas
tions with the environment; in which case, the embedded view keeps the vehicles on the
we should, for simplicity's sake, appeal to this inside but, typically, binds them in a context-
organismically bounded cognitive capacity to specific way to aspects of the immediate
explain the results of any specific trial. environment. Of course, the HEC theorist
15 Consider a further worry about perception or the advocate of the embedded approach
and HEC. In perception and in action based could take an eliminativist view of repre-
on perception, humans often think about or sentation (Brooks, 1991), more plausibly at
perceive the same things with which they the subpersonal than at the personal level
interact; if the cognitive system is individ- (Dennett, 1987). Note, however, that if HEC
uated liberally, these things are part of the theorists commit to eliminativism about rep-
subjects' minds, because the subjects' per- resentation at the very level of the extended
ception depends heavily on them. But this model, their talk about external vehicles is
114
ROBERT RUPERT

misleading (what do the vehicles bear, if not in a straightforward way to context-specific


content?) (cf. Clark, 2005, m; Hurley 1998). representations.
19 I adopt the following orthographic conven- 21 Gallistel (1990) and Crush (1997) offer related
tions: terms referring to properties or kinds, views.
in the abstract, as well as terms that refer to 22 Cf. Cummins's discussion of indexicality and
mental contents, are set in italics; concepts, nested intenders (1996, pp. 118-120).
considered as mental particulars, are set in 23 Rupert (1996,1998,1999, 2001) develops many
capital letters, where a given concept's label of the details of such a view; see also the work
(HORSE, for instance) derives from the con- of Fodor (1987, 1990, 1998), Margolis (1998),
tent we assume to be carried by that mental and Prinz (2000), for views that are amenable
particular. in one way or another to the sort of position
20 Note, though, that many of these theories outlined in the text. Note that the present
are designed, in the first instance, to apply question concerns primitive central repre-
to representational structures that persist and sentations, not structured central represen-
are repeatedly activated (or tokened), carry- tations that somehow copy the structure
ing their standard meaning on each occasion of complex sensory representations; thus,
of activation - which seems to remove these the antiempiricist objections raised by Fodor
theories from the running in the present con- (2003) do not apply.
text. Consider Fred Dretske's (1988) influ- 24 If the human organism is innately endowed
ential account of representational content. with the tendency to create or structure envi-
Dretske's presentation relies in a substantive ronments so as to lead to concept acquisition
way on processes that extend through time. in the manner described in the text, then
A structure that at one time merely indi- a further innately determined source con-
cates a state of the environment acquires, by tributes in a significant way to the content
a kind of reinforcement-based learning, a role of central representations.
in the cognitive system (e.g., the function
of controlling a particular motor response).
That structure thereby becomes a represen-
tation, its content being whatever property References
or state the structure indicated such that
the structure's indication of that property Ariew, A. (1999). Innateness is canalization. In
or state explains why the structure acquired V. Hardcastle (Ed.), Biology meets psychology:
its motor-controlling role in the cognitive Conjectures, connections, constraints (pp. 117-
system. Granted, although Dretske's presen- 138). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
tation typically suggests longer time scales, Bahrick, H. P. (1979). Maintenance of knowledge:
the relevant learning process could occur Questions about memory we forgot to ask.
very quickly. Keep in mind, however, that Journal of Experimental Psychology: General,
Dretske also intends to solve the problem 108, 296-308.
of misrepresentation: later tokenings of the
Bahrick, H. P. (1984). Semantic memory content
structure in question misrepresent when the
in permastore: Fifty years of memory for Span-
structure's tokening is caused by something
ish learned in school. Journal of Experimental
other than what it indicated when it first
Psychology: General, 113,1-29.
acquired its function in the cognitive sys-
Ballard, D. H., Hayhoe, M. M., Pook, P. K.,
tem and in virtue of the indication of which
& Rao, R. P. N. (1997). Deictic codes for
it acquired that (unction. Without work-
the embodiment of cognition. Behavioral and
ing through the details, we cannot be sure
Brain Sciences, 20, 723-742.
whether Dretske's theory could be plausibly
Block, N. (1981). Introduction: What is innate-
adapted to cover context-specific representa-
tions, that is, whether his story about learn- ness? In N. Block (Ed.), Readings in the philos-
ing could plausibly apply on very short time ophy of psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 279-281). Cam-
scales and in a way that handles the prob- bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
lem of misrepresentation. Instead of taking on Bloom, P. (2000). How children leant the meanings
this project, though, it seems better advised of words. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
to look for a theory of content that applies Brooks, R. (1991). Intelligence without represen-
tation. Artificial Intelligence, 47,139-159.
115
I N N A T E N E S S AND THE SITUATED MIND

Butler, K. L. (1998). Internal affairs: Making Fodor, J. (197.5). The language of thought Cam-
room for psychosemantic intemalism. Boston: bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Kluwer. Fodor, J. (1981). The present status of the innate-
Carey, S. (1995). Conceptual change in childhood. ness controversy. In J. Fodor (Ed.), Represen-
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. tations (pp. 257-316). Cambridge, MA: MIT
Churchland, P. S., R amacbandran, V., & Press.
Sejnowski, T. (1994). A critique of pure vision. Fodor, J. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cam-
In C. Koch & J. Davis (Eds.), Large-scale neu- bridge, MA: MIT Press.
ronal theories of the brain (pp. 23-60). Cam- Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics: The problem of
bridge, MA: MIT Press. meaning in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge,
Clark, A. (1989). Microcognition: Philosophy, cog- MA: MIT Press.
nitive science and parallel distributed processing. Fodor, J. (1990). A theory of content and other
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Clark, A. (1995). Moving minds: Situating con- Fodor, J. (1998). Concepts: Where cognitive science
tent in the service of real-time success. In went wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
J. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives: Fodor, J. (2003). Hume variations. Oxford:
Vol. 9. Al, connectionism, and philosophi- Oxford University Press.
cal psychology (pp. 89-104). Atascadero, CA: Gallistel, C. R. (1990). The organization of learn-
Ridge view. ing. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, Goldin-Meadow, S., & Zheng, M. (1998).
and world together again. Cambridge, MA: Thought before language: The expression of
MIT Press. motion events prior to the impact of a con-
Clark, A. (1998). Magic words: How language ventional language model. In P. Carruthers 8c
augments human computation. In P. Car- J. Boucher (Eds.), Language and thougfit: Inter-
ruthers &. J. Boucher (Eds.), Language and disciplinary themes (pp. 26-54). Cambridge:
thought: Interdisciplinary themes (pp. 162-183). Cambridge University Press.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Griffiths, P. (2002). What is innateness? Monist,
Clark, A. (2003). Natural-born cyborgs. Oxford: 85, 70-85-
Oxford University Press. Griffiths, P., | Gray, R. (2004). The devel-
Clark, A. (2005). Intrinsic content, active mem- opmental systems perspective: Organism-
ory, and the extended mind. Analysis, 65,1—11. environment systems as units of development
Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended and evolution. In K. Preston & M. Pigliucci
mind. Analysis, 58, 7-19. (Eds.), Phenotypic integration: Studying the ecol-
Clark, A., & Thornton, C. (1997). Trading spaces: ogy and evolution of complex phenotypes (pp.
Computation, representation, and the limits 409-431). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
of uninformed learning. Behavioral and Brain Griffiths, P., & Stotz, K. (2000). How the mind
Sciences, 20, 57-66. grows: A developmental perspective on the
Cowie, F. (1999). What's within? Nativism recon- biology of cognition. Synthese, 122, 29-51.
sidered. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Grush, R. (1997). The architecture of representa-
Cummins, R. (1996). Representations, targets, and tion. Philosophical Psychology, 10,5-23.
attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Haugeland, J. (1995)- Mind embodied and
Dennett, D. (1987). The intentional stance. Cam- embedded. In Y. Houng & J. Ho (Eds.),
bridge, MA: MIT Press. Mind and cognition (pp. 3-37). Taipei, Taiwan:
Dennett, D. (1996). Kinds of minds: Toward Institute of European and American Studies,
an understanding of consciousness. New York: Academia Sinica.
Basic Books. Houghton, D. (1997). Mental content and exter-
Dretske, F. (1998). Explaining behavior: Reasons nal representations. Philosophical Quarterly,
in a world of causes. Cambridge, MA: MIT 47' l59~i77-
Press. Hurley, S. (1998). Vehicles, contents, conceptual
Elman, J., Bates, E., Johnson, M., Karmiloff- structure, and externalism. Analysis, 58,1-6.
Smith, A., Parisi, D., & Plunkett, K. (1996). Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cam-
Rethinking innateness: A connectionist perspec- bridge, MA: MIT Press.
tive on development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Keil, F. (1989). Concepts, kinds, and cognitive
Press. development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
u6 ROBERT RUPERT

Keil, F. (1990). Constraints on constraints: Sur- theory of mental content. Journal of Philoso-
veying the epigenetic landscape. Cognitive Sci- phy, 98, 499-530.
ence, 14,135-168. Rupert, R. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis
Margolis, E. (1998). How to acquire a concept. of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy,
Mind Language, 13, 347-369. 101, 389-428.
Markman, E. (1989). Categorization and naming Samuels, R. (2002). Nativism in cognitive science.
in children: Problems of induction. Cambridge, Mind & Language, 17, 233-265.
MA: MIT Press. Sterelny, K. (2004). Externalism, epistemic arte-
McClamrock, R. (199;). Existential cognition: facts and the extended mind. In R. Schantz
Computational minds in the world. Chicago: (Ed.), The externalist challenge: New studies
University of Chicago Press. on cognition and intentionality (pp. 239-254).
McGinn, C. (1989). Mental content. Oxford: Basil Berlin: de Gruyter.
Blackwell. Sterelny, K., & Griffiths, P. (1999). Sex and
Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, thought, and death : An introduction to philosophy of biology.
other biological categories: New foundations for Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
realism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Thelen, E., & Smith, L. (1994). A dynamic systems
O'Regan, J. K. (1992). Solving the "real" mysteries approach to the development of cognition and
of visual perception: The world as an outside action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
memory. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 46, Treisman, A. (1998). The perception of features
461-488. and objects. In R. D. Wright (Ed.), Visual
Prinz, J. (2000). The duality of content. Philosoph- attention (pp. 26-54). Oxford: Oxford Univer-
ical Studies, 100,1—34. sity Press.
Rowlands, M. (1999). The body in mind: Under- Varela, F., Thompson, E., 81 Rosch, E. (1991). The
standing cognitive processes. Cambridge: Cam- embodied mind: Cognitive science and human
bridge University Press. experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Rupert, R. (1996). The best test theory of extension. Wilson, R. ( 1 9 9 9 ) . The individual in biology and
Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University psychology. In V. G. Hardcastle (Ed.), Where
of Illinois at Chicago. biology meets psychology: Philosophical essays
Rupert, R. (1998). On the relationship between (pp. 3 5 7 - 3 7 4 ) . Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
naturalistic semantics and individuation crite- Wilson, R. ( 2 0 0 4 ) . Boundaries of the mind: The
ria for terms in a language of thought. Syn- individual in the fragile sciences. Cambridge:
these, 117, 95-131. Cambridge University Press.
Rupert, R. (1999). The best test theory of exten- Wimsatt, W. ( 1 9 9 9 ) . Generativity, entrenchment,
sion: First principle(s). Mind & Language, 14, evolution, and innateness: Philosophy, evolu-
321-355- tionary biology, and conceptual foundations
Rupert, R. (2001). Coining terms in the language of science. In V. G. Hardcastle (Ed.), Where
of thought: Innateness, emergence, and the biology meets psychology: Philosophical essays
lot of Cummins's argument against the causal (pp. 1 3 9 - 1 7 9 ) . Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
CHAPTER 7

Situated Representation

Mark Rowlands

PART I: CRITERIA OF constraint is less than transparent. First,


REPRESENTATION none of these "generally accepted" con-
straints on representation comes even close
In the voluminous literature on the sub- to univocal acceptance; and some con-
ject, it is possible to identify six generally straints are more controversial than others.
accepted criteria of representation: (1) the Second, on certain interpretations, some of
combinatorial constraint, fizj the informa- the constraints are incompatible with oth-
tional constraint, (3) the teleological con- ers. Third, none of the conditions in itself
straint, (4) the decouplability constraint, (5) is taken to be sufficient for representation.
the misrepresentation constraint, and (6) the However - and this is why the constraints
causal constraint. The final constraint claims count as constraints - if we assume that a
that in order for an item, r, to qualify as naturalistic account of representation is pos-
a representation, it must play an appropri- sible, there is general consensus that the con-
ate role in guiding a subject's behavior. The ditions collectively provide a necessary and
first five constraints can be regarded as con- sufficient condition for representation. That
straints on what makes an item representa- is, if any item were to satisfy all five condi-
tional: that is, the sort of item that could tions, then it would count as a representa-
be about something else. The final con- tion if anything does.'
straint provides an additional condition that This chapter divides fairly naturally into
an item must meet in order to be counted two halves. The first half surveys and expli-
not only as representational but also as a rep- cates each of the first five constraints; that is,
resentation. In this chapter, I shall have little the constraints that delineate, given broadly
to say about the causal constraint but a lot naturalistic assumptions, which sorts of
to say about the first five constraints on the items might qualify as representational. The
list. second half shows how the constraints apply
Even focusing only on the first five con- in the specific context of situated models of
straints, however, the logical status of each cognition.
117
MARK ROWLANDS

i. The Combinatorial Constraint them. Thus, any relation between a word


and object that is to count as reference must
It is often claimed that for any item to count potentially satisfy clauses of the form: if F
as representational, it must form part of a refers to dogs and a refers to Nina, then Fa is
general representational scheme or frame- true if, and only if, Nina is a dog. A relation
work (Haugeland, 1991, p. 62). That is, a that did not meet this requirement would
representational stand-in must be part of a not count as reference, at least not of the
larger scheme of stands-ins. This allows the sort that can legitimately be applied to sub-
standing in to occur systematically and for sentential components. And the reason is, of
a variety of related representational states. course, that this relation would not be
In other words, representational items are appropriately connected to the concept of
subject to a combinatorial constraint: truth.
However, it would be a mistake to sup-
Combinatorial constraint: For any item r to pose that all representational systems pos-
qualify as representational, it must occur not sess semantic structure. For example, a cog-
in isolation but only as part of a more general nitive map (or mental model), like any map,
representational framework. mirrors (i.e., is geometrically isomorphic
with) the region it maps, and it does so if
The combinatorial requirement is contro- it accurately replicates the region's geomet-
versial, but much of this controversy can be ric features. In doing so, a cognitive map
obviated by careful attention to two distinc- is clearly a representational item. But the
tions: (1) the distinction between semantic notions of truth and reference that under-
and iconic forms of representation and (2) lie the representational features of proposi-
the vehicle-content distinction. tions are not applicable to cognitive maps.
Crucially, the concept of geometric isomor-
Semantic and Iconic Representations phism does not interact in the same way
with the logical connectives. The negation of
The most familiar example of a representa- a sentence is another sentence. But the nega-
tional system that satisfies the combinatorial tion of a map is not a map. To the extent we
condition is human language. In virtue of can make sense of a negated map, the idea
its structure, linguistic forms are suscepti- would be that a negated map is a different
ble to certain sorts of transformation. This map. So, in this sense of negation, any map
susceptibility is underwritten by semantic distinct from m would be a negation of m.
structure; specifically, which modes of com- Yet, it is not true that any sentence distinct
bination are permitted and which are not from p is a negation of p. Similarly, what is
are determined by their relation to semantic the geometric analogue of disjunction? The
properties such as truth and reference. Thus, disjunction of two maps is not itself a map -
the paradigmatic combinatorial mechanisms but the disjunction of two sentences is a sen-
are the logical connectives: and, or, not, if tence.
and then, some, all, and so on. The fact that These sorts of points are familiar ones
the sentences of a language are truth evalu- (see McGinn, 1989). They are rehearsals of
able entails that the language admits struc- the idea that the way a model represents
turing by way of these connectives. Thus, the world is different from the way a sen-
when we talk about the truth of a sen- tence represents the world. Nevertheless, a
tence or proposition, we are talking about mental model is certainly no less a repre-
a property that bears this sort of relation sentational device than a sentence of "men-
to the logical connectives. Second, the con- talese." Thus, while we might accept that
cept of reference, as applied to constituents any representational item must be part of
of propositions, is a function of the contri- a general representational framework, we
bution these constituents make to the truth should reject the claim that the mode of
conditions of the propositions that contain combination involved in such a framework
SITUATED REPRESENTATION «9

must be semantic. Mental models are what ity of s given r must be 1. A weaker version
we might call "iconic representations." Cor- of the informational constraint (e.g., Lloyd,
rectness conditions for representations are 1989) associates an increase in conditional
not coextensive with truth conditions; and probability but not necessarily an increase
the domain of representation is broader than to the value of 1. On this weaker view, r will
the domain of reference. 2 carry information about s if the probability
of s given r is greater than the probability of
Vehicles and Contents s given not r.
On either account of information, the
Transformations of the sort characterized
concept of information can be further expli-
formally by way of the logical connectives
cated in terms of the concept of law. On
are expressions of certain transitions that the
the more stringent conception of informa-
content of representations may undergo. To
tion that requires a conditional probability
use these to deduce claims about the struc-
of 1, the laws in question must be strict. On
ture of the representational vehicles of that
the weaker conception of information, the
content would be to fall victim to a vehicle-
laws in question need be only probabilistic
content confusion. Thus, we cannot, legiti-
rather than strict. But, in both cases, the idea
mately, use these sorts of transformations to
of information can be further explained in
argue for a language-of-thought hypothesis.
terms of the concept of law. Therefore, if r
The representational properties of represen-
consists of a mechanism M's going into state
tations may be intimately bound up with
F, and s consists in the world W being in con-
patterns of semantic combination, but this
dition G, then r carries information about s
does not entail that the vehicles that carry
if, and only if, it is a law that M is F only if
these properties are similarly structured. All
W i s G.
we can conclude, in fact, is this: in the case of
Informational approaches to representa-
some representations, the representational
tion are committed to regarding informa-
vehicles need to be such that the content
tion as a perfecdy objective commodity. The
they bear is susceptible to the sort of trans-
strategy is to explain the representational
formations licensed by the logical connec-
in terms of the informational. This strat-
tives. This does not entail that the vehicles
egy would be obviously circular if the infor-
themselves be structured in the same way as
mational were dependent on the represen-
the content.
tational. The objectivity of information is
also evident in the response of informational
approach to what is known as the "prob-
2. The Informational Constraint
lem of the relativity of information." The
information that r carries about s may, it
Many people, though by no means all, claim
seems, vary depending on what information,
that the idea of representation can be cap-
Q, is already available to the subject of r.
tured, in part, in terms of the concept of
Dretske (1981, pp. 78-81) provides what has
information:
become a well-known illustration. Consider
Informational constraint: An item r qualifies four shells, beneath one of which is a peanut.
as a representational item only if it carries Suppose person A has already turned shells
information about some state of affairs s that 1 and 2 and found them empty. Person B has
is extrinsic to it. not. If so, then finding shell 3 empty does
not supply A and B with the same informa-
Information is generally understood as tion. Finding shell 3 empty informs A that
consisting of relations of conditional proba- the peanut is under shell 4, but informs B
bility. The most uncompromising account of only that it is under shell 1, 2, or 4.
information associates it with a conditional This relativity of information seems,
probability of 1 (Dretske, 1981). So, for r to prima facie, to provide a problem for the
carry the information that s, the probabil- attempt to reduce the representational to
120 MARK ROWLANDS

the informational. The difference in infor- ing of HORSE. According to informational


mation acquired by A and B derives from the accounts, representation is to be explained
fact that prior to the turning over of shell 3, in terms of nomic dependence. However, if
A knew things that B did not or was aware the representation H O R S E can be tokened
of things of which B was not. But knowing in the absence of horses, then H O R S E does
is a representational state; and so the rela- not seem nomically dependent on horses.
tivity of information seems to indicate that Rather, what HORSE does seem nomically
the attempt to reduce the representational dependent on is not the property of being a
to the informational is circular. horse but the disjunctive property of being a
I think that Dretske's (1981) attempt to horse or a donkey in the distance or a cow on
deal with this problem is exactly right. a dark night. Thus, if information is a matter
According to Dretske, we must clearly dis- of nomic dependence, and if representation
tinguish the idea that the information con- is purely a matter of information, then we
tained in a signal is relative, in general, from seem forced to say that what H O R S E rep-
the idea that it is relative specifically to the resents is not the property of being a horse
representational states of a subject. In the but the preceding disjunctive property.
case of the shells, the information is relative It might be thought that we could avoid
simply to further information - information this problem simply by abandoning the
contained in the configurations of the shells stringent version of the concept of informa-
and their history - but not relative to repre- tion - the version that associates information
sentational states of these subjects. with a conditional probability of 1. Then, the
Another important implication of the fact that HORSE is not correlated in a strict
concept of information as nomic depen- exceptionless way with horses would not
dence is that information is ubiquitous. It count against the former carrying informa-
exists wherever there are nomic dependen- tion about the latter. However, this response
cies of the required sort. Such dependencies fails to understand the real problem. This
may exist between an internal configuration is a problem concerning the normativity of
and an external state of affairs. But, equally, representation, and, as such, is indifferent to
they can exist in the relation between two the character of the laws thought to under-
external, and nonmental, states of affairs. write the concept of information: for both
A persistent problem for purely informa- strict and probabilistic laws fail to accom-
tional approaches has been accommodating modate this normative dimension. Thus, it
the normativity of representation. If r repre- is true that the tokening of H O R S E in a sub-
sents that s, then given the instantiation of ject might increase the probability of there
r, the world should be s. To see the prob- being a horse in the environment. However,
lem, consider a now-classic example from the tokening of HORSE, we are supposing,
Fodor (1990). Let us refer to the representa- can also be caused by donkeys in the dis-
tion of a horse by way of the capitalized tance and cows on a dark night but not,
HORSE. The representation HORSE, it presumably, by other things. Therefore, the
seems, means "horse." And, at the very least, tokening of HORSE also increases the prob-
this means that the tokening of the represen- ability of there being a cow or donkey in the
tation makes a normative claim about the environment.
way the world should be. When HORSE is Even if we retreat to the more sophisti-
tokened, the environment should contain, cated idea of relative increases in conditional
in an appropriate way, a horse. However, probability - the idea that H O R S E means
it also seems possible, indeed likely, that "horse" because the probability of the latter
HORSE can be caused by things that are not given the former is greater than the prob-
horses. Donkeys in the distance and cows on ability of the presence of cows or donkeys
a dark night might, in certain circumstances, given the latter - the problem of norma-
be equally efficacious in causing a token- tivity remains. In such cases, the problem
SITUATED REPRESENTATION 121

can be made graphic by considering vari- F in the past, and X exists because of this
ous twin- or inverted-Earth-type scenarios performance; or (2) X is the product of a
where malign or unfortunate environmen- device that had the performance of F as a
tal circumstances have conspired to remove proper function and normally performs F by
horses from the environment while making way of producing an item like X.
subjects incapable of registering this fact. If This definition, though simplified, takes
HORSE is tokened, then the world should some unpacking. The concept of a proper
contain, in the relevant way, a horse. But function is a normative concept. The proper
nomic dependence - whether strict or prob- function of an item is defined in terms of
abilistic - is not normative in this way. The what an item should do, not what it gener-
representation HORSE is nomically con- ally does or is disposed to do. What some-
nected to whatever does, in fact, produce thing does, or is disposed to do, is not always
it and not to what should produce it. Thus, what it is supposed to do. This is for three
to arrive at an adequate account of repre- reasons. First, any mechanism, trait, or pro-
sentation, we need to inject an element of cess will do many things, not all of which are
normativity that is lacking on the purely part of its proper function. A heart pumps
informational approach. This has led many blood; it also makes a thumping noise and
to suppose that informational accounts need produces wiggly lines on an electrocardio-
either supplementation with or replacement gram. But only the first of these is its proper
by a teleological account. function, because only pumping blood is
something performed by hearts in the past
that explains the existence of hearts in the
3. The Teleological Constraint present. Second, a mechanism, trait, or pro-
cess can have a proper function even if it
Many suppose that models of representa- never, or hardly ever, performs it. To use
tion are subject to a teleological constraint. a flagship example of Millikan's, the proper
Roughly: function of the tail of a sperm cell is to pro-
pel the cell to the ovum. The vast majority
Teleological constraint: An item r qualifies as of sperm cell tails, however, do not accom-
representational only if it has the proper plish this task. Third, a mechanism, trait,
function either of tracking the feature or or process may have a proper function and
state of affairs s that produces it, or of yet not be able to perform it properly. A
enabling an organism or other representa- person's heart may be malformed and thus
tional consumer to achieve some (beneficial) not able to pump blood properly. Never-
task in virtue of tracking s.' theless, pumping blood is its proper func-
tion because ancestors of the person whose
Central to teleological approaches is the heart it is had hearts that pumped blood and
concept of proper function. The proper this (in part) explains why they survived and
function of some mechanism, trait, state, or proliferated and, thus, why the person in
process is what it is supposed to do, what question possesses a heart.
it has been designed to do, what it ought to Underlying the normativity of proper
do. Consider the following simplified ver- functions is their essentially historical char-
sion of Millikan's already-simplified version acter. The proper function of an item is
of her definition of proper function given determined not by the present characteris-
in Language, Thought, and Other Biological tics or dispositions of that item but by its
Categories (1984).4 history. This is the import of (i) in Milli-
An item X has proper function F only if kan's definition of proper function. Hearts
(1) X is a reproduction of some prior item have the proper function of pumping blood
that, because of the possession of certain because hearts possessed by our ancestors
reproduced properties, actually performed succeeded in pumping blood, and we have
122 MARK ROWLANDS

hearts today because the hearts of our ances- are derived from the proper functions of
tors were successful in this regard. That (i) the mechanisms that produce them.*
be satisfied is a necessary condition of an
item possessing what Millikan calls a "direct
proper function." Such possession is essen- Like direct proper functions, both adapt-
tially a matter of history. There are no first- ed and derived proper functions are norma-
generation direct proper functions. tive in character. However, unlike direct
There is, however, an important distinc- proper functions, there can be first-
tion to be observed between (1) direct, (2) generation adapted and derived proper func-
adapted, and (3) derived proper functions. tions. The pigmentation mechanism has the
For example, chameleons are able to cam- adapted proper function of producing a
ouflage themselves. They do this by way of Pollockian skin pattern, and the pattern has
a pigmentation mechanism that alters the the derived proper function of matching the
distribution of pigment in the chameleon's chameleon to the Pollock No. 4, even if no
skin. chameleon has been placed on a Pollock No.
4 before - hence, even if the pattern has
1. The direct proper function of the pig- never been produced before.
mentation mechanism is to cause the The proper function - whether direct,
chameleon's skin to match its immedi- adapted, or derived - of many evolved items
ate surroundings. The chameleon pos- is often relational in character. A device has a
sesses this (token) mechanism because relational proper function if it is its function
its ancestors possessed (token) mecha- to produce something that bears a specific
nisms that performed this function. It relation to something else - for example,
is the performing of the function that the relation "same color as." More generally,
explains why such mechanisms prolif- many evolved devices have proliferated pre-
erated. cisely because they enable the organism to
2. Suppose, now, that the chameleon is cope with its environment: to locate food,
placed in a particular immediate en- evade predators, protect itself from heat and
vironment. In fact, let's make the cold, and so on. This is what underwrites
chameleon work hard and place it on a their relational character. All of the three
Jackson Pollock No. 4. The chameleon's types of proper function identified herein
skin, therefore, takes on a "Pollockian" can be relational.
arrangement. In these circumstances, The core idea of the teleological ap-
the pigmentation mechanism has the proaches to representation is that the mech-
adapted proper function of producing anisms responsible for mental representa-
a Pollockian skin pattern. This is not a tion are evolutionary products, and that we
direct proper function of the device: the can therefore understand representation in
device has not proliferated as a result of terms of the apparatus of direct, adapted,
producing, specifically, Pollockian skin derived, and relational proper functions.
patterns. Producing such a pattern is a Suppose we have a mechanism M that is
proper function only adapted to a given capable of going into a variety of states or
context. Such a pattern is what Millikan configurations. The direct proper function
calls an "adapted device." of mechanism M is, let us suppose, to enable
3. Adapted devices possess derived proper the organism to track various environmental
functions. The derived proper function contingencies. In the event that the environ-
of the Pollockian arrangement of pig- mental contingency is the world W's being
mentation in the chameleon's skin is G, M has, let us suppose, the adapted proper
to match the chameleon to the Jack- function of entering state or configuration F.
son Pollock No. 4 on which the poor And the state that consists in M's being F
chameleon has been placed. In general, has, therefore, the derived proper function
the proper functions of adapted devices of occurring only when W is G. And it is
123
situated representation

this derived proper function that makes M's have internal magnets, magnetosomes,
being F a representation of W ' s being G. which function like compass needles: they
The normativity of proper functions is align the bacteria parallel to the earth's mag-
crucial to this story. M is supposed to netic field. The result is that bacteria in the
enable organism O to track various envi- Northern Hemisphere propel themselves in
ronmental contingencies. To this end it is the direction of geomagnetic north. In the
supposed to go into state F when and only Southern Hemisphere, the magnetosomes
when W is G. A n d M's being F is sup- are reversed, and southern bacteria propel
posed to occur only when W is G. This themselves toward geomagnetic south. T h e
elegant account of the normativity of repre- survival value of these magnetosomes is that
sentation is generally regarded as an impor- they allow the bacteria to avoid the oxygen-
tant strength of the teleological approach rich surface water that would be lethal to
to representation, particularly in compari- them. In the Northern Hemisphere, move-
son with a purely informational alternative. ment toward geomagnetic north will take
Thus, according to teleological approaches, the bacteria away from oxygen-rich surface
HORSE represents the property of being water toward the comparatively oxygen-firee
a horse and not the disjunctive property water lower down.
(horse or donkey in the distance or cow What is the adapted proper function of
on a dark night) because the direct proper the magnetosomes? Is it to indicate the
function of the mechanism M is to adopt direction of geomagnetic north? Or is it to
certain configurations contingent on the indicate the direction of oxygen-free water?
presence of certain environmental states of Geomagnetic north provides the stimulus
affairs. Therefore, M also has the adapted that allows the magnetosomes to perform
proper function of producing H O R S E in their proper function: the magnetosomes
the presence of horses. That is what (pre- track geomagnetic north and track oxygen-
sumably among other things) the mecha- free water only in so far as this is cor-
nism has been selected for. It does not have related with geomagnetic north. But it is
the adapted proper function of producing oxygen-firee water that provides the ben-
HORSE in the presence of donkeys or cows, efit to the organism of the magnetosomes
whether in the distance or on a dark night. tracking geomagnetic north. Is representa-
And, on a teleological account, the content tion determined by stimulus or benefit?
of HORSE derives from the adapted proper Dretske endorses a stimulus-based account:
function of M. Thus, H O R S E is about horses
and not about donkeys, cows, or disjunc- When an indicator, C, indicates both F
tions of the three. Providing a solution to and G, and its indication of G is via its
indication ofF... then despite the fact that
the misrepresentation problem requires, in
it is the existence of G that is most directly
effect, detaching the content of a represen-
relevant to explaining C's recruitment as a
tation from the property with which it is cause of M (F is relevant only in so far as
maximally correlated. A n d this is precisely it indicates that G exists), C acquires the
what the teleological account allows us function of indicating that F. It is F - the
to do. (as it were) maximally indicated state -
that C comes to represent. (Dretske, 1990,
p. 826)
4. Stimulus and Benefit
The magnetosomes, thus, represent geo-
in Teleosemantics
magnetic north. This is the stimulus for
the magnetosome, and representation tracks
The preceding section slid over a cru-
stimulus, not benefit. Millikan, on the other
cial ambiguity in the concept of a proper
hand, endorses a benefit-based approach:
function - whether direct, adapted, or
derived. Consider an example, made famous What the magnetosome represents is
by Dretske (1986). Some marine bacteria only what its consumers require that it
124 mark r o w l a n d s

correspond to in order to perform their has to be set up with the motor cortex. At
tasks. Ignore, then, how the representa- this level, too, we have representational con-
tion .. .is normally produced. Concentrate sumers. These are the mechanisms whose
instead on how the systems that react to the operation will eventually allow the beaver
representation work, on what these systems to dive into the lake. So, in addition to per-
need in order to do their job. What they sonal consumers - other beavers - we also
need is only that the pull be in the direction have subpersonal consumers.
of oxygen-free water at the time. For exam-
ple, they care not at all how it came that This ambiguity passes over and infects the
the pull is in that direction What the notion of a consumer performing its allot-
magnetosome represents, then, is univocal; ted task and the related idea of what it
it represents only the direction of oxygen- needs to do its job. T h e allotted task of the
free water. (Millikan, 1989/1993, p. 93) beaver, in this case, is evading predators. So
what it needs to do its job is that the splash
This disagreement is usually taken as a prob- be, within certain limits, reliably correlated
lem for teleosemantic accounts: the idea is with the presence of predators. So, in the
that because such accounts cannot adjudi- case of personal consumers, one could plau-
cate between stimulus- and benefit-oriented sibly argue that representation tracks ben-
interpretations means that they are com- efit. And as we have seen, this is precisely
mitted to the claim that the content of Millikan's claim. However, w h e n we switch
such representational states is indetermi- to subpersonal consumers, an entirely dif-
nate. However, I think that there is, in ferent story emerges. W h a t do the acoustic
fact, no incompatibility between stimulus- mechanisms responsible for registering the
and benefit-based accounts of representa- tail splash require to do their job? Basically,
tion and no problem of indeterminacy. it seems, they require that the splash has cer-
The notion of a representational con- tain appropriate acoustic properties. What
sumer is ambiguous between personal and do the motor mechanisms that produce the
subpersonal levels. Here is one of Millikan's beaver's rapid motion into the lake require
examples. The beaver's tail splash indicates to do their job? Basically, they require that
danger - typically, the presence of a preda- message of a certain type has been transmit-
tor. When a beaver splashes its tail, other ted from the beaver's perceptual cortex. No
beavers quickly return to the water. If we part of their job requires sensitivity to the
allow that the tail splash is a representation, benefit associated with the splash. Personal-
what, in this case, is the consumer of the level consumers are sensitive to the benefit
representation?6 The most obvious answer of a representational item; subpersonal con-
is other beavers. The consumers of the rep- sumers are not.
resentation are, thus, other organisms. The On the basis of the distinction between
same is true of another example commonly
personal and subpersonal consumers of a
employed by Millikan: the dance of the
representation, we can introduce a corre-
honeybee. Here, the consumers are other
sponding distinction between personal and
bees. In both examples, we have personal-
subpersonal proper functions. This distinc-
level consumers.7 The crucial idea is that the
tion allows us to reconcile stimulus- and
representational consumers are organisms,
benefit-based accounts of representation.
and not internal, subpersonal, mechanisms
Thus, suppose mechanism M of organism P
possessed by organisms.
goes into state S in the presence of environ-
However, beavers do not just jump into mental item E. Going into S in the presence
the water on hearing the tail splash. Their of E is, let us suppose, an adapted proper
motor response is mediated by way of vari- function of M. Then, the orthodox teleo-
ous mechanisms. The acoustic properties of
semantic story is that state S has the derived
• t h e splash have to be registered and trans-
proper function of occurring in the presence
mitted to the brain, and in the brain a link
of E, and thus represents, or is about, or
situated representation
125

means E. The distinction between personal To see why, consider another well-known
and subpersonal proper functions applies to example. Rattlesnakes have certain cells that
the derived proper functions of S; thus, (1) fire only if two conditions are satisfied. First,
subpersonal derived proper function, track- the snake's infrared detectors, situated in
ing E, and (2) personal derived proper func- its nose, must be stimulated. Second, the
tion, enabling P to (p in virtue of tracking visual system must get positive input. T h e
E, where (p denotes a form of action or former condition is satisfied when there is
behavior. a localized source of warmth in its envi-
Generally, a subpersonal derived proper ronment, the latter when there is a local-
function will be to track (i.e., occur in and ized source of movement. When these two
only in the presence of) some or other fea- systems are simultaneously activated, the
ture of the environment. A personal derived snake's hunting mechanisms are engaged.
proper function will be to enable an organ- In the snake's ancestral home, there will
ism to accomplish some or other task indeed be food about, because the com-
in virtue of tracking that feature. Each dis- bined input is typically caused by a field
tinct derived proper function will license the mouse, the snake's usual prey. Of course,
attribution of a distinct content. And, cru- the rattlesnake can be easily fooled. An
cially, they will license the attribution of artificially warmed imitation mouse on the
this distinct content to distinct individuals. end of a stick would do the trick. So,
Subpersonal derived proper functions li- what is the adapted proper function of the
cense the attribution of content to subper- snake's prey-detection mechanism? What
sonal mechanisms. Personal derived proper does it represent? Stimulus-based accounts
functions license the attribution of (a dis- would focus on what activates the mech-
tinct) content to the organism ("person") as anism (i.e., localized warmth and move-
a whole. ment) and claim that the relevant state of
the mechanism represents those features.
Suppose we have an organism O sensi-
Benefit-based accounts would focus on the
tive to some feature of the environment E.
benefit associated with the mechanism per-
On the basis of this sensitivity, let us sup-
forming its proper function - the snake
pose, we can attribute a content Co to the
gets to eat - and claim that the relevant
organism. However, O ' s sensitivity to this
state of the mechanism represents food.
feature of the environment is underwritten
However, the distinction between personal
by mechanism M, whose direct proper func-
and subpersonal derived proper functions
tion is to track a certain range of environ-
allows us to see that these answers are not
mental features and whose adapted proper
incompatible.
function is to enter state S in the presence
of E. Therefore, the derived proper function First, there is the personal derived proper
(see section 3) of S is to track E, and, on the function of the state S of the rattlesnake's
basis of this, we can attribute the content Cm system (S is understood to be a conjunction
to S. It does not follow, however, and indeed of states, one in the infrared detection mech-
is usually false, that Co = Cm- This is true anism and one in the movement detection
even though it is M's being S that allows O mechanism). The personal derived proper
to be sensitive to its environment in a way function of S is to enable the rattlesnake
that warrants the attribution of content Co (the "person") to do something - namely,
to it. That is, even though it is the adapted to detect a certain affordance of the envi-
proper function of M that allows the attri- ronment. S enables the rattlesnake to detect
bution of Cm to S, and even though it is the that the environment affords eating. Thus,
fulfilling of M of its adapted proper function the personal derived proper function of
that allows the content Co to be attributed S is sensitive to the benefit of the prey-
to 0, it does not follow, and indeed is almost detection mechanism fulfilling its adapted
always false, that Co = C M - proper function.
126 MARK ROWLANDS

Second, there is the subpersonal derived in the sense of being able to occur in the
proper function of S. The prey-detection absence of the feature whose function it is
mechanism's fulfilling of its personal derived to track. That provides us with our fourth
proper function is what enables the rat- putative constraint on representation:
tlesnake to detect that the environment
affords eating. However, it does this by way Decouplability Constraint: Item r qualifies as
of a certain method or algorithm: the detec- representing state of affairs s only if r is, in
tion of warmth and movement. The subper- an appropriate sense, decouplable from s.
sonal derived proper function of the state S
of M is to track warmth and movement. This This is one (but, 1 think, not the only) way to
latter proper function is, therefore, sensitive give expression to the idea that representa-
to the stimulus, rather than the benefit, of tions are distinct from what they represent.
the mechanism fulfilling its adapted proper A representation is decouplable when the
function. representing organism is able to deploy it
Each proper function licenses the attri- to guide its behavior in the absence of the
bution of a distinct content to a distinct environmental feature of which that repre-
individual. The personal derived proper sentation is a representation. For something
function warrants the attribution of the con- to count as a representation, it must be the
tent "Eatability, there!" to the ratdesnake sort of thing that is capable of deployment
as a whole. The subpersonal derived proper in off-line contexts. Or, as Haugeland puts
function licenses the attribution of the con- it, to count as a genuinely representation-
tent "Warmth/movement, there!" to the using system, that system must (1) be able to
state S of mechanism M. So not only do we coordinate its behaviors with environmental
have attributions of distinct contents, but features that are not always reliably present
also those attributions are made to distinct to it, and (2) do this by having something
things. else stand in or go proxy for a signal direcuy
In such cases, we have neither indetermi- received from the environment and use this
nacy of function nor indeterminacy of con- to guide behavior in its stead (Haugeland,
tent. We have two individual things - one an 1991).
organism, the other a mechanism - perform- Decouplability is a far more controversial
ing distinct but entirely determinate func- condition on representation than the infor-
tions. Because the resultant contents are also mational or teleological conditions, and it
attributed to distinct things, there is no basis is far from clear that the constraint can be
for the worry that this is a case of the indeter- accepted as a general condition on repre-
minacy of content. Two distinct but entirely sentation. As Andy Clark (1997, pp- >44~
determinate contents do not add up to one 145) points out, at least some cases of rep-
indeterminate content. resentation do not satisfy the decouplability
Seen in this light, stimulus- and benefit- requirement. For example, there is a pop-
based accounts are not competing accounts ulation of neurons in the posterior parietal
of representation. They correspond to two cortex of rats whose function is to carry, by
distinct types of derived proper function. way of an appropriate coding system, infor-
Both stimulus- and benefit-based accounts, mation about the direction in which the rat's
therefore, have a legitimate role to play in a head is facing. However, this population
teleological account of representation. functions only in tandem with a continuous
stream of proprioceptive information from
the rat's body. Thus, it does not seem to sat-
5 . T h e D e c o u p l a b i l i t y Constraint isfy the decouplability requirement. Never-
theless, the neuronal population's function
It is common to hold that, to be regarded as is pretty clearly representational. Glossing
genuinely representational, a representation states of the population as codings for spe-
must be decouplable from the environment, cific head positions allows us to understand
situated representation 127

the flow of information within the system framework for this is provided by what has
(e.g., when we find other neuronal groups become known as "vehicle externalism" or
that consume the information encoded in the "extended mind." 8 The general contours
the target population). Thus, as Clark points of this position are given by way of the fol-
out, treating the neuronal encodings as rep- lowing claims:
resentations buys us genuine explanatory
leverage, and it is, therefore, unclear w h y 1. T h e world is an external store of infor-
we should deny these encodings the status mation relevant to cognitive processes
of representations. Decouplability is, almost such as perceiving, remembering, rea-
certainly, a feature of many representations, soning, and so on.
perhaps most. But it is not clear that it is a
feature of all representations. Still less is it
It is such a store because, as we have seen,
clear that it is a necessary feature of repre-
information is ubiquitous. One item will
sentations.
carry information about another in virtue of
appropriate relations of conditional proba-
bility between them. But such relations can
6. The Misrepresentation Constraint be instantiated in the environment just as
much as in the relation between an internal
As we have seen, in connection with the
representation and its external correlate. In
informational constraint, the possibility of virtue of this, information exists in the envi-
representation is closely tied to the possibil- ronment, and there are certain environmen-
ity of misrepresentation. tal structures that carry information relevant
to cognition.
Misrepresentation Constraint: Item r qualifies
as representing state of affairs s only if it is
capable of misrepresenting s. 2. Cognitive processes are essentially
hybrid - they straddle both internal and
The misrepresentation constraint is not external forms of information process-
controversial. Indeed, it is a relatively ing.
straightforward consequence of the norma- 3. T h e external processes involve manip-
tivity of representation. A representation ulation, exploration, exploitation, and
makes a claim about the way the world transformation of environmental struc-
should be, given that the representation is tures that carry information relevant to
activated, and this must accommodate the the accomplishing of the cognitive task
possibility that the world is not, in fact, at hand.
that way. In this sense, the misrepresenta- 4. At least some of the internal processes
tion constraint is derivative of the norma- involved are ones concerned with sup-
tivity constraint: any model that satisfies the plying the cognizing organism with the
latter automatically satisfies the former also. ability to appropriately use relevant
If you can satisfy the normativity constraint, structures in its environment.
the misrepresentation constraint comes for
free. T h e traditional construal of representa-
tions sees them as internal configurations
of a subject, individuated by way of their
PART II: REPRESENTATION AND higher-order physical or functional proper-
SITUATED COGNITION ties. Different versions of vehicle external-
ism have different conceptions of how much
Much recent work on cognition is charac- of the function of representations, thus con-
terized by an augmentation of the role of strued, can be usurped by action. At one
action coupled with an attenuation of the extreme are eliminativist treatments that see
role of representation. A general theoretical essentially no role left over for traditional
u8 MARK ROWLANDS

representations.g Other versions are less san- direction of a dual-component account of


guine and see the role of action as supple- representation." According to this interpre-
menting, rather than supplanting, that of tation, a case of representation can be fac-
traditional representations.10 However, all tored into two components, one that is gen-
forms of vehicle extemalism agree that at uinely representational and one that is not.
least some of the role of representations, What is involved in being a genuinely rep-
traditionally construed, can be taken over resentational component of action is some-
by action. Accordingly, an appeal to action thing that can be cashed out in terms of
is to be found at the core of any such one's preferred account of the representa-
extemalism. tional relation. This genuinely representa-
tional component, on the dual component
interpretation of the extended model, func-
7. Representation and the Extended tions in tandem with suitable acts of envi-
ronmental action - worldly manipulation,
Mind: Two Interpretations
exploitation, and transformation, for exam-
ple. The relation between these two com-
One claim that unites all forms of vehi-
ponents can be extremely intimate. It may
cle extemalism is that the role traditionally
be, for example, that the genuinely rep-
assigned to representations can, at least to
resentational component of at least some
some extent, be taken over by suitable action
representations has been designed to func-
on the part of the representing organism.
tion in tandem with acts of environmental
In interpreting the role of representation
activity, so that the former cannot fulfill its
within this framework, the first question
function in the absence of the latter. How-
that must be addressed is, Can all of the roles
ever, what is crucial to the dual-component
traditionally assigned to representations be
interpretation is the claim that the action-
played by suitable action on the part of the
based component is (1) logically distinct
representing organism? If you answer yes
from the representational component and
to this question, then you combine vehi-
(2) is not, therefore, itself representational.
cle extemalism with a form of eliminativism
The action-based component allows or facil-
about representation.
itates the genuinely representational compo-
Certain interpretations of vehicle exter- nent, sometimes perhaps essentially, but it
nalism do indeed go hand in hand with a does not itself represent anything.
general antipathy toward the idea of rep-
resentation. For example, many dynamicist For the purposes of this chapter, what
approaches staunchly reject the idea that is important is not how eliminativist and
the concept of a representation will play dual-component interpretations differ but
any genuine role in accounting for cognition. what they share. And what they share is
Among dynamicists, such sentiments have the idea that representation and action are
been expressed by Maturana and Varela two logically distinct activities. Given this
(1980), Skarda and Freeman (1987), Smithers assumption, it becomes a fundamentally
(1994), Thelen and Smith (1994), Wheeler empirical question how much of each activ-
(1994), and van Gelder (1995). Nor are these ity is involved in an organism's ability to
sentiments restricted to narrowly dynami- successfully negotiate its environment. The
cist approaches. In situated robotics, we find eliminativist interpretation says (crudely),
Webb (1994) endorsing a similar rejection "All action, no representation," and the
of representations. And in the very differ- dual-component interpretation says, "Some
ent arena of visual perception, many of the
action, some representation." According
pronouncements of O'Regan and Noe (2001,
to the former, then, action supplants or
2002) seem to veer in this general elimina-
replaces representation; according to the lat-
tivist direction.
ter, action supplements it.
Some, however, answer no to the ques- In the rest of this chapter I shall
tion. This typically drives them in the draw attention to the formidable difficulties
situated representation 129

involved in the claim that action can either many. Thus, if my intention is to pat my
supplant or supplement representation. In head while rubbing my stomach - a single
either case, the appeal to action is in danger intention - then the action counts as one
of being impaled on one or another horn of action. If, on the other hand, I am the subject
a dilemma. of two distinct intentions - to pat my head
and to rub my stomach - which just happen
to be contemporaneously activated, then the
8. The First H o r n : A c t i o n as action counts as two, rather than one.
Presupposing R e p r e s e n t a t i o n Traditional accounts of action make both
the status of an event as an action and its
Traditionally understood, action can neither identity as the particular action it is essen-
supplant nor supplement representation for tially dependent on its relation to other
the simple reason that it presupposes repre- intentional states. But intentional states are
sentation. Specifically, both the status of an individuated by their content. And content
event as an action and its identity as the par- arises through representation. So, the appeal
ticular action it is depend on its connection to action presupposes representation and
to prior intentional, hence representational, therefore cannot be used either to supplant
states. The precise nature of this connection or supplement it.
will depend on which theory of action you
endorse, but all theories assert that there is
some appropriate connection. For example, 9. T h e Second Horn: T h e
suppose you are patting your head while Contribution of Action
rubbing your stomach. What makes this as Merely Causal
an action? On any traditional philosophi-
cal account of action, its status as an action The most obvious response to the first horn
depends on its standing in some appropri- of the dilemma is to recast the type of action
ate connection to intentional, hence repre- involved in the elimination of representation
sentational, states. The term appropriate is as nonintentional activity of some sort. This
defined only within a theory. On a causal response, however, is likely to lead to a dis-
theory of action, for example, appropriate tinct but equally serious problem: it means
is explained in terms of certain sorts of the appeal to action will fail to play the role
causal relations - the movement constitutes required of it. In particular, action will be
an action because it is caused by some prior able to play no role in accounting for the
intentional state or complex - an intention, normativity of representation.
volition, belief-desire coupling, and so on.
The danger underlying the second hom
Other theories give very different accounts
of the dilemma is that the retreat from an
of what an appropriate relation is, but all
intentional conception of action will leave us
assert that bearing some relation to other
with something very much like bodily move-
intentional states is essentially involved in
ment. And the contribution that bodily
being an action (as opposed to bodily move-
movement can make to representation is a
ment).
purely causal one. This causal contribution
Second, consider the identity of actions. may, at some level, be extremely useful in
Is patting your head while rubbing your helping us represent the world. It may play a
stomach one action, or two, or many? Again, very important role in facilitating our ability
on traditional accounts, the individuation of to represent the world. However, this facil-
actions is essentially bound up with the indi- itatory role is restricted to causal impinge-
viduation of other intentional states. Return- ments: it allows us to causally affect the
ln
g to the causal theory, for example, the world in new and expedient ways, but it has
idea would be that if the intention or voli- no normative dimension.
tion that causes my action is a single state, This interpretation entails that action can
tnen the action counts as one rather than play no role in explaining the normative
83 mark r o w l a n d s

dimension of representation. But this it is a part not provided by any internal rep-
dimension of representation derives from its resentational core.
content - it is because representations pos- It is characteristic of vehicle externalist
sess content that they make claims about the approaches, to the extent they have any-
way the world should be. This means that if thing to say about representation, to be
the action-based component of representa- committed to the claim that the content of
tion plays a purely causal, facilitatory role, representations exceeds that which can be
then it can play no role in explaining repre- provided by what is inside the head of the
sentational content. To do so, it would have representing subject. But content, however
to be possible to factor off content into nor- it is constituted, is an essentially normative
mative and nonnormative components. But phenomenon. Therefore, if the conception
normativity is an essential feature of con- of action we employ to explain or explain
tent; anything that is to count as content away this content is nonnormative — if, for
must be normative. Therefore, it is not pos- example, we invoke a merely causal con-
sible to factor off content in this way. There- ception of action - then this conception of
fore, any purely causal component of repre- action cannot explain what it is required
sentation could play no role in explaining to explain. No addition of nonnormative
representational content. material can ever provide us with an under-
Given one further assumption, however, standing of a phenomenon that is essentially
this failure of a purely causal conception of normative. No number of exculpations can
action to play a role in explaining repre- ever add up to a justification. This is not
sentational content leads to serious trouble to deny, of course, that the action-based
for the idea that action can be employed to dimension of representation does provide
either supplant or supplement representa- us with additional means of causally affect-
tion. The assumption is this: the norma- ing the world. There is a causal story to tell
tively constrained content of a representa- here. But if the normative dimension of rep-
tion exceeds that which can be provided resentation exceeds that which can be pro-
by any internal, genuinely representational vided by the internal, genuinely representa-
core. Most forms of vehicle externalism, if tional, component alone, and if action is to
they have anything at all to say about repre- play a role in representation, there must be
sentation, are committed to this claim.11 more than a causal story to tell about this
To take just one example, consider the role. In such circumstances, action must be
enactive or sensorimotor model of visual infused with normativity if it is to play any
perception developed by O'Regan and Noe role in helping us understand representation.
(2001, 2002) and Noe (2004). They have The action-based dimension must itself be
shown that our sense of encountering in normative; it must be part of the space of
perception a complex, rich, and detailed reasons.
world is something that cannot be explained
purely by reference to what is going on
inside the head - for what is going on there 10. Representation in Action
can, at most, provide us with the rough gist
of the situation. Rather, our sense of encoun- We are now in a position to appreciate the
tering a complex, rich, and detailed world is problematic nature of an appeal to action
underwritten, partly but essentially, by the in our attempt to understand - explain or
fact that the world we encounter is visually explain away - representation. In the tradi-
complex, rich, and detailed, and we exploit tional sense of action, both the status of an
this complexity, richness, and detail in the item as an action and its identity as the par-
formation of our experiences. This complex- ticular action it is derive from its connection
ity, richness, and detail is, accordingly, part to antecedent intentional, hence representa-
of the content of our visual experience, but tional, states. Therefore, to appeal to action
84
situated representation

in this sense is to presuppose representation if the action acquires its normative status
rather than explain it. from something else - for example, from a
Essentially the same problem would also prior intentional state. But suppose, how-
arise if we were to appeal to a conception of ever, that the normative status of the action
action that inherits not full intentional sta- is not derived from anything else. Sup-
tus from antecedent representational states pose actions can be normative for the same
but merely some of the necessary features of reason that intentional states are norma-
representation. For example, if the actions tive. For example, suppose the historical
to which we appeal were to possess a nor- account of normativity defended in part 1
mative status that they have inherited f r o m of this chapter were correct. Then suppose
the normative character of antecedent inten- also that essentially the same story could
tional states, we would be presupposing one be told of at least certain sorts of actions,
of the defining features of representation and could be told quite independently of
rather than explaining it. And, of course, in the connection these states bear to other
the project of understanding representation, intentional, hence representational, states.
this would be a Pyrrhic victory at best. Then, whatever reasons we have for sup-
However, neither can we appeal to a con- posing representational states to be norma-
cept of action that is not normative. We tive, we would also have precisely the same
cannot understand action as merely provid- reasons for supposing that these sorts of
ing us with additional means of causally actions were normative. In such circum-
impinging on or affecting the world. Rep- stances, the appeal to this type of action
resentation is essentially normative, and the would not beg the question. A n d in employ-
normatively constrained content of repre- ing this concept of action, we would not be
sentation exceeds that which can be pro- reiterating a purely causal, nonnormative,
vided by some putative internal represen- conception of the role played by action in
tational core. Therefore, if the conception of representation.
action to which we appeal is not normative, Elsewhere, I argue that the requisite con-
it can play no role in helping us understand ception of action exists. Moreover, these are
representation. precisely the sorts of actions that are likely to
Therefore, the appeal to action faces a be involved in our representing of the world
dilemma. If representation is an essentially (Rowlands, 2006). Moreover, as we have
normative phenomenon, and this normative seen, normativity is likely to lie at the core
dimension exceeds that which can be pro- of any account of representation. A n d this
vided by an internal representational core, raises an even more intriguing possibility:
then appeal to a nonnormative conception that certain sorts of actions themselves sat-
of action can in no way help us understand isfy the criteria of representation discussed
representation. If, on the other hand, we in the first part of this chapter. If this were
appeal to a concept of action that acquires so, then there would be no possibility of
its normative status from antecedent inten- separating off, as the dual-component inter-
tional - hence normative - states, then pretation would have it, the genuinely rep-
we have simply presupposed the most per- resentational from the action-based compo-
plexing feature of representation and not nent of representation. Therefore, a fortiori,
explained it. So, it seems the concept of there is no possibility of eliminating rep-
action to which we appeal in our goal of resentation in favor of action. Actions and
representations do not make even notionally
understanding representation must both be
separable contributions to the overall task of
and yet cannot be a normatively constrained
representing the world. Representation and
concept.
action are, indeed, essentially connected -
There is, however, a way out of this
because acting can be a form of represent-
dilemma. The appeal to a normative con-
ing. Representation does not stop short of its
ception of action will beg the question only
132
MARK ROWLANDS

objects: r e p r e s e n t a t i o n is r e p r e s e n t a t i o n all 7 Here the content of the personal is given sim-


t h e w a y out.13 ply by its opposition to the concept of the
subpersonal. So, there is no claim that bees,
or even beavers, are persons. If you do not like
Acknowledgments the terminology, feel free to replace personal
with organismic (the terminology I employed
I am grateful to the Arts and Humanities Re- in earlier work) .
search Council for providing me with a research- 8 This view of the mind has, in recent years,
leave grant. This chapter was written during been defended by Donald (1991), Hutchins
the period of this grant. Thanks to Chris Elia- (1995), Clark (1997, 2004), Wilson (1995,
smith for comments on an earlier version of this 2004), Clark and Chalmers (1998), Hurley
chapter. (1998), and Rowlands (1999, 2003).
9 Certain dynamicist accounts fit this profile.
See, for example, van Gelder (1995).
Notes 10 See, for example, Clark (1997), Clark and
Toribio (1994), and Rowlands (1999).
11 The label is intended to draw attention to the
1 I do not, in fact, think that a complete
parallels with an interpretation of good old-
account of representation can be given within
fashioned content externalism. For a cogent
a naturalistic framework. This chapter, there-
defense of this interpretation of content
fore, is best viewed as an attempt to e x a m -
externalism, see McGinn (1982).
ine the implications of a naturalistic account
12 For detailed defense of this claim, see Row-
of representation for situated models of
lands (2006).
cognition.
13 1 defend this conception of action in Row-
2 Thus, my interpretation of the combinatorial
lands (2006).
constraint is quite distinct from that made
famous by Fodor. Fodor (1990) argues that
the m o d e of combination invoked by the con-
straint must be semantic. I, for the reasons References
outlined previously, disagree.
3 O n e need not, in fact, regard the teleologi- Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body,
cal constraint as a constraint at all. Rather, and world together again. Cambridge, MA:
one might regard it as a theory introduced MIT Press.
to meet other constraints - for example, the Clark, A. (2003). Natural-bom cyborgs. New York:
misrepresentation constraint. This complica- Oxford University Press.
tion will have little bearing on the discussion Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended
to follow, and one is accordingly free to read mind. Analysis, 58, 7-19.
the teleological account as providing either a Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without
constraint or a theory. representing. Synthese, 101, 401-431.
4 This definition is taken from Millikan (1993, Donald, M. (1991). Origins of the modern mind.
p. 123). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
5 I am going to ignore Millikan's distinc- Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of infor-
tion between adapted derived proper func- mation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
tions and invariant derived proper functions. Dretske, F. (1986). Misrepresentation. In R. Bog-
Although important in some contexts, the dan (Ed.), Belief (pp. 17-36). Oxford: Oxford
distinction will play no role in this chapter. University Press.
6 It is not, in fact, a full-blown representation, Dretske, F. (1990). Reply to reviewers. Philoso-
as it presumably fails to satisfy some of the phy and Phenomenological Research, 1(4), 819-
criteria of representation (e.g., combinato- 839.
rial constraint). It corresponds to w h a t Mil- Fodor, J. (1990). A theory of content and other
likan calls an "intentional icon" rather than essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
a full-blown representation. This does not Haugeland, J. (1991). Representational genera. In
matter for our purposes. W h a t does matter W. Ramsey, S. Stich, & J. Garron (Eds.), Phi-
is that it has at least proto-representational losophy and connectionist theory (pp. 61-89).
status. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
86
S I T U A T E D REPRESENTATION

Hurley, S. (1998). Consciousness in action. C a m - standing cognitive processes. Cambridge: C a m -


bridge, MA: Harvard University Press. bridge University Press.
Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. C a m - Rowlands, M. (2003). Extemalism: Putting mind
bridge, MA: MIT Press. and world back together again. London: A c u -
Lloyd, D. (1989). Simple minds. Cambridge, M A : men.
MIT Press. Rowlands, M. (2006). Body language: Representa-
Maturana, H., & Varela, F. (1980). Autopoiesis tion in action. Cambridge, M A : M I T Press.
and cognition. Dordrecht, T h e Netherlands: Skarda, C., 81 Freeman, W. (1987). H o w brains
Reidel. make chaos in order to make sense of the
McGinn, C. (1982). The structure of content. world. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 10, 161-
In A. Woodfield (Ed.), Thought and object *95-
(pp. 207-258). Oxford: O x f o r d University Smithers, T. (1994). Why better robots make it
Press. harder. In D. Cliff, P. Husbands, J. Meyer, 81
McGinn, C. (1989). Mental content. Oxford, UK: S. Wilson (Eds.), From animals to animats 3
Blackwell. (pp. 64-72). Cambridge, M A : M I T Press.
Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought and other Thelen, E., & Smith, L. (1994). A dynamic systems
biological categories. Cambridge, M A : M I T approach to the development of cognition and
Press. action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Millikan, R. (1989/1993). Biosemantics. In R. Mil- van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be,
likan (Ed.), White queen psychology and other if not computation? Journal of Philosophy, 91,
essays for Alice (pp. 83-101). Cambridge, M A :
345-3 8 1 -
MIT Press. (Reprinted from Journal of Philos-
Webb, B. (1994). Robotic experiments in cricket
ophy, 86,281-297.)
phonotaxis. In D. Cliff, P. Husbands, J.
Millikan, R. (1993). White queen psychology and
Meyer, 8c S. Wilson (Eds.), From animals to
other essays for Alice. Cambridge, M A : M I T
animats 3 (pp. 45-54). Cambridge, M A : M I T
Press. Press.
Noe, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, Wheeler, M. (1994). From activation to activ-
MA: MIT Press. ity. Artificial Intelligence and the Simulation of
O'Regan, J. K., & Noe, A. (2001). A sensorimo- Behaviour Quarterly, 87, 36-42.
tor account of vision and visual consciousness. Wilson, R. (1995). Cartesian psychology and phys-
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23, 939-973. ical minds: Individualism and the sciences of the
O'Regan, J. K., & Noe, A. (2002). What it is like mind. N e w York: Cambridge University Press.
to see: A sensorimotor theory of perceptual Wilson, R. (2004). Boundaries of the mind: The
experience. Synthese, 79, 79-103. individual in the fragile sciences. N e w York:
Rowlands, M. (1999). The body in mind: Under- Cambridge University Press.
CHAPTER 8

Dynamics, Control, and Cognition

Chris Eliasmith

i. Once upon Real Time which many of these same contemporary


theorists agree). After a discussion of the
A dynamic object is an object whose prop- importance and roots of dynamics in cog-
erties change over time. A static object is an nitive theorizing, I describe the role of time
object whose properties do not change over in each of the three main approaches to cog-
time. Given such an idealization, the notion nitive science: symbolicism, connectionism,
of "static" lies at an extreme end of the spec- and dynamicism. Subsequendy, I outline a
trum of temporal relations between objects recently proposed method, the neural engi-
and properties. Indeed, modem physics tells neering framework (NEF), that, unlike past
us that no objects are truly static. Neverthe- approaches, permits a principled integration
less, many of our physical, computational, of dynamics into biologically realistic mod-
and metaphysical theories turn a blind eye els of high-level cognition. After briefly pre-
to the role of time, often for practical rea- senting a model, BioSLIE, that demonstrates
sons. So, perhaps it is not surprising that this integration using the NEF, I argue that
in the philosophy of mind - where phys- this approach alone is in a position to prop-
ical, computational, and metaphysical the- erly integrate dynamics, biological realism,
ories meet - there has been a consistent and high-level cognition.
tendency to articulate theories that con- Historically, many cognitive theories
sider function and time independently. As have not been particularly informed by our
a result, contemporary theories in cogni- understanding of biological systems. Argu-
tive science consider time unsystematically ably, this is because our understanding of
(for specific examples, see the next section). the mechanisms driving biological systems
In this chapter, 1 suggest that the prob- was in its infancy until very recently. This
lem with this "ad-hockery" is that the sys- suggests that there was little opportunity
tems we are trying to characterize are real- for theories of mind to gain insight from
time systems, whose real-time performance our understanding of the kinds of systems
demands principled explanation (a point on that putatively have minds. So, there was

»34
DYNAMICS, CONTROL, AND COGNITION 135

little inspiration to be drawn from biology quence. And it was clear to anyone studying
regarding mentality. However, recent de- computer systems that the central proces-
cades have seen a radical change in this state sor was the most important part of the sys-
of affairs. Neuroscience, the subdiscipline of tem. This characterization is efficiently cap-
biology most relevant to theories of mind, tured in the now-famous mind-as-computer
began to systematically explore neural metaphor that has so dominated the history
mechanisms only quite recently (e.g., after of cognitive science.
the pioneering experiments of Hodgkin & Perhaps one way to move past this
Huxley, 1952; Hubel & Wiesel, 1962; Wiesel metaphor for mind is to learn more about
& Hubel, 1963).1 Despite these relatively the target of the metaphor. That is, it may
recent beginnings, the annual conference be no coincidence that, as our understand-
of the Society for Neuroscience features ing of the brain has improved, the standard
approximately thirty thousand attendees, conception of cognition has become more
most of whom are directly involved in dynamical. In other words, I suspect that the
exploring the mechanisms of the brain. I sus- broad dynamical shift of cognitive science is
pect that all of them, almost without excep- widely inspired by the "neuralizing" of the
tion, are acutely aware of the dynamics of discipline.
the mechanisms they are studying. Although our improved understanding of
The importance of the dynamics of neu- neural mechanisms has likely cemented the
ral mechanisms for understanding the brain importance of dynamics for understanding
can be gleaned from the kinds of vocabu- cognition, another route to this view can be
lary typically employed by neuroscientists. found in the history of psychology. In par-
They inevitably speak of time constants; ticular, the work of psychologist J. J. Gibson
time courses; fluctuations; firing rates; spike- and his colleagues at Cornell University pro-
timing dependent plasticity; oscillations; vides further impetus for taking dynamics
molecular kinetics; membrane dynamics; seriously (Gibson, 1966; Gibson & Gibson,
protein dynamics; short and long-term plas- 1955). In fact, the focus of this research was
ticity; synchrony; temporal correlations; and not on dynamics per se but on the active role
so on. In other words, a careful examination that a perceiver takes in exploiting its own
of the mechanisms underlying mental phe- motion to extract relevant information or
nomena have demanded temporally laden to underwrite environmental interactions.
descriptions. Gibson described agents as resonating with
Of course, there is no obvious reason why certain information in their environment
it is necessary to learn about the brain before that is relevant for their potential actions.
gleaning the importance of dynamics. Per- His well-known notion of an "affordance"
haps the traditional division between cogni- captures this theoretical position. It is afford-
tion and perception/action, reflected neatly ances, after all, that agents are specially
in the notion of humans as rational animals, tuned to pick up as environmental objects of
suggested to many early cognitive scientists interest to them (e.g., a tree stump affords
that rationality, a reasonably outside-of-time living quarters for an insect but a seat for us).
kind of behavior, is their target of inquiry. This emphasis on the environment, and
Unfortunately, this view relegates many of on the relation between agents and envi-
the dynamical aspects of behavior to the ronments, has served as a theoretical prede-
status of an afterthought. No doubt this cessor to the contemporary concern for the
perspective was bolstered by the develop- situatedness and embodiedness of agents.2
ment of the von Neumann architecture for Such theories, including Gibson's original
computers, which neatly distinguishes input characterization, focus attention on move-
and output functions from central process- ments of an agent within an environment.
ln
8/ whose temporal properties are deter- This necessarily highlights the importance
mined by a clock that can be sped up or of characterizing both environmental and
slowed down with little functional conse- agent-centered dynamics. For instance, an
CHRIS ELIASMITH

approach to characterizing visual percep- In short, experimental considerations of


tion championed by Dana Ballard, animate neural mechanisms and theoretical consid-
vision, focuses on determining what infor- erations of agent-environment interactions
mation agents actively extract from a visual conspire to suggest that dynamics are an
scene through rapid eye movements, rather inescapable feature of cognitive systems.
than taking the traditional Marrian approach This is in contrast to the traditional view
of trying to reconstruct the entire visual that cognitive systems are best character-
scene in a three-dimensional internal rep- ized through a firm theoretical grounding
resentation (Ballard, 1991). It is the dynam- in computational theory. The problem with
ics of the agent and the environment that this traditional picture is that artificial intel-
determine what information is available to ligence and computer science researchers
be acted on. are not especially interested in dynamical
Despite the fact that traditional com- systems. That is, although the design of
putational approaches to understanding real-time systems is only one small part of
cognitive function often label themselves computer science, the only kind of systems
"information-processing approaches," the ever designed by Mother Nature are real-
strongest arguments for the importance of time systems. At the moment, by far the
situatedness come from information theo- most impressive cognitive systems are natu-
retic considerations. Simply put, there is too ral ones.
much information in an environment for
any known sensory organ to extract it all.
Sensory organs clearly have limited band- 2. Dynamic Duels: Dynamics
width; that is, a limited ability to extract and Cognitive Architectures
the various information available in natu-
ral environments. And although there is evi- Having briefly argued for the importance
dence that many such systems are near their of dynamics to understanding cognition, I
theoretical limits for extracting information turn to the issue of how dynamics have been
(Rieke, Warland, de Ruyter van Steveninick, integrated into various theories of cognition.
& Bialek, 1997), even reaching such limits After a brief historical discussion, I describe
will not ameliorate the problem of dealing the strengths and weaknesses of the three
with all the information in an environment. main contenders in cognitive science, espe-
Given such hard constraints, it is not sur- cially in relation to their incorporation of
prising that biological systems have devel- time into their methods of model construc-
oped various means of targeting evolution- tion.
arily relevant information sources in their
environment. It is those sources, after all,
2.1. Behaving in Time
that determine whether they live or die. As
a result of these considerations it becomes In the early part of the past century, the
clear that how these systems target informa- dominant theory in psychology was behav-
tion is as important as how they pick up that iorism. Famously, behaviorism espoused the
information once they are oriented toward view that the only scientifically respectable
it. Furthermore, if those methods of tar- "observables" that could underwrite a psy-
geting are highly sensitive to environmental chological theory were behavioral events.
dynamics, as they clearly seem to be,' then They argued that only such external events
it is also essential to understand the dynam- were objectively observable, and thus that
ics of such an environment. As a result, the only they could be the subject of an objec-
dynamics of the agent, the dynamics of the tive scientific theory (Watson, 1913). It
environment, and equally important, their is somewhat unclear from their collective
interaction, are what need to be understood writings exactly how important dynamics
to properly characterize information pro- were, or were not, for supporting this under-
cessing in biological systems. standing of psychological agents.4 Whatever
dynamics, c o n t r o l , and cognition »37

the case, their behavioral standpoint was To this day, classical control methods are
unarguably infused with dynamics in the taught to engineers to provide them with
hands of the cyberneticists. strong intuitions about how simple con-
Cybernetics is the study of feedback and trol systems can be analyzed and designed.
control in both artificial and biological sys- These methods play this role because they
tems. It grew f r o m a w a r t i m e interest in real- are largely graphical; are easily applicable to
world, goal-directed systems - especially simple, single input-single output systems;
enemy-directed systems. N o r b e r t Wiener and introduce a number of useful heuris-
(1948), who coined the term "cybernetics," tics for control design. However, when try-
was a mathematician w i t h interests in com- ing to understand a complex control system
munication theory w h o w o r k e d on gun con- like the brain, many of these pedagogical
trollers. It has been suggested that Wiener strengths become practical weaknesses. For
realized that the study of stability and con- instance, there is no reason to think that
trol of the antiaircraft systems he w a s work- a biological system is a single input-single
ing on could be e x t e n d e d to the operator of output system. As well, when dealing with
the system as well (Freudenthal, 1970-1990]. complex controllers, graphical methods
As a result, he had the insight that the same soon become limiting and clumsy because of
mathematical tools f o r understanding goal- their restricted dimensionality. Additional
directed artificial systems could be applied theoretical limitations on classical control
to goal-directed natural systems. include an inability to quantify optimal con-
The mathematical tools that W i e n e r used trol, to characterize adaptive control, and
are typically grouped under the heading to systematically include considerations of
of "classical control t h e o r y . " V e r y briefly, noise.
classical control theory considers the sys- Despite these limitations, classical con-
tem under study as implementing a t e m p o - trol successfully began a practical quan-
ral transfer function, w h i c h describes h o w tification of real-time systems. As well,
inputs are converted into outputs over time. the cyberneticist focus on temporal input-
The point of classical control is to design a output relations (captured by the transfer
control system that can be used to alter the functions) integrated well with the behav-
inputs of the system to achieve a desired iorist psychology of the day. That is, both
output. In open-loop control, the con- classical control theorists and behaviorists
troller simply provides inputs that should, did not need to look inside the systems they
under normal circumstances, achieve the were interested in understanding. What the
desired outputs. H o w e v e r , b e c a u s e normal control theorists added, of course, was an
circumstances are o f t e n difficult to define explicitly dynamical dimension to an other-
in advance, and the circumstances them- wise static characterization of cognitive sys-
selves are likely to change over time, a m o r e tems.
sophisticated f o r m of control, closed-loop
control or feedback control, is m o r e c o m -
monly employed. In closed-loop control, the 2.2. A Cognitive Resolution
inputs provided to the system d e p e n d on T h e famous cognitive revolution that took
its current outputs, w h i c h are o f t e n a f f e c t e d
place in the mid-1950s is often hailed as
by the current circumstances (e.g., in auto-
an essential turning point in the history
mobile cruise control, road conditions, hills,
of cognitive science, a turning point with-
and so on, greatly a f f e c t the e f f e c t of var-
out which cognitive science would not have
ious accelerator inputs). T h e effectiveness
fruitfully developed (Bechtel & Graham,
of closed-loop controllers w a s demonstrated
1999; Thagard, 1996). This may be true in
time and again during W o r l d W a r II, by their
part, but there was also a significant price
inclusion in target trackers, self-guided tor-
that was paid for the sweeping adoption of
pedoes, and various other servomechanisms
the cognitivist view. This is because the reso-
(Mindell, 1995).
lution of behaviorist difficulties came in two
i38 CHRIS ELIASMITH

parts. One was a shift in focus from input- However, I believe it clearly is the case that
output relations to internal states of cogni- they have great difficulty meeting this essen-
tive systems. The second was a shift from tial constraint.
mathematical models of behavior to compu- Newell appeals to various neurological
tational ones. With this second shift came a data to lend support to his assumption that
general acceptance that the relevant formal any particular step (or "production") in a
theory for characterizing cognitive systems cognitive algorithm operates on the time
was grounded in abstract entities that have scale of approximately 10 ms (Newell, 1990,
no connection to time: Turing machines. For p. 127). However, his application of this con-
instance, Newell and Simon (1972) wrote in straint seems rather contrived. For instance,
their historical epilogue: in one application, S O A R employs a single
production to encode whether or not a light
The formalization of logic showed that sym- is on (Newell, 1990, p. 275). But, in a sec-
bols can be copied, compared, rearranged, ond application, S O A R uses a single pro-
and concatenated with just as much defi- duction to encode: "If the problem space is
niteness of process as boards can be sawed,
the base-level-space, and the state has a box
planed, measured, and glued— Symbols
with nothing on top, and the state has input
became, for the first time, tangible - as
tangible as wood or metal. The Turing that has not been examined, then make the
machine was an all-purpose planar and comprehend operator acceptable, and note
lathe for symbols, (pp. 877-878) that the input has been examined" (Newell,
1990, p. 167). It seems highly unlikely that
A basic assumption of this kind of com- both of these productions should fire within
putational theory is that resources are infi- the same time scale (i.e., approximately 10
nite. So a computable function is one that ms). Time values, the number of produc-
can be accomplished regardless of tempo- tions per step, and the complexity of those
ral, memory, or other constraints. Unfor- productions have clearly been chosen to
tunately, despite the fact that considering allow the total reaction time of the models to
internal states is independent of the for- fall within human limits found through psy-
mal theory for considering such states, it chological experimentation. The claim that
so happened that, by adopting computa- SOAR has somehow allowed rough predic-
tional theory, time was pushed aside by the tions of human reaction time is thus very
cognitive sciences. In other words, it just unconvincing, given this ad hoc methodol-
so happened that the formal theory that ogy. It is rather more likely that the mod-
informed this symbolicist characterization eler's analysis, experience with psychologi-
of cognition cleaved time from function - cal results, and chosen time values allowed
an assumption not reflected in natural cog- such predictions (Newell, 1990, pp. 274-282).
nitive systems. In summary, there is no mention of how to
As a result, it is not surprising that in systematically relate productions to neural
their attack on the temporal deficiencies of firings, and worse, the few examples pro-
these symbolic characterizations of cogni- vided are highly unsystematic.
tive systems, Port and van Gelder (1995) Although it may not be completely futile
claim that the symbolicists "leave time out for the symbolicist to attempt to incorpo-
of the picture" (p. 2, italics original). But, rate realistic time constraints into his or her
on the face of it, this is untrue. Consider, model, it is undeniably more natural for
for instance, Newell's (1990) paradigmatic this constraint to be satisfied by intrinsi-
symbolicist cognitive model SOAR. In his cally dynamic models - that is, models
discussion of this model, and its theoretical that, in virtue of their underlying formal
underpinnings, Newell includes "operate in theory, have time constraints included. In
real time" as the third of thirteen constraints the end, symbolicists have not convincingly
that shapes the mind (p. 19). Thus, it is sim- described how time in their model of cog-
ply not the case the symbolicists ignore time. nitive processes (model time) systematically
DYNAMICS, CONTROL, AND COGNITION »39

relates to time in a natural cognizer (real from the adoption of dynamic systems the-
time). This is important because, as Newell ory as a formal means of describing their
(1990) himself notes, "minor changes in models. So it may not be surprising that the
assumptions move the total time account- antirepresentationalist stance of dynamicists
ing in substantial ways that have strong con- is generally considered a poorly motivated
sequences for which model fits the data" aspect of dynamicism (Bechtel, 1998; Elia-
(p. 294). This comment reflects two impor- smith, 2003).6
tant conclusions of this discussion. First, There have been a number of other
time is o f t e n included in symbolicist mod- concerns expressed with the dynamicist
els-symbolicists clearly took time very seri- approach, including the following (Elia-
ously, contrary to some characterizations. smith, 1996, 2000, 2001):
Second, there is a massive slippage between
a cognitive model and a real cognitive sys- 1. The lumped parameters (i.e., param-
tem for symbolicists. This is the high price eters that somehow summarize the
symbolicists have paid for considering time underlying neural complexity) and vari-
independently of cognitive function. ables in the differential equations
used by dynamicists are generally not
mapped to physical states of the system
2.3. Dynatnicism: Mind as Motion
(except inputs and outputs). As a result,
In the mid-1990s, a movement in cognitive it is difficult to gain independent empir-
science called "dynamicism" began to flour- ical support for the models (e.g., there
ish by arguing that these kinds of tempo- is no role for or relation to neural data).
ral limitations of symbolicism doomed it 2. The exemplar dynamical system, the
to failure (Abraham, Abraham, & Shaw, Watt governor (van Gelder, 1995), is
1991; Busemeyer & Townsend, 1993; Port a typical classical control system. This
& van Gelder, 1995; Robertson, Cohen, & means that the espoused methods are
Mayer-Kress, 1993; Thelen & Smith, 1994; classical input-output analyses, which
van Gelder, 1995, 1998). The dynamicists do not account for considerations of
espoused what they characterized as a dia- multiple inputs and outputs, noise, mul-
metrically opposed view, which elevated tiple loops, optimality, and so on.
time to be the single most important con- 3. From the preceding concern, another
straint on good cognitive models. In doing arises that dynamicism will have all of
so, they embraced a different formal theory, the same problems that behaviorism
dynamic systems theory, which is a branch has had (e.g., difficulties explaining cog-
of mathematics that describes time-varying nitive behaviors not obviously linked
behavior using sets of differential equations. to input states; difficulties explaining
Often explicitly, the dynamicist move- recursive processing). This concern is
ment was a theoretical transition back to the strengthened by the dynamicist rejec-
methods and commitments of the cyberneti- tion of internal representation.
cists. Perhaps reflective of the cyberneticist 4. Dynamicists restrict themselves to low-
relation to behaviorism, dynamicists tend to dimensional dynamical systems (in an
reject both computation and representation attempt to distinguish their models
(Port & van Gelder, 1995; Thelen & Smith, from connectionist ones; van Gelder,
'994)i5 despite the fact that cyberneticists 1998).7 This gready reduces the flexibil-
W remained largely silent on this point. As ity of the system and opens the possi-
We
1 this concern with representation and bility that certain natural behaviors will
computation may have seemed more press- fall outside of the dynamicist approach.
m
g as a result of the dynamicist discontent
with the symbolicist paradigm. In any case, Perhaps the most important of these limi-
't should be clear that the rejection of com- tations for this discussion is expressed by the
putation and representation does not follow first concern. Ironically, from that concern it
CHRIS ELIASMITH

follows that there is no explicit link between (nodes) connected together in large, usu-
dynamicist models and the temporal con- ally parallel, networks. The units produce a
straints imposed on real cognitive systems. numerical output based on weighted numer-
This is because those temporal constraints ical input from the other nodes to which
are most obvious, and best understood, at they are connected. The interpretations of
the level of single neurons and small net- such models have ranged widely, both in
works of neurons. Because there is no map- terms of what each unit represents and in
ping between dynamicist model parameters terms of the kinds of network topologies that
and the physical substrate that these mod- are relevant for understanding the mind.
els are trying to explain, it is unclear to The models range from atemporal localist
what extent the time in the models reflects models (e.g., Thagard, 1992), in which each
the time in the real system. So, although node represents the strength of a concept or
dynamicists have inherendy included time sentence, to atemporal distributed models
in their models, it is unclear whether it is (Elman, 1991), in which concepts are repre-
the correct, biologically relevant (i.e., real) sented by the activity of several nodes com-
time. Because there is no commitment to an bined, to (usually distributed) models whose
explicit mapping between model time and dynamics are of central interest (Lockery,
real time, it is up to each individual mod- Fang, & Sejnowski, 1990). However, it is
eler to choose some mapping or other that fair to say that the core of connection-
will result in the appropriate outputs. This ism, represented by the best-known con-
difficulty, of course, is reminiscent of the nectionist models, is atemporal (Gorman &
massive slippage between cognitive model Sejnowski, 1988; Rumelhart & McClelland,
and cognitive system that plagued the sym- 1986; Sejnowski & Rosenberg, 1986). As a
bolicists. So, similarly, this degree of arbi- result, the case can be made that the spirit
trariness is damaging to the dynamicists' of connectionism is not essentially dynam-
claim that they are trying to understand ical. This captures at least one concern of
"cognitive phenomena, like so many other the dynamicists regarding the connectionist
kinds of phenomena in the natural world" approach to understanding the mind (Port
(Port & van Gelder, 1995, p. 6), given that 8t van Gelder, 1995).
they have provided no systematic relation Nevertheless, the contrary case can be
between time in their explanations and real, made as well, albeit for a subset of con-
natural, cognitive time. nectionist models: distributed recurrent net-
As a result of the variety of difficul- works. The timing of such networks is, as in
ties mentioned previously, dynamicism, as a any dynamical system, integral to the equa-
cognitive paradigm, has become somewhat tions describing the system. Connectionists
marginalized in cognitive science. Neverthe- constructing such models do not need to
less, dynamicism has left a valuable legacy of contrive to include time in a model of cog-
researchers no longer being able to simply nition, as symbolicists do. Rather, such net-
ignore temporal constraints or assume that work models naturally incorporate time con-
those constraints will somehow be taken straints. Hence, Churchland and Sejnowski
care of after the fact. (1992) claim: "A theme that will be sounded
and resounded throughout this book con-
2.4. Connectionism in Time cerns time and the necessity for network
models to reflect the fundamental and
The place of time in connectionist modeling essential temporal nature of actual nervous
is much more complicated than for either systems" (Churchland 81 Sejnowski, 1992,
symbolicism or dynamicism. This is largely p. 117). I take this to be a supremely dynam-
because the label "connectionism" applies to icist sentiment.
a wide variety of modeling assumptions. In As a result, some connectionist models
general, a model is considered connectionist clearly have the potential to be inherendy
if it consists of simple computational units
temporal. A connectionist network can be,
»37
DYNAMICS, C O N T R O L , AND COGNITION

after all, "a dynamical system, meaning its networks. Most researchers in this domain
inputs and internal states are varying with refer to themselves as computational neuro-
time; it is basically engaged in spatiotem- scientists or theoretical neuroscientists and
poral vector coding and time-dependent consider what they do quite distinct from
matrix transformations" (Churchland & artificial neural networks or connectionism
Sejnowski, 1992, p. 338). T h e main difficulty (although the historical and theoretical rela-
for connectionists is not whether they can tions are clear). It is in these biologically
include time but whether they can do so in plausible models where real-world dynamics
a way that can be informative of the sys- become an inescapable feature of the mod-
tems being studied. To better understand els. It is here that there is a systematic rela-
this challenge, consider the vast literature tion between model time and real time. In
on attractor networks (see, e.g., Plaut & particular, the empirically measurable time
McClelland, 1993). Attractor networks are constants, voltage and current rate changes,
recurrent networks that, as their name sug- and so on, of real neurons are explicitly
gests, evolve over time to exploit the exis- included in the models. So, as modelers
tence of state space attractors (i.e., points or begin to map computational units in their
sets of points that are dynamically stable). model networks onto computational units
However, the particular length of time it in biological systems (i.e., neurons), and
takes a connectionist attractor network to as these model units resemble the biologi-
setde is seldom related to the time con- cal units more and more, dynamics, espe-
straints imposed on real nervous systems. cially the particular dynamics of natural sys-
Rather, it is determined by how big the tems, become crucial for explaining network
time step that is chosen by the modeler hap- behavior. This is hardly surprising because
pens to be (where a time step is the length these modelers are now directly addressing
of time it takes to complete one stage in the same phenomena that gave rise to the
the recurrent processing). As a result, such dynamics-laden vocabulary of neuroscien-
networks are essentially temporal, but that tists. One way to characterize this important
temporality is not linked to real organisms and unique step in understanding cognitive
(i.e., it is not linked to real time). This, of systems is to realize that temporal assump-
course, is the same problem that, as I have tions regarding the model parameters are
already argued, plagues dynamicists and independendy testable assumptions. That is,
symbolicists: how should model time and neuroscientists can go to the system being
real time be systematically linked? Nev- described and measure those parameters
ertheless, attractor networks are a useful direcdy. This is not true for firing times of
advance over completely atemporal connec- productions, time courses of lumped param-
tionist networks. eters, or time steps in recurrent networks.

It is important to note that there is Unfortunately, a new problem arises for


another subset of connectionist models that these biologically plausible networks. If this
are direcdy constrained by observed tem- biological connectionism, like dynamicism
poral properties of organisms. These are and symbolicism, is to be a paradigm for
the so-called low-level connectionist mod- understanding cognitive systems, it is essen-
els, where the nodes are mapped one-to- tial to describe how these low-level biolog-
one onto real neurons. However, these kinds ical models relate to high-level cognition.
of low-level models are considered distinct Simply including the dynamics of neurons
enough from core connectionism that there does not explain how or why those dynam-
are unique conferences (e.g., Computa- ics give rise to complex, higher-level cogni-
tional Neuroscience [ C N S ] , Computational tive dynamics. In general, it is fair to say that
and Systems Neuroscience [ C O S Y N E ] ) and the extent to which most such models have
journals (e.g., Journal of Computational Neu- included real time is proportional to the
roscience, Biological Cybernetics) that focus extent to which they are noncognitive. What
on these far more biologically plausible is missing is a systematic method for growing
CHRIS ELIASMITH
M2

extremely complex dynamical models from ods for growing this mapping to an appro-
these well-grounded beginnings. priate level of complexity.
In the remainder of this chapter, I
describe a framework that shows how to
2.5. Dynamic Difficulties
resolve these remaining difficulties (see also
Given the preceding discussion, it seems Eliasmith, 2003).
that the history of cognitive science teaches
us three main lessons about dynamics. The
first, noted most effectively by the dynam- 3. Dynamics and the Neural
icists, is that cognitive systems are organ- Engineering Framework
isms embedded in natural environments to
which they are dynamically coupled. As a The neural engineering framework (NEF)
result, it is highly unlikely that address- is a general theory of neurobiological sys-
ing the organism's cognitive behaviors inde- tems proposed in Eliasmith and Anderson
pendendy of temporal constraints on those (2003). The theory consists of three quanti-
behaviors will result in explanatorily fruitful fied principles that characterize neural rep-
theories. resentation, computation, and dynamics. In
The second lesson is that model time this discussion, I focus on the third principle.
and real time must be systematically related. It is stated in Eliasmith and Anderson (2003)
It is one thing to write down a differen- as follows: "Neural dynamics are character-
tial equation over the variable f, but it is ized by considering neural representations as
another thing to say how that t relates to the control theoretic state variables. Thus, the
real f observed by experimentalists. Because dynamics of neurobiological systems can be
the mapping between nodes for connection- analyzed using control theory" (p. 15).
ists, or parameters for dynamicists, and the Although succinct, this principle makes
underlying neural implementation is not sys- plain how the difficulties faced by symbol-
tematized by either paradigm, it is a mistake icism, connectionism, and dynamicism are
to suppose that time will somehow take care addressed. In short, the systematic mapping
of itself. Despite the switch in formal theo- between model time and real time is accom-
ries, this problem is closely related to the plished in virtue of the fact that the rep-
mistaken assumption of symbolicists that resentations whose dynamics are expressed
time is somehow independent of function. by control theoretic equations are precisely
The difference is that for dynamicists and neural representations. This means that the
connectionists the independence is more various time constants of single neurons are
subde. Although they include time variables mapped onto appropriate time constants in
in their models, the lack of an explicit rela- model neurons. In other words, there is a
tion between model components and the one-to-one mapping between model neu-
physical system being modeled means that
rons and modeled neurons, just as for the
it may well not be the right time.
computational neuroscientific subset of con-
The third and final lesson is that, even nectionism. However, the N E F goes beyond
once an explicit mapping has been made standard computational neuroscience meth-
between model time and organism time, ods by providing an additional suggestion for
more work must be done to understand truly how to write modem control theoretic equa-
cognitive dynamics. This is simply a conse- tions over these neural representations.
quence of the fact that typically cognitive Because control theoretic equations sim-
phenomena are the result of complex inter- ply are sets of differential equations, as in
actions between millions, if not billions, of dynamicism, the NEF essentially integrates
neurons. Although an explicit, systematic the biological connectionist view with the
relation between models and physical imple- dynamicist view of cognitive systems. The
mentation may exist at the neuron level, to
benefit is that, unlike dynamicism, the NEF
make such models cognitive requires meth-
sets up a systematic mapping between
DYNAMICS, CONTROL, AND COGNITION 143

model time and organism time, and unlike used to accumulate information over time,
standard computational neuroscience, the tracking long-term changes. More generally,
NEF explicitly describes the relation be- such a network acts as one of the basic tem-
tween neuron activity and higher-level vari- poral transfer functions, integration. Inte-
ables of the system. So, the N E F simulta- gration is so important for understanding
neously suggests a method for building dynamical systems, that it is the basic trans-
toward cognitive dynamics and remains fer function for modem control theory. T h e
responsible to single-cell dynamics. ubiquity of recurrent connections in the
In addition, the kind of control theory brain, coupled with the ease of building
adopted by the NEF, modern control the- integrators with recurrent networks, and
ory, suffers none of the limitations of the the importance of integrators for imple-
tools used by the cyberneticists. As sug- menting a wide variety of dynamical behav-
gested by the dynamics principle of the iors suggests that neural integration may
NEF, modern control theory considers the be a fundamental neural function. Indeed,
internal states of the system (i.e., the state the integrator has been used in models of
variables) to understand the dynamics of a wide variety of neural systems, includ-
the system's output given its input. As well, ing working memory (Miller, Brody, Romo,
modem control theory provides for the anal- & Wang, 2003), head-direction tracking
ysis of multiple input-multiple output sys- (Zhang, 1996), eye-position control (Seung,
tems and multiple-loop systems, and incor- 1996), the vestibular-ocular reflex (Elia-
porates noise, optimality constraints, and smith, Westover, & Anderson, 2002), and
adaptive control. In short, modern control allocentric position tracking in an environ-
theory is an excellent formalism for analyz- ment (Conklin & Eliasmith, 2005).
ing and synthesizing real-world physical sys- Characterizing the precise relation be-
tems - including the brain. tween integration and any one of these
To better understand how this principle, specific models would take us too far afield,
and modem control theory, is applied in the so let us consider a generic neural integrator.
NEF, let us consider a simple example. One That is, let us assume that we wish to
of the most basic and central properties of build a neural circuit that has the proper-
recurrent networks is their ability to extend ties described previously: a circuit whose
network time constants far beyond the time network time constant far exceeds the
constants of the individual cells that con- time constants of any of the constituents.
stitute the network (time constants, here, Employing the NEF, we first take the com-
measure how long a signal takes to decay). putational units in our model to be sin-
So, for instance, if we expose a single cell gle neurons whose temporal properties are
to a brief pulse (e.g., 1 ms) of input current, matched to those of the neural system we
there will be a more slowly decaying current are studying. This gives rise to a variety
in its cell body (e.g., that lasts, say, 5 ms). of single-cell models whose distribution of
Although this intrinsic current will outlast input-response functions reflects the exper-
the length of the actual input, in general it imentally observed distribution in the rele-
does not last much longer. However, if we vant part of the brain. 8 These constitute the
take an ensemble of such cells and connect computational elements of the model, and
them appropriately, we can cause a simi- their dynamics are assumed to be carefully
lar injection of current to the population of matched to the dynamics of the neural sys-
neurons to be effectively sustained over a tem.
very long period of time (e.g., 10 s). Second, it is generally observed in the
This property can be extremely compu- brain that many different cells carry infor-
tationally useful. For instance, it can cause mation about a given set of internal or
a population of neurons to act like a mem- external states. As a result, we must deter-
ory encoding information about an event mine how the cells in our circuit relate to
that occurred in the past. As well, it can be the states of interest to them. Again, this
H4 CHRIS ELIASMITH

information can be gathered experimentally. Even in the simple integrator circuit, we


This is a typical step in single-cell physiol- can see how the difficulties faced by past
ogy experiments, when neuroscientists con- methods are resolved. First, the dynam-
struct what they often term "tuning curves." ics of natural systems are mapped direcdy
These curves determine which activity states onto the dynamics of constituents of the
of neurons carry information about which circuit. This solves the problem faced by
states of the world (e.g., a neuron in the both dynamicists and connectionists regard-
nucleus propositus hypoglossi is said to carry ing adopting natural, realistic dynamic con-
information about eye position as reflected straints in their models. Second, the de-
by its tuning curve, which is a monotoni- scription of our model necessarily includes
cally increasing firing rate as a function of eye time, as it is written as a set of differen-
position). 9 It is the population-wide neural tial equations. Third, unlike computational
representation of those states of the world neuroscientists, we have an explicit method
that are considered state variables in our for relating the activities of individual cells
control theoretic description of the behav- in the circuit to higher-level behaviors of
ior of the circuit. the group of cells (e.g., integration in this
Third, we must express the dynamics of case). This simple circuit, of course, does
the circuit in control theoretic terms. Sim- not demonstrate that the method will help
ply put, this means writing a set of differ- build traditionally cognitive models. For this
ential equations that describe the overall reason, in the next section I briefly present
circuit dynamics in terms of the state vari- an application of the N E F to a more typical
ables. In the case of a single variable neural cognitive phenomenon.
integrator, we can write the integration as
x(t) = fu(t)dt, where x is the state variable,
and u is the input to the circuit. As a sim- 4. From Neurons to C o g n i t i o n
ple control structure, this can be written as
x=dx/dt=Ax(t) + Bu(t), where A = 0 and Fodor and Pylyshyn (1988), and more
B = 1. However, because neurons have in- recendy Jackendoff (2002), have suggested
trinsic dynamics dictated by their particular that neurally plausible architectures do not
physical characteristics, we must adapt this naturally support structure-sensitive com-
standard control structure to a neurally rele- putation, and that such computation is
vant one. Fortunately, this can be done in the essential for explaining cognition. Notably,
general case (Eliasmith & Anderson, 2003). Fodor and Pylyshyn (1988) in particular
Finally, we must use our characteriza- have further argued that, to the extent
tion of single-cell representation and cir- such architectures could be forced into per-
cuit dynamics to determine the connection forming this kind of computation, they
weights between neurons that exploit the would turn out to be merely implementa-
single-cell properties to realize the defined tions of symbolicist cognitive systems. For
control structure. The details of the analyt- the purposes of this section, I accept that
ical methods to determine the weights are structure-sensitive processing is fundamen-
found in Eliasmith and Anderson (2003). It is tal to understanding cognition but show
also demonstrated there that the preceding how neurally plausible architectures can
steps can be carried out in the general case; support such processing in a nonsymboli-
that is, for linear or nonlinear control struc- cist way. The specific model I present cap-
tures, and for scalars, vectors, functions, or tures the context-sensitive linguistic infer-
any combination of these under noise (for ence exhibited by human subjects in the
examples of each of these cases, see Elia- Wason card task (Wason, 1966). To do
smith, 2005b). There is no reason to sup- so, the model employs biologically realis-
pose that this degree of generality will, in tic neurons to leam the relevant structural
any way, be limiting to constructing models transformations appropriate f o r a given con-
of cognitive systems. text, and it generalizes such transformations
»37
dynamics, c o n t r o l , and cognition

to novel contents with the same syntactic and tensor products, Smolensky, 1990). Few
structure. Given the salient properties of the of these approaches have been used to build
model, I refer to it as BioSLIE (Biologically models of cognitive phenomena (but see
plausible Structure-sensitive Learning Infer- Eliasmith & Thagard, 2001). However, none
ence Engine]. of these methods has been employed in a
In the Wason task, subjects are given a biologically plausible computational setting.
conditional rule of the form, "If P, then Fortunately, the NEF can be employed to
Q." They are then shown four cards. Each implement the necessary nonlinear vector
card expresses the satisfaction (or not] of computations demanded by these solutions.
condition P on one side and the satisfac- In particular, BioSLIE employs one-
tion (or not) of condition Q on the other. hundred-dimensional HRR vectors to en-
The four visible card faces show representa- code linguistic structure. The details of
tions of P, Q, not-P, and not-Q. Subjects are implementing HRRs using the N E F can be
instructed to select all cards, which must be found elsewhere (Eliasmith, 2004). In short,
turned over to determine whether the con- we can construct rules, like those needed
ditional rule is true. A vast majority of sub- to understand the Wason task, using vec-
jects (greater than 90 percent) do not give tor multiplication and addition in a biologi-
the logically correct response (i.e., P and cally plausible network. So, for instance, the
not-Q). Instead, the most common answer rule "If a, then b," or Implies(a,b), can be
is to select the P and Q cards, or just the P encoded into a single vector:
card (Oaksford & Chater, 1994). However,
it became apparent that performance on the
task could be greatly facilitated by changing R = relation ® implies
the content of the task to be more realistic or + antecedent ® a + consequent ® b,
thematic, often by making the rule a permis-
sive one (e.g., "If someone is drinking alco-
where each variable in this equation is a
hol, then that person is over twenty-one";
one-hundred-dimensional vector, and each
Sperber, Cara, & Girotto, 1995). To distin-
such vector is represented by neural spik-
guish these two versions of the task, I refer
ing. It is here, in constructing our repre-
to them as the abstract and permissive ver-
sentation R in this manner, that we avoid
sions of the task, respectively. Human per-
merely implementing a symbolicist system.
formance on the Wason task is an ideal tar-
This is because this representational format,
get for providing a neural model of cognition
being a compressed vector representation,
because it is considered a phenomenon that
does not explicitly include the constituents
can be explained only by invoking structure-
of the representation R in the representa-
sensitive processing. As a result, the task
tion itself. As a result, the representation
allows BioSLIE to demonstrate its ability to
is noncompositional, violating a basic con-
generalize across structures - that is, to be
straint that Fodor and Pylyshyn (1988) place
systematic - an ability that many, including
on symbolicist cognitive systems (for further
Fodor, Pylyshyn, and Jackendoff, take to be
discussion, see Eliasmith, 2005a). Notably,
a hallmark of cognitive systems.
the resultant representation, R, can be
The model takes advantage of the NEF, transformed in various ways to provide
recent advances in structured vector rep- information about the contents of that
resentations, and relevant physiological and vector representation. In particular, R can
anatomical data from frontal cortices. Since be transformed to report any of the con-
the early 1990s, there has been a series of sug- stituents of the representation or transfor-
gestions as to how to incorporate structure- mations of those constituents as demanded
sensitive processing in models employing by a given task. It is precisely such transfor-
distributed, vector representations (includ- mations that the system must learn in per-
ing spatter codes, Kanerva, 1994; holographic forming the Wason task. In short, BioSLIE
reduced representations [HRRs], Plate, 1991; must leam how to transform R in different
146 CHRIS ELIASMITH

Figure 8.1. Functional decomposition and anatomical mapping of


the model. The single letters indicate the vector signals in the
model associated with the area.

contexts (i.e., the permissive and abstract and apply the appropriate transformation to
contexts) to return the appropriate elements solve the Wason task (Parsons & Osherson,
of the structure (e.g., a and not-b in the 2001). It is during the application of the
permissive case, and a and b in the abstract transformation that learning is also pre-
case). sumed to occur in an associative memory.
Of course, to use this characterization of Given this mapping to anatomy, we can
structure-sensitive processing in an explana- appeal to work in frontal cortices that have
torily useful model, it is essential to suggest characterized the kinds of tuning curves
which anatomical structures may be per- pyramidal cells in these areas display.
forming the relevant functions. Only then To perform the needed H R R vector oper-
is it possible to bring to bear the additional ations, learning, and so on, B i o S L I E fur-
constraints of (and make predictions relat- ther decomposes this high-level functional
ing to) single-cell physiology and functional mapping into neural subsystems responsible
imaging data. Figure 8.1 shows how BioSLIE for these tasks. T h e resulting set of subnet-
is mapped to functional anatomy. Specifi- works is shown in Figure 8.2, w h i c h is a
cally, the network consists of (a) input from model that consists of ten interconnected
ventromedial prefrontal cortex (VMPFC), neural populations, for a total of approxi-
which provides familiarity, or context, infor- mately seventeen thousand neurons.
mation that is used to select the appro- When run, the model is able to repro-
priate transformation (Adolphs, Bechara, duce the typical results f r o m the W a s o n task
Tranel, Damasio, & Damasio, 1995), (b) under both the abstract and permissive con-
left language areas, which provide repre- texts (not shown). Simply put, this means
sentations of the rule to be examined (Par- that the model is taught and successfully
sons, Osherson, & Martinez, 1999), and (c) reproduces the transformation, "If a then
the anterior cingulate cortex (ACC), which b - > { b , a } " in the abstract c o n t e x t and the
gives an error signal consisting of either the transformation "If a then b { ~ b , a } " in
correct answer or an indication that the the permissive context. So, w h e n the con-
response was correct or not (Holroyd & text signal is switched, the model applies a
Coles, 2002). The neural populations that different transformation, as expected. The
make up BioSLIE itself model the right infe- point of mentioning these results is simply
rior frontal cortex, where V M P F C and lin- to emphasize that this is done using biolog-
guistic information is combined to select ically plausible neurons in a c o m p l e x neural
DYNAMICS, C O N T R O L , AND COGNITION »37

(driving, over-16) along with their expected


answers are presented to the network. T h e
learning is then turned off, and it is pre-
sented with the novel rule Implies(voting,
over-18). Notably, because the context is the
same in the novel case as in the previous
examples, the same transformation should
be applied. Indeed, BioSLIE infers that "vot-
ing" and "not-over-18" are the expected
answers (i.e., the cards that need to be
checked to ensure the rule is not violated).
Figure 8.2. The complete network at the In the last quarter of the simulation, no rule
population level. The lowercase letters indicate is presented and thus no answer is produced
populations of approximately two thousand (i.e., all similarity measures are very low).
neurons each. Uppercase letters indicate the
Figure 8.3 thus demonstrates that Bio-
signals being sent along the relevant projections.
S L I E is systematically processing language-
The dotted boxes indicate how this diagram
relates to the functional decomposition of like structures with biologically realistic
Figure 8.1, and hence the anatomical mapping computational components. As a result, it
discussed earlier. not only provides an explicit counterexam-
ple to Fodor, Pylyshyn, and JackendofPs
claims but also demonstrates how the N E F
network, not by having a computer perform can relate single-neuron dynamics to the
these logical transformations directly. And, dynamics of cognitive behavior. Admittedly,
although simple, this model does show rudi- BioSLIE most directly addresses the issue
mentary structural transformations. This, of how the appropriate representations and
however, is not enough to support the claim transformations for accomplishing cognitive
that the model is structure sensitive. T h e tasks can be understood in a neurally plau-
obvious concern is that the model is simply sible way. It does not directly map onto
"memorizing" a mapping it has seen (i.e., it the observed dynamics of human perfor-
is constructing a lookup table). If this were mance on the Wason task (the model is
true, the model would not truly be gener- much faster, though it is appropriately con-
alizing over the appropriate syntactic struc- strained by single-neuron dynamics). This,
tures, as demanded by systematicity. no doubt, is because far more than the
To demonstrate that the network is truly few brain areas modeled by BioSLIE are
learning a languagelike transformation in a employed by human subjects to perform
context, Figure 8.3 shows that it does in fact the task. Nevertheless, timing constraints on
generalize learned, structure-sensitive trans- certain aspects of the task can be inferred
formations to unfamiliar contents (i.e., "If from BioSLIE's performance (e.g., mini-
someone votes, then that person is over eigh- mum transformation times). And, more
teen") in a familiar context (i.e., the permis- importandy for this discussion, the meth-
sive context). This demonstrates that the ods provided are general enough to address
system has learned a systematic syntactic a wide variety of cognitive tasks in a way
regularity. That is, it can transform novel that directly incorporates underlying neuro-
structured representations based solely on dynamical constraints.
the syntax of the representation.
Let us consider Figure 8.3 in more de-
tail. In the simulation the permissive context 5. Embeddedness and the NEF
signal is kept constant and there are three
separate rules that are presented to BioSLIE. To this point I have discussed how the
While learning is on, the rules Implies N E F relates low-level neural dynamics with
(drinking-alcohol, over-21) and Implies higher-level circuit dynamics, and I have
148 CHRIS ELIASMITH

Time (ms)
Figure 8.3. Generalization across different rules in the same
context. Each line indicates the value of one dimension of the
one-hundred-dimensional vector encoded in neural spiking in the /
population from Figure 8.2. The top three similarity results of each
transformation are shown to demonstrate that simple thresholding
results in the correct answer. See text for further discussion.

demonstrated that it is possible to build tem and the system's e n v i r o n m e n t becomes


rudimentary cognitive systems using the very difficult - system boundaries b e c o m e
NEF. Earlier, I briefly touched on the shared obscure. Dynamicists o f t e n claim that this
inspiration for taking dynamics seriously and result is a unique strength of t h e dynami-
for being concerned with the embedded- cist approach and an accurate reflection of
ness, or situatedness, of cognitive agents. the true state of cognitive systems (Port &
Here I want to discuss what, if any, conse- van Gelder, 1995). Similarly, those focused
quences the N E F has for our understanding on the situatedness of cognitive systems
of cognitive embeddedness. have argued that the traditional bound-
Note that for some dynamicists, taking aries between an agent and its environ-
dynamics seriously means holding a fairly ment, provided by the skin, are unreason-
strong embedded view: "In this vision, the ably hegemonic and that, instead, "the mind
cognitive system is not just the encapsu- extends into the w o r l d " ( C l a r k & Chalmers,
lated brain; rather, since the nervous system, 1998/2002, p. 647).
body, and environment are all constantly I suspect that such conclusions are mis-
changing and simultaneously influencing guided, and we can turn to the N E F to see
each other, the true cognitive system is a w h y . A s discussed, t h e N E F adopts mod-
single unified system embracing all three" ern control theory as a m e a n s of specify-
(van Gelder, 1995, p. 373). For dynami- ing dynamics. Control theory, as opposed
cists, then, a distinction between the sys- to dynamic systems theory, has a number
DYNAMICS, CONTROL, AND COCNITION 149

of benefits for describing cognitive systems.


First, control theory explicitly acknowledges
system boundaries, in virtue of identifying
state variables with subsystems of the over-
all system of interest. Second, control the-
ory explicitly introduces the central notion
of control and related notions such as con-
trollability. These notions help underwrite
distinctions between systems whose dynam- Figure 8.4. Brain, body, and world as controllers
ics are fixed or otherwise independent of one and plants. Drawing such system boundaries
another. And finally, control theory has its and making plant-controller distinctions make
roots in engineering, a discipline concerned clear the differences between subsystems and
with implementational aspects of physical their interactions.
systems, including noise and other compo-
nent limitations. These concerns contrast a single unified system is both impractical
with dynamic systems theory, whose roots and uninformative from a scientific point of
are in mathematics. This is not to say that view - it in no way helps determine what
either control theory or dynamic systems the components are. Notice that advocat-
theory is somehow more mathematically ing the identity of system components does
powerful, but rather it is to point out that not imply that such decompositions should
the methods have different emphases, one of not be reassembled for explaining certain
which is more appropriate for understand- properties. Rather, it is the observation that
ing physically realized, natural cognitive sys- to explain a large, complex system requires
tems. identification and explanation of both its
Let us consider each of the first two subsystems and their interactions. And, to
benefits in more detail. The importance of do that, those subsystems must themselves
acknowledging system boundaries cannot be be identified and well understood.
overstated when pursuing system analysis. This leads naturally to the second point:
Decomposition of complex systems is essen- that the introduction of the notion of control
tial for our understanding of such systems, helps to categorize different kinds of subsys-
whether they be biological, ecological, eco- tems. A typical dynamical system in control
nomic, meteorological, or what have you. As theory consists of a plant and a controller.
Bechtel and Richardson (1993) have argued The plant is a physical system whose inputs
at length, "a mechanistic explanation iden- we would like to change to result in particu-
tifies these [system] parts and their orga- lar outputs from that system. The controller
nization, showing how the behavior of the plays the role of producing the necessary
machine is a consequence of the parts and inputs to result in those particular outputs.
organization.... A major part of develop- This basic distinction is one that helps us
ing a mechanistic explanation is simply to understand the different roles brain, body,
determine what the components of a sys- and world play in an overall explanation of a
tem are and what they do" (pp. 17-18). Blur- behaving agent in an environment. With this
ring, shifting, or removing system bound- distinction, we can see what is special about
aries, as dynamicist and embedded agent the brain. We have fairly good physical the-
theorists often advocate, is seriously detri- ories that can be used to explain the kinetics
mental to making progress in our expla- and dynamics of bodies and of the world.
nations of such systems. This is especially However, we have little idea how to under-
tnie if there are no theoretical principles stand the more complex dynamics found in
for determining which shifting or removing the brain. As a result, it is natural to consider
the brain as the controller of the body as a
of boundaries is justified and which is not.
plant, together acting as controller for the
As a result, considering a cognitive system
environment as a plant (see Figure 8.4).
(constituted by brain, body, and world) as
CHRIS EUASMITH

O u r goal in understanding a cognitive 6. Dynamics + Control = Cognition


system is to elucidate the qualitatively dif-
ferent dynamics internal to the brain. The It is important to take t h e critical consid-
most obvious differences are the speed of erations of this c h a p t e r in t h e i r a p p r o p r i a t e
information flow (i.e., bandwidth), and the context. Although I have expressed serious
degree and kind of coupling. Because bod- concerns with b o t h dynamicism a n d e m b e d -
ies have mass, they tend to slow down the ded approaches to u n d e r s t a n d i n g cognitive
transfer of information to the world from systems, it should be clear t h a t t h e positive
the brain (i.e., they effectively act as a low- view I have espoused is highly sensitive to
pass filter). However, no such impediment the concerns t h a t gave rise to these posi-
to information flow exists between brain tions. T h e N E F undeniably d r a w s inspira-
areas. This results in a huge difference tion from dynamicism, as it includes at its
between the kinds of coupling that can be core an acknowledgment of t h e i m p o r t a n c e
supported between brain subsystems and of time for understanding natural cognitive
between the brain and the external environ- systems. Although t h e N E F rejects t h e non-
ment. In short, interactions with the envi- computationalism and antirepresentational-
ronment are slower than intrabrain inter- ism of dynamicism, it does so in a way
actions. I find it rather ironic, or perhaps that is consistent with dynamicist a r g u m e n t s
surprising, that researchers who embrace against t h e symbolicist t r e a t m e n t of time.
the importance of dynamics for understand- As well, t h e f u n d a m e n t a l insights of those
ing cognitive function, and who argue that interested in t h e e m b e d d e d n e s s of cognitive
differences in dynamics are cognitive differ- systems is not lost in t h e N E F . C h a r a c t e r -
ences (when confronting symbolicists; van izing the brain as a control system means
Gelder, 1998, p. 622), then suppose that dif- understanding t h e dynamics of its inputs
ferences in dynamics between brain-brain and its coupling to t h e e n v i r o n m e n t . H o w -
and brain-world interactions can be over- ever, I have suggested t h a t this can be d o n e
looked when arguing for embeddedness in such a way t h a t traditional distinctions
(Clark & Chalmers, 1998/2002, p. 648; van among brain, body, and world are preserved.
Gelder, 1995, p. 373). I think it is much In other words, consideration of ecological
better to consistendy claim that differences (i.e., real) operating e n v i r o n m e n t s is imper-
in dynamics often result in distinct proper- ative for trying to comprehensively under-
ties and behaviors. If we adopt that view, stand a dynamical system interacting with
it becomes clear that the suggestion that that environment. This is t r u e regardless
"nothing [other than the presence of skin] of how that system m i g h t be b r o k e n into
seems different" between brain-brain and subsystems. In fact, t h e r e are good reasons,
brain-world interactions (Clark & Chalmers, even dynamical reasons, for p e r f o r m i n g a
1998/2002, p. 644) is plainly false. decomposition consistent w i t h traditional
I should note that I do not want to sug- boundaries. It is evidently a mistake, then,
gest that determining the appropriate sys- to rule out decomposition m e r e l y because
tem boundaries will be an easy task (nor that of dynamic coupling. U n f o r t u n a t e l y , this
it stops at the skin). Indeed, it is unclear seems to have been t h e t e n d e n c y of those
whether we will be able to identify gen- espousing t h e embodied, e m b e d d e d , and
eral, consistent principles for identifying sys- extended views of cognition.
tem boundaries. Nevertheless, it is essential In summary, t h e intent of t h e N E F is to
to realize that this is a task worth pursu- provide a suggestion as to h o w we might
ing, and that simply blurring systems over take seriously m a n y of t h e i m p o r t a n t in-
boundaries, or suggesting that such bound- sights generated f r o m cognitive science: in-
aries do not really exist, is bad for both prac- sights f r o m symbolicists, dynamicists, and
tical (i.e., trying to do science) and theoreti- connectionists. I have argued t h a t it em-
cal (i.e., appropriate conceptual application) braces realistic neural dynamics, can help
reasons. us understand high-level cognition, and is
dynamics, c o n t r o l , and cognition
»37

consistent with traditional boundaries tion: "Dynamical models usually also incor-
among brain, b o d y , a n d w o r l d . I s u s p e c t it is porate representations, but reconceive them
far from a c o m p l e t e t h e o r y , b u t p e r h a p s it as dynamical entities (e.g., system states, or
trajectories shaped by attractor landscapes).
is a useful start.
Representations tend to be seen as transient,
context dependent stabilities in the midst of
change, rather than as static, context-free,
Notes
permanent units" (p. 244). Nevertheless, the
original nonrepresentational ideal remains:
1 Of course, much of the groundwork was laid "Interestingly, some dynamicists claim to
before this. But even as late as 1906, there have developed wholly representation free
was still public debate (at the Nobel Prize models, and they conjecture that represen-
awards ceremony) regarding the existence tation will turn out to play much less of a
of individual nerve cells. As well, intracel- role in cognition than has traditionally been
lular recording techniques were not devel- supposed" (ibid.).
oped until the 1940s, and basic single-cell
ion dynamics were not characterized until 7 For instance, van Gelder (1998) states:
the 1950s. For an extended account of the "Another noteworthy fact about these mod-
early history of neurobiology, see Finger els is that the variables they posit are not
(2000). low-level (e.g., neural firing rates), but rather
macroscopic quantities at roughly the level
2 Although it should be noted that some sym-
of the cognitive performance itself' (p. 619).
bolicists also seem to have been sensitive
Similarly, Port and van Gelder (1995) note
to the importance of this interaction, "[a]
that the purpose of a dynamicist model is to
proper understanding of the intimate interde-
"provide a low-dimensional model that pro-
pendence between an adaptive organism and
vides a scientifically tractable description of
its environment is essential to a clear view of
the same qualitative dynamics as is exhibited
what a science of an adaptive species can be
by the high-dimensional system (the brain)"
like" (Newell & Simon, 1972, p. 870).
(p. 28).
3 This is just the observation that change is
8 Input response functions are a plot of the
often an important environmental cue. Thus,
input current versus the resultant firing rate.
visual features such as motion are often used
This is like an input-output response function
to orient an animal toward potentially inter-
for a cell. More precisely, these curves have a
esting or dangerous aspects of its environ-
temporal dimension as well, given dynamic
ment.
single-cell effects like adaptation. For sim-
4 Neither Skinner nor Watson, for instance,
plicity, this will be ignored in the present
makes special mention of dynamics. How-
example.
ever, Hull (1935), in his quest to write
9 Again, this is a simplification, as many neu-
Newtonian-like laws for behavior, seems
rons carry information about internal states
somewhat concerned with the effects of
or act largely in a control capacity. This sim-
interstimulus delays during learning. How-
plification serves a pedagogical purpose and
ever, none of the equations he explicidy
does not speak to a limitation in the general-
writes have a time parameter.
ity of the NEF.
5 Van Gelder (1995) is quite explicit in his
rejection of representation, noting that "the
notion of representation is just the wrong
sort of conceptual tool to apply" (p. 353) in
describing dynamical systems. Similarly, Port References
and van Gelder (1995) state that cognitive sys-
tems are not best understood as the result of Abraham, F. D., Abraham, R., & Shaw, C. D.
computing over representations: "a cognitive (1991). A visual introduction to dynamical sys-
system is not a discrete sequential manip- tems for psychology. Santa Cruz, C A : Aerial
ulation of static representational structures" Press.
(P-3)- Adolphs, R., Bechara, A., Tranel, D., Damasio,
" In fact, more recent work by van Gelder H., & Damasio, A. R. (1995). Neuropsycho-
(1999) and others also begins to backpedal logical approaches to reasoning and decision-
on the earlier stricture against representa- making. In A. R. Damasio, H. Damasio, &
1
52 CHRIS ELIASMITH

Y. Christen (Eds.), Neurobiology of decision- the Wason task. In G. Bara, L. Barsalou, &
making (pp. 157-80). New York: Springer- M. Bucciarelli (Eds.), Proceedings of the 2yth
Verlag. Annual Meetingofthe Cognitive Science Society.
Ballard, D. H. (1991)1 Animate vision. Artificial Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Intelligence, 48, 57-86. Eliasmith, C. (2005b). A unified approach to
Bechtel, W. (1998). Representations and cogni- building and controlling spiking attractor
tive explanations: Assessing the dynamicist networks. Neural Computation, 17(6), 1276-
challenge in cognitive science. Cognitive Sci- 1314.
ence, 22, 295-318. Eliasmith, C., & Anderson, C. H. (2003). Neu-
Bechtel, W., & Graham, G. (Eds.). (1999). A com- ral engineering: Computation, representation
panion to cognitive science. London: Blackwell. and dynamics in neurobiological systems. Cam-
Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (1993). bridge, MA: MIT Press.
Discovering complexity: Decomposition and Eliasmith, C., 8t Thagard, P. (2001). Integrating
localization as strategies in scientific research. structure and meaning: A distributed model
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. of analogical mapping. Cognitive Science, 25(2),
Busemeyer, J. R., & Townsend, J. T. (1993). 245-286.
Decision field theory: A dynamic-cognitive Eliasmith, C., Westover, M. B., & Anderson,
approach to decision making in an uncer- C. H. (2002). A general framework for neu-
tain environment. Psychological Review, 100(3), robiological modeling: An application to the
432-459. vestibular system. Neurocomputing, 46, 1071-
Churchland, P. S., 81 Sejnowski, T. (1992). The 1076.
computational brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Elman, J. L. (1991). Distributed representations,
Press. simple recurrent networks, and grammatical
Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (2002). The extended structure. In D. Touretzky (Ed.), Connection-
mind. In D. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of ist approaches to language learning (pp. 91-122).
mind: Classical and contemporary readings Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer.
(pp. 643-652). New York: Oxford University Finger, S. (2000). The minds behind the brain:
Press. (Reprinted from Analysis, 58,10-23.) A history of the pioneers and their discoveries.
Conklin, J., & Eliasmith, C. (2005). An attractor Oxford: Oxford University Press.
network model of path integration in the rat. Fodor, J., 8l Pylyshyn, Z. (1988). Connectionism
Journal of Computational Neuroscience, ¡8,183- and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis.
203. Cognition, 28, 3-71.
Eliasmith, C. (1996). The third contender: A crit- Freudenthal, H. (1970-1990). Norbert Weiner. In
ical examination of the dynamicist theory of C. C. Gillespie (Ed.), Dictionary of scientific
cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 9(4), 441- biography. New York: Scribner's.
463. Gibson, J. J. (1966). The senses considered as per-
Eliasmith, C. (2000). Is the brain analog or digital? ceptual systems. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
The solution and its consequences for cogni- Gibson, J. J., & Gibson, E. J. (1955). Perceptual
tive science. Cognitive Science Quarterly, 1(2), learning: Differentiation or enrichment? Psy-
147-170. chological Review, 62, 324-341.
Eliasmith, C. (2001). Attractive and in-discrete: A Gorman, R. P., & Sejnowski, T. J. (1988). Analysis
critique of two putative virtues of the dynam- of hidden units in a layered network trained
icist theory of mind. Minds and Machines, u, to classify sonar targets. Neural Networks, 1,
417-426. 75-89.
Eliasmith, C. (2003). Moving beyond metaphors: Hodgkin, A. L., & Huxley, A. F. (1952). A quan-
Understanding the mind for what it is. Journal titative description of membrane current and
of Philosophy, 100(10), 493-520. its application to conduction and excitation in
Eliasmith, C. (2004). Learning context sensitive nerve. Journal of Physiology, 117, 500-544.
logical inference in a neurobiological simula- Holroyd, C., & Coles, M. (2002). The neural basis
tion. In S. Levy & R. Gayler (Eds.), AAA! of human error processing: Reinforcement
Fall Symposium: Compositional Connectionism learning, dopamine, and the error-related neg-
in Cognitive Science (pp. 17-20). Menlo Park, ativity. Psychological Review, 109, 679-709.
CA: Association for the Advancement of Arti- Hubel, D., & Wiesel, T. (1962). Receptive fields,
ficial Intelligence Press. binocular interaction and functional architec-
Eliasmith, C. (2005a). Cognition with neurons: ture in the cat's visual cortex. Journal of Phys-
A large-scale, biologically realistic model of iology (London), 160,106-154.
D Y N A M I C S , C O N T R O L , AND C O G N I T I O N
»37

Hull, C. (1935)- The conflicting psychologies of Port, R., & van Gelder, T. (Eds.). (1995). Mind as
learning - a way out. Psychological Review, 42, motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cogni-
491-516. tion. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Jackendoff, R. (2002). Foundations of language: Rieke, F., Warland, D., de Ruyter van
Brain, meaning, grammar, evolution. Oxford: Steveninick, R., &. Bialek, W. (1997). Spikes:
Oxford University Press. Exploring the neural code. Cambridge, MA:
Kanerva, P. (1994). The spatter code for encoding MIT Press.
concepts at many levels. In M. Marinaro & P. Robertson, S. S., Cohen, A. H., & Mayer-Kress,
G. Morasso (Eds.), Proceedings of the Interna- G. (1993). Behavioural chaos: Beyond the
tional Conference on Artificial Neural Networks metaphor. In L. B. Smith & E. Thelen (Eds.),
(Vol. 1, pp. 226-229). Sorrento, Italy: Springer- A dynamic systems approach to development:
Verlag. Applications (pp. 120-150). Cambridge, MA:
Lockery, S., Fang, Y., & Sejnowski, T. (1990). MIT Press.
A dynamical neural network model of sen- Rumelhart, D. E., & McClelland, J. L. (1986). On
sorimotor transformation in the leech. Neural learning the past tenses of English verbs. In
Computation, 2, 274-282. | L. McClelland 8c D. E. Rumelhart (Eds.),
Miller, P., Brody, C. D., Romo, R., & Wang, X. J. Parallel distributed processing: Explorations in
(2003). A recurrent network model of somato- the micrvstructure of cognition (Vol. 2, pp. 216-
sensory parametric working memory in the 271). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
prefrontal cortex. Cerebral Cortex, 13, 1208- Sejnowski, T. J., & Rosenberg, C. R. (1986).
1218. Nettalk: A parallel network that learns to read
Mindell, D. (1995). Engineers, psychologists, aloud. Cognitive Science Quarterly, 14, 179-
and administrators: Wartime control systems 211.
research, 1941-1945. IEEE Control Systems Mag- Seung, H. S. (1996). How the brain keeps the eyes
azine, 15(4), 91-99- still. In Proceedings of the National Academy of
Newell, A. (1990). Unified theories of cognition. Science, 93,13339-13344.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Smolensky, P. (1990). Tensor product variable
Newell, A., & Simon, H. A. (1972). Human prob- binding and the representation of symbolic
lem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice structures in connectionist systems. Artificial
Hall. Intelligence, 46,159-217.
Oaksford, M., & Chater, N. (1994). A rational Sperber, D., Cara, E., 8c Girotto, R. (1995). Rele-
analysis of the selection task as optimal data vance theory explains the selection task. Cog-
selection. Psychological Review, 101(4), 608- nition, 57, 31-95.
63.. Thagard, P. (1992). Conceptual revolutions. Prince-
Parsons, L., 8c Osherson, D. (2001). N e w evidence ton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
for distinct right and left brain systems for Thagard, P. (1996). Mind: Introduction to cognitive
deductive versus probabilistic reasoning. Cere- science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
bral Cortex, li, 954-965. Thelen, E., 8c Smith, L. B. (1994). A dynamic
Parsons, L., Osherson, D., & Martinez, M. (1999). systems approach to the development of cog-
Distinct neural mechanisms for propositional nition and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT
logic and probabilistic reasoning. Paper pre- Press.
sented at the 40th Annual Meeting of the Psy- van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if
chonomic Society, Dallas, T X . not computation? Journal of Philosophy, 91(7),
Plate, A. (1991). Holographic reduced representa- 345-381.
tions: Convolution algebra for compositional van Gelder, T. (1998). The dynamical hypothe-
distributed representations. In Proceedings of sis in cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain
the 12th International Joint Conference on Artifi- Sciences, 21(5), 615-665.
cial Intelligence (pp. 30-35). San Francisco, C A : van Gelder, T. (1999) Dynamic approaches
Morgan Kaufmann. to cognition. In R. Wilson & F. Keil (Eds.),
p
laut, D. C., & McClelland, J. L. (1993). Gener- The MIT encyclopedia of the cognitive sci-
alization with componential attractors: Word ences (pp. 244-246). Cambridge, MA: MrT
and nonword reading in an attractor network. Press.
In Proceedings of the 15th Annual Conference Wason, P. C. (1966). Reasoning. In B. M. Foss
of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 824-829). (Ed.), New horizons in psychology (pp. 131-151).
Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin.
CHRIS ELIASM1TH

Watson, J. (1913). Psychology as the behaviorist iology of cells in the cat's lateral genicu-
views it. Psychological Review, 20,158-177. late body. Journal of Neurophysiology, 26, 978-
Wiener, N. (1948). Cybernetics: Or the control and 993-
communication in the animal and the machine.Zhang, K. (1996). Representation of spatial orien-
N e w York: John Wiley. tation by the intrinsic dynamics of the head-
Wiesel, T. N . , & Hubel, D. H. (1963). Effects of direction cell ensemble: A theory. Journal of
visual deprivation on morphology and phys- Neuroscience, 16, 2112-2126.
CHAPTER 9

Explanation
Mechanism, Modularity, and Situated Cognition

William Bechtel

The situated cognition movement has further than demanding ecologically valid
emerged in recent decades (although it has experiments - it insists that an agent's cogni-
roots in psychologists working earlier in tive activities are inherently embedded and
the twentieth century including Vygotsky, supported by dynamic interactions with the
Bartlett, and Dewey) largely in reaction to agent's body and features of its environment.
an approach to explaining cognition that Sometimes advocates of a situated
tended to ignore the context in which cogni- approach to cognition present their position
tive activities typically occur. Fodor's (1980) in an extreme manner that sets the situ-
account of the research strategy of method- ated approach in opposition to attempts in
ological solipsism, according to which only cognitive science and cognitive neuroscience
representational states within the mind are to understand the mechanisms within the
viewed as playing causal roles in produc- mind/brain that underlie cognitive perfor-
ln
g cognitive activity, is an extreme char- mance (Agre, 1995; Beer, 1995; Brooks, 1991;
acterization of this approach. (As Keith Suchman, 1987,1993; Thelen 8c Smith, 1994).
Gunderson memorably commented when Advocates of the extended-mind perspec-
Fodor first presented this characterization, tive maintain that cognitive activities (per-
it amounts to reversing behaviorism by con- ceiving, reasoning, problem solving, remem-
n i n g the mind as a white box in a black bering) do not happen just in the head but
world.) Critics as far back as the 1970s extend out into the environment. These
and 1980s objected to many experimental environmental factors become, in this view,
paradigms in cognitive psychology as not part of the mind (Clark & Chalmers, 1998).
being ecologically valid; that is, they main- Such challenges are sometimes presented as
lined that the findings applied only to the opposing the search for mechanisms inside
artificial circumstances created in the labo- the head to explain cognitive activity.
ratory and did not generalize to real-world
My contention is that an appropriate
settings (Neisser, 1976, 1987). The situated
understanding of the situatedness of cog-
°gnition movement, however, goes much
nition does not require the denial that the

155
i56 WILLIAM BECHTEL

proper locus of control (I will elaborate on mechanisms, it will turn out, are always sit-
this notion, developed in Bechtel & Richard- uated and dependent on their environments
son, 1993, further herein) for cognitive activ- as well as in a critical sense distinct from
ity is the mind/brain. That is, for mental them.
phenomena it is appropriate to treat the The same theoretical considerations that
mind/brain as the locus of the responsible inform discussion of the situatedness of cog-
mechanism and to emphasize the boundary nition also provide insight into a related
between the mind/brain and the rest of the controversial topic in cognitive science -
body and between the cognitive agent and the modularity of cognitive systems. In this
its environment. The phenomena for which case, however, the insights into the nature
such a strategy is not appropriate are ones in of mechanisms will lead to rejection of the
which the agent is so intertwined with enti- extreme claims made on behalf of modular-
ties outside itself that the responsible system ity. On the surface, advocates of modular-
includes one or more cognitive agents and ity seem simply to be advancing the same
their environment. These are prototypically claim as those identifying the mind/brain as
social phenomena, not behavioral or psycho- the locus of control for mental activity, only
logical ones. There are explanatory princi- this time at a finer level, identifying it not
ples that determine when it is appropriate to with the whole mind/brain but with a mod-
identify the mind-brain as the locus of con- ule within it. But this strategy of identifying
trol and when it is appropriate to identify the locus of control for a mental activity at a
a larger system as responsible. I will artic- finer level in a mental module is, in general,
ulate a view that maintains that for most poorly motivated. It fails to consider that
explanatory challenges addressed by cogni- explaining the mind/brain's performance of
tive science, the mind/brain is the appropri- a cognitive task involves decomposing it into
ate locus of control even for activities that component operations, each of which con-
depend critically on how the agent is situ- tributes differentially to the performance
ated in an environment. of the task. Performance of most cognitive
Reconciling the cognitive science project tasks requires the orchestrated contribution
of identifying and describing the operations of many components of the cognitive sys-
of mechanisms inside the head with the tem, not just one subsystem.
claims that cognition is situated requires The tension in rejecting modularity and
an appropriate understanding of mecha- yet treating the mind/brain as the locus
nisms. Mechanisms are bounded systems, of control for cognitive activity should be
but ones that are selectively open to their apparent: modularity is rejected as failing to
environment and that often interact with recognize the diverse components involved
and depend on their environment in giv- in performing a cognitive task, and advo-
ing rise to the phenomenon for which they cates of situated cognition likewise main-
are responsible. Moreover, biological mech-
tain that many cognitive activities involve
anisms operate in the context of active, self-
components outside the agent itself. Yet it
maintaining organisms that are dependent
is a consistent position to reject modular-
on their environments and, yet are in an
ity within the mind/brain and yet maintain
important sense autonomous from them.
that the mind/brain is the locus of control
Developing this perspective, however, will
for cognitive activities. Showing w h y this
require a bit of an excursion through theo-
is consistent requires developing in more
retical biology. It will bear fruit as I consider
detail the project of explanation in terms
later in the chapter how the mind and its
of mechanism. To set the context for that,
cognitive mechanisms should be considered
I will begin by exploring the reasoning that
distinct systems while acting through and
has guided advocates of modularity and con-
depending on the world external to them.
trast that with the mechanistic perspec-
Biological mechanisms, including cognitive
tive.
EXPLANATION: MECHANISM, MODULARITY, AND SITUATED COGNITION xfrj

i. Dividing Minds that emphasize more or less separation of


the activities associated with modules. Per-
Dividing the mind/brain into component haps the most extreme view of the segrega-
systems or modules has been a common tion of modules is found in Fodor (1983).
strategy in both philosophical and psycho- He identifies nine characteristics of mod-
logical theorizing. Plato's tripartite division ules: they (1) are domain specific, (2) are
of the soul into a reasoning, a spirited, and mandatory in their operation, (3) allow only
an appetitive element was an early exem- limited access to the computations of other
plar. Faculty psychology, as developed in the modules, (4) are fast, (5) are information-
eighteenth century by Christian von Wolff ally encapsulated, (6) have shallow outputs,
and Thomas Reid, appealed to separate (7) are associated with fixed neural archi-
mental faculties responsible for activities tectures, (8) exhibit characteristic and spe-
such as reasoning, remembering, judging, cific breakdown patterns, and (9) exhibit a
and willing. At the outset of the nineteenth characteristic pace and sequence in devel-
century Franz Joseph Gall (1812) aligned opment. Of these, the fifth, informational
the division of the mind into faculties with encapsulation, is both the feature Fodor
his differentiation of regions in the brain. most emphasizes and the one that makes his
Gall's characterization of brain regions in account of modules especially strong. Infor-
terms of cranial protrusions and inden- mational encapsulation, for Fodor, entails
tations was problematic, but the project that a module only employs information
of localizing mental faculties in the brain encoded within it in its processing; it cannot
obtained greater respectability when Paul use information stored in another module,
Broca (1861) proposed the localization of or in what he terms central cognition. Cen-
articulate speech in the left prefrontal cor- tral cognition, in contrast, is holistic in that
tex on the basis of deficits in patients with anything a person knows might be applied
brain lesions. in revising one's beliefs or determining how
The localization projects of the nine- well supported a belief is. As a result of being
teenth century were supplanted in the early encapsulated, modules for Fodor do not
twentieth century by more holistic views exhibit much intelligence; accordingly, he
of the brain and the behaviorist tradition views only input processing, language pro-
in psychology (both traditions are exem- cessing, and possibly motor-output process-
plified in the work of Karl Lashley, 1950). ing as modular. He construes the modularity
The behaviorist tradition emphasized gen- of input processing as in fact a virtue. Inso-
eral learning procedures and hence rejected far as input modules cannot be influenced by
the quest for discrete psychological mecha- one's knowledge and expectations, they can
nisms underlying different behaviors. One of provide information about the world that
the features of the development of cognitive is not theory laden and can hence provide
psychology in the 1950s and beyond was the a theory-neutral basis on which to evalu-
attempt to identify different mechanisms as ate competing scientific hypotheses (Fodor,
responsible for different abilities (consider, 1984).
for example, the different types of memory Evolutionary psychologists have adopted
stores posited in Atkinson & Shiffrin's 1968 Fodor's conception of modules without lim-
classical memory model, as well as the dif- iting them to input systems. Instead, they
ferentiation of memory systems by Tulving "see cognition as modular right through
and his collaborators; see Schacter & Tulv- from input to decision processes" (Shetde-
ing, 1994). worth, 2000, p. 54). Although there are
In this context the term module began to weaker notions of modularity avadable,
be employed for the mechanisms respon- there is a powerful, if ultimately mistaken,
sible for different types of processing. T h e consideration that leads evolutionary psy-
term has been used in a variety of ways chologists to extend Fodor's conception of
WILLIAM BECHTEL

encapsulated modules. A major objective unity of mind. The rejection of the possibil-
of evolutionary psychology is to show how ity of dividing minds was a central feature of
human cognitive abilities such as reasoning Descartes' contention that the mind could
about coalitions, detecting cheaters, mak- not be a physical entity but must be immate-
ing risk-aversive decisions, or understanding rial. It also figured prominently in Flourens's
other minds could have emerged through (1824) criticisms of Gall's phrenology and
evolution. For theorists such as Cosmides in the early-twentieth-century rejection of
and Tooby (1994; see also Cosmides, Tooby, neural localization by Lashley (1929) and
& Barkow, 1992), the evolution of new others. A similar holist bent manifests in
modules, especially in the relatively recent many contemporary dynamical systems the-
period since the Pleistocene, is possible only orists who reject the decomposition of the
if the modules are encapsulated and able mind into component functions and the at-
to be selected individually. Cummins and tempt to localize such functions in the brain
Allen (1998) succinctly capture the close either through lesion experiments or func-
affinity evolutionary psychologists identify tional neuroimaging (Uttal, 2001; van Orden
between modularity and evolution: & Paap, 1997; van Orden, Pennington, &
Stone, 2001).
Taking an evolutionary approach to the
Fodor's rejection of modules in central
explanation of cognitive function follows
naturally from the growing body of neuro- cognition ironically aligns him (an arch
scientific evidence showing that the mind defender of symbolic accounts of cognition)
is divisible The Cartesian view of a with dynamical systems theorists. His con-
seamless whole makes it hard to see how strual of central cognition as using any infor-
such a whole could haw come into being, mation the agent possesses reflects a strong
except perhaps by an act of divine creation. holistic perspective. But whereas Fodor sees
By recognizing the modularity of mind, the inability to differentiate central cogni-
however, it is possible to see how human
tion into modules as undermining the possi-
mentality might be explained by the grad-
bility of scientific explanation (Fodor's first
ual accretion of numerous special function
pieces of mind. (p. 3J law of the nonexistence of cognitive sci-
ence), dynamical systems theory advances a
Not all theorists who invoke mental mod- scientific program for explaining the activ-
ules treat encapsulation as the central fea- ities of cognitive systems. The strategy is
ture. Dan Sperber (1994, 2001, 2005), for to develop differential equations relating
example, construes as the defining mark of variables that characterize the system being
modules the fact that they operate on spe- modeled. The nonlinear nature of these
cific domains of inputs. On such an account, equations generates complex patterns of
domains such as arithmetic, face recogni- change that can be represented in diagrams
tion, and reading are viewed as processed showing, for example, the attractor land-
by distinct dedicated modules. Even for scape of such a system, but not easily charac-
Sperber, modules operate relatively inde- terized in terms of the behavior of individual
pendently of one another: a module is trig- system components.
gered by input within its specific domain Not only do some dynamical systems the-
and, "once it is performing its function, a
orists resist any attempt to decompose the
module works on its own and is unable to
mind into separate modules (van Gelder,
take advantage of information that might be
199.5, >998), but also they reject drawing a
present in the system as a whole but that is
sharp distinction between the mind/brain
found neither in the input nor in the pro-
and the rest of the body and the environ-
prietary data-base of the module" (Sperber,
ment in which the mind operates. Equations
2005, p. 56).
describing the relations between variables
The opposition to dividing the mind into within the brain can be coupled with those
modules is usually portrayed as stemming characterizing variables external to it (Beer,
from radical holists who emphasize the 2000; Keijzer, 2001; Kelso, 1995). Because on
xfrj
e x p l a n a t i o n : mechanism, m o d u l a r i t y , a n d situated c o g n i t i o n

such an approach there is no fundamental of humans and animals as hydraulic sys-


difference between variables characterizing tems in which the flow of animal spirits was
the cognitive system and those characteriz- altered by sensory experience and directed
ing features outside the system, the dynami- through the system so as to cause the motion
cal approach is readily able to integrate phe- of the limbs. Subsequent to Descartes, the
nomena from the mind and the world and strategy of explaining biological phenomena
capture the embodied and situated nature in terms of machines was pursued by many
of cognition. biologists, though contested by others who
Although much is often made of the insisted that some features of living systems
opposition between modular and holistic simply could not be explained in mechani-
approaches, I will argue that the dichotomy cal terms and required something extra. This
is actually a false one. This is best appreci- was the basis of the long-enduring vitalist/
ated by considering the nature of mechanis- mechanist controversy in biology.
tic explanation. Whereas most philosophical For Descartes and other early mechanists,
accounts, including philosophical accounts a mechanism produced its behavior in virtue
of psychology, advert to laws as the vehicle of the size, shape, and motion of its parts.
of explanation, most explanations advanced Over time the repertoire of types of compo-
in the life sciences make no reference to nent parts expanded and these parts increas-
laws, and when laws do appear, they do ingly were conceived of as entities actively
so in an ancillary role. As Robert Cummins doing things. For example, after Berzelius
(woo) notes, in psychology laws are typi- (1836) introduced the notion of a catalyst
cally referred to as effects, and they typically as an entity that promoted a chemical reac-
characterize phenomena in need of expla- tion without being consumed in it, chemists
nation but do not themselves explain the commonly invoked catalysts to explain reac-
phenomena. Rather, what serves to explain tions that would not otherwise occur under
a phenomenon is an account of the mech- the conditions realized (e.g., at the exist-
anism responsible for producing it. As will ing temperature). In the early nineteenth
be discussed herein, the parts of biological century many chemists construed yeast not
mechanisms are not totally isolated mod- as a living organism but simply as a chem-
ules. Rather, the parts of a mechanism are ical catalyst that promoted fermentation.
often highly interactive in the production Once it was determined to be a living organ-
of any phenomenon. Yet they also have an ism in the middle of the century, chemists
identity of their own, and there are good and subsequendy biochemists sought cata-
explanatory reasons to differentiate them lysts, later termed enzymes, within yeast that
from their environmental context. could account for fermentation. This project
finally bore fruit in the early decades of
the twentieth century (Bechtel, 1986, 2006,
| Mechanisms and M e c h a n i s t i c chap. 3). Implicit in early accounts of mech-
Explanations anism was the fact that the parts of a mech-
anism had to be appropriately organized to
The conception of mechanism has its roots perform their functions; the emphasis on
in the machines that humans build. Much organization became far more explicit after
Greek philosophy viewed machines as Bernard (1865) appealed to the organization
operating in opposition to nature. For many in living systems in his attempt to explain
natural philosophers of the scientific revo- how organisms could do the sorts of things
lution, however, machines came to provide vitalists had claimed would not be possible
the model for understanding processes in if the organisms were mere mechanisms.
®e natural world (Garber, 2002). Descartes Recendy, a number of philosophers have
extended the idea of mechanism not only to advanced accounts of what counts as a
the inorganic world but also to the animate mechanism in biology (Bechtel & Richard-
world itself, construing the nervous systems son, 1993; Glennan, 1996, 2002; Machamer,
Darden, & Craver, 2000). My preferred into component parts (structural decom-
account is this one: "A mechanism is a position). Ultimately, the goal is to line
structure performing a function in virtue of up the parts with the operations they per-
its component parts, component operations, form, which Richardson and I refer to as
and their organization. The orchestrated "localization" (Bechtel & Richardson, 1993).
functioning of the mechanism is responsi- Although the notion of levels has proved a
ble for one or more phenomena" (Bechtel, vexed one (Craver, 2007), there is a clear
2006; Bechtel & Abrahamsen, 2005). sense in which the parts and operations
Mechanisms exist in nature, whereas within a mechanism are situated at a lower
mechanistic explanation involves an inves- level of organization than is the mecha-
tigator presenting an account of the mech- nism itself. Mechanistic explanation is in this
anism taken to be responsible for a given sense reductionist (Bechtel, 2007). The fact
phenomenon. Typically, the explanation that the operations that parts of a mecha-
involves describing or depicting the com- nism perform are different from the phe-
ponent parts, operations, and their organi- nomenon exhibited by the whole mecha-
zation (diagrams are often far more useful nism and individually do not realize the
than linguistic descriptions for this purpose). phenomenon makes the working parts of a
Understanding how the orchestrated opera- mechanism different from domain-specific
tion of the parts produces the phenomenon modules.
of interest, investigators must simulate the The parts of a mechanism need not be
operation of the mechanism, either mentally spatially contiguous but may be distributed
or by using model systems or computer sim- throughout the mechanism. What is essen-
ulations. tial for something to count as a part is that it
At the heart of the understanding of a performs an operation for the mechanism
mechanism is the idea that it consists of parts that is different from the operations per-
that perform different operations. Already formed by other parts. The cardiovascular
here the conception of components of a system of an organism and the glycolysis
mechanism departs from the conception of system of a cell each consists of distributed
modules. Although advocates of modules parts that perform different operations.
do sometimes talk in terms of submodules, Individual enzymes, for example, catalyze
they do not focus on the decomposition of different reactions, whereas individual co-
what the overall system does into contribut- factors are reversibly oxidized in particular
ing operations. Rather, a module is identified reactions. These are distributed through the
with a domain of performance - the mod- cytoplasm of the cell, but their operations
ule performs one of the tasks performed by are so coordinated as to constitute the mech-
the overall system. In fact, sometimes the anism of fermentation. As I will develop in
discovery of a mechanism begins in this way the next section, neither such mechanisms
(in Bechtel & Richardson, 1993, we spoke themselves nor their parts are encapsulated
of this as simple localization). But over time from each other in the manner of Fodorian
investigators often learn that other parts are modules.
involved in producing the phenomenon and
that the part in question only performs one
of the required operations. The result is a 3. Nearly Decomposable Mechanisms
model of an integrated system responsible versus Encapsulated Modules
for the phenomenon, not a single compo-
nent. At first pass, mechanistic explanation may
Identifying the parts and their opera- seem not to alter the modules/holism
tions requires decomposing the mechanism. dichotomy but rather simply to take the
Different techniques enable investigators to side of modularity. A mechanism is dif-
decompose a mechanism into component ferentiated from its environment and the
operations (functional decomposition) or mechanism is decomposed into parts that
xfrj
e x p l a n a t i o n : mechanism, m o d u l a r i t y , and situated c o g n i t i o n

perform their own operations. In fact, tak- theoretical consequences of near decompos-
ing mechanisms seriously and focusing espe- ability:
cially on the sorts of mechanisms that arise
in biology radically alters the picture. It is (1) in a nearly decomposable system the
no longer appropriate to think in terms of a short-run behavior of each of the compo-
dichotomy between modular accounts and nent subsystems is approximately indepen-
dent of the short-run behavior of the other
holistic ones, but of a continuum in which
components; (2) in the long run the behav-
various designs of mechanisms occupy the
ior of any one of the components depends
middle. The differentiation of mechanisms in only an aggregative way on the behavior
from one another and the division of mech- of the other components, (p. 198)
anisms into component parts and operations
is partial. This is because the operations of One factor making for nearly decomposable
the component parts of a mechanism are systems in the organic world is the fact that
determined not just by their internal con- chemical bonds are of different strengths.
stitution (their subparts, the operations of Covalent bonds require much more energy
these subparts, and the way they are orga- to make or break than do ionic bonds, and
nized) but also by both the conditions arising these in turn are stronger than hydrogen
within the mechanism as a result of the oper- bonds. Structures built with stronger bonds
ation of other components and the exter- will remain stable despite the formation or
nal factors impinging on the mechanism. breaking of weaker bonds, enabling higher-
The boundaries of the part partially isolate level structures to form without disrupting
it from other parts but do not completely more basic structures. Thus, the system can
encapsulate it in Fodor's sense. Rather, each be decomposed at one level, leaving intact
part is typically affected in a variety of ways structures at levels lower in the hierarchy.
by activity occurring elsewhere in the mech- Hierarchical, nearly decomposable sys-
anism. tems are not the only possible complex sys-
The assumption of decomposability in tems. But Simon offers a powerful reason for
scientific investigations is a heuristic as- thinking that natural systems, especially bio-
sumption that is only partially true of any logical systems, will be such: nearly decom-
given mechanism. Herbert Simon articu- posable systems are much more likely to
lated the idea that natural systems would form, especially via processes such as nat-
most likely be nearly decomposable, hierar- ural selection. Simon illustrates this point
chical systems and that our ability to under- through the parable of two watchmakers
stand them depends on this characteristic. who make equally fine watches of one
By characterizing natural systems as hier- thousand parts. Tempus shuns hierarchical
archical, Simon (1996) claims that they are designs and makes watches in which all one
"composed of interrelated subsystems, each thousand parts must be in the right config-
of the latter being in turn hierarchic in struc- uration before the watch is stable. Hora, on
ture until we reach some lowest level of ele- the other hand, adopts the principle of hier-
mentary subsystems" (p. 184) and, moreover, archical design in which the whole watch
that there is a "small or moderate number'' of consists of ten stable subassemblies, each
types of subsystem at any level in the hier- comprising ten parts that are in turn sta-
ble subassemblies made of ten parts. Allow-
archy (p. 186). Decomposability refers to the
ing that there is a small probability (.01) of
independence of the subsystems at any given
interruption per addition of a part (e.g., for
level. If the subsystems are completely inde-
phone calls to take orders), Simon estab-
pendent, except for sending outputs from
lishes that it will take Tempus four thou-
°ne subsystem to another, the system is
sand times as long to make a watch as Hora.
fully decomposable. If the interactions are
Simon generalizes this point to evolution
weak, but not negligible, according to Simon
by arguing that stable subassemblies can be
the system is nearly decomposable. Simon
selected for even in the absence of the fully
(1996) offers the following as the main
i6z WILLIAM BECHTEL

developed system that is responsible for a Although Simon phrases his account in
trait in modern organisms, whereas without terms of near decomposability rather than
stable subassemblies the emergence of com- strict decomposability, he does not advance
plex systems would be virtually impossible reasons for thinking that living systems will
because it would require a very unlikely con- be only nearly decomposable rather than
stellation of independent events. strictly decomposable. But a brief glance at
Simon (1996) thinks not only that systems the genetics of modern organisms suggests a
in nature are nearly decomposable hierar- reason: most genes do not directly code for
chical ones but also that we may be able to traits but rather regulate the expression of
understand only those systems in our world other genes. This suggests that evolution has
that are such: not worked simply by promoting individual
components but by modulating the behav-
The fact then that many complex sys- ior of already-existing components. Such
tems have a nearly decomposable, hierar- modulation of one component by another
chic structure is a major facilitating factor is manifest not just in genetic regulation
enabling us to understand, describe, and
but also in the operation of components
even "see" such systems and their parts.
within organisms. The biochemical system
Or perhaps the proposition should be put
the other way round. If there are important in even relatively simple organisms involves
systems in the world that are complex with- a huge number of interactions among dif-
out being hierarchic, they may to a consid- ferent chemical pathways, allowing differ-
erable extent escape our observation and ent pathways to shunt products elsewhere
understanding. Analysis of their behavior or recruit materials from elsewhere. This
would involve such detailed knowledge and quickly reduces the decomposability of the
calculation of the interactions of their ele- overall system, yet it does not yield com-
mentary parts that it would be beyond plete holistic integration. Individual path-
our capacities of memory or computation, ways operate semiautonomously even while
(p. 207)
coordinating and orchestrating their opera-
Already in Simon's account of Tempus tion with other components. Scientists can
and Hora there is clearly a strong contrast isolate subsystems, either in their models or
between modular accounts in cognitive sci- in their experiments, and render the oper-
ence and components of a system for Simon. ation of the whole system intelligible in
The parts of a watch do not themselves keep terms of its parts, even while recognizing
time but perform operations that enable the how different components can also mod-
watch to keep time. Likewise, it is not the ulate the operation of other components.
tasks carried out by the whole cognitive sys- In their understanding, the components are
tem that are assigned to parts, but operations independent only to a first approximation.
that work together to perform the task. Near This first account can then be elaborated in
decomposability allows that the compo- a more refined account that recognizes the
nents, to a first approximation, depend only interaction of the components.
on the overall operation of the other com- Simon provides one avenue for appreci-
ponents, not on the individual steps in the ating the sorts of differentiation of compo-
operation of the other components. Opera- nents that arise in biological systems and
tions within components, Simon maintains, how such differentiation differs from that
will transpire on a shorter time scale than proposed in modular accounts of cognition.
operations between components and can be But a different perspective can be provided
averaged over. Moreover, modifications in by considering some of the basic demands
one component that do not affect features placed on living organisms, demands that
on which other components depend can be make it important for them to segregate
made independently, allowing selection to themselves from their environments and
promote variants in one component without ultimately to segregate some of their mech-
sacrificing the success of other components. anisms from one another. As a result of
xfrj
e x p l a n a t i o n : m e c h a n i s m , MODULARITY, a n d s i t u a t e d c o g n i t i o n

being highly organized, biological systems, they are in higher concentration to the
like humanly constructed mechanisms, must side in which they are in lower concen-
be assembled and will dissipate over time. tration. Accordingly, while segregating
Unlike humanly constructed mechanisms, many of their constituents from the exter-
however, biological systems cannot rely on nal milieu, membranes do not cut them
external agents either for their initial assem- off completely. Membranes, moreover, are
bly (development) or for maintenance and not limited to passive transport but can
repair. The living organism must perform incorporate enzymes that actively trans-
these activities itself. port selected substances across them, either
Performance of these activities requires to move substances across the membrane
that organisms exist in energy gradients from that are unable to pass through it on their
which they can extract and use free energy own or to move substances in opposition
and raw materials. Any living system there- to their concentration gradients. Through
fore requires metabolic processes that cap- opportunistically designed transport mech-
ture and render energy in usable forms. anisms, living systems are able to admit
Metabolism is also required to process mat- selectively those substances they need to
ter recruited from outside into a form from continue the process of constituting and
which its parts can be constructed or recon- reconstituting themselves and to remove
structed, and additional mechanisms are substances, including the waste products of
required to carry out these constructions. their metabolism, that will prove toxic to
Although it is conceivable that such pro- their internal operations. Of course these
cesses could occur in an aqueous milieu capacities of the membrane do not come
that imposed no separation from the sur- for free - they must be paid for in the cur-
rounding environment as long as the requi- rency of energy and constructed through
site metabolites and enzymes were in suf- the mechanism of catabolism and synthe-
ficiendy high concentrations, such a set of sis. But the critical point is that a minimal
metabolic and constructive processes would living system such as I have characterized
be extremely vulnerable. Biochemical reac- constitutes what Alvero Moreno, following
tions depend on concentrations of reactants, Maturana and Varela (1980), calls an "auton-
and most reactions are reversible and will omous system": "a far-from-equihbrium sys-
run in the opposite direction when reactant tem that constitutes and maintains itself
concentrations are unfavorable. Thus, some establishing an organizational identity of
means must be found to segregate these con- its own, a functionally integrated (home-
stituents of living systems from their envi- ostatic and active) unit based on a set of
ronments and maintain them in high con- endergonic-exergonic couplings between
centration if the reactions are to function internal self-constructing processes, as well
properly. Living systems rely on biologi- as with other processes of interaction with
cal membranes to segregate themselves, and its environment" (Ruiz-Mirazo, Peret6, &
component systems within them, from their Moreno, 2004, p. 330). A critical feature of
environment. Following such a line of rea- an autonomous system is that it is an active
soning, Tibor GSnti (1975, 2003) incorpo- system that operates to maintain itself. As
rated a metabolic system and a membrane- such, it imposes a demand on the sub-
construction system as two of the three systems (mechanisms) that constitute it -
constituents in his "chemoton" model of the their operation is keyed to the survival of
simplest chemical system exhibiting the fea- the system itself.1
tures of life. G&nti effectively demonstrated Even in this minimal configuration, an
how such a system would exhibit many of autonomous system is operating on its envi-
the features we associate with life. ronment by extracting nutrients from it and
Biological membranes are semiperme- excreting waste products into it. If the envi-
able. Even passively they allow some ronment is particularly hospitable and con-
metabolites to pass from the side in which stant, such a simple organism may succeed
164 WILLIAM BECHTEL

in preserving itself by absorbing metabolites the environment so as to procure these


and expelling waste. Many marine inverte- resources. But there is also systemic clo-
brates, such as jellyfish, are osmoconform- sure - the parts and operations within the
ers - they are isotonic with their saltwater system operate to maintain themselves as
environment and rely on that environment a system even as environmental conditions
to provide the appropriate concentrations change. Understanding how they do so is
of salt and other essential solutes. Typically, an important scientific challenge and justi-
however, such a hospitable environment fies the strategy of conceptualizing them as
cannot be counted on and an organism must independent.
be proactive and generate the right circum- So far I have focused only on segregating
stances in its environment or navigate to the whole living organism from its external
suitable environments. But the principles environment. Simple living organisms such
already articulated can be extended to allow as bacteria have only a membrane surround-
for a broader range of engagements with ing their whole cytoplasm. This provides
the environment, including operations that for extremely efficient exchange between
change conditions in the environment. For different chemical constituents such as the
example, a cell might excrete chemical metabolic pathways, the process of protein
substances into the environment that alter synthesis, and the information-storage
the environment in ways advantageous to system (DNA). But as more complex
the organism. Once an organism develops systems evolved, a new problem arose - the
mechanisms for locomotion (e.g., flagella possibility that different mechanisms would
in single-celled organisms), it is no longer interfere with one other. A particularly
dependent on the environment to bring dramatic example is provided by the intro-
nutrients to it and remove its waste, but it duction of hydrolytic enzymes that serve to
can move to secure nutrients and avoid the decompose cellular structures as they age
toxic effects of its waste products. These or are no longer needed so that their con-
operations of the living system involve stituents can be either reused by the cell or
changes to the environment outside the expelled. Such enzymes play an important
organism, but the operations are performed role in enhancing the autonomy of these
by the organism (or mechanisms with- cells. Because such enzymes would clearly
in it). be dangerous if they were allowed to float
Focusing on the fact that biological sys- free in the cytoplasm, internal membranes
tems are autonomous systems in the sense had to evolve to segregate them from the
described, we can understand why, in the- rest. In eukaryote cells several such sets of
orizing about them, it is appropriate to membranes have evolved to segregate sets
construe them as differentiated from their of enzymes responsible for different cell
environments. Their autonomy depends on operations into distinct organelles. As with
their having component mechanisms that the cell membrane itself, though, these
perform the necessary operations to main- membranes are semipermeable and, though
tain themselves and that these are organized they concentrate particular materials,
so as to operate appropriately together. As provide them with a hospitable context
such, living systems are appropriate objects to perform their operations and somewhat
of analysis. They are what Richardson and I segregate them from other cell components,
termed loci of control for various vital phe- they do not impose absolute boundaries.
nomena. This does not mean that they are In fact, impenetrable boundaries between
isolated and totally independent of their component organelles would be extremely
environment. Rather, as open systems, they deleterious for a cell because coordinating
are critically dependent on their environ- the operations performed by the different
ment for energy and raw materials and to organelles typically relies on complex mes-
remove their waste products. In more com- saging systems linking different mechanisms
plex organisms, operations reach out into and parts of mechanisms.
EXPLANATION: MECHANISM, MODULARITY, AND SITUATED COGNITION .65

A. Situated a n d E m b o d i e d tasks becomes possible, making each depen-


Cognitive M e c h a n i s m s dent on the operations of the others. As a
result, a cell republic (multicellular organ-
Having argued that mechanistic explana- ism), like a political republic, is capable of
tion does not have to endorse either the doing things that an individual cell or person
strongly modular approach of Fodor and cannot. The whole organism now becomes
evolutionary psychologists or the extreme an autonomous system, needing to construct
holism of dynamicist critics, but allows for and maintain itself in the face of environ-
identifying systems on a continuum between mental factors that would lead to its dissipa-
them, I turn now to the specific implica- tion.
tions of thinking about cognition as embod- The division of labor and mutual depen-
ied and situated. As we will see, the account dency between parts of the system is espe-
I have offered supports an understanding cially clear with organisms composed of
of embodiment and situatedness without different organ systems. Individual organs
requiring that we extend the mind out into perform different operations that are
the world or deny the differentiation of the required by the whole organism - extracting
mind/brain from the rest of the organism nutrients and oxygen from the environment,
and the external world. distributing these through the organism,
We have already seen in the previous executing locomotion, and so on. Segregat-
section that living organisms are differen- ing these activities in different organs allows
tiated from their environments as systems each to perform its operations without con-
that construct and reconstruct themselves. tinual interference from the others. But it
Moreover, to understand how organisms is also important that these systems remain
accomplish this, scientists need to differ- open to one another so as to maintain the
entiate the organism from its environment appropriate conditions for the operation of
while recognizing the various ways in which each component. In an early attempt to
the organism engages its environment. In the understand such coordinated operation, and
account so far I have focused only on indi- thereby provide an answer to vitalists (e.g.,
vidual cells and single-celled organisms. The Bichat, 1805) who thought maintaining life
evolutionary route from single-celled organ- was beyond the capability of any mecha-
isms to multicellular organisms is far from nism, Claude Bernard (1865) introduced the
clear, but it is evident that true multicel- idea of differentiating two environments -
lular organisms are more than an aggrega- the environment in which the organism as
tion of single-celled organisms. Rather, they a whole lives and the internal environment
involve a differentiation of cell types that in which the different organ systems oper-
perform different operations. Once cells are ate. By construing each organ as responsive
differentiated and perform different func- to the conditions of the internal, not exter-
tions, some means of integrating them into nal, environment, Bernard proposed to show
an operative whole is required. Such integra- that their operations were causally determi-
tion does not obviate the demand that indi- nate, which Bichat had denied. But more
vidual cells maintain themselves but extends importantly, he viewed each organ as oper-
the resources for doing so by allowing for ating so as to maintain specific aspects of
specialization of the functioning of individ- | the internal environment in a constant con-
ual cells so that each performs a differ- dition, thereby making the whole organism
ent set of operations needed by the oth- stable against perturbations in the exter-
ers. Accordingly, theorists such as Rudolf nal environment. This idea was further
virchow (1858), who played a major role developed by Walter Cannon (1929), who
in establishing that cells derived from pre- introduced the concept of homeostasis and
existing cells via cell division, conceived of described a number of mechanisms through
multicellular organisms as cell republics. 2 which organs of the body helped main-
Although each cell is a living unit, division of tain homeostasis. These mechanisms may
i66 WILLIAM BECHTEL

involve behaviors of the whole organism world in which it operates but is nonethe-
that configure the environment in a manner less highly connected to that world. Even the
that preserves the homeostasis of the indi- simplest living organisms, as we have already
vidual (Richter, 1942-1943).' noted, are distinct autonomous systems that
Many of the control mechanisms Cannon extract energy and raw materials from their
identified involved the brain, specifically the environment and put these to use to con-
autonomic nervous system. As important as stitute and reconstitute themselves. But in
the brain is as a regulator of what occurs else- more complex animals, this will involve per-
where in the body, there is a risk of focus- forming a larger variety of behaviors (prey-
ing exclusively on it. When we conceptu- ing on other organisms or avoiding preda-
alize control, we often think hierarchically tors) and navigating the environment. These
and situate all decision making at the top of interactions with the environment alter it,
the hierarchy. This, however, works poorly often in ways that affect the organism itself.
in both biology and social institutions. As a Accordingly, there is both isolation from the
result, biological systems usually have mul- environment as the organism maintains its
tiple layers of control arranged such that own identity and engagement with it.
higher-level control systems can bias the The dependencies on the environment
functioning of lower-level ones (often by are particularly important in understanding
affecting the conditions under which more higher cognitive tasks. There has been a ten-
local control systems operate) but do not dency to think of these as occurring solely
direcdy determine the behavior of the lower in the organism, but doing so runs the risk
level systems. This can be appreciated by of assuming that the mind can do more than
focusing on organisms in which cortical- it in fact can. The symbolic tradition in cog-
level control systems have been removed - nitive science, for example, tends to assume
in such cases, many functions continue that the mind itself has the power of a uni-
unimpaired but cannot be (directly) coor- versal computer. It is useful in this regard
dinated in the service of higher-level objec- to recall how Turing (1936; see also Post,
tives (Stein & Smith, 1997). (They can some- 1936) himself was led to the conception of
times be indirecdy coordinated via their a Turing machine as an abstract model for
interaction with other components of the a computer. Extant computers - humans
system that may still be under higher-level whose profession was to carry out com-
control. Thus, in patients in which a sev- plex arithmetic calculations - provided the
ered corpus callosum prevents direct com- model for the Turing machine. These indi-
munication between the two hemispheres viduals learned and applied a finite number
of the brain, one hemisphere can still learn of procedures to problems that were written
from observing the behavior resulting from on paper. In turn they wrote the results of
the motor commands that the other hemi- successive operations on the paper and used
sphere has issued.) The existence of mul- these as inputs for further operation. The
tiple control systems all modulating the human provided the model of the finite state
behavior of local components requires that device in the Turing machine, and the paper
these components not be encapsulated from became the model for the tape (or memory
other components of the system but open in in the computer). In thinking of the mind
appropriate ways to them. itself as a Turing machine or a computer, the
The perspective of organisms as auton- operations that reached out into the envi-
omous systems maintaining themselves ronment are resituated inside the mind. But
through their activities, including activities the mind/brain may not have such resources
that modify the world around them, pro- and, by thinking it does, cognitive scientists
vides a way to conceptualize the mind/brain may set themselves up for failure. 4
both as an organ of a living organism and as Nonetheless, while relying on environ-
embodied and situated in the world. As part mental resources, it is still the cognitive
of an organism, it is differentiated from the agent that is performing these activities in
e x p l a n a t i o n : mechanism, m o d u l a r i t y , a n d situated c o g n i t i o n xfrj

pursuit of its ends. It is the cognitive agent nistic explanation as applied to biological
that has an interest in performing the task organisms, I have extracted some insights
and in recruiting components of its environ- into both the modularity of the mind/brain
ment to enable such performance. Indeed, and the situatedness of cognition. Biologi-
in the case of the human computer per- cal systems are typically bounded, and there
forming calculations, he or she typically did are good reasons for the mechanisms within
so for basic biological ends - securing a them, including cognitive ones, to be segre-
paycheck that would provide the food and gated from one another. But the boundaries
other resources needed to maintain him- or between the organism and its environment
herself. In this the cognitive agent is like and between components and subcompo-
autonomous biological systems that perform nents within it are permeable. Accordingly,
operations in their environment so as to even when we identify a particular sys-
secure matter and energy needed to build tem as a locus of control of a particular
and repair themselves and dispose of wastes function, we need not impute full respon-
that are toxic to them. sibility to that component. Its operation
may be dependent on features of its envi-
Just as the move from individual cells to
ronment, whether an internal environment
cell republics resulted in identifying a new
within the organism or an external envi-
locus of control at the level of the organ-
ronment in which the organism functions.
ism for the behaviors of the organism, so
It may act on and alter its environment
researchers may find the need to move to a
in ways that facilitate maintaining itself as
more inclusive system for explaining some
an individual system. Thus, we can demar-
phenomena involving humans or other ani- cate the cognitive system whde still exam-
mals. Just as individual cells may specialize ining how it is situated in and interactive
their operations and coordinate them so as to with the rest of the organism and the envi-
maintain a multicellular organism, so indi- ronment in which the organism is situ-
vidual organisms may specialize their activi- ated.
ties and coordinate them to maintain a larger
system such as a social network. In these Turning to organisms, I have identified
cases, the social network becomes the locus reasons why it is useful to segregate differ-
of control for certain phenomena — those ent operations in different organs or parts of
that are carried out by the social network the system. Unlike in appeals to modularity,
in the service of it. Such activity, however, the focus in developing mechanistic expla-
takes us beyond situated cognition to social nations is on decomposing the overall activ-
activity. Moreover, there is a principled rea- ity into component activities. Segregating,
son for shifting the locus of control to the however, does not mean isolating. In fact,
social network: it is the network itself that living systems are typically highly integrated
is being maintained by the operations per- despite the differentiation of operations
formed (either between the constituents of between different organs and cell types. The
the network or in the environment in which mind/brain seems to be no different on this
the social network is situated). Situated cog- score - it consists of component processing
nition, though, refers to the cognitive activ- areas that perform different computations
ities of agents situated in an environment, that are nonetheless highly integrated with
and the locus of control for these cognitive one another. Such a mechanism does not
activities remains the individual cognitive typically include encapsulated modules, and
agent. one is not likely to find them in the mind/
brain.
Turning to the whole organism, the tra-
5- Conclusions ditional view, which treats the skin as the
boundary of the organism and the mind
By considering the kind of explanation as coterminous with the brain and cen-
appropriate to biological systems, mecha- tral nervous system, is well motivated. The
i6S WILLIAM BECHTEL

organism is the system that maintains itself activity may rely not on internal symbols but
as a result of the operations it performs, and on external ones on which a mind, oper-
the brain and central nervous system com- ating like a connectionist network that has
learned to associate one pattern with another,
prise the system within it that performs crit-
may operate. For further discussion, see Clark
ical regulatory tasks. The mind/brain itself
(1987) and Bechtel and Abrahamsen (2002).
and the organism as a whole are open sys-
tems and dependent on the environment;
hence, the quest to understand how a cogni- References
tive agent together with its various cognitive
mechanisms is situated in its environment is Agre, P. E. (1995). Computational research on
also well motivated. interaction and agency. Artificial Intelligence,
72,1-52.
Atkinson, R. C., & Shiffrin, R. M. (1968). Human
Acknowledgment memory: A proposed system and its control
processes. In K. W. Spence & J. T. Spence
I thank Carl Craver both for very helpful com- (Eds.), The psychology of learning and motiva-
ments on a draft of this chapter and for many pro- tion: Advances in research and theory (Vol. 2,
ductive discussions about mechanism and mech- pp. 89-195). New York: Academic Press.
anistic explanation. Bechtel, W. (1986). The nature of scientific inte-
gration. In W. Bechtel (Ed.), Integrating sci-
entific disciplines (pp. 3-52). Dordrecht, The
Notes Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff.
Bechtel, W. (2006). Discovering cell mechanisms:
1 I will refer to the whole living organism as a The creation of modem cell biology. Cambridge:
system, not a mechanism per se. The ques- Cambridge University Press.
tion of whether an organism itself should Bechtel, W. (2007). Reducing psychology while
count as a mechanism is complicated. Typ- maintaining its autonomy via mechanistic
ically, one begins the analysis of a mecha- explanation. In M. Schouten &. H. Looren
nism with an account of the phenomenon de Jong (Eds.), The matter of the mind: Philo-
for which it is responsible. There are a host sophical essays on psychology, neuroscience and
of different phenomena one might associate reduction (pp. 172-198). Oxford, UK: Black-
with an organism, and depending on which is well.
selected, researchers will select different parts Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2002). Con-
of the organism as the responsible mechanism nectionism and the mind: Parallel processing,
and develop a different decomposition of it dynamics, and evolution in networks (2nd ed.).
into parts (Kauflman, 1971). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
2 Virchow's (1858) emphasis in developing this Bechtel, W., 8t Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explana-
metaphor was to focus the study of living tion: A mechanist alternative. Studies in His-
processes, especially those involved in pathol- tory and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical
ogy, on the individual cells. Cells were the Sciences, 36, 421-441.
most basic organized form: "the last constant Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (1993). Discover-
link in the great chain of mutually subordi- ing complexity: Decomposition and localization
nated formations that form tissues, organs, as strategies in scientific research. Princeton, NJ-
systems, the individual. Below them is noth- Princeton University Press.
ing but change." Quoted in Coleman, 1977, Beer, R. D. (1995). A dynamical systems perspec-
p. 32. tive on agent-environment interaction. Artifi-
3 I thank Carl Craver for pointing me to cial Intelligence, 72,173-215.
Richter's development of homeostasis to Beer, R. D. (2000). Dynamical approaches to cog-
include behaviors that served to maintain nitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4,
internal homeostasis. 9*"99- I , f
4 Turing's initial perspective was rekindled
Bernard, C. (1865). An introduction to the study °J
in Rumelhart, Smolensky, McClelland, and
experimental medicine. New York: Dover.
Hinton's (1986) account of human perfor-
Berzelius, J. J. (1836). Einige Ideen uber bei
mance in multiplying large numbers. Such
der Bildung organischer Verbindungen ' n
EXPLANATION: MECHANISM, MODULARITY, AND SITUATED COGNITION 169

der lebenden Naturwirksame, aber bisher Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cam-
nicht bemerke Kraft. Jahres-Berkcht über die bridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fortschritte der Chemie, 15, 237-245. Fodor, J. A. (1984). Observation reconsidered.
Bichat, X. (1805). Recherches physiologiques sur la Philosophy of Science, 51, 23-43.
vie et la mort (3rd ed.). Paris: Machant. Gall, F. J. (1812). Anatomie et physiologie du
Broca, P. (1861). Remarques sur le siège de système nerveaux et général, et du cerveau en
la faculté du langage articulé, suivies d'une particulier, avec des observations sur la possi-
observation d'aphemie (perte de la parole). bilité de reconnoitre plusieurs dispositions intel-
Bulletin de la Société Anatomique, 6, 343- lectuelles et morales de l'homme et des ani-
357- maux, par la configuration de leur tètes. Paris:
Brooks, R. (1991)- Intelligence without represen- F. Schoell.
tation. Artificial Intelligence, 47,139-159. Gânti, T. (1975). Organization of chemical reac-
Cannon, W. B. (1929). Organization of physio- tions into dividing and metabolizing units:
logical homeostasis. Physiological Reviews, 9, The chemotons. BioSystems, 7,15-21.
Gânti, T. (2003). The principles of life. New York:
399-43 -
1

Oxford University Press.


Clark, A. (1987). Microcognition: Philosophy, cogni-
Garber, D. (2002). Descartes, mechanics, and
tive science, and parallel distributed processing.
the mechanical philosophy. Midwest Studies
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
in Philosophy, 26,185-204.
Clark, A., 8t Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended
mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7-19. Glenn an, S. (1996). Mechanisms and the nature
Coleman, W. (1977). Biology in the nineteenth cen- of causation. Erkenntnis, 44, 50-71.
tury. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Glennan, S. (2002). Rethinking mechanistic
Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (1994). Origins of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 69, S342-
domain specificity: The evolution of func- S353-
tional organization. In L. S. Hirschfeld & S. Kauffman, S. (1971). Articulation of parts expla-
A. Gelman (Eds.), Mapping the mind (pp. nations in biology and the rational search
85-116). Cambridge: Cambridge University for them. In R. C. Bluck & R. S. Cohen
Press. (Eds.), PSA, 1970 (pp. 257-272). Dordrecht,
Cosmides, L., Tooby, J., & Barkow, J. H. (1992). The Netherlands: D. Reidel.
Introduction: Evolutionary psychology and Keijzer, F. (2001). Representation and behavior.
conceptual integration. In J. H. Barkow, L. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Cosmides, & J. Tooby (Eds.), The adapted Kelso, J. A. S. (1995). Dynamic patterns: The self-
mind: Evolutionary psychology and the gener- organization of brain and behavior. Cambridge,
ation of culture (pp. 3-18). New York: Oxford MA: MIT Press.
University Press. Lashley, K. S. (1929). Brain mechanisms and intel-
Craver, C. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mecha- ligence. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
nisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. New Lashley, K. S. (1950). In search of the engram.
York: Oxford University Press. Symposia of the Society for Experimental Biol-
Cummins, D. D., & Allen, C. (1998). Introduc- ogy, IV: Physiological mechanisms in animal
tion. In D. D. Cummins &. C. Allen (Eds.), The behaviour (pp. 454-482). New York: Academic
evolution of mind (pp. 3-8). Oxford: Oxford Press.
University Press. Machamer, P., Darden, L., 81 Craver, C. (2000).
Cummins, R. (2000). "How does it work?" versus Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Sci-
what are the laws?": Two conceptions of psy- ence, 67,1-25.
chological explanation. In F. Keil & R. Wilson Maturana, H. R., & Varela, F. J. (1980).
(Eds.), Explanation and cognition (pp. 117-144). Autopoiesis: The organization of the living.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. In H. R. Maturana & F. J. Varela (Eds.),
Flourens, J. P. M. (1824). Researches expéri- Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the
mentales sur les propriétés et les fonctions du living (pp. 59-138). Dordrecht, The Nether-
système nerveux dans les animaux vertëbris. lands: D. Reidel.
Paris: Crevot. Neisser, U. (1976). Cognition and reality: Princi-
Fodor, J. A. (1980). Methodological solipsism ples and implications ofcognitive psychology. San
considered as a research strategy in cognitive Francisco: W. H. Freeman.
psychology. Behainoral and Brain Sciences, 3, Neisser, U. (1987). Introduction: The ecological
63-109. and intellectual bases of categorization. In U.
»7° WILLIAM BECHTEL

Neisser (Ed ), Concepts and conceptual develop- ible and context-sensitive? In P. Carruthers,
ment: Ecological and intellectual factors in cat- S. Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.), The innate
egorization (pp. 1-10). Cambridge: Cambridge mind: Structure and content (pp. 53-68).
University Press. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Post, E. L. (1936). Finite combinatorial pro- Stein, P. S. G., 8c Smith, J. L. (>997). Neural and
cesses - formulation I. Journal of Symbolic biomechanical control strategies for different
Logic, 1,103-105. forms of vertebrate hindlimb motor tasks. In
Richter, C. P. (1942-1943). Total self-regulatory P. S. G. Stein, S. Grillner, A. I. Selverston, &
functions in animals and human beings. Har- D. G. Stuart (Eds.), Neurons, networks, and
vey Lectures, 37, 63-103. motor behavior (pp. 61-73). Cambridge, MA:
Ruiz-Mirazo, K., Peretb, J., & Moreno, A. (2004). MIT Press.
A universal definition of life: Autonomy and Suchman, L. (1987). Plans and situated actions:
open-ended evolution. Origins of Life and Evo- The problem of human-machine communication.
lution of the Biosphere, 34, 323-346. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rumelhart, D. E., Smolensky, P., McClelland, Suchman, L. (1993). Response to Vera and
J. L., & Hinton, G. E. (1986). Schemas and Simon's situated action: A symbolic interpre-
sequential thought processes in PDP models. tation. Cognitive Science, 17, 71-75.
In J. L. McClelland, D. E. Rumelhart, & T. P. Thelen, E., 8t Smith, L. (1994). A dynamic systems
R. Group (Eds.), Parallel distributed processing: approach to the development of cognition and
Explorations in the microstructure of cognition action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
(Vol. 2, pp. 7-57). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Turing, A. (1936). On computable numbers, with
Schacter, D. L., & Tulving, E. (1994). What are an application to the Entscheidungs problem.
the memory systems of 1994? In D. L. Schac- Proceedings of the London Mathematical Soci-
ter & E. Tulving (Eds.), Memory systems, 1994 ety, 2nd ser., 42, 230-265.
(pp. 1-38). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Uttal, W. R. (2001). The new phrenology: The lim-
Shetdeworth, S. (2000). Modularity and the evo- its of localizing cognitive processes in the brain.
lution of cognition. In C. Heyes 8c L. Huber Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
(Eds.), The evolution of cognition (pp. 43-60). van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be,
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. if not computation? Journal of Philosophy, 91,
Simon, H. A. (1996). The sciences of the artificial 345-381.
(3rd ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. van Gelder, T. (1998). The dynamical hypothe-
Sperber, D. (1994). The modularity of thought sis in cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain
and the epidemiology of representations. In Sciences, 21, 615-628.
L. Hirschfeld & S. Gelman (Eds.), Mapping van Orden, G. C., 8c Paap, K. R. (1997). Func-
the mind: Domain specificity in cognition and tional neural images fail to discover the pieces
culture (pp. 39-67). Cambridge: Cambridge of the mind in the parts of the brain. Philoso-
University Press. phy of Science, 64(4), S85-S94.
Sperber, D. (2001). In defense of massive mod- van Orden, G. C., Pennington, B. F., 8c Stone,
ularity. In E. Dupoux (Ed.), Language, brain, G. O. (2001). What do double dissociations
and cognitive development: Essays in honor of prove? Inductive methods and isolable sys-
Jacques Mehler (pp. 47-57). Cambridge, MA: tems. Cognitive Science, 25,111-172.
MIT Press. Virchow, R. (1858). Die cellularpathologie in ihrer
Sperber, D. (2005). Modularity and relevance: begriindung auf physiologische und pathologis-
How can a massively modular mind be flex- che gewebelehre. Berlin: August Hirschwald.
C H A P T E R 10

Embedded Rationality

Ruth Millikan

Philosophers and laypeople alike have tradi- it slowly in several different ways and then
tionally assumed that whether you can rea- illustrate it with a variety of examples.
son well, make valid inferences, avoid logical Among the most common informal falla-
mistakes, and so forth, is entirely a matter of cies in reasoning are fallacies of ambiguity.
how well the cogs in your head are fashioned These are mistakes that hinge on a word or
and oiled. Partner to this is the assumption phrase that has one meaning in some or all
that careful reflection is always the method of the premises of the argument but another
by which we discover whether an inference meaning in other premises or in the conclu-
or reasoning process is correct. In particular, sion. A traditional toy example runs as fol-
further experience, observation, or experi- lows:
ment never bear on the question of whether
an inference is valid. Validity is best checked The police enforce the laws.
with your eyes tightly closed so you can The law of gravity is a law.
attend solely to the internal relations among So the police enforce the law of gravity.
your ideas.
There seems to be no need to defend Real examples of this fallacy are not so bla-
these assumptions, nor, to my knowledge, tant, of course: But according to tradition, if
has anyone ever tried. They are pure com- any such fallacy should occur in one's rea-
mon sense. Occasionally, however, common soning, it will always be detectable by care-
sense is a repository for obdurate error. My ful enough reflection on the meanings of the
daim is that that is so in this case. Rather terms in the premises and the conclusion.
than being an a priori matter, I will argue, Terms in a language (words, phrases) are
good reasoning needs constant empirical importandy unlike terms in one's thought
^PPort. Clear thinking is possible only as (mental terms, thoughts of things) in that
embedded in a cooperative external world, exactly the same word can denote different
because this claim flies rather rudely in the things in different contexts, but the same
•ace of common sense, I wall first introduce thought always denotes the same thing.

171
RUTH MILLJKAN
•7*

Thoughts are never ambiguous, never equiv- But tradition then says that inferences like
ocal. By paying careful attention to the the preceding woodchuck-groundhog one
thoughts behind the words, refusing to let are invalid, even if you do already happen
the words get in the way, a rational person to know that woodchucks are groundhogs.
can always avoid fallacies of ambiguity. They are invalid, that is, unless you explic-
That is the first part of the view to be itly add into your premises that woodchucks
challenged. I will argue that one can fail to are the same thing as groundhogs. The infer-
know that the denotation of a thought is ence is invalid because one does not know of
unstable. It is possible to have an equivo- the identity of woodchucks and groundhogs
cal thought, to possess a single mental term by mere reflection, so one cannot know just
that denotes more than one thing. You can by reflection that the conclusion of such an
have two people confused together in your argument follows from the premises.
mind, taking them for the same person, stor- These doctrines both flow directly from
ing all the information you have about each the premise that what logically follows can
of them in one and the same bin in your always be known a priori. If you can always
head. Or you can have two properties con- tell by reflection alone that an argument is
fused in your mind, as mass and weight were valid and does not equivocate, then the same
confused together in people's minds before mental term must always denote the same
Newton. Just like words, equivocal thoughts thing. And if you cannot tell by reflection
do not display their ambiguities on the sur- alone that different mental terms denote the
face. It is, in general, an a posteriori mat- same, then arguments that turn on differ-
ter, a matter of experience, whether one's ent thoughts of the same (woodchuck and
thoughts are equivocal. So it is possible to groundhog) are invalid. Both these conclu-
fall into fallacies of ambiguity that are not sions follow from the premise that the world
discernible by hard thinking alone. outside you, the world known through sen-
The opposite of fallacies of ambiguity are sory experience, is in no way involved in
inferences one fails to make because one is your being rational. Being rational is some-
unaware that two words or phrases denote thing you do in your head.
the same thing. For example: But again, I will argue, this is a mistake.
Whether a mental term is equivocal is an a
Woodchucks are mammals. posteriori matter, a matter of experience. So
Mammals are warm blooded. if any inferences at all are to count as valid,
Therefore groundhogs are warm blooded. inferences that are valid in all other ways and
that also do not commit fallacies of ambigu-
This is a perfectly rational inference if you ity should surely count as valid, even though
happen to know that woodchucks are the the fact that they are not prey to ambigui-
same thing as groundhogs, but, of course, ties is known only a posteriori. Otherwise
you might not know that. Although tradi- no mediate inferences at all (that contain
tion says that the same thought is always a empirical terms) will ever count as valid.
thought of the same thing, it also accepts, That is, either we define valid inference such
what is obvious, that different thoughts can that all inferences that are valid must be
be of the same thing and can be so with- known to be valid a priori but there are no
out your knowing it. You can think of Mark valid inferences, or we define valid inference
Twain and then think of Samuel Clemens such that there are some valid inferences but
without knowing they are the same man, they are not known to be valid a priori. The
or think of woodchucks and then think of latter seems a more sensible way to speak.
groundhogs without knowing they are the We do not want the term valid inference to
same species. The same mental term always be empty. But the way experience teaches us
denotes the same thing, but different mental whether a mental term is equivocal or not
terms can also denote the same thing, and is exacdy the same way that it teaches us
this will not generally be known a priori. whether one term is equivalent to another.
embedded r a t i o n a l i t y 173

So if one knows from experience that two A ubiquitous contemporary and parallel
terms denote the same thing, inferences in move is clearly illustrated by Michael Dum-
which one freely substitutes the one term mett (1978): "Meaning is transparent in the
for the other should be valid so long as no sense that, if someone attaches a meaning to
other fallacy is present. each of two words, he must know whether
Here is a third way of explaining the pro- these meanings are the same" (p. 131).
posal I want to make. Closely related to But, of course, you can fail to know that
the rationalist view of rationality described two words in your vocabulary stand for the
previously is the commonsense view that same thing. You can fail to know that Mark
if you are genuinely thinking of something, Twain is Samuel Clemens; you can fail to
you really cannot fail to know what it is you know that woodchucks are groundhogs. You
are thinking of. Bertrand Russell put the can have two thoughts of the same thing
matter this way: "it is scarcely conceivable without knowing it. Still, according to Dum-
that we can make a judgment or entertain mett you cannot attach the same meaning
a supposition without knowing what it is to two words without knowing it. It fol-
we are judging or supposing about" ( 1 9 1 2 , lows that the meaning you think of when
p. 58). • you understand a word must be separa-
So if you were thinking of two different ble from the thing you think of when you
things merged into one thought, of course hear the word. It must be separable from
the word's referent or denotation. Although
you would know it. But Russell drew a
Mark Twain and Samuel Clemens refer to
more dramatic conclusion. The passage con-
the same man, they must have different
tinues:
meanings or express different thoughts. Per-
haps they express different descriptions, as
We must attach some meaning to the Russell suggested, through which one thinks
words we use, if we are to speak signifi- of the same man. Although woodchuck and
cantly and not utter mere noise; and the groundhog denote the same species, they,
meaning we attach to our words must be too, must have different meanings or express
something with which we are ac-
different thoughts, perhaps expressing dif-
quainted ... [but] Julius Caesar is not
ferent descriptions of this species. Accord-
himself before our minds, since we are not
ingly, numerous philosophers have distin-
acquainted with him. We have in mind
some description ofJulius Caesar... some guished what they call "reference" - what
description of him which is composed the thought is of - from something else,
wholly of particulars and universals with which has gone under various different
which we are acquainted. (1912, pp. 58-59) names, such as sense, mode of presentation,
intension, or sometimes just meaning or
thought.
By "not acquainted with" Julius Caesar, Rus-
sell means not that we have never met Julius According to this view, valid arguments
Caesar but that Julius Caesar is not a sense can be known to be valid a priori because
datum! For, Russell supposes, only sense instead of concerning what thoughts are
data, sensory impressions, auditory or visual about - reference, denotation - correct rea-
sensations, and so on, and their properties, soning concerns only senses, modes of pre-
can literally be directly before one's mind, sentation, or whatever. It concerns only
and only if what one thinks of is, in this what is before the mind, but referents (e.g.,
way, literally before or within one's con- Julius Caesar himself) are never directly
scious mind could one be sure what it was before the mind, of course. Sense deter-
one was thinking of. The immediate result mines reference: there are no equivocal
of this sort of Russellian move was the emer- thoughts; the same thought always has the
gence of various versions of verificationism same referent. It is just that reference does
and phenomenalism, an era to which we not determine sense: the same referent is not
nave no wish, I imagine, to return. always thought of in the same way. Thus it
>74 RUTH MILLIKAN

is that the previous toy argument about laws at some length in Millikan, 2000) is that,
can be known to be invalid a priori and the with few exceptions, words that denote do
one about woodchucks and groundhogs can not correspond to any definition or mode of
be known to be invalid a priori as well. presentation that all competent users under-
That meaning is not the same thing as ref- stand in common. But that will be only a sec-
erence makes a lot of sense when one con- ondary theme in this essay, for I want to talk
siders words like moreover and hurrah and mainly about thought rather than language.
or that clearly do have meanings yet do not The second question to be distinguished
seem to have any referents at all. Similar are might count as the central theme of this
words like phlogiston and Santa Clans. But to essay. The question is whether when one
claim that words that do have referents and thinks of a thing such as Mark Twain or
do have the same referents always have dif- woodchucks one does generally think of it
ferent meanings whenever someone might under some mode of presentation or, as is
not know their referents were the same is often said, in some particular way. When I
peculiar. I have a daughter who collects think to myself Mark Twain was a writer and
nicknames the way fugitives collect aliases. when I think to myself Samuel Clemens was
Natasha gets called "Tasha," she gets called a writer, am I really thinking two different
"Nat," sometimes "Ta" sometimes "Banana," thoughts? When I think to myself Wood-
often "Mouse" or "Mousie," and so forth. chucks look like they have zippers down the
There may easily be folks who do not know, front and when I think to myself Ground-
say, that Nat Millikan is Ta Millikan. Does it hogs look like they have zippers down the front
really follow that Nat Millikan and Ta Mil- am I really thinking two different thoughts?
likan have different meanings? Indeed, do Obviously, if I don't know that Mark Twain
woodchuck and groundhog really have differ- is Samuel Clemens or if I don't know that
ent meanings? woodchucks are groundhogs then these are
Two different questions, often confused, indeed different thoughts. They form, as it
should be distinguished here. The first is were, different patterns in my head. But
whether a name such as Mark Twain or does it follow that they remain different
Tasha Millikan or woodchuck corresponds thoughts after I am thoroughly convinced
to some one particular thought or sense or of the relevant identities? Moving closer to
mode of presentation (or whatever) that home, I cannot really make out how my
every competent user of that name must thoughts Nat is gray eyed and Ta is gray eyed
have in mind when using that name, differ in any way. Try it yourself with an
or whether, instead, different competent old friend and the friend's nickname. Per-
speakers may use different thoughts, dif- haps different associations may go with a
ferent modes of presentation, when under- person's formal name and his or her nick-
standing a name of this kind. For example, name, but a whole different way of thinking
is there a particular description or descrip- about them?
tions of Mark Twain that everyone who uses The mistake that has been made, I
the name Samuel Clemens with comprehen- believe, is to confuse different ways of recog-
sion must have in mind, or might different nizing, or different keys to recognizing what
competent people associate entirely disjoint it is that one is receiving information about,
sets of descriptions with Samuel Clemens? with different ways of thinking about that
Is there some definition of woodchuck that thing. How I recognize that it is my daugh-
is different from the definition of ground-
ter that someone is talking about is not a way
hog that every competent user of woodchuck
of thinking of her. I recognize who is being
must have in mind? Or perhaps you are
talked about when people say, "Ta," and
not a competent user of the word wood-
when they say, "Nat," and when they say,
chuck unless you know that woodchucks are
"Mousie," and so forth, but surely I have only
groundhogs (and vice versa)? The position
one way of thinking about this daughter. I
that I would argue for (and have argued for
have only one term in my mental vocabulary
EMBEDDED RATIONALITY 175

for her. There could be some people, of putting all the incoming information into
course, that I have different ways of rec- one folder (see Millikan, 2000, chaps. 8-u;
ognizing without knowing it so that I keep Strawson, 1974). That is the thesis I will sup-
in my mind more that one mental term for port, mostly by displaying a variety of illus-
them. But surely for my very good friends, I trative examples.
generally have very many different ways of Good examples with which to begin
recognizing them, both in direct perception are thoughts of empirical properties. Many
and through a variety of linguistic manifes- modern theories describe concepts of indi-
tations such as names and descriptions, but viduals or kinds as though these thoughts
only one way of thinking of them, only one were reducible to thoughts or judgments
mental term for them. Indeed, the idea that about complexes of properties and then
every way that I have of recognizing a thing ignore the question of what it is to think
yields a different way of thinking of it, a dif- of a property. Thoughts of individuals are
ferent mode of presentation of it, drifts into analyzed in terms of definite descriptions
incoherency as soon as we seriously try to (as in the previous quote from Russell)
count ways of recognizing. Ways of recog- and thoughts of kinds in terms of proper-
nizing a thing typically are as uncountable ties supposed to define them. Soon I will
as portions of water in a pond. Ways of rec- argue against these classical analyses; but
ognizing is not a count noun - or so I will supposing they were right, then showing
argue. that thoughts of properties are discovered
to be univocal only a posteriori would show
To have a concept of an individual, of an
that thoughts of individuals and kinds were
empirically evidenced natural property, or
so as well.
of a natural kind, typically involves a capac-
ity to recognize that same thing, as such, Thoughts of properties obviously can-
in a great variety of ways. Speaking more not all be analyzed in terms of thoughts
exacdy, typically it involves a keen, though of complexes of more fundamental proper-
fallible, ability to channel both natural infor- ties without regress. The objects (the con-
mation of numerous kinds that may affect tent) of our most basic concepts of per-
one's sensory surfaces and much informa- ceptual properties must be determined by
tion contained in the language one hears so our capacities to respond to these properties
that it comes to a single focus in one's mind, when they are made manifest to our senses
being understood to concern one and the through natural information (on natural
same thing. Knowing what you are thinking information, see Millikan, 2004, chaps. 3-4).
of is having this capacity with regard to the To have a concept of square, for example,
thing you are thinking of, and Russell was involves the capacity to respond to natu-
surely right that one cannot "make a judg- ral information concerning the presence of
ment or entertain a supposition" about some square things as it impinges on one's senses -
thing without having this capacity at least similarly for concepts of other perceptible
to some degree. But Russell was wrong to shapes, of sizes, of colors, of textures, of
suppose that knowing what you are think- softness and hardness, of heaviness and light-
ing about is an all-or-nothing affair. Many ness, of lengths and distances. So let us con-
forms of information may be recognized as sider how some of these properties are in
fact recognized.
concerning the same thing without all forms
of information about that thing being rec- What is involved in being able to rec-
ognized. And although it may not be usual, ognize, for example, shapes? Think of the
it certainly is possible to have two concepts, variety of proximal visual stimulations to
two focal points for information, two men- which a given shape may give rise when
tal terms, for the same thing - "without viewed from various angles, from differ-
knowing it" obviously goes without saying, ent distances, under different lighting con-
for knowing it could be constituted only by ditions, through various media such as mist
merging these two mental terms into one, or water, when colored in different ways,
RUTH MILLIKAN
176

when partially occluded and so forth. How a string, or measuring as a surveyor does by
the visual system achieves shape constancy, triangulation, or measuring with an odome-
the capacity to recognize the same shape ter or a micrometer or by timing the return
as the same under a wide range of condi- of light, are also ways of determining dis-
tions, is a problem of nearly unimaginable tances.
complexity on which psychologists of per- That all of these ways of determining
ception are still hard at work. And shape a particular distance are ways of recording
is also perceived by the haptic system. You one and the same property obviously is not
can feel the shape of a small object in your something determined by reflection alone.
hand in a variety of ways, for example, with Coordination of these diverse ways of iden-
these fingers or with those, when the object tifying one and the same property has been
is turned this way or that way in your hand, achieved through long experience, experi-
perhaps by using two hands, either merely ence of the race during evolution, experi-
by holding the object or by actively feeling ence of the growing child resulting in per-
or stroking it. You can perceive larger shapes ceptual tuning, experience in measuring and
(say, in the dark) by exploring with larger calculating with die use of a wide variety
motions that involve your arms, body, and of instruments. Evidence that our concepts
perhaps legs and by employing the touch- of distances are univocal concepts is deeply
ing surfaces of a wide variety of your body empirical.
parts. This kind of perception of shape, Several more points deserve to be made
involving the coordination of information here. First, none of these ways of telling dis-
about the exact positions of one's body parts tances is infallible, certainly none is known
with information about what touches these to be infallible a priori. Second, none of
parts, is of such a complex nature that, to these ways of telling distances is any more
my knowledge, psychologists have not even definitional of our concepts of distances than
attempted to study it. any other. No one of them defines dis-
Similarly, how color constancy, texture tance, the others being merely correlated,
constancy, size constancy, distance con- yet each adds something to our concepts of
stancy, and sound constancy are achieved distances; nor could we have distance con-
are enormously complicated matters. (We cepts at all were we not in command of
are adept at identifying sounds, especially at least some of these methods of recog-
speech sounds, as the same sound at origin nition. Third, it should be clear that these
whether near or far, through air or through various ways of telling distances do not
water, muffled or distorted, and so forth.) In correspond to a collection of prior con-
each of these cases in which perceptual con- cepts of properties that are then judged
stancy is achieved, it is abundandy clear that to concern one and the same property. If
no single rule is applied. Different clues are there were such a collection of prior con-
used by the perceptual systems in different cepts, with which we would make judg-
circumstances, separately or together. For ments about distance-as-perceived-thuslyi
example, depth is perceived with the help versus distance-as-perceived-thusly 2 , and so
at least of ocular disparity, tension in the forth, presumably these concepts would be
focusing muscles, occlusion of one object by countable. But ways of perceiving a prop-
another, knowledge of the size of objects erty are not countable, not just because they
viewed, and atmospheric haze. We also rec- are too numerous but also because they are
ognize distances by touch and stretch using not the right kind of thing to count. Think,
many different parts of the body, and by ear for example, of the myriad different per-
we recognize fairly well the distances from ceptual data structures, in meandering con-
ourselves of things that make noises. The tinuous patterns merging into one another,
blind can often tell where nearby walls are any one of which might lead you to judge
located by reflected sound. Measuring dis- that you had perceived, by sight and/or by
tances with a ruler or a tape measure or just feel, something of a particular shape, say, the
EMBEDDED RATIONALITY >75

shape of a hammer. These could no more be Indeed, for any single way of identifying
counted than, say, the number of areas there Natasha it is not determined a priori even
are on a sheet of paper. That basic percep- that this single method always captures the
tual properties are thought of through myr- same person. Whatever appearances I go
iad different modes of presentation that are by, it is not determined a priori that I
then judged to be presentations of the same will never encounter someone else who has
is a hopeless idea. that appearance as well. It is similar for
The situation is similar with thoughts of descriptions: descriptions are never known
individuals. Traditionally it is supposed that a priori to fit one and only one individual;
to think of an individual is either to cap- they can be empty and they can fail to be
ture that individual in one's mind with some unique. Thoughts apparently of individuals
description that uniquely identifies it or to can be equivocal (Tweedledum mixed with
be able to recognize it perceptually. But un- Tweedledee) and they can be empty (Santa
countably many different descriptions will Claus) without one's knowing this a priori.
fit any individual uniquely and there are un- Thoughts of individuals can also be
countably many ways that any individual redundant without one's knowing it. You
might be recognized in perception, for ex- can have two different thoughts of Samuel
ample, (if it is a person) by family members Clemens without knowing it or fail to know
or close friends. A family member might be that two people named Dr. Jones are in fact
recognized, say, from front, back, or side; by the same person. When this latter happens
the stance of his or her body, by voice, by there will indeed be separate ways that you
characteristic expressions or doings, under go about identifying Dr. Jones that feed into
each of myriad different lighting- or sound- your separate mental terms for him, separate
mediating conditions, and so forth. There congeries of overlapping methods. But these
are innumerable alternative methods that will not be different ways of thinking of
might result in thinking of the same indi- Dr. Jones, different modes of presentation
vidual. Different people can have quite dif- of him, but only separate ways that thoughts
ferent kinds of concepts of the same individ- of him are stimulated. If you discover that
ual by using quite different descriptions or this is really one and the same man, then
methods of recognition, and a single person that will not result in a new beUef taking
may be in command of innumerable differ- up residence in your head, a special kind of
ent ways of identifying the same individual. belief called an "identity belief." The result
Surely the ways I have of recognizing each of will be that you merge your two concepts
my daughters are not countable. Nor do any of Dr. Jones into one, now bringing all your
of these methods constitute a definition of methods to a single focus. The result will be
any of my daughters for me. Natasha, say, that you now know somewhat better than
is not defined for me by the way I recog- you did before just who it is you are think-
nize her, by the look of her face (from this ing of when you think of Dr. Jones.
angle or that), by the sound of her voice Thoughts of biological kinds can be con-
(when she is happy or sad), and so forth. She sidered in somewhat the same light. This is
does not have a definition, either an appear- what J. S. Mill said about them: "A hundred
ance or a set of properties, that makes her generations have not exhausted the com-
be who she is. None of the ways I can recog- mon properties of animals or plants... nor
nize her either in perception or by descrip- do we suppose them to be exhaustible, but
tion is more important than any other in proceed to new observations and experi-
determining who my Natasha thought is a ments, in the full confidence of discover-
thought of. ing new properties which were by no means
Nor is it determined a priori that my implied in those we previously knew" (from
Natasha thought is of any one definite per- Hacking, 1991, p. 118).
son, that these various methods of recog- We now know what Mill did not know;
nition all converge on the same thing. namely, why this is the case. Biological
i78 RUTH MILLIKAN

species are not mere classes. The members you have of recognizing the presence of a
of a species are not bound into a unit by pos- dog or a cat or a horse. For many familiar
sessing certain defining properties in com- species, one's ability to recognize the species
mon. Members of the same species originate may be constantly improving, as one learns
in the same gene pool, but gene pools typ- to recognize it by a wider and wider diver-
ically contain alleles for all or most genes. sity of diagnostic signs and under a wider
Typically, there are no genes that every diversity of conditions.
member of the species has in common with Nor do any of the particular methods
every other member. On the other hand, as that a person uses for recognizing a species
Mill observed, the members of a species do constitute some sort of final criterion of
tend to be like one another in an enormous encounter with that species. None is more
number of respects. This is partly because definitional than any other, even for that
they originate from genes that have been individual. So the same situation obtains
replicated from one another and like genes here as with concepts of individuals and of
(in like genetic context) often produce like empirical properties. There is no a priori
phenotypes. It is also because a variety of guarantee that it is really the same species,
factors that tend to produce homeostasis in the same glued-together unity, that one's
the gene pool so that novel genes entering various ways of identifying are reaching. Nor
the pool are unlikely to survive unless they is there an a priori guarantee that any one
produce extremely minor changes. Thus, way that one tries to identify a species always
the various individuals within a species reaches the same kind. It is not known a pri-
mostly resemble one another in a great vari- ori that my ways of identifying dogs, say,
ety of ways, but they do not all resemble one
do not lump two or more species together
another in any particular ways. What pulls
under one concept, making that concept
them together as a group is not just that
equivocal. It is not even given a priori that
they have common or overlapping proper-
they do not ever fail to reidentify anything
ties but that they have common and overlap-
objective at all, that they are not empty.
ping properties for a good reason. There is a
That my ways of identifying reach an actual
good reason why one member of the species
species is not a priori.
will probably be like the next in very numer-
Because there is a reason w h y the mem-
ous respects. This is why "a hundred genera-
tions have not exhausted the common prop- bers of a species are like one another, var-
erties of animals or plants." ious kinds of inductions drawn over the
members of a species will mostly yield true
Because biological species are not classed conclusions for a reason. That these con-
together merely by some set of common or clusions turn out to be true is not acci-
overlapping properties, the extension of the dental. Thus, again following Mill, species
concept of a species cannot be determined are what can be called "real kinds"; they
merely by a conjunctive or disjunctive set of are not merely nominal kinds. Elsewhere I
properties represented in the mind. More- have argued that there is a variety of dif-
over, just as no common way of identifying ferent principles that can cement the mem-
an individual or a property is required of bers of real kinds together such that there
all who think of that individual or prop- is a reason why one member of the kind
erty, there is no central set of properties is likely to be like another (see Millikan,
that everyone must use to identify a given 2000). Some real kinds, such as the various
species. Typically there are very numerous biological species, are historical kinds, their
properties that, taken either alone or in small members being alike because something like
sets, are each diagnostic of the kind. And copying has been going on against the back-
just as with individuals and with proper- ground of some relevant, ongoing histori-
ties, it is true that each person may have cal environment. Copying from one another
very many alternative ways of recognizing a
or from the same original plan is why the
species. Consider how many different ways
restaurants within a given restaurant chain
>75
embedded r a t i o n a l i t y

tend to be alike, w h y various renditions fying members of historical kinds that will
of Beethoven's Fifth Symphony or of "The illustrate why they are never defined by just
Irish Washerwoman" are much alike, why one method of recognition.
Greek salads tend to be similar, w h y Gothic Consider again the various biological
cathedrals have similar plans, why Amer- species. Aristode thought that what bound
ican doctors have so many bits of knowl- individual organisms into the same species
edge and also so many attitudes in common, was that they had a single (Aristotelian)
and so forth. A different but more familiar form in common. Roughly, he thought
example of a principle that binds real kinds of species as being Putnam-style natural
together binds natural kinds (in Putnam's kinds. After the Darwinian/Mendelian rev-
sense) together. T h e members of natural olution, we think we know better. We know
kinds are alike because they possess a com- that species are historical kinds: dogs are
mon inner nature of some sort, such as an dogs because they partake not of the same
inner molecular structure, from which the form but of the same gene pool. Aristode's
more superficial or easily observable prop- mistake dlustrates a very important point;
erties of the kind's instances flow. T h e inner namely, that you can have perfecdy good
structure results in a certain selection of sur- concepts of real kinds without necessar-
face properties or in given selections of prop- ily having an understanding of what holds
erties under given conditions. these kinds together. Surely Aristode was
I have argued that the majority of kinds as capable of having thoughts of dogkind or
that are recognized by natural language are humankind as we are. To think of a real kind
real kinds (Millikan, 2000). This is because you do not have to grasp its basic princi-
only real kinds can be genuine subjects of ple of unity. But suppose that you do grasp
knowledge. It is only when individuals are this principle. So you decide to use as your
banded together such that there is a reason basic criterion for whether a creature is a
why each individual should be like the oth- dog that it was bom of a dog (better, of two
ers in various respects that we can obtain dogs). Now, how will you tell whether it
knowledge about this unit as such, unless, of was bom of a dog? Well, first you have to be
course, by examining each member sepa- able to recognize whether its mother was a
rately. Thoughts of units of this kind are dog (and its father)! Knowing the principle
the seeds from which all empirical knowl- of unity that binds the members of a his-
edge is built, for all empirical knowledge is torical kind into a unit takes you nowhere
inductive. toward recognizing these members. We are
But more important for our purposes back where we started then; there are many
here, it is always possible to have a concept equally good ways of recognizing dogs, none
of a real kind in any of a variety of differ- of them definitional, and they converge on
ent ways, using a variety of different tech- the same species as a matter only of empiri-
niques for recognizing its members, either cal fact.
separately or together. This is obvious, for N o w consider renditions of "The Irish
example, in the case of Putnam-style natu- Washerwoman." What makes a playing of
ral kinds. There are, in general, many differ- "The Irish Washerwoman" into a playing
ent techniques for detecting any particular of "The Irish Washerwoman" is that it is
chemical element or compound, many reli- copied from an earlier rendition of "The
able tests for it. Of course the basic structure Irish Washerwoman" or played from a score
of the element or compound may be known copied from earlier renditions and so forth.
as a result of scientific investigation (i.e., But that does not tell you how to recognize
from experience), but one does not just look "The Irish Washerwoman." On the other
and see, say, that a substance is composed of hand, if you can recognize this tune, it is
atoms with sixteen protonsl Historical kinds likely that no more than ten consecutive
are less often talked about, so let me finish notes anywhere in it will be enough for you
by giving some examples of ways of identi- to identify it. A tune has no definition. It can
i8o RUTH MILLIKAN

be played badly or well, by this instrument or even who to ask to find out the details
or that, with missed notes and sour notes, of these facts (I found a medical student
with variations. But a tune, a ballad, a sym- to ask, who did not know exactly but sent
phony, an opera, is a real kind, and despite me to a Web site), yet this ignorance does
having no definition, it can, of course, be not inhibit them from thinking thoughts of
thought of perfecdy well. doctors. Second, consider what accredited
Similarly, a Gothic cathedral is one means or what licensed by a legal authority
because it has been copied from other means, and so forth. Well, that is compli-
Gothic cathedrals. Otherwise it is not actu- cated, and different things are entailed in
ally Gothic. But knowing that does not tell different countries and states. But, in gen-
you anything about the character of Gothic eral, it will involve certain actions on the
cathedrals. You have to see one or hear it part of certain institutions that have been
described. Gothic cathedrals are pretty eas- granted certain authorities by certain polit-
ily recognizable by any number of features, ical bodies. In the abstract, that a certain
but Gothic cathedrals do not have a defi- person is a medical doctor will rest on the
nition. That the various different patterns actions of certain social bodies. Take one
of features by which they might be reliably of them, for example, the American Med-
identified are diagnostic of a single architec- ical Association. Which social body is that?
tural style is an a posteriori matter, a matter How are we to recognize it? Social bodies do
of causal-historical connections. not have definitions any more than people
do. An individual social body is composed
As a final and more sophisticated exam-
of a historically situated group of people
ple, consider Western medical doctors. Chil-
who bear certain complex relations to one
dren recognize doctors by their stethoscopes
another. Identifying the American Medical
and tongue depressors, by the fact that they
Association is in many ways like identifying
are taken to see doctors when they are hurt
an individual person, or perhaps like identi-
or ill, by the fact that people call them
fying activities of the species dog. There are
"doctor" and talk about having going to
lots of ways to identify this organization or
them when they were hurt or ill, and so
its activities, but none are definitional, and
forth. Adults know which are the doctors
the fact that these various ways all connect
by where their names are listed in the Yel-
with the same organization is an empirical
low Pages and by the signs on their office
matter, not something known a priori.
doors, because they say they are doctors, and
because other people say they are, and so Then, do medical doctors, Western style,
forth. But all of that is superficial, you will form a real kind? There is much knowledge
say; what really makes a doctor into a doctor, and many skills that they mostly have in
in the Western world anyway, is that he or common, and many attitudes and practices,
she has been trained in an accredited medi- and these similarities obtain for a good rea-
cal school, passed certain examinations, and son. Doctors have learned from one another;
fulfilled various other requirements (e.g., from teachers who have learned from one
residency), and been licensed to practice another; from the same traditions, indeed,
medicine by the appropriate legal authority from many of the same textbooks and jour-
in some country or state. In North Amer- nals. Their techniques and attitudes have
ica, for example, medical schools are accred- been passed from teacher to student and
ited by the Liaison Committee on Medical from colleague to colleague, across national
Education (LCME), which is sponsored by lines and within them. There are good rea-
the Association of American Medical Col- sons why certain generalizations apply to
leges and the American Medical Associa- most or many Western doctors and good
tion. But first, note that children and prob- empirical reasons why doctors can be iden-
ably many adults do not know that fact, nor tified - though fallibly, of course - in any
would they, for the most part, even know number of ways. Modern Western medical
there were such formal facts about doctors doctors do not merely form a class. They
embedded r a t i o n a l i t y > 7 5

form a real kind about which a good deal the fallible process of learning what informa-
can be learned. tion is carried through what media. Having
The case of Western doctors is a rather made this step helps to perfect one's concep-
complicated case. But think back now to the tual repertoire; it does not add a necessary
earlier discussions of empirical properties, of step or a new premise in one's valid reason-
individuals and of biological species. These ing from knowledge of properties of Twain
paradigms guide us easily to the following to properties of Clemens or from proper-
general conclusions. ties of woodchucks to properties of ground-
Abilities to identify and reidentify ap- hogs. Learning to identify things in new ways
pearances of the same objective thing as is not storing away special beliefs called
appearances of the same constitute a sub- "identity beliefs" but improving one's con-
stantial part of the possession of any empir- cepts, improving one's basic abilities to think
ical concept. Whether these concepts are of at all.
empirical properties, of individuals or of real Like all other abilities that rest partly on
kinds, the abilities to reidentify that underlie the structure of the world outside the organ-
them rest on the natural laws that structure ism, of course these abilities are not infalli-
natural information. An ability to recognize ble. It is always possible that an empirical
something is, obviously, not contained in concept binds together information about
your head alone, any more than the ability things that are not the same, hence becomes
to ride a bicycle is contained in your head. It equivocal, the test for this being, in general,
depends on causal interactions between you further experience. Ultimately, then, that an
and what you perceive, on the way chan- empirical concept is not prey to ambiguities
nels of natural information are structured, is known to one only a posteriori; that one's
and so forth. Perfecting the ability to collect mediate inferences are valid is known in
this information accurately and efficiently - the same way. One's rationality depends at
an ability originally derived through evo- every point on the complex causal and infor-
lutionary history; then through perceptual mational structure of the empirical world.
learning; and finally through experience in Rationality is firmly embedded in the world
making judgments based on perception, lin- outside the mind.
guistic input, and inference - is at every stage
an empirical matter. The tests by which
References
we tune our abilities to recognize what is
objectively the same as the same are empir-
Dummett, M. (1978). Truth and other enigmas.
ical tests all the way down. (These tests are
London: Duckworth.
described in some detail in Millikan, 1984, Hacking, I. (1991). A tradition of natural kinds.
chaps. 18-19, 2 0 0 0 / chap. 7; 2004, chap. 19.) Philosophical Studies, 91,109-126.
Learning what is the same as what is at Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, thought and
the base of all conceptual development, and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA:
conceptual development is a rich and struc- MIT Press.
tured interaction between the organism and Millikan, R. G. (2000). On clear and confused
its environment. To be thinking at all is ideas. Cambridge: Cambridge University
already to be employing abilities that are Press.
deeply embedded in the world. Millikan, R. G. (2004). Varieties of meaning. Cam-
bridge, MA: MIT Press.
To discover that Mark Twain is Samuel
Russell, B. (1912). The problems of philosophy. New
Clemens or that woodchucks are ground- York: Henry Holt.
nogs is just one further small step in con- Strawson, P. F. (1974). Subject and predicate in
ce
ptual development, one more small step in logic and grammar. London: Methuen.
Part III

EMPIRICAL
DEVELOPMENTS
CHAPTER 11

Situated Perception and Sensation


in Vision and Other Modalities

A Sensorimotor Approach

Erik Myitt and J. Kevin O'Regan

Voir un objet, c'est ou bien I'avoir en marge that moment is sought by moving the eye,
du champ visuel et pouvoir le fixer, ou bien the body, or by shifting attention to where
repondre effectivement a cette solicitation en in the world this information is to be
lefixant. Quandje le fixe, je m'ancre en lui, found.
mais cet 'arret' du regard n'est qu'une In this chapter, we will set out how an
modalite de son mouvement: je continue a account of vision in which the world is con-
I'interieur d'un objet lexploration qui, tout a sidered to form an external memory allows
I'heure, les survolait tous. for explanation of the experienced continu-
ity of vision. We will show how the hypoth-
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, 1945 esis of the world as an outside memory is
supported by findings in the change and
attentional blindness paradigms, as well as
| Introduction by the study of vision in action.
Then we turn to the sensorimotor contin-
Seeing and perceiving are not achievements gency approach to sensation and perception
of an isolated head or brain, quietly hum- in general. Here, as in the hypothesis of the
•ning along on its own. The organism moves world as an outside memory, the explana-
its eyes, repositions its body to get a bet- tory load for understanding the character
ter perceptual grip on the objects that sur- of sensory experience is put on the pre-
round it, and thereby attempts to advance cise ways in which an organism perceptually
in the execution of the hierarchy of ongoing interacts with its environment. We present
projects it is engaged in. The locus of per- recent empirical research from the sensori-
ceptual processing includes the world rather motor perspective, and end by pointing out
than being just confined to the head. In how a sensorimotor account provides the
the case of vision, at any moment, only possibility of explaining how perception dif-
e
precise information that is needed at fers from thought.

185
186 ERIK MYIN AND J. KEVIN O ' R E G A N

2. The Visual Field and the World continuity of the world, but anatomical fac-
as an Outside Memory tors pose problems concerning the world's
apparent spatial continuity.
2.1. Continuity in Experience First of all, the retina is not a uniform sen-
What do you see when you see? Differ- sor: photoreceptors are arranged in a non-
ent things at different times, of course, but homogeneous fashion, most closely spaced
your visual experience almost always has at the center of the fovea, with spacing
the character of a seen scene. You see an increasing linearly all the way through the
expanse of objects and backgrounds, with fovea and out to about ten to fifteen degrees
their shapes, colors, and motions, which in periphery. The type of receptor also
stretches out from a certain extent to your changes as you move out into the periph-
left, to a certain extent to your right, as well ery, with cones being in the majority up
as up and down. It certainly appears to us as to about five degrees, and then rods taking
if what is often called our "visual field" is spa- over as the main receptor type further out
tially continuous in the sense that everything in periphery. A second curious fact about
in it is seen in roughly the same way. Things the retina is the fact that it is inverted, with
to the side of what you are most point- the axons and blood vessels that irrigate it
edly looking at, even if at the periphery, placed on the anterior surface; that is, fac-
surely seem seen, and they have the same ing the light. This means that shadows of
visual characters (e.g., shape, color, motion) these structures obscure the light-sensitive
as that which you directly look at. surface. In one particular place on the retina,
the axons and blood vessels come together
Consider your current visual experience
to leave the eyeball where they form the
as you are reading this page. Don't you see
optic nerve. At this location about ten to fif-
the whole page, book, or even part of your
teen degrees on the nasal side of each eye
hands or the desk that is supporting it - even
there can be no photoreceptors and there
if you are only reading part of the text at
is a scotoma, or blind spot, whose approxi-
each moment? And aren't the pages sprayed
mate six-degree projection in the visual field
with what is definitively text - in regular
is sufficient to engulf an orange held at
format?
arm's length. And yet despite these defects
Corollary to this spatial continuity, vision
of the eye's receptor surface, we do not
also seems temporally continuous. The con-
see spatial nonhomogeneities in our visual
tents of the visual field change frequently,
fields.
but, unless we close our eyes, the field
remains continually present. Another curious fact concerns the optics
Yet temporal continuity loses its aura of of the eye. Compared to even a low-cost
evidence when confronted with the mun- camera, the eye's lens lacks surprisingly in
dane observation that we blink every few quality. Chromatic aberration creates a dif-
seconds. Why doesn't this lead to an inter- ference of about 1.6 diopters in the focal
ruption of visual experience - as happens length for red and blue light - meaning that
when we are in a room in which the light the eye cannot simultaneously focus features
goes out from time to time? Worse than of different colors. Spatial distortions due to
blinks, eye movements create displacements imperfections in the lens shape and to the
of the retinal image at a rate of about three to sphericity of the eyeball are also significant
five times a second all the waking day. One outside the foveal zone.
might think that we should see our world It is striking, however, that none of these
continually jumping around. Why don't we? anatomical particularities are reflected in the
experienced phenomenal field. If they were,
we would experience our visual field not
2.2. Anatomical Discontinuity
only as inverted but also as having a small
There not only would appear to be a prob- central region in full color and detail and a
lem in explaining the perceived temporal blurred surround in drained colors.
SITUATED PERCEPTION AND SENSATION IN VISION AND OTHER MODALITIES 187

But of course the visual field does not thing than the fact that one notices when-
appear to us that way. Instead it looks ever it changes?
smooth and roughly continuous: with things In which sense is our pretheoretical un-
in it seen in roughly the same way all over. derstanding of seeing as continuous wrong
How is this possible? How can our experi- and in which sense is it right? It is wrong
ence have the continuity it has despite what to the extent that in a certain sense we
seem like grave defects in the anatomy? do not really fully see all the detail at any
moment; in fact, seeing is sequential rather
than continuous.' It is right in that in some
2.3. The Hypothesis of the World sense we still do actually see it!
as an Outside Memory
The approach we propose can be called
To begin to answer this question, consider the hypothesis of the world as an outside
the light in a refrigerator (Thomas, 1999). memory, following O'Regan (1992), because
Unless we knew better, we would believe of the emphasis on the fact that it is the
that the refrigerator's light is always on. world itself, rather than some internal mem-
Indeed, whenever we open the door to ory store, that is continually interrogated
look at it, it is on. It seems continuously and dealt with.
on, not because it is always on, and cer- So, the apparent contradiction between
tainly not because we continuously see it as the smoothness of experience and the appar-
being on, but because it is on whenever we ent defects of our retinas can be avoided by
look. understanding the active nature of vision,
In a similar vein, we suggest, the scene and by realizing that no internal replica
we are confronted with seems to be detailed, of the world needs to be reconstructed
not because we see all of the details all of the inside the brain to account for every fea-
time but because we find the details when- ture of awareness. For example, the very
ever we look for them. strong nonhomogeneity of retinal sampling,
That is, the elements of the scene that with resolution dropping off drastically for
are in peripheral vision or are currently not every degree we move out into peripheral
attended to are seen only in a secondary vision, the poor optical quality of periph-
sense. The retina registers these elements, eral vision, and the lack of color-sensitive
but we do not see them fully as we see some- cones in periphery do not give us the phe-
thing we attend to. Only when we turn to nomenal feel of a poor-quality, out-of-focus,
them and scrutinize them, do we actually monochrome world in our peripheral fields.
see all the detail. Again, the reason is that we do not see the
Our sense of seeing everything all at once retina: we see the world, as probed by the
is gready enhanced by the property we call retina, which we use as a tool. This is analo-
"grabbiness." Grabbiness refers to the fact gous to what happens when we feel a table
that the visual system is so wired that visual through tactile exploration: we do not feel
transients - sudden changes in visual stim- our hands and their imperfections - gaps,
ulation (e.g., those arising from a sudden fingernails, differences in tactile resolution -
motion or a sudden change in color) - gen- rather, we feel the table by using our hand as
erally trigger a jump of the eye so as to bring a tool. We do not think there are gaps in the
the fovea in line with it. This means that tabletop where there are gaps between our
normally a significant visual change in the fingers. This is presumably not because we
scene will be immediately recognized and have a gap-filling-in mechanism to compen-
scrutinized. Grabbiness supports our feel- sate the gaps but because feeling the table
ing of visually experiencing the whole scene does not consist in exhaustively scanning the
because it, n o r m a l l y , ensures that no signifi- table to re-create inside the head a kind of
cant change in visual properties escapes our internal model. Rather, feeling the table is
notice. W h a t better evidence could one have an ongoing exploratory activity in which we
that one is fully and continually seeing some- can instantaneously access any information
188 ERIK MYIN AND J. KEVIN O'REGAN

we require by displacing our hand. In the


same way, in vision, eye movements and
attention changes can instantaneously pro-
vide any information that may be necessary
about objects in the visual field. As MacKay
suggested (1962,1967,1973), the retina is like
a giant hand that can be moved over the
scene.

3. Change Blindness

An interesting empirical prediction follows


from the hypothesis of the world as an out-
side memory. Under this view, the impres- Figure 11.1. Example of the mud-splash
sion of seeing everything in the visual field phenomenon (O'Regan, Rensink, & Clark 1999).
If the five patterned ellipses (mud splashes)
in front of us derives not from all the detail
appear very briefly and disappear at the same
actually being continuously represented in
time as a large change in the picture (e.g., the
the brain, but from its immediate accessibil- solid white line in the street becomes a dashed
ity at the mere flick of the eye or of atten- line), this will often not be noticed. For other
tion. If this is true, then large changes in demonstrations of change blindness, see
an image should surely go unnoticed when http://nivea.psych0.univ-paris5.fT.
these occur on parts of the image that are not
currendy part of what the viewer is visually
exploring. local transients is to make them occur
The problem is that this prediction can- extremely slowly (see Auvray & O'Regan,
not be tested under normal circumstances 2003; Simons, Franconeri, & Reimer, 2000).
because of the grabbiness we have just The results of all these experiments confirm
described: usually changes in an image pro- the following: unless observers happen to
voke rapid motion signals and contrast- be scrutinizing the changing location as the
change signals in the low-level visual system change occurs, they tend to miss the change.
that immediately grab the viewer's atten- The change blindness paradigm has gen-
tion. If it were possible to prevent such tran- erated much research (cf. Simons & Rensink,
sients from occurring, or to somehow mask 2005) and can be observed in a variety of
them, then, under the view of the world other situations (when the image change
as an outside memory, the changes should occurs during eye saccades, eye blinks, cuts
not be noticed (unless by chance the viewer in a film sequence, or even in candid-
happened to be scrutinizing the very loca- camera type situations in everyday life; cf.
tion that changed). Simons & Levin, 1997). It is a direct pre-
These ideas were the motivation for the diction of the idea of the world as an out-
paradigm of change blindness that O'Regan, side memory. It was discovered following
Rensink, and Clark (1999) and Rensink, elaboration of that idea, and it can be con-
O'Regan, and Clark (1997,2000) introduced. sidered striking empirical support for the
In this paradigm a large change in an image theory.
is made but a brief flicker or "mud splash" is Further empirical confirmation of the
simultaneously superimposed on the screen idea that we do not continually represent
(see Figure 11.1). This produces transients all the entire visual field in all its richness comes
over the image that drown out the local tran- from the inattentional blindness paradigm
sient that corresponds to the true image- (see Mack & Rock, 1998; Simons & Chabris,
change location. Another effective way to 1999). In this it is shown that when observers
prevent the attention-grabbing action of are intently engaged in a task like following
SITUATED PERCEPTION AND SENSATION IN VISION AND OTHER MODALITIES 189

a ball in a complex scene, they can fail to


notice a totally obvious and striking event
occurring right before their eyes, such as
a person dressed in a gorilla outfit passing
through the scene. Phenomena like this are,
in fact, well known as "looked but failed to
see" errors in ergonomics, where it has been
observed that vehicle drivers frequently col-
lide with obstacles that they are directly
looking at (e.g., trains passing by at rail-
way crossings, police cars stopped by the
side of the road, bicycles passing directly in
front of them, airplanes parked in the middle
of the runway; see Herslund & Jorgensen,
2003; Hills, 1980; Langham, Hole, Edwards,
&0'Neil, 2002). They show again the impor-
Figure 11.2. Example from Rensink, O'Regan,
tance of attentive exploration of the scene and Clark (1997) in which a change in the size
for there to be awareness of its contents. of the glass of milk is generally noticed
This further bolsters the hypothesis of the immediately because this is a central interest
world as an outside memory. part of the picture.

4. Clarification Concerning do not fail to notice it, despite an inserted


Representations blank screen (Rensink et al., 1997) or the
presence of mud splashes (see Figure 11.2;
It is important to point out exactly how O'Regan et al., 1999).
the hypothesis of the world as an outside Because you do not fully see the periph-
memory offers a different explanation of eral or unattended details, it seems pointiess
the experience of visual continuity from to try to account for their being seen via a
that of the more traditional representational fully detailed representation. Rather, what
account. should be given an explanation is the pre-
What the hypothesis denies is not the theoretical conviction that we nevertheless
general claim that there are representations see everything continually. Such an explana-
operative in one or various stages of visual tion is precisely what is provided for in the
processing but that the feeling of seeing all approach of the world as an outside mem-
the detail at any moment is the result of a ory: you think you see all the detail at any
fully detailed, continuously present repre- moment not because you actually see it con-
sentation of all the detail. 1 tinuously but because you see detail when-
What change blindness highlights, ac- ever you care about detad - remember the
cording to the hypothesis of the world as refrigerator light.5
an outside memory, is the falseness of the Thus, no detailed representation is nec-
idea that you see all the detail at any essary to account for visual awareness
moment. Regions that are seen peripher- according to the world-as-an-outside-mem-
ally, or that are not attended to, are not ory hypothesis, which provides a simpler
seen in detail. If they were, you would see account without such a detaded represen-
the changes. Indeed, in the change blind- tation and is in accordance with data from
ness paradigm exposure, if you happen to visual anatomy. It leads to correct predic-
be focusing on or attending to the elements tions for the phenomenon of change blind-
to which the changes occur, you do see the ness. Further evidence for the hypothesis
changes. If the change occurs in the the- can be found in the study of vision in
matically central element of the scene, you the context of activities such as reading,
190 ERIK MYIN AND J. KEVIN O'REGAN

playing a ball game, and solving a visual tend to require more numerous or longer-
problem, which will be reviewed in the next duration fixations, and word-skipping tac-
section. tics may be influenced by local moment-
to-moment lexical, syntactic, or semantic
processing (Reichle, Rayner, & Pollatsek,
5. Vision in Action 2 0 0 3 ; Reilly & Radach, 2003). This suggests
that text processing occurs to some extent
Data obtained by studying vision in natural in an on-line fashion, at the locus of fixa-
conditions have highlighted features that are tion, instead of being carried out on the basis
strongly supportive of the hypothesis of the of information stored in a cumulative visual
world as an outside memory. In particular, buffer. This is further evidenced by the fact
such studies have indicated the large degree that changes made to the text during a fixa-
to which seeing is the following: tion affect both the duration of the current
fixation and the size of the subsequent sac-
cade (Rayner, 1 9 9 8 ) .
• Economical or sparse, in the sense that,
at successive moments of visual activity, Although the seven- to nine-letter span
only a very small part of a scene is actually covered by saccades is sampled by foveal
being processed vision, some general information (e.g.,
• Task dependent, or specifically adapted word-boundary information) in a span up
to the ongoing project, because what is to about fourteen letter spaces from the
looked at is that about which informa- fixation point affects the reading pro-
tion is currendy needed to support one's cess (Rayner, 1 9 9 8 ) Interestingly, and very
current activity telling, changes outside the fourteen-letter
1 On-line and on-demand, which means span have virtually no effect on processing
that visual processing happens at the or on the reader's awareness. So subjectively
moment the object or part of the scene there is no difference between a reader in
of interest is attended to front of a computer screen in which changes
in peripheral text areas is synchronized with
For example, in reading, though eye the reader's gaze changes and that same
movements follow a general reading-specific reader in front of a regular, static, text- filled
pattern, they are influenced by specifics of screen. Thus, vision in reading is sparse:
the text being read (cf., e.g., O'Regan, 1 9 9 0 ; readers are, at any moment, only effectively
Rayner, 1 9 9 8 ) . General features of eye move- visually in touch with a small part of the
ments in reading are a sequence of forward- environment - in this case, essentially the
going saccades with length seven to nine let- seven- to nine-letter portion of the page
ter spaces, to a certain extent independent or screen that is currently being processed.
of font size, with occasional backward-going Note that, nevertheless, as emphasized ear-
regressions. Saccades are separated by eye lier, the experienced visual field covers sig-
fixations with durations of about 1 5 0 ms to nificantly more.
3 5 0 ms. Saccade lengths and fixation dura- Studies of visual exploration during
tions are determined by a number of fac- everyday activities such as making tea (Land,
tors, ranging from low level to high level. Mennie, 8c Rusted, 1 9 9 9 ) or preparing a sand-
Thus, whereas there is clearly an ongoing wich (Hayhoe, 2 0 0 0 ) confirm this concep-
reading rhythm or strategy (O'Regan, 1 9 9 0 ; tion of vision as very much an on-line activ-
Vitu, 1 9 9 9 , 2 0 0 3 ; Yang & McConkie, 2 0 0 1 , ity, which, through its task dependence, is
2 0 0 4 ) , ongoing cognitive processing at the sparse. Invariably such studies have found
fixation location clearly affects the precise that the gaze is almost uniquely directed to
eye-movement scanning parameters, at least the objects relevant to the task (e.g., the ket-
on a temporal scale extending over two or de, its lid, the tap, and the stove), and that
three fixations (Rayner, Sereno, & Raney, objects are looked at in serial order, roughly
1 9 9 6 ) . For example, more difficult words as long as it takes to manually deal with the
s i t u a t e d p e r c e p t i o n a n d s e n s a t i o n i n vision a n d o t h e r m o d a l i t i e s 1 4 4

object. Several saccades (up to eleven for Pook, and Rao (1997). Here subjects were
the initial visual manipulation of the kettle) given the task of copying a pattern of colored
can be made to (different parts of) the same blocks shown on a computer screen, using a
object. In the tea-making study, the overall resource of similar blocks in no particular
structure of gaze dynamics and the num- order shown next to it. Using a mouse, sub-
ber of fixations to different objects were jects could pick up, drag, and drop blocks
found to be similar across subjects. In the from the resource area to create the copy
sandwich- and tea-making studies, the func- in a work space. Eye movements and mouse
tionality and economy of looking is conspic- manipulations were continually monitored.
uous. For example, it was found out that A typical sequence of fixations and actions
the number of task-irrelevant objects viewed was as follows:
was less than 19 percent, and often less than
5 percent (Land, 2004). 1. A fixation at a block in the model
Investigations of seeing in steering (Land 2. A fixation at a block in the resource area
6 Lee, 1994) and ball-game playing (Land that matches the color
& McLeod, 2000) have shown that subjects 3- Picking it up
direct their gaze at the richest source of rel- 4- A fixation at the block in the model
evant information. In steering on a wind- (again)
ing road, for example, a driver will look 5- A fixation at the corresponding place in
(i.e., fixate) ahead at the tangent point on the resource area
the upcoming bend; the batsman in cricket 6. Dragging and dropping of the chosen
will look at the place where the ball is block
expected to bounce. In both cases, these
points are most informative with respect to This work of Ballard and colleagues once
the action the subject is about to under- more testifies to the task-oriented, on-
take (turning the steering wheel, return- demand character of saccade dynamics. This
ing the ball). In the former case, this is so comes out most clearly in the fact that
because the angle between the line of sight the amount of visual information taken in
and the tangent point corresponds to the appeared to be minimal, determined only
angle to which the steering wheel has to by the current task demands. Thus, instead
be turned to keep the car on the road; in of remembering a block's color and location,
the latter case, it is because knowing about most of the time subjects revisited a block to
the location where the bouncing ball hits the find out about its destination location after
ground disambiguates a previously multiply previously having been at the same block to
interpretable input and allows thus for pre- check for its color. In other words, the world
diction of precisely where the ball will be at serves as an outside memory. 4
a point optimal for the returning shot (Land
& Furneaux, 1997).
In driving, other relevant cues, especially 6. The Sensorimotor Approach
the car's position relative to the nearer parts
of the road (as opposed to the more distant We have described how the hypothesis of
tangent point) are continually monitored by the world as an outside memory accounts
Peripheral vision. This is shown by the fact for the continuity of vision by emphasizing
that tampering with this source of informa- a particular way a perceiver interacts with
tion results in the driver's holding the road his or her environment. Indeed, relative to
Position less accurately (for further data and a traditional representational account, the
discussion, see Land, 2004). explanatory load for the continuity of visual
Similar findings were reported in a well- experience shifts firom the internal (what is
known study of eye movements in a manipu- in the head) to the external: the temporally
l e task, described i n Ballard, Hayhoe, Li, spread interaction of a perceiver with his or
and
Whitehead (1992) and Ballard, Hayhoe, her environment.
191 ERIK MYIN AND J. KEVIN O'REGAN

In the sensorimotor contingency ap- potentialities for action becomes available;


proach to sensation and perception, this namely, the assembly of action potential-
shifting of the explanatory load is car- ities that corresponds to the felt position.
ried further and applied across the board. For example, if someone taps my leg, the
According to this approach, the perceived sensation is perceived on my leg and not on
quality of sensory stimulation is determined my foot because moving my leg, but not my
by the particular way subjects interact with foot, can cause the sensation to change. The
their surroundings rather than by the spe- sensation is also perceived on my leg because
cific character of any intervening brain pro- I can touch my finger to that location and
cesses or representations. create a similar feeling to the one that I am
In the sensorimotor contingency theory, currendy feeling. Furthermore, I can move
the experienced quality of perceptual feel- my eyes to the location on my leg and see
ings is taken to arise from the precise ways the person tapping, whereas if I move my
in which one perceptually explores one's eyes to other parts of my body, I do not see
environment. Sensorimotor contingencies (a the person tapping.
term borrowed from MacKay, 1962) are the It is worth mentioning that as regards
ways in which, during such an exploration, the notion of location, the conception of
perceptual input varies as a function of per- the sensorimotor approach is related to
ceptual exploratory actions.5 Poincar6's (1905) conception of space as inti-
Consider the tactile perception of the mately connected with action: the measure
softness of a sponge (O'Regan, Myin, & Noe, of the position of an object is constituted by
2005a, 2005b). According to the sensorimo- the sequence of actions that I can potentially
tor approach, perceiving the softness of the undertake to reach it. Philipona, O'Regan,
sponge derives from regularities such as the and Nadal (2003) and Philipona, O'Regan,
fact that if one presses, the sponge yields. If Nadal, and Coenen (2004) have indeed
one manually explores an object and finds shown how an organism can infer the notion
that such sensorimotor interactions hold, of three-dimensional space from sensorimo-
one perceives softness. If one would detect tor contingencies. By studying the laws that
that on pressing there is strong resistance, determine how sensory input changes as a
one perceives hardness. function of actions, an organism can dis-
In the following sections, we will consider cover which bodily actions produce the dif-
some consequences of this view, as concerns ferent types of translations and rotations in
perception of space, position, color, as well the world it inhabits, and thereby find out
as sensory modality. about spatial structure in general. It can do
this without knowledge of the neural code
that codes its sensory inputs or motor out-
6.1. An Example: Felt Location puts 9 in fact, it can do this without know-
When there is tactile stimulation of the ing from what kind of sensors it is getting
body, the location where it is experienced is sensory input, and even without knowing
usually thought to be the result of activation which neural signals are sensory and which
of a cortical map in the brain corresponding are motor.
to that location. Although the sensorimotor
approach accepts that such cortical activa-
tion occurs and is necessary for the sensa- 6.2. The Rubber Hand Experiment
tion of local touch to occur, the approach The rubber hand experiment of Botvinick
questions the explanatory weight that the and Cohen (1998) provides excellent con-
activation itself carries. Under the sensori- firmation of these ideas. Precursors of the
motor approach, the sensation of location experiment have been known since Aris-
does not arise because of activation in a cor- totle, and more recently Tastevin (1937) .The
tical map per se. Instead, it arises because, principle has been put to use by Ramachan-
by this activation, a particular assembly of dran and Rogers-Ramachandran (2000) in
s i t u a t e d perception a n d s e n s a t i o n i n vision a n d o t h e r modalities 193

the rehabilitation of chronic phantom-limb modified by the visual-tactile correlations


pains. that he observes in the immediately preced-
The subject sits with his or her hand lying ing stimulation phase.
on a table. The hand is hidden from the
subject's view by an opaque screen. Instead
6.3. Sensory Quality and Sensory
of his own hand, the subject sees a rubber
replica, also in front of him on the table.
Substitution Experiments
The experimenter taps, touches, and moves An obvious experimental prediction of the
the fingers of the rubber hand while the sub- sensorimotor theory is that it should be
ject watches. At the same time, the experi- possible to create substitution of one sense
menter exacdy replicates his or her actions modality by another. It should, for exam-
on the subject's real hand behind the screen. ple, be possible to obtain a visual sensory
He takes care to make the manipulation syn- experience through auditory input. This is
chronous on the real and the rubber hand. predicted because the theory claims that
After about two minutes the rubber hand a particular sensory experience does not
illusion occurs: subjects have the distinct derive direcdy from the neural channels that
feeling that the rubber hand is their own are involved in transmitting the informa-
hand. This first result, already demonstrated tion but from the sensorimotor laws that
by Botvinick and Cohen (1998), shows that link input to output. A visual stimulation
the sense of ownership and felt position of a is one that obeys certain laws that are typ-
tactile stimulation is modified very rapidly ical of the visual modality: the stimula-
by correlations between visual and tactile tion changes drastically when one blinks,
stimulations. This is expected from the it is modified in precise ways when one
sensorimotor theory, because by definition approaches or recedes from an object, infor-
what is meant by the experience of location mation from objects can be interrupted by
at a body position is, among other things, the other objects occluding them, and so on.
fact that tactile stimulation at that location Auditory stimulation, for example, obeys
will be correlated with visual changes occur- other laws: the stimulation is not affected
ring when the eyes are directed at the loca- by blinks but by head movements. Sound
tion. A number of authors have confirmed sources do not occlude one another in the
that, when stimulation of rubber and real way visual sources occlude one another, and
hand is asynchronous, the illusion does not so on. If one were able, for example, to re-
occur, as expected from sensorimotor the- create the laws usually associated with see-
ory (e.g., Tsakiris 8c Haggard, 2005). ing but in the auditory modality, then one
Cooke and O'Regan (2005) also examine should, according to the sensorimotor the-
what happens when the rubber hand is big- ory, be able to see through one's ears.
ger or rather smaller than the subject's hand. The idea of sensory substitution is not
After the illusion sets in, the experimenter new, and it had been experimented with by
asks the subject to close his eyes and to Paul Bach-y-Rita and collaborators as early
attempt to touch his thumb and index finger as the 1950s, with the tactile visual sen-
to two points that are marked on the table sory substitution device (Bach-y-Rita, 1967,
in front of him, in a sort of pincer motion. 1972; Bach-y-Rita, Collins, Saunders, White,
It is observed that in the synchronous condi- 8c Scadden, 1969). This device converted a
tion, the size of the pincer motion is strongly video image into a tactile stimulation on a
affected. When the rubber hand is smaller twenty-by-twenty matrix of vibrators that
than the subject's hand, the pincer motion a blind person, for example, could wear
is too large. When the rubber hand is larger on his or her abdomen. For technical rea-
than the subject's hand, the pincer is too sons, among others, the work is only gradu-
small. This is consistent with the possibil- ally coming to fruition. Today a number of
'ty, expected in the sensorimotor theory, sensory substitution devices are being per-
that the subject's perceived hand size is fected and put to use to transform from
ERIK MYIN A N D J . K E V I N O ' R E G A N

one sensory modality to another (cf. Bach-y- prising success, by Philipona and O'Regan
Rita & Kercel, 2 0 0 3 ) . For reasons related to (2006). The idea is to propose that color
the feasibility of creating devices that can should not be conceived of as resulting from
translate the very high spatial resolution of activation of color channels in the brain.
the human eye into another sense modality, Instead, perceiving color is a perceptual
visual substitution devices are only partly interaction that involves monitoring the way
effective. Nevertheless, there are blind peo- colored surfaces change incoming light into
ple who use them regularly and report that outgoing light. As one moves a red piece
in some sense they see with these devices of paper around under different illumina-
(Apkarian, 1 9 8 3 ; Guamiero, 1 9 7 4 ) . Devices tions, the light reflected off the paper into
that convert between other modalities are one's eye is different, depending on whether
also being developed. Some that convert the paper is mainly receiving bluish sky-
vision into sound are moderately successful light, yellowish sunlight, or reddish lamp-
(Arno et al., 2001; Cronly-Dillon, Persaud, light. The idea is to suggest that perceiving
& Gregory, 1999; Cronly-Dillon, Persaud, 8c the color red corresponds to the observer
Blore, 2 0 0 0 ; Meijer, 1 9 9 2 ; see also an evalu- having implicit knowledge about the law
ation of this latter device in Auvray, Han- that governs how the piece of paper affects
neton, 8c O'Regan, 2 0 0 7 ) . The question of the incoming light. The analogy with the
whether observers can really experience the sponge is now apparent: just as softness is
existence of an outside world with such a property of the sponge that can be tested
devices has been investigated with vary- by pressing on it, redness, it is claimed, is a
ing results (Auvray, Hanneton, Lenay, 8c property of the red paper that can be tested
O'Regan, 2 0 0 5 ; Epstein, Hughes, Schneider, by moving the paper around under different
8c Bach-y-Rita, 1 9 8 6 ) . A particularly success- light sources (or by moving oneself around
ful device is one that allows patients with the piece of paper).
vestibular lesions to regain their sense of bal- Applying these ideas to the sensation
ance. Here an accelerometer is coupled to a of color allows for a surprisingly accurate
tongue-display unit that delivers stimulation account of color judgments, particularly the
to a twelve-by-twelve matrix of electrodes fact that certain colors — namely red, yel-
worn on the tongue (Tyler, Danilov, 8c low, blue, and green - are in a very precise
Bach-y-Rita, 2 0 0 3 ) . The tongue-based device sense special: they affect incoming light in a
has also been used for vision (Bach-y- simpler way than do all other colors. From
Rita, Kaczmarek, Tyler, 8c Garcia-Lara, 1998; this finding it is possible to deduce accu-
Sampaio, Maris, 8c Bach-y-Rita, 2 0 0 1 ) . rate predictions for well-established results
from color science, in particular facts about
color naming, unique hues, and hue can-
6.4. The Sensory Quality of Color cellation (Philipona 8c O'Regan, 2006). The
A major challenge for a sensorimotor theory predictions are in fact more compatible with
of sensation is the problem of color, as it is known empirical data than are predictions
difficult at first to envisage how the experi- made from standard neurophysiologically
ence of, say, a flash of red light, could in any based, opponent-channel models of color
way be conceived of as involving a sensori- perception (see Figure 11.3).
motor interaction. There would appear to
be no exploratory behavior in color percep-
tion that might be analogous to pressing the 6.5. Experiments on Adaptation of Color
sponge. Experience to Action
Yet given the advantage of taking the sen- If the quality of a sensory experience is
sorimotor approach, it is worthwhile to try determined by the sensorimotor interac-
to find some way to apply the approach to tions involved in that experience, it should
color. The fact that it is possible to do this be possible to change sensory quality by
has recently been demonstrated, with sur- changing the interactions that are generally
s i t u a t e d p e r c e p t i o n a n d s e n s a t i o n i n vision a n d o t h e r m o d a l i t i e s
195

perceived as gray, apparently to counterbal-


ance an excess of perceived blue on the left.
When the observer looks right, the patch has
to be tinted with blue for it to be perceived
as gray, apparently to cancel an excess of
perceived yellow on the right. This confirms
that the same retinal region can give rise to
two different color percepts, depending on
the eyes' direction of gaze.
The result is consistent with the idea,
implied by the sensorimotor approach, that
Figure u. j. Comparison between observed and experience of color depends on potential
predicted salience of different surface colors. associations with actions. Further experi-
The coordinate system for a selection of Munsell ments have confirmed that the effect can be
color chips is the one used by Kay, Regier, and obtained without tinted spectacles, by sys-
Cook (2003). For example F17 would be a tematically linking particular color changes
particular green, G2 a particular red, C9 a
occurring on a computer monitor to partic-
particular yellow, and G28 a particular blue. The
ular eye-movement directions (Bompas &
contour plots indicate the peaks where the
theory proposed by Philipona and O'Regan O'Regan, 2006b). In all cases, the effects
(2006) predicts that surface colors should be are not explicable by peripheral adaptation
singular. The patches near these peaks are taken phenomena, because the very same retinal
from Berlin and Kay's (1969) world color survey cones are being stimulated in exactly the
(see also Kay, Regier, & Cook, 2003) and same way, and simply depending on gaze
correspond to surface colors that, across a direction the color percept is different.
sample of 110 different languages, possessed a
name for more than 20 percent of the maximum
number of speakers. Thus, colors predicted to 6.6. Situating Sensory Consciousness
change light in a singular way are seen to
O'Regan et al. (2004, 2005a, 2005b) have
correspond quite precisely with those given
names across different languages. argued that the sensorimotor approach
allows one to understand what is specif-
ically sensory about perceptual conscious-
associated with a stimulation. In an attempt ness by means of the concepts of bodiliness
to verify this prediction of the sensori- (also corporality) and grabbiness (also alert-
motor approach, Bompas and O'Regan ing capacity), introduced in O'Regan and
(2006a, 2006b) performed a series of experi- Noe (2001 a,b) and in Myin and O'Regan
ments in which a new, artificial dependency (2002). Basically, the concepts offer an analy-
was created between a displayed color and sis of the way in which conscious perception
eye movements. In one experiment, the sub- differs from thinking or imagining.
ject wore spectacles tinted blue in one hemi- Consider what it is to actually stand in
field and yellow in the other. This situa- front of an elephant compared to what it
tion has the effect that when the observer is to think about an elephant or to imagine
moves her eyes, say, to the left, the world standing in front of an elephant. In the first
» tinted with blue, and when she moves case, the elephant is experienced as having
them to the right, the world is tinted with a sensory presence. This presence, follow-
yellow. After approximately forty-five min- ing philosophers such as David Hume and
utes of adaptation with such spectacles, the Edmund Husserl, can be taken as a defin-
observer removes the spectacles and her per- ing characteristic of sensory and perceptual
ception of color is tested. It is found that experience.
w
hen the subject looks to the left, a gray O'Regan et al. (2004, 2005a, 2005b) sug-
Patch of color on a computer monitor now gest that there are several important char-
ta to be tinted with yellow for it to be acteristics of the perceptual interactions
196 ERIK MYIN A N D J. KEVIN O ' R E G A N

involved in sensation that in a natural way you because they have the potential to sur-
provide a plausible account of this percep- prise you and to divert your normal thought
tual presence. processes. In fact, even without the action of
First and foremost, sensation, considered hardwired detectors of sudden change, sen-
a sensorimotor interaction, is in an essential sory skills necessarily involve the organism
way related to body movements. Whereas trying to adapt to outside events that have
the processes of thinking, deciding, and a life of their own, escaping to some extent
remembering can occur without potential the control of the perceiver. Thoughts and
bodily motions, the sensory processes like memories on the other hand are (barring
seeing, hearing, and touching involve poten- exceptional cases like obsessive thoughts)
tial body action in a fundamental way. This completely the product of the individual's
is what O'Regan et al. (2004, 2005a, 2005b) mind, and so do not have the autonomy that
call "bodiliness," or corporality: when one characterizes sensory input. It is therefore
sees, the slightest movement of one's eyes, natural that a perceiver will have quite a dif-
body, or the object in question necessar- ferent feeling: less a feeling of control, more
ily immediately provokes changes in sensory a feeling of imposition, when he or she is
input. The sensory input from the elephant engaging in sensory interactions than when
changes drastically if one so much as slightly he or she is thinking or remembering.
moves one's head. On the other hand, bodily Bodiliness and grabbiness are dynamic
actions do not in such a necessary fashion perceiver-environment relations that are
change the contents of our memories or our typical and unique for sensation and percep-
thoughts. One can keep on entertaining the tion, and absent in other mental phenomena
same thought even while walking; and start- such as thinking or desiring. The sensori-
ing to walk does not automatically makes motor proposal, then, is that these unique
one think a different thought. When sen- features provide an account for the particu-
sations are considered sensorimotor inter- lar sensory or perceptual feel that differen-
actions it becomes possible to account for tiates awareness in sensation and perception
the difference between sensations and men- from awareness in thoughts. So, focusing,
tal processes in terms of the effects bodily through bodiliness and grabbiness, on the
actions have on the former but not on the embodied and situated interaction with the
latter. environment leads - at the very least - to an
The already-introduced notion of grabbi- interesting perspective on one of the most
ness, or alerting capacity (O'Regan et al., puzzling problems of the science of vision
2004, 2005a, 2005b), refers to a complemen- and perception in general, the question
tary aspect of sensory systems. Grabbiness of consciousness and perceptual awareness.
occurs because sensory systems in biological Because the sensorimotor account consid-
organisms are hardwired in such a way to ers that the perceived quality of a sensation
detect sudden changes. When these occur, is not generated by some as-yet-unknown
alerting mechanisms incontrovertibly notify brain process but rather is constituted by
the perceiver, so that his normal cognitive the inherent nature of the exploratory inter-
functioning is interrupted. When the ele- action that is involved, the concepts of bodi-
phant moves slightly, or when a bird flies liness and grabbiness take on an explanatory
by or a light flashes, one will automatically status. Now it is possible to explain, without
cast one's eye or attention on that sudden appeal to further brain mechanisms, the dif-
event. ferences within and between sensory modal-
ities, and why sensations have the presence
This suggests that this potential alerting
that thoughts lack. Whatever's one's opin-
capacity of sensory channels is another con-
ion on whether this achieves the goal of fully
stitutive difference that accounts in a natural
bridging the explanatory gap (Levine, 1983)
way for the difference in presence between
between perceptual consciousness and the
sensation and other mental processes like
physical world, it certainly seems to testify
thoughts. Sensations impose themselves on
situated perception a n d sensation in vision a n d o t h e r modalities 201
150

once more to the f r u i t f u l n e s s a n d t h e p o t e n - of vision: Pattern recognition by the blind.


tial inherent in thinking of sensation a n d p e r - Applied Cognitive Psychology, 15, 509-519.
ception - in vision a n d o t h e r m o d a l i t i e s ! Auvray, M., Hanneton, S., Lenay, C., & O'Regan,
from a sensorimotor p e r s p e c t i v e . J. K. (2005). There is something out there: Dis-
tal attribution in sensory substitution, twenty
years later. Journal of Integrative Neuroscience,
4(4). 505-521-
Acknowledgments
Auvray, M., Hanneton, S., & O'Regan, J. K.
(2007). Learning to perceive with a visuo-
Erik Myin is grateful for funding from the Re- auditory substitution system: Localization and
search Foundation-Flanders (FWO). object recognition with "The vOICe." Percep-
tion, 36(3), 416-430.
Auvray, M., & O'Regan, J. K. (2003). L'influence
Notes des facteurs sémantiques sur la cécité aux
changements progressifs dans les scènes
1 As also stressed in Findlay and Gilchrist visuelles. Année Psychologique, 103, 9-32.
(2003). Bach-y-Rita, P. (1967). Sensory plasticity: Appli-
2 These points are also noted and discussed by cations to a vision substitution system. Acta
Noë (2004, chap. 2). Neurological Scandinavica, 43(4), 417-426.
j Nothing in our approach precludes that the Bach-y-Rita, P. (1972). Brain mechanisms in sen-
not-fiilly-seen elements have effects on mem- sory substitution. New York: Academic Press.
ory or behavior. There is plenty of evidence Bach-y-Rita, P., Collins, C. C., Saunders, F.,
that is often interpreted in this way (for a White, B., 8t Scadden, L. (1969). Visual sub-
recent overview and discussion, see Simons stitution by tactile image projection. Nature,
& Silverman, 2004). But none of the evidence 221, 963-964.
seems to us to indicate that you fully see every Bach-y-Rita, P., Kaczmarek, K., Tyler, M., &
detail of the whole scene at any time. In other Garcia-Lara, J. (1998). Form perception with
words, none of this evidence disconfirms our a 49-point electrotactile stimulus array of the
account. tongue. Journal of Rehabilitation Research and
4 Note that subjects can also do the task in an Development, 35(4), 427-430.
internalist way, though less efficiendy (Bal- Bach-y-Rita, P. W., 8t Kercel, S. (2003). Sensory
lard et al., 1997). The externalist mode seems substitution and the human-machine inter-
to be the preferred and most optimal way to face. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(12), 541-
operate (this primacy of the external mode is 546.
a leading theme in Findlay & Gilchrist [2003], Ballard, D. H., Hayhoe, M. M., Li, F., & White-
which provides an excellent overview of the head, S. D. (1992). Hand-eye coordination
active vision field). during sequential tasks. Philosophical Transac-
5 Note that contingency is not the normal phil- tions of the Royal Society, Series B, 337, 331-339.
osophical use of the term: what is meant are Ballard, D. H., Hayhoe, M. M, Pook, P. K.,
the necessary laws linking potential actions & Rao, R. P. N. (1997). Deictic codes for
and their sensory consequences. the embodiment of cognition. Behavioral and
6 Hume (1777/1975) talks about vivacity, Brain Sciences, 20, 723-767.
Husserl (1907/1973) about Leibhaftigkeit. On Berlin, B., & Kay, P. (1969). Basic color terms: Their
the latter notion and its potential relevance universality and evolution. Berkeley: Univer-
for cognitive science, see Pacherie (1999). sity of California Press.
Bompas, A., & O'Regan, J. K. (2006a). Evidence
for a role of action in colour perception. Per-
References ception, 35(1), 65-78.
Bompas, A., & O'Regan, J. K. (2006b). More evi-
Apkarian, P. (1983). Visual training after long- dence for sensorimotor adaptation in color
term deprivation: A case report. International perception. Journal of Vision, 6(2), 145-
Journal of Neuroscience, 19(1-4), 65-83. 153-
A ™ , P., Vanlierde, A., Streel, E., Wanet- Botvinick, M., & Cohen, J. (1998). Rubber hands
Defalque, M.-C., Sanabria-Bohorquez, S., "feel" touch that eyes see [Letter]. Nature,
& Veraart, C. (2001). Auditory substitution 391(6669), 756.
i 8 s erik myin a n d j . k e v i n o ' r e g a n

Cooke, E., & O'Regan, J. K. (2005). Manipula- Land, M. F., & McLeod, P. M. (2000). From eye
tions of the body schema. Masters thesis, Mas- movements to actions: How batsmen hit the
ter de Sciences Cognitives, Ecole Normale ball. Nature Neuroscience, 3,1340-1345.
Supérieure and Université Paris Descartes. Land, M. F., Mennie, N., 8c Rusted, J. (1999).
Cronly-Dillon, J., Persaud, K., & Blore, F. (2000). The roles of vision and eye movements in the
Blind subjects construct conscious mental control of activities of daily living. Perception,
images of visual scenes encoded in musical 28,1311-1328.
form. Proceedings of the Royal Society London, Langham, M., Hole, G., Edwards, J., 8c O'Neil,
Series B, 267, 2231-2238. C. (2002). An analysis of "looked but failed
Cronly-Dillon, J., Persaud, K, 8c Gregory, R. to see" accidents involving parked police vehi-
P. F. (1999). The perception of visual images cles. Ergonomics, 45(3), 167-185.
encoded in musical form: A study in cross Levine, J. (1983). Materialism and qualia: The
modality information transfer. Proceedings of explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quar-
the Royal Society London, Series B, 266, 2427- terly, 64, 354-361.
*433- Mack, A., & Rock, I. (1998). Inattentional blind-
Epstein, W., Hughes, B., Schneider, S., 8c Bach-y- ness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Rita, P. (1986). Is there anything out there? A MacKay, D. A. (1962). Theoretical models of
study of distal attribution in response to vibro- space perception. In C. A. Muses (Ed.),
tactile stimulation. Perception, 15, 275-284. Aspects of the theory of artificial intelligence
Findlay, J. M., & Gilchrist, I. D. (2003). Active (pp. 83-104). New York: Plenum.
vision: The psychology of looking and seeing. MacKay, D. M. (1967). Ways of looking at per-
Oxford: Oxford University Press. ception. In W. Wathen-Dunn (Ed.), Models
Guarniero, G. (1974). Experience of tactile vision. for the perception of speech and visual form
(pp. 25-43). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Perception, 3,101-104.
MacKay, D. M. (1973). Visual stability and volun-
Hayhoe, M. (2000). Vision using routines: A func-
tary eye movements. In R. Jung (Ed.), Hand-
tional account of vision. Visual Cognition, 7,
book of sensory physiology (Vol. 7/3A, pp. 307-
43-64.
331). Berlin: Springer.
Herslund, M. B., & Jorgensen, N. O. (2003).
Meijer, P. B. L. (1992). An experimental sys-
Looked-but-failed-to-see-errors in traffic. Ac-
tem for auditory image representations. IEEE
cident Analysis and Prevention, 35(6), 885-891.
Transactions on Biomedical Engineering, 39(2),
Hills, B. L. (1980). Vision, visibility, and percep-
112-121.
tion in driving. Perception, 9(2), 183-216.
Hume, D. (1975). Enquiries concerning human Merleau-Ponty, M. (1945). Phénoménologie de la
understanding and concerning the principles perception. Paris: Gallimard.
of morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Myin, E., 8c O'Regan, J. K. (2002). Perceptual
(Original work published 1777) consciousness, access to modality and skill the-
Husserl, E. (1973) Ding und Raum. Vorlesun- ories. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 9(1), 27-
gen 1907. [Thing and space. Lectures 1907.] 46.
In U. Claesges (Ed.), Hussserliana 16. The Noë, Alva (2004). Action in perception. Cam-
Hague: M. Nijhoff. (Original work published bridge, MA: MIT Press.
1907) O'Regan, J. K. (1990). Eye movements and
Kay, P., Regier, T., & Cook, R. S. (2003). Focal reading. In E. Kowler (Ed.), Eye movements
colors are universal after all. Proceedings of the and their role in visual and cognitive processes
National Academy of Sciences, 102, 8386-8391. (pp. 395-453). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Land, M. F. (2004). Eye movements in daily life. O'Regan, J. K. (1992). Solving the "real" mysteries
In L. M. Chalupa & J. S. Werner (Eds.), The of visual perception: The world as an outside
visual neurosciences (Vol. 2, pp. 1357-1368). memory. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 46,
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 461-488.
Land, M. F., 8l Furneaux, S. (1997). The knowl- O'Regan, J. K., Myin, E., 81 Noë, A. (2004)
edge base of the oculomotor system. Philo- Towards an analytic phenomenology: The
sophical Transactions of the Royal Society, Series concepts of "bodiliness" and "grabbiness." In
B. 352> «31-1239- A. Carsetti (Ed.), Seeing, thinking and know-
Land, M. F., 8c Lee, D. N. (1994). Where we look ing(pp. 103-114). Dordrecht, The Netherlands:
when we steer. Nature, 369, 742-744. Kluwer.
s i t u a t e d p e r c e p t i o n a n d s e n s a t i o n i n vision a n d o t h e r modalities 2 0 3 152

O'Regan, J. K. ( Myin, E., & Noe, A. (2005a). Sen- trol in reading: Comparisons to other models.
sory consciousness explained (better) in terms Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 26, 445-526.
of "corporality" and "alerting capacity." Phe- Reilly, R., 8c Radach, R. (2003). Foundations of an
nomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 44(4), interactive activation model of eye movement
369-387. control in reading. In J. Hyônâ, R. Radach, &
O'Regan, J. K., Myin, E., & Noe, A. (2005b). Skill, H. Deubel (Eds.), The mind's eye: Cognitive
corporality and alerting capacity in an account and applied aspects of eye movements (pp. 429-
of sensory consciousness. In S. Laureys (Ed.), 455). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Progress in brain research (Vol. 150, pp. 55- 68). Rensink R. A, O'Regan, J. K., 8c Clark, J. J.
Amsterdam: Elsevier. (1997). To see or not to see: The need for
O'Regan, J. K., 81 Noe, A. (2001a). A sensorimo- attention to perceive changes in scenes. Psy-
tor account of vision and visual consciousness. chological Science, 8, 368-373.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24(5), 883-917. Rensink, R. A., O'Regan, J. K., & Clark, J. J.
O'Regan, J. K., 8c Noe, A. (2001b). Acting out (2000). On the failure to detect changes in
our sensory experience. Behavioral and Brain scenes across brief interruptions. Visual Cog-
Sciences, 24(5), 955-975- nition, 7,127-146.
O'Regan, J. K., Rensink, R. A., 8c Clark, J. J. Sampaio, E., Maris, S., 8c Bach-y-Rita, P. (2001).
(1999). Change blindness as a result of "mud- Brain plasticity: "Visual" acuity of blind per-
splashes." Nature, 398, 34. sons via the tongue. Brain Research, 908, 204-
Pacherie, E. (1999), Leibhaftigkeit and represen- 207.
tational theories of perception. In J. Petitot, Simons, D. (2000). Current approaches to change
F. Varela, B. Pachoud, 8c J.-M. Roy (Eds.), blindness. Visual Cognition, 7,1-16.
Naturalizing phenomenology: Issues in contem- Simons, D. J., 8c Chabris, C. F. (1999). Gorillas in
porary phenomenology and cognitive science our midst: Sustained inattentional blindness
(pp. 148-160). Stanford, C A : Stanford Univer- for dynamic events. Perception, 28(9), 1059-
sity Press. 1094.
Philipona, D., 8c O'Regan, J. K. (2006). Color Simons, D. J., Franconeri, S. L., 8c Reimer, R. L.
naming, unique hues and hue cancellation (2000). Change blindness in the absence of
predicted from singularities in reflection prop- visual disruption. Perception, 29,1143-1154.
erties. Visual Neuroscience, 23(3-4), 331-339. Simons, D. J., & Levin, D. T. (1997). Change
Philipona, D., O'Regan, J. K., 8c Nadal, J.-P. blindness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 1, 261-
(2003). Is there something out there? Infer- 267.
ring space from sensorimotor dependencies. Simons, D. J., 8c Rensink, R. A. (2005). Change
Neural Computation, 15(9), 2029-2050. blindness: Past, present, and future. Trends in
Philipona, D., O'Regan, J. K, Nadal, J.-P., 8c Cognitive Sciences, 9,16-20.
Coenen, O. J.-M. D. (2004). Perception of the Simons, D. J., & Silverman, M. (2004). Neu-
structure of the physical world using unknown ral and behavioral measures of change detec-
multimodal sensors and effectors. Advances in tion. In L. M. Chalupa 8c J. S. Werner (Eds.),
Neural Information Processing Systems, 15. The visual neurosciences (Vol. 2, pp. 1524-1537).
Poincare, H. (1905). La valeur de la science. Paris: Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Flammarion. Tastevin, J. (1937). En partant de l'expérience
Ramachandran, V. S., 8c Rogers-Ramachandran, d'Aristotle. L'Encephale, 1,157-184.
D. (2000). Phantom limbs and neural plastic- Thomas, N. (1999). Are theories of imagery the-
ity. Archives of Neurology, 57(3), 317-320. ories of imagination? An active perception
Rayner, K. (1998). Eye movements in reading and approach to conscious mental content. Cog-
information processing: 20 years of research. nitive Science, 23, 207-245.
Psychological Bulletin, 124(3), 372-422. Tsakiris, M., 8c Haggard, P. (2005). The rubber
Rayner, K., Sereno, S. C., 8c Raney, G. E. (1996). hand illusion revisited: Visuotactile integra-
Eye movement control in reading: A compar- tion and self-attribution. Journal of Experimen-
ison of two types of models. Journal of Experi- tal Psychology: Human Perception and Perfor-
mental Psychology: Human Perception and Per- mance, 31, 80-91.
formance, 22(5), 1188-1200. Tyler, M., Danilov, Y., 8c Bach-y-Rita, P.
Reichle, E. D., Rayner, K., 8c Pollatsek, A. (2003). (2003). Closing an open-loop control system:
The E-Z reader model of eye movement con- Vestibular substitution through the tongue.
i8S erik myin and j. kevin o'regan

Journal of Integrative Neuroscience, 2(2), 159—Yang, S.-N., & McConkie, G. W. (2001). Eye
164. movements during reading: A theory of sac-
Vitu, F. (1999). About saccade generation in read- cade initiation times. Vision Research, 41,3567-
ing. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22, 702- 3585-
7°3- Yang, S.-N., & McConkie, G. W. (2004). Saccade
Vitu, F. (2003). The basic assumptions of E-Z generation during reading: Are words neces-
reader are not well-founded. Behavioral and sary? European Journal of Cognitive Psychology,
Brain Sciences, 26(4), 506-507. 16(1-2), 226-261.
CHAPTER 12

Spatial Cognition

Embodied and Situated

Barbara Tver sky

What does it mean to say that cognition is Less immediately, that is, off-line, cog-
situated? Like many interesting questions, nition is situated by facts about our bodies
this one has many answers, probably at least and the world they inhabit. Bodies and the
one for every chapter in this volume (for an world have properties that afford, enable,
early one, see Varela, Thompson, & Rosch, and constrain perception and action. These
1991). Cognition is inescapably affected by affordances, enablings, and constraints have
the immediate who, what, where, when, enduring, biasing effects on cognition. Here
and perhaps why. Walking past a gift store are some of them. We are upright crea-
is a reminder to buy a birthday present; tures with three axes: an elongated, asym-
leftovers in the fridge inspire a new recipe; metric head-to-feet axis that is aligned with
fingers are handy for counting. T h e world gravity, which is a strong asymmetric axis
serves not just our own minds but also our of the world; and two axes that are not
communications with other minds: a glance aligned with gravity, a front-back axis that
at the door tells a partner it is time to leave; is asymmetric, and a left-right axis that is
the salt and pepper shakers on a dinner table for the most part symmetric (these ideas
act as props in a dramatic retelling; here, draw on and expand ideas articulated by
that, and this way can be understood effi- Clark, 1973, and Shepard, 1984). We have
ciently but only in context. This kind of four mobile appendages, two legs that can
cognition can be called "on-line" situated move us preferentially in one direction on
cognition. the ground, the direction we call "forward,"
and two arms that are free to manipulate
objects in the world, preferentially in the
wsed in part on collaborative work with, in order
of mention: Julie Morrison, Nancy Franklin, David forward direction. We have a set of sense
Pjyant, Holly Taylor, Jeffrey M. Zacks, Bridgette organs oriented in the direction of move-
Mtrtin Hard, Paul Lee, Julie Heiser, and Angela ment. Our actions in the world are for the
wsel). I am grateful for the opportunity to work with
"*» a talented set of individuals. most part goal directed and hierarchically so.

201
2o2 barbara t v f . r s k y

Those actions as well as the structure and (the previous, and too many to list, some
movement of the other things in the world herein and some in the companion chapters
are constrained by gravity and the other of this handbook). We say that our thoughts
things in the world. Of primary importance run in circles, we hope that the D o w Jones
among those other things are other beings tops the charts, we give a thumbs-up to
like us. We are deeply social creatures, a performance. External representations as
dependent on others to fulfill our needs and well as internal ones reflect spatial think-
desires throughout our entire fives. Coordi- ing: charts of social networks, like family
nating our needs and desires with those of trees or organizations; depictions of religious
others depends on communication, verbal ideas, like mandalas or Kabbalah; diagrams
and nonverbal, explicit and implicit. of scientific theories, like the structure of an
atom or the expression of a gene, are spatial
These facts about the world, in constrain-
whether in the mind or on paper.
ing perception and behavior, bias and con-
strain mental representations of space and Space for the mind is not like space for the
of action. The interactions of the body in physicist or surveyor, where the dimensions
the external world not only bias percep- of space are primary and things in space are
tion and action but also craft symbolic per- located with respect to those dimensions.
ception and action, and form the basis for For people, the things in space are primary
abstract thought. This view follows from the and the reference frames are constructed out
ideas that the brain and the body evolved, of them. Which things and which reference
among other things, to manage perception frames depends on which space, how it is
and action in the world, and that evolu- perceived, and how it serves. Because spa-
tion builds new functions from old struc- tial thinking is central in existence, all peo-
tures. Cognition is not just situated, it is also ple become expert in it - which is far from
embodied, in ways that are hard to untangle. saying that they are perfect at it; on the
These are heady ideas. To develop them, contrary, spatial memory and cognition have
two questions will be addressed: How does systematic biases (e.g., Tversky, 1981, 2000).
the body in the world shape thought? How The thesis to be developed is that peo-
does the body in the world shape communi- ple's conceptions of space differ for differ-
cation? The answers will come from research ent spaces and are a joint product of percep-
in our laboratory, neglecting many of the tion and action appropriate for those spaces.
rich contributions of others, only some of People act differently in different spaces: the
whom are represented in these pages. We space of the body, the space immediately
begin at the beginning: thinking about space. around the body, and the space of navi-
gation, the space too vast to be seen from
a single viewpoint. Because perception and
Shaping Thought: Space and Action action in each space differ, so conceptions of
these spaces differ. One reason the mind cre-
Spaces for Thought
ates mental spaces is to understand percep-
SPACE IS SPECIAL tion and action; another reason is to enable
Spatial thinking is essential for survival. Ele- perception and action. Correspondingly, the
mentary to survival is knowing where to go discussion will shift emphasis from space to
to find food, water, and shelter and know- action.
ing how to return, as well as how to gather
the food and water when they are located.
Space of the Body
Perhaps because of its centrality for survival,
spatial thinking forms a foundation for other The body is the first space encountered, even
thought, amply illustrated in the ways we before birth. Experience of other spaces is
talk (e.g., Clark, 1973; Lakoff & Johnson, channeled through the body, through per-
1 9 8 0 ; Talmy, 1 9 8 3 ) , the ways we depict (e.g., ception and action. Like other objects, bod-
Tversky, 1993, 2 0 0 1 ) , and the ways we reason ies have parts. Decomposing an object into
spatial cognition 203

parts is an important w a y to k n o w an object, not facilitated by movement (Reed, 2002;


as different parts have different appearances Reed & Farah, 1995). For bodies, appar-
and different functions, and the appearance ent motion follows biomechanical trajecto-
of parts can serve as clues to their f u n c - ries rather than the shortest path, as for
tions (Tversky & H e m e n w a y , 1984). Promi- other objects (Chatterjee, Freyd, & Shiffrar,
nent among body parts are those named 1996; Shiffrar & Freyd, 1993). Size, how-
frequently across many languages, includ- ever, enjoys support in object cognition. In
ing head, chest, back, arms, hands, legs, and imagery, large parts of animals, such as the
feet (Andersen, 1978; Brown, 1976). T h e y are back of a rabbit, are verified faster than small
prominent, in part, literally because they distinctive parts, such as the ears of a rab-
extend from the contour of the body; they bit (Kosslyn, 1980). Intuitively as well, large
literally stick out. T h e y are the parts drawn parts should be detected faster, just as find-
by children all over the world, the famil- ing a large person in a crowd is easier than
iar tadpole figures (e.g., G o o d n o w , 1977; finding a small person.
Kellogg, 1969). For objects in general, the Does part distinctiveness and function or
parts that are defined by discontinuities in part size dominate the body schema? To
object contour are perceptually salient (e.g., address this, Morrison and Tversky (2005;
Hoffman & Richards, 1984), are frequently see also Tversky, Morrison, & Zacks, 2002)
named, and are rated as good parts (Tver- investigated a body-part verification task,
sky & Hemenway, 1984). T h e y are also parts using the parts named across cultures: head,
with functional significance. Consider the front, back, arm, hand, leg, and foot. In some
legs of tables and jeans and horses, the han- experiments, the body-body task, partici-
dles of hammers and suitcases. It is note- pants saw pairs of realistic profiles of bod-
worthy that the parts of objects that enjoy ies in different orientations, each with a part
perceptual distinctiveness also enjoy func- highlighted by a white dot. In other experi-
tional significance. This supports inferences ments, the name-body task, participants saw
from perception to function ( H e m e n w a y & the name of a body part followed by a pic-
Tversky, 1984), a fact that children use in ture of a body with a part highlighted. In
bootstrapping from categories based on per- both tasks, participants were to respond as
ceptual similarity, like shape and color, to quickly and accurately as possible whether
categories based on function, like clothing the indicated parts were the same or dif-
and tools (Tversky, 1989). ferent. The data of interest were the same
Viewed from the outside, bodies are like reaction times to the different body parts.
other objects. But bodies are also experi- In all experiments, size lost. T h e parts
enced from the inside. T h e body parts that high in distinctiveness and function were
extend from the body contour act on the verified faster than the large parts; for exam-
world and sense the world. T h e y are over- ple, verifying head was faster than veri-
represented for their size in the sensorimo- fying back. The body-body task and the
tor cortex, as depicted in the homunculus name-body task differed in a subtle way,
popular in textbooks. These correspon- corresponding to the differences between
dences are a striking contrast to physi- part distinctiveness and part significance.
cal measurement: the brain, naming across Although part distinctiveness and functional
languages, and children's drawings across significance are correlated, the correlation
cultures converge to suggest that large parts is not perfect. In particular, the chest is
are not the most significant f o r bodies. regarded as a relatively significant body part
Other evidence indicates that bodies are even though it lacks perceptual distinctive-
perceived differently f r o m objects. Detect- ness. Its significance seems to derive from
•ng differences in body configurations is eas- the fact that it is the forward part of the
ier when participants move the relevant half body, the direction of perception and action,
°f the body, top or bottom, but detecting and the fact that it encases important inter-
differences in Lego figure configuration is nal organs. In the body-body verification
2o4 BARBARA TVERSKY

task, chest was relatively slow, reflecting the replaced descriptions with scenes, described
perceptual nature of the task. In the name- subsequendy), simultaneously showing that
body verification task, however, chest was worlds that are described rather than expe-
relatively fast. The compelling explanation rienced could be imagined and updated. We
for the advantage of functional significance is proposed that people keep track of the rela-
that language is abstract, so names are more tive positions of the objects around them as
likely to prime functional features than per- they move by constructing a spatial-mental
ceptual ones. This explanation is consonant framework out of the three axes of the
with other situations, where naming calls body and appending objects to it, updat-
attention to abstract features, notably func- ing it as the situation changes. We rea-
tion (Tversky, Zacks, Morrison, & Hard, in soned that accessibility of objects should
press). reflect characteristics of the body axes and
the world relevant to perception and action.
The space of the body serves us to keep
The head-feet axis has salient asymmetries
track of where body parts are relative to
both perceptually and behaviorally; more-
one another, either our own bodies, through
over, for the canonically upright observer,
proprioception, or other bodies, through
it correlates with the only asymmetric axis
vision. Where body parts are relative to one
in the world, the up-down axis of grav-
another affects and provides clues to what
ity. The front-back axis separates the world
body actions are possible and likely. On the
that can be easily perceived and acted on
whole, though not always, the parts that are
from the world that cannot be easdy per-
perceptually distinctive are also those that
ceived or acted on, but the left-right axis has
are functionally significant. Surprisingly, it is
few salient perceptual or behavioral asym-
not the large parts but those that are salient
metries. This analysis predicts that, for the
and significant that people recognize most
upright observer, things located along the
quickly and that appear to dominate the ter- head-feet axis should be fastest to retrieve,
rain of the space of the body. followed by things located on the front-back
axis, followed by things located on the left-
Space around the Body right axis. For the reclining observer, no
body axis correlates with gravity, so accessi-
Now we venture outside the body, to the
bility depends entirely on the body axes. In
space immediately surrounding it. This is
this case, things located along the front-back
the space of actual or potential perception
axis should be fastest because of the forward
and action, the space in reach of hand or
bias of perception and action.
eye. Of course, not all things in view can be
readily reached or acted on; Daedalus could The spatial framework pattern of reac-
not fly to the sun. People are remarkably tion times was compared to patterns pre-
adept at keeping track of the positions of dicted by two other theories in several
things in the world as they move about, even dozen experiments. According to a theory
when things are out of view, like the stores based purely on the physical situation, the
they have just passed while running errands. equiavailability model, no region of space
Storytellers rely on this ability by invoking has special status, so all directions should be
imaginary characters moving in imaginary equal. According to an account derived from
worlds. How do people keep track of loca- theories of mental imagery (e.g., Kosslyn,
tions of things as they move? 1980; Shepard & Podgorny, 1978), the mental
To study how people keep track of the transformation model, participants should
things around them as they move, Franklin imagine themselves in the scene. When a
and Tversky (1990) devised constrained direction is probed, they should imagine
worlds, objects around the body in natural themselves turning to face that direction
scenes, and constrained movements, rotat- to determine what object is there. Look-
ing in place. We instilled these worlds with ing should take longer the greater the angle
words, not with experience (though we later from forward. This model predicts that front
SPATIAL COGNITION 205

should be fastest, followed by left, right, look even though they could. Instead, they
head, and feet, with back the slowest. respond from memory, and their reaction
The spatial framework pattern of reaction times fit the spatial framework pattern; that
times, derived from an analysis of percep- is, responses to head and feet were fastest,
tion and action, has been found in numerous followed by responses to front and back, and
variations (e.g., Bryant, Tversky & Franklin, then responses to left and right.
1992; Franklin, Tversky, & Coon, 1992; Tver- The fact that responding from perception
sky, Kim, & Cohen, 1999). Although the pat- and responding from memory were differ-
tern of data does not fit the analog view of ent demonstrates that imagery is not simply
mental imagery, it does not fit a preposi- internalized perception; rather, it is a con-
tional account either (e.g., Pylyshyn, 1981). struction, and sometimes a reconstruction
In particular, participants readily reorient of perception. The advantage of using spa-
under instructions that the observer turns tial frameworks in memory rather than the
to face a new object, but participants find it particular views of perception is generality.
difficult to reorient under instructions that The more abstract spatial framework rep-
the room rotates so that the observer is fac- resentation allows for easy computation of
ing a new object, even though formally, the many views as well as easy transformation
two kinds of instructions require identical between views.
transformations (Tversky et al., 1999). Under Conceptions of the space around the
normal conditions, people turn but environ- body do not depend on the physical situ-
ments do not, and those expectations affect ation per se. Instead, as for the space of the
updating mental worlds. body, conceptions of the space around the
body derive from and are biased by endur-
IMAGINARY ACTIONS IN ing characteristics of perception and action
IMAGINARY WORLDS of the human body in the world, the asym-
The first investigations of the space around metries of the body that affect how the
the body followed the example of story- body can act and perceive, and the asymme-
tellers and used prose to instill the worlds tries of the gravitational axis of the world,
and changes in it. Later studies used models, which also affect human action and per-
diagrams, and real spaces to instill the worlds ception. The next space to be considered,
(Bryant & Tversky, 1999; Bryant, Tversky, the space of navigation, is also a constructed
& Lanca, 2001). Models induce observers to mental space that is biased by perception
take the view of the central figure, a perspec- and action.
tive embedded in the imaginary world. Dia-
grams induce observers to take a view from
Space of Navigation
above, a perspective external to the imagi-
nary world (Bryant & Tversky, 1999). One The space we experience as we hike in the
set of studies showed differences between mountains or go from home to work or wan-
locating objects from perception and from der through a museum is the space of nav-
memory (Bryant, Tversky, &. Lanca, 2001). igation. It is too large to be perceived from
When a scene is responded to from per- a single place, so it must be constructed
ception, the pattern of reaction times con- from separate pieces. The pieces can be
forms to what might be termed the physical views from experience, they can be descrip-
transformation model. Specifically, objects tions we have heard or read, or they can
directly in front are fastest, those displaced be maps we have studied. How are the dif-
by ninety degrees next - head, feet, left, and ferent pieces and different modalities com-
right - and objects behind are slowest. In bined, the smaller spaces to form a large
this case, observers are turning to look at one? To put the pieces together requires
the probed locations to determine what is in a common reference frame and reference
the probed direction. However, once partic- objects. These allow the separate pieces to
ipants learn the environment, they cease to be integrated, scaled, arranged. But the very
206 BARBARA TVERSKY

factors that allow integration also produce for cities; they also appear in memory for
distortions. meaningless blobs, in children as well as
Consider first reference objects. Cities or adults. They reflect general perceptual orga-
landmarks or landmasses are located and nizing principles, with effects in memory for
remembered with respect to one another. geography as well as other domains, such
North America is north of South Amer- as graphs (e.g., Schiano & Tversky, 1992;
ica. Philadelphia is west of Rome. Group- Tversky & Schiano, 1989).
ing of landmarks follows the gestalt prin- Other systematic errors in memory for
ciple of grouping by proximity. However, the space of navigation help to character-
when people remember landmarks or land- ize how that space is constructed. In nat-
masses relative to one another, they remem- ural spaces, some elements are naturally
ber them as more aligned than they actu- more prominent than others. In geographic
ally were. As a consequence, a significant space, these are landmarks: the Golden Gate
majority of observers chose a map in which Bridge in San Francisco, Times Square in
North America is more direcdy north of Manhattan, the Eiffel Tower in Paris. Every
South America than the true map in which city, every town, every campus, has them.
South America barely overlaps North Amer- Our lives, too, have temporal landmarks:
ica (Tversky, 1981). Likewise, a significant family events, educational achievements,
majority of respondents think that Boston and the like. When asked to estimate dis-
is east of Rio de Janeiro, though it is not. tances from an ordinary building to a land-
Landmasses oriented east-west are similarly mark, people give smaller distances than the
distorted. A significant majority of observers distances from a landmark to an ordinary
chose a map in which Europe is located building (e.g., Sadalla, Burroughs, & Staplin,
direcdy west of the United States rather 1980). Thus, distances in the mind are not
than the true map, in which Europe is north symmetrical! These asymmetries hold for
of the United States. Likewise, a significant metaphoric spaces as well as physical ones.
majority think that Philadelphia is north of For example, people think a son is more
Rome, though it is not. This error occurs for
like his father than the father like his son
artificial maps as well as true ones, and it
(Tversky & Gati, 1978). Mental representa-
holds for blobs not viewed as maps. Align-
tions of abstract spaces, like mental repre-
ment, then, is an inevitable consequence of
sentations of real spaces, have landmarks and
grouping.
prototypes.
A similar error, termed rotation, arises When conceptual spaces get too large, the
when reference frames are used to orga- mind divides them into parts and subparts -
nize elements within them, another promi- so, too, for geographic spaces. Geographic
nent gestalt perceptual organizing principle. spaces can be subdivided and grouped, by
When students were asked to place a cutout geographic, political, and other categories.
of a map of South America in an NSEW People judge distances between entities
frame, they placed South America upright. within a group to be less than distances
As it is, South American looks tilted: as an between entities situated in different groups
elongated shape, it generates its own set of (e.g., Hirtle & Jonides, 1985). Perspective
axes, which are at odds with the geographic also affects distance judgments, whether
ones. Another example comes from the San imagined or real. Students imagining them-
Francisco Bay Area. The region runs west selves in San Francisco estimated the dis-
as it goes north. Yet, the overall concep- tance from San Francisco to Salt Lake City
tion is that the Bay Area runs from north to
to be larger than those imagining them-
south, so residents are surprised to learn that
selves in New York City. Conversely, stu-
Berkeley is west of Stanford, and Santa Cruz
dents imagining themselves in New York
is east of Stanford.
City estimated the distance from New York
Alignment and rotation are widespread; City to Pittsburgh to be greater than did stu-
they occur for landmasses, for roads, and dents imagining themselves in San Francisco
spatial cognition 207

(Holyoak & Mah, 1982). Of course, Steinberg sion of these issues, see Tversky, 2003,
had spoofed this distortion on the covers of 2005b).
the New Yorker long before. Both distortions
due to grouping and distortions d u e to per- TALKING ABOUT LARGE ENVIRONMENTS
spective have analogues in abstract thought, Humans are talkative beings, and undoubt-
for example in judgments about in-group edly one of the early topics of conversa-
and out-group members (e.g., Quattrone, tion in the evolution of language was talk-
1986). ing about space, telling others where to find
These are not the only systematic errors f o o d and shelter and where to avoid danger.
in spatial judgments. T h e errors discussed Space is usually described from a perspec-
so far could be called "perceptual errors," tive, as a perspective allows locating things
based on perceptual processing. H o w e v e r , relative to one another and a frame of ref-
there are errors f r o m action or potential erence. Spontaneous descriptions of large
action as well. For example, routes that have spaces take one of two perspectives or, inter-
more turns or landmarks are judged longer estingly, a combination of both (Taylor &
than routes with f e w e r turns or landmarks Tversky, 1992, 1996). In a route perspective,
(Sadalla & Staplin, 1980a, 1980b). Trying to speakers take the imagined point of view of a
put together all these systematic distortions traveler in an environment and describe the
would not likely yield a cognitive m a p that locations of landmarks relative to the chang-
is consistent and coherent. For this reason, a ing position of the traveler in terms of left,
better metaphor for mental conceptions of right, front, and back. In a survey perspec-
large spaces is a cognitive collage (Tversky, tive, speakers take a bird's-eye view of an
1993). Like collages, mental conceptions of environment, as if from a tree or mountain-
space are constructed f r o m fragments, f r o m top, and describe the locations of landmarks
different perspectives, and f r o m different relative to one another in terms of north,
modalities. south, east, and west. Each of these perspec-
tives is situated; that is, each is a familiar way
WHY ARE THERE SYSTEMATIC ERRORS? of viewing and interacting with an environ-
At first thought, it is mystifying that the ment.
mind distorts the world. Further thought Significantly, survey and route perspec-
reveals that there are good reasons that it tives have parallels in thinking about the
does so. Take, for example, the visual sys- landscape of time, yielding a bias familiar
tem. The world does not give us edges, to academicians. When events are far in the
comers, and contours, yet these are effi- future, we find room for them in the survey-
cient for identifying the objects of impor- like representation we use for the vast
tance. It is the nervous system that gives future, but when events are located in the
us edges, comers, and contours by sharp- near future, we think about them as routes
ening and leveling - distorting - incoming from now to then, from here to there. Sud-
information. For the space of navigation, denly, the time and effort to get to that
what is important is integrating differ- gorgeous spot remote in a mountain range
ent views and different modalities into looms large, especially against the other
wholes that have some coherence. Inte- time-consuming events already scheduled
grating requires both extracting the entities (e.g., Trope & Liberman, 2003). More ab-
that are important f r o m all the views and stract parallels to route and survey perspec-
modes and coordinating reference frames. tives abound. A good information-systems
This process has t w o consequences that
designer needs to plan the overall configu-
lead to distortions: focusing on some infor-
ration of computers, servers, printers, and
mation at the expense of other and inte-
at the same time, take into account the set
grating approximately or schematically, as
of possible procedures users are likely to
the exact information is often missing or
need (Nickerson, Tversky, Corter, Zahner,
unnecessary (for a more detailed discus-
& Rho, in press). Similarly, determining the
208 BARBARA TVERSKY

organization of a manufacturing plant must Situated Mental Spaces


include both the divisions of operation and T h r e e s p a c e s c r u c i a l to h u m a n interactions
the tasks to be performed. The survey per- in t h e w o r l d h a v e b e e n discussed: the space
spective consists of wholes, parts, and sub- of t h e b o d y , t h e s p a c e around the body,
parts, and the route perspective of sequences and t h e s p a c e of navigation. There are other
within. More on sequences when we get to spaces and spatial r e f e r e n c e frames, notably,
events. the s p a c e a r o u n d t h e j a w or the hand (e.g.,
Gross & Graziano, 1995). Each of these
Spatial Mental Transformations spaces s u b s e r v e s d i f f e r e n t perceptual-motor
interactions, a n d c o n c e p t i o n s of those spaces
In cognitive science talk, representations are d i f f e r from p h y s i c a l measurements of the
static mappings of elements and relations in spaces in c o n c o r d a n c e w i t h those interac-
the world to elements and relations in the
tions. For t h e s p a c e of t h e body, functional
mind. Representations, though conceived to
significance r a t h e r t h a n size determines ac-
be static, can be used in mental actions. They
cessibility of b o d y parts. For the space
can be mentally scanned (Kosslyn, 1980)
around t h e b o d y , t h e a x e s of the body form
or searched or, importantly, transformed.
a r e f e r e n c e frame, in t h r e e dimensions, and
Mental transformations of or in mental rep-
the accessibility of a x e s depends on their
resentations again have situated and embod-
significance in p e r c e p t i o n and action. The
ied origins (Shepard, 1984); that is, they
space of n a v i g a t i o n is p i e c e d together from
reflect and derive from common percep-
different e x p e r i e n c e s by selecting common
tual experience. There are many (e.g., Tver-
entities - l a n d m a r k s - a n d a unifying frame
sky, 2oo5d), but two seem to be primary:
of r e f e r e n c e . T h e u s e of reference land-
imagining changes in objects, most notably,
marks and r e f e r e n c e frames lead to sys-
changes in orientation or mental rotation
tematic errors in j u d g m e n t s of distance and
(Shepard & Cooper, 1982), and imagin-
direction. T h e s e s p a c e s are used for thinking
ing changes to one's own orientation in
about other things, t i m e , value, power, and
space (e.g., Bryant & Tversky, 1999; Parsons,
a m u l t i t u d e of o t h e r abstract concepts, as
1987; Wraga, Creem, & Proffitt, 2000; Zacks,
Mires, Tversky, & Hazeltine, 2000). These revealed in l a n g u a g e , gesture, and graphics.
two spatial mental transformations are inde- T h e use of s p a c e f o r general thought is espe-
pendent, producing different patterns of cially e v i d e n t in t h e spaces people create to
reaction times and using different brain serve as tools to a u g m e n t their own cogni-
pathways (e.g., Bryant & Tversky, 1999; Par- tion, spaces in t h e w o r l d that serve internal
sons, 1987; Wraga et al., 2000; Zacks et al., spaces in t h e m i n d . T h i s discussion will be
2000; Zacks, Vettel, & Michelon, 2003). In continued later, w h e n we get to diagrams.
the course of their daily lives, people nat- But first we m o v e f r o m space to time, to the
urally change orientations in space them- events that t a k e p l a c e in time.
selves and naturally observe other objects
changing orientation. These spatial trans-
formations can be performed mentally and Action
applied to representations of the concrete PACKAGING LIFE INTO EVENTS
and the abstract, providing a spatial basis T h e w o r l d is n e v e r static. To make sense of
for imagination. Mental spatial transforma- the constant f l u x , t h e m i n d captures change
tions underlie a range of mental feats: fig- in packets, c a l l e d " e v e n t s . " Clues to those
uring out a route from a map and enact- packets c o m e from t h e w a y s we talk about
ing a route while navigating; constructing them: go to w o r k , eat dinner, see a movie.
a laparoscopic surgical procedure; inventing Thus, the c o n t i n u o u s events that occur in
acrobatics on ice, sea, or land; or design- time are s e g m e n t e d a n d categorized, much
ing the next great museum (see Shepard, as the t r e m e n d o u s variety of things in the
1978). world are g r o u p e d a n d categorized (e g -
spatial cognition 209

Rosch, 1978). For ordinary everyday events, often a social process, which occurs from
like making a bed or doing the dishes, event observing others perform actions. H o w
packets are perceived as a sequence of hier- might this happen? Recall the play-by-play
archical action-object couplets, culminating descriptions of events like making a bed.
in achievements or accomplishments (for They describe the actions of the actors and
an analysis and review, see Zacks & Tver- are from the perspective of the actor, not
sky, 2001). When asked to give play-by-play the perspective of the person who is viewing
descriptions of films of everyday events like and describing the scene. Understanding the
making a bed or doing the dishes, at coarse actions and inferring the intentions of others
and fine levels, people provide a sequence may begin with taking their perspective.
of actions on objects that are hierarchically Neurophysiological evidence lends sup-
organized into goals and subgoals (Zacks, port to this possibility. There is ample evi-
Tversky, 8c Iyer, 2001). T h e same occurs dence that watching others' actions and
when people describe the units and sub- imagining one's own actions activate brain
units of generic events (Zacks et al., 2001) areas associated with action planning and
and of remembered events, like going to the performance (e.g., Cross, Hamilton, 8c
doctor (Bower, Black, & Turner, 1979). T h e Grafton, 2006; Decety & Grezes, 2006;
units of events are not actions, but action- Koski, Iacoboni, Dubeau, Woods, & Mazz-
object couplets; put is not a unit, but put iotta, 2003; Rizzolatti, Fadiga, Fogassi, &
on the bottom sheet, put the dishes in the sink, Gallese, 1999; Ruby & Decety, 2001). What
and put the clothes in the washing machine are is more, the motor activation appears to
units of making a bed, doing the dishes, and correspond to an anatomical mapping of
doing the laundry, respectively (e.g., Tver- the actor's body to the observer's body
sky, Zacks, 8c Hard, 2008). Put is not the (Aziz-Zadeh, Maeda, Zaidel, Mazziotta, &
same for put on the bottom sheet or put the Iacoboni, 2002). As Aziz-Zadeh et al. note,
clothes in the dryer. As sequences of action- merely observing action seems to induce
object couplets, events are inherently situ- motor resonance or motor simulation on
ated, not just in the objects they entail but the part of the observer, a possible mech-
also in their characteristic actors and set- anism for action understanding and learn-
tings. The bed is made in the bedroom and ing, one that effectively embodies observed
the dishes are done in the kitchen, by house- behavior. Actively describing or imitating
hold residents or by their helpers. Events are actions from the actor's perspective may
the stuff of our lives, and our understanding promote action learning and understanding
of them is situated in the appropriate set- by enhancing these natural processes.
tings, objects, and actors. Hierarchical orga-
nization of action serves as an action plan, a
mental simulation of the action that embod- Shaping Communication: Gestures
ies the action (cf. Gallese, 2005; Goldman, and Diagrams
2005).
Gestures: External Spaces

ACTION UNDERSTANDING AND GESTURE IS EFFECTIVE IN


PERSPECTIVE TAKING COMMUNICATION
Events performed by people, in contrast The hands serve not just to perform actions
to natural events like hurricanes or earth- but also to explain them. When people
quakes, are of special importance to peo- tell stories or explain things, they use their
ple. We need to understand the actions and hands, especially when they relate how
intentions of others to understand what they things are arranged in space or how to
are doing, to react to what they are doing, do something or how something works
and to perform those actions ourselves. (e.g., Goldin-Meadow, 2003; McNeill, 2005).
Learning the action-object hierarchies that Of course, people gesture for many other
constitute events performed by people is reasons as well. Gestures appear to have
210 BARBARA TVERSKY

benefits both for those making the gestures Participants w e r e asked to solve a series of
and for those watching them. For perform- spatial p r o b l e m s , s o m e easy and some dif-
ers of gestures, gestures serve to find words; ficult. A f t e r t h e y s o l v e d them, they were
when speakers sit on their hands, they are asked to e x p l a i n their solutions to a video
less fluent (Krauss, Chen, & Chawla, 1996; c a m e r a so that s o m e o n e watching the video
Krauss, Chen, & Gottesman, 2000). Chil- w o u l d u n d e r s t a n d t h e solution (Kessell &
dren blind from birth gesture when describ- T v e r s k y , 2005). In explaining their solu-
ing a spatial layout, suggesting that gestures tions to t h e p r o b l e m s , nearly all participants
help to organize thought (Iverson & Goldin- gestured f o r all p r o b l e m s . Their gestures
Meadow, 1997). For viewers of gestures, served to r e p r e s e n t t h e problem, by using
gestures clarify meanings and facilitate iconic gestures reflecting the spatial layout,
comprehension (e.g., Alibali, Flevares, & and their gestures s e r v e d to demonstrate the
Goldin-Meadow, 1997; Goldin-Meadow, solutions to t h e p r o b l e m s - again, typically
2003; Kelly & Church, 1998; McNeill, iconic gestures s h o w i n g the transformations
Cassell, & McCullough, 1994; Valenzeno, n e e d e d f o r solution.
Alibali, & Klatzky, 2003). These many roles M o r e surprising w a s t h e finding that alone
of gestures are a testament to the varieties of in a r o o m , n o t speaking, many participants
embodied cognition in thinking, in express- gestured w h e n t r y i n g to solve certain prob-
ing thought, and in understanding thought. lems. O n l y t w o of t h e problems elicited
gestures in m o s t participants. Those that
GESTURES IN SPATIAL DESCRIPTIONS elicited gestures w e r e the problems with
Evidence for how gestures organize and high d e m a n d s on spatial working memory,
express thought comes firom a study in keeping track of m a n y rungs on a ladder or
which participants were asked to describe t h e locations a n d properties of six glasses.
environments they had learned from maps In these cases, t h e gestures represented the
(Emmorey, Tversky, & Taylor, 2000), mod- problems; t h e y c o r r e s p o n d e d to the spatial
eled on the previous work of Taylor and layouts, vertical f o r t h e ladder and horizon-
Tversky (1996) As before, some environ- tal f o r t h e glasses, w i t h t h e appropriate num-
ments elicited primarily route descriptions; bers f o r each. In a second parallel study,
others, primarily survey descriptions; and other participants w e r e given paper and
others, mixed descriptions. The gestures pencil w h e n solving t h e problems. These
corresponded to the description perspec- participants u s e d p a p e r and pencil for
tive, suggesting that both embodied ges- exactly t h e s a m e p r o b l e m s that had elicited
tures and symbolic language reflected the gestures in participants without paper and
way speakers thought about the environ- pencil. T o g e t h e r , t h e findings suggest that
ments. Frequendy, speakers used series of gestures w e r e u s e d to off-load and orga-
related gestures to create models of the envi- nize spatial w o r k i n g m e m o r y when internal
ronments. They virtually sketched the envi- capacity w a s t a x e d . Using paper to off-load
ronments in the air, anchoring them with and organize w o r k i n g m e m o r y makes sense,
some places and indicating locations of other it is p e r m a n e n t a n d can be referred to during
places relative to the anchors. The set of p r o b l e m solving. Using gestures to off-load
gestures, sometimes as long as fifteen ges- working m e m o r y is m o r e puzzling, as ges-
tures in a row, formed a coherent inter- tures are fleeting. W h y might gestures facil-
related sequence. itate w o r k i n g m e m o r y ?
O n e possible explanation for why ges-
GESTURES PLACE THINGS IN MEMORY tures are u s e d to o f f - l o a d working mem-
Remarkably, gestures occur in the absence ory is that p e o p l e r e m e m b e r where they
of speech and in the absence of communica- put things. Or t h e y r e m e m b e r better if they
tion, strong evidence that they serve thought put t h e things s o m e w h e r e than if someone
by embodying it. One activity people engage else did. P e o p l e r e m e m b e r routes when they
in throughout their lives is solving problems. navigate b e t t e r than w h e n they are taken
spatial cognition 211

somewhere. They remember actions better parallel the simplifications of internal repre-
if they do them themselves (Engelkamp, sentations of space. As noted, that may be
1998). The physical acts of placing or nav- one reason why they work; they include the
igating appear to be intimately involved information important to people and cap-
in spatial memory. Gesturing, putting, and ture the way people think. That information
placing, then, may invoke the same cogni- in maps is frequently omitted and distorted
tive networks in the service of conceptual often does not matter, as the environment
memory. supplements and disambiguates it.
Thinking can be regarded as action, inter- Given that people think about abstract
nalized. Indeed, we talk about thinking as concepts spatially, as evident in language
actions: we frame our thoughts, we pull like getting close to someone, feeling upbeat,
ideas together or take them apart; we buy arriving at an insight, entering a new field,
ideas, we sell them, we build one idea on wrapping one's head around an idea, it seems
another. This simple example, placing imag- surprising that external representations for
inary objects to support memory of them, abstract ideas were not common until the
shows how thinking can involve the body late eighteenth century (e.g., Beniger &
acting in the world. Robyn, 1978; Carswell & Wickens, 1988;
Tufte, 1983). Like maps, visualizations of the
abstract use elements and spatial relations
Diagrams: External Spaces among them, but they use them metaphori-
It seems that humans have always cre- cally to represent abstract elements and rela-
ated artifacts. It is well known that many tions. Part of their success is that they rely
of these were intended to increase physi- on human facility in understanding spatial
cal well-being, such as tools for harvesting information and making spatial inferences
and preparing food. But many are intended (e.g., Larkin & Simon, 1987; Tversky, 1993).
to increase mental well-being, such as to
augment memory and facilitate informa- NATURAL CORRESPONDENCES
tion processing. Trail markers, tallies, pic- Spatial relations in graphics are readily pro-
tographs, and maps are some of the cognitive duced and understood, even by preschool
took created by cultures all over the globe. children. In one experiment, preschoolers,
Often people do not have to create artifacts children, and adults were asked to arrange
to augment cognition; they just co-opt what stickers on paper to express various spatial,
is there. Fingers get used for counting, and temporal, quantitative, and preference con-
hands and feet for measuring. cepts, for example, a TV show they loved,
Maps serve as a paradigm for a cre- a TV show they were indifferent to, and a
ated cognitive tool. Maps have dozens of TV show they disliked (Tversky, Kugelmass,
uses, not just to guide navigation but also & Winter, 1991). Most of the youngest chil-
to proclaim territory or to promote infer- dren arranged the stickers on a line, show-
ences about flows of populations, weather, ing that they saw a dimension underlying
or pollen. They use elements and spatial the elements, and ordered them accordingly.
relations among elements on stone, clay, For preference and quantity, they mapped
sand, or paper to convey elements and spa- more to up or left or right but almost never
tial relations in a larger world. But they do to down. That more goes up goes along
not just shrink the world, they omit much with language and reflects the asymmetry of
of the world and distort the world. Paths that axis in the world. Similarly, that more
and landmarks are included that would not equally goes left and right reflects the sym-
be visible at the scale of the map. Paths metry of the horizontal axis. Preteen chil-
are straightened, turns are schematized to dren also represented interval and ordinal
ninety degrees, distances are approximate. relations among elements. These results -
The reader will observe that these simplifi- from children from a variety of language cul-
cations to external representations of space tures - suggest that the correspondences of
BARBARA TVERSKY
212

proximity and direction in an abstract space USING MENTAL MAPS AND SKETCH MAPS
to proximity and direction on paper are nat- When asked to produce a map to aid a
ural and spontaneous. traveler to get f r o m one place to another,
The use of elements on paper to represent people usually produce rudimentary maps
elements in the world or the mind also seems (e.g., Tversky & Lee, 1998, 1999). Most of
to have natural correspondences. Early writ- the detail is left out, and what is left in,
ten languages provide examples, as they typically, the paths that form the route, is
depicted meanings rather than recorded lan- distorted. Intersections are usually drawn
guage as spoken (e.g., Gelb, 1963). Wherever at right angles and distances are approxi-
possible, resemblance was used, but many mate. Like mental maps of environments,
concepts are difficult to depict. Then, figures sketch maps are distorted, and they are dis-
of depictions, analogous to figures of speech, torted in similar ways. Nevertheless, both
synecdoche (association represents element; mental maps and sketch maps serve their
e.g., scales for scales of justice) or metonymy purpose; they help people find their des-
(part of element represents element; e.g., tinations. H o w is that? Like mental maps,
horns of a sheep) are used (e.g., Tversky, sketch maps are situated, used in context,
1995, 2001,2005a). Diagrams and interfaces in environments, and the environments dis-
use similar techniques; think of icons in air- ambiguate and correct (Tversky, 2003). If a
port signs or on computers. Another readily turn is eighty or one hundred degrees instead
comprehended kind of element is common of ninety, the traveler will turn the way
in diagrams, schematic geometric forms like the road goes. T h e traveler will turn upon
lines, arrows, and blobs (Tversky, Zacks, reaching the next landmark, whatever the
Lee, & Heiser, 2000). In quantitative graphs, distance. All that is needed from the map
for example, lines connect; they show that is where to turn and which way, and in
two (or more) variables share an underlying fact, that is the information included in ver-
attribute but have different values. Bars con- bal directions. Intersections and turns can
tain and separate. The justification for using be checked against the world. Actual nav-
bars or lines relies on assumptions about the igation is even m o r e deeply situated. After
underlying data, lines for interval data and checking the landmarks and turns of either
bars for categorical data. People's interpreta- mental or paper maps against the world, suc-
tion and production of bars and lines appears cessful navigation depends on coordinating
to derive from the natural graphic mean- eye and body to make the turns correctly.
ings of bars and lines. People, then, should
Although these schematic elements -
readily interpret lines as trends and bars as
lines, arrows, blobs - have meanings that are
discrete comparisons, and they do. What is
readily interpreted in context, they have lan-
more, they produce lines for trends and bars
guagelike properties. Like words, they are
for discrete comparisons. For both interpre-
categorical and can be combined to create
tation and production, the graphic forms are
many possible graphics, for example, route
stronger than the actual underlying dimen-
maps and networks. Context disambiguates
sions (Zacks & Tversky, 1999). Arrows are
asymmetrical lines and suggest asymmetri- them - a line in a graph has a different mean-
cal relations. Arrows are frequently added to ing from a Une in a map. Context is neces-
diagrams to suggest a variety of meanings: sary to disambiguate the words that parallel
order, cause, motion, outcome, and more. these forms. An occupational line and a train
When asked to interpret diagrams that do line are not likely to be confused in context,
not have arrows of mechanical systems like nor are mathematical and romantic relation-
pumps and brakes, people provide structural ships. Yet, unlike words, the meanings ot
descriptions of the spatial arrangement of these forms are readily available.
the parts. When asked to describe diagrams External spaces serve cognition, both
with arrows, people provide step-by-step individual and group, in a multitude of ways-
causal relations (Heiser & Tversky, 2006). They off-load the contents of memory, free-
ing working m e m o r y to manipulate extern
spatialcognition217

tokens instead of internal ones. They relieve Some of the discussion has been reviewed else-
working memory further by allowing exter- where, and parts were reworked from Tversky
nalization of intermediate products of men- (2005c).
tal manipulations. They promote organiza-
tion and reorganization of the contents of References
memory. They can be viewed and manipu-
lated by groups, thereby ensuring common Alibali, M. W., Flevares, L., & Goldin-Meadow,
understanding and facilitating collaboration. S. (1997). Assessing knowledge conveyed in
Because they are based on natural cogni- gesture: Do teachers have the upper hand?
tive correspondences, external spaces both Journal of Educational Psychology, 8 9 , 1 8 3 - 1 9 3 .
reflect and support human thought, con- Andersen, E. S. (1978). Lexical universals ofbody-
crete and abstract. part terminology. In J. H. Greenberg (Ed.),
Universals of human language (pp. 335-368).
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Aziz-Zadeh, L., Maeda, F., Zaidel, E., Mazziotta,
Situated Thought
J., & Iacoboni, M. (2002). Lateralization in
motor facilitation during action observation:
We cannot get out of our bodies and we can- A TMS study. Experimental Brain Research,
not get out of the world. We can do so only 144,127-131.
in our imaginations, but as we have seen, the Beniger, J. R., 8l Robyn, D. L. (1978). Quanti-
imagination is constrained by our bodies and tative graphics in statistics. American Statisti-
the world. Spatial thinking comes from and cian, 32,1—11.
is shaped by perceiving the world and acting Bower, G. H., Black, J. B., & Turner, T. J. (1979).
in it, be it through learning or through evo- Scripts in memory for text. Cognitive Psychol-
lution. The embodied and situated cognitive ogy, 1 1 , 1 7 9 - 2 2 0 .

structures and biases of thought about space Brown, C. H. (1976). General principles of
human anatomical partonomy and specula-
and about action limit and bias abstract
tions on the growth of partonomic nomen-
thought as well. Thought is grounded in the clature. American Ethnologist, 3,400-424.
world and in the body. Our bodies not only Bryant, D. J., 8c Tversky, B. (1999). Mental rep-
sense but also participate in thought; we use resentations of spatial relations from diagrams
our bodies to locate, to refer, to measure, to and models. Journal of Experimental Psychol-
arrange and rearrange, to transform. Imag- ogy: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 25, 137-
ination is not limited by the body and the 156.
world; it is enabled by the body and the Bryant, D. J., Tversky, B., 8c Franklin, N. (1992).
world. The representations and processes Internal and external spatial frameworks for
used to understand the spatial world and act representing described scenes. Journal of Mem-
in it are those that allow invention, creativ- ory and Language, 31, 74-98.
Bryant, D. J., Tversky, B., 8c Lanca, M. (2001).
ity, and discovery.
Retrieving spatial relations from observation
and memory. In E. van der Zee St U. Nikanne
(Eds.), Conceptual structure and its interfaces
Acknowledgments with other modules of representation (pp. 116-
139). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
I am grateful to the insightful comments of Pas- Carswell, C. M., 8c Wickens, C. D. (1988). Com-
cale Michelon on an earlier draft of this chapter. parative graphics: History and applications of
Preparation of this chapter and/or of some of the perceptual integrality theory and the proximity
research reported were supported by the follow- compatibility hypothesis (Tech. Rep.). Urbana:
ing grants: NSF BNS 8002012; AFOSR 89-0076; Institute of Aviation, University of Illinois at
the Edinburgh-Stanford Link through the Cen- Urbana-Champaign.
ter for the Study of Language and Information Chatterjee, S. H., Freyd, J. J., 8c Shiffrar, M.
at Stanford University; Office of Naval Research (1996). Configural processing in the percep-
Grants NOOO14-PP-1-O649, N000140110717, and tion of apparent biological motion. Journal
N000140210534, NSF REC-0440103; and the Stan- of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception
ford Regional Visualization and Analysis Center. and Performance, 22, 916-929.
2o6 barbara tvf.rsky

Clark, H. H. (1973). Space, time, semantics, and Hoffman, D. D., & Richards, W. A. (1984). Parts
the child. In T. E. Moore (Ed.), Cognitive of recognition. Cognition, 18, 65-96.
development and the acquisition of language Holyoak, K. J., & Mah, W. A. (1982). Cognitive
(pp. 27-63). New York: Academic Press. reference points in judgements of symbolic
Cross, E. S., Hamilton, A. F., & Grafton, S. T. magnitude. Cognitive Psychology, 14,328-352.
(2006). Building a motor simulation de novo: Iverson, J. ( & Goldin-Meadow, S. (1997). What's
Observation of dance by dancers. Neuroimage, communication got to do with it? Gesture in
children blind from birth. Developmental Psy-
Decety, J., & Grazes, J. (2006). The power of chology, 33, 453-467.
simulation: Imagining one's own and other's Kellogg, R. (1969). Analyzing children's art. Palo
behavior. Brain Research, 1079,4-14. Alto, C A : National Press.
Emmorey, K, Tversky, B., & Taylor, H. A. Kelly, S. D., & Church, B. (1998). A com-
(2000). Using space to describe space: Perspec- parison between children's and adults' abil-
tive in speech, sign, and gesture. Journal of ity to detect conceptual information con-
Spatial Cognition and Computation, 2,157-180. veyed through representational gestures.
Engelkamp, J. (1998). Memory for actions. Hove, Child Development, 69, 85-93.
UK: Psychology Press. Kessell, A., & Tversky, B. (2005). Gestures for
Franklin, N., & Tversky, B. (1990). Searching thinking and explaining. In B. G. Bara, L. W.
imagined environments. Journal of Experimen- Barsalou, 8l M. Bucciarelli (Eds.), Proceedings
tal Psychology: General, 119, 63-76. of the Cognitive Science Society Meetings (p.
Franklin, N., Tversky, B., & Coon, V. (1992). 2498). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Switching points of view in spatial mental Koski, L., Iacoboni, M., Dubeau, M.-C., Woods,
models acquired from text. Memory and Cog- R. P., & Mazziotta, J. C. (2003). Modula-
nition, 20, 507-518. tion of cortical activity during different imi-
Gallese, V. (2005). "Being like me": Self-other tative behaviours. Journal of Neurophysiology,
identity, mirror neurons, and empathy. In S. 89, 460-471.
Hurley & N. Chater (Eds.), Perspectives on imi- Kosslyn, S. M. (1980). Image and mind. Cam-
tation: From neuroscience to social science (Vol. bridge: Harvard University Press.
1, pp. 108-118). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Krauss, R. M., Chen, Y., & Chawla, P. (1996).
Gelb, I. (1963). A study of writing (2nd ed.). Nonverbal behavior and nonverbal commu-
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. nication: What do conversational hand ges-
Goldin-Meadow, S. (2003). Hearing gesture: How tures tell us? In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances
our hands help us think. Cambridge, MA: Bel- in experimental social psychology (pp. 389-450).
knap Press. San Diego, C A : Academic Press.
Goldman, A. (2005). Imitation, mindreading, and Krauss, R. M., Chen, Y., 8c Gottesman, R. (2000).
simulation. In S. Hurley & N. Chater (Eds.), Lexical gestures and lexical access: A process
Perspectives on imitation: From neuroscience to model. In D. McNeill (Ed.), Language and
social science (Vol. 2, pp. 79-93). Cambridge, gesture (pp. 261-284). Cambridge: Cambridge
MA: MIT Press. University Press.
Goodnow, J. (1977). Children's drawing. London: Lakoff, G., 8c Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors we
Open Books. live by. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Gross, C. G., & Graziano, M, S. A. (1995). Multi- Larkin, J. H., 8c Simon, H. A. (1987). Why a
ple representations of space in the brain. Neu- diagram is (sometimes) worth ten thousand
mscientist, 1,43-50. words. Cognitive Science, 11, 65-99.
Hegarty, M., Carpenter, P. A., & Just, M. A. McNeill, D. (2005). Gesture and thought. Chicago:
(1990). Diagrams in the comprehension of sci- University of Chicago Press.
entific text. In R. Barr, M. L. Kamil, P. Mosen- McNeill, D., Cassell, J., 8c McCullough, K.
thal, & P. D. Pearson (Eds.), Handbook of read- E. (1994). Communicative effects of speech-
ing research. New York: Longman. mismatched gestures. Research on Language
Heiser, J., & Tversky, B. (2006). Arrows in com- and Social Interaction, 27, 223-237.
prehending and producing mechanical dia- Morrison, J. B., & Tversky, B. (2005). Bodies and
grams. Cognitive Science, 30, 581-592. their parts. Memory and Cognition, 33, 696-
Hirtle, S., & Jonides, J. (1985). Hierarchies in 7°9-
cognitive maps. Memory and Cognition, 13,
Nickerson, J., Tversky, B., Corter, J., Zahner,
208-217.
D., 8c Rho, Y.-J. (in press). Diagrams as a
spatial cognition 215

tool in the design of information systems. In Shepard, R. N. (1984). Ecological constraints on


J. S. Gero & A. Goel (Eds.), Design Comput- internal representations: Resonant kinematics
ingand Cognition '08. Dordrecht, T h e Nether- of perceiving, imagining, thinking, and dream-
lands: Springer. ing. Psychological Review, 91,417-447.
Parsons, L. M. (1987). Imagined spatial transfor- Shepard, R. N., & Cooper, L. (1982). Mental
mation of one's body. Journal of Experimental images and their transformation. Cambridge,
Psychology: General, 116,172-191. MA: MIT Press.
Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1981) The imagery debate: Ana- Shepard, R. N., 8c Podgomy, P. (1978). Cognitive
logue media versus tacit knowledge. Psycho- processes that resemble perceptual processes.
logical Review, 88,16-45. In W. K. Estes (Ed.), Handbook of learning
Quattrone, G. A. (1986). On the perception of a and cognitive processes (Vol. 5, pp. 189-237).
group's variability. In S. Worchel 8c W. Austin Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
(Eds.), The psychology of intergroup relations Shiffrar, M., 8c Freyd, J. J. (1993). Timing and
(pp. 25-48). New York: Nelson-Hall. apparent motion path choice with human
Reed, C. L. (2002). Body schemas. In A. Meltzoff body photographs. Psychological Science, 4,
8c W. Prinz (Eds.), The imitative mind (pp. 379-384.
233-243). Cambridge: Cambridge University Talmy, L. (1983). How language structures space.
Press. In H. L. Pick, Jr. 8c L. P. Acredolo (Eds.),
Reed, C. L., 8c Farah, M. J. (1995). The psy- Spatial orientation: Theory, research, and appli-
chological reality of the body schema: A test cation (pp. 225-282). New York: Plenum Press.
with normal participants. Journal of Experi- Taylor, H. A., 8c Tversky, B. (1992). Descriptions
mental Psychology: Human Perception and Per- and depictions of environments. Memory and
formance, 21, 334-343. Cognition, 20,483-496.
Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., 8c Gallese, Taylor, H. A., 8c Tversky, B. (1996). Perspective
V. (1999). Resonance behaviors and mirror in spatial descriptions. Journal of Memory and
neurons. Archives Italiennes de Biologie, 137, Language, 35, 371-391.
85-100. Trope, Y., 8c Liberman, N. (2003). Temporal con-
Rock, I. (1973). Orientation and form. N e w York: strual. Psychological Review, no, 403-421.
Academic Press. Tufte, E. R. (1983). The visual display of quan-
Rosch, E. (1978). Principles of categorization. titative information. Cheshire, CT: Graphics
In E. Rosch & B. B. Lloyd (Eds.), Cognition Press.
and categorization (pp. 27-48). Hillsdale, NJ: Tversky, B. (1981). Distortions in memory for
Lawrence Erlbaum. maps. Cognitive Psychology, 13,407-433.
Ruby, P., 8c Decety, J. (2001). Effect of subjec- Tversky, B. (1989). Parts, partonomies, and tax-
tive perspective taking during simulation of onomies. Developmental Psychology, 25, 983-
action: A PET investigation of agency. Nature 995-
Neuroscience, 4, 546-550. Tversky, B. (1993). Cognitive maps, cognitive col-
Sadalla, E. K., Burroughs, W. J., 8c Staplin, L. I. lages, and spatial mental models. In A. U.
(1980). Reference points in spatial cognition. Frank 8c I. Campari (Eds.), Spatial information
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human theory: A theoretical basis for GIS (pp. 14-24).
Learning and Memory, 5,516-528. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
Sadalla, E. K., 8c Staplin, L. J. (1980a). An infor- Tversky, B. (1995). Cognitive origins of graphic
mation storage model for distance cognition. conventions. In F. T. Marchese (Ed.), Under-
Environment and Behavior, 12, 183-193. standing images (pp. 29-53). New York:
Sadalla, E. K., 8c Staplin, L. J. (1980b). The per- Springer-Verlag.
ception of traversed distance: Intersections. Tversky, B. (2000). Remembering space. In E.
Environment and Behavior, 12,167-182. Tulving 8c F. I. M. Craik (Eds.), Handbook
Schiano, D., 8c Tversky, B. (1992). Structure and of memory (pp. 363-378). New York: Oxford
strategy in viewing simple graphs. Memory and University Press.
Cognition, 20,12-20. Tversky, B. (2001). Spatial schemas in depic-
Shepard, R. N. (1978). Externalization of mental tions. In M. Gattis (Ed.), Spatial schemas and
images and the act of creation. In B. S. Rand- abstract thought (pp. 79-111). Cambridge, MA:
hawa 8c B. F. Coffman (Eds.), Visual learn- MIT Press.
ing, thinking, and communication (pp. 133-189). Tversky, B. (2003). Navigating by mind and by
London: Academic Press. body. In C. Freksa, W. Brauer, C. Habel, 8c K.
BARBARA TVERSKY
zi6

F. Wender (Eds ), Spatial cognition III: Routes Prinz (Eds.), The imitative mind: Development
and navigation, human memory and learning, evolution and brain bases (pp. 221-232). Cam-
spatial representation and spatial reasoning (pp. bridge: Cambridge University Press.
1-10). Berlin: Springer-Verlag. Tversky, B., 8c Schiano, D. (1989). Perceptual and
Tvereky, B. (2005a). Functional significance of conceptual factors in distortions in memory
visuospatial representations. In P. Shah & for maps and graphs. Journal of Experimental
A. Miyake (Eds.), Handbook of higher-level Psychology: General, 118, 387-398.
visuospatial thinking. Cambridge: Cambridge Tversky, B., Zacks, J. M., 8c Hard, B. M.
University Press. (2008). The structure of experience. In T.
Tversky, B. (2005b). How to get around by mind Shipley & J. M. Zacks (Eds.), Understanding
and body: Spatial thought, spatial action. In events (pp. 436-464). Oxford: Oxford Univer-
A. Zilhao (Ed.), Cognition, evolution, and ratio- sity Press.
nality: A cognitive science for the twenty-first cen- Tversky, B., Zacks, J., Lee, P. U., & Heiser, J.
tury. London: Roudedge. (2000). Lines, blobs, crosses, and arrows: Dia-
Tversky, B. (2005c). La cognition spatiale: grammatic communication with schematic
Incarnee et desincarn£e. In A. Berthoz & R. figures. In M. Anderson, P. Cheng, 8c V.
Recht (Eds.), Les espaces de I'homme (pp. 161— Haarslev (Eds.), Theory and application of
184). Paris: Odile Jacob. diagrams (pp. 221-230). Berlin: Springer-
Tversky, B. (2005d). Visuospatial reasoning. In Verlag.
K. Holyoak & R. Morrison (Eds.), Handbook Tversky, B., Zacks, J. M., Morrison, J. B., 8c Hard,
of reasoning (pp. 209-249). Cambridge: Cam- B. M. (in press). Talking about events. In E.
bridge University Press. Pederson, J. Bohnemeyer, 8c R. Tomlin (Eds.),
Tversky, B., & Gati, I. (1978). Studies of simi- Event representation. Cambridge: Cambridge
larity. In E. Rosch & B. Lloyd (Eds.), Cogni- University Press.
tion and categorization (pp. 79-98). New York: Valenzeno, L., Alibali, M. W., 8c Klatzky, R.
Wiley. (2003). Teachers' gestures facilitate students'
Tversky, B., & Hemenway, K. (1983). Categories learning: A lesson in symmetry. Contemporary
of scenes. Cognitive Psychology, 15,121-149. Educational Psychology, 28,187-204.
Tversky, B., & Hemenway, K. (1984). Objects, Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., 8c Rosch, E.
parts, and categories. Journal of Experimental (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science
Psychology: General, 113,169-193. and human experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Tversky, B., Kim, J., 81 Cohen, A. (1999). Men- Press.
tal models of spatial relations and transforma- Wraga, M., Creem, S. H., 8c Proffitt, D. R. (2000).
tions from language. In C. Habel 8c G. Rick- Updating displays after imagined object and
heit (Eds.), Mental models in discourse process- viewer rotations. Journal of Experimental Psy-
ing and reasoning (pp. 239-258). Amsterdam: chology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 26,
North-Holland. 151-168.
Tversky, B., Kugelmass, S., 8c Winter, A. (1991). Zacks, J. M., Mires, J., Tversky, B., 8c Hazeltine,
Cross-cultural and developmental trends in E. (2000). Mental spatial transformations of
graphic productions. Cognitive Psychology, 23, objects and perspective. Spatial Cognition and
5*5-557- Computation, 2, 315-332.
Tversky, B., 8c Lee, P. U. (1998). How space struc- Zacks, J., 8c Tversky, B. (1999). Bars and lines: A
tures language. In C. Freksa, C. Habel, & K. F. study of graphic communication. Memory and
Wender (Eds.), Spatial cognition: An interdisci- Cognition, 27,1073—1079.
plinary approach to representation and process- Zacks, J. M., & Tversky, B. (2001). Event struc-
ing of spatial knowledge (pp. 157-175). Berlin: ture in perception and conception. Psycholog-
Springer-Verlag. ical Bulletin, 127, 3-21.
Tversky, B., 8c Lee, P. U. (1999). Pictorial and ver- Zacks, J., Tversky, B., 8c Iyer, G. (2001). Perceiv-
bal tools for conveying routes. In C. Freksa 8c ing, remembering, and communicating struc-
D. M. Mark (Eds.), Spatial information theory: ture in events. Journal of Experimental Psychol-
Cognitive and computational foundations of geo- ogy: General, 130, 29-58.
graphic information science (pp. 51-64). Berlin: Zacks, J. M., Vettel, J. M., 8c Michelon, P. (2003)-
Springer-Verlag. Imagined viewer and object rotations dissoci-
Tversky, B., Morrison, J. B., 8c Zacks, J. (2002). ated with event-related fMRI. Journal of Cog-
On bodies and events. In A. Meltzoff 8c W. nitive Neuroscience, 1 5 , 1 0 0 2 - 1 0 1 8 .
C H A P T E R 13

Remembering

John Sutton

i. Introduction: T h e Interdisciplinary Critics of classical cognitive science often


Framework painted mainstream theories of memory as
rigidly mechanistic and individualist, offer-
The case of remembering poses a partic- ing disparate phenomenological, Wittgen-
ular challenge to theories of situated cog- steinian, or direct realist alternatives (Ben-
nition, and its successful treatment within Zeev, 1986; Bursen, 1978; Casey, 1987; Krell,
this framework will require a more dramatic 1990; Malcolm, 1977; Sanders, 1985; Stem,
integration of levels, fields, and methods 1991; ter Hark, 1995; Turvey & Shaw,
than has yet been achieved. The challenge
1979; Wilcox & Katz, 1981). Although the
arises from the fact that memory often takes
more recent work on memory in situ-
us out of the current situation: in remember-
ated cognition and related (dynamical, dis-
ing episodes or experiences in my personal
tributed, enactive, and embodied) traditions
past, for example, I am mentally transported
away from the social and physical setting in described in this chapter has drawn sub-
which I am currendy embedded. Our ability stantially on these positive alternatives, the
to make psychological contact with events oppositional nature of the earlier debates
and experiences in the past was one motiva- has dissipated somewhat. Indeed the mod-
tion, in classical cognitive science and cogni- em history of memory research across the
tive psychology, for postulating inner mental disciplines undermines that easy stereo-
«presentations to hold information across type of the cognitive sciences as mono-
the temporal gap. Theorists of situated cog- lithically logicist and internalist. Not only
•"tion thus have to show how such an appar- had key precursors of situated cognition
ently representation-hungry and decoupled long been points of reference in particu-
nigh-level cognitive process may nonethe- lar subdomains of memory theory, such
less be fruitfully understood as embodied, as the developmental psychology of auto-
eontextualized, and distributed (cf. Clark, biographical memory (Vygotsky, 1930/1978);
2005a).
through independent internal movements
within computational, cognitive, and social
217
218 john sutton

psychology alike over twenty-five years or tutional, and so on - shape, constrain, and
more, situated or ecological approaches to enable practices and activities of remem-
memory have come themselves to occupy bering. The case of memory should ide-
the mainstream.1 Although their integra- ally fit David Kirsh's (2006) description of
tion with traditional laboratory methods the general study of distributed cognition
did not always come easily, the pluralism as "the study of the variety and subtlety
of contemporary memory studies is rea- of coordination... how the elements and
sonably happy; ambitious recent syntheses components in a distributed system - peo-
deliberately triangulate robust data and con- ple, tools, forms, equipment, maps and less
straints from distinct sources, incorporating obvious resources - can be coordinated well
as appropriate evidence from phenomenol- enough to allow the system to accomplish
ogy; from neuroimaging and neuropsychol- its tasks" (p. 258; cf. Wilson & Clark, this
ogy; and from cognitive, affective, develop- volume). 2
mental, social, and personality psychology
all at once (Conway & Pleydell-Pearce, 2000;
Siegel, 2001; Welzer & Markowitsch, 2005). 2. Remembering as Constructive
The sciences of memory have occasion- Activity and Interpersonal Skill
ally seemed somewhat isolated from broader
shifts in cognitive science. But their more Remembering is an activity that takes place
direct integration with the ideas discussed in and over time. Neither the form of that
throughout this volume is now leading activity nor the detailed nature of what is
both to reevaluations of the relevance of remembered is straightforwardly or mono-
other harbingers of the modem construc- causally determined by any internally stored
tivist psychological and social sciences of information. Inner memory traces - what-
memory, such as Bartlett (1932) and Halb- ever they may be — are merely potential
wachs (1925/1992,1950/1980), and to explic- contributors to recollection, conspiring with
itly situated or distributed theories that see current cues in rich contexts (Schacter, 1996,
the vehicles of representation in memory, pp. 56-71; Tulving, 1983, pp. 12-14). But a
as well as the processes of remembering, as focus on this occurrent activity, which is
potentially spreading across world and body always situated in a range of contexts, does
as well as the brain (Clancey, 1997, 1999; not on its own ground a situated approach
Donald, 1991; Rowlands, 1999; Sutton, 2003, to memory. Individualists, too, can acknowl-
2004; Tribble, 2005; Wilson, 2004,2005). This edge the existence of a range of contexts; so
chapter offers a synoptic overview of sit- talk of (for example) the external or cultural
uated work on memory and remembering, or social context of remembering is not suf-
skating fast and light over vast and dis- ficient to give us a substantial situated view.
parate literatures to sketch a positive syn- Remembering itself, after all, might still be
thesis of the field. It covers, in turn, rel- firmly contained within the bounds of the
evant movements in cognitive psychology skull. On stronger situated theories, presum-
(section 2), developmental psychology (sec- ably, our understanding of the memory to
tion 3), the social sciences and social phi- which modifiers like extended or distributed
losophy (section 4), and distributed cogni- are applied should itself be significanuy
tion (section 5). Conceptual tools from all revised (Wertsch, 1999). This means, fur-
of these fields are required to address the ther, that no neat division of labor between
challenge of situating memory. The aim is an the cognitive and the social sciences of mem-
account of memory in general, or of the vari- ory can be maintained, because the domain
eties and forms of memory in general, which is not neatly sliced into distinct psychologi-
can then be applied to diverse case stud- cal and public aspects that may or may not
ies across the disciplines to suggest just how interact (Sutton, 2004).
in practice various coordinated contexts - In "A Theory of Remembering," the cen-
neural, bodily, affective, technological, insti- tral chapter of his great work Remembering
remembering 219

A Study in Experimental and Social Psychol- are independent from one another, stored
ogy, Bartlett (1932) wrote: at separate locations in some memory sys-
tem. It is this localist picture of memory
Suppose I am making a stroke in a quick storage, which allows for no integration of
game, such as tennis or cricket.... When enduring data with ongoing processing, that
I make the stroke I do not, as a matter makes it difficult to update relevant back-
of fact, produce something absolutely new,
ground knowledge without explicit search
and I never merely repeat something old.
(Copeland, 1993). This is why alternative
The stroke is literally manufactured out of
models of memory were at the forefront
the living visual and postural "schemata"
of the moment and their interrelations. I of the revival of connectionism in the 1980s
may say, I may think that I reproduce and have continued to play a central role
exactly a series of text-book movements, in attempts to align neural network model-
but demonstrably 1 do not; just as, under ing with neuropsychology (Churchland &
other circumstances, I may say and think Sejnowski, 1992; Gluck 8l Myers, 2000).
that I reproduce exactly some isolated event
Occurrent remembering in connection-
which I want to remember, and again
demonstrably I do not. (pp. 201-202) ist cognitive science is the temporary reac-
tivation of a particular pattern or vector
For Bartlett, explicit remembering is a skill, across the units of a network. This recon-
with just the same peculiar features - com- struction is possible because of the conspir-
bining the familiar and the unique - as com- ing influences of current input and the his-
plex embodied skills. There are a range of tory of the network, as sedimented in the
intriguing and relevant questions, which I connection weights between units. So mem-
cannot address here, about skill and habit, ory traces are not stored separately between
two key varieties of what psychologists experience and remembering but are piled
label "procedural memory," and about how together or "superposed" in the same set
these forms of remembering relate to more of weights. In fully distributed represen-
explicit and consciously accessible mem- tation, the same resources or vehicles are
ory (Sheets-Johnstone, 2003); but in this thus used to carry many different contents
chapter, I describe situated accounts of the (Clark, 1989; van Gelder, 1991). As McClel-
declarative forms of memory, with a focus land and Rumelhart (1986] put it:
on personal or recollective or autobiographi-
cal memory, which is both theoretically and We see the traces laid down by the pro-
cessing of each input as contributing to the
personally important because of its emo-
composite, superimposed memory represen-
tional and moral significance and its role
tation. Each time a stimulus is processed,
in temporally extended agency. 5 As back- it gives rise to a slightly different mem-
ground to the general consensus in situated ory trace - either because the item itself
cognitive psychology on constructivism, the is different or because it occurs in a dif-
most celebrated of Bartlett's theses, we ferent context that conditions its represen-
examine the related ideas of remembering tation - the traces are not kept separate.
as skilled activity, and of the dynamic nature Each trace contributes to the composite, but
of the enduring states that ground that the characteristics of particular experiences
activity. tend nevertheless to be preserved, at least
until they are overridden by canceling char-
acteristics of other traces. Also, the traces
21. Representations and Storage of one stimulus pattern can coexist with
the traces of other stimuli, within the same
Situated approaches to memory not only composite memory trace, (p. 193J
depart from the intemalism or methodolog-
ical solipsism of the way internal repre- Connectionist remembering is thus an
sentations were evoked in classical cogni- inferential process, constructive not repro-
tive science but also, in general, reject the ductive. Information survives only in dis-
distinct idea that individual representations positional form: "the data persist only
120 JOHN SUTTON

implicitly by virtue of the effect they have context. As the developmental psychologist
on what the system knows" (Elman, 1993, Susan Engel (1999) argues, often "one creates
p. 89). In this dynamic vision of repre- the memory at the moment one needs it,
sentations, connectionism is clearly heir to rather than pulling out an intact item, image,
Bartlett's (1932) vision: or story" (p. 6). So memory's temporal
cross-referencing does not run only between
Though we may still talk of traces, there present recall and past experience, because
is no reason in the world for regarding remembering also has a raft of distinctive
these as made complete at one moment, forward-looking or anticipatory features and
stored up somewhere, and then re-excited functions.
at some much later moment. The traces
that our evidence allows us to speak of are
interest-determined, interest-carried traces. 2.2. Constructivism and Relational
They live with our interests and with them Remembering
they change, (pp. 211-212)
A situated approach to memory, then, is one
Neither this point that traces are plastic that treats this multifarious range of mate-
and malleable nor the more general con- rials as potentially integral, complementary
structivist movement in the cognitive psy- aspects of a cognitive system and its pro-
chology of memory directly entails a sit- cesses of remembering. Such an approach
uated approach. But there is one natural can thus fruitfully draw on the resources of
link (Clark, 1997): stability over time in con- personality and social psychology, as well as
nectionist representational systems is main- on cognitive psychology. Attention to social
tained not through permanent storage, but scaffolding and to technological mediations
through context-dependent reconstruction. of memory is entirely compatible with an
Sometimes, then, remembering requires the interest in individual differences in memory.
interaction or coupling of complementary Just because remembering is selective in this
biological and external resources into tem- way, peculiarities of affective style or self-
porarily extended cognitive systems. On this conception directly shape the way mem-
view, brains like ours need media, objects, ory narratives condense, summarize, and
and other people to function fully as minds. edit past experiences for present purposes
Seeing the brain as a leaky associative engine (Mcllwain, 2006). Bartlett had explicitly
(Clark, 1993), its contents flickering and argued that temperament, history, belief,
unstable rather than mirroring the world in and expectation should be incorporated
full, forces attention to the diverse formats within theories of memory when he adapted
of external representations in the technolog- the term schema to refer to "an active orga-
ical and social wild. If biological "engrams" nization of past reactions, or of past expe-
are typically integrative and active in the riences" that act together "as constituents
way connectionism suggests, perhaps it is of living, momentary settings" (1932, p. 201;
natural for creatures like us in using them to also pp. 308-314). 4 His interest was in the
hook up with more enduring and transmissi- pervasive effects of preexisting beliefs and
ble "exograms," in Merlin Donald's coinage attitudes, or of an idiosyncratic personal his-
(1991, pp. 308-333). We compile memories tory acting as a mass in filtering recall. But
(whether in thought or in public expression)
the constructivist consensus in the modem
on the fly, working them up or improvising
subdisciplines of psychology, which devel-
them out of whatever materials we have:
oped independently of connectionist com-
the vivid sensory detail that comes to mind
putational modeling, has in some respects
in episodic fragments and the resources pro-
remained narrower in focus. Research on
vided by external symbol systems, as well as
suggestibility and the effects of misinfor-
the multiple influences of knowledge about
mation on memory, developed initially in
the self and the world; of goals, motivations,
the context of eyewitness testimony, was
and moods; and of the current interpersonal
dramatically extended in the 1990s to the
remembering 221

heart o f p e r s o n a l m e m o r y ( H y m a n & L o f - may be incorporated into many people's


tus, 1998; L o f t u s , 2003; Roediger, 1996) - personal memories of childhood experi-
" a variety o f c o n d i t i o n s e x i s t , " w r o t e D a n i e l ences, S t r a n g e , G e r r i e , a n d G a r r y (2005) dis-
Schacter ( 1 9 9 5 ) , " i n w h i c h s u b j e c t i v e l y c o m - cuss further similar experiments in w h i c h
pelling m e m o r i e s are grossly inaccurate" subjects e x p o s e d to false information about
[p. 22). M a i n s t r e a m p s y c h o l o g y o f a u t o b i o - their past w e r e encouraged to discuss their
graphical m e m o r y h a s continued to treat memories with a sibling. Acknowledging
the ongoing, i n t e r p e r s o n a l l y a n c h o r e d r e v i - that in real settings, " w h e n c o n f r o n t e d w i t h a
sion and r e m o l d i n g o f t h e r e m e m b e r e d p a s t difficult to r e m e m b e r narrative about [their]
a s the o r d i n a r y m e a n s b y w h i c h n a r r a t i v e s childhood, p e o p l e are likely to rely on oth-
o f the self d e v e l o p (Conway, Singer, &. ers t o v e r i f y t h e i r m e m o r i e s " (p. 241), t h e s e
Tagini, 2004; R o s s , 1989); t h e s e v i e w s are researchers f o u n d that after discussion w i t h
thus entirely c o m p a t i b l e w i t h s i t u a t e d c o g - a sibling the proportion of false m e m o r i e s
nition. B u t m u c h w o r k o n " f a l s e m e m o r y " dropped dramatically.
has f o c u s e d o n m o r e m a l i g n f o r m s o f i n f l u - Of course, such negotiations about the
ence, o n s p e c i f i c d i s t o r t i o n s o r m i s l e a d i n g past do not always bring either agreement
additions i n s e r t e d i n t o t h e i n d i v i d u a l ' s m i n d or truth; but the forthcoming examina-
by some e x t e r n a l s o u r c e . tion of the development of autobiographi-
This s t r a n d o f c o n s t r u c t i v i s t m e m o r y t h e - cal m e m o r y w i l l suggest t h a t w e also learn
ory tends t h u s t o r e m a i n i n d i v i d u a l i s t i c i n to deal with disagreement about the past
orientation (cf. Campbell, 2004; Haaken, m o s t directly and effectively through early
1998). First, c o n s t r u c t i o n t e n d s t o b e s i m p l y m e m o r y - s h a r i n g practices. A n d in adult life,
equated w i t h d i s t o r t i o n , t h u s n e g l e c t i n g t h e a s S u e C a m p b e l l (2006) argues, o u r a t t e m p t s
adaptability o f m e m o r y ' s i n t r i n s i c d y n a m i c s , to be faithful to the past are often sup-
b y which t h e v e r y m e c h a n i s m s t h a t u n d e r l i e ported and positively guided by listeners
generalization c a n i n c e r t a i n c i r c u m s t a n c e s or by joint participants in shared mem-
lead u s a s t r a y ( M c C l e l l a n d , 1 9 9 5 ; S c h a c t e r , o r y activities. B o t h ordinary m e m o r y nar-
1999). S e c o n d , i n f l u e n c e i s c h a r a c t e r i z e d a s ratives and m o r e public testimonial expres-
essentially o r p r i m a r i l y n e g a t i v e , t h e r e l e n t - sions of m e m o r y can be co-constructed
less intrusion o f t h e s o c i a l i n t o m a l l e a b l e w i t h o u t other people's role bringing cor-
individual m e m o r y . Q u e s t i o n s a b o u t t r u t h ruption. C a m p b e l l argues, in particular, that
in memory do t a k e on a n e w u r g e n c y w i t h i n locating appropriate emotion in remember-
a constructivist f r a m e w o r k , but the point ing activities can be a significant c o m p o -
need n o t b e e i t h e r t h a t r e l i a b i l i t y i s i m p o s - nent of recollective accuracy, w h e r e accu-
sible o r t h a t i n t e r p e r s o n a l m e m o r y d y n a m - r a c y in u n d e r s t o o d in a c o n t e x t - d e p e n d e n t
ics must b r i n g e r r o r a n d c o n f u s i o n . T r u t h w a y ; representational success in m e m o r y is
and related v a l u e s l i k e a c c u r a c y a n d f i d e l i t y rarely a s i m p l e matter of matching an iso-
in memory n e e d be n e i t h e r s i m p l e n o r sin- lated present i t e m to a single past e v e n t (cf.
gular. I n l e g a l c o n t e x t s , f o r e x a m p l e , c o n - Schechtman, 1994). Remembered events,
cerns a b o u t c o n t a m i n a t i o n a n d c o n f o r m i t y a f t e r all, especially ones that matter, are
i n witnesses' m e m o r i e s m a y b e a p p r o p r i - themselves complex and structured. We
ate. But e l s e w h e r e , o r d i n a r y a n d s u c c e s s f u l o f t e n find ourselves striving f o r the n e e d e d
remembering m a y b e r e l a t i o n a l ( C a m p b e l l , affective shifts in relation to particular m e m -
2003), d e p e n d i n g d i r e c t l y o n t h e s u p p o r t a n d ories through renegotiating in company
involvement o f o t h e r p e o p l e a n d o n o u r a b i l - the meanings of the personal past. These
ities t o c r e a t e m o r e o r l e s s e n d u r i n g m e m - commonplace ways of sharing memories,
ory systems t h a t t r a n s c e n d t h e c a p a c i t i e s o f in co-constructing, jointly reevaluating, or
the brain a l o n e . O n e e x a m p l e c o m e s f r o m j u s t actively listening, bring obligations a n d
false m e m o r y r e s e a r c h i t s e l f ; after show- accountability with them; and when the
ln
g that m i s l e a d i n g v i s u a l o r v e r b a l i n f o r - negotiations concern experiences that w e r e
mation, w h e n p r e s e n t e d i n certain ways, themselves shared, the epistemic, affective,
JOHN SUTTON

determine how social and cognitive sources


and mnemonic interdependence is magni-
are combined in varying ways" (p. 487).
fied further. Robust experimental data in this tradi-
So, one respect in which a thoroughly tion addresses the shaping of the child's
situated approach to memory can push developing memory by parental and cultural
the existing ecological focus on real-lite or styles or models for the recounting of past
everyday memory phenomena further is in events. In general, for example, the spon-
presenting constructive processes in remem- taneous later memory activity of children
bering - and, more generally, memory's whose parents' talk about the past is more
openness to various forms of influence - as elaborate and rich, or more emotional, is
more mundane or natural than inevitably itself more elaborative or emotional (Reese,
dangerous. In the remaining sections, I try Haden, & Fivush, 1993); and in general, both
to merge these ideas about interpersonal mothers and fathers talk more richly and
memory dynamics with the postconnection- more emotionally about the past with girls
ist picture of human beings as essentially than with boys (Fivush, 1994). A range of
incomplete machines, apt to incorporate cultural differences track these interactions,
what has - in the course of evolutionary, cul- so that, for example, Caucasian American
tural, and developmental history - become children's spontaneous memories highlight
apt for incorporation (cf. Clark, 2006). the self more, in general, than do those
of Korean children (Mullen & Yi, 1995; cf.
Leichtman, Wang, & Pillemer, 2003).
3. Remembering as Social Interaction
Some presentations of these results sug-
and Joint Attention to the Past
gest that parental influence - in particular
Children start talking about the past pretty maternal reminiscence style - is the pri-
much as soon as they start talking, but their mary driving force behind the emergence
initial references are fleeting and fragmen- of autobiographical memory; the structure
tary, and the capacity to refer to specific and content of the child's early thought
events in the personal past develops only and talk about the past is provided to a
gradually. A situated approach to the devel- large degree by adults, whose communica-
opment of autobiographical memory needs tive actions construct the scaffolding for
to characterize the explanatory target richly, such early memories. The idea that the
and then seek to extend dynamical models direction of influence is from social and nar-
from more basic domains to capture these rative context to autobiographical memory
high-level cognitive phenomena. The child's is perhaps encouraged by some uses of the
emerging ability to think about experiences Vygotskian scaffolding metaphor.
at particular past times is more than the But it seems likely that elaborative
capacity to understand sequences of events parental talk, commonly defined as adding
or intervals between events and more than details or richness about a particular aspect
general knowledge of how things usually go. of a past event, is not as vital as the related
A sociocultural developmental theory must but distinct feature of contingency in con-
address multiply interactive developmental versation; a contingent utterance is related
systems spanning the child's brain and local in content to the conversational partners
narrative environment. Nelson and Fivush prior utterance, whereas some elaborations
(2004), building on a twenty-year tradition may not be relevant to the specific conver-
of social interactionist work, characterize sational context and thus not genuinely dia-
the emergence of autobiographical memory logical (Petra, Benga, & Tineas, 2005). Here,
as "the outcome of a social cultural cogni- a better metaphor is that of a spiral process,
tive system, wherein different components in which the child's changing competence m
are being opened to experiences over time, dialogue about the past itself in turn directly
wherein experiences vary over time and influences the parent's reminiscence style,
context, and wherein individual histories encouraging the dynamic co-construction of
223
REMEMBERING

richer narratives (Haden, Haine, & Fivush, the world and the self are causally con-
1997)' On a thoroughly situated perspec- nected over time. Their idea is that the
tive, we should reconstruct the difference memory sharing in which parents and chil-
between scaffolding and spiral models not dren engage can best be understood as a
as a theoretical choice with only one right peculiar form of joint attention, directed -
answer but as an empirical spectrum of unlike other forms of joint attention - at
possibilities. This requires a developmen- the past. To grasp "the causal significance
tal systems framework in which the relative of the order in which sequences of events
influence of multiple concurrent processes unfold," the child needs to understand that
can vary across cases (cf. Griffiths & Stotz, "later events in the sequence can obliterate
2000; Smith & Thelen, 2003). So, recent pre- or change the effect of earlier ones," so that
sentations of the social-interactionist the- the state of the world and of the child's cur-
ory address not only the roles of language rent feelings depends on this independently
and the local narrative environment but also ordered history (Hoerl & McCormack, 2005,
the neural and psychological development pp. 267-270).
of other memory systems, the development Using a delayed video-feedback tech-
of a self-schema and of theory of mind, the nique in which children are shown two
emergence of a concept of the past, and the games in different orders, Povinelli, Landry,
role of affective factors such as motivation Theall, Clark, and Castille (1999) demon-
and attachment security (Nelson & Fivush, strated that three-year-olds could not use
2004; Reese, 2002). Autobiographical mem- information about which of two events hap-
ory development can thus be highly buffered pened more recently to update their model
in that different factors play different roles of the world as a series of causally related
at different stages for different chddren. events unfolds, but that with clear instruc-
For example, children with weaker linguis- tions, five-year-olds could do so. Budding
tic skills but stronger early self-recognition on these methods in ingenious experiments
skills, Elaine Reese (2002) has shown, "enter that examine not only temporal updating
the system through a less verbal and more but also the ability to make temporal-causal
autonomous route" (p. 252) than children inferences, McCormack and Hoerl (2005)
who engage in highly elaborative conversa- have shown that chddren under age five
tions about the past. And when dealing with and some five-year-olds who can success-
such highly history-dependent developmen- fully engage in simple updating of their
tal processes, in which social and neural knowledge base when they observe or infer
influences are "bidirectionally and funda- the world being modified have serious dif-
mentally interactive at all levels of organi- ficulty in making these more sophisticated
zation" (Bjorklund, 2004, p. 344), we would temporal-causal inferences in which they
also expect the degree of significant individ- must grasp the objective sequence of events.
ual variability that requires substantial longi- They suggest that this kind of temporal-
tudinal study (Harley & Reese, 1999; Reese, causal reasoning is just what conversations
2002). about past events elicit or jointiy generate,
In an exemplary cross-disciplinary collab- as parent and child together construct a tem-
oration, philosopher Christoph Hoerl and porally structured narrative that explains the
psychologist Teresa McCormack have inves- influence of the past on the present. In joint
tigated more precisely the role of the joint reminiscence, a parent is often not merely
reminiscing activities studied in this social- modeling these narrative abilities but also
interactionist tradition. Budding on John direcdy exerting an influence on the child
Campbell's (1997) point that mature auto- by encouraging the child to see that things
biographical memory requires us to coor- are not now as they once were. The context
dinate and align egocentric and objective is very often directly affective; the sore fin-
conceptions of time, Hoerl and McCormack ger that caused the child's past sadness and
suggest that children need to grasp that both pain is no longer sore, because since then
JOHN SUTTON

Daddy came and made it better (Hoerl & Elam, 1996; Kansteiner, 2002; Klein, 2000).
McCormack, 2005, p. 275, quoting Fivush, This situation exemplifies the ongoing and
1994, p. 149)1. The shared outlook on the damaging lack of contact between the cog-
past that emerges is thus also evaluative, nitive and the social sciences; in this case it
and in turn grounds other ongoing collabo- is partly because the only English transla-
rative activities; children then come to value tion of Halbwachs's 1925 book simply omits
memories of particular past events for them- most of the relevant material (the first four
selves, "because the sharing of such memo- chapters, which cover 145 pages in the sec-
ries is a way of establishing, maintaining, or ond French edition of 1952, are condensed
negotiating a distinctively social relationship into 13 pages in the 1992 translation), and
with others" (Hoerl & McCormack, 2005, partly because relevant ideas in situated or
distributed cognition remain inaccessible to
p. 283).
those social theorists who are keen to forge
So, this may be how the local narrative
links with psychology (Bloch, 1998; Middle-
practices studied by the social interaction-
ton & Brown, 2005; Olick, 1999; Winter &
ists, with all their cultural idiosyncrasies,
Sivan, 1999). The time is ripe for integra-
themselves put the child in touch with an tive work to close these gaps (Nelson, 2003;
objective conception of time and causation. Rubin, 1995; Sutton, 2004; Wertsch, 2002;
The practical engagement involved in jointly Wilson, 2005).
attending to past events and sharing mem-
ories helps the child understand that there Halbwachs argues that what individuals
can be different perspectives on the same retain of the past, if considered outside of
once-occupied time; and thus such shared, their ordinary social context as (for exam-
co-constructed narratives shape the child's ple) in dreaming, is often incomplete or
initial grasp of the causal connectedness of shrouded, based only on "the disordered
self and world. The acquisition of compe- play of corporal modifications" (1992, pp. 41-
tence in these shared narratives is, inextri- 42; 1980, pp. 71-76). My memory traces
cably, cognitive and social development at are not "fully formed in the unconscious
once. mind like so many printed pages of books
that could be opened, even though they
no longer are," a view Halbwachs attributes
4. Shared Remembering both to Freud and to his own teacher Berg-
son (1980, p. 75). In remembering and recon-
4.1. Halbwachs on Collective Memory structing the past, we normally draw not just
Maurice Halbwachs is not often explicitly on such episodic fragments as we hold on
recognized as a forerunner of situated cog- our own but also on the vast and uneven
nition, but in fact his conceptual contribu- resources of our multiple social groups,
tions are as relevant as those of Bartlett or material symbols, and social practices with
Vygotsky. In The Social Frameworks of Mem- which we have surrounded ourselves. This
ory (1925) and the posthumous The Collective is so not only when actually remembering
Memory (1950/1980), Halbwachs developed in company but also by way of the virtual
striking views about shared remembering groups we turn toward affectively when we
and applied them in studies of family mem- revivify experiences; ways of thinking and
ory, religious memory, memory and place, feeling that did not originate with me stay
and musicians' memory. Halbwachs's influ- with me as the influences of various groups
ence has been felt much less in the psychol- and continue to animate the explicit memo-
ogy of memory than in history and the social ries I draw from my world (1980, p. 24; on the
sciences (Hutton, 1994; Misztal, 2003; Olick necessity of an affective community, see also
& Robbins, 1998), where many have criti- pp. 30-33). I do have my own unique mem-
cized the vagueness of invocations of collec- ories, as a result of my idiosyncratic history,
tive memory and social memory in contem- but this is just a contingent fact about the
porary social theory (Berliner, 2005; Gedi & complexity of the particular intersection of
remembering 225

social groups and influences at w h i c h they required, though, to ground the stronger
lie (1980, pp. 44-49)- idea we found in Halbwachs that a group
Robert Wilson (2005), arguing that itself can remember is some alternative way
of characterizing the kind of more or less
Halbwachs anticipates "something like an
transient, socially extended cognitive sys-
extended mind view of m e m o r y " [pp. 229-
tems that can have distributed memories or
231), suggests that slightly different theses
intentions or beliefs, or can engage in gen-
are defended at different points in Halb-
uinely joint action. This demand might be
wachs's works. On the one hand, "it is in-
met by applying to memory the notions of
dividuals as group members w h o r e m e m -
mutual knowledge and of the plural subject
ber" (Halbwachs, 1980, p. 48), b u t m e m o r y
developed in the field of social ontology, as
is always and constitutively socially mani-
a w a y of taking ordinary ' W e remember"
fested. On the other hand, "it is only natu-
statements seriously.
ral that we consider the group in itself as
having the capacity to r e m e m b e r " (Halb- Some people w h o happen to have shared
wachs, 1992, p. 54). Wilson sees some tension experiences clearly do not have a shared or
between these claims, characterizing the lat- collective memory; even if each of them sep-
ter as an application to m e m o r y of a more arately retains information about the same
general thesis about group-level cognition, event, and even though their distinct mem-
which is also found in ideas about super- ories could in principle be aggregated, the
organisms and swarm intelligence in biology social dimension of memory in this case is
(Wilson, 2004, pp. 265-307). But Halbwachs in an obvious sense accidental or superfi-
himself saw the two claims as not just com- cial. In contrast, think of the way certain
patible but complementary: " O n e m a y say ordinary small groups - friends, partners, or
that the individual remembers by placing a family, for example - may continue to
himself in the perspective of the group, but revisit their shared experiences, when the
one may also affirm that the m e m o r y of the events they remember together may have
group realizes and manifests itself in individ- a distinct interpersonal and affective signif-
ual memories" (1992, p. 40). Neither individ- icance alongside their personal significance.
ual nor shared memory has ontological pri- Perhaps they reevaluate parts of their lives,
ority. Methodologically, as D a v i d V e l l e m a n in part, on the basis of - or just by way of -
(1997) argues for the case of shared inten- retelling and reinterpreting some of these
tion, before we rule out the possibdity of earlier shared experiences. Occasionally, in
shared cognitive states on the ground that a long-standing close network, significant
there are no group minds to have them, we renegotiation of relationships and plans may
should first offer independent characteriza- be partly enacted through this ongoing joint
tions of the cognitive states in question and reinterpretation of the still-live shared past.
investigate whether they can be held in com- Clearly, there are many intermediate cases;
mon (cf. Clark, 1994; Gilbert, 1989, pp. 432- but it is only in the latter kind of case that
434)- the commonplace notion of a group being
partly held together by, or identified with,
some of its memories has a grip.
4.2. The Plural Subject of Memories
T h e sharing of memories in this stronger
Indeed it is far f r o m clear that propo- sense is a pervasive social phenomenon, built
nents of socially situated cognition in gen- in to the interpersonal fabric of human
eral need the idea of collective minds; life in significant ways. How should it
•nind is a much trickier concept than be understood? The plural-subject analysis
(for example) memory, intention, belief, or developed in other contexts by Margaret
action, and is much less entrenched in ordi- Gilbert (1989, 2003, 2004) may capture fea-
nary usage and perhaps far more cultur- tures of this kind of shared remembering
% and historically variable (MacDonald, that cannot be accounted for so easily in
200
3; Wierzbicka, 1992). W h a t is arguably alternative theoretical models. For example,
226 JOHN SUTTON

collective-memory phenomena could be and regret m i g h t be partly illuminated by


treated as the aggregate of many indi- such an analysis of s h a r e d m e m o r y , as there
vidual memories. This kind of summative is plausibly s o m e link b e t w e e n responsibility
approach is exemplified, in the social sci- and m e m o r y (on t h e ethics of memory, see,
ences of memory, by survey-based studies e.g., Margalit, 2 0 0 2 ) .
of what and how the members of groups
or generations remember about some set of
events. Schwartz and Schuman ( 2 0 0 5 ) , for 4 . 3 . Collaborative Recall
example, react against models that exclude To this kind of c o n c e p t u a l analysis of shared
the individual by surveying what many m e m o r y p h e n o m e n a , we can add the exper-
individual Americans of different genera- imental dimension p r o v i d e d by psychologi-
tions remember about Abraham Lincoln. cal studies of collaborative recall. Some of
Whether examining memories of historical this w o r k shares t h e individualistic orienta-
and public events or of more personal expe- tion of false m e m o r y research as mentioned
riences, this collected memory approach - previously, f o c u s i n g f o r e x a m p l e on mem-
to use Olick's ( 1 9 9 9 ) useful label - does ory contagion and m e m o r y conformity in
not directly address the active interper- groups ( G a b b e r t , M e m o n , & Allan, 2003;
sonal dynamics of memory sharing; it might Roediger, B e r g m a n , & M e a d e , 2 0 0 1 ) ; but the
be merely accidental that the aggregated methods d e v e l o p e d in these paradigms do
individual memories converge to whatever not inevitably rely on t h e assumption that
extent they do. external influence necessarily distorts indi-
vidual m e m o r y . Studies of transactive mem-
So, a fuller account of genuinely shared
ory, for e x a m p l e , treat t h e emergent and
memory must allow for it to be common
often implicit structures of memory orga-
knowledge among the members of the group
nization in small groups, families, or cou-
that they all share the memories in question.
ples as key c o m p o n e n t s of shared exper-
In the strongest cases, this common knowl-
tise in successfully negotiating a complex
edge must not itself be accidental but must
shared environment (Moreland, Argote, &
result from and involve the members' open
Krishnan, 1 9 9 6 ; W e g n e r , Erber, & Raymond,
expressions of willingness to remember
1 9 9 1 ) . A n d in collaborative recall paradigms,
jointly and to remain jointly ready and com-
groups working together typically remem-
mitted to the shared remembering. By thus
ber more than individuals recalling alone
pooling their wills, the members of a group
but less than t h e n o m i n a l pooled sum of
become for these purposes a plural subject,
the individual m e m o r i e s (Basden, Basden, &
the subject of the "we remember" thoughts
Henry, 2 0 0 0 ; W e l d o n 8c Bellinger, 1 9 9 7 ) . Tne
and claims. This kind of analysis, here very
causes of this collaborative inhibition effect,
roughly adapted from Gilbert's ( 1 9 8 9 , pp.
in which individuals' retrieval strategies are
1 5 4 - 1 6 7 , 2 8 8 - 3 1 4 ) treatments of shared action
somehow disrupted in t h e collaborative pro-
and collective belief, could potentially cover
cess, are far firom clear, and little work in the
both occurrent joint activities of remem-
area has dealt w i t h emotional or autobio-
bering and the standing shared memories
graphical memories ( Y a r o n - A n t a r 8c Nach-
to which groups retain a joint commitment
son, 2 0 0 6 ) . Further investigations of the cog-
over time. It should also begin to explain
nitive, social, and motivational parameters
the characteristic structure of obligations,
of group influence are needed, as of the
commitments, and expectations that partic-
impact of subtle differences in the mech-
ipation in a community of memory brings.
anisms of collaboration and in the specific
This, of course, is compatible with the
nature and history of t h e groups in question.
fact that there is always room for disagree-
ment and renegotiation over the details and In one suggestive line of research, William
meaning of shared memories. And, fur- Hirst and his colleagues (Hirst 8c Manier,
ther, the problematic but pervasive notions 1 9 9 6 ; Hirst, Manier, 8c Apetroaia, 1 9 9 7 ; Hirst,
of collective and shared responsibility Manier, 8c C u e , 2 0 0 3 ) e x a m i n e the way in
182
remembering231

which specific group dynamics and pro- ory as specific auditory reminiscences and
cesses can influence individual members' that our untrained natural memory for
subsequent enduring memories. In the basic sounds is sufficient to explain the expert's
design, each individual first gives his or competence. But because musicians have
her memories of an event that the whole wholly assimilated the conventional system
group has seen or lived through. A f t e r var- of musical notation, they do not need to
ious delays, the group as a whole is then conserve all relevant combinations distincdy
asked to recall what happened; after a fur- in their brains. External representations can
ther manipulable delay, each member again then be used to preserve the complex com-
offers his or her own memory. Hirst is par- binations: "the score in this case functions
ticularly interested in cases in which a dom- exactly as a material substitute for the
inant individual or narrator — such as one brain" (1980, p. 162). In the long process of
parent in a family group - has a dispropor- acquiring musical skills, musicians not only
have learned how to read these external
tionate influence on the content (or emo-
symbols but also have artificially remolded
tional tone, or narrative structure) of both
their onboard representational apparatus,
the group's consensual account (where one
and they come to rely on these new mecha-
emerges) and members' subsequent individ-
nisms in their musical habits and thinking
ual recollections. Memory contents migrate
whether or not they are actually using a
in the process of shared remembering, so
score.
that sometimes each member's later recall
incorporates, without his or her awareness, In our terms, Halbwachs is arguing that
elements that were only offered by the dom- onboard biological memory is transformed
inant narrator in the group phase. Basic rather than simply augmented. He imag-
cognitive-affective processes and subde sit- ines an alien neurophysiologist ignorant of
uational factors operate together both in human musical culture and notation. The
the group's production of a shared or social alien might, Halbwachs suggests, come to
memory and in the effect of collaboration understand the basic representational work-
on subsequent individual memories. ings of the human auditory system as it
responds to natural sound. But it could not
make sense of the traces connected to musi-
5. Distributed Cognition and cal characters. These culturally laden traces
Exograms "reveal the action exerted on the human
brain b y . . . a system or colony of other
Most socially distributed transactive mem- human brains" (1980, p. 163), and the musi-
ory systems are not, in fact, exclusively social cal system with which they operate is shared
in that the spread of resources drawn on across the entire musical world of a culture.
in complex activities of remembering may So, for Halbwachs, in these entirely typical
include material, symbolic, technological, respects, the human brain "cannot be con-
and cultural artifacts and objects as well as sidered in isolation" (p. 164); or, as we might
other people. It is not enough to see exter- put it, the musical mind extends beyond the
nal resources or representational systems as brain. The external symbol system of musi-
merely adding supplementary storage capac- cal notation has been annexed, exploited,
ity; again, the most trenchant individualist and assimilated "deep into our mental pro-
could accept this. files" (Clark, 2003, p. 198; Wilson 8c Clark,
Again, we can draw on Halbwachs's this volume). 6
direct anticipation of distributed cognition.
In The Collective Memory of Musicians,5
5.1. The Cognitive Life of Things
H a l b w a c h s a s k s how classical musicians reli-
ably remember how to play such an enor- So, where classical cognitivists projected
mous array of pieces of music. He denies stability in information storage onto our
both that musical sounds are fixed in mem- internal psychological economy, situated
228
JOHN SUTTON

approaches to memory see it as an emer- (Knappett, 2005; R e n f r e w & Scarre, 1999),


gent product of organisms' meeting, within and sociologists of science (Bowker, 2005)
specific cognitive niches, with external sym- offer rich studies of cases in which exter-
bol systems and other resources. As Clark nal resources are less passive and medium-
(1997) puts it in his account of Hutchins's independent than on Donald's basic scheme.
case study of expert navigation, "the compu- So, as Clark (2002) writes, the urgent task for
tational power and expertise is spread across a science of biotechnological memory sys-
a heterogeneous assembly of brains, bod- tems is to understand "the range and variety
ies, artifacts, and other external structures" of types of cognitive scaffolding," by con-
(p. 77; Hutchins, 1995, 2006). The point is structing "a t a x o n o m y of different types of
not that the external resources do the cog- external prop, a n d . . . of h o w they help (and
nitive work on their own; it is no argument hinder) h u m a n performance" (p. 29; see also
against a situated approach to emotion, for Susi, 2005).
example, to complain that "the black tie I In addition to this direct mediation
wear at the funeral isn't doing my grieving of m e m o r y by the use of cognitive arti-
for me" (Harris, 2004, p. 729). Neither, after facts, however, h u m a n s also characteristi-
all, do brains tend to perform their cognitive cally learn, in some circumstances, to drop
functions in isolation. the real external object and thereby cre-
Studies of such cases as the sketch ate an inner surrogate f o r it. The requisite
pads without which artists cannot itera- auxiliary stimuli are "emancipated from pri-
tively reimagine and successfully create an mary external f o r m s " w h e n we internally
abstract artwork (van Leeuwen, Verstij- reconstruct the familiar active operations
nen, & Hekkert, 1999) can be character- and means of recall (Vygotsky, 1930/1978,
ized as investigations of "the cognitive life of p. 45; cf. pp. 52-57). So, not all cognitive
things" (Sutton, 2002, extending Appadurai, technologies must in fact be outside the
1986). In his initial discussion of the changes skin. A m o n g the many resources we use
to human memory that resulted from the to think about the past are a range of
spread of external representations, Merlin internalized representations, symbol sys-
Donald (1991, pp. 315-316) focused on typ- tems, and habits of thought, which we leam
ical differences between engrams and exo- (historically and developmentally) to man-
grams; the latter, in general, last longer, have age with both idiosyncratic and culturally
greater capacity, are more easily transmissi- specified strategies. We are not untouched
ble across media and context, and can be by our ongoing interaction with different
retrieved and manipulated by a wider vari- media and symbolic technologies; even lan-
ety of means. Hooking up with such sys- guage, as used cognitively, provides us with
tems of exograms in more or less transient more memorable, context-resistant mental
networks for particular purposes, we can - objects to carry around with us and take as
collectively and individually - dramatically objects of thought in their own right (Clark,
transform our cognitive profile and hold 1997, p. 210; 2006). Lasting changes in our
information more securely over time than minds result f r o m internalizing the mediat-
our fragile biological memory allows.7 But, ing function of artifacts. For instance, we
of course, not all external representations become capable of self-scaffolding, engag-
need be permanent or endlessly reformat- ing in various f o r m s of virtuoso artificial
table. Some of the liveliest recent applica- self-manipulation by w a y of words, tags,
tions of situated cognition to the case of and maxims that can freeze, counteract,
memory show that systems of exograms are recalibrate, or b u f f e r us against our ordi-
not necessarily meant to be permanent or nary cognitive-affective flow (Clark, 2005b;
limitlessly transmissible, or turn out to be Hutchins, 2005).
less stable in practice than in intention. Art So, it is one natural tendency of social-
historians and theorists (Forty, 1999; Klein, ized brains like ours to co-opt cultural and
1997; Kwint, 1999), cognitive archaeologists moral, as well as linguistic, inner prostheses,
remembering 229

altering our own cognitive machinery by of particular past experiences. I offered an


exploiting and importing whatever tools and integrative picture of shared memory and
labels we can. Questions about the loca- social memory, triangulating a rereading of
tion of memory processes may no longer Halbwachs with a new social ontology of
seem so important; rather, we are studying memory and a sketch of ongoing experi-
the transformation and propagation of rep- mental investigations of collaborative recall.
resentational states "across a set of malleable And finally I rehearsed some central ideas in
media," whether inside or outside the skin the situated and distributed cognition move-
ments about the role of material and tech-
(Hutchins, 1995, p. 312; Latour, 1996, 1999).
nological artifacts in complex cognitive and
We can acknowledge that embodied organ-
mnemonic practices.
isms bring something specific to the inter-
face, underpinning their enduring individual The last point here about the internaliza-
histories and idiosyncratic styles of planning tion of memory prostheses is crucial for the
and remembering, without assuming dis- overall response to the challenge. The world
tinct inner and outer realms of engrams and may be "an outside memory" in the context
exograms, the natural and the artificial, each of visual processing, in that the detail of the
with its own inevitable proprietary charac- visual scene is all out there and potentially
teristics (Sutton, in press). available to the viewer (Myin & O'Regan,
this volume), but it would seem that the
present world cannot function as an out-
6. Conclusion side memory in support of memory itself,
because the detad of the past simply is not
The challenge set by the nature of human always recoverable from the current situa-
memory to theories of situated cognition, as tion. Even when there are interpersonal or
I mentioned at the outset of this chapter, material supports to remembering, they still
is to see how social or material resources need the embodied remembering agent to
outside the brain could possibly be an inte- bring considerable history to bear in the
gral or constitutive feature of memory states memory process; and often, in any case,
or processes, when the events or episodes there simply are not any relevant external
remembered are long gone. We now have triggers or cues in the present environment.
the elements of a response in place - as on But our assessment of the role of situa-
many issues in inchoate research programs tions in driving and shaping memory need
these are not so much arguments as sets not be restricted to the role of contex-
of attitudes or possible ways of approach- tual features that happen to be outside the
ing difficult topics. We retain the invoca- skin: that might be a relatively superficial
tion of representations while departing from characteristic. In even the most abstruse
classical cognitivism in two ways: by treat- and detached activities of autobiographical
ing inner representations and traces as often remembering, our memory processes still
incomplete, partial, and context-sensitive, lean and operate on the internal wing of
to be reconstructed rather than reproduced, the vast, extended system of cultural and
and by widening the representational realm personal habits, hints, and patterns through
outside the organismic boundary (Wdson, which the inner representational regime has
2004). This leads to the expectation that
been sculpted and disciplined (cf. Clark,
mnemonic stability is often supported by
2005b, p. 264). Again, adding a genuinely
heterogeneous external resources as well
as diachronic dimension to our picture of the
i and in complementary interaction with,
neuroscience and psychology of memory
neural resources. I examined the social
means that we do not have to see the tem-
nature of human memory in its develop-
porarily isolated brain as fundamentally or
ment, suggesting that joint attention to the
intrinsically alone, having to revert to some
past is integral to the cognitive shift by
purely biological starting state whenever the
which children come to grasp the specificity
trappings of culture are not around. For,
JOHN SUTTON

again, in our unusual case, the biological 4 There is ongoing controversy - both concep-
brain is itself incomplete and always already tual and empirical - over Bartlett's account
permeated by structures and history that of schemas and conventionalization (Brewer,
2000; Roediger et al., 2000); but the recent
take it out of itself.
history of the schema concept is an intrigu-
ing illustration of the potential links between
cognitive-connectionist computational theo-
Acknowledgments
ries of memory and more obviously situated
approaches (Rumelhart, Smolensky, McClel-
My warm thanks to the editors for their patience land, & Hinton, 1986; Strauss & Quinn,
and support. I am also grateful for help with 1997)-
this material to Amanda Bamier, Pascal Boyer, 5 First published as a separate case study in
Andy Clark, Ed Cooke, Christoph Hoerl, Doris 1939, translated in 1980, pp. 158-186.
Mcllwain, Monte Pemberton, Lyn Tribble, and 6 For an intriguing historical study in dis-
Rob Wilson. tributed cognition, see Tribble (2005), which
in impressive detail applies Hutchins's frame-
work in Cognition in the Wild to a histori-
Notes cal puzzle about how Shakespearean actors
remembered a staggering number of plays
1 In 1978, for example, Ulric Neisser could without fixed scripts or extended rehearsal
fairly lament, "If X is an interesting or socially periods.
significant aspect of memory, then psycholo- 7 "Even such comparatively simple operations
gists have hardly ever studied X" (1978/2000, as tying a knot or marking a stick as a
p. 4). But by the time of the second edition reminder change the psychological structure
of Memory Observed: Remembering in Natu- of the memory process. They extend the
ral Contexts, Neisser and Hyman could afford operation of memory beyond the biologi-
understatement in noting that the study of cal dimensions of the human nervous sys-
everyday or real-world memory "has now tem and permit it to incorporate artificial, or
become an influential and widely accepted self-generated, stimuli, which we call signs"
research tradition" (2000, p. xiii; see also (Vygotsky, 1930/1978, p. 39).
Neisser, 1997).
2 Situated approaches are potentially relevant
to a number of further topics in the inter-
disciplinary study of memory, which I do not References
discuss in this chapter. As well as issues about
memory systems, amnesia, and localization, I Appadurai, A. (1986). Introduction: Commodi-
should particularly mention questions about ties and the politics of value. In A. Appadu-
reduction and interlevel relations in the sci- rai (Ed.), The social life of things: Commodities
ences of memory, with which the integra- in cultural perspective (pp. 3-63). Cambridge:
tive version of a situated approach to mem- Cambridge University Press.
ory which I sketch here needs to engage (see, Bartlett, F. C. (1932). Remembering: A study »'
e.g., Craver, 2002). experimental and social psychology. Cambridge:
3 However, one plausible lesson of the con- Cambridge University Press.
structivist research in cognitive psychology Basden, B. H., Basden, D. R., & Henry, S. (2000).
described in this section is that the processes Costs and benefits of collaborative remember-
and contents of personal memory are thor- ing. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 14,497-5°7-
oughly entangled with factual or semantic Ben-Zeev, A. (1986). T w o approaches to mem-
memory, the other central form of declarative ory. Philosophical Investigations, 9, 288-301.
memory. Indeed, some situated approaches Berliner, D. (2005). T h e abuses of memory:
threaten the idea of firm conceptual and psy- Reflections on the memory boom in anthro-
chological distinctions between these auto- pology. Anthropology Quarterly, 78,197-2"-
biographical and semantic memory systems, Bjorklund, D. F. (2004). Introduction: Special
and between memory and other psychologi-
issue on memory development in the new mil-
cal capacities (Toth & Hunt, 1999).
lennium. Developmental Review, 24, 343-346.
REMEMBERING 231

Bloch, M. (1998). How we think they think: Anthro- Clark, A. (2003). Natural-born cyborgs: Minds,
pological approaches to cognition, memory, and technologies, and the future of human intelli-
literacy. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. gence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bowker, G. C. (2005). Memory practices in the Clark, A. (2005a). Beyond the flesh: Some lessons
sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. from a mole cricket. Artificial Life, 11, 233-244.
Brewer, W. F. (2000). Bartlett's concept of the Clark, A. (2005b). Word, niche and super-niche:
schema and its impact on theories of knowl- How language makes minds matter more.
edge representation in contemporary cogni- Theoria, 20, 255-268.
tive psychology. In A. Saito (Ed.), Bartlett, cul- Clark, A. (2006). Material symbols. Philosophical
ture, and cognition (pp. 69-89). London: Psy- Psychology, 19(3), 291-307.
chology Press. Conway, M. A., & Pleydell-Pearce, C. W. (2000).
Bursen, H. A. (1978). Dismantling the memory The construction of autobiographical memo-
machine. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: D. ries in the self memory system. Psychological
Reidel. Review, 107, 261-288.
Campbell, J. (1997). The structure of time in Conway, M. A., Singer, J. A., & Tagini, A. (2004).
autobiographical memory. European Journal The self and autobiographical memory: Cor-
of Philosophy, 5,105-118. respondence and coherence. Social Cognition,
Campbell, S. (2003). Relational remembering: 22,491-529.
Rethinking the memory wars. Lanham, MD: Copeland, J. (1993). Artificial intelligence: A philo-
Rowman 81 Litdefield. sophical introduction. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
Campbell, S. (2004). Models of memory and Craver, C. F. (2002). Interlevel experiments and
memory activities. In P. DesAutels 8t M. U. multilevel mechanisms in the neuroscience of
Walker (Eds.), Moral psychology: Feminist memory. Philosophy of Science, 69(Suppl. 3),
ethics and political theory (pp. 119-137). Lan- S83-S97.
ham, MD: Rowman & Litdefield. Donald, M. (1991). Origins of the modem mind:
Campbell, S. (2006). Our faithfulness to the past: Three stages in the evolution of culture and cog-
Reconstructing memory value. Philosophical nition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Psychobgy, 19(3), 361-380. Press.
Casey, E. S. (1987). Remembering: A phenomeno- Elman, J. L. (1993). Learning and development in
logical study. Bloomington: Indiana University neural networks: The importance of starting
Press. small. Cognition, 48, 71-99.
Churchland, P. S., & Sejnowski, T. (1992). The Engel, S. (1999). Context is everything: The nature
computational brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT of memory. New York: W. H. Freeman.
Press. Fivush, R. (1994). Constructing narrative, emo-
Clancey, W. J. (1997). Situated cognition: On hu- tion, and self in parent-child conversations
man knowledge and computer representations. about the past. In U. Neisser &. R. Fivush
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Eds.), The remembering self (pp. 136-157).
Clancey, W. J. (1999). Conceptual coordination: Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
How the mind orders experience in time. Hills- Forty, A. (1999). Introduction. In A. Forty & S.
dale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. Kuchler (Eds.), The art of forgetting (pp. 1-18).
Clark, A. (1989). Microcognition: Philosophy, cog- Oxford, UK: Berg.
nitive science and parallel distributed processing. Gabbert, F., Memon, A., 81 Allan, K. (2003).
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Memory conformity: Can eyewitnesses influ-
Clark, A. (1993). Associative engines: Connec- ence each other's memories for an event?
lionism, concepts and representational change. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 17, 533-544.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Gedi, N., 81 Elam, Y. (1996). Collective memory:
Clark, A. (1994). Beliefs and desires incorporated. What is it? History and Memory, 8, 30-50.
Journal of Philosophy, 91, 404-425. Gilbert, M. (1989). On social facts. London: Rout-
Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, ledge.
and world together again. Cambridge, MA: Gilbert, M. (2003). The structure of the social
MIT Press. atom: Joint commitment as the foundation of
Clark, A. (2002). Towards a science of the bio- human social behavior. In F. F. Schmitt (Ed.),
technological mind. International Journal of Socializing metaphysics (pp. 39-64). Lanham,
Cognition and Technology, 1, 21-33. MD: Rowman & Litdefield.
236johnsutton

Gilbert, M. (2004). Collective epistemology. Epis- Hutchins, E. (2005). Material anchors for con-
teine, 1, 95-107. ceptual blends. Journal of Pragmatics, 37, i®*.
Gluck, M., 8t Myers, C. (2000). Gateway to mem- »577-
ory: An introduction to neural network modeling Hutchins, E. (2006, April). The cognitive life
of the hippocampus and learning. Cambridge, of things. The Cognitive Life of Things-
MA: MIT Press. Recasting the Boundaries of Mind symposium
Griffiths, P. E., & Stotz, K. (2000). How the mind conducted at the meeting of the McDonald
grows: A developmental perspective on the Institute for Archaeological Research, Cam-
biology of cognition. Synthese, 122, 29-51. bridge, UK. Retrieved May 20, 2008, from
Haaken, J. (1998). Pillar of salt: Gender, memory, http ://liris. enrs. fr/enaction/docs/documents
and the perils of looking back. New Brunswick, 2oo6/ImaginingCogLifeThings.pdf.
NJ: Rutgers University Press. Hutton, P. (1994). Sigmund Freud and Maurice
Haden, C. A., Haine, R. A., 8t Fivush, R. (1997). Halbwachs: The problem of memory in his-
Developing narrative structure in parent-child torical psychology. History Teacher, 27,145-
reminiscing across the preschool years. Devel- 158.
opmental Psychology, 33, 295-307. Hyman, I. E., & Loftus, E. F. (1998). Errors in
Halbwachs, M. (1992). The social frameworks autobiographical memory. Clinical Psychology
of memory. In L. A. Coser (Ed.), On collec- Review, 18, 933-947.
tive memory (pp. 35-189). Chicago: University Kansteiner, W. (2002). Finding meaning in mem-
of Chicago Press. (Original work published ory: A methodological critique of collective
1925) memory studies. History and Theory, 41, no-
Halbwachs, M. (1980). The collective memory (F. 197.
J. Ditter & V. Y. Ditter, Trans.). New York: Kirsh, D. (2006). Distributed cognition: A
Harper and Row. (Original work published methodological note. Pragmatics and Cogni-
1950) tion., 14(2), 249-262.
Harley, K., & Reese, E. (1999). Origins of autobio- Klein, K. L. (2000). On the emergence of mem-
graphical memory. Developmental Psychology, ory in historical discourse. Representations, 69,
35,1338-1348. 127-150.
Harris, R. 2004. Integrationism, language, mind Klein, N. M. (1997). The history of forgetting. Lon-
and world. Language Sciences, 26, 727- don: Verso Books.
739- Knappett, C. (2005). Thinking through mate-
Hirst, W., & Manier, D. (1996). Remembering rial culture: An interdisciplinary perspec-
as communication: A family recounts its past. tive. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania
In D. C. Rubin (Ed.), Remembering our past Press.
(pp. 271-290). Cambridge: Cambridge Univer- Krell, D. F. (1990). Of memory, reminiscence, and
sity Press. writing: On the verge. Bloomington: Indiana
Hirst, W., Manier, D., & Apetroaia, I. (1997). University Press.
The social construction of the remembered Kwint, M. (1999). Introduction: The physical
self: Family recounting. In J. Snodgrass & R. past. In M. Kwint, C. Breward, 8t J. Aynsley
Thompson (Eds.), The self across psychology (Eds.), Material memories (pp. 1-16). Oxford,
(pp. 163-188). New York: New York Academy UK: Berg.
of Sciences. Latour, B. (1996). Cogito ergo sumus! Or, psy-
Hirst, W., Manier, D., & Cue, A. (2003). The con- chology swept inside out by the fresh air of the
struction of a collective memory. In B. Koki- upper deck: Review of Hutchins 1995. Mind,
nov & W. Hirst (Eds.), Constructive memory Culture, and Activity, 3,54-63.
(pp. 111-116). Sofia: New Bulgarian University. Latour, B. (1999). A collective of humans and
Hoerl, C., & McCormack, T. (2005). Joint rem- nonhumans. In Pandora's hope: Essays on the
iniscing as joint attention to the past. In N. reality of science studies (pp. 174-215). Cam-
Eilan, C. Hoerl, T. McCormack, & J. Roessler bridge, M A : Harvard University Press.
(Eds.), Joint attention, communication, and Leichtman, M., Wang, Q., & Pillemer, D.
other minds: Issues in philosophy and psychol- (2003). Cultural variations in interdependence
ogy (pp. 260-286). Oxford: Oxford University and autobiographical memory: Lessons from
Press. Korea, China, India, and the United States, In
Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cam- R. Fivush & C. Haden (Eds.), Autobiographical
bridge, MA: MIT Press. memory and the construction of a narrative sell-
remembering 237

developmental and cultural perspectives (pp.73- New York: Worth. (Original work published
08). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. 1978)
Loftusi E. F. (2003). Our changeable memo- Neisser, U., 8c Hyman, I. E., Jr. (2000). Preface.
ries: Legal and practical implications. Nature In Memory observed: Remembering in natural
Reviews Neuroscience, 4, 231-234. contexts (2nd ed., pp. xiii-xiv). New York:
MacDonald, P. S. (2003). History of the concept of Worth.
mind. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate. Nelson, K. (2003). Self and social functions: Indi-
Malcolm, N. (1977). Memory and mind. Ithaca, vidual autobiographical memory and collec-
NY: Cornell University Press. tive narrative. Memory, 11,125-136.
Margalit, A. (2002). The ethics of memory. Cam- Nelson, K., 8c Fivush, R. (2004). The emergence
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press. of autobiographical memory: A social cultural
McClelland, J. L. (1995). Constructive memory developmental theory. Psychological Review,
and memory distortions: A parallel distributed 111, 486-511.
processing approach. In D. L. Schacter (Ed.), Olick, J. K. (1999). Collective memory: The two
Memory distortion: How minds, brains, and cultures. Sociological Theory, 17, 333-348.
societies reconstruct the past (pp. 69-90). Cam- Olick, J. K., 8c Robbins, J. (1998). Social mem-
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ory studies: From "collective memory" to the
McClelland, J. L., & Rumelhart, D. E. (1986). historical sociology of mnemonic practices.
A distributed model of human learning and Annual Review of Sociology, 24,105-140.
memory. In J. L. McClelland 8 1 D . E. Rumel- Petra, L., Benga, O., 8c Tineas, I. (2005). A
hart (Eds.), Parallel distributed processing: dynamic approach to the co-construction
Explorations in the microstructure of cognition of autobiographical memory: Insights from
(Vol. 2, pp. 170-215). Cambridge, MA: MIT dyadic conversations about the past. In Pro-
Press. ceedings of the 2jth Annual Conference of
McCormack, T., 8l Hoerl, C. (2005). Children's the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 1732-1738).
reasoning about the causal significance of the Wheat Ridge, CO: Cognitive Science Society.
temporal order of events. Developmental Psy- Povinelli, D. J., Landry, A. M., Theall, L. A.,
chology, 41,54-63. Clark, B. R., 8c Castille, C. M. (1999). Devel-
Mcllwain, D. (2006). Already filtered: Affec- opment of young children's understanding
tive immersion and personality differences in that the recent past is causally bound to the
accessing present and past. Philosophical Psy- present. Developmental Psychology, 35, 1426-
chology, 19(3), 381-389. H39-
Middleton, D., 8c Brown, S. D. (2005). The social Reese, E. (2002). A model of the origins of auto-
psychology of experience: Studies in remembering biographical memory. In J. W. Fagen 8c H.
and forgetting. London: Sage. Hayne (Eds.), Progress in infancy research (Vol.
Misztal, B. (2003). Theories of social remembering. 2, pp. 215-260). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erl-
Maidenhead, UK: Open University Press. baum.
Moreland, R. L., Argote, L., 8c Krishnan, R. Reese, E., Haden, C. A., 8c Fivush, R. (1993).
(1996). Socially shared cognition at work: Mother-child conversations about the past:
Transactive memory and group performance. Relationships of style and memory over time.
In J. L. Nye 8c A. M. Brower (Eds.), What's Cognitive Development, 8, 403-430.
social about social cognition? Research on Renfrew, C., 8c Scarre, C. (Eds.). (1999). Cogni-
socially shared cognition in small groups (pp. tion and material culture: The archaeology of
57-84). London: Sage. symbolic storage. Cambridge, UK: MacDonald
Mullen, M. K., 8c Yi, S. (1995). The cultural con- Institute for Archaeological Research.
text of talk about the past: Implications for Roediger, H. L. (1996). Memory illusions. Journal
the development of autobiographical mem- of Memory and Language, 35, 76-100.
ory. Cognitive Development, 10, 407-419. Roediger, H. L., Bergman, E. T., 8c Meade, M.
Neisser, U. (1997). The ecological study of mem- L. (2000). Repeated reproduction from mem-
ory. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal ory. In A. Saito (Ed.), Bartlett, culture, and
Society B: Biological Sciences, 352,1697-1701. cognition (pp. 115-134). London: Psychology
Neisser, U. (2000). Memory: What are the impor- Press.
tant questions? Reprinted in U. Neisser 8c I. E. Roediger, H. L., Meade, M. L., 8c Bergman, E. T.
Hyman, Jr. (Eds.), Memory observed: Remem- (2001). Social contagion of memory. Psycho-
bering in natural contexts (2nd ed., pp. 3-18). nomic Bulletin and Review, 8, 365-371.
john sutton

Ross, M. (1989). The relation of implicit theo- actions. In Proceedings of the 271/1 Annual Con-
ries to the construction of personal histories. ference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 211(>_
Psychological Review, 96, 341-357. 2115). Wfaeat Ridge, CO: Cognitive Science
Rowlands, M. (1999). The body in mind: Under- Society.
standing cognitive processes. Cambridge: Cam-Sutton, J. (2002). Porous memory and the cogni-
bridge University Press. tive life of things. In D. Tofts, A. Jonson, & A
Rubin, D. C. (1995). Memory in oral traditions: Cavallaro (Eds.), Prefiguring cyberculture: An
The cognitive psychology of epic, ballads, and intellectual history (pp. 130-141). Cambridge
counting-out rhymes. Oxford: Oxford Univer- MA St. Sydney: MIT Press/Power Publications.
sity Press. Sutton, J. (2003). Memory. In E. N. Zalta
Rumelhart, D. E., Smolensky, P., McClelland, (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philoso-
J. L., & Hinton, G. E. (1986). Schemata and phy. Retrieved May 20, 2008, from http://
sequential thought processes in PDP models. plat0.stanford.edu/archives/spr2003/entries/
In J. L. McClelland & D. E. Rumelhart (Eds.), memory/.
Parallel distributed processing (Vol. 2, pp. 7- Sutton, J. (2004). Representation, reduction, and
57). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. interdisciplinarity in the sciences of mem-
Sanders, J. T. (1985). Experience, memory, and ory. In H. Clapin, P. Staines, 8t P. Slezak
intelligence. Monist, 68, 507-521. (Eds.), Representation in mind: New approaches
Schacter, D. L. (1995). Memory distortion: His- to mental representation (pp. 187-216). Amster-
tory and current status. In D. L. Schacter dam: Elsevier.
(Ed.), Memory distortion: How minds, brains, Sutton, J. (in press). Exograms and interdisci-
and societies reconstruct the past (pp. 1-43). plinarity: History, the extended mind, and the
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. civilizing process. In R. Menary (Ed.), The
Schacter, D. L. (1996). Searching for memory: The extended mind. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.
bruin, the mind, and the past. New York: Basic ter Hark, M. (1995). Electric brain fields and
Books. memory traces: Wittgenstein and Gestalt psy-
Schacter, D. L. (1999). The seven sins of memory. chology. Philosophical Investigations, 18, 113-
American Psychologist, 54,182-203. .38.
Schechtman, M. (1994). The truth about mem- Toth, J. P., § Hunt, R. R. (1999). Not one ver-
ory. Philosophical Psychology, 7, 3-18. sus many; but zero versus any: Structure and
Schwartz, B., & Schuman, H. (2005). History, function in the context of the multiple mem-
commemoration and belief: Abraham Lin- ory systems debate. In J. K. Foster & M. Jeli-
coln in American memory, 1945-2001. Amer- cic (Eds.), Memory: Systems, process, or func-
ican Sociological Review, 70,183-203. tion? (pp. 232-272). Oxford: Oxford University
Sheets-Johnstone, M. (2003). Kinesthetic mem- Press.
ory. Theoria et Historia Scientiarum, 7, 69-92. Tribble, E. (2005). Distributing cognition in
Siegel, D. J, (2001). Memory: An overview, with the globe. Shakespeare Quarterly, 56, 135—
emphasis on developmental, interpersonal, »55-
and neurobiological aspects. Journal of the Tulving, E. (1983). Elements of episodic memory.
American Academy of Child and Adolescent Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Psychiatry, 40,997-1011. Turvey, M. T., & Shaw, R. (1979). The pri-
Smith, L. B., & Thelen, E. (2003). Development macy of perceiving: An ecological reformula-
as a dynamic system. Trends in Cognitive Sci- tion of perception for understanding memory.
ences, 7, 343-348. In L.-G. Nilsson (Ed.), Perspectives on memoiy
Stem, D. G. (1991). Models of memory: Wittgen- research (pp. 167-222). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
stein and cognitive science. Philosophical Psy- Erlbaum.
chology, 4,203-218. van Gelder, T. (1991). What is the "D" in "PDP"?
Strange, D., Gerrie, M. P., Garry, M. (2005). A survey of the concept of distribution. In W.
A few seemingly harmless routes to a false Ramsey, S. P. Stich, &. D. E. Rumelhart (Eds),
memory. Cognitive Processing, 6, 237-242. Philosophy and connectionist theory (pp. 33—59)-
Strauss, C., & Quinn, N. (1997). A cognitive theory Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
of cultural meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge van Leeuwen, C., Verstijnen, L, &. Hekkert,
University Press. P. (1999). Common unconscious dynamics
Sua, T. (2005). In search of the holy grail: Under- underlie uncommon conscious effects: A
standing artefact mediation in social inter- case study in the interaction of perception
remembering

and creation. In J. Jordan (Ed.), Modeling to cognitive science (pp. 518-525). Oxford, UK:
consciousness across the disciplines (pp. 179- Blackwell.
218). Lanham, MD: University Press of Wertsch, J. V. (2002). Voices of collective remem-
America. bering. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Velleman, D. (1997)- How to share an intention. Press.
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 57, Wierzbicka, A. (1992). Semantics, culture, and cog-
29-50. nition: Universal human concepts in culture-
Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mind in society: The devel- specific configurations. Oxford: Oxford Univer-
opment of higher psychological processes. Cam- sity Press.
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Orig- Wilcox, S., & Katz, S. (1981). A direct realist alter-
inal work published 1930) native to the traditional conception of mem-
Wegner, D. M., Erber, R., 8c Raymond, P. (1991). ory. Behaviorism, 9, 227-239.
Transactive memory in close relationships. Wilson, R. A. (2004). Boundaries of the mind.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 61, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
923-929. Wilson, R A. (2005). Collective memory, group
Weldon, M. S., & Bellinger, K. D. (1997). Col- minds, and the extended mind thesis. Cogni-
lective memory: Collaborative and individual tive Processing, 6, 227-236.
processes in remembering. Journal of Exper- Winter, J., 8c Sivan, E. (1999). Setting the frame-
imental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and work. In J. Winter 8c E. Sivan (Eds.), War and
Cognition, 23,1160-1175. remembrance in the twentieth century (pp. 6-
Welzer, H., & Markowitsch, H. J. (2005). 39). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Towards a bio-psycho-social model of auto- Yaron-Antar, A., 8c Nachson, I. (2006). Col-
biographical memory. Memory, 13, 63-78. laborative remembering of emotional events:
Wertsch, J. V. (1999). Mediated action. In W. The case of Rabin's assassination. Memory, 14,
Bechtel 81 G. Graham (Eds.), A companion 46-56.
warn

CHAPTER 14

Situating Concepts

Lawrence W. Barsalou

i. Conceptual Systems gorizations by mapping perceived entities


and events to specific categories; and (4) it
A conceptual system represents an individ- produces inferences based on categorization
ual's knowledge about the world. Concep- about the properties of perceived entities
tual systems differ significantly from record- and events, their origin, what they are likely
ing systems that capture holistic images to do next, how to interact with them, and
(e.g., cameras, tape recorders). Rather than so forth.
being a collection of holistic images, a con- The conceptual system also supports off-
ceptual system is a collection of category line processing during memory, language,
representations, with each category rep- and thought, as people represent entities
resenting a different component of expe- and events not present. During memory pro-
rience. Knowledge of these components cessing, the conceptual system elaborates
includes categories for agents, objects, loca- perceived entities and events at encoding,
tions, times, events, actions, interoceptive organizes them in storage, and produces
states, relations, roles, and properties.' reconstructive memory inferences about
The conceptual system supports the spec- them at retrieval. During language compre-
trum of cognitive activities. During on-line hension, the conceptual system contributes
processing, as people achieve goals in physi- to the interpretation of words, phrases, sen-
cal settings, the conceptual system performs tences, and texts, and to the generation of
many important functions: (1) it supports inferences that augment these interpreta-
perceptual processing via figure-ground seg- tions. During thought, the conceptual sys-
regation, anticipation, and filling in; (2) it tem represents the objects, events, and men-
predicts the entities and events likely to be tal states that constitute the content of
present in the current situation, speeding reasoning, decision making, and problem
up their processing; (3) it produces cate- solving.

6
situating concepts 192
specific systems (e.g., for vision, action,
i.i. The Dominant Theory of the
affect). Instead, these representations con-
Conceptual System: Semantic Memory
tain arbitrary symbols that stand in for
Although modern researchers have enter- modality-specific representations and for the
tained many accounts of the conceptual entities in the world that produce them.
system, the semantic memory view has Third, semantic memory representations
dominated. This way of thinking about are decontextualized. In a typical theory, a
the conceptual system arises from Tulving's category representation is a prototype (or
(1972) classic distinction between episodic definition) that extracts probable (or defini-
and semantic memory. According to this dis- tive) properties across exemplars. Idiosyn-
tinction, episodic memory contains mem- cratic properties of exemplars and back-
ories of specific episodes whose time and ground situations are typically lost in the
location can be remembered, along with distillation process. Thus, the representa-
other memory content. In contrast, seman- tion of BIRD might be a decontextualized
tic memory contains conceptual knowl- prototype that includes wings, feathers, and
edge whose episodic origins have been lost. beak, with idiosyncratic properties and back-
Many subsequent models of the conceptual ground situations filtered out.2 As a conse-
system have instantiated the general con- quence, semantic memory representations
struct of semantic memory, including fea- often seem like encyclopedia entries that
ture set models (e.g., Hampton, 1979; Rosch describe sets of category members generi-
& Mervis, 1975) and network models (e.g., cally.
Collins & Loftus, 1975; Collins & Quillian, Fourth, semantic memory representa-
1969). E. E. Smith (197,8) provides an inte- tions are stable. When representing a given
grative review of these early accounts. Since category, different people share roughly the
then, the central assumptions of seman- same knowledge, and the same person uses
tic memory models continue to shape how the same knowledge on different occasions.
researchers think about the conceptual sys-
tem. Throughout cognitive science and cog-
nitive neuroscience, researchers continue to 1.2. Overview
incorporate various forms of the semantic A different perspective on the conceptual
memory view into their research. system is adopted here. The following two
From the perspective of the alternative sections present the theoretical assump-
view developed here, four critical assump- tions of this approach. Section 2 proposes
tions underlie the semantic memory view that simulations in the brain's modality-
(for further detail, see Barsalou, 2003b). specific systems underlie conceptual pro-
First, semantic memory is a modular sys- cessing. Section 3 proposes that these sim-
tem, being autonomous relative to episodic ulations are inherently situated, tailored to
memory, and relative to systems in the brain guide goal-directed action in particular situ-
for perception, action, and interoception. ations. Section 4 reviews empirical evidence
From this perspective, the conceptual sys- that conceptual representations are situated.
tem does not share representation and pro- Section 5 raises issues for future study.
cessing mechanisms with these other brain
systems but is an independent module that
operates according to different principles. 2. Modality-Specific Simulations
Second, representations in semantic in Conceptual Processing
memory are amodal. Semantic memory rep-
resentations are redescriptions or transduc- In this section, three subsections introduce
tions of modality-specific representations the constructs of reenactment, simulator,
into a new representation language that and simulation, respectively. According to
differs from representations in modality- this account, the conceptual system shares
242lawrencew.b a r s a l o u

mechanisms with modality-specific systems, pattern, w i t h e a c h neuron typically coding


such that the conceptual system is not many d i f f e r e n t patterns (i.e., coarse coding;
modular. As a consequence, conceptual rep- but see Q u i r o g a , R e d d y , Kreimen, Koch
resentations are at least partially modal, not & Fried, 2005). D a m a s i o (1989) refers to
completely amodal. these association areas as convergence zones
and r e v i e w s e v i d e n c e for their presence
at multiple hierarchical levels in the brain
1.1. Reenactments of Perception, Action,
(for f u r t h e r d e v e l o p m e n t of this account
and Interoception
see S i m m o n s 81 Barsalou, 2003). Initially,
Modal reenactments of perceptual, motor, convergence z o n e s near a modality cap-
and interoceptive states constitute the cen- ture patterns t h a t b e c o m e active within it.
tral mechanism of the theory presented Association areas near the visual system cap-
here (for further detail, see Barsalou, 1999b, ture visual representations, whereas associa-
2003a; Damasio, 1989). The reenactments tion areas near t h e auditory system capture
that underlie knowledge are assumed to be auditory representations. Later, cross-modal
approximately the same as the reenactments association areas in t h e temporal, parietal,
underlying mental imagery in working mem- and frontal lobes integrate activations from
ory (e.g., Farah, 2000; Finke, 1989; Grezes different m o d a l i t i e s to establish multimodal
& Decety, 2001; Kosslyn, 1994; Zatorre, representations.
Halpern, Perry, Meyer, & Evans, 1996). T h e
process of reenactment has two phases: (1) 2.1.2. REENACTING MODALITY-SPECIFIC
storing modality-specific states and (2) par- STATES
tially reenacting these states at later times. T h e architecture j u s t presented has the abil-
Each is addressed in turn. ity to partially r e e n a c t t h e multimodal rep-
resentations it c a p t u r e s . O n c e conjunctive
2.1.1. STORING MODALITY-SPECIFIC neurons across association areas capture a
STATES collection of modality-specific features, they
When an entity or event is experienced, it can later r e a c t i v a t e t h e s e features for repre-
activates feature detectors in the modality- sentational p u r p o s e s . To remember an expe-
specific systems that perceive and act on it. rience w i t h a dog, f o r example, conjunc-
While processing a dog visually, for exam- tive neurons partially reactivate the visual
ple, neurons in the visual system fire for states active w h i l e perceiving it. To remem-
edges and planar surfaces, whereas oth- ber an action p e r f o r m e d on the dog, con-
ers fire for color, movement, and config- junctive n e u r o n s partially reactivate the rel-
ural properties. The activations across this evant m o t o r states. T h e reenactment process
distributed, hierarchically organized system never p r o d u c e s a c o m p l e t e reinstatement of
represent the entity visually (e.g., Zeki, the original e x p e r i e n c e . In addition, a wide
1993). Analogous activations in other sen- variety of biases m a y enter in and distort
sory systems represent how the dog feels to it. A l m o s t a l w a y s , reenactments tend to be
the touch and how it sounds. Activations partial and s o m e w h a t biased. Most impor-
in the motor system execute actions while tant, h o w e v e r , s o m e semblance of the orig-
interacting with the dog. Other activations inal state is r e e n a c t e d . A m o d a l symbols are
underlie the interoceptive states that arise not d e p l o y e d . 3
during the interaction, such as activations in C o n s c i o u s e x p e r i e n c e s do not always ac-
the amygdalae and orbitofirontal cortex that c o m p a n y t h e r e e n a c t m e n t process. Al-
represent emotional reactions. though c o n s c i o u s reenactment is typically
As feature representations become active assumed to a c c o m p a n y mental imagery,
in a modality, conjunctive neurons in asso- reenactments n e e d n o t produce conscious
ciation areas capture them for representa- mental images. Instead, the reenactments
tional purposes on later occasions. A pop- that underlie m e m o r y , conceptualization,
ulation of conjunctive neurons codes the c o m p r e h e n s i o n , a n d reasoning may often
situating concepts 194

be unconscious to a large extent (Barsalou, construing it as a category member and pro-


1999b). viding inferences based on previous mem-
bers (Barsalou, 2003a). The simulator func-
tions as a type that interprets the instance as
2.2. Simulators and Simulations a token in a type-token relation.
Barsalou (1999b, 2003a) proposed that a fully Consider the simulator for the category
functional conceptual system can be built on of D O G S . Across experiences with different
reenactment mechanisms (for a brief review, dogs, visual information about dogs becomes
see Barsalou, Simmons, Barbey, & Wilson, integrated in the simulator, along with audi-
2003b). As these articles illustrate, reenact- tory information, somatosensory informa-
ment mechanisms can be used to implement tion, motor procedures, affective responses,
the type-token distinction, categorical infer- and so forth. Over time, a distributed sys-
ence, productivity, propositions, abstract tem develops throughout the brain's feature
concepts, and a wide variety of basic cogni- and association areas that accumulates con-
tive processes, including working memory, ceptual content for the category.
short-term memory, language comprehen-
sion, and various forms of thought. Because 2.2.2. SIMULATIONS
these phenomena are not relevant here, they Once a simulator exists for a category, it
will not be addressed further. reenacts subsets of its content as simula-
The two central constructs of this tions. Not all of the content in a simulator
approach are simulators and simulations. becomes active at once. Instead, only a small
Whereas simulators integrate multimodal subset becomes active to represent the cat-
information across a category's instances, egory in a given situation (for further detail,
simulations represent specific conceptual- see Barsalou, 1987, 1989, 1993). Thus, the
izations of the category. Each construct is D O G simulator might simulate a sleeping
addressed in turn. puppy on one occasion, whereas on others it
might simulate a working sheepdog or a dog
2.2.1. SIMULATORS pulling its master along a sidewalk. Because
The properties of a category's members tend a tremendous amount of experienced con-
to be correlated (e.g., McRae, de Sa, & Sei- tent for dogs resides in the DOG simulator,
denberg, 1997; Rosch & Mervis, 1975)- As diverse subsets are simulated across different
a result, interacting with different instances situations.
of the same category should activate similar Simulations can serve many different cog-
neural patterns in feature systems (cf. Cree nitive functions (Barsalou, 1999b, 2003a).
& McRae, 2003; Farah & McClelland, 1991; Simulations can represent a category's in-
McCrae & Cree, 2002). In turn, similar popu- stances during memory, language, and
lations of conjunctive neurons in association thought. Simulations can produce infer-
areas tuned to these particular conjunctions ences about a category's perceived instances,
of features should tend to capture these sim- using the pattern completion procedure
ilar patterns (Simmons & Barsalou, 2003). described later. Simulations can combine
Across different category members, a multi- productively to construct infinitely many
modal representation of the category results, conceptual combinations. Simulations, to-
distributed across relevant feature systems gether with simulators, can represent the
and the association areas that integrate classic truth-evaluable propositions that
them. According to Barsalou (1999b) each underlie interpretation and comprehension.
of these distributed systems is a simulator Simulations can also represent novel cate-
that functions as a conceptual type, because gory instances not stored in a simulator from
it integrates the multimodal content of a cat- previous experience. For example, instances
egory across its experience members. Later, stored previously may merge together dur-
when an instance of the category is per- ing retrieval to produce reconstruction and
ceived, the simulator becomes bound to it, averaging effects. Remembering a previous
244 lawrence w. barsalou
dog seen just once might be distorted toward that a listener represents the claim (perhaps
a similar dog seen many times. Additionally, as a simulation), compares it to percep-
deliberate efforts to combine simulations of tion of the actual situation, and decides
conceptual components can produce simu- whether the claim interprets the situation
lations that do not correspond to an expe- accurately. If the simulated claim repre-
rienced category member. Someone could sents the perceived situation accurately, the
simulate a dog and then vary simulations claim is interpreted as true. Thus, TRUTH
of its color and patterning systematically to is grounded in a complex multimodal sit-
represent a wide variety of novel dogs never uation extended over time. According to
experienced. this account, people simulate situations like
these to represent abstract concepts and
2.2.3. TYPES OF SIMULATORS focus attention on relevant content within
A potentially infinite number of simula- them. For TRUTH, people focus on the
tors can become established in the cog- speaker's claim, their simulation of its mean-
nitive system. Simulators can develop for ing, their perception of the corresponding
all aspects of experience, including agents, situation, their comparison of the simulated
objects, properties, settings, events, actions, claim to the perceived situation, and their
interoceptions, and so forth. In general, a conclusion about whether the two match.
simulator develops for any component of Although much of the situation is back-
experience that attention selects repeatedly grounded, it frames the focal content dis-
(Barsalou, 1999b, 2003a). For example, if tributed across multimodal content in per-
attention focuses repeatedly on a type of ception, action, and interoception.
object (e.g., DOGS), a simulator develops Besides offering this simulation-based
for it. Analogously, if attention focuses on account of TRUTH, Barsalou (1999b) also
a type of action (e.g., SCRATCHING) or offers accounts of NEGATION and
on a type of interoception (e.g., LOVE), DISJUNCTION, and suggests similar ap-
simulators also develop to represent them. proaches for implementing mathematical
The open-ended potential to establish sim- and logical reasoning. In general, many
ulators is consistent with Schyns, Goldstone, abstract concepts, such as FREEDOM and
and Thibaut's (1998) proposal that the flex- INVENTION, can be viewed as grounded
ible use of selective attention creates new in complex simulations of multimodal
primitive properties that become relevant situations, with simulated content about
for categorization. Notably, these proper- events, interoceptive states, and the rela-
ties do not result from combining existing tions between them being foregrounded.
properties productively, but instead result Barsalou and Wiemer-Hastings (2005)
from focusing attention on regions of per- and Wiemer-Hastings, Krug, and Xu (2001)
ception for which no primitive property offer preliminary support for this proposal.
currendy exists. Whenever the flexible and First, they show that the meanings of both
open-ended process of attention selects a abstract and concrete concepts are situated.
component of experience repeatedly, a sim- In general, people appear to frame concepts
ulator develops for the component, repre- in terms of situations, often producing broad
senting it conceptually in a wide variety of situational content when asked to describe
cognitive processes.4 concepts. Just as people frame abstract con-
Another central issue is how simula- cepts in situations, they similarly situate
tors represent abstract concepts. According concrete concepts in situations, as when rep-
to Barsalou (1999b), simulators for abstract resenting HAMMER in the context of its
concepts are grounded in situations. Con- functional use. Second, these researchers
sider how a simulator might represent one show that subjects focus on aspects of the
everyday sense of TRUTH. Imagine that a situation central to the meaning of spe-
speaker makes a claim about a situation, cific concepts, describing these aspects more
such as, "It's sunny outside." Further imagine than less relevant ones. Whereas subjects
situating concepts 192

focus on the physical aspects of situations tions to represent a category, they should
when representing concrete concepts (e.g., simulate the category in relevant percep-
objects, settings, simple actions), they focus tual situations, not in isolation. When peo-
on other aspects of situations for abstract ple conceptualize D O G , for example, they
concepts (e.g., events, interoceptions, the should simulate not only a dog but also a
relations between them). Clearly, much fur- more complete perceptual situation, includ-
ther theory and research is necessary to ing the surrounding space, along with any
develop this account of abstract concepts. relevant agents, objects, events, actions, and
interoceptions.

y Situating C o n c e p t s
3.2. Origins of Situated Concepts
This section begins with an analogy: con- T h e situational analogy between perception
ceptual representations are situated because and conception may reflect two origins: evo-
perceptions are situated. A second sub- lutionary convenience and optimizing pre-
section suggests that concepts are situ- diction. Each is addressed in turn.
ated because of evolutionary convenience
and computational efficacy. A third section 3.2.1. EVOLUTIONARY CONVENIENCE
presents definitions for concepts, situations, As described earlier, the human concep-
and the relations between them. T h e final tual system appears to be grounded in the
section presents the central construct of sit- brain's modality-specific systems. One rea-
uated conceptualization. son for this relation between perception and
cognition may be that evolution capitalized
on existing brain mechanisms to implement
3.1. A Situational Analogy from Perception
conceptual systems rather than creating new
to Conception mechanisms (e.g., Gould, 1991).
If simulation underlies conceptual process- If so, the importance of situations in
ing, a potential implication for the repre- conception could simply reflect the impor-
sentation of concepts follows: if a concep- tance of situations in perception, such that
tual representation simulates a perceptual the presence of situations in conception
experience, it should simulate a situation, is largely accidental and inconsequential.
because situations provide the background As described next, however, there is good
of perceptual experiences. To see this anal- reason to believe that situations play fun-
ogy, consider the content of perception. damentally important roles in optimizing
At any given moment, people perceive the cognitive processing. Rather than merely
space around them, which may include being an accident, situational representa-
agents, objects, and events. T h e i r percep- tions make cognitive computation tractable.
tual experience is multimodal, potentially
containing visual, auditory, tactile, gusta- 3.2.2. OPTIMIZING PREDICTION
tory, olfactory, proprioceptive, and intero- Researchers across multiple disciplines have
ceptive information. Most important, w h e n argued that situating cognition greatly
people focus attention on a particular entity enhances cognitive processing. During lan-
or event in perception, they continue to per- guage comprehension, a text can be incom-
ceive the background situation. T h e situa- prehensible if the relevant situation is not
tion does not disappear, leaving the focal apparent (e.g., Bransford & Johnson, 1973).
entity or event in a perceptual vacuum. During conversation, shared situations help
If perceptions take the f o r m of situa- human speakers establish common ground
tions, and if conceptual representations sim- (e.g., Clark, 1992); shared situations also help
ulate perceptions, then conceptual repre- nonhuman communicators (e.g., Smith,
sentations should take the f o r m of perceived 1977). Extensive evidence demonstrates
situations. When people construct simula- that situation models underlie people's
LAWRENCE W. BARSALOU

representations of text meaning (e.g., San- kitchens, dining rooms, offices). Such infer-
ford & Garrod, 1981; Zwaan & Kaschak, ences also provide important information
this volome; Zwaan & Radvansky, 1998). about nearby objects and likely actions
In general, language comprehension appears Representing a table in a dining room, for
to be a heavily situated process (Barsalou, example, is likely to also represent nearby
1999a). During problem solving and reason- chairs, which could be helpful while plan-
ing, drawing valid conclusions without the ning actions in the situation, such as sitting
support of concrete situations is often diffi- at the table to eat. As this example illus-
cult (e.g., Cheng & Holyoak, 1985; Gick & trates, situating an object concept produces
Holyoak, 1980; Johnson-Laird, 1983). In cog- a broad range of inferences useful to goal-
nitive development, situations appear cen- directed pursuit.
tral to acquiring cognitive and social skills Framing concepts with respect to situa-
(e.g., Vygotsky, 1991). During social inter- tions also increases the specificity of infer-
action, situations are central to predict- ences. Once the background situation for
ing behavior (e.g., Mischel, 1968; Smith & a focal object is known, specific inferences
Semin, 2004; Smith & Conrey, this volume). about the object's properties follow. For
In linguistics, situations underlie the theory example, when one expects to find a chair in
of construction grammar, with the content a dining room, the chair is likely to have four
and relations of syntactic structures evolv- long legs, a relatively flat and rigid seat, and a
ing out of die analogous structure in situa- relatively upright back. In general, knowing
tions (e.g., Goldberg, 1995). In philosophy, the situation produces a variety of specific
situations motivated the theory of situation inferences about everything found in the sit-
semantics, with logical inference being opti- uation, along with specific relations between
mized in the context of specific situa- them. Drawing inferences about a particular
tions (e.g., Akman, this volume; Barwise & chair and its relations to other setting objects
Perry, 1983). In artificial intelligence, situ- depends on whether the chair is found in a
ating robotic cognition in physical environ- dining room, living room, office, theater, jet,
ments gready enhances practical intelligence ski lift, and so on.
(Brooks, 1991; Kirsh, 1991). At a broader By organizing knowledge around situa-
level, general arguments about the central- tions, the cognitive system greatly simpli-
ity of situations in cognition have been pre- fies the many tasks it faces. Rather than
sented by Clark (1997), Dunbar (1991), Glen- searching through everything in memory,
berg (1997), Greeno (1998), Barsalou et al. the system need only focus on the knowl-
(1993), and Barsalou (2003b). edge and skills relevant for the current
Situations appear to enhance cognitive situation. Knowing the current situation
processing by optimizing prediction. Specif- makes it easier to recognize objects and
ically, these benefits appear to result from events, to retrieve relevant knowledge and
increasing the breadth and specificity of skills, to understand language, to solve prob-
inference. Situations broaden inference by lems, and to predict the actions of other
extending processing beyond a focal object agents. Clearly, entities and events can occur
or event. When representing TABLE, for in unexpected situations. As the literature
example, a conceptual system could sim- illustrates overwhelmingly, however, such
ply infer the likely properties of a table per occurrences challenge processing consider-
se. Such isolated inferences, however, omit ably. In contrast, when entities and events
broader situational information that may be occur in their expected situations, process-
highly useful for processing. If one wishes ing is relatively easy and effective. 5
to find a table, for example, it is helpful to
know locations that contain them. By repre-
senting tables conceptually in their respec- 3.3. Definitions
tive situations, agents can draw immediate
Now that the relation between concepts and
inferences about where to find them (e.g.,
situations has been introduced, each can be
SITUATING CONCEPTS 198

defined a little more carefully. As will be simulators for settings, agent», events, and
apparent, developing such definitions is crit- interoceptive states become linked to simu-
ical, because a central question is whether lators for objects, thereby representing their
situational content resides inside or outside background situations.
concepts. As will be seen, the latter possibil-
ity is pursued. 3.3.2. SITUATIONS
Within the framework developed here, a sit-
1.3.1. CONCEPTS uation is a region of perceived space that
It is first important to distinguish between surrounds a focal entity over a temporal
concepts acquired from experience versus duration, perceived from the subjective per-
concepts established by means of produc- spective of an agent. The space surrounding
tivity and reasoning. Of primary interest the entity may include various entities and
here are concepts acquired f r o m experi- events, and the agent's subjective perspec-
ence. Nevertheless, it is possible for people tive on the region may contain a variety of
to combine concepts acquired f r o m experi- interoceptive states. For detailed accounts of
ence to represent concepts that they have situational content, see the coding schemes
never experienced (e.g., STRIPED WATER- in Wu and Barsalou (2008), Cree and McRae
FALLS), concepts that do not exist (e.g., (2003), and Barsalou and Wiemer-Hastings
UNICORNS), and concepts that are impos- (2005)7
sible (e.g., SQUARE CIRCLES). Barsalou Within this framework, simulators for
(1999b, 2003a) proposes h o w simulation- settings, events, mental states, and so forth
based approaches can represent these latter combine to represent background situations
concepts. Wu and Barsalou (2008) offer pre- (e.g., Barsalou, 2003b; Barsalou et al., 1993;
liminary evidence. Barsalou, Niedenthal, Barbey, & Ruppert,
Within the framework developed here, 2003a). When people represent someone
a concept acquired f r o m experience is working in an office chair, simulators for the
the accumulated information in m e m o r y setting (OFFICE), the action (SITTING),
extracted for a category via selective atten- and the interoception (e.g., THINKING)
tion, where a category is a set of things might all contribute simulations to the over-
all representation of the background situ-
perceived as the same type for one of
ation for this particular chair. When the
many possible reasons. As described ear-
exemplar of the category changes, so do
lier, a multimodal simulator implements a
the simulations that combine to represent
concept, where a simulator is an organized
its background situation. When people con-
body of knowledge that produces specific
ceptualize sitting in a living room chair, for
simulations of a category's instances. For
example, simulators for LIVING ROOM
example, the simulator for CHAIR might
and RELAXING might contribute to the
simulate a DINING ROOM CHAIR, a
background situation, and the simulator for
LIVING ROOM RECLINER, an OFFICE
SITTING contributes a different simulation
SWIVEL CHAIR, and so on. W h a t links
of sitting.
all these different conceptualizations of
CHAIR together is the fact that a c o m m o n
simulator produces them. Although tremen- 3.3.3. RELATIONS BETWEEN CONCEPTS
dous variation exists at the level of simula- AND SIMULATIONS
tions, stability exists at the level of simula- As these definitions illustrate, this approach
tors, because a relatively discrete simulator assumes that information about concepts
represents a category. 6 is abstracted. Nevertheless, this abstracted
A central assumption is that the simulator content remains tightly coupled with the
for a category does not include background background situations that framed it origi-
situations. Instead, the simulator represents nally. As we shall see in the literature review
only information abstracted f r o m category to follow, these relations between concepts
exemplars per se. As described shortly, other and situations constantly come into play
244 LAWRENCE W. BARSALOU

during conceptual processing, thereby pro- Barsalou (2003b) referred to a particu-


ducing ubiquitous situation effects. lar package of situation-specific inferences
as a situated conceptualization. For exam-
ple, the simulator for D O G can activate
3.4. Situated Conceptualizations
many different situated conceptualizations,
Barsalou (2003b) contrasts two theoretical each tailored to helping an agent interact
perspectives that researchers have taken on with dogs in different contexts. No general
concepts (see also Barsalou, 1999a). Many description of the category exists, although
researchers view concepts implicidy as attempts to construct ad hoc generalizations
detached databases, as in traditional seman- can occur online (Barsalou, 2003a). One
tic memory theories. According to this per- conceptualization for D O G might support
spective, the properties and exemplars of a interacting with a timid puppy, whereas oth-
category are integrated during learning into ers might support interacting with a defen-
a database of information about the category sive guard dog, or with a dog that wants to
that is relatively detached from the goals and chase a ball. From this perspective, the con-
situations relevant to specific agents. These cept for DOG is not a detached statistical
databases capture the statistical properties database of category information. Instead,
of a category and can be consulted when the concept is the ability to construct a wide
these statistical tendencies are of interest. In variety of situated conceptualizations that
support goal achievement in diverse con-
many such theories, but not all, it is often
texts.
further assumed that a person uses the same
general abstraction established for a cate-
gory to represent it in different situations. 3.4.1. MULTIMODAL SIMULATIONS
For example, the same prototype or rule IMPLEMENT SITUATED
for CHAIR is used to represent a currently CONCEPTUALIZATIONS
experienced chair, regardless of whether it Within the framework developed here, a
is an office chair, living room chair, jet chair, complex simulation becomes active across
or theater chair. modalities to implement a situated concep-
Alternatively, concepts can be viewed as tualization (for further detail, see Barsalou,
agent-dependent instruction manuals. On a 2003b; Barsalou et al., 2003a). Consider a sit-
given occasion, a concept delivers a spe- uated conceptualization for interacting with
cialized package of inferences to guide an a dog that seeks petting. This conceptualiza-
agent's interactions with a particular cate- tion simulates h o w the dog appears percep-
gory instance in the current situation. Across tually. When dogs want petting, their bodies
different situations, the same concept deliv- adopt particular shapes, they perform cer-
ers different packages of inferences, each tai- tain actions, and they produce distinctive
lored to current instances, goals, and other sounds. All of this perceptual content can
situational constraints. Because a single gen- be represented as modal simulations in the
eral description would be too vague to sup- situated conceptualization.
port all the relevant inferences in a particular A situated conceptualization about a dog
situation, more specialized representations that seeks petting is also likely to simulate
are constructed instead. From this perspec- actions that the agent could take in the situ-
tive, a concept is neither a static database nor ation, such as petting the dog. Again, modal
a single abstraction, instead, it is an ability or simulations can represent these aspects of
competence to produce specialized category the situated conceptualization, this time via
representations that support goal pursuit simulations in the motor system.
in the current setting, where each special- A situated conceptualization about a dog
ized representation is akin to an instruction that seeks petting is also likely to include
manual for interacting with a particular cat- simulations of interoceptive states. Because
egory member. people experience particular internal states
situating concepts 192
while petting dogs, the respective situated becomes entrenched in memory, thereby
conceptualizations include simulations of supporting automated performance in
motivations, goals, emotions, and so on. them. Entrenched knowledge can also be
Finally, a situated conceptualization for a extended analogically to interactions in
dog that seeks petting is also likely to simu- novel situations that are similar to famil-
late a setting in which the event could take iar situations (e.g., Andersen & Chen, 2002).
place. The event is not simulated in a vac- Although entrenched knowledge may not
uum. Thus, petting a dog might be simu- always fit perfectly, it may often fit well
lated in a kitchen, yard, park, and so on. enough to provide useful inferences.
Again, such knowledge is represented with Within the framework developed here,
a simulation, this time as a reenactment of a situated conceptualizations represent peo-
particular setting. ple's entrenched knowledge of repeated
In summary, a situated conceptualization situations. As a situation is experienced
is defined as typically simulating four basic repeatedly, multimodal knowledge accrues
types of situational content: (1) perceptions in the respective simulators for the rel-
of relevant people and objects, (2) agentive evant objects, people, actions, interocep-
actions and other bodily states, (3) intero- tions, and settings. Specifically, the com-
ceptive states, such as motivations, emo- ponents of the situated conceptualization
tions, and cognitive operations, and (4) likely become entrenched in the respective sim-
settings. Thus, a situated conceptualization ulators, as do associations between these
is a multimodal simulation of a multicompo- components. Over time, the situated con-
nent situation, with each modality-specific ceptualization becomes so well established
component simulated in the respective brain in memory that it comes to mind automati-
areas. Barsalou (2005) conjectures that situ- cally as a unit when the situation is detected.
ated conceptualizations provide continuity After petting a particular dog on many occa-
of the conceptual system across species, on sions, for example, the situated conceptuali-
the basis of evidence for situated conceptu- zation that represents this situation becomes
alizations in monkeys (Gil-da-Costa et al., entrenched, such that minimal cumg acti-
2004), and the likely presence of them in vates it on later occasions.
other organisms. Once situated conceptualizations be-
Finally, a situated conceptualization come entrenched in memory, they play im-
places the conceptualizer directly in the portant roles throughout cognition. In per-
respective situation, creating the experi- ception, they support efficient processing of
ence of being there (Barsalou, 2002). By re- familiar scenes (e.g., Biederman, 1981). In
enacting agentive actions and interoceptive memory, they produce reconstructive mem-
states during the process of representing cat- ory retrieval (e.g., Brewer & Treyens, 1981}
egories, situated conceptualizations create In language, they produce situation mod-
the experience of the conceptualizer being els and diverse forms of inference (e.g.,
in the situation. The situation is not repre- Zwaan & Radvansky, 1998). In reasoning,
sented as detached and separate from the they provide background content that facil-
conceptualizer. The conceptualizer is in the itates deduction (e.g., Johnson-Laird, 1983).
representation. In social cognition, they provide inferences
about myriad aspects of interpersonal inter-
3.4.2. ENTRENCHED SITUATED action (e.g., Barsalou et al., 2003a).
CONCEPTUALIZATIONS
Over the course of their lives, people expe- 3.4.3. PATTERN-COMPLETION
rience many situations over and over again INFERENCES
in their interactions with people, artifacts, Entrenched situated conceptualizations sup-
social institutions, and so on. In the process, port these diverse forms of cognition via
knowledge about these familiar situations a pattern completion inference process. A
246 lawrence w. barsalou

àbiated conceptualization can be viewed as essentially an attractor, that is, an associ-


a pattern; namely, a complex configuration ated collection of simulations that is easy
of multimodal components that represents to settle on because t h e associations linking
the respective situation. When a compo- them have b e c o m e strong through frequent
nent of this pattern matches something in a use. Infinitely m a n y states near the attrac-
perceived situation (e.g., a person, a setting, tor, however, o f f e r d i f f e r e n t versions of the
an object), the pattern becomes active in same conceptualization, each representing a
memory, with the unobserved pattern com- different adaptation to the situation. Thus
ponents constituting inferences about what the entrenched conceptualization for inter-
else could be present. Because the remainingacting with a dog that seeks petting is not
components have occurred frequently with a static representation, b u t rather the abil-
the perceived components in the past, infer- ity to produce m a n y related simulations. On
ring the remaining components is plausible. encountering the s a m e situation on differ-
Thus, when a partially viewed situation acti- ent occasions, t h e situated conceptualiza-
vates a situated conceptualization, the con- tions that guide processing vary dynamically,
ceptualization completes the pattern that depending on a w i d e variety of factors that
the situation suggests. It is useful for the influence the contributing simulators.
agent to anticipate what will happen next, As a c o n s e q u e n c e , t h e inferences that
so that optimal goals can be adopted and arise via pattern c o m p l e t i o n also vary
optimal actions taken. The agent attempts dynamically. As t h e conceptualizations that
to draw inferences that go beyond the represent a situation v a r y across occasions,
information given (e.g., Bruner, 1957). the pattern c o m p l e t i o n s that follow also
Consider the example of seeing a partic- vary. S o m e w h a t d i f f e r e n t inferences result
ular dog. Imagine that the dog's face, fur, from completing s o m e w h a t different pat-
and bark initially match modality-specific terns.
simulations in one or more situated concep-
tualizations that have become entrenched
in memory for DOG. Once one concep- 4. Evidence for Situated Concepts
tualization comes to dominate the activa-
tion process, it provides inferences via pat- This section r e v i e w s evidence for the
tern completion, such as actions that this account of situated c o n c e p t s just presented.
particular dog is likely to take, responses Although e v i d e n c e f o r t h e modality-specific
that the agent typically makes, interoceptive nature of c o n c e p t s is n o t presented, it is
states that typically result, and so forth. The reviewed e l s e w h e r e (e.g., Barsalou, 2003b,
unfolding of these pattern completion infer- 2008; Barsalou, S i m m o n s , Barbey, & Wilson,
ences - realized as simulations - produces 2003b; Martin, 2001; Thompson-Schill, 2003;
useful prediction. see also Pecher 8l Z w a a n , 2005). T h e review
of situation e f f e c t s here, h o w e v e r , assumes
3.4.4. THE STATISTICAL CHARACTER that multimodal simulations represent situ-
OF INFERENCE ated conceptualizations.
All aspects of the pattern completion infer- T h e first e v i d e n c e r e v i e w e d for situa-
ence process have a statistical character (e.g.,tion effects illustrates classic effects in mem-
Barsalou, 1987,1989,1993; Smith & Samuel- ory and conceptualization. W h e n concepts
son, 1997). Each simulator that contributes become active, a c c o m p a n y i n g representa-
to a situated conceptualization is a dynam- tions of situations b e c o m e active as well.
ical system capable of producing infinite In turn, situational representations dynam-
simulations (Barsalou, 1999b, 2003a, 2003b). ically a f f e c t t h e c o n t e n t of the concepts
In a given situation, each simulation con- they f r a m e . T h e s e c o n d and third sub-
structed reflects the current state of the sim- sections r e v i e w e v i d e n c e f o r situated con-
ulator, its current inputs, and its past history.ceptualizations in c o g n i t i v e psychology and
An entrenched situated conceptualization is social psychology, r e s p e c t i v e l y . In each case,
situatingconcepts192

situated inferences about objects, people, one view, all information for a concept is
settings, action, interoceptions, and perspec- active in every situation. However, informa-
tives become active to guide goal pursuit in tion that is relevant in the current situation
specific situations. T h e fourth and final sub- is weighted more heavily than information
section reviews evidence for the central role that is not irrelevant. According to a sec-
of situations in representing abstract con- ond view, only a small subset of a concept's
cepts. Although all concepts appear to be content is active in a given situation (Barsa-
framed in relevant situations, abstract con- lou, 1987,1989,1993). Only a small subset is
cepts appear to rely on them particularly active for two reasons. First, because much
heavily. of the possible content for a concept is likely
to reside at low levels of accessibility in
memory, it is unlikely that it all becomes
4,1. Evidence for Situated Representation
active simultaneously. Second, if all of this
in Memory and Conceptualization
information did become active at once,
Yeh and Barsalou (2006) review classic sit- it would produce a computational night-
uation effects in memory and conceptual mare. While processing an office chair, for
processing. In particular, the literature that example, activating information about living
they review supports two theses about the room chairs, jet chairs, and theater chairs
relations between concepts and situations. 9 would be distracting and potentially mis-
According to thesis 1, situational informa- leading. Although current evidence proba-
tion is linked to concepts, producing the bly does not distinguish between these two
following two consequences. W h e n a con- accounts of how thesis 2 is implemented,
cept becomes active, it activates associ- the second account is probably more plau-
ated situations. Conversely, w h e n a situation sible. Regardless, both views are consistent
becomes active, it activates associated con- with thesis 2, proposing that the information
cepts. Because tables are stored with dining most functional for a concept varies across
rooms, activating the concept for DINING situations. Exactly how the functionally rel-
ROOM is likely to activate TABLE. Con- evant content of a concept is implemented
versely, activating TABLE is likely to acti- remains an important issue.
vate DINING ROOM. Thus, concepts tend Y e h and Barsalou (2006) first review evi-
to be processed not in a v a c u u m but in a dence from the episodic memory literature
situated manner. that supports theses 1 and 2. One might
According to thesis 2, a concept produces wonder why findings from episodic memory
different conceptualizations in different sit- are relevant to situation effects on concepts.
uations, with each form relevant to the cur- Because concepts enter centrally into mem-
rent situation. Thus, the concept TABLE ory during encoding, storage, and retrieval,
may be represented as an attractive wooden however, episodic memory provides a win-
table in a dining room or as a more functional dow on conceptual processing. People do
but less attractive table in an office. Con- not simply store and retrieve surface stim-
versely, activating the concept of DINING uli, such as pictures and words, in the way
ROOM tends to produce conceptualizations that cameras and audio recorders do (Barsa-
of TABLE that are attractive and wooden, lou, 1999b). Instead, concepts become active
whereas activating OFFICE tends to acti- at encoding as people process stimuli, such
vate conceptualizations of TABLE that are that the stored memory contains concep-
more functional and less attractive. Most tual information as well as the actual infor-
important, concepts are not represented as mation presented (e.g., Craik 81 Lockhart,
generic, highly abstracted data structures. 1972). Furthermore, concepts become active
Instead, their content is tailored to the cur- at retrieval, producing extensive effects of
rent situation. reconstructive memory (e.g., Bartlett, 1932).
Thesis 2 could be implemented compu- For these reasons, phenomena from the
tationally in at least t w o ways. According to episodic memory literature provide a rich
252lawrencew.barsalou

window onto situation effects in conceptual situation provided access to the episodic
processing. memory.
Consider an example for episodic mem- Yeh and Barsalou (2006) also review
ory of visual objects. In Mandler and Stein research that assesses the role of situations
(19-4), children viewed a pictured set of in conceptual processing more directly. In
objects either arranged as in a real-world sit- particular, they review situation effects in
uation or arranged randomly. Several pieces classic conceptual tasks, such as categori-
of furniture, for example, might be shown zation, lexical decision, property verifica-
arranged as in a living room, or they might be tion, and property generation. As in episodic
shown spatially scrambled. When the chil- memory, people exhibit widespread situa-
dren later recalled the objects, they remem- tion effects that are consistent with theses 1
bered more from the meaningfully arranged and 2. Because conceptual knowledge devel-
sets than from the randomly arranged ones. ops from episodic memories, these parallels
Consistent with thesis 1, viewing mean- are not surprising. Just as episodic memo-
ingfully organized objects activated scene ries exhibit a situated character, so does the
schemata, which organized and elaborated conceptual knowledge that evolves out of
the presented visual objects. As a result, them. During the abstraction of concepts
the children were later able to remem- from experience, concepts do not discard
ber the objects and their positions better their situational histories.
than when they had not imagined situations Consider one example each from the
for the scrambled scenes. As this finding, and visual object processing and language pro-
many others like it, illustrates the episodic cessing literatures. Classic work by Bieder-
memory literature provides extensive sup- man (1972) found that people categorize a
port for thesis 1. As people encode stimuli visually presented object faster in a coher-
into long-term memory, situational repre- ent background scene than in a jumbled
sentations become active, such that situa- one, when the object's location in the dis-
tional information is stored in the resultant play is cued beforehand. Consistent with
memory representation. thesis 1, the ability to process the object
Much evidence from the episodic mem- in a coherent scene facilitated object cate-
ory literature is also consistent with thesis gorization. Recognizing the scene produced
2, namely, the situation present at encod- top-down activation to associated object cat-
ing - either actual or inferred - affects the egories that facilitated recognizing the tar-
content stored for the stimulus. Consider get object. Conversely, when the ability to
a classic experiment by Barclay, Bransford, process the scene was compromised (i.e., in
Franks, McCarrell, andNitsch (1974). Partic- the jumbled scenes), categorization suffered
ipants studied a critical word (e.g., "piano") because top-down support was not avail-
in a sentence that stressed either its physi- able.
cal properties ("The man lifted the piano") Classic work by Miller and Isard (1963)
or its musical properties ("The man tuned similarly showed that the ability to identify
the piano"). At test, participants received spoken words was more accurate when the
a cue for recalling the critical word (e.g., words belonged to a meaningful sentence
"piano"). For some participants, the cue was than when the words belonged to an anoma-
related to the specific meaning of the criti- lous sentence. Again, when associations
cal word in the sentence (e.g., "heavy" for between focal categories and backgrounds
the sentence about moving a piano). For situations remained intact, categorization
other participants, the cue was unrelated benefited. Analogous to categorizing objects
(e.g., "nice sound" from the sentence about in coherent scenes, categorizing words in
moving a piano). Consistent with thesis 2, coherent sentences produced beneficial top-
recall was better with related cues than with down support.
unrelated cues. When the cue activated the Many other findings from the visual-
situation stored with the target word, the object and language-processing literatures
SITUATING CONCEPTS 198

further document the tight coupling be- for the four types of inference that under-
tween categories and background situations. lie situated conceptualization is reviewed in
Thus theses 1 and 2 apply to diverse stimu- turn.
lus domains and diverse forms of process-
ing performed on them. In general, con- 4.2.1. CONTEXTUALIZED CATEGORY
cepts and situations are closely coupled, INFERENCES
such that each activates the other, and situ- Evidence from multiple literatures shows
ations dynamically affect the content repre- that concepts do not produce the same rep-
sented for a concept on a particular occasion. resentation in a situation invariant man-
ner (e.g., Barsalou, 2003b; Yeh & Barsalou,
2006). Instead a concept produces one of
4,2. Evidence for Situated
many possible representations tailored to
Conceptualizations from Cognitive the current context. In on-line studies of
Psychology sentence processing, context effects on lex-
Barsalou (2003b) reviews evidence that sup- ical access are widespread (e.g., Barsalou,
ports the construct of situated conceptual- 1982; Kellas, Paul, Martin, & Simpson, 1991;
ization presented earlier, specifically, evi- Tabossi, 1988). For example, reading the
dence showing that conceptualizations of word "basketball" does not normally activate
categories often contain four types of situ- the feature floats in most contexts. "Basket-
ated information: ball" does activate floats, however, when a
context makes it relevant, as when in need
1. Properties of the focal category that are of a life preserver and a basketball is nearby.
relevant in the current situation Similar inferences occur in memory (e.g.,
2. Information about the background set- Barclay et al., 1974; Greenspan, 1986; Tulv-
ting ing 8c Thompson, 1973). As described earlier,
3. Possible actions that the agent could when people read the word "piano" in a sen-
take to achieve an associated goal tence about moving a piano, the property
4. Possible interoceptive states that the heavy is more active than the property nice
agent might have while interacting sound, with the opposite occurring when
with the category, including evalua- people read about playing a piano.
tions, emotions, cognitive operations, In category learning, background knowl-
and so forth. edge about a situation constrains the proper-
ties of objects salient in them (e.g., Murphy,
As described earlier, it is assumed that 2000). For example, if people are learning
these four types of inferences are repre- about a vehicle that is to be used for trans-
sented via neural simulations in the respec- portation in the Arctic, they acquire features
tive modality-specific systems. For example, relevant to the situation (e.g., skis, insula-
contextually relevant object properties are tion), not features that are irrelevant (e.g.,
simulated in the ventral stream, settings are tires, netting).
simulated in parietal areas, actions are simu- In general, concepts are not represented
lated in motor areas, and interoceptive states in a vacuum, nor are they represented in a
are simulated in areas that process emotion, generic, abstract manner. Instead, concepts
reasoning, and so forth. Together, simula- are contextualized such that they contain
tions of these four inference types produce information relevant in the current situa-
the experience of being there conceptually tion.
(Barsalou, 2002). When a person processes
a category, the concept that represents the 4.2.2. SETTING INFERENCES
category triggers a situated conceptualiza- When the conceptual system represents a
tion, which represents the multimodal expe- category, it typically situates the category
rience of what it would be like to process the in a background setting. T h e category is
category in the current situation. 1 0 Evidence not represented in isolation. Again much
254 l a w r e n c e w. BARSALOu

work supports this conclusion (Barsalou, agents in these settings, producing infer-
2003b; Yeh & Barsalou, 2006). Numerous ences about the actions they could take
researchers have found that when people are on situated objects and interoceptive states
asked to perform various tasks on individ- likely to occur, respectively. A variety of
ual concepts, information about background neuroimaging experiments show that the
settings is activated implicitly. For example, motor system becomes active when people
Vallée-Tourangeau, Anthony, and Austin process pictures of functional objects (e.g.
(>998) found that when people produce Chao & Martin, 2000; Kellenbach, Brett
instances of categories, situations become 8c Patterson, 2003) and when they process
active to guide the search process (see also words for actions (e.g., Hauk, Johnsrude,
Bucks, 1998; Walker & Kintsch, 1985). When 8c Pulvermuller, 2004). Martin (2001, 2007)
participants produced instances of FURNI- reviews additional findings. For example,
TURE, for example, they imagined situ- viewing a picture of a manipulable object
ations in which furniture is found (e.g., (e.g., HAMMER) for a few seconds and
LIVING ROOM), scanned across the situ- naming it does not simply activate visual and
ations, and reported the category instances linguistic areas, it also activates the grasp-
observed (e.g., SOFA, TABLE). Similarly, ing circuit in the brain, indicating that the
Wu and Barsalou (2008) found that when brain is preparing for situated action with
the object (Chao 8c Martin, 2000). Similarly,
people are asked to generate the features
reading the word for a mouth action (e.g.,
of objects, they also describe background
"lick") or a foot action (e.g., "kick") activates
situations, which appear to be represented
the respective area of motor cortex for mov-
implicidy (see also Barsalou & Wiemer-
ing a foot or the face (Hauk et al., 2004).
Hastings, 2005). For example, when par-
Again, representing a concept does not just
ticipants were asked to produce features
activate an abstract semantic representation
of APPLE, they produced features about
but instead induces preparation for situated
associated settings (e.g., kitchen), events
action. In related behavioral research, Glen-
(e.g., eating), and interoceptive states (e.g.,
berg and Kaschak (2003) found that when
enjoyable). Although the explicit instruc-
people read sentences that describe actions
tions were to describe features of the target
("You open a drawer"), they represented the
object, participants appeared to implicidy meanings of these sentences as simulations
simulate a background situation, scan across in their motor systems.
it, and describe features encountered out- Other research demonstrates that lesions
side the object. As we saw earlier, much in motor and somatosensory areas disrupt
work on visual object processing similarly motor inferences (e.g., Adolphs, Damasio,
shows that representing objects activates Tranel, Cooper, 8c Damasio, 2000; Martin,
background scenes (e.g., Biederman, 1981; 2001). For example, lesions in somatosensory
Bar & Ullman, 1996; Intraub, Gottesman, & cortex compromise the visual categorization
Bills, 1998; Mandler & Parker, 1976; Mandler of emotional expressions on faces (Adolphs
& Stein, 1974; Murphy & Wisniewski, 1989). et al., 2000). Although the task appears
When an isolated object is perceived, a back- purely visual, the motor system immediately
ground scene is typically inferred immedi- mimics the perceived expression in prepa-
ately if one is not present. Bar (2004) reviews ration for situated action, with feedback
brain areas that underlie the representation from the somatosensory system offering an
of background settings. important cue for the particular emotion
4.2.3. ACTION INFERENCES being perceived. When somatosensory feed-
As we have seen, conceptual representa- back is not available, categorization suffers.
tions contain contextually relevant content Much related work in social psychology sim-
and are framed against background settings. ilarly shows that the motor and somatosen-
The findings in this subsection and the next sory systems become active as people per-
show that the conceptual system represents ceive social objects, in preparation for social
situating concepts 192

interaction (e.g., Niedenthal, Brauer, Hal- (2000) found that participants simulated a
berstadt, & Innes-Ker, 2 0 0 1 ; Wallbott, 1 9 9 1 ) . particular perspective when hearing descrip-
Developmental psychologists have also tions of settings (e.g., listening to a descrip-
argued that the motor system is central tion of a skyscraper and then looking up
to higher cognitive processes (e.g., Smith as if they were there). Barsalou, Barbey,
& Gasser, 2005; Smith, Thelen, Titzer, & and Hase (2008) obtained a similar result
McLin, 1999; Thelen, 2000). For example, as people produced features of concepts
the A-not-B, error in children's reasoning (e.g., describing features of BIRDS and
results, in part, from perseveration of action looking up). Many other findings in the
representations in the motor system. comprehension literature demonstrate sim-
Together all these findings demonstrate a ilar effects (e.g., Anderson 8c Pichert, 1978;
dose coupling between the motor and con- Black, Turner, 8c Bower, 1979).
ceptual systems. When people conceptual-
ize a category, they infer relevant actions 4.2.5. BEING THERE CONCEPTUALLY
that they could take on it. Barsalou et al. T h e findings reviewed in the previous four
(2003a) review many further findings in subsections support the conclusion that
social psychology that yield the same con- the conceptual system does not repre-
clusion. sent categories in an abstract, detached,
generic manner. Instead, the conceptual
4.2.4. INTEROCEPTIVE AND PERSPECTIVE system constructs situated conceptualiza-
INFERENCES tions dynamically, tailoring them to the
People not only represent themselves in current needs of situated action. Further-
situated conceptualizations by simulating more, the brain appears to implement
actions but further represent themselves in these situated conceptualizations via simu-
situated conceptualizations by simulating lations in the relevant modality-specific sys-
interoceptive states likely to arise, and by tems, such that experiences of being there
simulating subjective perspectives that they with category members result. Together
could take on settings. First consider intero- these packages of simulated inferences pre-
ceptions. Wu and Barsalou ( 2 0 0 8 ) found pare agents for situated action. Because
that when participants are asked to gener- these inferences have similar representa-
ate the features of target objects, they also tional forms as perceptions, actions, inte-
roceptive states, and perspectives, they can
described interoceptions that they would
be used to monitor and guide goal-directed
be likely to have while interacting with
performance as it unfolds in the current
these objects (see also Barsalou 8c Wiemer-
situation.
Hastings, 2 0 0 5 ) . Specifically, participants
often described emotions, evaluations, and
cognitive operations relevant to interacting
4.3. Evidence for Situated
with a target object. Although the explicit
Conceptualizations from Social
instructions were to describe the object's
Psychology
features, participants appeared to implicitly
simulate accompanying interoceptions from Much further evidence for situated concep-
the background situation, which then leaked tualizations comes from decades of research
into their feature listings. that has documented the effects of bodily
Another class of findings demonstrates states on social cognition. On the basis
that people simulate the subjective perspec- of these findings, Barsalou et al. (2003a)
tive that they would adopt on the situation concluded that people establish entrenched
that frames a target concept. Rather than simulations of frequently experienced situ-
represent the situation in a detached, objec- ations, where a given simulation includes
tive manner, people represent it f r o m a par- (among many other things) a variety of
ticular interoceptive perspective. For exam- bodily states, such as facial expressions,
ple, Spivey, Tyler, Richardson, and Y o u n g arm movements, and postures (see also
256 lawrence w. b a r s a l o u

Niedenthal. Barsalou, Winkielman, Krauth- from out-groups, their faces adopt negative
Gruber. & Rie, 2005). Barsalou et al. (2003a) expressions (e.g., V a n m a n 8c Miller, 199V
proposed that these situated conceptualiza- Vanman, Paul, Ito, 8c Miller, 1997). Posture
tions play a variety of important roles in pro- too, is affected. W h e n students receive a
cessing social information. good grade, their posture tends to become
erect; when they receive a poor grade, they
4.3.1. SOCIAL INFORMATION PROCESSING tend to slump (Weisfeld 8c Beresford, 1982).
PRODUCES EMBODIED STATES As these studies show, perceiving social
Many experiments show that activating stimuli triggers associated embodiments.
knowledge about a social concept gener- Social stimuli do not simply activate amodal
ates associated bodily states. For example, data structures that describe social situations
Bargh, Chen, and Burrows (1996) activated and how to act in them. Instead, social stim-
various stereotypes by asking participants to uli activate simulations of these situations
process associated words. To activate the that include relevant embodied states.
ELDERLY stereotype, for example, partic-
ipants processed words for elderly proper- 4.3.2. EMBODIED STATES AFFECT SOCIAL
ties like gray, bingo, and Florida, and were INFORMATION PROCESSING
then asked them to use them in a sentence. As we just saw in t h e previous subsec-
Once the elderly stereotype became active, tion, processing social information produces
people walked more slowly to the elevator accompanying embodiments as effects. In
when they thought that the experiment was this subsection, we see that embodiments
over, relative to when no stereotype was also function as potent causes in social sit-
activated. In a related study, activating the uations. States of the face, head, arms, and
elderly stereotype slowed the time to verify torso all affect social cognition.
that letter strings are words (Dijksterhuis, Much work has shown that when the
Spears, & Lepanasse, 2001). face adopts a particular expression, it trig-
Other stereotypes produce analogous gers associated emotions, w h i c h in turn color
embodiments. Priming the OBNOXIOUS- social processing (for a review, see Adel-
NESS stereotype, for example, makes par- mann 81 Zajonc, 1989). In the typical exper-
ticipants increasingly likely to interrupt a iment, participants are induced to adopt a
conversation (Bargh et al., 1996). Prim- facial expression under the guise of another
ing the POLITICIAN stereotype increases task that obscures the nature of the expres-
participants' long-windedness in writing an sion and its hypothesized effects. Once the
essay. As Dijksterhuis and Bargh's (2001) face is configured into a particular expres-
review of this literature demonstrates, acti- sion, it produces corresponding emotional
vating a stereotype readily activates associ- states (e.g., Duclos et al., 1989). In turn,
ated embodied states. As we will see in the these emotions affect other tasks. Induced
next subsection, these embodiments have facial expressions, f o r example, affect the
causal effects on social cognition, suggest- perceived funniness of a joke (Strack, Mar-
ing that they play central, not peripheral, tin, 8c Stepper, 1988), or the perceived fame
roles (Barsalou et al., 2003a, provide further of a face (Strack 8c N e u m a n n , 2000).
discussion on this issue). Inducing participants to perform various
Other social stimuli besides words for head movements also affects social process-
stereotypes also trigger embodied responses. ing. In one type of frequently performed
As people view positive versus negative experiment, participants w e r e induced to
scenes, their facial musculature adopts pos- either nod their heads f o r w a r d and back-
itive or negative expressions, respectively ward, or to shake their heads sideways,
(e.g., Cacioppo, Petty, Losch, & Kim, 1986). believing that they w e r e trying to dislodge
As participants view the faces of people headphones from their heads while listening
from in-groups, their own faces adopt posi- to music (e.g., T o m , Pettersen, Lau, Bur-
tive expressions; as participants view people ton, 8c Cook, 1991; Wells 8c Petty, 1980).
situatingconcepts198

Performing the nodding action led partic- come to mind eventually, it often takes
ipants later to rate messages heard during awhile to retrieve a relevant situation. Con-
this time as more compelling, and to judge versely, situations seem to come to mind
products as more valuable, relative to per- more easily for concrete concepts. For
forming the shaking action. Because nod- CHAIR, situations like dining rooms and
ding is associated with positive affect and offices come to mind rapidly."
shaking with negative affect, the different Schwanenflugel, Shoben, and their col-
actions produced different affects, which in leagues showed that the retrieval of situa-
turn produced different judgments. tions affects the processing of both abstract
Inducing participants to perform arm and concrete concepts across a variety
actions also affects social cognition. An arm of cognitive tasks, including lexical deci-
action that pulls an entity toward a person sion, comprehension, and memory (e.g.,
(approach behavior) produces more positive Schwanenflugel, Harnishfeger, 8c Stowe,
judgments than an arm action that pushes 1988; Schwanenflugel 8c Shoben, 1983;
something away (avoidance behavior). For Schwanenflugel 8c Stowe, 1989; Watten-
example, these different arm motions pro- maker 8c Shoben, 1987). Their findings led
duce differential liking of novel visual figures to two conclusions about processing words.
(Cacioppo, Priester, & Bernston, 1993). First, the meanings of words are not estab-
Finally, inducing postures also affects lished in isolation. A word's meaning is typ-
social processing. Adopting an upright pos- ically not a stand-alone representation that
ture produces positive affect and judgment, describes its associated category. Instead,
whereas adopting a slumping posture pro- words are typically understood against back-
duces negative affect and judgment. For ground situations. When a situation is not
example, researchers have shown that pos- available, a concept is difficult to process.
ture affects participants' confidence in task Many early studies on language compre-
performance (Riskind & Gotay, 1982) and hension reached the same conclusion (for
how proud they are of it (Stepper 81 Strack, reviews, see Bransford 8c Johnson, 1973;
Bransford 8c McCarrell, 1974). Much recent
As the results in this subsection illustrate, work reaches this conclusion as well (e.g.,
embodiment not only results from perceiv- Barsalou, 1999a; Clark, 1992; Clark, 1997). In
ing social stimuli but also causally affects general, situations provide essential infor-
subsequent social processing. When a par- mation for representing and understand-
ticular bodily state is adopted, it activates ing concepts. Understanding the meaning of
situated conceptualizations that contain it. TABLE relies not only on properties of the
As these patterns become active, they trig- physical object but also on the situations in
ger related emotional states that can then which it is found (e.g., dining rooms) and
influence a variety of cognitive processes. the activities performed in them (e.g., eat-
ing) . Knowledge about TABLE is inadequate
In general, these conceptualizations prepare
if a person does not know how to interact
agents for situated social interaction.
with them in relevant situations.
A second conclusion also follows from the
4.4. Evidence for Situations in the
results of Schwanenflugel, Shoben, and their
Representation of Abstract Concepts
colleagues: retrieving situations for abstract
4.4.1. SITUATION A V A I L A B I L I T Y concepts is generally more difficult than
In a classic series of studies, Schwanenflugel, retrieving situations for concrete concepts.
Shoben, and their colleagues showed that At least two factors may be responsible.
it is often difficult to retrieve situations First, abstract concepts may be linked to
for abstract concepts (for a review, see a wider variety of situations (Galbraith 8c
Schwanenflugel, 1991). For example, what Underwood, 1973). As a result of greater
is a situation in which TRUTH occurs? interference, retrieving a single situation for
Although a jury trial in courtroom might an abstract concept may be more difficult
258 l a w r e n c e W. b a r s a l o u

than retrieving one for a concrete concept. hypothesis 2, however, the distributions of
Second, when people process abstract con- content were not identical for abstract and
cepts during everyday activities, a relevant concrete concepts. Whereas abstract con-
situation may typically be in place already cepts produced higher rates of information
(Barsalou & Wiemer-Hastings, 2005). Peo- about interoceptions and events, concrete
ple may not usually entertain a concept concepts produced higher rates of infor-
like TRUTH unless a relevant situation has mation for objects and settings. Although
already been represented (or perceived) to both concept types were represented in
which the concept applies. Consequendy, a situated manner, they highlighted dif-
the conceptual system becomes accustomed ferent aspects of their background situa-
to retrieving information about abstract con- tions. Regarding hypothesis 3, abstract con-
cepts with relevant situations already in cepts appeared to be more complex and
place. Conversely, because it is relatively distributed across situations than concrete
unusual to process abstract concepts in a concepts, with abstract concepts organized
situational vacuum, people draw blanks, at around larger and deeper hierarchical struc-
least initially, when receiving them out of tures.
context. Together, all these findings further impli-
cate situations in conceptual processing.
4.4.2. CONTRASTING THE CONTENT OF Both abstract and concrete concepts appear
ABSTRACT AND CONCRETE CONCEPTS to be represented in a situated manner.
It is widely assumed, at least implicidy,
that abstract and concrete concepts have lit-
tle in common. Alternatively, Barsalou and 5. Further Issues
Wiemer-Hastings (2005) argued that con-
crete and abstract concepts share important The findings reviewed here strongly sug-
simdarities, captured in three hypotheses gest that conceptual processing is situ-
that they investigated empirically. Accord- ated. Rather than processing concepts in
ing to hypothesis 1, abstract and concrete a vacuum, people activate relevant back-
concepts share common situational con- ground situations. Presumably the purpose
tent. According to hypothesis 2, however, of these situations is to prepare agents
abstract and concrete concepts differ in their for situated action and to represent the
focus within background situations, with focal category in a situationally appropri-
concrete concepts focusing on objects and ate manner. Although it seems clear that
abstract concepts focusing on events and situations are implicated in conceptual pro-
interoceptions. Finally, according to hypoth- cessing, we have only begun to understand
esis 3, abstract concepts are more complex situational representations and their interac-
than concrete concepts, containing more tions with concepts. Several of many out-
content and being more distributed across standing issues that remain are discussed
situations. briefly.
Barsalou and Wiemer-Hastings (2005)
reported evidence that supports these three
5.1. Radial Categories
hypotheses. Regarding hypothesis 1, abstract
and concrete concepts shared extensive sit- One important problem is explaining how
uational content. Both types of concepts different conceptualizations of the same
activated information about events, settings, category become linked together. How do
agents, objects, actions, and mental states. the various conceptualizations of CHAIR,
Indeed, the distributions of this content for example, become integrated into a sin-
were remarkably similar. For both con- gle category? One possibility is that they
cept types, participants appeared to repre- become integrated by analogy. When a per-
sent complete situations, which framed the ceived entity activates a structurally analo-
focal content of interest. Consistent with gous conceptualization in memory, the two
situatingconcepts192

become linked (e.g., Brooks, 1978; Gent- vary from situation to situation. Further-
ner & Markman, 1997; Holyoak & Thagard, more, the key proposal is that conceptual-
1989; Nosofsky, 1984). Perceiving an office izations are represented against background
chair, for example, may activate the con- situations. They are not simply subordinates
ceptualization of a kitchen chair via their represented in isolation. Finally, the present
shared physical structure or via the com- framework extends well beyond subordinate
mon actions performed on it. As a result, categories. Consider CARS. The present
the two conceptualizations become inte- framework predicts that a single subordi-
grated in memory. As different kinds of nate, such as SEDAN, will be conceptual-
chairs are increasingly encountered in dif- ized in a variety of situations, such as driving
ferent situations, their respective conceptu- a sedan, watching a sedan drive by, filling
alizations become related to similar concep- a sedan's gas tank, parking a sedan, and
tualizations, thereby forming linked chains. so forth. Instead of conceptualizing sedans
Although core properties could ultimately as a subordinate in a generic, situation-
become established across the various con- independent manner, people conceptualize
ceptualizations of a concept, they need not them differently in these various situations,
be. When core properties do not develop, focusing on different perspectives and prop-
the linked chains of conceptualizations form erties in each. In these ways, the theoretical
a radial concept, with each conceptualiza- proposal here extends beyond the fact that
tion being closely related to at least one categories have subordinates.
other (e.g., Lakoff, 1987; Malt, Sloman, Gen-
nari, Shi, 8c Wang, 1999).
5.2. Dimensions of Situations
Essences could constitute another possi-
ble linking mechanism to integrate the dif- Creating a taxonomy of relevant phenom-
ferent conceptualizations of a category. If all ena often lays the groundwork for mechanis-
known conceptualizations of a category are tic models. In this spirit, Yeh and Barsalou
believed to share a common essence, they (2006) developed a taxonomy of situation
become linked around the essence, even types. Specifically, they proposed that three
when their physical appearances differ (e.g., factors - grain size, meaningfulness, and tan-
Gelman & Diesendruck, 1999). Depending gibility - can be used to construct a taxon-
on the category, the essence could reflect omy of situations.
a real essence that actually exists across
instances, or it could simply reflect the belief 5.2.1. GRAIN SIZE
that an essence exists, even when one does The situations that have been reported to
not. affect conceptual processing range from
As these suggestions illustrate, the situ- large to small grain sizes. Toward one
ated conceptualizations for a category could extreme, a situation can be an entire phys-
become linked in various ways. Following ical setting over an extended period of
Barsalou (1999b, 2003b), the result is a sim- time, such as the classroom in which course
ulator capable of producing many situated material is learned over a one-hour period.
simulations of a category (see also Barsalou Toward the other extreme, a situation can
etal.,1993). be the stimulus immediately adjacent to a
This claim does not simply reduce to target stimulus for a few moments, such as
the fact that a category has subordinates. a context word that primes a target word
The claim is significantly stronger. A cat- momentarily.
egory does not just take different subordi- Both spatial and temporal extent under-
nate forms. Instead, these different forms lie grain size. Spatially, a situation can range
accommodate the constraints of different from a large physical setting (e.g., a park) to
situations. Conceptualizations of CHAIRS, a computer that presents a pictured scene,
for example, take different forms because to an adjacent stimulus within a computer
the constraints on having somewhere to sit display (the object next to a target object in a
LAWRENCE w . b a r s a l . o l

pictured scene). Temporally, a situation can an arbitrary relation to its situation, associa-
range from the entire learning phase of an tions develop between the object and sit-
experiment, to the serial presentation of sev- uation that produce these effects. Impor-
eral stimuli, to a trial that contains a single tantly, however, situation effects appear to
configuration of stimulus elements. Thus, be greater in meaningful situations, probably
a situation can vary from a large region of because stronger relations develop between
space over an extended period of time, down situations and objects.
to a small region of space for a moment.
Typically, a given stimulus exists in a hier- 5.2.3. TANGIBILITY
archically organized set of situations across Situations also vary in the extent to which
multiple grain sizes simultaneously. There they are physically present versus imagined.
is not just a single situation for a stimulus - For any stimulus, a physical situation is
typically there are many. Furthermore, it is always present. However, people also fre-
difficult, if not impossible, to specify the quently imagine background situations for
potential space of situations exhaustively. A focal stimuli. While recalling a word list in a
focal stimulus can potentially occur in an new room, for example, participants might
infinite number of situations and be viewed imagine the original room in which the list
from an infinite number of perspectives. The was learned. As Yeh and Barsalou (2006)
situations that pervade cognition are open review, a focal stimulus often induces par-
ended and difficult to enumerate. As Yeh ticipants to imagine a background situation
and Barsalou (2006) show, situation effects that is meaningfully related to the stimu-
at diverse grain sizes affect conceptual pro- lus, especially when a meaningful situation
cessing. is not provided. Participants might see a hat
above a shirt, for example, and imagine that
5.2.2. MEANINGFULNESS a nondepicted person is wearing them. Or
The relation between a focal object and a participant might see a picture of a bird
a situation can range from arbitrary co- with its wings extended and imagine it fly-
occurrence to meaningful interdependence. ing through the sky. Many situation effects
In arbitrary co-occurrence, there is no expla- result from imagined situations that target
nation for why an object occurs in a situation stimuli elicit.
and vice versa. Furthermore, predicting that
the situation will contain the object is not
5.3. The Cumulative Nature of Situations
possible. When participants leam random
words in a particular classroom, for exam- As we just saw, situations appear to vary
ple, the relation between the words and the in grain size, meaningfulness, and tangibil-
classroom is arbitrary. Knowing the situa- ity. A potential implication is that people
tion does not explain or predict the focal often perceive and imagine a complex set of
elements of interest. hierarchically organized situations simulta-
Alternatively, the relationship between neously for a given focal stimulus. At this
an object and a situation can be meaning- time, we do not have accounts of what
ful and predictable. In these situations, the a hierarchically organized set of situations
object and situation belong to a coherent sys- contains, or how it is constructed. What
tem whose parts have strong dependencies situations are present at what grain sizes?
between them. In a classroom that contains How do they originate? Are some always
desks, chairs, and blackboards, for example, present in perception, perhaps because they
people can explain why these entities belong reflect obligatory processing during percep-
together, and they can predict one from per- tion? Are others created in an ad hoc manner
ceiving the other. as they become relevant to current goals?
As Yeh and Barsalou (2006) show, both A related issue concerns how all of the
arbitrary and meaningful situations produce situations represented simultaneously at a
situation effects. Even if an object only bears given time become integrated to create the
situating concepts 192

illusion of a single coherent situation. Also, they may not operate as stand-alone symbols
how do situations at small grain sizes c o m e but may primarily serve to activate modality-
and go while situations at large grain sizes specific patterns that play central roles in the
remain r e l a t i v e l y constant? These are just a representation process. Furthermore, these
few of the many fundamental issues asso- patterns are likely to have modality-specific
tunings, such that they are actually not
ciated with situated conceptualization that
amodal. Indeed, the fact that association
remain n o t just unresolved b u t unaddressed.
areas often lie within modality-specific sys-
H o p e f u l l y , issues such as these will receive
tems argues against their being completely
significant attention in future research.
amodal. For further discussion of these issues,
see Damasio (1989) and Simmons and Barsa-
Acknowledgments lou (2003).
4 Why does selective attention focus on some
components of experience but not others?
I am grateful to Phil Robbins and Eric Margolis
Many factors influence this process, includ-
for helpful comments on an earlier version of this
ing genetics, language learning, cultural trans-
chapter. This work was supported by National
mission, and goal pursuit. Explaining these
Science Foundation Grants SBR-9421326, SBR-
mechanisms lies beyond the scope of this
9796200, and BCS-0212134 to Lawrence W.
chapter. Furthermore, this is the classic prob-
Barsalou. Address correspondence to Lawrence
lem of relevance (e.g., Murphy 8c Medin,
W. Barsalou, Department of Psychology, Emory
1985; Sperber & Wilson, 1986), and any theory
University, Atlanta, GA 30322 (barsalou@
of knowledge (not just this one) must address
emory.edu, http://userwww.service.emory.edu/
it.
~barsalou/).
5 The mechanism of situational constraint may
also play a significant role in minimizing the
frame problem, along with related problems
Notes associated with nonmonotonic reasoning.
6 Although this definition of concepts stresses
1 Interoception will refer to the perception of empirical factors, genetic factors undoubt-
internal states, including affects (e.g., calm- edly play central roles as well. There is no
ness), emotions (e.g., happiness), motivations a priori reason, for example, why a simu-
(e.g., hunger), pains (e.g., headache), cogni- lator could not originate genetically. More
tive states (e.g., belief), cognitive operations plausibly, genetic factors probably play major
(e.g., comparison), and so forth. Interocep- roles in specifying the feature and associa-
tion will not include somatosensory states, tion areas that underlie the empirical acqui-
given their close coupling with the motor sys- sition of simulators (e.g., Simmons & Barsa-
tem. lou, 2003). Furthermore, these genetic factors
2 Quotes will be used to indicate linguistic may reflect evolutionary history by anticipat-
forms, and italics will be used to indicate ing features and conjunctions of features that
conceptual representations. Within concep- are important for acquiring relatively con-
tual representations, uppercase italic font will stant categories in the environment, action,
indicate categories, whereas lowercase italic and interoception (cf. Caramazza 8c Shelton,
font will indicate properties of categories. 1998).
Thus, BIRD indicates a category, whereas 7 The definition of situation adopted here is
feathers indicates a property, with "bird" and designed to handle everyday situations that
"feathers" indicating the respective linguistic people encounter during daily activity. It
forms. does not attempt to cover more specialized
3 I do not mean to rule out the possibility situations that occur in technical and formal
of amodal symbols in the brain, although I activities (e.g., mathematics). Situations are
am increasingly skeptical that they exist in likely to be just as important in these other
classically postulated form. Perhaps a more domains (e.g., Barwise 81 Perry, 1983; Chi, Fel-
likely possibility is that patterns of active neu- tovich, 8c Glaser, 198; Greeno, 1998). How-
rons in association areas constitute amodal ever, they are not pursued here.
recodings of activations in modality-specific 8 As described later in the section on radial
areas. Should such patterns exist, however, categories, this proposal about situated
258 lawrence w. barsalou

conceptualizations is not equivalent to stan- Bar, M., 8t Ullman, S. (1996). Spatial context in
dard accounts of subordinate categories. recognition. Perception, 25, 343-352.
Rather than simply represent a subordinate as Barclay, J. R., Bransford, J. D., Franks, J, J
an isolated category, the proposal here is that McCarrell, N. S., & Nitsch, K. (1974). Com!
specific types of instances (including subordi- prehension and semantic flexibility. Journal of
nates) are represented in background settings, Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 13, 4™..
such that a given subordinate might be repre- 481.
sented separately in many possible situations Bargh, J. A., Chen, M., & Burrows, L. (1996).
in which it occurs regularly. Automaticity of social behavior: Direct effects
9 Yeh and Barsalou also propose a third the- of trait construct and stereotype activation on
sis not discussed here, which states that the action. Journal of Personality and Social Psy.
first two theses hold only when people per- chobgy, 71, 230-244.
form conceptual processing and do not rely Barsalou, L. W. (1982). Context-independent and
on superficial processing strategies, such as context-dependent information in concepts.
using familiarity to guide performance. Memory & Cognition, 10, 82-93.
10 The expression "being there conceptually" Barsalou, L. W. (1987). The instability of
could be understood as claiming that agents graded structure: Implications for the nature
experience these situations consciously. The of concepts. In U. Neisser (Ed.), Con-
sense of being there conceptually intended cepts and conceptual development: Ecological
here, however, is that neural systems ready and intellectual factors in categorization (pp.
themselves for perceptions, actions, and in- 101-140). Cambridge: Cambridge University
teroceptions likely to be relevant in the cur- Press.
rent situation. Although these neural systems Barsalou, L. W. (1989). Intraconcept similarity
may often produce conscious states, the focus and its implications for interconcept similar-
remains on the neural processing that under- ity. In S. Vosniadou 8c A. Ortony (Eds.), Sim-
lies consciousness. ilarity and analogical reasoning (pp. 76-121).
11 In this literature, Schwanenflugel and other Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
researchers refer to "situation availability" as Barsalou, L. W. (1993). Flexibility, structure, and
"context availability." Situation is used here linguistic vagary in concepts: Manifestations
instead, because it has roughly the same of a compositional system of perceptual sym-
meaning and is the central construct in this bols. In A. F. Collins, S. E. Gathercole, M.
chapter. A. Conway, 8c P. E. Morris (Eds.), Theories of
memory (pp. 29-101). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum.
Barsalou, L. W. (1999a). Language comprehen-
References sion: Archival memory or preparation for
situated action? Discourse Processes, 28, 61-
Adelman, P. K., & Zajonc, R. B. (1989). Facial 80.
efference and the experience of emotion. Barsalou, L. W. (1999b). Perceptual symbol sys-
Annual Review of Psychology, 40, 249-280. tems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22, 577—
Adolphs, R., Damasio, H., Tranel, D., Cooper, 660.
G., & Damasio, A. R. (2000). A role for Barsalou, L. W. (2002). Being there conceptually:
somatosensory cortices in the visual recog- Simulating categories in preparation for sit-
nition of emotion as revealed by three- uated action. In N. L. Stein, P. J. Bauer, 8c
dimensional lesion mapping. Journal of Neu- M. Rabinowitz (Eds.), Representation, mem-
roscience, 20,2683-2690. ory, and development: Essays in honor of Jean
Andersen, S. M., & Chen, S. (2002). The rela- Mandler (pp. 1-16). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence
tional self: An interpersonal social-cognitive Erlbaum.
theory. Psychological Review, 109, 619-645. Barsalou, L. W. (2003a). Abstraction in percep-
Anderson, R. C., & Pichert, J. W. (1978). Recall of tual symbol systems. Philosophical Transac-
previously unrecallable information following tions of the Royal Society of London: Biological
a shift in perspective. Journal of Verbal Learn- Sciences, 358, 1177-1187.
ing and Verbal Behavior, 17,1-12. Barsalou, L. W. (2003b). Situated simulation in
Bar, M. (2004). Visual objects in context. Nature the human conceptual system. Language and
Reviews Neuroscience, 5, 617-629. Cognitive Processes, 18, 513-562.
situatingconcepts198

Barsalou, L. W. (2005). Continuity of the concep- hension: Some thoughts about understand-
tual system across species. Trends in Cognitive ing what it means to comprehend. In W. B.
Sciences, 9, 309-311. Weimer 8c D. S. Palermo (Eds.), Cognition and
Barsalou, L.W. (2008). Grounded cognition. the symbolic processes (pp. 377-399). Hillsdale,
Annual Review of Psychology, 59, 617-645. NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Barsalou, L. W., Barbey, A., 8c Hase, S. (2008). Brewer, W. F., 8c Treyens, J. C. (1981). Role of
Spontaneous body movements during property schemata in memory for places. Cognitive Psy-
generation for concepts. Manuscript in prepara- chology, 13, 207-230.
tion. Brooks, L. R. (1978). Nonanalytic concept forma-
Barsalou, L. W., Niedenthal, P. M., Barbey, A., 8c tion and memory for instances. In E. Rosch
Ruppert, J. (2003a). Social embodiment. In B. 8c B. B. Lloyd (Eds.), Cognition and categori-
Ross (Ed.), The psychology of learning and moti- zation (pp. 169-211). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
vation (Vol. 43, pp. 43-92). San Diego, CA: Erlbaum.
Academic Press. Brooks, R. A. (1991). Intelligence without rep-
Barsalou, L. W., Simmons, W. K., Barbey, A. K., resentation. Artificial Intelligence, 47, 139-
& Wilson, C. D. (2003b). Grounding concep- 159-
tual knowledge in modality-specific systems. Bruner, J. S. (1957). Going beyond the informa-
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, 84-91. tion given. In J. S. Bruner, E. Brunswik, L.
Barsalou, L. W., 8c Wiemer-Hastings, K. (2005). Festinger, F. Heider, K. F. Muenzinger, C. E.
Situating abstract concepts. In D. Pecher 8c R. Osgood, 8c D. Rapaport (Eds.), Contempo-
Zwaan (Eds.), Grounding cognition: The role of rary approaches to cognition (pp. 41-69). Cam-
perception and action in memory, language, and bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
thought (pp. 129-163). New York: Cambridge Bucks, R. S. (1998). Intrusion errors in Alzheimer's
University Press. disease. Unpublished doctoral dissertation,
Barsalou, L. W., Yeh, W., Luka, B. J., Olseth, University of Bristol.
K. L., Mix, K. S., 8c Wu, L. L. (1993). Con- Cacioppo, J. P., Petty, R. E., Losch, M. E., 8c
cepts and meaning. In K. Beals, G. Cooke, D. Kim, H. S. (1986). Electromyographic activity
Kathman, S. Kita, K. E. McCullough, 8c D. over facial muscle regions can differentiate the
Testen (Eds.), Chicago Linguistic Society 29: valence and intensity of affective reactions.
Papers from the parasession on the correspon- Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 50,
dence of conceptual, semantic and grammatical 260-268.
representations (pp. 23-61). Chicago: Chicago Cacioppo, J. T., Priester, J. R., 8c Bernston, G. G.
Linguistic Society. (1993). Rudimentary determination of atti-
Bartlett, F. C. (1932). Remembering: A study in tudes: II. Arm flexion and extension have dif-
experimental and social psychology. New York: ferential effects on attitudes. Journal of Person-
Cambridge University Press. ality and Social Psychology, 65, 5-17.
Barwise, J., 8c Perry, J. (1983). Situations and atti- Caramazza, A., 8c Shelton, J. R. (1998). Domain-
tudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. specific knowledge systems in the brain: The
Biederman, I. (1972). Perceiving real-world animate-inanimate distinction. Journal of Cog-
scenes. Science, 177, 77-80. nitive Neuroscience, 10,1-34.
Biederman, I. (1981). On the semantics of a glance Chao, L. L., 8c Martin, A. (2000). Representation
at a scene. In M. Kubovy 8c J. R. Pomerantz of manipulable man-made objects in the dor-
(Eds.), Perceptual organization (pp. 213-253). sal stream. Neuroimage, 12, 478-484.
Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. Cheng, P. W., 8c Holyoak, K. J. (1985). Pragmatic
Black, J. B., Turner, T. J., 8c Bower, G. H. (1979). reasoning schemas. Cognitive Psychology, 17,
Point of view in narrative comprehension, 391-416.
memory, and production. Journal of Verbal Chi, M. T. H., Feltovich, P. J., 8c Glaser, R. (1981).
Learning and Verbal Behavior, 18, 187-198. Categorization and representation of physics
Bransford, J. D., 8c Johnson, M. K. (1973). Con- problems by experts and novices. Cognitive
siderations of some problems of comprehen- Science, 5,121-152.
sion. In W. G. Chase (Ed.), Visual information Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body,
processing (pp. 383-438). New York: Academic and world together again. Cambridge, MA:
Press. MIT Press.
Bransford, J. D., 8c McCarrell, N. S. (1974). A Clark, H. H. (1992). Arenas of language use.
sketch of a cognitive approach to compre- Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
160 lawrence w. barsalou

Collins, A. M., 8t Loftus, E. F. (1975). A spread- chological essentialism. In I. E. Siegel (Ed.),


ing activation theory of semantic processing. Theoretical perspectives on the concept of repre-
Psychological Review, 82,407-428. sentation (pp. 87-111). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence
Collins, A. M., &Quillian, M. R (1969). Retrieval Erlbaum.
time from semantic memory. Journal of Verbal Gentner, D., & Markman, A. B. (1997). Structure
Learning and Verbal Behavior, 8, 240-248. mapping in analogy and similarity. American
Craik, F. I. M., & Lockhart, R. S. (1972). Lev- Psychologist, 52, 45-56.
els of processing: A framework for memory Gick, M. L., 8c Holyoak, K. J. (1980). Analogical
research. Journal of Verbal Learning and Ver- problem solving. Cognitive Psychology, 12,306-
bal Behavior. 11, 671-684. 355-
Cree, G. S., & McRae, K. (2003). Analyzing the Gil-da-Costa, R., Braun, A., Lopes, M., Hauser,
factors underlying the structure and compu- M. D., Carson, R. E., Herscovitch, P., et al.
tation of the meaning of chipmunk, cherry, (2004). Toward an evolutionary perspective
chisel, cheese, and cello (and many other such on conceptual representation: Species-specific
concrete nouns). Journal of Experimental Psy- calls activate visual and affective processing
chology: General, 132,163-201. systems. Proceedings of the National Academy
Damasio, A. R. (1989). Time-locked multi- of Sciences, 101,17516-17521.
regional retroactivation: A systems-level pro- Glenberg, A. M. (1997). What memory is for.
posal for the neural substrates of recall and Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 20,1-55.
recognition. Cognition, 33, 25-62. Glenberg, A. M., 8c Kaschak, M. P. (2004).
Dijksterhuis, A., & Bargh, J. A. (2001). The Grounding language in action. Psychonomic
perception-behavior expressway: Automatic Bulletin &£ Review, 9, 558-569.
effects of social perception on social behavior.Goldberg, A. E. (1995). Constructions: A construc-
In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimen- tion grammar approach to argument structure.
tal social psychology (Vol. 23, pp. 1-40). San
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Gould, S. J. (1991). Exaptation: A crucial tool for
Dijksterhuis, A., Spears, R., & Lepanasse, V. an evolutionary psychology. Journal of Social
(2001). Reflecting and deflecting stereotypes: Issues, 47, 43-65.
Assimilation and contrast in automatic behav- Greeno, J. G. (1998). T h e situativity of knowing,
ior. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
learning, and research. American Psychologist,
37,286-299.
53- 5-* 6 -
Duclos, S. E., Laird, J. D., Schneider, E., Sex-
Greenspan, S. L. (1986). Semantic flexibility
ter, M., Stem, L., & Van Lighten, O. (1989).
and referential specificity of concrete nouns.
Emotion-specific effects of facial expressions
Journal of Memory and Language, 25, 539-
and postures on emotional experience. Journal
of Personality and Social Psycholog, 57, 100- 557-
108. Grezes, J., 8c Decety, J. (2001). Functional
Dunbar, G. (1991). The cognitive lexicon. anatomy of execution, mental simulation,
Tübingen, Germany: Gunter Narr Verlag. observation, and verb generation of actions:
Farah, M. J. (2000). The neural bases of men- A meta-analysis. Human Brain Mapping, 12,
tal imagery. In M. S. Gazzaniga (Ed.), The 1-19.
cognitive neurosciences (2nd ed., pp. 965-974). Hampton, J. A. (1979). Polymorphous concepts
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. in semantic memory. Journal of Verbal Learn-
Farah, M. J., & McClelland, J. L. (1991). A ing and Verbal Behavior, 18, 441-461.
computational model of semantic memory Hauk, O., Johnsrude, I., 8c Pulvermiiller, F.
impairment: Modality specificity and emer- (2004). Somatopic representation of action
gent category specificity. Journal of Experimen- words in human motor and premotor cortex.
tal Psychology: General, no, 339-357. Neuron, 41, 301-307.
Finke, R. A. (1989). Principles of mental imagery. Holyoak, K. J., 8c Thagard, P. R. (1989). Analogi-
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. cal mapping by constraint satisfaction. Cogni-
Galbraith, R. C., & Underwood, B. J. (1973). tive Science, 13, 295-356.
Perceived frequency of concrete and abstract Intraub, H., Gottesman, C. V . , 8c Bills, A. J.
words. Memory & Cognition, 1, 56-60. (1998). Effects of perceiving and imagining
Gelman, S. A., & Diesendruck, G. (1999). What's scenes on memory for pictures. Journal of
in a concept? Context, variability, and psy- Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, &
Cognition, 24,186-201.
sm JATING CONCEPTS

Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1983). Mental models. Cam- Mischel, W. (1968). Personality and assessment.
bridge/ MA: Harvard University Press. New York: Wiley.
(Celias, G., Paul, S. T., Martin, M., & Simpson, Murphy, G. L. (2000). Explanatory concepts. In
G. B. (1991)- Contextual feature activation R. A. Wilson 8c F. C. Keil (Eds.), Explanation
and meaning access. In G. B. Simpson (Ed.), and cognition (pp. 361-392). Cambridge, MA:
Understanding word and sentence (pp. 47-71). MIT Press.
New York: Elsevier. Murphy, G. L., 8c Medin, D. L. (1985). The role
Kellenbach, M. L., Brett, M., 8c Patterson, K. of theories in conceptual coherence. Psycho-
(2003). Actions speak louder than functions: logical Review, 92, 289-316.
The importance of manipulability and action Murphy, G. L., 8c Wisniewski, E. (1989). Cat-
in tool representation. Journal of Cognitive egorizing objects in isolation and in scenes:
Neuroscience, 15, 30-46. What a superordinate is good for. Journal of
Kirsh, D. (1991). Today the earwig, tomorrow Experimental Psychology: Learning Memory, S£
man? Artificial Intelligence, 47,161-184. Cognition, 15, 572-586.
Kosslyn, S. M. (1994). Image and brain. Cam- Niedenthal, P. M., Barsalou, L. W., Winkiel-
bridge, MA: MIT Press. man, P., Krauth-Gruber, S., 8c Ric, F. (2005).
Lakoff, G. (1987). Women, fire, and dangerous Embodiment in attitudes, social perception,
things: What categories reveal about the mind. and emotion. Personality and Social Psychology
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Review, 9(3), 184-211.
Malt, B. C., Sloman, S. A., Gennari, S., Shi, M., Niedenthal, P. M., Brauer, M., Halberstadt, J. B.,
8c Wang, Y. (1999). Knowing versus naming: 8c Innes-Ker, A. H. (2001). When did her smile
Similarity and the linguistic categorization of drop? Facial mimicry and the influences of
artifacts. Journal of Memory and Language, 40, emotional state on the detection of change in
230-262. emotional expression. Cognition and Emotion,
Mandler, J. M., 8c Parker, R. E. (1976). Mem- 15, 853-864.
ory for descriptive and spatial information in Nosofsky, R M. (1984). Choice, similarity, and
complex pictures. Journal of Experimental Psy- the context theory of classification. Journal of
chology: Human Learning, S¿ Memory, 2, 38- Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, 3d
48. Cognition, 10,104-114.
Mandler, J. M., 8c Stein, N. (1974). Recall and Pecher, D., 8c Zwaan, R. (Eds.). (2005). Ground-
recognition of pictures by children as a func- ing cognition: The role of perception and action
tion of organization and distractor similarity. in memory, language, and thought. New York:
Journal of Experimental Psychology, 102, 657— Cambridge University Press.
669. Quiroga, R. Q., Reddy, L., Kreimen, C., Koch,
Martin, A. (2001). Functional neuroimaging of G., 8c Fried, I. (2005). Invariant visual rep-
semantic memory. In R. Cabeza 8c A. King- resentation by single neurons in the human
stone (Eds.), Handbook of functional neu- brain. Science, 435,1102-1107.
roimaging of cognition (pp. 153-186). Cam- Riskind, J. H., 8c Gotay, C. C. (1982). Physical
bridge, MA: MIT Press. posture: Could it have regulatory or feedback
Martin, A. (2007). The representation of object effects on motication and emotion? Motiva-
concepts in the brain. Annual Review of Psy- tion and Emotion, 6, 273-298.
chology, 58, 25-45. Rosch, E., & Mervis, C. B. (1975). Family resem-
McRae, K., 8c Cree, G. S. (2002). Factors under- blances: Studies in the internal structure of
lying category-specific semantic deficits. In categories. Cognitive Psychology, 7, 573-605.
I M. E. Forde 8c G. Humphreys (Eds.), Sanford, A. J., 8c Garrod, S. C. (1981). Understand-
Category-specificity in mind and brain (pp. 211- ing written language: Explanations of compre-
249). East Sussex, UK: Psychology Press. hension beyond the sentence. Chichester, UK:
McRae, K., de Sa, V. R., & Seidenberg, M. S. Wiley.
(1997). On the nature and scope of featural Schwanenflugel, P. J. (1991). Why are abstract
representations of word meaning. Journal of concepts hard to understand? In P. J.
Experimental Psychology: General, 126, 99-130. Schwanenflugel (Ed.), The psychology of word
Miller, G. A., 8c Isard, S. D. (1963). Some percep- meaning (pp. 223-250). Mahwah, NJ: Law-
tual consequences of linguistic rules. Journal rence Erlbaum.
of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behainor, 2, 217- Schwanenflugel, P. J., Harnishfeger, K. K., &
228. Stowe, R. W. (1988). Context availability and
266
lawrence w. barsalou

lexical decisions for abstract and concrete feelings. Journal of Personality and Social Psy.
words. Journal of Memory $8 Language, 27, chology, 64, 211-220.
499-520. Strack, F., Martin, L. L., 8c Stepper, S. (1988)
Schwanenflugel, P. J., & Shoben, E. J. (1983). Dif- Inhibiting and facilitating conditions of the
ferential context effects in the comprehension human smile: A nonobtrusive test of the facial
of abstract and concrete verbal materials. Jour- feedback hypothesis. Journal of Personality and
nal of Experimental Psychology; Learning, Mem-Social Psychology, 54, 768-777.
ory, id Cognition, 9, 82-102. Strack, F., 8c Neumann, R. (2000). Furrowing
Schwanenflugel, P. J., & Stowe, R. W. (1989). the brow may undermine perceived fame:
Context availability and the processing of The role of facial feedback in judgments of
abstract and concrete words in sentences. celebrity. Personality and Social Psychology
Reading Research Quarterly, 24,114-126. Bulletin, 26, 762-768.
Schyns, P. G., Goldstone, R. L., 8c Thibaut, J. P. Tabossi, P. (1988). Effects of context on the
(1998). The development of features in object immediate interpretation of unambiguous
concepts. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21, nouns. Journal of Experimental Psychology:
f_
54- Learning, Memory, &Î Cognition, 14,153-162.
Thelen, E. (2000). Grounded in the world: Devel-
Simmons, K., & Barsalou, L. W. (2003). The
opmental origins of the embodied mind.
similarity-in-topography principle: Reconcil-
Infancy, 1, 3-30.
ing theories of conceptual deficits. Cognitive
Thompson-Schill, S. L. (2003). Neuroimag-
Neuropsychology, 20,451-486.
ing studies of semantic memory: Inferring
Smith, E. E. (1978). Theories of semantic mem-
"how" from "where." Neuropsychologia, 41,
ory. In W. K. Estes (Ed.), Handbook of learning
280-292.
and cognitive processes (Vol. 6, pp. 1-56). Hills-
Tom, G., Pettersen, P., Lau, T., Burton, T., &
dale, NJ Lawrence Erlbaum.
Cook, J. (1991). The role of overt head move-
Smith, E. R., 8c Semin, G. R. (2004). Socially situ-
ment in the formation of affect. Basic and
ated cognition: Cognition in its social context.
Applied Social Psychology, 12, 281-289.
Advances in Experimental Socud Psychology, 36,
Tulving, E. (1972). Episodic and semantic mem-
53-117.
ory. In E. Tulving 8c W. Donaldson (Eds.),
Smith, L. B., & Gasser, M. (2005). The develop-
Organization and memory (pp. 381-403). New
ment of embodied cognition: Six lessons from
York: Academic Press.
babies. Artificial Life, 11,13-30.
Smith, L. B., 8c Samuelson, L. K. (1997)- Per- Tulving, E., 8c Thomson, D. M. (1973). Encoding
ceiving and remembering: Category stability, specificity and retrieval processes in episodic
variability, and development. In K. Lamberts memory. Psychological Review, 80, 352-373.
&. D. Shanks (Eds.), Knowledge, concepts, and Vallée-Tourangeau, F., Anthony, S. H., 8c Austin,
categories (pp. 161-196). London: Psychology N. G. (1998). Strategies for generating mul-
Press. tiple instances of common and ad hoc cate-
Smith, L. B., Thelen, E., Titzer, R., 8c McLin, D. gories. Memory, 6, 555-592.
(1999). Knowing in the context of acting: The Vanman, E. J., 8c Miller, N. (1993). Applications
task dynamics of the A-not-B error. Psycholog- of emotion theory and research to stereotyp-
ical Review, ¡06, 235-260. ing and intergroup relations. In D. M. Mackie
Smith, W. J. (1977). The behavior of communi- 8c D. L. Hamilton (Eds.), Affect, cognition, and
cating. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University stereotyping: Interactive processes in group per-
Press. ception (pp. 213-238). San Diego, CA: Aca-
Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1986). Relevance: demic Press.
Communication and cognition. Cambridge, Vanman, E. J., Paul, B. Y., Ito, T. A., 8c Miller,
MA: Blackwell. N. (1997). The modern face of prejudice and
Spivey, M., Tyler, M., Richardson, D., & Young, structural features that moderate the effect of
E. (2000). Eye movements during comprehen- cooperation on affect. Journal of Personality
sion of spoken scene descriptions. In Proceed- and Social Psychology, 73, 941-959.
ings of the 22nd Annual Conference of the Cog- Vygotsky, L. S. (1991). Genesis of the higher
nitive Science Society (pp. 487-492). Mahwah, mental functions. In P. Light, S. Sheldon, &
NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. M. Woodhead (Eds.), Learning to think: Child
Stepper, S., 8c Strack, F. (1993). Proprioceptive development in social context (Vol. 2, pp. 32-41)'
determinants of emotional and nonemotional London: Routledge.
situatingconcepts198

Walker, W. H., & Kintsch, W. (1985). Automatic Science Society (pp. 1134-1139). Mahwah, NJ
and strategic aspects of knowledge retrieval. Lawrence Erlbaum.
Cognitive Science, 9, 261-283. Weisfeld, G. E., 8c Beresford, J. M. (1982). Erect-
Wallbott, H. G. (1991). Recognition of emo- ness of posture as an indicator of dominance
tion from facial expression via imitation? or success in humans. Motivation and Emotion,
Some indirect evidence for an old theory. 6,113-131.
British Journal of Social Psychology, 30, 207- Wu, L., & Barsalou, L. W. (2008). Perceptual sim-
219. ulation in property generation. Manuscript sub-
Wattenmaker, W. D., & Shoben, E. J. (1987). mitted for publication.
Context and the recallability of concrete and Yeh, W., & Barsalou, L. W. (2006). The situated
abstract sentences. Journal of Experimental character of concepts. Journal of American Psy-
Psychobgy: Learning, Memory, SC Cognition, 13, chology; 119, 349-384.
140-150. Zatorre, R. J., Halpern, A. R., Perry, D. W.,
Wells, G. L., & Petty, R. E. (1980). The effects of Meyer, E., 8c Evans, A. C. (1996). Hearing in
overt head movements on persuasion: Com- the mind's ear: A PET investigation of musical
patibility and incompatibility of responses. imagery and perception. Journal of Cognitive
Basic and Applied Social Psychology, 1, 219- Neuroscience, 8, 29-46.
230. Zeki, S. (1993). A vision of the brain. Oxford, UK:
Wiemer-Hastings, K., Krug, J., 8c Xu, X. (2001). Blackwell Scientific.
Imagery, context availability, contextual con- Zwaan, R. A., 8c Radvansky, G. A. (1998). Situ-
straint, and abstractness. In Proceedings of ation models in language comprehension and
the 23rd Annual Conference of the Cognitive memory. Psychological Bulletin, 123,162-185.
C H A P T E R I 5

Problem Solving and Situated Cognition

David Kirsh

Introduction exploratory process is not well understood,


as it is not always systematic, but various
In the course of daily life we solve prob- heuristic search algorithms have been pro-
lems often enough that there is a special posed and some experimental support has
term to characterize the activity and the been provided for them.
right to expect a scientific theory to explain Situated cognition, by contrast, does not
its dynamics. The classical view in psychol- have a theory of problem solving to compete
ogy is that to solve a problem a subject with the classical view. It offers no com-
must frame it by creating an internal rep- putational, neuropsychological, or mathe-
resentation of the problem's structure, usu- matical account of the internal processes
ally called a problem space. This space is underlying problem cognition. Nor does it
an internally generable representation that explain the nature of the control of exter-
is mathematically identical to a graph struc- nal processes related to problem solving.
ture with nodes and links. The nodes can Partly this is a matter of definition. Prob-
be annotated with useful information, and lems are not regarded to be a distinct cate-
the whole representation can be distributed gory for empirical and computational analy-
over internal and external structures such sis because what counts as a problem varies
as symbolic notations on paper or diagrams. from activity to activity. Problems do arise
If the representation is distributed across all the time, no matter what we are doing.
internal and external structures the sub- But from a situated cognition perspective
ject must be able to keep track of activ- these problems should not be understood
ity in the distributed structure. Problem as abstractions with a formal structure that
solving proceeds as the subject works from may be the same across different activities.
an initial state in this mentally supported Each problem is tied to a concrete setting
space, actively constructing possible solu- and is resolved by reasoning in situation-
tion paths, evaluating them and heuristi- specific ways, making use of the material and
cally choosing the best. Control of this cultural resources locally available. What is

264
problem s o lving a n d situated cognition
177

called a problem, therefore, depends on the explain how people solve problems that are
discourse of that activity, and so in a sense, is ill defined, which they recognized a large
socially constructed. There is no natural kind class of problems to be.
called "problem" and no natural kind process To develop their theory they presented
called "problem solving" for psychologists to subjects with a collection of games and puz-
study. Problem solving is merely a form of zles with unique solutions or solution sets.
reasoning that, like all reasoning, is deeply Having a correct answer - a solution set -
bound up with the activities and context in is the hallmark of a problem being well
which it takes place. Accordingly, the situ- defined. Problems were posed in contexts
ational approach highlights those aspects of in which the experimenter could be sure
problem solving that reveal h o w much the subjects had a clear understanding of what
machinery of inference, computation, and they had to solve. Games and puzzles were
representation is embedded in the social, chosen because they are self-contained; it is
cultural, and material aspects of situations. assumed that no special knowledge outside
This critical approach to problem solving of what is provided is needed to solve them.
is what I shall present first. In Part 11 discuss These sorts of problems have a strict defi-
the assumptions behind the classical psycho- nition of allowable actions (you move your
logical theory. In Part 2 I present the major pawn like this), the states these actions cause
objections raised by those believing that cog- (the board enters this configuration), and a
nition must be understood in an embodied, strict definition of when the game or puzzle
interactive, and situated way, and not pri- has been solved, won, or successfully com-
marily as a cognitive process of searching pleted (opponent's king is captured). It was
through mental or abstract representations. assumed that subjects who read the prob-
There is a tendency in the situated cogni- lem would be able to understand these ele-
tion literature to be dismissive of the clas- ments and create their internal representa-
sical view without first acknowledging its tion. Such problems are both well defined
flexibility and sophistication. Accordingly, I and knowledge lean, as "everything that the
present the classical account in its best form subject needs to know to perform the task
in an effort to appreciate what parts may be is presented in the instructions" (VanLehn,
useful in a more situated theory. In Part 3 I 1989, p. 528). No special training or back-
collect pieces from both accounts, situated ground knowledge is required.
and classical, to move on to sketch a more
positive theory - or at least provide desider-
ata for such a theory - though only frag- 2. T a s k E n v i r o n m e n t
ments of such a view can be presented here.
In the classical theory, the terms problem
and task are interchangeable. Newell and
PART 1 : T H E C L A S S I C A L T H E O R Y Simon introduced the expression task envi-
ronment to designate an abstract structure
1. Newell and S i m o n ' s T h e o r y that corresponds to a problem. It is called an
environment because subjects who improve
In an extensive collection of papers and task performance are assumed to be adapt-
books, Herbert Simon, often with Allen ing their behavior to some sort of environ-
Newell, presented a clear statement of the mental constraints, the fundamental struc-
now-classical approach to problem solv- ture of the problem. It is abstract because
ing (see, among others, N e w e l l & Simon, the same task environment can be instan-
1972). Mindful that science regularly pro- tiated in very different ways. In chess, for
ceeds from idealization, Simon and N e w e l l example, the task environment is the same
worked from the assumption that a the- whether the pieces are made of wood or sil-
ory based on how people solve well-defined ver or are displayed on a computer screen.
problems can be stretched or augmented to A n y differences arising because agents need
DAVID KIRSH

to interact differently in different physical nomenon. The same would apply to other
contexts are irrelevant. It does not matter things nonexperts do when they play, SUcj1
whether an agent moves pieces by hand, as putting a finger on a piece, trying |f
by mouse movements, by requesting some- possible actions on the board, using pencil
one else to make the move for them, or and paper, talking to oneself, or consulting
by writing down symbols and sending a a book (if allowed at all). All are assumed
description of their move by mail. Issues irrelevant to task performance. They may
associated with solving these movement or occur while a subject is working on a prob-
communication subtasks belong to a differ- lem, or while playing chess, but, according
ent problem. to the classical account, they are not liter-
A task environment, accordingly, delin- ally part of problem-solving activity. This is
eates the core task. It specifies an under- obviously a point of dispute for situation-
alists, as many of these actions are regularly
lying structure that determines the rele-
observed during play, and they may critically
vant effects of every relevant action that a
affect the success of an agent.
given agent can perform. This has the effect
that if two agents have different capacities
for action they face different task environ-
ments. When four-legged creatures confront 3. Problem Space
an obstacle, they face a different locomo-
tion problem than two-legged creatures, and Task environments are differentiated from
both problems are different from the loco- problem spaces, the representation sub-
motion problem the obstruction poses to jects are assumed to mentally construct
a snake. Thus, two agents operating in the when they understand a task correctly. This
same physical environment, each facing the problem-space representation might be dis-
same objective - get from a t o b - may face tributed over external resources. It encodes
different task environments because of their the following:
different capacities. Their optimal path may
be different. Moreover, of all the actions a | The current state of the problem. At the
creature or subject can perform, the only beginning this is the initial state.
ones that count as task relevant are the ones • A representation of the goal state or con-
that can, in principle, bring it closer to or far- dition - though this might be a procedure
ther from an environmental state meeting or test for recognizing when the goal has
the goal condition. It is assumed that dif- been reached, rather than a declarative
ferences in expertise and intellectual ability statement of the goal.
affect search and reasoning rather than the I Constraints determining allowable moves
definition of the task itself. and states, hence the nodes and allow-
Task environments are theoretical projec- able links of the space I these too
tions that let researchers interpret problem- may be specified implicitly in procedures
solving activity in concrete situations. They for generating all and only legal moves
identify what counts as a move in a problem rather than explicitly in declarative state-
(for a given agent). As such, they impose ments.
a powerful filter over the way a researcher • Optionally, other representations that
interprets subjects' actions. Scratching one's may prove useful in understanding prob-
head during chess, for instance, is an action lem states or calculating the effects of
that would be interpreted by a researcher as action.
irrelevant to the game. It not only would lie
outside the task environment of chess con- Some of these other representations encode
strued as the set of possible chess moves but
knowledge of problem-solving methods,
also would be treated as having no relevance
heuristics, or metrics specific to the cur-
to the game in any other way - an epiphe-
rent task environment. Others encode
PROBLEM SOLVING AND SITUATED COGNITION
267

Figure 1 5 . 1 . The different versions of the Tower of Hanoi shown in


15.1a share the same abstract task environment, shown in the graph
structure displayed in 15.1b. All the versions have the same legal
moves in an abstract sense, the goal of the game is the same, and
the strategies for completion are the same. At a more microscopic
level, moving heavy pieces in one game may require additional
planning, but these extra moves and extra plans are not thought to
be part of the game. Because the game is defined abstractly, any
differences in the action repertoire of an agent are irrelevant. In
other tasks we base our analysis of the task on the actions the agent
can perform, so that more powerful agents may face different tasks
than less powerful ones. Choice of level of abstraction is a
theoretical decision.
223davidkirsh

methods, heuristics, and metrics that are P A R T 2: C R I T I C I S M OF THE


domain independent, such as general meth- CLASSICAL THEORY
ods of search, measures of when one is
getting closer to a goal, and typical ways 1. Initial S u m m a r y of Objections
of overcoming impasses that arise in the
solution-finding process. The ideas of task environment and problem
space have a formal elegance that is seduc-
tive. They encourage treating problem solv-
4. Ill-Defined Problems ing as an area of psychology that can be stud-
ied using existing methods of mathematics
Puzzle and game cognition seems to fit this and experimentation. But they can also jus-
formal, knowledge-lean approach - at least tifiably be attacked from many sides, and
in part. But Simon recognized that most of not just because efforts to extend the the-
the problems we encounter in life are not ory to ill-defined problems have been mostly
well defined in this formal sense. Some have unsuccessful. Four objections that are con-
no unambiguously right answer, the result genial to a situated approach to cognition
of applying an operational goal condition deserve close examination.
to possible solutions. This may be because
there are many grades and forms of adequate
1.1. Framing and Registration
answer, as is typical of problems arising in
architecture, engineering, cooking, writing, Framing and registration processes are inte-
and other creative or design-related work. gral to the problem-solving process and
Or it may be because the notion of what arguably the hardest part of it. The formal
constitutes an adequate answer is not known theory treats the heart of problem solving
in advance, and part of what a problem to be search. Indeed, this is the only part
solver must learn in the course of working on explained by the classical theory. But search
a problem is what counts as a better answer. in a problem space only makes sense after
Still other problems have no fixed set of the hard work of framing has been done -
operators relevant to a problem space - no after a problem has been well posed and
fixed set of choice points, fixed conse- put into a searchable graph structure. It is
quence function, fixed evaluation func- one thing to do this for games where the
tion, or well-defined constraints on feasible operations and objectives are typically told
actions. Think of the problem a painter faces to us explicitly. It is another to do this for
when confronting a blank canvas in a studio everyday problems, where we have to decide
with all the paints, media, brushes, and tools what is relevant and what is irrelevant. In
he or she might ever want. Goals, operators, artificial intelligence, a closely related prob-
choice points, consequence, and evaluation lem of bounding the scope of what needs
functions are either undetermined by the to be considered in planning, reasoning, and
very nature of the problem, or they have to solving problems is called the "frame prob-
be learned microgenetically, in the course of lem," and it remains an open question how
activity. The problem is largely being made people do this.
up as it is being worked on (cf. Reitman,
Moreover, what is the justification for
1964}.
treating the abstraction or framing part
Simon regarded the prevalence of ill- of problem solving to be separate and
defined problems as a challenge to the clas- unconnected from the problem-solving part,
sical theory but not an insurmountable one. which is assumed to be search? It may seem
Cognitive theories should start first with the intuitive to see problem solving as having
clear, central cases of problems - which parts: recognize a problem in a concrete sit-
for Simon are well defined and knowledge uation; abstract, frame, or bound the prob-
lean - and then move outward to harder lem; find a solution; and reinterpret the
cases. solution in the concrete setting. It may seem
problem s o lv i n g a n d situated c o g n i t i o n
177

intuitive that we can modularize these parts and proceed without consulting and recon-
and study each component. B u t whether suiting the recipe? Plan and execution are
justified or not - and there are good reasons connected in nonsimple ways. The interim
to challenge the modularization of steps - effects of following a recipe alert a cook to
why accept that the locus of difficulty, the details of the steps that need close atten-
real challenge of problem solving, concerns tion. This interactive process of going back
the search part? Framing is notoriously hard, and forth, between world and representa-
and so is registration. tion (recipe), shows that there are two sides
To understand the registration problem, to the registration problem: encoding and
imagine yourself in a shopping mall, stand- decoding.
ing in front of a wall m a p , trying to find a Registration and framing are related
path from your current location to a spe- because in registering a problem one also has
cific store. Which is harder: figuring out to find a way of tying concrete elements of
where you are relative to the m a p , assum- a situation with a problem representation.
ing the map does not h a v e an icon with a Framing adds a further element: a bias on
"You are here" label, or finding a path f r o m the knowledge that is relevant. When peo-
a to b on the map? For m o s t of us find- ple think about something they see as prob-
ing the path is the easy part. T h a t is the lematic, they typically frame their difficulty
part that is analogous to search in a problem in terms of their immediate understanding
space. It is far harder to figure out where you of their situation, an understanding that
are and then translate the path y o u found comes with preconceptions of what is
back into action in the world. T h o s e are the relevant and potentially useful. This is
registration parts: connecting the abstract often constraining. Problems of cooking, for
search space (whether internal or external) instance, are framed in terms of ingredients,
to the real world, and then reinterpreting the flame size, and pots and pans, rather than in
results of search, or some other action per- terms of concepts in chemistry (e.g., reac-
formed on an abstract representation, back tion potential, catalyst) we may have learned
into domain-specific terms. in school and that are, in principle, rele-
Given the interactive nature of problem vant to understanding the cooking process.
solving, the back-and-forth process of act- Expert chemists may bring such domain-
ing, observing the result, and then thinking external views to the cooking process. And
of the next move, agents almost never do all expert mathematicians or expert modelers
their work in a problem space and then act in may bring the capacity to neatly formal-
the world. They constantly translate moves ize the concrete. But for the rest of us it
in their abstract problem space into actions is hard to get beyond the concrete to the
in their concrete context and back again. abstract and general. If we could appreci-
How subjects frame and interpret a problem ate the abstract in the concrete, we would
therefore is essential to h o w they will pro- recognize analogies and be able to transfer
ceed and how easy it is to translate between learning from one domain to another more
problem space and world. T h e more abstract readily than we do. The reason we do not
a problem space, the m o r e distant it is from is because our understanding of problems
the specifics of the current situation, and the is usually tied to the resources and tools
harder this translation process is. Think of at hand. We are hampered by the mindset
the distance between a recipe in a cookbook appropriate to the setting in which our activ-
and its concrete execution by a cook in the ity takes place.
kitchen. The recipe represents a solution to Given the way problems arise in natural
the problem of creating a certain dish given contexts, the burden of explanation ought
certain ingredients. But w h e n cooks execute to lie in psychology to show both that (a)
a recipe they go back and forth between people do have an abstract problem space
the paper representation and their kitchen. representation of problems they solve, and
Why can't they just r e m e m b e r the steps (b) the hard part of problem solving is not
270 david kirsh

to be found in the process of going back and graph paper, calculators, algorithms, tricks
forth between situational understanding and of the trade, free advice - that make their
problem space understanding, but in search. reasoning job easier. Even when no problem
This is the challenge which greater attention aids are lying around, the type of problem
to the processes of framing and registration encountered is not a worst-case problem but
pose to the classical view. To my mind it has a simpler version of a problem that only in
never been answered. its general f o r m is hard to solve. It is well
known that problems that are computation-
ally complex w h e n conceived in their gen-
1.2. Interactivity and Epistemic Activity
eral form invariably have many special forms
Examination of actual problem solving in that are quite easy to solve. Usually these
ecologically natural contexts as opposed to are the ones people actually confront, and
white-room environments reveals a host of posing a problem in its more general form,
interactions with resources and cultural ele- as so often is done in the classical approach
ments that figure in the many phases of makes the problem harder, encouraging cog-
problem solving, such as understanding the nitive scientists to propose solution methods
problem, exploring its scope and constraints, that people do not have to follow.
getting a sense of options, and developing It is not an accident that we encounter
a metric for evaluating progress toward a special cases. We live most of our life in
solution. People generate a range of inter- constructed environments. Layers of arti-
mediate structures. In reducing problem facts saturate almost every place we go,
solving to search in a problem space, the and there are preexisting practices for doing
classical approach minimizes and misunder- things. These artifacts and practices have
stands the complexity and centrality of local been designed, or have coevolved, to make
interaction. us smarter, to make it easier for us to
There is much more going on dur- solve our problems and perform our habit-
ing problem solving than searching in an ual tasks. E v e r y w h e r e there are scaffolds and
abstracted problem space. Most of these other resources to simplify problem solving,
actions-interactions lie outside the narrow including people to ask. Part of what we
definition of the problem. Although this learn is h o w to use these resources and par-
echoes the first objection in stressing that ticipate in the relevant practices. Approach-
problem solving is not reducible to search, ing a problem as if it must be posed in
it pushes that argument further by focusing its general form ignores the efficiencies and
on the nature of agent-environment inter- kludges that t y p i f y natural beings living in
action during problem solving. People do worlds scaffolded and designed for them.
many more task-relevant things when prob- It supposes that our main problem-solving
lem solving than those allowed for in the skills are tied to search, when in fact they
strict definition of their task or problem. may be more closely related to our abil-
The notion of a task environment is far ity to manage our artifacts, make effective
too narrow. These task-exogenous actions use of scaffolds, and conform to practice.
affect both the process and success of prob- To focus on the 3 percent of problems only
lem solving. Addressing this issue requires some of us solve risks misunderstanding the
ethnographic attention to the real-world remaining 97 percent of problems we all
details of problem solving. solve.

1.3. Resources and Scaffolds 1 . 4 . Knowledge Rich

Once focus shifts from puzzles to real prob- Most problems people face in daily life are
lems arising in everyday environments, it is not like knowledge-lean problems in which
apparent that subjects have access to cul- all relevant aspects of each problem can
tural products - tools, measuring devices, be given in a c o m p a c t problem statement.
277
problem s o lving a n d situated cognition

Naturally occurring problems rarely occur matter even more. They activate an inter-
¡ n a vacuum, where all an agent needs to pretive framework that primes agents to
bow can be encapsulated in a f e w simple look for and conceptualize features of their
sentences. We typically bring more knowl- environment in activity-specific ways, bias-
edge and expertise than formal accounts ing what they see as problematic and what
of problem solving discuss. Consider cook- they see as the natural or at-hand resources
ing, cleaning, shopping, gardening, the tasks available to solve such problems. Problems,
confronted in offices that involve computer goals, operators, and representations are not
applications, or editing documents. In each abstract. They arise in concrete settings
case an intelligent novice performs less well where agents have certain activities they
than experienced participants. It might be have to perform. Features of these activity
that experience can be reduced to familiar- spaces affect the way the problem is repre-
ity with search heuristics, domain metrics, sented and framed.
and the like. But much surely has to do Lave (1988) and others (Rogoff & Lave,
with knowing how to pose, view, dissolve, 1984) have explored the effects of con-
and work around problems, and knowing text on problem conceptualization. In com-
what is most effective in specific situations menting on her well-known ethnography
and how to coordinate the use of local of mathematical activity in supermarkets,
resources - a deep knowledge of cases. Theo- Lave wrote: "I have t r i e d . . . to understand
ries of knowledge-rich problem solving have how mathematical activity in grocery stores
become important in the literature since the involved being 'in' the 'store,' walking up
1980s. But even these studies place too lit- and down 'aisles,' looking at 'shelves' full of
tle emphasis on the centrality of resources, cans, bottles, packages and jars of food, and
scaffolds, interactivity, and cultural support. other commodities" (Lave, 1996, p. 4). Each
Almost none explain the process by which of these domain-specific terms has an impact
people understand problems. on the way problems are conceptualized and
In the next sections I will develop each posed.
argument further, calling attention to sup- To show that mathematical activity is not
porting articles in both the situated and the same across settings, Lave looked at the
classical literature where many of these techniques and methods shoppers in super-
concerns have been recognized but left markets use to solve some of their typical
unanswered. problems of choice, such as whether can
A is a better buy than can B. She found
that even though unit prices are printed on
2, Framing a n d R e g i s t r a t i o n supermarket labels, shoppers rarely check
them to decide what to buy. Instead they
2.1. Framing
use less general strategies such as, "Prod-
The heart of the framing and encoding uct A would cost $10 for 10 oz., and prod-
argument is that natural problems arise in uct B is $9 for 10 oz., hence product B is
concrete settings where agents are already the cheaper buy." Or faced with a choice
operating in activity-specific provinces of between a 5 oz. packet costing $3.29 and a
meaning. It matters whether an agent is 6 oz. packet priced at $3.59, the shopper
playing chess by mail or playing chess with would argue, "If I take the larger packet, it
a young child using Disney characters. T h e will cost me 30 cents for an extra ounce. Is it
context affects the way the game is concep- worth it?"
tualized and framed (e.g., chess for com- W h y do shoppers ignore unit price? It is
petition, chess for teaching beginners). This clear that they are not indifferent to unit
framing colors choice, evaluation, and local price because they usually use strategies that
objectives, all factors involved in creating a involve price comparison between specific
problem space. In tasks that are less abstract items. But as retailers well know, the actual
than chess the setting and local resources problem a shopper solves has many more
271 DAVID KIRSH

variables. When people make a decision same problems in school, where they used
about what to take home they also con- the school-taught procedures. The authors
sider where they will store the items, how noted that in the street, both children and
long each item will last, how quickly it older vendors used convenient groups for
will be used, and the family's attitude to their additions, such as "three for 105," and
brand. Cans are hefted, labels are exam- that simple multiples of these groups, two
ined, and the factors that influence shop- or three of these three-for's were also very
pers have been made sufficiendy prominent highly practiced so that, in effect, the ven-
by producers and retailers that shoppers dors were substituting memory for summa-
can be certain to notice them. The effect tion or multiplication whenever they could.
is that reducing the problem of choice Predictably, school-taught procedures inter-
to comparing unit price strips the actual fered with this type of situation-specific
shopping problem of its complexity. More- problem solving, and predictably, the street
over, by placing competing brands side by vendor kids performed better on the street
side and placing related products nearby than nonvendors with comparable educa-
(spaghetti sauce near pasta), supermarkets tion. Context and experience framed how
provide a structure or organization for cog- the kids approached their problems and the
nitive activity that biases they way shop- resources and tools they deemed appropri-
pers think. Layout affects the way option ate. Their activity in street environments
sets are conceptualized (e.g., "I came in to was different than in classroom environ-
buy spaghetti and decided to get linguini ments. Arguably, the cognitive resources in
because I liked the look of the new Alfredo the street coevolved with the demands of
sauce"). This dynamic between product dis- street calculation.
play and consumer framing of choice has In another study, this time by Scribner
coevolved. (1984), there is an account of how milkmen
In an earlier study, Carraher, Carraher, filled orders for different kinds of milk -
and Schliemann (1985) presented a related white milk, chocolate milk, half-pints,
view. They found that Brazilian children quarts - by packing their delivery cases to
selling goods in street markets invented make delivery more efficient and physically
special purpose procedures to add up less effortful. This again is a numerical prob-
prices and calculate change rather than use lem that was solved using contextualized
the more general pencil-and-paper meth- knowledge.
ods they learned in school. They framed Scribner noted that old-time milkmen
their problem in a domain-specific manner used their delivery case itself as a thing to
because the specialized cognitive artifacts think with, and they filled orders faster and
they used to help them calculate were the more accurately than students who filled
ones built up in local practice and readily orders using arithmetic calculations. The
available in the situation. milkmen learned the numerical relations
For example, a girl who made money for of various configurations of milk containers
the family as a street vendor, when asked the (one layer of half-pints is 16, two rows of
price of 10 coconuts selling at 35 cruzeiros quarts are 8, hence half as many as pints, and
per piece, did not use the add-o method for so forth) and used the compositional struc-
multiplying by 10, as she had been taught in ture of layers and half layers, and so on, to fill
school. She used the cost of three coconuts cases with multiples of items without count-
(105), which was a convenient group she reg- ing out each item. If they needed 35 half-
ularly sold coconuts in, added to this the pints to fill an order, they would know to fill
cost of two more of these threesomes (210), two layers and then add three more on top.
then added the cost of a single coconut (35) Deliverymen solved billing problems using a
to the running total. She correctly reported similar process of taking overlearned quan-
the price of 10 coconuts as 350 cruzeiros. tities or patterns, pulling them apart, and
Street market children did less well at these putting them back together. For instance, to
problem s o l v i n g a n d s i t u a t e d c o g n i t i o n 1 7 7

figure out the cost of 98 half-pints a natu- tles. Idiosyncrasies of the problem instance,
ral strategy was to take two times the case such as what is near to what, or how infor-
price (a case holds 48 half-pints and its price mation about price, volume, and so on, is
was memorized) and add the price of two displayed, do not matter. All that matters
half-pints. The patterns of milk cartons in is the topological structure of the problem
the case are the elements of calculation. space, or the mathematical structure of the
They became things to think with, patterns problem. And that may be the same what-
to decompose and recompose, to mentally ever the labels are for nodes and links: can
manipulate. Again context and experience size, number of bottles, distances, or simply
framed the way they saw their problems. numbers.
The methods they developed were not uni- Two findings discussed at length in the
versal, based on general algorithms for solv- problem-solving literature - problem iso-
ing arithmetic problems; they were special- morphism and mental set - bear on this
ized and situation specific. And their deep question of framing and abstraction. Both
familiarity with different situations showed support the view that subjects are sensitive
in performance. to surface attributes of a problem, so much
Cognitive scientists interested in learning so that two problems that are formally the
theory have called the mathematical knowl- same, or formally very similar, may be solved
edge displayed here "intuitive" or "naive," in such different ways and with such dif-
to distinguish it from the formal knowledge ferent speed-accuracy profiles that a process
taught in school (Hamberger, 1979). Intu- theory should treat them as different. Litde
itive knowledge is thought to be bound to is gained by seeing them as only different
the context in which the knower solves per- problem-space representations of the same
sonally relevant problems. task environment.
The issue of who is right - the situation- Take problem isomorphism first. Tic-tac-
al who looks at local resources as things toe and the game of fifteen are superficially
to think with, or the formalist who frames different versions of the same problem (see
the task more abstractly as a general type Figure 15.2). Legal moves and solutions in
of problem, in these cases math problems tic-tac-toe and legal moves and solutions in
that must be interpreted or applied to local the game of fifteen can be put in one-to-
conditions - lies at the heart of the situ- one correspondence. From a formal point
ated challenge. Which problem are people of view the problems, therefore, are iso-
trying to solve? If a subject thinks about a morphic. They have the same mathematical
problem in concrete terms such as cans and structure. Yet subjects conceptualize them
shelves, and so has an internal conception differently and their performance is differ-
and an external discourse that makes it seem ent, as measured by their speed-accuracy
as if the problem were about attributes of profiles and the pattern of errors they gen-
cans (e.g., their appearance, shape, volume, erate. Predictably, subjects rarely transfer
price, brand], why suppose he is deluded their expert methods for tic-tac-toe to the
and is really talking about a basic num- game of fifteen; they relearn them. Evi-
ber problem that happens to be couched in dendy, then, algorithms are sensitive to sur-
terms of cans? From his point of view, his face structure even if their success condi-
problem is a naturally occurring one, quite tions are not.
unlike the contrived sentence problems pre- What can be inferred? The obvious con-
sented in math class ("a bachelor comes to clusion is that details of the problem con-
a supermarket with $15 looking for the best text - the way it is presented and concep-
way to spend his money on pasta and beer. tualized, the richness of cues in the local
Spaghetti costs $1.75, fusilli cost $2.50, beer environment - determine what subjects
costs..."). From the formalist point of view, count as a solution and the resources they
however, it is irrelevant that the numbers of see as available to solve it. In the game
interest refer to attributes of cans or bot- of fifteen, if paper and pen are handy, for
david k1rsh

Figure 15.2. The task environment of the game of fifteen and


tic-tac-toe is isomorphic because there is a one-to-one
correspondence between the legal permissible moves in tic-tac-toe
and the game of fifteen. In the game of fifteen, players take turns
choosing from a set of numbered tiles. The first player to collect
three tiles that sum to fifteen wins. Because it is easy to see
opportunities for three in a row visually, but harder to see
opportunities for summing to fifteen, subjects can play tic-tac-toe
faster and with fewer errors than in fifteen. Their skills in tic-tac-toe
do not transfer and they have to releam the tricks.

instance, subjects will often mark down cess model of problem-solving cognition, we
sums and consequences of moves. How ought to attend to the way subjects distri-
shall we view these paper actions? On the bute relevant states over environmental arti-
one hand, because actions on paper cannot facts (scrap paper as well as the spatial lay-
improve the pragmatic position of a subject, out of cards or the way the tic-tac-toe board
paper and the actions it affords do not seem is filled in), and how they work out game
to be part of the problem context. On the moves by performing epistemic actions
other hand, for those who rely on paper to (Kirsh & Maglio, 1995).
work out their next move, it is an impor- Our concern here is with the possibil-
tant part of their problem-solving activity ity of finding the right level of abstraction
and makes a difference to their outcomes. to characterize the psychological processes
In tic-tac-toe, scratch paper only gets in the involved in solving problems, even well-
way. Our visual system makes spotting con- defined ones, such as the game of fifteen.
sequences of moves easy. So in the game In the gestalt theory of problem solving, it
of fifteen versus tic-tac-toe, the resources, is assumed that people see a problem as a
actions, and calculations relevant to a solu- meaningful question only against a back-
tion are, for many subjects, quite different. ground of assumptions. To a given subject
The formal state space of the two versions of something is foregrounded as problematic
the game is the same, but that space seems only against this backdrop of the unprob-
to abstract away from too many psychologi- lematic (Luchins, 1942). The possible lines of
cally and activity-relevant details to explain solution that subjects will consider, accord-
the cognitive processes involved in problem ingly, are constrained by their mental set,
solving. In fact, given such differences in which limits the information they attend
problem-solving activity, why suppose the to and the conjectures and resources they
two even share an isomorphic task environ- think are relevant. Sometimes the mental
ment? The level of abstraction needed to
set a person brings to a task or situation is
view them in the same way seems too high.
appropriate and helps in finding a solution.
Because the purpose of a task-environment
Sometimes it does not.
and problem-space approach is to provide us
An example of ways of framing and men-
with constructs sufficient to explain psycho-
tal set can prevent problem solving is found
logical and behavioral activity, we need to
in insight problems, where to solve the prob-
find the right level of abstraction to capture
lem subjects must break out of conventional
generalizations. In these two cases, there
thinking and try something nonstandard,
seems too much difference in behavioral
a trick. Usually this trick involves break-
performance. Moreover, if our goal is a pro-
ing preconceptions about what is allowable
problem s o lving and situatedcognition 177

method on new problems and persevere in


using it, even when there is a much bet-
ter way to solve the new problems. This
was seen as strong evidence for mental set
because when other subjects were shown
these alternative problems before the ini-
tial problem, they would soon learn the easy
solution methods, suggesting that learning
Figure 15.3. The nine-dot problem and its on one problem can interfere with learn-
solution. The task is to connect all dots using ing and performance on another. Further
four straight lines without lifting one's pen.
support for the presence of mental set was
Subjects frame the problem narrowly by
found by Sternberg and Davidson (1983)
assuming that lines must begin or end on dots
and Gick and Holyoak (1980, 1983), who
and cannot extend beyond them. They
incorrectly assume that all turning occurs on confirmed in new experiments that prior
dots. solution methods - prior set - worked
against finding solutions to different prob-
lems, problems that subjects without that
or what is the function of an available bias would be expected to solve.
resource. The relevance of mental set for the sit-
For instance, in the nine-dot problem, uated approach is that how agents frame
Maier (1930) told subjects to find a way problems, what they see as possible actions,
to connect all the dots in a three-by-three and good methods for success, depend on
matrix by using four straight lines, with- how they interpret their situation and their
out lifting their pens or retracing any lines mindset in approaching a problem. To an
(see Figure 15.3). T h e problem is hard experienced shopper, supermarket prob-
precisely because participants do not con- lems are their own sort of problem, quite
sider making non-dot turns (Kershaw, 2004). unlike the general arithmetic problems
They rarely consider constructing lines that learned in school. To the strongly math-
extend beyond the dots, and w h e n they ematically inclined, however, supermarket
do they seldom consider making a turn in problems are more likely seen as a special
empty space, either between the dots or case of general arithmetic problems. Math-
somewhere outside the matrix. T h e prob- ematicians see through the particulars of
lem statement does not exclude these pos- the shopping situation, grasping the more
sible actions. But subjects f r a m e the prob- abstract mathematical problem. Their men-
lem as if they consider these impermissible. tal set is very different. And they worked
Framing has prevented the subject f r o m cre- hard to achieve that competence. To less
ating the right problem space, perhaps even mathematical reasoners, however, the sup-
from grasping the right task environment. porting resources and scaffolds are so differ-
In separate work on mental set, in what is ent and the tricks and visible cues are so dif-
commonly regarded as the classical demon- ferent that, initially, at any rate, their whole
stration of set, Luchins (1942) presented sub- mindset is different. The problem is differ-
jects with water-jug problems in which they ent.
had to figure out how to get a certain amount Even if one recognizes the abstract prob-
of water (e.g., five cups), using any combi- lem posed, the resources available still can
nation of three jugs: jug A holds eighteen strongly affect the method used to solve it.
cups, jug B holds forty-three cups, and jug For instance, in math class at school students
C holds ten cups. T h e y w e r e free to dip their have pencil and paper. They write numbers
jugs into a well as many times as they like. down and rely on algorithms defined over
Luchins found that after subjects get the the inscriptions they create. To multiply two
hang of the solution method and have more numbers they line them up and use one
or less automatized it, they try to use that of the multiplication algorithms. T h e same
276
DAVID KIRSH

holds for division and determining ratios. and rerepresenting, so that reformulation is
Without pencil and paper, however, tech- a key part of problem solving, and that fram-
niques and methods usually change. Even ing, therefore, does not occur once and prob-
mathematicians might prefer to think with lem solving begins afterward; the two are
local artifacts if faced with a problem that is often intertwined. Second, even when a sub-
cumbersome to solve in their head. ject is searching a problem space the search
The upshot is that though a task anal- process is complicated by the need to con-
ysis may be important to determine the tinually anchor t h e search space in locally
success conditions of different approaches, meaningful ways. Search itself is an interac-
and indeed necessary to explain why they tive process that should not be reduced to
work, such analyses seem remote from a pro- internal symbol manipulation.
cess theory. A psychological theory ought to To appreciate these points, it is illumi-
explain the many phases and dynamics of nating to contrast t h e concepts of registra-
the problem-solving process: how one sees tion and translation. In mapping a game of
a problem; why one sees it that way; and fifteen back into tic-tac-toe, we perform a
how one exploits resources, interacts with translation. We similarly perform a transla-
resources, and solves the problem in accept- tion w h e n we m a p a word problem (Mary
able time. The bottom line, for the moment, is two inches taller than Peter who is...)
is that how agents frame a problem, how into a simple algebraic statement, or puzzles
they project meaning into a situation, deter- and games (nine dots, chess) into searchable
mines the resources they see as relevant to its graphs, or a problem in Euclidean geom-
solution. If street vendors frame the "How etry into a problem in analytic geometry
much for ten of these?" problems in terms using Cartesian coordinates. The value of
of today's price for three and today's price the mapping is t h a t t h e new representation
for one, then they prime a set of tools of offers another perspective with different
thought distinct from those they learned in methods and techniques, often simplifying
school. They do not look at the problem problem solving. But the mapping process
deeply. As work on transfer has shown, they links two representations, or representa-
stay on the surface, interpreting the problem tional systems, and that is the key thing.
in superficial ways. Well-defined entities or relations in one rep-
resentational system are mapped onto well-
defined entities or relations in the other.
2.2. Registration
By contrast, w h e n we orient and reori-
As important as it is to extend the theory ent a city or mall m a p to determine how
of problem solving to explain how problems the representations of buildings, pathways,
are framed, this way of structuring problem and openings correspond with the buildings,
solving still seems to locate the real part - pathways, and openings in the actual space,
the solving part - to take place after a task we are registering t h e map, not translating
has been represented as a problem space; it, because we are trying to match up dis-
that heuristic search, in one form or another, crete representational elements in the two-
is the driving force in problem solving, and dimensional m a p with nonrepresentational
that expertise is substantially about acquir- and often nondiscrete elements in the three-
ing the right heuristics, metrics, and gener- dimensional world, t h e arena where we per-
alizations of cases as if framing is just a way form physical actions. This means that much
of preparing for problem solving, not of solv- of problem-solving acumen, when registra-
ing it. tion is involved, may lie in knowing how
Two reasons to question this clean to link representations (whether internal,
account are that first, creating a problem external, or distributed over the two), with
space may be a highly interactive process of entities, attributes, and relations in the phys-
framing, representing, exploring, reframing, ical domain.
problem s o lving and situated cognition 277

Examples of registration-heavy problems then, fourth, follow it. But discovering and
often arise when something goes wrong following a route is typically interactive:
during practiced activity, when the normal look at the map, look at the surroundings,
method we use to get something done fails, locate oneself, interpret map actions in phys-
and we are thrown into problem-solving ical terms, and repeatedly do this until the
mode to figure out how to recover. Cooking, goal is in sight.
cleaning, driving, shopping, assembly, and Navigational capacities depend on con-
construction are all everyday domains where tinually linking symbolic elements in the
problems typically arise when there is a map to physical referents in the space. These
breakdown in normal activity. Much of what referents serve as anchors tying the map
makes such problem solving hard is that down to the world so that a trajectory in the
the agent is not yet sure what to attend to: map can be interpreted in terms of visible
what events, structures, or processes to see structures in space. Thus, in a shopping mall
as relevant. Every person has many frames we look for signs and arrows pointing to the
for thinking about things, but which are the food court or stores of interest to help us fig-
ones that fit the current situation? ure out where we are. We interactively make
Here is a trivial example, computer cases. our way, often by working off the physical
Computer companies regularly devise new setting rather than the map. But when plot-
ways to open and close their cases and it can ting a course we use all these cues to help
be surprisingly difficult to determine how to us orient and make sense of the path we
get inside a computer without first check- devised using the map. Subjects go back and
ing the manual. Problem solving consists of forth between map and world. The reason
pushing or pulling on pieces, scrutinizing the this constant anchoring has not been a major
case for telltale cues, for clear affordances issue is that in games such as chess, Tower
or explicit indicators. It might be said that of Hanoi, and tic-tac-toe, in math problems,
this activity is a form of external search. But and other verbally stated problems, inter-
more likely it is a form of registration: of action is focused on a spatially constrained
trying to discover a pattern of cues that can representation, the chess board, the tower,
be fit to a method we already know or to a the formulation of the problem. This sus-
mechanical frame that will make sense of tains the dlusion that problem solving is pri-
the release mechanism. This is a form of marily a matter of controlling operators in
registering because much of the reasoning an abstract representation.
involved in determining how to open the The upshot is that in many naturally aris-
case is tied to exploring the affordances of ing problems the locus of difficulty may lie as
the object and looking for ways to concep- much in the registration process, the activ-
tualize or reconceptualize its different parts. ity of selecting environmental anchors to tie
In fact, in many everyday problems, the reg- mental or physical representations to the
istration phase is more complex than the world, as it does in searching for paths in
search phase. the representation itself.
In some instances, the phases of reg-
istration and search are virtually impossi-
ble to separate. We can rationally recon- 3. Interactivity and Epistemic Actions
struct problem solving so that there are
distinct phases, but in fact the actual pro-
3.1. People Solve Problems Interactively
cess is more interactive. This is especially In most problem-solving situations people
trueofwayfinding with a map. We can, if we do not sit quiedy until they have an answer
like, describe map use sequentially: first, ori- and then announce it all at once. They do
ent the map with immediate landmarks to things along the way. If it is a word prob-
establish a correspondence; second, deter- lem (John is half as tall as M a r y . . . ) , they
mine current position; third, plot a route; mutter, they write things down, and they
DAVID KIRSH

check the question several times. If they are complexity of a problem, or as a mechanism
solving an assembly task (here are the parts for exploring the structure of a problem or
of a bicycle, assemble it), they will typi- as a way of engaging other sorts of behaviors
cally feel the pieces, try out trial assemblies, that might help subjects solve their prob-
and incrementally work toward a solution. lems. External activity was still related to
Rarely does anyone work out a complete search, one way or another. A theory of sit-
solution in their head and then single- uated problem solving should give the prin-
mindedly execute it. People, like most other ciples of more interactive approaches.
creatures, solve things interactively in the
world. 3.2. The Role of External Representations
The classical approach to problem solv-
ing failed to adequately accommodate this Although Simon and other exponents of the
in-the-world and not just in-the-head inter- classical theory never accepted the central-
activity in two ways. First, the classical the- ity of interactivity, they took an important
ory, in its strictest form, assumed that users step forward when they began paying more
completely search an internal representation attention to the role external representations
of their problem before acting. Heuristics play. Larken and Simon (1987) enlarged the
were proposed as a mechanism for reduc- orthodox account to allow problem states to
ing the complexity of this internal search so be partially encoded internally and partially
that solutions could actually be found. They encoded externally. Accordingly, to solve
were not meant to help a user figure out a geometric or algebraic problem, subjects
the next single action to perform; they were might rely on applying operators to external
meant to help a user figure out a whole plan, symbols, equations, illustrations of geomet-
an entire sequence of actions. This "Make a ric figures, and so forth. Instead of repre-
plan before you act" hypothesis was derived senting the transformations of the equation
from Miller, Galanter, and Pribram (i960), 2x + 4y = 40 in one's head, as in mental rep-
and not surprisingly was repeatedly chal- resentations for 2(x + 237) = 40 followed by
lenged in the planning literature, both in AI x + 2y = 20, Larken and Simon showed that
and in psychology. it might be easier to generate such represen-
The second way interactivity was mis- tational states in the world and track where
understood was that it was never seen as a one is both mentally and physically to decide
force for reshaping either the search process what to do next.
or the problem space. Artificial intelligence The special value of external representa-
theorists were quick to appreciate the value tions is obvious in visual problems, such as
of incorporating sensing and perception into tic-tac-toe. Vision is a computational prob-
planning. But most AI planners incorrectly lem that terrestrial animals devote huge neu-
assumed that any actions that users per- ral resources to solve. In tic-tac-toe, the
form in the world during problem solving computational cost of evaluating the con-
are either sequences of a move can be borne by the
visual system, which exploits parallel and
• External analogues of internal search - highly efficient methods to project the out-
instances of searching in the world instead comes of placements. This makes it easy to
of in the head, or see that one or another move is pointless.
• Stepwise execution of an incomplete For instance, in Figure 15.4a, given a visual
plan - starting to implement a partial display of the board, it is obvious where 0
solution (or plan) before having the com- must move to prevent immediate defeat.
plete one in mind - then replanning in Choice can be made without serious con-
light of the resultant world state. sideration of other moves. Solving the same
problem algebraically, as in the game of fif-
External interactivity was never (or rarely) teen, or solving the same problem in one s
seen as a mechanism for reducing the head, especially more complex versions (see
problem s o l v i n g a n d s i t u a t e d c o g n i t i o n 1 7 7 177

explore a mental image of the same


thing (see Figure 15.5).

If you look at a Necker cube for half


a minute or more your interpretation will
almost certainly toggle, and the surfaces you
see as front and back will swap places. That
is, if you first see A as the front face and B
as the back, then after a short while you will
Figure 15.4. In harder versions of tic-tac-toe it is see B as the front and A as the back. This
nearly impossible to determine the best moves swapping of faces, this reinterpretation of
without a visual representation of the board. the figure, does not occur in mental images.
Although the board state of 15.4a can be A mental image is an intentional object and
generated internally, and players can easily play as such must be sustained under an interpre-
without looking at the board, the cost of tation. If a mental image were conceptual-
sustaining such states in mind increases with the ized as an organized set of lines not yet inter-
complexity of the mental image or preted as a cube, then new mental images
representation. In 15.4b, the five-by-five board is
might arise from thinking about the image.
much less easy to keep in mind. To win it is
But if it is maintained as a unified object -
necessary to get four in a row anywhere. As the
structure of the problem increases and the a gestalt - it will not toggle unless decon-
complexity of the current state rises, vision pays structed into constituent lines. People rarely
off. The interactive nature of vision scales better deconstruct their mental images.
with board complexity. What if the same cognitive limitations
apply to internal problem spaces? What if
visual operators can explore parts of a search
Figure 15.4b) is significantly harder. It is both space more broadly than internal operators
cognitively easier and computationally sim- acting on mental representations of the same
pler to use the external representation than structure? This would suggest that certain
an internal representation. problems might be solved only when they
In treating problem solving as a process
that may be partly in the mind and partly
in the world, the classical view took a big
step toward a more situated perspective. But
the assumed value of external representa-
tions lay in the increased efficiency of apply-
ing visual operators and the stimulating role
external representations can play in search.
Using external representations was not seen
as forcing a revision of the way problem solv-
ing unfolds. In particular, a concern with
external representations did not lead to a
discussion of other ways external resources
figure in problem solving. Let us consider Figure 15.5. The Necker cube and other visually
the role of external representations more ambiguous structures have more than one
closely. interpretation, which subjects discover after a
short while. When the cube is visually before
them, they scan the edges, propagating
Expanding the search space. In an elegant constraints. But when the same image is
demonstration, Chambers and Ries- imagined, the ambiguity of the figure goes
berg (1985) showed that how people undetected. It is grasped as a whole, without the
visually explore an external represen- need of "mental saccades" to test its integrity
tation is often different from how they and sustain it.
223davidkirsh

are represented externally in figures or sym- decimal notation is better than binary f0r
bols. This would be a curious form of cogni- certain operations, such as dividing by 1-
tive set. the binary is simpler for other operations
In some of his work, Simon came close such as dividing by 64. The proponents of
to making this point. In several coauthored the classical view certainly knew this and
articles he considered the role that auxil- often discussed the importance of problem
iary representations play in helping subjects representation, but they never took the next
solve algebraic word problems. He found step.
that students used diagrams to detect addi- Their appreciation of the importance
tional assumptions about the problem situ- of diagrams, illustrations, and word for-
ation that were not obvious from the ini- mulations for problem-solving performance
tial algebraic encoding of word problems never led to a major departure from
(Simon, 1979). Although such additional the problem-space, task-environment idea.
assumptions could in principle be discov- Externalization was not seen as establishing
ered from the algebraic encoding alone, sub- a need to shift focus from problem spaces to
jects found the cost of elaboration too great. affordances or to the cues and constraints of
Discovering such assumptions without dia- external structures. It never led to a revised
grams requires far too much inference. concern for observing what people actually
Given the interest in problem isomorphs do, in an ethnographic sense, when they
at the time, proponents of the (revised) clas- solve problems.
sical view did not regard the value of exter-
nal representations as grounds for shifting 3 . 3 . Adding Structure to the Environment
the focus of problem-solving research away
from heuristic search in problem spaces, to W h e n we do look closely at the range of
replace it with a study of how subjects inter- activities that people perform during the
actively engage external resources. It was course of solving or attempting to solve
instead seen as further evidence that how problems, we find many things that do not
subjects interpret problems affects their neatly fit the model of search in an internal
problem-solving behavior. It nicely fit the or external problem space.
problem isomorph literature showing that For instance, in their account of subjects
surface representation strongly determines playing the computer game Pengo, Agre and
problem-solving trajectory. Chapman (1987) discussed how a computer
In some respects it is surprising that the program, and by analogy humans, could
classical theory did not embrace interactivity exhibit planned behavior without search.
at this point. The idea that it is useful, and at Their program worked interactively. It used
times necessary, to transform problems into a set of simple rules to categorize the envi-
different representational notations or rep- ronment in a highly context-sensitive man-
resentational systems is a truism in problem ner. The environment that Pengi - the name
solving in math, and in science more gener- of the computerized penguin that Pengo
ally. Every representational system makes it players were attempting to control - con-
easy to represent certain facts or ideas and sists of blue ice-blocks distributed in a ran-
harder to represent others. What is explicit dom maze. Pengi starts in the center and
in one representation may be implicit in the villains of the game, the sno-bees, setoff
another (Kirsh, 1991, 2003)1 For example, in from the corners. If Pengi is stung it dies, but
decimal notation it is trivial to determine it can defend itself by kicking an ice-block
that 100 is divisible by 10. But when 100 directly in front of a sno-bee thereby crush-
is represented in binary notation as 110010 ing it. If Pengi was chasing a bee, Agre and
it is no longer trivial. This holds whether Chapman's system would classify the struc-
we translate 10 into its binary equivalent, tural arrangement of the ice-blocks one way.
101, or keep it in decimal notation. The If Pengi was running away from a bee, the
problem s o lvinga n d s i t u a t e d cognition1 7 7
177

system would classify the v e r y s a m e arrange- problem to another person is an effec-


ment of ice-blocks another w a y . To achieve tive method to identify and clarify givens,
this difference in classification the system to articulate problem requirements, and to
attached visual markers - visual m e m o r y expose constraints on problem solutions or
projections or annotations - to certain parts solution paths (Brown, Collins, & Duguid,
of the situation. T h u s , on t w o occasions, the 1989). Some of this facilitation, no doubt,
same objective state m i g h t be classified in occurs because different representations ele-
two ways depending on w h i c h of Pengi's vate different aspects of a problem. But
goals were active, b e c a u s e t h e w o r l d w o u l d some of it, as well, is due to the known value
be visually annotated d i f f e r e n t l y (see Fig- of talking out loud during problem solving
ure 15.6). (Behrend, Rosengren, & Perlmutter, 1989).
Agre and C h a p m a n then s h o w e d that T h e thread common to all these differ-
with these visual markers t h e c o m p u t e r pro- ent actions is that they reduce the complex-
gram was able to b e h a v e in a strategic man- ity of the momentary computational prob-
ner using a f e w reactive rules. It w a s not lems that agents face. They help creatures
necessary to search a p r o b l e m space as long with limited cognitive resources perform at
as the system could project additional rep- a higher level.
resentational structure onto the visible envi- Here is another, more prosaic example.
ronment. T h e implication w a s that humans In a card game, such as gin rummy, play-
work this way, too. By p e r f o r m i n g certain ers tend to reorganize their hand as they
types of visual actions, including actions that play. Reorganizing a hand cannot change the
affected visual m e m o r y , h u m a n s are able to value of current cards or the value of subse-
solve problems w i t h o u t search that are both quent cards. Whether or not an ace of spades
complex and that on a priori grounds ought will be a good card to accept and the three
to require extensive search. of clubs a good card to throw away is un-
This tactic of adding structure, either affected by the way players lay out the cards
material or mental, to the e n v i r o n m e n t to in their hand. The objective problem state of
simplify problem solving is surprisingly per- the hand is invariant across rearrangement.
vasive. People mentally enrich their situa- Y e t from a psychological perspective, re-
tions in all manner of w a y s . To h e l p i m p r o v e arrangements help players to notice possi-
recall there are strategies such as the m e t h o d ble continuations and to keep track of plans.
of loci, which involves associating m e m o r y Thus, the strategy sort by suit then sort in
items with spatial positions or w e l l - k n o w n ascending order across suit, is an effective way
objects in one's environment. To improve to overcome cognitive set, or continuation
performance in geometric p r o b l e m solving, blindness. This simple interactive procedure
people project constructions, mental anno- effectively highlights possible groupings. It
tations (see Figure 15.7). is an epistemic activity. The knowledge div-
People have even m o r e diverse w a y s of idend it pays exceeds its cost to an agent in
materially enriching their situations. T h e y terms of time and effort (Kirsh, 1995b).
add reminders, perhaps w i t h Post-it Notes,
perhaps by rearranging t h e l a y o u t of books,
3.4. Epistemic Actions
papers, desktop icons, and so forth. T h e y
annotate in pen or colored pencil; they In a series of papers Kirsh (1995a, 1995b;
encode plan fragments in layouts; they keep Kirsh 8t Maglio, 1995) have argued that this
recipes open; and of course they talk with sort of epistemic activity is far more preva-
one another, o f t e n asking f o r h e l p or to lent than one might expect. Even in contexts
force themselves to articulate their ideas, where agents must respond very quickly it
using their voice as an externalized thought. still may be worth their while to perform
Indeed, it is widely a c c e p t e d that the act epistemic actions. For instance, in the arcade
of collecting one's thoughts to present a game Tetris, the problem facing players is to
237davidkirsh

Figure 15.6. Here we see the game board of Pengo as a human sees
it and a blowup of one section of a game where Pengi projects
visual markers, indicated by dots, to allow it to act as if it has a rule
"Kick the 'block-in-front-of-me' to the 'block-in-its-path.'" The dot
markers serve as indexical elements that Pengi can project so that
its current visual working memory has enough structure to drive
the appropriate reactive or interactive rules it relies on to determine
how to act. Some of these rules tell Pengi to add visual structure
and others to physically act.
problem s o lving and situated c o g n i t i o n 177

ing place. T h e novel feature of these epi-


stemic actions is that their value depends
crucially on when they are done. Because
the game is fast paced, information becomes
stale quickly. Twirling a "zoid" the moment
it enters the board is a valuable action, but it
is near useless to an expert 200 ms later.
Twirling must be timed to deliver infor-
mation exactly when it will be useful for
an internal computation. From a purely
problem-space perspective, where states
and operators have a timeless validity, there
is no room to explain these time-bound
actions. Even though epistemic actions help
agents to solve problems, and they can be
understood as facilitating search by increas-
bisecting angles, and generally adding mental
ing the speed at which a correct problem
annotations. In this example, an agent is shown
representation can be created, they are not,
a rectangle and asked to prove that a line that
cuts a rectangle in half will also cut all diagonals on the classical view, part of problem solv-
of the rectangle in half. In those cases where ing, and they do not lie on a solution path.
subjects do not draw in the diagonal and T h e y help to discover solutions, but for
bisector, they still can often find a solution by some reason they are not part of the solu-
projecting first a diagonal and then a section line tion path.
that bisects the rectangle. It is possible to add
letters to projected points such as the
intersection of the dotted bisection and the solid
diagonal. This same capacity can be used in
creative ways to add structure to other sorts of
situations by envisioning the results of
performing actions before performing them.

decide how to place small tetrazoidal shapes


on a contour at the b o t t o m of t h e b o a r d
(see Figure 15.8). As t h e g a m e speeds up, it
becomes harder f o r players b o t h to decide
where to put the shapes a n d to m a n i p u l a t e
them via a keyboard to p u t t h e m into place.
What Kirsh and M a g l i o (1995) f o u n d w a s
that players, even e x p e r t players, regularly
performed actions that h e l p e d t h e m to rec-
ognize pieces, v e r i f y t h e goodness of poten- Figure 15.8. In Tetris the goal of play is to
tial placements, and test plans (e.g., drop- relentlessly fill gaps on the bottom layers so as to
ping a piece f r o m high up on t h e b o a r d ) complete rows. The game ends when the board
clogs up and no more pieces can enter. Because
despite there being a cost to their actions in
there are mirror pieces, and the choice of where
terms of superfluous m o v e s . E v i d e n t l y the
to place a Tetris piece is strategic, players need
cost of moving a p i e c e o f f its o p t i m a l tra-
many hours of practice to become expert. We
jectory was more than c o m p e n s a t e d f o r by found that players often perform unnecessary
the benefits of s i m p l i f y i n g s o m e aspect of rotations to speed up their identification
the cognitive p r o b l e m i n v o l v e d in i d e n t i f y - process, especially among pieces with mirror
ing the piece and d e t e r m i n i n g its best rest- counterparts. (Kirsh & Maglio, 1995)
239davidkirsh

a b
Figure 15.9. The consequence of thoughtful redesign is that tasks that were error prone and hard to
manage become progressively easier. The two interfaces are small environments - tools, in a sense -
that agents must thoughtfully use to complete a task. In this case the task is to set the font style of a
region of text. By redoing the graphic layout, as in 15.9b, designers are able to lower the costs of
planning what to do, monitoring what one is doing, and verifying that one has completed the task. If
this task was treated as a problem to solve, the effect of redesign is that it is now easier, even though
the task environment is the same.

The challenge epistemic actions pose to are laden w i t h mental aids, so problem solv-
the classical approach, and to the psycholog- ing is m o r e a matter of using those aids effec-
ical study of behavior more generally, is that tively. Supermarkets tend to display com-
without an analysis of the possible episte- petitive items beside one another to help
mic functions of an action it may be nearly shoppers choose; large buildings tend to
impossible to identify the primary function have signs and arrows showing what lies
of an action and so label it correctly. Actions d o w n a corridor because people need to
that at first seem pragmatic, and so to an find their w a y ; microwaves and ovens have
observer may seem to be an ordinary move, buttons and lights that suggest what their
may not be intended by the player to be f u n c t i o n is b e c a u s e people need to know
an ordinary move. Their objective may have w h a t their options are; and most of our
been to change the momentary epistemic assembly tasks take place when we have dia-
state of the player, not the physical state grams and instructions. Wherever we go, we
of the game. This important category of are sure to find artifacts to help us. Rarely
problem-solving activity lies outside the do we f a c e knowledge-lean problems like
classical theory because the classical theory t h e T o w e r of H a n o i or desert-island prob-
operates with a fixed set of actions and a lems. O u r p r o b l e m s arise in socially orga
fixed evaluation metric. Both action reper- nized activities in w h i c h our decisions am
toire and metric are taken as objective fea-
activity are s u p p o r t e d .
tures of the task environment and assumed
T h e r e are several reasons why cultun
insensitive to the momentary epistemic state
products and artifacts saturate everyda
of the agent.
environments. First, m o s t of the enviror
m e n t s we act in h a v e b e e n adapted to hel
us. G o o d designers intentionally modify ei
4. Resources and Scaffolds v i r o n m e n t s to p r o v i d e problem solvers wi1
m o r e and b e t t e r scaffolds and resourcf
The classical theory also fails to accommo- designs t h a t m a k e it easier to complete tas
date the universality of cultural products (see F i g u r e 15.9 a n d caption). And if desig
that facilitate activity-specific reasoning. ers are n o t t h e c a u s e of redesign, it oft
Environments in which people regularly act h a p p e n s a n y w a y , as a side effect of previc
problem s o lv i n gandsituated cognition177 177

agents leaving behind useful resources after


having dealt with similar problems. Rarely
are we the first to visit a problem.
A second reason resources and scaffolds
almost always exist in our environments
is that, as problem solvers, we ourselves
construct intermediate structures that pro-
mote our own interactive cognition. As
already mentioned, we create problem- Figure 15.10. Multiplication problems are rarely
aiding resources such as illustrations, piles, solved in the head. Problem solvers reach for
annotations, and notes that function like pen and paper, line up the numbers in a strict
cognitive tools to help us to understand manner, and then produce intermediate
and explore questions and coordinate our products that are then relied on in their
algorithm. Paper, pen, graph paper, and lines are
inquiry. When we f a c e problems, we typi-
all scaffolds that help agents to reduce error. In
cally have a host of basic resources at hand:
this figure we see three ways to multiply. The
tools such as pen, paper, calculators, and
most noteworthy feature of these structures is
rulers; manipulables such as cans, cups, and the lines that guide the user. They are not
chopping boards; cultural norms of ges- elements of the algorithm. They are scaffolds
ture, style, language; and, of course, cultural indicating where the multiplicands end and the
resources and practices such as tricks f o r intermediate products of the problem solver are
solving problems, techniques, algorithms, to be placed, and so on. They help agents stay in
methods of illustration, note taking, and so control, keep on track, monitor where they are,
on. When we attempt to solve a problem, we prevent error.
reach for these aids or call on tricks and tech-
niques we have learned. M a n y of our solu-
tions or intermediate steps t o w a r d solution of the term, used it. In his view scaffolds
take the form of actions on or w i t h these are support structures in learners' immedi-
materials. They seed the environment w i t h ate environment that might permit them to
useful elements (e.g., lemmas), they m a k e solve problems that are at the periphery of
it possible to see patterns or see continua- their problem-solving ability, problems that
tions (e.g., the lines in tic-tac-toe), or they reside in what he called the "zone of prox-
make it easier to f o l l o w rules (e.g., the lines imal development." They are akin to hints.
in multiplication; see Figure 15.10). A n d intrinsic to this notion is the assump-
A final source of resources and scaffolds tion that as soon as the student internal-
is found in our neighbors or colleagues w h o izes the requisite methods, norms, heuris-
are often willing to give us a helping hand, tics, and construction skills, scaffolding will
offering hints, suggestions, tools, and so on. be unnecessary and no longer found in the
In educational theory, t h e t e r m scaffolding problem-solving situation. Workers put up
refers to the personalized problem-solving scaffolds to help them reach parts of a build-
support that an expert provides a novice. ing they cannot otherwise reach. But as soon
Help is too simple a term to describe this as they have finished their job, they remove
support because a g o o d teacher gives a the scaffold. Training wheels are a classi-
student tools, methods or m e t h o d frag- cal example of scaffold in the learning lit-
ments, and tricks about t e c h n i q u e that the erature. Other examples include the use of
student is ready to absorb b u t that, taken v o w e l markers in beginners' Hebrew that are
on their own, do not provide an answer to omitted in normal Hebrew writing because
the student's impasse. S c a f f o l d s e x t e n d the context and knowledge make them redun-
reach of a student, b u t only if t h e student is dant.
in a position to m a k e use of t h e m . T h i s w a s a
Outside of learning theory, the term
key aspect of the w a y V y g o t s k y , t h e author
scaffold is used to refer to the cultural
286 241 DAVID KIRSH

resources - artifacts, representations, norms,


policies, and practices - that saturate
our everyday work environments and that
remain even after we have internalized their
function. They reflect the supports present
in most work environments. The major-
it)' of our problem-solving abilities evolved
in these resource-heavy environments; they
rely on those resources being there.
Take the case of geometric problems. Figure 15.11. The written or formal statement of
Students leam a variety of ways to solve a geometric problem is almost impossible to
such problems but most involve construct- understand without translating it first to a
ing illustrations. Part of a student's problem- geometric diagram. In proving KL == BL,
virtually all problem solvers use the figure as an
solving competence consists in the ability to
arbitrary version of the problem that feeds
create apt illustrations and then to use them,
intuitions. Students find it simpler to reason
not just to understand the problem but to using the figure because it is easier to notice
work inside, annotating them, to solve the visual or geometric relations between properties
problem. In Figure 15.11, we see an exam- in this problem than it is to notice algebraic
ple. Rather than tackle the problem alge- relations. The validity of the proof depends on
braically, an easier approach is to modify universal generalization: a proof method where
the problem-solving environment so that it one assumes an entity, an isosceles triangle of
supports a range of different actions that certain dimensions; one then proves a key
statement about this triangle; and then one
the user finds easier to control and work
shows that nothing in the proof depended on
with. As discussed earlier, these represen-
having chosen this particular triangle as the
tations have a structure that makes the rel- example. The proof generalizes to all
evant attributes of the problem easier to right-angled isosceles triangles.
manage.

Formal Problem. A B C is an isosceles


problem as his friend w h o uses an illustra-
right-angled triangle with the right
tion? Do they operate in the same task envi-
angle at C. Points D and E, equidistant
ronment? A task environment, after all, is
from C, are chosen arbitrarily on AC
defined w i t h respect to operators too. How
and BC. Line segments from D and C
about a student w h o uses a pocket calculator
are perpendicular to AE and meet the
to determine t h e square root of 1600 versus
hypotenuse AB at K and L. Prove that
her friend, w h o calculates the value by hand:
KL = BL.
is it t h e same task environment? Tools, scaf-
folds, and resources seem to interact with
The presence of resources and scaffolds tasks, usually changing them, often in ways
in an environment does not, in itself, chal- that r e d u c e their complexity.
lenge the view that people solve problems
by searching through a problem space that
is distributed over structures in the world 5. Special-Case Solutions
and structures in the head. But it does call
into question how to formulate the prob- A favorite pastime of situationalists is to
lem that people are solving. If the resources enumerate instances in which resources in
at hand change, or are different from situa- the e n v i r o n m e n t h a v e been put to creative
tion to situation, why assume the problem use to transform the complexity of prob-
is the same? Does a student who uses alge- lem solving. No discussion of situated prob-
braic techniques solve the same geometric l e m solving w o u l d be complete without
PROBLEM SOLVING AND SITUATED COGNITION 1*7

mentioning the infamous example, "The


intelligence is in the cottage cheese" (see Fig-
ure 15.12)-
Although the method shown in Fig- Figure 15.12. To solve the problem of how much
ure 15.12 is certainly simple, it is worth not- cottage cheese two-thirds of three-quarters of a
ing just how narrow it is. It is only because cup is, a subject was observed to turn over a
the daily allotment of cottage cheese is 3/4 of one-cup tub of cottage cheese, crisscross it to
mark four quarters, remove one quarter, then
a cup, and tubs are exactly 1 cup (or because
take two of those three quarters, which is
consumers have a measuring cup on hand),
one-half. It would have been easy enough to
that it is possible to execute the algorithm
multiply 2/3 by 3/4, but typical subjects require
and use the visual cues provided by the criss- pencil and paper to do that and regard the task
crossing. This is a very special case. Weight to be effortful and confusing. The cup-sized
watchers' dieticians might have allowed 7/16 cottage cheese itself became a thing to think
of the daily portion of cottage cheese as the with.
lunch portion. And they might have decided
that the daily allotment was 3/5 of a cup.
But why would they? Problems and the
environments in which they are solved are Yet in practice, most of the problem
rarely independent. If for some reason 21/80 instances a traveling salesman actually faces
of a cup became important among a subset are not nasty. Indeed, depending on the road
of consumers, how long would it be before layout of a given sales region, it may be quite
manufacturers would change the tub size to easy to compute an optimal tour (see Fig-
make such calculations easy? ure 15.13). Would a salesman well adapted to
This highlights a key fact about situ- his specific region leam a slow general algo-
ated problem solving: it is usually narrow, rithm for solving the problem in all cases
special-case-oriented, and shallow. T h e rea- or a fast special algorithm that satisfactorily
son such approaches work is that most solves just his customary problems? Who
instances of naturally occurring problems, would be better adapted to his task? And,
even problems that are theoretically hard, if there happens to be one or two worst-case
are confined to those versions of the prob- problems lurking in his sales region where
lem that can be solved easily. T h e ones that his method gives him a suboptimal tour, the
resist simple methods are part of a small set overall cost of traveling that imperfect tour
of worst-case versions (technically known as one day a month is more than compensated
the complexity core) that people rarely if by the benefits of having cheaply found opti-
ever encounter. On those improbable occa- mal or near optimal tours the rest of the
sions where they do encounter an instance times he has gone out.
of this core, they usually do poorly. Findings in complexity theory justify
Here is an example. T h e traveling sales- this perspective. Hard problems are almost
man problem is computationally intractable always easier if a second-best answer will be
in the general case. There exist some nasty adequate much of the time. More precisely,
problem instances - the worst cases, the a problem that is NP-complete (or worse)
complexity core - where the only way to can usually be solved in polynomial time if
determine an optimal tour among all the it is acceptable to give a solution that is 1 - 6
cities the salesman must visit is by check- from the perfect answer (Padadimitriou &
ing every conceivable tour. Because a tour Yannakakis, 1988).1 The more tolerant one
consists of visiting every destination exactly is about the precision of the answer - that
once, there are as many tours as sequences is, the further from the perfect answer one
of destinations, and that is n factorial tours. can tolerate, the faster the algorithm. So
For ten cities that means checking 10! or if our traveling salesman does not require
3,628,800 tours. having the absolutely shortest path but will
david kirsh
i8s

of a more general mathematical, logical 0


planning problem. This raises a hard prob.
lem for formalists. H o w should the con-
ceptualization people actually work with -
the conceptualization that somehow figures
Easy Tour Hard Tour
in the problem space an agent creates - be
Figure 15.13. Compare these two instances of matched against the real task environment
the traveling salesperson problem. Why is the associated with the problem in its more gen.
easy tour easy to compute and the hard tour eral form?
hard? Because the easy tour lies on a convex
hull. If we know this fact, then we can use a fast The answer to this question has deep
algorithm based on the truth of that implications for problem-solving methodol-
assumption. If there is no convex hull, or if we ogy. As empiricists we ought to accept that
have no reason to think that there is, then there it is an empirical question which of the many
is no fast algorithm to guarantee an optimal possible task environments that might fit a
tour. In many cities, roads are laid out on a grid problem is the actual task environment that
structure, which makes the determination of problem solvers must adapt to. It is not to
optimal tours more like easy than hard tours. be answered in ignorance of the frequency of
the problem instances real problem solvere
face. Presumably, it is misleading to choose
settle for one that he knows is close to the too general a task environment if, in fact
shortest, then he can have a quick, reli- problem solvers never face more than a small
able method of finding that path. And the subset of the problem instances that fit the
same benefits apply if he can tolerate a lit- general task specification. That would be a
tle uncertainty in his answer. Thus if he bad framing of the problem.
can accept being right at least 99 percent of For example, the task environment for
the time, or more precisely, have confidence the Tower of Hanoi, in most renderings of
1 - E that his answer is optimal, then a fast the task, is structurally the same whether it
algorithm exists (Karp, 1986). The reason applies to towers made with thirty disks or to
such algorithms exist is that in all prob- those made with three disks. From a mathe-
lems there is a large class of instances where matical point of view the task environment
there is structure in the problem that can be is the same because a recursive algorithm
exploited. In Figure 15.13, the structures are is used to generate the formal structure of
apparent. In Figure 15.12, the cottage cheese the problem. Just as we treat multiplication
case, the structure is the obvious relation of two thirty-digit numbers to be the same
between the numerator and denominator basic task as multiplication of two two-digit
of the fractions 2/3 x 3/4,1/2 x 2/3, 3/4x4/5, numbers, so it might seem natural to treat
and so on. An agent does not have to know solving thirty-disk problems to be the same
about this structure or understand it to rely basic task as solving three-disk problems. Of
on algorithms or heuristic methods that are course the actual problem space is much
valid in virtue of this structure. But an agent larger in the thirty-disk case than in the
who is ignorant of the relevance of this struc-
three-disk case because there are so many
ture will never know whether she is cur-
more combinations to consider. But why
rendy confronting an instance of the hard
should that matter? If we think that sub-
core or why her method sometimes fails.
jects solve Tower of Hanoi problems with a
The adequacy of special-case solutions recursive algorithm, it ought to be the same
suggests that, in general, agents operate with whether they face thirty disks or three.
an understanding of their problems that is Yet people who solve the three-disk prob-
good enough for the cases they normally lem often fail on larger problems, even ones
encounter. They conceptualize their con- as small as seven- or eight-disk problems.
text rather differendy than formalists, who They usually have trouble keeping track of
see the problem being solved as an instance where they are in the problem; they have
problem s o l v i n g a n d s i t u a t e d c o g n i t i o n 1 7 7

trouble maintaining current state. At some and methods of coping, we would expect
point they need a separate strategy to stay on that most problem solving in well-designed
course, and typically this is to use paper or environments is computationally easy, with
some other way of encoding state. Can we external supports that ensure it is so. No one
pretend that this auxiliary strategy is not part has argued that situated problem solving is
of their problem-solving method for larger better than other methods. It is just more
problems? like the way we think. And that was the
This raises the question: Do they face the question at issue.
same problem in both cases but use differ-
ent methods because of memory and com-
putational limits? Or do they face different 6. Knowledge-Rich Cognition
problems because small and large versions
of the Tower of Hanoi are actually different Experts know a lot about their domains.
problems given the resources and methods Even if they cannot articulate their knowl-
subjects have? The answer depends on why edge, they have built up methods for
we think it useful to invoke a task environ- achieving their goals, dealing with hassles
ment. The notion of a task environment was and breakdowns, finding work-arounds, and
introduced to explain what rational agents more to make them effective at their tasks.
adapt to as they get better at solving a prob- That is why they are experts.
lem. Namely, they adapt to the problem's In regarding agents in their everyday con-
structure, to the cues and constraints on texts to be well adapted to their contexts of
paths to a solution. The paradox of large work and activity, we are treating them as
problems is that rational agents never do rich in knowledge, as more or less experts in
adapt. They cannot use the algorithms they their commonsense world. They know how
use for smaller instances of the "same" prob- to get by using the material and symbolic
lem, at least not in their head. A n d when resources supporting action. Perhaps the
they use paper, they perform many other difference between situated cognition and
actions related to managing their inscrip- problem-space cognition is the difference
tions that have nothing to do with the core between knowledge-rich and knowledge-
algorithm. Why, then, maintain that the lan- lean cognition.
guage of task environments is helpful? What An old distinction, still useful but poten-
does it predict? It does not predict the per- tially misleading, distinguishes declarative
formance and pattern of errors that problem from procedural knowledge: knowledge of
solvers display as the problem gets larger, facts and explicit rules from the type of
because performance depends on the algo- knowledge displayed in skills. Typical stud-
rithms actually in use. All it can predict is ies in knowledge-rich problem solving focus
how an ideally rational agent, unaffected by on the dense matrix of facts, procedures,
resource considerations, would behave. heuristics, representational methods, and
If it is true that people do not use the cases that experienced agents bring to their
same method in large and small versions of tasks. This is a mixture of declarative and
the Tower of Hanoi, why assume that they procedural knowledge, though presumably
should use the same methods in other envi- some of the knowledge that experts have
ronments, such as shopping, assembly, sell- is related to knowing how to publicly use
ing, or navigation? representations, to exploit their social net-
The upshot is that situated problem solv- works, and to use tools - skills that seem
ing emphasizes that people solve problems to be more embodied than can be encapsu-
in specific contexts. T h e methods they have lated in a set of procedures. Because most
learned are well adapted or efficient in those people become experts or near experts in
contexts but may be limited to special cases, dealing with their everyday environments -
not generalizable, and often idiosyncratic. shopping, driving, socially conversing, pre-
Indeed, given the coevolution of settings paring their meals, coping with familiar
245davidkirsh

technology - they probably know enough tant in the literature since the 1980s. But
about these domains to have effective even these accounts place too little empha-
problem-solving methods for handling the sis on the centrality of resources, scaffolds
majority of problems they confront. For interactivity, and cultural support. There is
the few problems they cannot handle, they far more going on in solving a real-world
usually have work-arounds, such as calling problem than in searching a problem space
friends for advice or knowing how to halt or
abort a process, that let them prevent catas-
trophic failure. P A R T 3: P O S I T I V E A C C O U N T -
On the classical account, a major source A FEW IDEAS
of the improved performance that experts
display is to be explained in terms of The view articulated so far is that problem
improved search or improved representa- solving is an interactive process in which
tion of problems. They have better methods subjects perceive, change, and create the
for generating candidate solutions and better cues, constraints, affordances, and larger-
metrics for evaluating how good those can- scale structures in the environment, such
didates are. It has also been observed that as diagrams, forms, scaffolds, and artifact
experts spend more time than novices in ecologies that they work with as they make
the early phases of problem solving, such their way toward a solution. This looks like
as determining an appropriate representa- the basis for an alternative and positive the-
tion of a problem. To cite one study (Les- ory of how people overcome problems in
gold, 1988), when a fund manager considers concrete settings. The positive element in
stocks to include and exclude from her port- situated cognition is this emphasis on agent-
folio, she is systematically reviewing a set of environment interaction. All that is missing
candidates. So we might start our interpreta- from such a theory are the details!
tion of her problem solving with a problem How and when do people externalize
space and operators. But before she makes inner state, modify the environment to gen-
her final decision she will have done many erate conjectures, interactively frame their
things, perhaps over several days, to uncover problems, cognize affordances and cues, and
more information about stocks, and to get allocate control across internal and external
hints about what the Street thinks about resources? These are fundamental questions
each stock. Some of the things she might that must be answered by any positive
do include retrieving charts, extending and account that attempts to locate problem
interpreting those charts, contacting ana- solving in the interaction between internal
lysts, reading their reports, examining the representations or processes and external
portfolios of her competitors, reading eco- representations, structures, and processes. If
nomic forecasts, and possibly even visiting problem solving emerges as a consequence
companies.
of a tight coupling between inside and out-
This appreciation of the value of prepa- side that is promoted and sustained by cul-
ration reveals that when experts solve ture and the material elements of specific
knowledge-rich problems they engage their environments, then we need an account of
environment in far more complex ways than the mechanisms involved in these couplings,
just implementing operators. They interac- and ultimately, of how culture, learning, and
tively probe the world to help define and the structure of our artifacts figure in shap-
frame their problems. This suggests that ing that coupling.
deeper ethnographic studies of everyday It is beyond the goals of this article to
problem solving may show a different style present a positive theory, or even a sketch
of activity than found in formal accounts of one. I will discuss, however, four areas in
of problem solving. Theories of knowledge- which adherents of situated cognition, in my
rich problem solving have become impor- opinion, ought to be offering theories - areas
problem s o l v i n g a n d s i t u a t e d c o g n i t i o n 1 7 7

¡n which a situationalist might construc- important element of the culture of problem


tively add value to the problem solving lit- solving (Kokinov, Hadjiilieva, & Yoveva,
erature. My remarks should be seen more 1997)-
as suggestions or desiderata for a situated A simple theory of hints might begin by
theory of problem solving than as an actual defining a hint to be a verbal or nonverbal
sketch of one. The four areas are as follows: cue that acts like a heuristic bias on search.
This would nicely fit the classical theory.
i, Hints Consider the hints people give in the game
| Affordances of I Spy - a child's game in which one player,
, Thinking with things the spy, gives clues about an object he or she
Self-cueing observes and the other player(s) attempt to
guess what the object is.
It is important to appreciate that this pos-
itive approach is not meant to label other I "You're getting hotter" - metric informa-
theories - more classical theories - as useless. tion - your current guess is better than
Insight into problem solving can be found in your last.
the gestalt literature, in articles on clinical I "It's bigger than a loaf of bread" - con-
problem solving, in the study of learning and straint on candidate generation and an
education, and also in the literature on task acceptable solution.
environments just criticized. What is offered I "More over there" — gesture that biases
here should be seen as an addition to those the part of the search space to explore.
literatures, part of what one day might be a I "Try eliminating big categories of things
more integrated approach, though the proof first like 'Is it a living thing?'" - heuristics
that such as theory is viable will require for efficiently pruning the space.
the sort of dedication to ethnography, • "Don't ignore the color" - critical features
experimental research, and model build- to attend to that bias generation and eval-
ing that has so far been lacking in situated uation.
cognition. • "Back up - abstract away from these sorts
of details" - recharacterize the search
space.
i. Sketch of a T h e o r y of Hints
In thinking of hints in this way, we tie them
Hints come in all forms. They are a part to their role in both candidate generation
of the natural history of problem solving. and evaluation.
Here are a few examples drawn from the Situated cognition downplays search in
classroom. A teacher may tell or show a stu- a problem space as the determinant of
dent how to use a special method or algo- problem-solving behavior. Psychological,
rithm ("Here's a faster way to determine social, cultural, and material factors are
square root"), give advice on framing the treated as more important. Nonetheless no
problem ("First state the givens and thing to approach to problem solving can overlook
be shown, then eliminate irrelevant details the importance of both candidate generation
and distracters"), or suggest useful strategies and evaluation. Ideas, possibilities, and pos-
("Generate as many lemmas as you can in sible ways of proceeding are always involved
order to fill your page with potentially useful in problem solving, as is their evaluation
things"). A fellow student may share illustra- as being fruitful, off the mark, or sugges-
tions or models, mention an analogous prob- tive. Even in insight problems (Mayer, 1995),
lem, give part of the answer, suggest a way where discovering a solution requires break-
of thinking or representing the problem, and ing functional set - as when a subject sud-
so on. Is there a theory that might explain denly realizes that an object can be used in a
why a hint is a hint? Hints represent an nonstandard way - it is still necessary to try
247davidkirsh

out ideas of different ways of using objects.


So there is always a component of generat-
ing candidate actions and testing their ade-
quacy.
What drives the generation process? It
depends on how easy it is to know that one
is at a choice point and the set of actions
available there. In knowledge-lean problems
such as the Tower of Hanoi, there are a small
Figure 15.14. Try solving the flagpole problem.
number of possible moves at each step, and
Why is it hard? It is not because we cannot think
an agent knows what these are. The problem of a way to represent it. We can extract the
is discrete, candidate generation is easy, and givens, the solution condition, and constraints.
state-space search is a good formalization of Making an illustration is easy, as shown here.
the problem, even though the agent's psy- But is this a good illustration? If you have not
chological task changes when the problem solved the problem, here is a hint: work in from
increases in size. In knowledge-lean prob- the extremes to see how the vertical drop
lems the difficulty lies more in evaluation changes as the separation between the trees
than in generation - in deciding whether a increases or decreases. What kind of hint is this?
given option is a good one. Hints therefore
ought to offer advice or heuristics for mov-
ahead, exchange pieces, not pawns." "Don't
ing in a good direction. For instance, work place your pawns on the same color squares
toward clearing a peg completely; there are as your bishop." 2
no short cuts.
In problems that do not count as
In games like chess where there are many knowledge-lean, or problems where it is not
more possible actions at each choice point, a easy to determine when one is at a choice
state space still captures the formal structure point and what the options are, the hardest
of the problem, because the agent knows step is often to figure out how to think about
perfecdy well where the choice points are. the problem, to pose it or frame it in a con-
Given how much knowledge is required structive way. Consider the problem in Fig-
for expertise it seems odd to call chess a ure 15.14. W h a t should one do? Making an
knowledge-lean problem. In chess it is hard illustration is always a good idea, but which
to see the downstream effects of action, illustration, and h o w should it be annotated?
because one's opponent is unpredictable. So T h e space of possible drawings and textual
it is hard to generate plausible chains of "If I actions is huge. Moreover, once a sketch has
do this, then you are likely to do that." The been made there remains the question of
branching factor of the game is large and how to proceed.
the space of possible continuations huge.
This puts greater pressure on prudent can- Flagpole problem (Figure 15.14): Two
didate generation at each level of the search palm trees are standing, each 100 feet
space. Accordingly, in chess, hints and sug- tall. A 150-foot rope is strung from
gestions often have to do with biasing gen- the top of one of the palm trees to
eration. For instance, typical rules for open- the top of the other and hangs freely
ing are these: "Open with a center pawn." between them. The lowest point of
"Knights before bishops." "Don't move the the rope is 25 feet above the ground.
same piece twice." "Always play to gain con- H o w far apart are the two flagpoles?
trol of the center." Typical rules for middle (Ornstein & Levine, 1993)
game include these: "In cramped positions
free yourself by exchanging." "Don't bring O n e reason some problems are hard is
your king out with your opponent's queen that people find it difficult to escape their
on the board." And in the end game rules familiar way of proceeding, a n o t h e r instance
include these: "If you are only one pawn of mental set. Aspects of a problem may
p r o b l e m s o l v i n g a n d s i t 177
uated cognition177

remind them of p o s s i b l e m e t h o d s or m e t h o d (Laird, Newell, & Rosenbloom, 1987), fail-


fragments, b u t if t h e s e s e e m u n p r o m i s i n g , ure to generate a feasible action creates
what is to be d o n e ? T h e d i f f i c u l t y hardly an impasse and a new subproblem to be
seems to lie in finding s o m e t h i n g to do. It lies solved. An alternative suggestion by Greeno
in finding an interesting t h i n g to do. W h e r e and colleagues (Greeno, Smith, & Moore,
do interesting ideas c o m e f r o m ? D o e s star- 1993; Greeno & Middle School Mathematics
ing at a problem h e l p ? S h o u l d t h e p r o b l e m through Applications Project Group, 1998)
solver do things n o t d i r e c t l y c o n n e c t e d w i t h is that problem solvers recognize possible
taking a step f o r w a r d in t h e p r o b l e m , such as moves by being attuned to affordances and
doodling, reading m o r e a b o u t r e l a t e d prob- constraints. If at first an agent does not see
lems, talking to c o l l e a g u e s , b r a i n s t o r m i n g ? a possible action, she can interact with the
How many candidate s t e p s c o m e f r o m inside environment and increase her chances of dis-
an agent's head a n d h o w m a n y c o m e f r o m covering it. This is a promising approach that
prompts f r o m artifacts, g r o u p d y n a m i c s , and deserves elaboration and study.
so forth? T h e inspiration for seeing problem solv-
Early e x p e r i m e n t s b y G e s t a l t p s y c h o l o - ing emerging out of interaction with re-
gists have s h o w n t h e v a l u e of e n v i r o n m e n t a l sources and environmental conditions is
cues, such as w a v i n g a s t i c k or setting a string drawn f r o m Gibson's (1966, 1977, 1979)
in motion (Maier, 1970), t h a t call attention theory of perception. Gibson regarded an
to an item that m i g h t f i g u r e in a solution. affordance as a dispositional property like
But a more t h e o r e t i c a l l y m o t i v a t e d e x p l a - being graspable, pullable, or having a struc-
nation of h o w t h e s e c u e s trigger candidate ture that can be walked on, sat on, picked
generation is n e e d e d . A n d , o n c e subjects do up, thrown, climbed, and so on. These prop-
have a new line of t h o u g h t to p u r s u e , w h e r e erties of objects and environments are what
do they get their m e t r i c s on goodness, their make it possible for an agent with particu-
ability to discriminate w h a t is an interest- lar abilities to perform actions: pulling X,
ing avenue to f o l l o w a n d w h a t looks useless? walking on X, sitting on X, picking up X,
How does the e n v i r o n m e n t h e l p ? throwing X, climbing over X. Agents with
different abilities would encounter different
A theory of s i t u a t e d p r o b l e m solving
affordances. For example, relative to a leg-
should explain w h y hints are s u c c e s s f u l and
less person, no environment, regardless of
the many w a y s o u r e n v i r o n m e n t s o f f e r us
h o w flat it is, affords walking. The same
hints on h o w to s o l v e o u r p r o b l e m s . At a
applies to other actions and skills. Only
minimum there is a large b o d y of relevant
relative to an action or activity reper-
data to be f o u n d in h i n t - g i v i n g and hint-
toire does an environment have well-defined
receiving behavior.
affordances.

Because affordances are objective fea-


2. Affordances and Activity tures of an environment, there may be af-
fordances present in a situation that are
A second e l e m e n t in a p o s i t i v e t h e o r y w o u l d never perceived at the time. The affordances
explain h o w p e o p l e d i s c o v e r c a n d i d a t e steps that are actually perceived depend on the
in a problem solution by i n t e r a c t i v e l y engag- cues available during activity. The more
ing their e n v i r o n m e n t . In classical accounts, attuned a creature is to its environment,
if a task e n v i r o n m e n t is w e l l d e f i n e d there the more it picks up affordance-revealing
is a set of feasible actions s p e c i f i e d at each cues and the more readily it accomplishes
choice point. An agent is a s s u m e d to recog- its tasks. So runs the theory according to
nize choice p o i n t s a n d a u t o m a t i c a l l y gen- Gibson.
erate feasible actions. In situations w h e r e Problem solving, Greeno and colleagues
problems have n o t b e e n w e l l f r a m e d , h o w - suggest, should likewise be seen as an active,
ever, discovering m o v e s to c o n s i d e r can dynamic encounter of possibilities and reg-
be challenging. In N e w e l l ' s t h e o r y , S O A R istering of affordances, constraints, and
249davidkirsh

invariants. When engaged in a task, or when Imagine the affordances, constraints, and
trying to solve a problem, skillful agents invariants that a chef must pick up when
recognize aflbrdanees that are relevant to preparing an egg sunny-side down. First a
their immediate goals. A cook recognizes hard edge must be found for cracking the
the affordances of the stove, the knobs, egg cleanly, then the egg itself must be held
blenders, and ingredients. Because many of correctly when opened, the frying process
must be monitored, and the egg shifted at
these affordances are representational (e.g.,
the right time so that it does not stick. Flip,
a dial) or rule based (e.g., it is a convention
ping has its own complexities. Throughout
that pulling a lever forward increases rather
the process a cook must be sensitive to the
than decreases the magnitude of what-
preconditions of actions, the indicators that
ever it controls), the world of affordances
things are going well or beginning to go
and constraints that a cook is sensitive to
awry, and the moment-by-moment dynam-
must include properties that are socially,
ics of cooking. A sunny-side-down cooking
culturally, and conventionally constructed. trajectory, under normal conditions, is sup-
Thus linguistic structures as well as nonlin- posed to be an invariant for a competent
guistic ones can be affordances for Greeno. cook. In the theory of attunement to affor-
In his view, it is not relevant that linguis- dances and constraints, all these cues, affor-
tic and nonlinguistic affordances are learned dances, constraints, and invariants of normal
differendy or that they are grasped differ- practice are precisely the things that skilled
endy: that the way someone knows what agents are supposed to be attuned to.
depressing a button with the linguistic label In extending affordances to include the
"abort" will do is conceptual, whereas the affordances that situations provide for tools
way someone knows that a knife affords (in the hands of competent users), Greeno
hefting or cutting is probably nonconcep- and colleagues pushed the concept well
tual. Both types of possibilities for action beyond what can be perceived through nor-
are "seen" and qualify as affordances for mal perception - even ecological percep-
Greeno. tion. Their theory goes even further, though,
This inclusiveness represents a major to include affordances for reasoning. Such
extension of the concept of affordance and things as marking up diagrams, working
constraints, as understood in ecological psy- with illustrations, and manipulating sym-
chology, but if it can be made to work, it per- bolic representations are all actions that
mits seeing problem solving to be the out- experienced agents can perform and that
come of a more embodied encounter with serve as steps in reasoning.
cultural resources. Greeno and colleagues For instance, when a student of geom-
assume that people can perceive or regis- etry sees an illustration as in Figure 15.15,
ter affordances for activities that are quite it is assumed that she can recognize a host
complex. For instance, they assume that of affordances for construction. To some-
the more familiar we are with tools, such one w h o has learned to make triangular con-
as hammers, screwdrivers, chisels, knives, structions it is natural to look at Figure 15.15b
machine saws, and lawn mowers, the more and imagine dropping perpendiculars, as in
we can see opportunities for using them. Figure 15.15c. With practice and a little prod-
Carpenters can make hundreds of percep- ding, most students realize that the area of
tual inferences about wood. And someone Figure 15.15b is the same as the rectangle in
who mows his lawn every week can see Figure 15.15a, and both are base times height
when grass is ready for its next cutting or (b x h). T h e proof involves noting that the
too dense for a given lawn mower. This is triangles in Figure 15.15c are congruent. If
an important and useful extension but not someone cut out the left-hand triangle, he
without difficulties. could paste it on the right and produce a
Because using tools invariably involves rectangle just like Figure 15.15a. It is possible
mastering practices, the affordances that to prod students to recognize and generalize
tool users perceive must be complex.
PROBLEM SOL VING AND SITUATED COGNITION 177

is a stretching operation that transforms


Figure 15.16a into Figure 15.16b. How many
people see it? Because there are an infi-
Figure 15.15. For a student of geometry, 15.15b nite number of ways to stretch the figure,
affords many different types of constructions, it requires an insightful mind to envisage
including dropping perpendiculars from vertices the transform. Figure 15.16b gives one set
as in 15.15c, adding diagonals, bisecting, and so of deformations that shows the equivalence.
forth. These affordances for constructions can
Yet how many people can see even the first
be projected mentally onto the figure or added
transform from 1 to 2? A theory of affor-
by pencil or pen on the figure itself. Although
there are an infinite number of constructions the dance pickup must tell us who, when, and
figure affords, a geometer only considers those why some people can see this invariance
constructions that are part of the standard and who, when, and why certain others can-
practices. For instance, in 15.15CI a clever student not. It also must explain why the most use-
might realize that the area of a trapezoid can be ful affordances are the ones that come to
proved similar to the area of a rectangle by mind.
noticing that triangles constructed through the Education researchers would love to pro-
midsection of each vertical side are congruent
vide a theory of attunement learning, though
and create a rectangle whose length is (top +
so far advances have been empirical rather
bottom)/2.
than theoretical. For instance, Sayeki, Ueno,
and Nagasaka (1991) found that students
who were given a chance to play with a deck
this idea by giving them paper and scissors of cards as shown in Figure 15.17a, and then
and the chance to cut and paste. When they to chat about their activity, were soon able
perform this physical action a few times, or to recognize the invariance of the area in the
perform the construction on paper, they figures shown in Figure 15.17b. Physical expe-
come to see an invariance preserved under rience with the deck helped to imbue stu-
a shearing transformation. Clever students dents with a strong sense of the transforma-
who are able to prove the equality of area tions that preserve area. Presumably subjects
theorem more analytically may even be able who played with clay structures shaped into
to recognize opportunities for making less the structure shown in Figure 15.16a would
obvious constructions, as in Figure 15.15c!, similarly have an easier time following the
thereby generalizing further the equality of constructions in Figure 15.16b.
area theorem and recognizing the invariance Greeno and colleagues viewed this con-
under further transforms. sequence of practice as support for their
The idea that an experienced subject can theory that problem solving is the result of
become attuned to both affordances and rel- attunement to affordances, constraints, and
evant invariants is powerful but constitutes
a theory of problem solving only if it offers
predictions. This is a challenge for an attune-
ment theory. It is not a lost cause but is cer-
tainly one that has yet to be met. Exactly
when will a subject pick up affordances for
construction and, given the vast number of
such affordances, exactly which ones will
she attend to? This last concern applies to
all theories of affordances but is especially
Figure 15.16. All the figures shown in 15.16a and
problematic for those that presume afford- 15.16b are topologically the same: 15.16b is a
ances for reasoning. sequence of transforms that is meant to prove
To see how serious this challenge is, con- the equivalence of figures in 15.16a. As with
sider Figure 15.16. The two shapes in Fig- most proofs, not everyone is able to "see" the
ure 15.16a are topologically invariant. There validity of each inferential step.
300davidkirsh

out before grasping deep analogies. fa


affordance detection approach would p r e
diet that problem solvers would be actively
a b engaging their environment, both by pro.
jecting and by acting. In the classical the-
Figure 15.17. Students were shown a deck of
ory, by contrast, the reason a subject is able
cards as in 15.17a. The front face initially formed
a square. As the deck was pushed around it to transfer problem-solving expertise from
became apparent that many four-sided and one problem to another is that the subject
non-four-sided shapes could be constructed. is able to detect deep structural similari-
The attribute common across all transformations ties, and so methods found successful in the
is that the area of the front side always remains source domain are mapped over to the target
constant. The equivalence of the two images in domain. There is no deep need to interact
15.17b became obvious, intuitive, known in an
with the problem environment.
embodied way.
If the theory of attunement were better
specified, these advantages would be sub-
stantial. But the theory, as developed to
in variance. Practice and engagement leads to date, falls short of details. How, for instance
improved attunement, which in turn leads does a subject choose which affordance to
to better solution exploration. act on? There are infinitely many afford-
This is a rather different view than the ances available in any situation. This is par-
classical account for two reasons. First, ticularly true once the notion of an afford-
in the classical account, problem solving ance has been broadened to include the
always involves search in a problem space. possibility of projecting structure or creat-
In the attunement account, problem solv- ing structure. In Figure 15.16a, for instance,
ing involves evaluating perceived or regis- there is no end of ways to deform the clay
tered affordances. This bypasses the need model. The challenge is to know which of
for a problem space where feasible actions the many ways to pursue.
are internally represented. Choice points are In Greeno et al. (1998) it is suggested that
encountered rather than internally gener- dynamical system models may help here.
ated. And the choice points encountered It is easy to see why. If problem solving is
depend on the actions actually taken by the a dynamic encounter with an affordance-
agent - including mental projection actions. rich environment, the language of attrac-
This means that the environment an agent tors and repellors ought to be helpful in
encounters is partly co-constructed by its explaining why some affordances are per-
actions. As an agent begins to see things ceived rather than others, or why some
differently, especially ways it can project or actions are pursued rather than others. Eco-
construct, it partly creates new task afford- logical psychologists have often advanced
ances. Constructions support new projec- dynamical system accounts. But again, prior
tions and so on, though it must be said that to a more complete account of the details,
there remains a need to triage or evaluate the we can only wonder what controls this
many affordances registered and projected. dynamic encounter. Discourse about basins
Second, in the attunement theory, trans- of attraction and repulsion - the favorite
fer is the result of detecting similar afford- terms in discussions of dynamical systems -
sound remarkably like the discourse of gra-
ances and constraints or invariances. Trans-
dient ascent: an action is selected if it
fer is a direct consequence of being able to
yields a higher value. This is the method
detect affordances and constraints, whether
of hill climbing and is one of the cor-
or not the agent has much grasp of the struc-
nerstone methods of problem-space search.
ture of a problem. Because similar afford-
Yet it is not enough. To explain much
ances can be found in many situations,
of the observed behavior of subjects on
including those that pose very different
knowledge-lean problems, it has been found
problems, agents are more likely to try things
problem s o l ving and situated c o g n i t i o n 177

expect a positive theory of situated problem


solving to study and explain. In discussing
how milkmen used their bottle cases to
calculate efficient plans, we considered how
overlearned patterns supported or embed-
ded in artifacts - such as the regular pattern
Figure 15.18. By adding annotations or other that forty-two bottles makes in a forty-eight-
markings it is easier to envision the way this bottle milk case - could be used to help
structure can be deformed. Such cues help to them solve specific planning and accounting
anchor projection and facilitate envisionment. It problems. Experienced algebraicists use pat-
is a rich area for study.
terns in matrix representations to recognize
properties of linear equations, and experi-
necessary to introduce other weak meth- enced milkmen use patterns of bottles, both
ods such as difference reduction, depth- present and imagined. These patterns figure
first search, breadth-first search, minimax in special-case solutions they have learned.
search, abstraction, and others. Attunement The infamous weight watcher's example
theory owes us the details of how these shows a similar trick: the physical form and
sort of mechanisms of control can be imple- size of cottage cheese when dumped from its
mented. If on the other hand dynamical carton can be used to support highly specific
systems are going to supplant the need for arithmetic operations that would be harder
these additional control mechanisms, then for most subjects to perform in their head.
we need to know more about how they will The idea of cutting a regular cylinder in
cope with the details of control that have half is so intuitive that for many people it
seemed so useful in the classical theory. is understood more directly than fractions.
There are further questions. Why are They can think with the parts the way they
affordances and constraints sometimes vis- can think with symbols. C. S. Peirce (1931-
ible and sometimes not? In Figure 15.16b, for 1958) first mentioned this idea - that people
example, it is hard for most people to see the use external objects to think with - in the
legality of the transform between 1 and 2. But late nineteenth century, when he said that
in Figure 15.18, with the simple addition of chemists think as much with their test tubes
annotations, or hints, or material anchors, it as with pen and paper.
is much easier. The details of an attunement The notion that we use things to think
model should explain the biases on afford- with, that we distribute our thinking across
ance and constraint detection. It should tell internal and external representations or
us the types of detection errors that sub- manipulables, is relatively uncontentious
jects make and why. It should tell us the when the artifacts used are symbolic, such as
biases we observe in human problem solv- written sentences, illustrations, numbers, or
ing. And it should tell us the time course of even gestures. Much ethnographic research
affordance-constraint detection: why some has shown in detail how people use artifacts
are quickly seen and others are detected to encode information: how people repre-
slowly. There is substantial opportunity for
sent information in external structures and
theory and experiment here. It may eventu-
then manipulate those external structures
ally pay off but it is clear there is much to
and read off the results. The same applies
be done.
to gesture. People use body gestures to help
them think in context, both when they think
individually and when they think as a group
3. Thinking with T h i n g s or in a team. Gestures help them remem-
ber ideas, formulate thoughts, and not just
How people use artifacts, resources, and supplement vocalization. A slightly different
tools as things to think with delineates a idea attaches to the use of artistic media. No
third class of phenomena that we would one would deny that a sculptor is thinking
302davidkirsh

or solving certain problems when using clay toward this theory can be taken by look-
any more than someone would deny that an ing at how people co-opt things to perform
author is thinking or solving problems with computations. Computation is about har-
the help of pen, paper, and written sentence. nessing states, structures, or processes to
The medium has important properties that generate rational outcomes. It is about using
the artist or author is trying to exploit. Inter- things to find answers. The most familiar
action is essential to the process. And though forms of computation are digital, the manip.
one might say that all the relevant cogni- ulation of symbol strings, as in math, engi-
tion occurs inside the head of the human, neering, or computer science. But all sorts
the physical materials, scaffolds, tools, and of nonsymbolic systems can be harnessed
structures are an important factor in the to perform computations. For instance a
outcome. They help to structure the afford- slide rule is an analog mechanism for per-
ance landscape. forming multiplication, addition, and a host
The question of how people think with of other mathematical operations. It does
things, how the determinants and dynamics not have the precision of a calculator, or
of cognition depend on properties of arti- the range of functions of many other digital
facts and the context of action, is unques- devices. B u t because it preserves key rela-
tionably at the heart of the theories of situ- tionships - linear distance along each scale
ated, distributed, and interactive cognition. of the rule is proportional to the logarithm
But as with other tenets, it is in need of of the numbers marked on it - moving the
greater elaboration and empirical study. To slides in the correct w a y allows a user to
date, the majority of studies have been con- perform multiplications. It can be used to
fined to ethnographic examinations of par- simulate the outcome of digital multiplica-
ticular cases. This is a necessary step given tion because it preserves key relationships. It
the importance of details. But little atten- replaces symbol manipulation with manip-
tion has been paid to the distinction between ulation of physical parts.
using objects to solve special-case problems T h e same can be said, though less eas-
- a method that reflects memorized tech- ily, for illustrations, sketches, and three-
niques - and using objects or systems in dimensional models. For instance, one of the
more general ways as an intrinsic part of most common ways we think with things is
reasoning and problem solving. The distinc- by using t h e m as model fragments. A struc-
tion is important because if most instances ture or process can be said to model or partly
of thinking with things are highly specific, model another if it is easy to manipulate and
if most are cases where dedicated tools examine the model and then read off impli-
are used to solve domain-specific problems, cations about the target structure or process.
then too much of the rest of problem solv- An extreme example is seen in the architec-
ing is left out and any hope of a more gen- tural practice of building miniature three-
eral theory of problem solving looks bleak. dimensional models of buildings. The oper-
How much did we really leam about prob- ations that architects perform on their small
lem solving by observing weight watchers models are sufficiently similar to actions that
partition cottage cheese? inhabitants will perform on or in full-sized
The theory situated cognition owes us is buildings that architects can try out on the
one that will explain how people harness model ways the full-sized building may be
physical objects to help them reason and used. T h e y can act on the model instead
solve problems. What characteristics must of the real object. This saves time, effort,
a thing to think with have if it is to be effec- and cost because mistakes have few conse-
tive, easy to use, and handily learned? quences in models and simulations. This can
Although a comprehensive theory would even be done using two-dimensional dia-
provide a principled taxonomy of the ways grams, as shown by Murphy (2004), who
we can think with things, a tiny step recorded h o w architects reason about the
problem s o lvingandsituatedcognition177

uses of a building by bringing their bod- If a robot were sufficiently tuned to the reg-
ies into interaction with their architectural ularities of its environment and the tasks it
drawings. needed to perform, it could be driven by a
The formal part of a thinking-with-things control system that would guarantee with
theory should provide the analytic tools for high probability that the robot would even-
evaluating why certain things can function tually reach its goals, though not necessarily
successfully as things that can be thought by the shortest path. If this sounds similar to
with. Much of this work has already been the theory of attunement to affordances and
constraints it is because it is the same theory
done in other fields. For example, in math
though restricted here to problems such as
it is well understood that a powerful tech-
trajectory planning, grasping, and physical
nique of reasoning is to map structures into
manipulation, and without the requirement
different representational systems. Problems
of mental projection.
that may be hard to solve in one system, say,
Euclidean geometry, may be easy to solve in Although such an approach may seem the
analytic geometry. This mapping between antithesis of problem solving, it is a legiti-
representational systems may not seem to mate way of dealing with real-world prob-
be a computation, but it is. It is a trick that lems - but only if certain conditions are met.
is widely used. For instance, when sailors Specifically:
plot a course, they typically use more than
one map. Every map represents the world • The world must be relatively benign.
under a projection that preserves some rela- Moving toward goals can only rarely lead
tions while distorting others. Mercator pro- to disastrous downstream consequences
jections are good for plotting course but bad (Kirsh, 1991,1996).
for estimating distance or area. Sailors over- • The world must be reversible. If you do
come this problem by plotting their course not like your action, you can undo it and
in maps of different projection. They con- either return the world to the condition it
vert information from one map to another. was in before, or you can find a new path
The result is that they are able to track their to any of the states you could reach
location, distance, bearing, and speed more before.
accurately and more quickly than they oth-
erwise could (Hutchins, 1995). They think When can these conditions be counted on?
across maps. The result of using multiple Assembly tasks, math tasks, and puzzles,
maps is like using a fulcrum: it allows a such as tangrams, support undoing without
weak user to do some heavy lifting because penalty. The Tower of Hanoi is another clas-
the maps or relation between the maps does sic task supporting reversibility. And check-
much of the work. ers, chess, and other competitive games usu-
An even more complicated way of using ally have a form - correspondence chess,
things to think with is found when people checkers - where subjects can search over
use the very thing they are interested in as possible moves directly on the board before
its own model. For example, people solving deciding how to move. In other tasks, even if
tangrams seem to use the tangram pieces one cannot reverse the action, subjects can
as things to think with. So do people when get a second chance to solve the problem.
they assemble things without first reading So as long as it takes no longer to try out
the assembly manual. When Rod Brooks an action in the world than trying it out
(1991a, 1991b) initially offered the expression in a model, there are advantages to acting
"use the world as its own model," he meant directly in the world. First, subjects gain pre-
that a robot would be better off sensing and cision in the representation of the outcome
reacting to the world itself than by simu- because nothing is more precise than the
lating the effects of actions in an internal real thing. Second, subjects gain practice in
model of the world prior to selecting action. bringing things about, which can be of value
3oo david kirsh

where skill is required. Third, subjects save I personally think this is an exciting area
having to formulate a plan in their head, try of research. As with other areas this one lis
it out in a model, and then execute the plan much in need of clarification and empirical
in the world. The execution phase is folded exploration. Moreover, there is a danger that
into the discovery phase. this activity-centric model makes thought
But there are many other tasks where so relativistic and hermeneutic that o n l y
actions are not reversible and search in the violinists can understand other v i o l i n i s t s
world is a bad idea. In cooking, for example, only sculptors can understand other sculp'
as with many tasks, after an initial prepa- tors, and so on. Although I believe such con-
ration phase when a recipe is selected and cerns can be answered, they highlight that
ingredients gathered, there is an execution there are philosophical and methodological
problems as well as empirical ones that such
phase where there is no turning back. There
an approach may face.
are many places where a plan can be modi-
fied or updated to deal with errors, setbacks,
and unexpected outcomes. But in most tasks
there are commitment points where it is 4. Self-Cueing and Metacognitive
inappropriate to do anything but the next Control of Discovery
move.
Most tractable analyses of thinking ap- What controls search? In the classical theory
proach thought as a computational activity the firing of productions, a form of associa-
whether that computation is said to occur tive memory, drives search. If a rule exists
inside the head on internal representations, whose preconditions match patterns cur-
outside the head through the use of phys- rently in working memory, then it is trig-
ical objects, or in the interaction between gered, and unless other rules match current
inside and outside. An even more profound conditions and are therefore also triggered,
approach to thought sees it as a mechanism that solitary rule fires and causes a change
for extending our perception, action, and in working memory. Owing to this focus on
regulation. This is a radical vision of how what is in current working memory there
cognition is shaped through our interaction is an inescapable data-driven bias to search,
with artifacts. both on candidate generation and evalua-
The core idea in this more enactive the- tion. Only a change in working memory
ory of thought is that thinking is some- can trigger new productions. Environmental
how tied up with the way we encounter state enters working memory through per-
and engage the world. A violinist encoun- ception. A positive interactionist or situa-
ters the world through his violin in a way tionist theory ought to provide an account
that depends essentially on the violin. Vio- of how we interact with our environments to
lin problems are encountered only in vio- overcome the lock that data-driven thinking
lin playing and constituted in the interaction has on our creativity. It must provide a the-
of player and instrument. The same applies ory of the dynamics driving the interactive
to people who bicycle, whitde, manipu- exploration of a problem during the search
late cranes, or solve higher-math problems. for solution. One special line of inquiry looks
The material instruments, representational at the way we self-cue, how we alter the cue
languages, and sensorimotor extensions that structure of the environment to stimulate
artifacts provide offer new modes of experi- new ideas or candidate generation.
ence and involvement with the world. The
A nice example of how as data-driven
problems that arise are somehow essentially
creatures we self-cue to improve perfor-
tied to those interactions and therefore can-
mance can be found in the way people play
not be properly analyzed until we under-
Scrabble (see Figure 15.19). The basic prob-
stand what those who have those skills expe-
lem in Scrabble is to find the highest-value
rience as problematic.
words that can be made from the letters
PROBLEM SOLVING AND SITUATED COGNITION
301

in effect jumping to a new place in their


internal lexical space. By lexical space we
meant a system of discrete nodes consisting
of letter sequences. How close one node is to
another in this space is determined by such
things as phonemic closeness (bear is close
to bare and air), graphemic closeness (bear is
Figure 15.19. When people play Scrabble, they close to ear), and perhaps others things such
scan pieces on their tray, look for openings on as semantic closeness (bear is close to lair).
the board, and search through a developing In our simulation we defined closeness as
space of possible word and word fragments.
graphemic closeness alone. Thus two nodes
Most people also periodically move the letters
are neighbors in or simplified model of inter-
on their tray. Sometimes this is to hold their
current candidate. But often it is to highlight
nal lexical space if they can be reached by
high-frequency two- and three-letter shifting or removing a few letters or adding
combinations that figure in words. a letter if there is an additional letter on the
tray. Hence, bear is close to bar, bare, bra
and if there is another e on the tray, then
on one's tray after placing them in a permis-
the word beer is also a graphemic neighbor.
sible position on the board. The challenge
Letter sequences that do not form words,
for a psychological theory is to explain how
such as bre ebra, are also lexemic neighbors
the external cues, comprised of the ordered
but less strongly attractive if they are infre-
letters on tray and board, mutually inter-
quent sequences in English.
act with a subject's internal lexical system.
The challenge for an interactionist account In discussing our findings we reasoned
is to show how subjects intentionally man- that although subjects can in principle apply
age the arrangement of letters on their tray as many mental transforms in lexemic space
to improve performance. as they want and so, in both the no hands
In Maglio, Matlock, Raphaely, Cher- and hands condition, they can in principle
nicky, and Kirsh (1999), an experiment was move arbitrarily far from the letter layout
performed to test the hypothesis that peo- on their physical tray. We expected that in
ple who rearrange letters externally self-cue practice subjects would tend to get stuck in
and consequently perform better than those the lexical neighborhood near to the group-
who do not. The task was similar to Scrabble ings on their tray. This idea reiterates the
in that subjects were supposed to generate data-driven nature of Scrabble.
possible words from seven Scrabble letters. The power of using one's hands comes
Unlike Scrabble, though, they just called from the difference in the constraints on
out words as they recognized them; there physical movement and mental movement. A
were no constraints coming from the board just-so story runs like this. The letters that
or from values associated with letters. In subjects see exert a pull on their imagination
the hands condition, participants could use much like an elastic band. The farther that
their hands to manipulate the letters; in the subjects go in their lexemic space from the
no hands condition they could not. Results sequence on the tray the stronger the tension
showed that more words were generated in pulling them back. This tension is purely
the hands condition than in the no hands internal. In physical space, there is nothing
condition, and that moving tiles was more preventing players from moving their tiles
helpful in finding words that were more dis- ever further from their first layout. It is easy
tant from the opening letter sequence. to break the elastic-band effect. This means
Evidently, self-cueing helps beat the data- that a subject can jump to a new place in
driven nature of cognition. We conjectured lexical space, and so activate a new basin
that the reason moving tiles is helpful is of neighbors just by rearranging his or her
that when subjects rearrange tiles they are tiles. The new arrangement will prime or
DAVID KIRSH

cue a new set of lexical elements and make cal theory of problem solving. It has forced
it more likely that new words will be dis- us to reconsider the form an adequate the-
covered. ory should take. Is a general theory of prob-
This approach to problem solving, if lem solving possible? Is there enough resem-
intentional, looks a lot like metacognition. blance between the actions that problem
It is reminiscent of the behavior of Ulysses solvers take when solving or overcoming
(Elster, 1979), who recognized that he could problems to hope to discover a general the-
not overcome the lure of the Sirens except ory of the dynamics of problem solving,
by binding himself. To achieve his goal, regardless of domain? I argued that such a
given that he knew he would act inappro- theory must at least tell us for a given prob-
priately in the situation, he altered the situ- lem and situation how much of the control
ation. We do the same when we move our is to be found in internal processes, directed
eyes. Given that our visual system is auto- by such internal resources as problem-space
matic and data driven, we cannot help but representations and heuristic search, how
see what we look at. But we still can avert much of the control is to be found in the
our eyes or direct them to other things. setup or design of the environment influenc-
The decision to look elsewhere is often ing cognition through the affordances, cues,
intentional, and when it is, it counts as and constraints that a culture of activity has
metacognitive if it is based on reflectively built up over time, and how much is to be
exploiting the way our visual system works. found in the dynamic interaction between
The same applies to moving tiles in Scrab- internal and external resources.
ble and a host of problem-solving strategies This is a tall order. It requires develop-
we rely on in other domains. In math, for ing a set of supporting theories that explain
instance, we often copy onto a single page how cues, constraints, and affordances affect
the lemmas we generated over many pages. how a subject thinks and acts. This point
This increases the chance of seeing patterns. came up repeatedly: first when discussing
In algebra, students soon learn that it helps the processes of registration, then when dis-
to be neat because it is easier to see rela- cussing interactivity and epistemic actions,
tions and patterns. Indeed, the strategy of scaffolds, and resources, and later when
rearranging the environment to stimulate I discussed the direction a positive the-
new ideas when candidate generation slows ory might take: explaining attunement to
down is pervasive. The principle relied on is symbolic affordances and cues, explaining
self-cueing and metacognitive control. (For how subjects respond to hints, how they
a more complete discussion of the role of self-cue, and how they think with material
metacognition in reasoning and learning, see things. A general theory of problem solving
Kirsh, 3004.3 would have to pull all these supporting the-
The moral for research in problem solv- ories together to explain how subjects move
ing should be clear: by studying more care- back and forth among cues, scaffolds, vis-
fully how cues and affordance landscapes ible attributes and the mental projections,
bias cognition, new interactive strategies will structures, and problem spaces those sub-
be discovered that show unanticipated ways jects maintain on the inside. It would be an
subjects use the environment to shape their interactionist theory.
problem-solving cognition. The situationalist approach, secondly, has
exposed what is wrong with studying prob-
lem solving in constrained laboratory con-
Final Discussion and Conclusion texts, disconnected from the settings in
which those mental and interactive pro-
By exposing how cognition is closely cou- cesses originally developed. Subjects adapt
pled to its social, material, and cultural con- to the world they live in. The internal costs
text the situationalist approach has called of problem solving depend substantially on
attention to the deficiencies of the classi- how experienced a subject is, whether the
PROBLEM SOLVING AND SITUATED COGNITION

problem is presented to him or her in a of this chapter and for comments by Rick After-
familiar way, and how effectively he or she man and Jim Greeno. Joachim Lyon carefully
read the entire manuscript and gave thought-
can exploit the surrounding resources, cues,
ful remarks throughout. Support for this work
affordances, and constraints. This concern
came in part from ONR Award # N00014-02-3-
with cognitive costs and benefits is consis-
0457.
tent with the general theme of model build-
ing in cognitive science. But putting it into
practice means paying closer attention to the
Notes
details of natural contexts. This cannot be
done without close ethnographic and micro-
1 In computational complexity theory, prob-
analytic study. lems are ranked according to the resources
As a negative theory, situated cognition needed to solve their hardest instance, as
has been a success. B u t if approaches are measured by the number of steps and the
judged by their positive theories, situated amount of memory or scratch paper the best
cognition has been a failure. All efforts at algorithm will use. For instance, solving a
creating a substantive theory of problem traveling salesman problem with two cities
solving have been underspecified or frag- is trivial because there is only one combina-
tion of cities, one tour, to consider (A, B).
mentary. And it is too early to know whether
But as the number of cities increases, die
the next dominant theory will bear a situa-
number of candidate tours that have to be
tionalist stamp. written down and measured increases expo-
Building on the critique presented in Part nentially (as there are as many possible tours
One and Part T w o , I posed a set of ques- as sequences of all cities). It is the shape of
tions and initial approaches that might indi- this resource growth curve that determines
cate the direction situated research should the complexity class of a problem. A prob-
pursue next. These include an analysis of lem is said to be in the class of NP-complete
hints and scaffolds, symbolic affordances if, in the worst case, the best algorithm would
and mental projection, thinking with things, have to do the equivalent of checking every
self-cueing and metacognition, and an enac- tour, and the test to determine whether one
tive theory of thought. S o m e of these stud- tour is better than another is itself not an
NP-complete algorithm. There are infinitely
ies are being undertaken outside of cogni-
many problems that are harder than NP-
tive and computational psychology. They
complete ones, and infinitely many problems
explore how people interactively populate that are easier. The easier ones have polyno-
situations with extra resources and how they mial complexity.
exploit those resources to simplify reason- 2 Taken from "The Thirty Rules of Chess."
ing. Some of these studies, however, are not Retrieved May 31, 2008, from http://www.
yet being undertaken. T h e bottom line, it chessdryad.com/education/sageadvice/
seems to me, is that it is not enough that thirty/index.htm.
we recognize the central insight of situated
cognition - that the environment provides
organization for cognitive activity, that the
world enables and supports such activities References
1 we must go further. We must explain
how internal control processes work with Agre, P., & Chapman, D. (1987). Pengi: An imple-
these supports and organizational structures mentation of a theory of activity. In Proceed-
ings of the Sixth National Conference on Artifi-
to regulate intelligent activity.
cial Intelligence (pp. 268-272). Menlo Park, CA:
AAAI Press.
Baker, B. S. (1994). Approximation algorithms
Acknowledgments for NP-complete problems on planar graphs.
Journal of the ACM, 41(1), 153-180.
I am happy to thank the editors for their valuable Behrend, D. A., Rosengren, K., & Perlmut-
suggestions and moral support during the writing ter, M. (1989). Parent presence. International
3°4 DAVID KIRSH

Journal of Behavioral Development, 12(3), 305- Hamberger, J. (1979). Music and cognitive
research: Where do our questions come from?
Brooks, R. A. (1991a). Intelligence without rea- Where do our answers go? (Working Paper Ser
son. In Proceedings of the 1991 Joint Confer- No 2.). Cambridge: Massachusetts Institute of
ence on Artificial Intelligence (pp. 569-595). San Technology, Division for Study and Research
Francisco, CA: Morgan Kaufmann. in Education.
Brooks, R. A. (1991b). Intelligence without repre- Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cam-
sentation. Artificial Intelligence, 47,141—159. bridge, MA: MIT Press.
Brown, J. S., Collins, A., & Duguid, P. (1989). Hutchins, E., & Palen, L. (1997). Constructing
Situated cognition and the culture of learning. meaning from space, gesture, and speech. In
Educational Researcher, 18, 32-42. L. B. Resnick, R. Saljo, C. Pontecorvo, & B.
Carraher, T. N., Carraher, D. W., & Schliemann, Bürge (Eds.), Discourse, tools, and reasoning:
A. D. (1985). Mathematics in the streets and Essays on situated cognition (pp. 23-40). Hei-
in the schools. British Journal of Developmental delberg, Germany: Springer-Verlag.
Psychology, 3, 21-29. Karp, R. M. (1986). Combinatorics, complexity,
Chambers, D., & Reisberg, D. (1985). Can mental and randomness. Communications of the ACM
images be ambiguous? Journal of Experimen- 29(2), 98-109.
tal Psychology: Human Perception and Perfor- Kershaw, T. C. (2004). Key actions in insight
mance, 11, 317-328. problems: Further evidence for the impor-
Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, tance of non-dot turns in the nine-dot
and world together again. Cambridge, MA: problem. In K. Forbus, D. Gentner, & T.
MIT Press. Regier (Eds.), Proceedings of the Twenty-Sixth
Devlin, A. S., & Bernstein, J. (1996). Interactive Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Soci-
wayfinding: Use of cues by men and women. ety (pp. 678-683). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum.
Journal of Environmental Psychology, 16, 23-
39- Kirsh, D. (1991). When is information explicitly
represented? In P. Hanson (Ed.), Vancouver
Elster, J. (1979). Ulysses and the sirens. Cam-
studies in cognitive science (Vol. 1, pp. 340-365).
bridge: Cambridge University Press.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Gibson, J. J. (1966). The senses considered as
Kirsh, D. (1995a). Complementary strategies:
perceptual systems. Boston, MA: Houghton
Why we use our hands when we think. In J.
Mifflin.
D. Moore & J. F. Lehman (Eds.), Proceedings of
Gibson, J. J. (1977). The theory of affordances. In
the Seventeenth Annual Conference of the Cog-
R. E. Shaw & J. Bransford (Eds.), Perceiving,
nitive Science Society (pp. 212-217). Hillsdale,
acting, and knowing {pp. 67-82). Hillsdale, NJ:
NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Lawrence Erlbaum.
Kirsh, D. (1995b). The intelligent use of space,
Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to
Artificial Intelligence, 72(1-2), 31-68.
visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Kirsh, D. (1996). Today the earwig, tomorrow
Gick, M., & Holyoak, K. (1980). Analogical prob-
man? In M. Boden (Ed.), Artificial life (pp.
lem solving. Cognitive Psychology, 12, 306-355.
237-261). Oxford: Oxford University Press,
Gick, M., & Holyoak, K. (1983). Scheme induc-
(Reprinted from Artificial Intelligence, 47(3),
tion and analogical transfer. Cognitive Psychol-
161-184.)
ogy, 15(1),1-38
Kirsh, D. (2003). Implicit and explicit represen-
Greeno, J. G., & Middle School Mathematics
tation. In L. Nadel (Ed.), Encyclopedia of cog-
through Applications Project Group (1998).
nitive science (Vol. 2, pp. 478-481). London:
The situativity of knowing, learning, and
Nature Publishing Group.
research. American Psychologist, 53(1), 5-26.
Kirsh, D. (2004). Metacognition, distributed cog-
Greeno, J. G., & Moore, J. L. (1993). Situativity
nition and visual design. In P. Gärdenfors &
and symbols: Response to Vera and Simon.
P. Johansson (Eds.), Cognition, education and
Cognitive Science, 17,49-60.
communication technology (pp. 147-179). Hills-
Greeno, J. G., Smith, D. R., & Moore, J. L. (1993).
dale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Transfer of situated learning. In D. K. Detter-
man & R. J. Sternberg (Eds.), Transfer on trial: Kirsh, D., & Maglio, P. (1995). On distinguishing
Intelligence, cognition, and instruction (pp. 99- epistemic from pragmatic actions. Cognitive
167). Norwood, NJ: Ablex. Science, 18, 513-549.
PROBLEM SOi.VING AND SITUATED COGNITION

Kokinov, B., Hadjiilieva, K., & Yoveva, M. ( 1 9 9 7 ) . Murphy, K. M. ( 2 0 0 4 ) . Imagination as joint


Is a hint always useful? In Proceedings of the activity: The case of architectural interaction.
Nineteenth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Mind, Culture and Activity, 1 1 ( 4 ) , 2 7 0 - 2 8 1 .
Science Society. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erl- Newell, A. ( 1 9 9 0 ) . Unified theories of cognition.
baum. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Kotovsky, K., & Fallside, D. ( 1 9 8 9 ) . Representa- Newell, A., 8c Simon, H. ( 1 9 7 2 ) . Human problem
tion and transfer in problem solving. In D. solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Klar & K. Kotovsky (Eds.), Complex infor- Norman, D. A. ( 1 9 8 8 ) . The psychology of everyday
mation processing (pp. 6 9 - 1 0 8 ) . Hillsdale, NJ: thingX. New York: Basic Books.
Lawrence Erlbaum. Ornstein, A. C., 8c Levine, D. U . ( 1 9 9 3 ) . Founda-
Laird, J. E., Newell, A., & Rosenbloom, P. tions of education ( 5 t h ed.). Boston: Houghton
S. (1987) SOAR: An architecture for gen- Mifflin.
eral intelligence. Artificial Intelligence, 3 3 , 1- Paige, J. M., 8c Simon, H. ( 1 9 7 9 ) . Cognitive pro-
64. cess in solving algebra word problems. In H. A.
Larkin, J. H., & Simon, H. A . ( 1 9 8 7 ) . Why a Simon (Ed.), Models of thought. New Haven,
diagram is (sometimes) worth ten thousand CT: Yale University Press.
words. Cognitive Science, 11, 6 5 - 9 9 . Papadimitriou, C., 8c Yannakakis, M. ( 1 9 8 8 ) .
Lave, J. (1988). Cognition in practice: Mind, mathe- Optimization, approximation, and complex-
matics and culture in everyday life. Cambridge: ity classes. In Proceeding? of the Twenti-
Cambridge University Press. eth Annual ACM Symposium on Theory of
Lave, J. ( 1 9 9 6 ) . The practice of learning. In Computing (pp. 2 2 9 - 2 3 4 ) . New York: A C M
S. Chailkin 8c J. Lave (Eds.), Understanding Press.
practice: Perspectives on activity and context Peirce, C. S. ( 1 9 3 1 - 1 9 5 8 ) . The collected papers
(pp. 3 - 3 2 ) . New York: Cambridge University of Charles Sanders Peirce (C. Hartshorne, P.
Press. Weiss [Vols. 1 - 6 ] , 8c A. Burks [Vols. 7 - 8 ] ,
Lesgold, A. M. ( 1 9 8 8 ) . Problem solving. In R. J. Eds.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Sternberg 8c E. E. Smith (Eds.), The psychol- Press.
ogy of human thought (pp. 1 8 8 - 2 1 3 ) . New York: Pretz, J. E., Naples, A. J., 8c Sternberg, R. J.
Cambridge University Press. ( 2 0 0 3 ) . Recognizing, defining, and represent-
Luchins, A. S. ( 1 9 4 2 ) . Mechanization in problem ing problems. In J. E. Davidson 8c R. J. Stern-
solving: The effect of Einstellung. Psychologi- berg (Eds.), The psychology of problem solving
cal Monographs, 5 4 , 1 - 9 5 . (pp. 3 - 3 0 ) . Cambridge: Cambridge University
Luchins, A. S., 8c Luchins, E. H. ( 1 9 7 0 ) . Press.
Wertheimer's seminars revisited: Problem solv- Reitman, W. R. ( 1 9 6 4 ) . Heuristic decision proce-
ing and thinking (Vols. 1-3). Albany: State Uni- dures, open constraints, and the structure of
versity of New York Press. ill-defined problems. In M. W. Shelly & G. L.
Maglio, P., Madock, T., Raphaely, D., Chernicky, Bryan (Eds.), Human judgments and optimality
B., 8c Kirsh, D. (1999). Interactive skill in (pp. 2 8 2 - 3 1 5 ) . New York: John Wiley.
Scrabble. In Proceedings of Twenty-First Annual Rogoff, B., & Lave, J. (Eds.) ( 1 9 8 4 ) . Everyday cog-
Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. nition: Its development in social context. Cam-
(pp. 3 2 6 - 3 3 0 ) . Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erl- bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
baum. Sayeki, Y., Ueno, N., 8c Nagasaka, T. (1991).
Maier, N. R. F. ( 1 9 3 0 ) . Reasoning in humans: I. Mediation as a generative model for obtain-
On direction. Journal of Comparative Psychol- ing an area. Learning and Instruction, 1, 229-
OQT, 1 0 , 1 1 5 - 1 4 3 . M2- -M
Maier, N. R. F. ( 1 9 7 0 ) . Problem solving and cre- Scribner, S. ( 1 9 8 4 ) . Studying working intelli-
ativity. Belmont, C A : Brooks/Cole. gence. In B. Rogoff 8c J. Lave (Eds.), Every-
Mayer, R. E. (1995). The search for insight. In R. J. day cognition: Its development in social context
Sternberg 8c J. E. Davidson (Eds.), The nature (pp. 9 - 4 0 ) . Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univer-
of insight (pp. 3 - 3 2 ) . New York: Cambridge sity Press.
University Press. Scribner, S. ( 1 9 8 6 ) . Thinking in action: Some
Miller, G. A., Galanter, E., 8c Pribram, K. H. characteristics of practical thought. In R. J.
(i960). Plans and the structure of behavior. New Sternberg 8c R. K. Wagner (Eds.), Practical
York: Holt, Rinehart 8c Winston. intelligence: Nature and origins of competence
DAVID KIRSH

in tkr everyday world (pp. 13-30). Cambridge: Sternberg, R. J. (1997)- Thinking styles. New York
Cambridge University Press. Cambridge University Press.
Simon, H. A. (1969). The sciences of the artificial. Sternberg, R. J., & Davidson, J. E. (1983). i nsj h(
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, in the gifted. Educational Psychologist, 18,51_
Simon, H. A. (1979). Models of thought (Vol. 1). 57-
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. VanLehn, K. (1989). Problem solving and cog.
Simon, H. A., & Hayes, J. (1976). The under- nitive skill acquisition. In M. I. Posner (Ed)
standing process: Process isomorphs. Cognitive Foundations of cognitive science (pp. 527-;^)'
Psychology, 8,165-190. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
C H A P T E R 16

The Dynamic Interactions between


Situations and Decisions

Jerome R. Busemeyer, Ryan K. Jessup, and Eric Dimperio

The majority of judgment and decision- 1. Situated Decision Making


making research is based on laboratory
experiments using very simple and artifi- The term situated cognition may be unfamil-
cial stimulus conditions. Eliciting prefer- iar to many decision researchers, but the
ences between simple gambles of the form, ideas are not. Many decision researchers
"Get $% with probability p, otherwise $y" have considered, very seriously, the impor-
is the primary basis on which rational prin- tance of using realistic environments for
ciples of decision making are tested (Gold- the study of decision making. Decision
stein & Weber, 1995). The foundations of researchers have used terms such as social
modem decision theories (see Luce, 2000) judgment theory or decision analysis or nat-
are built on findings from these simple gam- uralistic decision making, which may be less
bling paradigms. These laboratory experi- familiar to cognitive scientists, to describe
ments are quite far removed from real-life their explorations into work in the area of
decisions; nevertheless, many of the find- situated cognition.
ings do generalize to real-world applications Social judgment theory (see Hammond,
(Levin, Louviere, Schepanski, & Norman, Stewart, Brehmer, & Steinmann, 1975) is
1983). However, new empirical phenom- generally interested in understanding how
ena and unique theoretical issues have sur- experts form judgments based on cues pro-
faced by studying decision making in more vided by the environment. For example, in
natural environments. One of the goals of an experimental study of highway safety
this chapter is to review these new find- policies (Hammond, Hamm, Grassia, &
ings and theoretical issues. A second goal Pearson, 1987), expert highway engineers
is to examine more closely whether the- were asked to predict accident rates for high-
ories built from simple laboratory experi- ways described by scenarios (e.g., videos).
ments are capable of addressing these new The scenarios were designed to manipulate
challenges. ten cues that were identified as essential by

5°"
jerome r . rl'semeyl-r, r y a n k . j e s s u p , a n d e r i c d t m p e r i o

the experts (e.g., highway size, traffic speed, T h e discovery of general principles 0 f
traffic volume). Each scenario was con- human judgment is a primary objective of
structed by sampling a combination of cue social judgment research. For example j n
values for the ten cues. To estimate each the highway-safety study, researchers may
expert's policy (i.e., the rule mapping cues be interested in h o w the presentation for-
to predictions), judgments were obtained mat of the cues (abstract bar graphs ver-
from each expert using forty different sus concrete videos) generally affects the
highway scenarios. Statistical models (e.g., experts' policies. Experimental methods are
regressing the judgments on the cue values) still preferred over natural observation or
were then used to estimate the expert's pol- field research for this purpose. However, the
icy. From these analyses one can determine experiments are designed so that both the
the importance weight of each cue for mak- stimuli (situations to be judged) and partic-
ing a judgment. ipants (judges) are sampled in a way that
represents the real-world population of sit-
Research in social judgment theory is
uations and people.
based on Egon Brunswik's (1952) concepts of
representative design and ecological valid- Decision analysis is concerned with
ity. A representative design is achieved by the development of prescriptive methods
sampling judgment situations by a method for improving difficult real-life decisions
that preserves ecological validity; ecologi- (Clemens, 1996; Keeney & Raiffa, 1976). •
cal validity holds when the sample correla- real-life e x a m p l e is a case in which an oil
tions between cues and the criterion match company had to select a site to drill for
the corresponding true correlations in the oil (see von Winterfeldt & Edwards, 1986).
population. For example, highway size, traf- The basic principle is to divide and con-
fic speed, and traffic volume are correlated quer - a c o m p l e x decision is broken down
with one another and correlated with acci- into small manageable parts, judgments are
dent rates in the real world, and these cor- made with respect to each part, and then
relations should be reflected in sample sce- these small parts are recombined to form
narios presented to the experts. Students an overall evaluation. Experts consult with
of Brunswik reject the use of experimen- decision analysts w h o help them form a rep-
tal designs that create artificial and unnatu- resentation of the problem in terms of deri-
ral situations that break these correlations. sion trees (actions and events over time).
For example, although the use of uncor- Then probability estimates are elicited from
rected cues (e.g., factorial designs) would the experts concerning the uncertain events
facilitate the statistical analysis of experts' on the branches of the decision tree. The
policies, this artificial design violates the nat- consequences of the actions along the
urally occurring correlations among cues. branches of the trees are decomposed into
According to Brunswik (and social judgment attributes, and each action is evaluated with
researchers; for a recent review, see Dhami, respect to each attribute. For example, on
Hertwig, & Hoffirage, 2004), tampering with the one hand, an oil site may have a large
the naturally occurring environmental rela- oil reserve, but on the other hand, it may
tions could destroy the phenomena under be located in an environmentally protected
investigation. Instead, judgment situations region. Finally, a rational or optimal rule,
should be sampled in a representative fash- called the "multiattribute expected utility
ion so that the ecological validities of cues rule," is used to combine the probabili-
are maintained. In the preceding example ties and values into a summary measure of
of highway safety judgments, a representa- utility.
tive sampling of situations was achieved by Research in decision analysis is primar-
designing cue combinations that reproduced ily concerned with the development and
the true or natural intercorrelations and eco- testing of methods for representing deci-
logical validities of cues for the population sion scenarios, tools for estimating proba-
of highways under study. bilities, and techniques for eliciting value
t h e d y n a m i c i n t e r a c t i o n s b e t w e e n s i t u a t i o n s and D E c i s i o n s

judgments. Decision-support systems serve help in these types of decisions - they are
as imp ortant external resources for decision much too complex and uncertain, and time
makers - statistical analyses and computer is much too short to evaluate all the feasible
simulations are used to help estimate event actions.
probabilities; computer analyses are used Consequently, research on naturalistic
to provide instant feedback about expected decisions has uncovered some new views of
utilities; and sophisticated human computer decision making (Lipshitz, Klein, Orasanu,
interfaces are used to help elicit judgments, & Salas, 2001). First, situation assessment
facilitate group discussion, and communi- seems to be the most crucial component
cate results. of the process for these types of decisions.
The most difficult and controversial Given a situational assessment, the next
aspect of this research is assessing the qual- most important process is option genera-
ity of decisions produced by these meth- tion. In many cases, following a situation
ods (see Yates, Veinott, & Patalano, 2003) assessment, the appropriate action is clear
One cannot simply rely on the outcome of and immediate. In these cases, the decision
a single decision because of its probabilis- seems fairly obvious, so that there is very lit-
tic nature. A rational decision process may tle in the way of actual evaluation of alter-
yield an unfortunate outcome by chance. native actions. This led Klein (1989) to pro-
For example, a carefully selected drilling site pose what he calls the "recognition-primed
may nevertheless turn out to be a disaster decision model." According to this model,
because of an unpredictable environmen- after completing a situation assessment and
tal event (e.g., a hurricane). Many impor- developing a mental model of the situation,
tant decisions, such as selecting a drilling the decision maker generates or retrieves an
site, are made only once, which provides action that matches the assessed situation.
little opportunity to learn from experience. Then this action is mentally simulated to
There are no absolute criteria for identifying determine its feasibility and the possibility
a "correct" decision because the decisions of failure to achieve the goal. If the initially
depend on personal beliefs and subjective generated action is evaluated as acceptable
values. Assessing decision quality has been a (likely to succeed in achieving the goal),
long-standing problem in the evaluation of then the action is carried out without further
decision-analysis tools. T w o minimal crite- deliberation or comparison with competing
ria for evaluating decision quality are consis- options. If it is not acceptable, then a second
tency and robustness - the decision should option is generated and evaluated for accept-
not be affected by irrelevant changes in rep- ability, and so forth. Thus, the options are
resentation or by small adjustments caused evaluated serially one at a time and never
by minor judgment errors (Kaplan, 1996). directly compared. This contrasts sharply
Naturalistic decision making is a research with traditional decision theory in which
methodology for understanding how actions all options are carefully compared simulta-
are selected in dynamic, complex, real- neously, and the best option in a choice set
life situations that involve high stakes, a is selected. In fact, the recognition-primed
high degree of uncertainty, and high time decision process is more closely related to
pressure (Zsambok & Klein, 1997). For Herb Simon's (1955) search and satisficing
example, in a study of emergency deci- principles. It is also closely related to the
sions, researchers followed thirty expert fire- "take the best" heuristic used by Gigerenzer
fighting units to 126 emergency scenes and and Todd (see Brighton & Todd's chapter in
observed and recorded their activities; they this volume).
also intensively interviewed the command Given the emphasis on real-life decisions,
and control decision makers immediately naturalistic decision making relies heavily
after the incidents (Klein, 1989). The find- on field research and interview methods,
ings from this field research indicated that and these methods have raised some con-
traditional decision theory provided little cerns (LeBoeuf & Shafir, 2001). One is that
jerome r . rl'semeyl-r, r y a n k . jessup, a n d e r i c dtmperio

field research methods lack the control and giving up the benefits of the laboratory ( e »
measurement precision needed to rigorously Brehmer & Allard's [1991] fire-fighting
test for decision biases. For example, much ulation task, or flight simulators for trainin
of naturalistic decision research is based on pilots). Second, the experimenter is g1Vm„
retrospective interviews, and basic research up a certain degree of control so that stim-
has shown that these retrospective reports ulus events are influenced by the behavior
(as distinct from on-line protocols) inaccu- of the subject. Thus, the design and analy.
rately reflect the basis of decisions (Erics- sis of such research would be better served
son & Simon, 1984; Nisbett & Wilson, 1977). if experimenters adapted a more cyber-
This is because of possible hindsight biases netic paradigm rather than the traditional
(Fischoff & Slovic, 1978), as well as memory- stimulus-response paradigm (cf. Brehmer
recall failures and distortions (Loftus, 2003). 1992; Rapoport, 1975).
One of the distinct advantages of nat- An important question that arises from
uralistic decision making is also one of its this research is h o w to characterize the
greatest disadvantages. On the one hand, an decision-making process for these complex
intense focus on a specific yet complex situa- dynamic tasks. O n e approach (Jagacinski &
tion generates a detailed description of that Hah, 1988; Jagacinski & Miller, 1978; Kirlik
one real-life decision. On the other hand, Miller, &. Jagacinski, 1993) is to estimate the
this understanding is limited to that par- decision maker's control policy by regress-
ticular situation, and very little generaliza- ing the control decision (e.g., the drug treat-
tion to other decision situations is possi- ment level) on the past decisions and past
ble. In other words, the approach produces states of the system (past treatments and
detailed descriptions but fails to produce health levels). This provides an understand-
general principles (Yates, 2004). ing of the importance of different kinds of
Dynamic decision-making tasks provide information used to make control decisions
a good compromise between experimental in dynamic tasks. For example, You (1989)
control needed for basic research and simu- found that subjects' treatment decisions on
lation of real-life decisions (Edwards, 1962). each trial could be represented by a linear
For example, You (1989) studied a simu- control model in which subjects made use
lated health-management task in which sub- of information about treatments and health
jects controlled their (simulated) patients' states lagging back in time up to two previ-
health using a (hypothetical) drug treat- ous (simulated) days.
ment. Participants chose a dosage level on Although human performers with exten-
each of fourteen (simulated) days on the sive task training remain suboptimal in
basis of feedback from a patient's previous dynamic decision tasks (Sterman, 1994),
records (treatments and health states). Each most of the past studies reveal regular learn-
simulated patient was actually programmed ing effects. Subjective policies may follow
to respond according to a delayed second- different paths but tend to evolve toward
order, linear-feedback system. The initially the optimal control policy over multiple trial
novice decision makers were given exten- blocks (Jagacinski 8l Hah, 1988; Jagacinski &
sive training with a total of twenty simulated Miller, 1978; Y o u , 1989). Therefore, it is the
patients so that they develop some expertise particular learning processes that are more
for this particular task. significant for explaining much of the vari-
These types of laboratory tasks have some ance in human performance on dynamic
trade-offs that should be recognized. First, decision tasks (cf. Hogarth, 1981). At least
these tasks are artificially made to allow three different approaches to learning to
for experimental control and theoretical control dynamic systems have been devel-
tractability, and they often end up over- oped. Anzai (1984) developed a production-
simplifying the real-life tasks they simu- rule model to describe how humans learn
late. Still, more complex tasks that provide to navigate a simulated ship. An artifi-
greater realism have been designed without cial neural-network model was developed
t h e d y n a m i c i n t e r a c t i o n s between s i t u a t i o n s a n d decisions

to describe learning in a sugar-production a blip moving on the screen is an enemy or


task (Gibson, Fichman, & Plaut, 1997). a friendly agent; or a radiologist may need
An exemplar (instance base or case base) to decide whether an image should be diag-
learning approach has been used in sev- nosed as a harmless tumor or a cancerous
eral dynamic control applications (Dienes node. In laboratory studies of signal detec-
& Fahey, 1995, Gilboa & Schmeidler, 1995; tion, highly practiced individuals make deci-
Gonzalez, Lerch, & Lebiere, 2003). sions under uncertainty (e.g., low signal-
According to the exemplar learning to-noise ratio) within short deadlines (e.g.,
approach, the decision maker matches the within a second) and real payoffs (e.g., lose
current state of the dynamic task with simi- $1.00 for each error). Although this situation
lar states that occurred in the past and recalls clearly differs from real-life emergency deci-
the outcomes of those past decisions. The sions, the basic theoretical ideas may still be
action producing the best outcome in the applicable.
past is then chosen for the current state. This The early versions of signal-detection the-
is related to the idea of matching situations ory (Green & Swets, 1966) were static and
with actions in the recognition-primed deci- assumed that a decision was based on a
sion model proposed by naturalistic decision fixed sample of information. These early
researchers. So it seems that lessons learned models were effective for describing how
from the laboratory using dynamic decision hits (correcdy responding signal) and false
tasks converge on the same answers as those alarms (incorrectly responding signal) varied
learned from studying naturalistic decision as a function of signal strength, prior prob-
situations. abilities, and payoffs. However, these early
models failed to account for speed-accuracy
trade-offs, as they provided no mecha-
2. Alternate A p p r o a c h e s to Naturalistic nism for predicting choice-response time.
Decisions: Sequential-Sampling The subsequent development of sequential-
Processes sampling models (Luce, 1986; Vickers, 1979)
provided a dynamic extension of signal-
Does the decision process really change detection theory, which accounted not
so dramatically for naturalistic decisions as only for hit and false-alarm rates but also
compared to laboratory decisions? Instead for choice-response time and the relation
of looking for help from traditional deci- between speed and accuracy.
sion theory, perhaps it would be better to The sequential-sampling model of deci-
look for help from cognitive psychology. sion making is quite different from the
Researchers from sensation (Smith, 1995), recognition-primed decision model in two
perception (Link & Heath, 1975), mem- important ways. First, several courses of
ory (Ratcliff, 1978), categorization (Ashby, action are evaluated in a parallel competi-
2000; Nosofsky & Palmeri, 1997), and deci- tion over time for selection rather than seri-
sion making under uncertainty (Busemeyer ally. Second, situation assessment dynam-
& Townsend, 1993) have converged on the ically interacts with decision making. The
common idea that decisions are made by assessment process does not run indepen-
a sequential-sampling process: information dently until completion; rather, it can
and evaluations are sequentially sampled terminate early or late during processing
and accumulated over time in parallel for depending on the relative strengths of the
each possible course of action, and the pro- competing alternatives. Let us analyze a
cess stops as soon as the strength for one real-life example to see how a sequential-
action exceeds a threshold bound. sampling model of decision making dif-
fers from the recognition-primed decision
Sequential-sampling models of decision
model.
making originated in research on signal-
detection types of decisions. For example, a An experienced motorcyclist is riding
radar operator may need to decide whether cross-country on his motorcycle, cruising
jerome r. rl'semeyl-r, r y a n k. jessup, a n d e r i c dtmperio

around eighty kilometers per hour down


a two-lane state highway when he comes
twenty-five meters behind a truck, loaded
down with old car tires, traveling in the same
direction. The highway is in poor condition,
filled with potholes left by snowplows from
the previous winter. The truck bumps into
of one of these pits, causing a tire to som-
ersault out of the truck and land flat on
the road, directly in the motorcyclist's path.
Thus, the motorcyclist faces an emergency
situation, in which he very quickly gener-
ates three potential plans of action: (a) drive
straight over the tire, (b) swerve to the side, Figure 16.1. Example of the decision process for
and (c) slam on the brakes.1 the motorcyclist's decision. Horizontal axis is
Now, the standard operating procedure time, and vertical axis is preference, and each
for most motorists in this situation is to slam trajectory represents an action. The top flat line
on the breaks, but the motorcyclist notices is the threshold bound.
that there was a line of cars following closely,
and he could get hit from behind. He could
also swerve to the side, but he noticed that favoring action A (drive straight over)
the road had no shoulder, and an abrupt steadily overcome action C (slam on brakes),
turn could topple the bike. The only remain- and action B (swerve) is driven systemat-
ing option under consideration is to drive ically downward in preference. Before 250
straight over the tire, but his chain may get ms, action C dominates the race; actions A
caught, causing the bike to flip over. These and C strongly compete at 350 ms; but after
and many other thoughts and feelings race 600 ms, action A overcomes action C, How-
through his head during the brief second in ever, the threshold is set to a low criterion,
which he must make a decision. allowing it to be reached for the first time by
The basic ideas behind the sequential- action C at 250 ms, and so action C is exe-
sampling model for this example can be cuted at this m o m e n t (for this example).
understood by considering Figure 16.1. The Notice that this description of the deci-
horizontal axis of the figure represents time, sion process is quite different from that
and the vertical axis represents the strength given by the recognition-primed decision
of preference. Each trajectory shows the model. According to the latter, the rider
preference strength for an action across would spend most of his time making a sit-
time. The zero time point marks the onset uation assessment and would not even con-
of the decision process (i.e., the onset of sider actions until the situation-assessment
the emergency situation). The top flat line process was complete. In contrast, the
represents the threshold bound (located at sequential-sampling model allows situation
.70 in the figure; i.e., the strength of prefer- assessment to f e e d on-line into action evalu-
ence that an action needs to exceed to make ation. It can stop early if there is a sufficiently
a decision). Note that action C (slam on strong preference to warrant action, or it can
brakes) begins with a positive bias because continue longer if necessary to more clearly
this is the standard operating procedure for discriminate the competing options.
this type of emergency; actions A and B start
According to the recognition-primed
at lower initial values because they are more
model, once the situation was assessed, a
unconventional.
single action that matches the situation is
As the deliberation process unfolds, eval- activated. T h e action that best matches this
uations start pouring into the decision particular situation would be to slam on
maker's mind. In this example, evaluations the brakes, w h i c h is the standard operating
t h e dynamic i n t e r a c t i o n s between s i t u a t i o n s a n d decisions

ocedure for this kind of situation for most other under certain circumstances. Suppose
drivers. Only if the evaluation of the first one used the sequential-sampling process to
^on failed to exceed a threshold would make decisions. If there is a strong bias for
another action be considered. Thus, actions the standard operating procedure for a given
are evaluated in a serial manner, and very situation, and if the threshold bound is set
likely only the first action is considered at all. very low under extreme time pressure, then
This contrasts sharply with the sequential- the sequential-sampling model behaves very
sampling model in which all three actions much like the recognition-primed decision
are retrieved simultaneously, and all three model. For in this case, it is very likely that
dynamically compete over time in a race for the sequential-sampling model will select
the threshold bound to be selected. the initially favored action for a particular
The threshold bound has a crucial func- situation.
tion in the sequential-sampling process. There is a simple empirical test that can
It determines the strength of preference be performed to distinguish these two mod-
required before making a decision. If this els. The sequential-sampling model predicts
is set to a very low value, then very little that the average amount of time required
strength is needed to make the decision. to make a decision depends not only on the
For example, if the threshold was set to action that is chosen but also on the nature
1,0 instead of .70, then action A would be of the action that was not chosen. If the
selected a little after 750 ms. Setting the discriminability is high (i.e., the incoming
threshold to a high value requires more information strongly and consistently favors
information to be processed and longer aver- one action over another), then a decision
age decision times. Thus, the threshold is will tend to be made very quickly; but if
used to control speed-accuracy trade-offs. the discriminability is low (i.e., the incoming
Short deadlines would require low thresh- information inconsistendy or weakly favors
olds to make quick decisions, but high stakes one action over another), then a decision
would push the threshold up higher to avoid will tend to be made more slowly. In short,
making fast errors. Impulsive decision mak- average decision time is inversely related
ers tend to use a low threshold and act with to discriminabdity between the competing
little thought, whereas careful decision mak- actions. In contrast, the recognition prime
ers tend to use a higher threshold and spend model assumes that actions are evaluated
more time in thought before acting. In short, serially, and the time required to evaluate
the threshold is a parameter used to control a given action depends only on the com-
the average amount of time spent on making parison of this action with a threshold, and
a decision. not on the strength of other possible com-
A threshold parameter is also used in the peting actions. In laboratory experiments
recognition-primed model, but it serves a using signal-detection-type tasks, the evi-
different purpose. Rather than controlling dence clearly indicates that decision time is
the length of time spent on situation assess- inversely related to discriminability between
ment, it determines the likelihood of choos- competing options (see Luce, 1986; Vick-
ing the first action that matches the situa- ers, 1979). However, this finding may be
tion. If the threshold is very high, then the restricted to choices between a small num-
first action is likely to be passed up even if it ber of competing options, and it may not be
is the best. If the threshold is very low, then true for situations that provide a very large
the first action is likely to be chosen even if number of choices (e.g., choosing a move in
it is actually the worst. Thus, increasing the chess; see Klein, 1989).
threshold does increase decision time, but it This brings us to ask, Under what condi-
does not necessarily increase accuracy in the tions might one expect the sequential-sam-
recognition-primed decision model. pling process versus a recognition-primed
Despite the differences mentioned be- decision process to be used in naturalistic
tween the two models, they can mimic each decisions? In the motorcyclist example, only
jerome r . rl'semeyl-r, r y a n k . j e s s u p , a n d e r i c d t m p e r i o

a very small number of competing actions (action B) is more likely to produce con-
are immediately available, and there is a sequence Cj, and slamming on the brakes
great deal of conflict among the competing (action C ) is more likely to produce conse-
actions. This is very likely to be a situation in quence cv The affective evaluation of the
which a sequential-sampling type of delib- jth consequence is symbolized as m;, which
eration process is needed to separate out is a real number that represents the decision
one option from a few strong competitors. maker's personal feelings about each conse-
However, consider for example searching quence, such that a higher mj is evaluated
through a very large set of possibilities, such as a better consequence (clearly m, > m >
as an escape route in an emergency with m, > m4 in this example).
many possible exits. Here a serial search Figure 16.2 provides a connectionist inter-
through options until one exceeds a thresh- pretation of decision-field theory for this
old is a more likely description of the pro- example. The affective evaluations shown
cess. There is a growing literature examining on the far left are the inputs to this network
stopping rules that individuals use to serially At any moment in time, the decision maker
search through large option sets (e.g., see anticipates the consequences of each action
Bearden, Murphey, & Rapoport, 2005; for a which produces a momentary evaluation
review, see Diederich, 2003). l/,(f), for action if shown as the first layer
of nodes in Figure 16.2. This momentary
evaluation is an attention weighted average
3. Decision-Field Theory of the affective evaluation of each conse-
quence: Ui(t) = EWiy(i)-m,. The attention
Figure 16.1 provides only a descriptive illus- weight, Wy(r) for consequence j produced
tration of how a sequential-sampling deci- by action i at time | is assumed to fluctu-
sion process works. To get a clearer idea, ate according to a stationary stochastic pro-
we will provide a more formal specification cess. This reflects the idea that attention is
of a theory, decision-field theory,2 which shifting from moment to moment, causing
was specifically designed for decision making changes in the anticipated consequences of
under uncertainty with time stress (Buse- each action across time. For example, atone
meyer & Townsend, 1993; Roe, Busemeyer, moment in time the decision maker may
& Townsend, 2001). However, we should believe he can successfully drive straight
mention that there are also other compet- over the tire, but at the next moment he may
ing theories that provide alternate dynamic change his mind and fear that the tire will
accounts of the decision-making process get entangled with the motorcycle chain.
(see, e.g., Holyoak & Simon, 1999; Usher & The momentary evaluation of each action
McClelland, 2004). is compared with other actions to form a
Consider the motorcyclist's decision once valence for each action at each moment,
again, and for simplicity, suppose that there Vi(t) = Ui(t) - U(t), where U(t) equals the
are four possible outcomes that could result average across all the momentary actions.
from each action: (c,) a safe maneuver with- The valence represents the momentary
out damage or injury; ( c j laying the motor- advantage or disadvantage of each action,
cycle down and damaging the motorcycle and this is shown as the second layer of nodes
but escaping with minor cuts and bruises; in Figure 16.2. If the decision maker is being
(c,) crashing into another vehicle, damaging attracted to one action by a positive valence,
the motorcycle, and suffering serious injury; then he or she must be repelled from other
and (c4) flipping the motorcycle over and actions by negative valences, so that the total
getting killed. In the motorcyclist's opin- valence balances out to zero. All the actions
ion, driving straight over the tire (action A) cannot become attractive simultaneously.
is very risky, with high possibilities for the Finally, the valences are the inputs to a
extreme consequences, c, and c 4 . Swerving dynamic system that integrates the valences
t h e dynamic i n t e r a c t i o n s between s i t u a t i o n s a n d decisions V7 PS

Figure 16.2. Connectionist interpretation of decision-field theory


for the motorcyclist's example.
jerome r. rl'semeyl-r, ryan k. jessup, a n d e r i c dtmperio

(Busemeyer & Townsend, 1993), the growth,


rate parameter is important for explaining
changes in strength of preference strength
as a function of deliberation time (see Buse-
meyer, 1985), and the initial bias is important
for producing reversals (for examples of bias
under time pressure, see Diederich, 2003)
In summary, we examined a claim that
naturalistic decisions required a completely
new type of decision theory. Next, we ar-
gued that sequential-sampling theory
which assumes a dynamic interaction be-
tween situation assessment and decision
processes, provides a viable explanation
for many naturalistic decisions. Finally, we
showed that sequential-sampling models
such as decision-field theory, can be viewed
as dynamic extensions of the traditional
decision theories. Therefore, sequential-
sampling models provide a theoretical
bridge between traditional decision theories
and naturalistic decisions.

4. Situated C o g n i t i o n in the
Laboratory: Context-Dependent
Preferences

Effects of choice context on preference


are not limited to naturalistic situations.
On the contrary, basic research with sim-
ple choice problems provides compelling
evidence that our preferences are con-
structed in a highly context-dependent man-
ner (Payne, Bettman, 8c Johnson, 1992). Con-
sider the following experiment by Tversky
and Kahneman (1991) that was designed to
test a rational principle of choice called
"independence f r o m irrelevant alternatives."
According to this principle, if option X is
favored over option Y in the choice con-
text that includes option R x , then option X
should also be preferred over option Y in the
choice context that includes option Ry.
T h e basic ideas of the experiment are
illustrated in Figure 16.3, where each let-
ter shown in the figure represents a choice
option described by two attributes; for
example, consumer products that vary in
price and quality. In this case, option X is
low on price and quality, whereas option
t h e d y n a m i c i n t e r a c t i o n s between s i t u a t i o n s a n d decisions V7

causing the preference order for X and Y to


reverse across the two contexts. This pref-
erence reversal violates the rational princi-
ple of choice known as independence from
irrelevant alternatives. This is just one exam-
ple violation of this principle, but there are
many others (see Roe et al., 2001; Tversky &
Simonson, 1993).
What causes these context effects on
preferences? Tversky and Kahneman (1991)
Price
interpreted this particular result in terms
Figure 16.3. illustration of stimuli used to of a loss aversion effect: option X was
produce reference-point effects. The horizontal favored when Y entailed large losses rela-
axis represents price, the vertical axis represents tive to the reference point R x , but the oppo-
quality, and each point represents a consumer site occurred when X entailed large losses
product. relative to the reference point R y . But this
explanation leaves one to wonder about the
Y is high on price and quality. W h e n pre- mechanism that causes loss aversion.
sented with a straight binary choice between Decision-field theory provides a dynamic
options X and Y, the options are (approxi- mechanism for explaining the reference-
mately) equally favored. T h e main theoreti- point effect as well as many other context-
cal question concerns the addition of a third dependent preference effects (see Buse-
option to the set, which is used to manipu- meyer & Johnson, 2004; Roe et al., 2001).
late the choice context. According to decision-field theory, these
The critical context manipulation in this context effects are generated by the recur-
experiment was the introduction of a third rent network shown as the third layer in
option, called the "reference option," rep- Figure 16.2. We will skip the mathematical
resented by either option R x or option derivations here and simply present the con-
Ry. Under one condition, participants were ceptual ideas.
asked to imagine that they currently owned According to decision-field theory, these
the commodity R x , and they w e r e then given effects are contrast effects like edge
a choice of keeping R x or trading it for enhancement effects that occur in the retina
either commodity X or commodity Y. From (alternatively, these effects can be conceptu-
the reference point of R x , option X has a alized in the context of the lateral inhibition
small advantage on price and no disadvan- occurring within the striatum, part of the
tage on quality, whereas Y has large advan- basal ganglia, during the process of action
tages on quality and large disadvantages on selection; see Frank, 2005; Wickens, 1997).
price. Under these conditions, R x was rarely T h e inferior reference option makes the
chosen, and X was favored over Y. Under closely related attractive option shine. First,
another condition, participants were asked consider the choice set that includes options
to imagine that they o w n e d option R y , and X, Y, and R x . Recall that according to
they were then given a choice of keeping decision-field theory, the lateral inhibitory
R y or trading it for either X or Y. From the links in the network depend on the simi-
reference point of R y , Y has a small advan- larity between options. Note that the refer-
tage and no disadvantages, whereas X now ence point R x is very similar to X, and so the
has both large advantages and disadvantages. lateral inhibitory link between these two is
Under this condition, R y was rarely chosen strong, whereas R x is very dissimilar to Y,
again, but now Y was favored over X. and so the lateral inhibitory link between
In summary, even though the reference these two is weak. Also note that R x always
options, R x and R y , were rarely chosen, they experiences a disadvantage with respect
nevertheless changed the choice context, to option X. This arrangement of options
jerome r. rl'semeyl-r, r y a n K. j e s s u p , AND ERIC DTMPERIO

then produces the following dynamics: as judgments using environmentally provided


processing time passes, option Rx is slowly cue-criterion relations. Decision analysis
driven down toward a negative preference endeavors to provide people with opti-
state; this negative preference feeds back mized decision tools for real-life decisions in
through a negative lateral inhibitory link to order to improve the quality of these deci-
produce an enhancement or bolstering of sions. Naturalistic decision making repre-
option X. In other words, the relatively poor sents a paradigm in which descriptive mod-
reference option, R x , makes its close neigh- els of dynamic, complex, high-uncertainty
bor, option X, shine brighter. The distant high-stakes, and real-life decision situations
option Y does not experience this enhance- are sought. Furthermore, in these complex
ment because the lateral inhibitory link is real-life situations there is not enough time
too weak. Therefore the preference state for or computational resources to systemati-
X gradually dominates Y. When the choice cally evaluate all the options. Consequently
context is changed to include X, Y, and R y , naturalistic decision researchers claim that
the same reasoning holds, but now option new theories and methods of research are
Y is bolstered by being close to a relatively needed.
poor reference R y . In this chapter, we have attempted to
The preceding explanation for context- address these concerns, specifically those
dependent preferences depends on a dy- of naturalistic decision researchers, through
namic inhibitory mechanism that takes time the use of dynamic, as opposed to static
to build up. Thus, decision-field theory pre- tools. Rather than reject traditional decision
dicts that these context effects should get theory and research when we enter natu-
stronger as deliberation time gets longer. In ralistic situations, we have tried to argue
contrast, if these effects were caused by the that a dynamic perspective (see Port & van
use of simple heuristics to save time and Gelder, 1995; van Gelder, 1998) provides
effort, then the opposite is predicted - con- a foundation for building bridges between
text effects should get larger with shorter traditional decision theories and naturalis-
deliberation times that force individuals to tic decisions. Sequential-sampling models
fall back on simple heuristic rules to save were developed from cognitive psychology
time. In fact, past research has found that to understand real-time cognitive processes
the context effects increase with longer observed in simple laboratory experiments.
deliberation times, consistent with the pre- According to these models, decision makers
dictions of a dynamic model and contrary to make an online assessment of the situation
a heuristic choice model (see Dhar, Nowlis, that interacts with the evaluation of com-
& Sherman, 2000; Simonson, 1989). peting options over time; likewise, infor-
mation accumulates in real time and deci-
sion times are influenced by a threshold
5. Concluding Comments for accrued information. We have argued
that dynamic theories of decision making
The majority of decision research is based have the power to explain the basic find-
on simple laboratory experiments, and mod- ings from laboratory experiments, such as
em decision theories have been built on context-dependent preferences, as well as
the basis of these findings. Recently, various new phenomena that arise in the study of
groups of researchers have questioned the naturalistic decisions.
usefulness of these theories when applied
to real-life situations. Three related pro- Notes
grams of research have examined judgment
or decision making through what could be 1 This incident happened to the first author,
called a "situated cognition" perspective. who decided to drive straight over the tire
Social judgment theory focuses on expert and survived to tell this story.
t h e dynamic i n t e r a c t i o n s between s i t u a t i o n s a n d decisions V 7 V9

The name decision-field theory reflects the context effects in choice. Journal of Consumer
influence of Kurt Lewin's (1936) field theory Psychology, 9,189-200.
Diederich, A. (2003). MDFT account of decision
making under time pressure. Psychonomic Bul-
of c o n f l i c t .
letin and Review, 10(1), 157-166.
Dienes, Z., 8c Fahey, R. (1995). Role of specific
instances in controlling a dynamic system.
References
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning,
Anzai, Y. (1984). Cognitive control of real-time Memory, Si Cognition, 21, 848-862.
event-driven systems. Cognitive Science, 8, 221- Edwards, W. (1962). Dynamic decision the-
254. ory and probabilistic information processing.
Ashby, F. G. (2000). A stochastic version of gen- Human Factors, 4, 59-73.
eral recognition theory. Journal of Mathemati- Ericsson, K. A., 8c Simon, H. A. (1984). Protocol
cal Psychology, 44,310-329. analysis: Verbal reports as data. Cambridge,
Beardon, J. N., Murphey, R. O., Rapoport, MA: MIT Press.
A. (2005). A multiattribute extension of the Fischoff, B., 8c Slovic, P. (1978). A little learning:
secretary problem: Theory and experiments. Confidence in multicue judgment tasks. Eugene,
Journal
422. of Mathematical Psychology, 49, 410- OR: Decision Research.
Brehmer, B. (1992). Dynamic decision making: Frank, M. J. (2005). Dynamic dopamine modu-
Human control of complex systems. Acta Psy- lation in the basal ganglia: A neurocomputa-
chologica, 81, 211-241. tional account of cognitive deficits in medi-
Brehmer, B., & Allard, R. (1991). Real-time cated and nonmedicated Parkinsonism. Jour-
dynamic decision making: Effects of task com- nal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 17(1), 51-72.
plexity and feedback delays. In J. Rasmussen, Gibson, F., Fichman, M., 8c Plaut, D. C. (1997).
B. Brehmer, 8c J. Leplat (Eds.), Distributed Learning in dynamic decision tasks: Compu-
decision making: Cognitive models for coop- tational model and empirical evidence. Orga-
erative work (pp. 319-334). Chichester, UK: nizational Behavior and Human Performance,
Wiley. l | 1-35-
Brunswik, E. (1952). The conceptual framework Gilboa, I., 8c Schmeidler, D. (1995). Case-based
of psychology. Chicago: University of Chicago theory. Quarterly Journal of Economics, no,
Press. 607-639.
Busemeyer, J. R. (1985). Decision making under Goldstein, W. M., 8c Weber, E. U. (1995). Con-
uncertainty: A comparison of simple scala- tent and discontent: Indications and implica-
bility, fixed sample, and sequential sampling tions of domain specificity in preferential deci-
models. Journal of Experimental Psychology, u, sion making. In J. R. Busemeyer et al. (Eds.),
538-564. The psychology of learning and motivation: Deci-
Busemeyer, J. R., 8c Johnson, J. G. (2004). Com- sion making from a cognitive perspective (Vol.
putational models of decision making. In D. J. 32, pp. 82-136). San Diego, CA: Academic
Koehler 8c N. Harvey (Eds.), Blackwell hand- Press.
book of judgment and decision making. Oxford, Gonzalez, C., Lerch, J. F., 8c Lebiere, C. (2003).
UK: Blackwell. Instance-based learning in dynamic decision
Busemeyer, J. R., 8c Townsend, J. T. (1993). making. Cognitive Science, 27, 591-635.
Decision field theory: A dynamic-cognitive Green, D. M., & Swets, J. A. (1966). Signal detec-
approach to decision making in an uncertain tion theory and psychophysics. Oxford, UK:
environment. Psychological Review, too, 432- Wiley.
459* Hammond, K. R., Hamm, R. M., Grassia, J., 8c
Clemens, R. (1996). Making hard decisions: An Pearson, T. (1987). Direct comparison of the
introduction to decision analysis (2nd ed.). efficacy of intuitive and analytical cognition
Boston: PWS-Kent. in expert judgment. IEEE Transactions on Sys-
Dhami, M. K., Hertwig, R., 8c Hoffrage, U. tems, Man, &J Cybernetics, 17(5), 753-770.
(2004). The role of representative design in an Hammond, K. R., Stewart, T. R., Brehmer, B.,
ecological approach to cognition. Psychological 8c Steinmann, D. O. (1975). Social judgment
Bulletin, 130(6), 9 5 9 - 9 8 8 . theory. In M. Kaplan 8c S. Schwartz (Eds.),
Dhar, R., Nowlis, S. M., 8c Sherman, S. J. (2000). Human judgment and decision processes (pp.
Trying hard or hardly trying: An analysis of 271-312). New York: Academic Press.
JEROME R. RISIM)\TH, RYAN K. JESSUP, AND ERIC DIMPERIO

Hogarth, R. M (1981). Beyond discrete biases: Measurement theoretical and experimental ap-
Functional and dysfunctional aspects of judg- proaches. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
mental heuristics. Psychological Bulletin, go, Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson, T. D. (1977). Telling
I97—2T?. more than we can know: Verbal reports on
Holyoak, K. J., & Simon, D. (1999).. Bidirectional mental processes. Psychological Review, fyM
reasoning in decision making by constraint sat- 231-259.
isfaction. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Nosofsky, R. M., & Palmeri, T. J. ( ^ j
General, 128(1), 3-31. An exemplar-based random walk model of
Jagacinski, R. J., & Hah, S. (1988). Progression- speeded classification. Psychological Review
regression effects in tracking repeated pat- 104, 226—300.
terns. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Payne, J. W., Bettman, J. R., & Johnson, E.
Human Perception and Performance, 14, 77-88. J. (1992). Behavioral decision research: A
Jagacinski, R. J, & Miller, R. A. (1978). Describ- constructive processing perspective. Annual
ing the human operator's internal model of Review of Psychology, 43, 87-131.
a dynamic system. Human Factors, 20, 425- Port, R. F., & van Gelder, T. (Eds.). (1995). My
433- as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cog-
Kaplan, M. (1996). Decision theory as philosophy. nition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rapoport, A. (1975). Research paradigms for
Keeney, R. L., & Raiffa, H. (1976). Decisions with studying dynamic decision behavior. In I
multiple objectives: Preferences and value trade- Wendt & C. Vlek (Eds.), Utility, probabil-
offs. New York: Wiley. ity, and human decision making (pp. 347-369).
Kirlik, A, Miller, R. A., 81 Jagacinski, R. J. (1993). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Reidel.
Supervisory control in a dynamic and uncer- Ratcliff, R. (1978). A theory of memory retrieval,
tain environment: A process model of skilled Psychological Review, 85, 59-108.
human environment interaction. IEEE Trans- Roe, R. M., Busemeyer, J. R., 8t Townsend, J. T.
actions on Systems, Man, and Cybernetics, 23, (2001). Multi-alternative decision field theory:
929-952. A dynamic connectionist model of decision-
Klein, G. A. (1989). Recognition primed deci- making. Psychological Review, 108,370-392.
sions. In W. B. Rouse (Ed.), Advances in man- Simon, H. A. (1955). A behavioral model of ratio-
machine systems research (Vol. 5, pp. 47-92). nal choice. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 69,
Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. 99-118.
LeBoeuf, R. A., & Shafir, E. (2001). Problems Simonson, I. (1989). Choice based on reasons:
and methods in naturalistic decision-making The case of attraction and compromise effects.
research. Journal of Behavioral Decision Mak- Journal of Consumer Research, 16,158-174.
ing, nisi 373-375- Smith, P. L. (1995). Psychophysical^ principled
Levin, I. P., Louviere, J. J., Schepanski, A. A., & models of visual simple reaction time. Psycho-
Norman, K. L. (1983). External validity tests logical Review, 102(3), 567—593.
of laboratory studies of information integra- Sterman, J. D. (1994). Learning in and about
tion. Organizational Behavior & Human Per- complex systems. System Dynamics Review, 10,
formance, 31(2), 173-193- 291-330.
Lewin, K. (1936). Principles of topological psychol- Tversky, A., 8l Kahneman, D. (1991). Loss aver-
ogy. New York: McGraw-Hill. sion in riskless choice: A reference dependent
Link, S. W., & Heath, R. A. (1975). A sequential model. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 106,
theory of psychological discrimination. Psy- 1039-1061.
chometrika, 40,77-111. Tversky, A., 8l Kahneman, D. (1992). Advancesin
Lipshitz, R., Klein, G., Orasanu, J., & Salas, E. prospect theory: Cumulative representations
(2001). Taking stock of naturalistic decision of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty,
making. Journal of Behavioral Decision Mak- 5, 297-323.
ing, 14(5), 331-352. Tversky, A., 81 Simonson, I. (1993). Context-
Loftus, E. F. (2003). Make-believe memories. dependent preferences. Management Science,
American Psychologist, 58(11), 867-873. 39, 1 1 7 9 - 1 1 8 9 .
Luce, R. D, (1986). Response times: Their role in Usher, M., & McClelland, J. L. (2004). Loss aver-
inferring elementary mental organization. New sion and inhibition in dynamical models of
York: Oxford University Press. multialternative choice. Psychobgical Review,
Luce, R. D. (2000). Utility of gains and losses: >»(3l 757~769-
the dynamic i n t e r a c t i o n s between situations a n d decisions V7

van Gelder, T. (1998). The dynamical hypothe- Yates, J. F., Veinott, E. S.( & Patalano, A. L.
sis in cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain (2003). Hard decisions, bad decisions: On deci-
Sciences, 21,1-14. sion quality and decision aiding. In S. L.
Vickers, D. (1979). Decision processes in visual per- Schneider 8c J. L. Shanteau (Eds.), Emerging
ception. New York: Academic Press, perspectives in judgment and decision making
von Winterfeldt, D., & Edwards, W. (1986). Deci- research (pp. 13-63). New York: Cambridge
sion analysis and behavioral research. Cam- University Press.
bridge: Cambridge University Press. You, G. (1989). Disclosing the decision-maker's
Wickens, J. (1997). Basal ganglia: Structure and internal model and control policy in a dynamic
computations. Network: Computation in Neu- decision task using a system control paradipn.
ral Systems, 8, R77-R109. Unpublished master's thesis, Purdue Univer-
Yates, J. F. (2004, March/April). "Let's just go sity.
with it.": The perils of decision neglect. Ivey Zsambok, C. E., 8c Klein, G. (1997). Natu-
Business Journal. Retrieved from http://www. ralistic decision making: Expertise, research
iveybusinessjournal.com/article.asp?intArticle and applications. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
_id=472 Erlbaum.
CHAPTER 17

Situating Rationality

Ecologically Rational Decision Making


with Simple Heuristics

Henry Brighton and Peter M. Todd

i. Introduction tion take the specific and concrete details


of the interaction between mind and envi-
Many within cognitive science believe that ronment to matter significantly, so much
rational principles rooted in probability the- so that seeking universal principles of ratio-
ory and logic provide valuable insight into nality is seen as one of the primary wrong
the cognitive systems of humans and ani- turns in the path of traditional approaches
mals. More than this, some say that ratio- to understanding cognition (e.g., Smith,
nal principles, such as Bayesianism, algorith- 1999)-
mic information theory, and logic, not only Other approaches to cognition find sim-
provide elegant and formally well under- ilar fault with the search for univer-
stood frameworks for thinking about cog- sal mechanisms or all-powerful inferential
nition but also are the very principles gov- machinery. The recently developed view of
erning thought itself, guiding inferences and ecological rationality places a strong focus on
decisions about the world (e.g., Chater & the structural properties of environments,
Vitanyi, 2003; Feldman, 2003). It is not diffi- and takes a structure-specific, and, as we will
cult to see why ascribing such principles to show in this chapter, situated approach to
the cognitive system is a tempting and desir- the study of cognitive processes. Ecological
able goal: if correct, these principles would rationality emerges when simple, cognitively
provide universal normative laws governing plausible heuristic processes exploit spe-
the cognitive system. Even faced with the cific environmental characteristics to make
adaptive choices in particular circumstances
diversity of tasks and environments handled
(Gigerenzer, Todd, & A B C Research Group,
by the cognitive system, a valid universal
1999). Adaptive choices are those that help
principle would have the advantage of pro-
an organism function successfully in its envi-
viding a theoretical handle with which to
ronment. Rather than view the mind as
grasp the range of cognition in a unified man-
a general-purpose processor endowed with
ner. In contrast, situated theories of cogni-

3M
situating rationality

the considerable computational resources 2. Mind and Environment: The Terms


demanded by classical notions of rational of the Relationship
inference, we instead explore the possibility
that the mind is more like a mixed bag In what ways does the environment influ-
of cognitive processes, each working within ence the contents of the mind? A wide range
the limitations of the cognitive system, and of possibilities exists. For some aspects of the
each tuned to specific structures occurring in cognitive system it could be that the envi-
natural environments. We term this mixed ronment plays an insignificant role in influ-
hag of simple heuristics the adaptive toolbox encing the contents of the mind. The human
(e.g., Gigerenzer & Selten, 2001). In section language faculty, for instance, is thought by
, we firm up this metaphor by providing some researchers to be shaped not by the
examples of simple heuristics, and we dis- environment but by boundary conditions
cuss work that demonstrates, through com- internal to the mind, in the sense that the
putational modeling and experimental stud- linguistic system is an optimal solution for
ies, that these heuristics are both plausible meeting the requirements of transforming
and often more effective than traditional thought between the conceptual-intentional
models of inference. system and the articulatory-motor system
In section 4 we address our main con- (Chomsky, 1995). According to this view, if
cern: situating rationality in such a way that we want to understand the language faculty,
then it pays not to consider the environ-
the specific, concrete, engaged, and located
ment at all, either over evolutionary or onto-
nature of human cognition is given due sig-
genetic timescales. But for many aspects
nificance. We argue that classical visions
of the cognitive system we cannot ignore
of rationality fail to consider the compu-
the important impact of the environment,
tational limitations of the cognitive system
and several possible forms of relationship
and the importance of the role of cognitive
between mind and environment need to be
exploitation of environment structure. On
considered. Within psychology, the ecolog-
this view, normative theories derived from
ical approach to cognition seeks to under-
classical notions of rationality prove limited
stand the terms of such relationships. We
in their ability to capture the specific nature begin by considering three metaphors (Todd
of how the cognitive system interacts adap- 8c Gigerenzer, 2001) that aim to capture
tively with the environment in inference and some key relationships.
decision-making tasks. Although systems of
logic, for example, can be tailored to spe-
cific tasks and environmental contexts (e.g., 2.1. Three Kinds of Relationships
Stenning & van Lambalgen, 2004), the issue
of how the cognitive system might plau- To understand the contents of the mind, we
sibly process information to achieve logi- should consider the environment in which it
cal consistency, and whether such a task is acts and in which it has evolved. This ecolog-
computationally feasible, remains unclear. ical, situated perspective has been promoted
In contrast, we argue that ecological ratio- within cognitive psychology in particular by
nality bounds rationality to the world by Roger Shepard's work (see, e.g., Shepard,
considering both ecological context and con- 2001, and other papers in the special issue of
straints on cognitive processing (Todd & Behavioral and Brain Sciences on Shepard's
Gigerenzer, 2003). This view of rationality research and related efforts it has inspired),
is closely allied with the situated cognition focusing on a particular vision of how the
movement, and in section 5 we clarify the external world shapes our mental mecha-
ways in which ecological rationality can be nisms. For Shepard (2001), much of per-
understood in terms of the key dimensions ception and cognition is done with mirrors:
of situated approaches proposed by Smith key aspects of the environment are inter-
IB nalized in the brain "by natural selection
HENRY BRIGHTON AND PETER M. TODD
BM

specifically to provide a veridical represen- Herbert Simon (1990) expressed a stiji


tation of significant objects and events in the looser coupling between mind and envj
external world" (p. 2). In particular, Shepard ronment: bounded rationality, he said
considers how the cognitive system reflects shaped by a pair of scissors whose tw0
features of the world, or laws, which sup- blades are the characteristics of the task
port, for example, tracking the movement environment and the computational capa
of objects in Euclidean space. These abstract bilities of the decision maker. Here, com
principles are based "as much (or possibly putational capabilities refer to sensory neu
more) in geometry, probability, and group ral, and other mental characteristics that
theory, as in specific, physical facts about may impose cognitive limitations on, f0r
concrete, material objects" (Shepard, 2001, example, memory and processing. Crucially
p. 601). Thus, the cognitive system possesses these capabilities, when coupled with cer-
deeply internalized, abstract, and univer- tain characteristics of the environment can
sal reflections of physical reality. Shepard's complement one another. Rather than the
work can be viewed as ecological in that mind reflecting or projecting properties of
an understanding of mind is taken to be the environment, Simon's scissors metaphor
fundamentally dependent on identifying the highlights a very different kind of relation-
important properties of the physical world. ship in which properties of mind are viewed
Yet this view also turns on the contentious as fitting properties of environments in an
issue of the mind representing properties of exploitative and complementary relation-
the world, albeit at a very abstract level. ship. From this perspective, it is less clear
Without entering into arguments over the how meaningfully one can characterize the
need for representations of any sort (for a relationship between mind and environment
discussion of the key issues, see, e.g., Brooks, in terms of internalization or representa-
1991; Markman & Dietrich, 2000), we can still tion, as some properties of the mind can
question whether assumed representations be only implicitly related to the environ-
should be veridical, constructed to accu- ment rather than more directly, as suggested
rately reflect the world, or instead be useful by metaphors of mirror images or projec-
in an adaptive sense. In short, whatever the tions. Considering this kind of exploita-
functional role of such representations, this tive relationship led Simon (1956) to con-
mirrorlike relationship characterizes those sider, in the context of decision making,
properties of mind that are present as a "how simple a set of choice mechanisms
result of an internalization of universal laws we can postulate and still obtain the gross
governing physical environments. features of observed adaptive choice behav-
ior" (p. 129). This question highlights how an
A less exacting view of internalization can
exploitative relationship between mind and
be seen in the work of Egon Brunswik (1955),
environment has implications for the kind
who proposed a lens model that reconstructs
of cognitive machinery used by the mind:
a representation of a distal stimulus on the
as Simon and others have since shown,
basis of the current proximal cues (whose
simple, boundedly rational decision mecha-
availability could vary from one decision sit-
nisms coupled with the right environmental
uation to the next) along with stored knowl-
context can yield adaptive choice behavior
edge of the environmental relationships
that is typically attributed to more complex
between those perceived cues and the stim-
and information-hungry mechanisms.
ulus. These relationships were later usually
conceived of as correlations in the field of
social judgment theory that followed from
Brunswik's work (see Hammond & Stewart, 2.2. Appropriate Metaphors
2001). For Brunswik, the mind models and for Higher-Level Cognition
projects the world more than reflects it (or, We expect that the mind draws on mecha-
as he also put it, mind and world accommo- nisms akin to all three tools, mirrors, lenses,
date each other like husband and wife). and scissors, from its adaptive toolbox
325
SITUATING RATIONALITY

(Gigerenzer & Todd, 1999). T h e question heuristic makes decisions about as well as
now becomes, Where can each be used, multiple regression in many environments
or where does each different view of sit- (Czerlinski, Gigerenzer, & Goldstein, 1999)
uated cognition best apply? In perception, but usually uses far less information (cues)
using Shepard's mirror or Brunswik's lens in reaching a decision. It does not incor-
may often be the right way to look at things, porate enough knowledge to reasonably be
but there are also examples in which these said to reflect the environment, nor even
tools are inappropriate. Consider the prob- to model it in Brunswik's sense (because it
lem of a fielder trying to catch a ball coming only knows cue order, not exact validities),
down in front of her. T h e final destination of but it can certainly match and exploit envi-
the ball will be complexly determined by its ronment structure: when cue importance
initial velocity, its spin, the effects of wind is distributed in something like an expo-
all along its path, and other causal factors. nentially decreasing manner (as is the case
But rather than perceive all these character- in some environments), Take the Best per-
istics, reflect or model the world, and com- forms about as well on training data sets as
pute an interception point to aim at, the multiple regression or any other linear deci-
fielder can use a simple heuristic: fixate on sion rule (Martignon & Hoffrage, 1999) and
the ball and adjust her speed while running generalizes to new data sets even better.
toward it so that her angle of gaze - the angle As another example, the QuickEst
between the ball and the ground from her heuristic for estimating quantities (Hertwig,
eye - remains constant (McLeod & Dienes, Hoffrage, & Martignon, 1999) is similarly
1996). By using this simple gaze heuristic, the designed to use only those cues necessary
fielder will catch the ball while running. No to reach a reasonable inference. QuickEst
veridical representations or models of the makes accurate estimates with a minimum
world are needed - just a mechanism that fits of information when the criteria of the
to and exploits the relevant structure of the objects it operates on follow a J-shaped
environment; namely, the single cue of gaze (power law) distribution, such as the sizes
angle. How widely such scissors-like heuris- of cities or the number of publications per
tics can be found in perception remains to be psychologist. Again this crucial aspect of
seen, but some (e.g., Ramachandran, 1990) environment structure is nowhere built into
expect that perception is a bag of tricks like the decision mechanism, but by processing
this rather than a box of mirrors. the most important cues in an appropriate
When we come to higher-order cogni- order, QuickEst can exploit that structure to
tion and decision making, our main con- great advantage. Neither of these heuristics
cern in this chapter, Simon's cutting per- (which we will describe in more detail in the
spective seems the most appropriate way next section) embodies logical rationality -
to extend Shepard's and Brunswik's eco- they do not even consider all the available
logical views. Consider a simple decision information - but rather they demonstrate
rule that has been proposed as a model of ecological rationality, making adaptive deci-
human choice: the Take the Best heuristic sions by relying on the structure of the envi-
(Gigerenzer & Goldstein, 1996). To choose ronment.
between two options on the basis of several Why might it be that Simon's scissors
cues known about each option, this heuris- could help us understand cognitive mecha-
tic says to consider one cue at a time in order nisms more than Shepard's mirror? We (and
of the ecological validity of each (i.e., how others) suspect that humans often use sim-
often each cue makes correct decisions), and ple decision-making mechanisms that are
to stop this cue search with the first one built on (and receive their inputs from)
that distinguishes between the options and much more complex lower-level percep-
make the final decision using only that cue tual mechanisms. For instance, the recogni-
(we will explain this heuristic in more detail tion heuristic, an elementary mechanism for
later in the chapter). This "fast and frugal" deciding between two options on the basis of
HENRY BRIGHTON AND PETER M. TODD

which of them are merely recognized, sim- here. For instance, people can (if given the
ply uses the binary cue of recognized ver- luxury of sufficient time and training)use
sus not recognized; however, the computa- more general methods of reasoning accord-
tional machinery involved in the lower-level ing to traditional norms of rationality, such
assessment of whether a voice, or face, or as the tools of logic or probability theory
name actually is recognized involves con- to come to decisions with little concern
siderable complexity (Todd, 1999). If these for adapting their reasoning to the spe-
decision heuristics achieve their simplicity cific structure of the current task environ-
in part by minimizing the amount of infor- ment. Or people may use simple decision
mation they use, then they are less likely to heuristics that try to exploit some features
reflect the external world and more likely to of the environment to allow for cognitive
exploit just the important, useful aspects of shortcuts, but in the wrong environment
it, as calculated and distilled by the percep- so that biased decision making arises (as
tual system (which may well base its compu- studied in the heuristics and biases research
tations on a more reflective representation). tradition; see, e.g., Kahneman, Slovic, &
Tversky, 1 9 8 2 ) . But we propose that much
Thus, in extending the search for the
of human decision making is ecologically
imprint of the world on the mind from per-
rational, guided by typically simple deci-
ception to higher-order cognition, we
sion heuristics that exploit the available
should probably look less for reflections
structure of the environment to make good
and more for complementary pairings a la
choices. Given the right environmental cir-
Simon's two scissors blades. This approach
cumstances, these simple methods perform
to studying environmentally situated deci-
adequately for many tasks and sometimes
sion mechanisms is just what we shall intro-
better than more complex mechanisms.
duce in this chapter. While Simon studied
One consequence of this theory is that a
bounded rationality, we use the term ecolog-
single all-purpose decision-making system
ical rationality to emphasize the importance
is no longer the appropriate unit of study,
of the match between the structure of infor-
as different tasks call for different simple
mation in the environment and the structure
mechanisms. The idea of the adaptive tool-
of information processing in the mind. In the
box leads us to consider a collection of sim-
next section, we introduce the notion of the
ple mechanisms drawn on by the cogni-
adaptive toolbox and describe how its con-
tive system. We view these mechanisms as
tents can be studied, before expanding on
structure specific rather than domain spe-
some examples of its contents by describing
cific. In contrast to the concept of domain
simple ecologically rational decision heuris-
specificity, structure specificity is the ability
tics. In section 4 we develop further the con-
of a process to deal effectively with infor-
cept of ecological rationality by discussing
mational structures found in environments
how it contrasts with traditional notions of
that may or may not be encountered in
rationality, and why, in the context of the
multiple domains (e.g., a systematic corre-
study of mind, ecological rationality is a
lation between recognition knowledge and
more appropriate notion when considering
some criterion of interest, which we discuss
aspects of high-level cognition. In section 5
herein). These mechanisms are built from
we relate these discussions to the study
basic, cognitively primitive building blocks
of situated cognition by framing ecological
for information search, stopping the search,
rationality as a form of situated cognition.
and making a decision based on the search's
results. How heuristics are constructed using
these building blocks, when and why one
3. The Adaptive Toolbox
heuristic is used over another, and h o w and
and Its Contents
how well they work in different situations
are all key issues confronting this research
It is certainly not the case that all of human
program. In this section, we give a taste
behavior is ecologically rational, as defined
SITUATING RATIONALITY vn
of how these issues are addressed and dis- the decision mechanisms that form the other
cuss how this approach can be a productive matching half. This can involve a further set
route to understanding the cognitive system of steps, as follows:
in terms of simple process models tuned to
environment structures. 1. Investigating, through simulation, can-
A number of steps are involved in study- didate models of cognitive processes
ing the contents of the adaptive toolbox. built from elementary processing abil-
First, after identifying a particular eco- ities such as search and recognition; to
logically important decision domain, we achieve this, a model selection criterion
must determine the structure of informa- is required (e.g., performance criteria
tion available to people in that domain. As such as predictive accuracy, frugality of
Shepard (2001) indicated, this involves dis- information use). These yardsticks set
covering the "general properties that char- the scene for comparisons with other
acterize the environments in which organ- models.
isms with advanced visual and locomotor 2. Identifying if and when these heuris-
capabilities are likely to survive and repro- tics perform well in certain environ-
duce" (p. 581) - these might include power ments, and what the characteristics of
laws governing scale invariance (Bak, 1996; these environments are, often using ana-
Chater & Brown, 1999) or costs of time and lytic methods. Is it possible to give pre-
cise environment-structure conditions
energy in seeking information (Todd, 2001).
for good or poor performance of the
Shepard (1987) considers only the longest-
heuristics? Do these conditions match
applying physical laws as stable parts of the
those of typical environments inhabited
environment, avoiding discussion of the bio-
by humans?
logical and social realms that he feels have
not been around as long and so will not have 3. With an understanding of how the
exerted as much pressure on our and other model and the environment (or task)
animals' evolved cognition. However, we structure match, carrying out empirical
have certainly evolved adaptive responses to studies to see if humans use these pro-
cesses in appropriate situations.
these realms of challenges as well, and so we
should extend the study of environmentally
matched decision heuristics to biological and The use of elementary processing abili-
social domains (as is done within evolution- ties to guide the construction of candidate
ary psychology; e.g., Barkow, Cosmides, & models reflects a commitment to bottom-up
Tooby, 1992; Buss, 2005). This means we design. One consequence of this approach is
should look for environmental-information that it leads to simple and testable models
regularities that may be internalized to guide with few parameters and therefore makes
our cognition when situated in different for a more transparent relation between the-
evolutionarily important domains, such as ory and data. Another consequence, which
predator risk (e.g., Barrett, 2005), knowledge affects a core concern for the study of
of infection and disease transmission (e.g., ecological rationality, is that the resultant
Rozin & Fallon, 1987), understanding genetic cognitive models, by virtue of their sim-
dynamics (e.g., kin selection; Hamilton, plicity and close reliance on fundamental
1996), and social interactions of various processing abilities, are more likely to be
types (e.g., on the dynamics of signaling cognitively plausible. This approach adopts
between agents with conflicting interests, the view that functioning cognitive models
see Zahavi & Zahavi, 1997; on mate choice, can be built with nontrivial consequences
social exchange, and dominance hierarchies, without needing to be monolithic, gener-
see Buss, 2005). ally applicable, and computationally com-
With these characteristic environment plex. In short, robust cognitive processing
structures in mind as one half of Simon's is achieved with simple and ecologically
scissors, we can look more effectively for targeted mental heuristics. The concept of
328 HENRY BRIGHTON AND PETER M. TODD

ecological rationality and the adaptive tool- recognized object as scoring higher on th
box, in some respects, is close in spirit to criterion. For example, given the names of
Anderson's rational analysis, where a con- two tennis players, the recognition heuris-
sideration of the structure of the environ- tic simplifies the task of deciding which of
ment constrains the development of cogni- these two tennis players is most likely to
tive models, and a focus on the plausibility win the next Grand Slam tournament' if
of the cognitive models then steers future we only recognize one of the players and
development (Anderson, 1990; Oaksford & not the other, then the recognition heuristic
Chater, 1998). However, rational analysis, tells us to pick the player we have heard of
in contrast to the approach explored here, (Pachur 8c Biele, 2007). Similarly, given the
places less of an emphasis on bottom-up task of choosing which of two cities has a
design. One consequence of this difference higher population, the recognition heuristic
is that the adaptive toolbox leads to a con- tells us to pick the city we have heard of over
sideration of multiple simple models rather the one we have not (Goldstein & Gigeren-
than fewer, more complex models. zer, 1999, 2002]. Clearly, the appropriate use
What is in the adaptive toolbox? Several of this heuristic depends on (a) applicabil-
classes of simple heuristics for making differ- ity, because to apply the recognition heuris-
ent types of decisions in a variety of domains tic certain conditions must be met, and (b)
have been investigated (see, e.g., Gigerenzer validity, because the ability to apply the
et al., 1999; Kahneman et al., 1982; Payne, heuristic does not necessarily imply that it
Bettman, & Johnson, 1993; Simon, 1990), will lead to accurate inferences. Specifically,
including ignorance-based heuristics that the recognition heuristic is applicable only
make decisions based on a systematic lack when the decision maker has an intermedi-
of information, one-reason heuristics that ate amount of (recognition) knowledge, not
make a choice as soon as a single reason is complete knowledge or complete ignorance
found on which to base that choice, elim- (which would render the recognition heuris-
ination heuristics that whittle down a set tic unusable). A n d this heuristic is only valid
of choices using as few pieces of informa- when the partial recognition knowledge is
tion as possible until a single choice is deter- systematic; that is, correlated with the crite-
mined, and satisficing heuristics that search rion on which the decision is being made -
through a sequence of options until a good- for example, given that winning tennis play-
enough possibility is found. Other tools are ers are talked about in person and in media
also present, and more await discovery. Here more than losing ones, more people will rec-
we present three examples of the heuristic ognize the best players, meaning that recog-
tools in the toolbox. nition is correlated with past success, and
hence, presumably, with future success as
well. Both these conditions place restrictions
3.1. Paired Comparison Using the on the kinds of environments in which the
Recognition Heuristic recognition heuristic will perform well, and
defining such environments and determin-
The capacity for recognition is common
ing how the heuristic operates in them are
to many species. The most basic cogni-
precisely the sorts of questions addressed
tive heuristic we will focus on exploits
and explored by the study of ecological
this capacity to make inductive inferences.
rationality.
Given the task of deciding which of two
objects in the world scores higher on some Using simple heuristics can also lead
criterion of interest, the recognition heuris- to surprising outcomes, which the eco-
tic can provide a quick and robust decision logical rationality framework can predict
procedure by exploiting a lack of knowl- and explain. For example, when knowledge
edge. If one of the objects being considered about and recognition of the objects in the
is recognized and the other is not, then the environment (e.g., cities) is positively cor-
recognition heuristic tells us to judge the related with the criterion of interest (e.g.,
situating rationality

population), then the recognition heuristic representing features of objects encountered


can lead an individual with less knowledge in the world:
to make more reliable decisions than a per-
son with more knowledge. This less-is-more 1. Search rules, which define how informa-
effect has been confirmed in simulations tion in the form of cues is searched for.
and demonstrated in experiments involving For example, one possible search rule
individuals (Goldstein & Gigerenzer, 1999, is to look through cues in an order that
2002) and groups of subjects (Reimer & reflects how useful these cues have been
Katsikopoulos, 2004). This example is strik- in the past.
ing because it shows how a simple mech- 2. Stopping rules, which define when cue
anism built on a basic cognitive capacity, search is to be terminated. For example,
here recognition memory, when used in given the task of comparing two objects
the right environmental setting, can enable in terms of their cue values, search can
the cognitive system to exploit environmen- be terminated when a stopping crite-
tal structure and subsequently make good rion of different cue values for the two
decisions with little information or pro- objects is met.
cessing. 3. Decision rules, which define how the
information found by the first two
building blocks is used to make a deci-
3.2. Paired Comparisons Using Take
sion. For example, given information
the Best about a cue that differs in value for two
If only one object in a paired compari- objects, the object with the higher cue
son task is recognized, then there is littie value could be chosen.
choice but to apply the recognition heuris-
tic. But when both objects are recognized, Take the Best is a simple heuristic built
and knowledge of several cues about each from three such budding blocks where (a)
object is available to aid the decision, then cues are searched in order of their ecologi-
many possible decision processes exist. For cal validity, (b) search stops at the first dis-
example, the paired comparison task is a criminating cue (i.e., the first cue that has
special case of the general task of learn- a different value for each object, and hence
ing to categorize from labeled examples, discriminates between the two objects), and
which is explored thoroughly in machine- (c) the object selected is the one indicated
learning research (Mitchell, 1997). In that by the discriminating cue. Ecological valid-
field, a litany of potential processes exist, ity is a property of a cue, which indicates
typically complex algorithms designed from how frequently in the past the discrimi-
an engineering perspective to approximate nating cue picked out the object with the
a general solution to the problem of learn- higher criterion value. (Discrimination rate
ing from examples, which leads these meth- is another important property of cues, indi-
ods to veer from considerations of cognitive cating how often a given cue discriminates
plausibility. In contrast, the study of ecolog- between pairs of objects in some environ-
ical rationality from the perspective of the ment.) For example, Take the Best could
adaptive toolbox takes the issues of cogni- decide which of two tennis players is more
tive plausibility and the specific nature of likely to win an upcoming competition by
the task as fundamental. These emphases first considering the most valid cue, say, "Has
are reflected in a bottom-up approach in this player won a Grand Slam competition in
which simple processes are built from ele- the past?" If this cue discriminates - that is, it
mentary building blocks chosen to match a is true for one player and not the other - then
particular task environment. In particular, Take the Best will stop information search
as mentioned earlier, Gigerenzer and col- and select the previous-winning player over
leagues (1999) have explored the following the other. If the first cue does not discrim-
types of building blocks for processing cues inate, then further cues are considered in
2 8 7 henry b r i g h t o n a n d p e t e r m . t o d d

order of ecological validity until one is found consuming to acquire (Broder, 2000; Broder
that does discriminate and is then used by & Schiffer, 2003; Newell & Shanks, 20o,.
itself to determine the decision. Rieskamp & Hoffrage, 1999). People || P
Unlike many other models of decision make socially and culturally influenced deci
making, which typically take all cues into sions based on a single reason through imi.
consideration and combine them somehow tation (e.g., in food choice; Ariely & Levay
to yield a decision, Take the Best is fru- 2000), norm following, and employing pro.
gal in its use of information. The decision tected values (e.g., moral codes that admit
is made only on the basis of the first dis- no compromise, such as never taking an
criminating cue, and all other information is action that results in human death; see Tan-
ignored. In this sense, Take the Best employs ner & Medin, 2004).
one-reason decision making. But does Take
the Best suffer, in terms of performance, by 3.3. Estimation Using QuickEst
ignoring so much of the available informa-
tion? No - Take the Best often performs just Not all choices in life are presented to us
as well as other less frugal and more compu- as convenient pairs of options, of course
tationally intensive models such as multiple Often we must choose between several
linear regression, even though it uses only alternatives, such as which restaurant to go
a fraction of the available information. But to or which habitat to settle in. In situa-
even more surprising is the fact that in a con- tions where each available cue dimension
siderable number of decision environments has fewer values than the number of avail-
examined so far, Take the Best can outper- able alternatives, one-reason decision mak-
form rival models of decision making when ing will usually not suffice, because a sin-
generalizing to new decisions (Czerlinski gle cue will be unable to distinguish among
et al., 1999). Furthermore, recent work all of the alternatives. For instance, knowing
demonstrates that Take the Best can even whether each of fifteen cities has a river is
beat the key models of inductive inference not enough information to decide which city
used in machine-learning research on con- is most habitable. But this does not doom
nectionist, rule-based, and exemplar-based the fast-and-frugal reasoner to a long pro-
approaches - as long as the environment has cess of cue search and combination in these
a particular information structure (Brighton, situations. Again, a simple stopping rule can
2006; Chater, Oaksford, Nakisa, & Reding- work to limit information search: seek cues
ton, 2003). Thus, this work has shown in (in an order specified by the search rule) only
principle that decision processes built from until enough is known to make a decision.
simple, cognitively plausible building blocks But now a different type of decision rule is
that use little processing and little infor- needed instead of relying on one reason. One
mation in ways that are matched to the way to select a single option from among
task environments in which they are sit- multiple alternatives is to follow the sim-
uated can outperform some of the most ple principle of elimination (Tversky, 1972):
widely used and studied models of induction successive cues are used to eliminate more
that take a domain-general, environment- and more alternatives and thereby reduce
agnostic approach. the set of remaining options, until a single
But in practice, do people use such sim- option can be decided on.
ple, fast-and-frugal heuristics to make deci- The QuickEst heuristic (Hertwig et al.,
sions? A growing body of experimental and 1999) is designed to estimate the values of
empirical work is demonstrating that peo- objects along some criterion while using as
ple do use one-reason decision heuristics little information as possible. The estimates
in appropriately structured environments, are constrained to map onto certain round
such as where cues act individually to sig- numbers (e.g., when estimating city popu-
nal the correct response (Rieskamp & Otto, lation sizes, QuickEst can return values of
2005) or where information is costly or time 1 0 0 , 0 0 0 , 1 5 0 , 0 0 0 , 200,000, 300,000, and other
s i t u a t i n g RATIONALITY

similarly round numbers), so this heuristic pattern applies to cities (Makse, Havlin,
can be seen as choosing one value from sev- & Stanley, 1995), and indeed big cities are
eral possibilities. The elimination-based esti- much less common than small ones. As a
mation process operates like a coal sorter, in consequence, when applied to a data set of
which chunks of coal of various sizes first cities, QuickEst is able to estimate rapidly
roll over a small slit, through which the the small sizes that most of them have.
smallest pieces fall into a bin for fine-grained
coal' the bigger pieces that remain then roll
over a wider slit that captures medium- 4. Rationality in the Real World: From
the Classical to the Ecological
sized pieces of coal into a medium bin; and
finally the biggest chunks roll into a large
The heuristics introduced in the previous
coal bin. In the case of QuickEst applied to
section are tools for making inductive infer-
city population estimates, the coal chunks
ences. Induction is the task of using the past
are cities of different population sizes; the
to predict and make decisions about the
bins are the rounded-number size estimates;
future. Without being able to look into the
and the slots are cues associated with city
future, we can never answer with certainty
size, ordered according to the average size
questions such as, say, which tennis player
of the cities without that cue (e.g., because will next win Wimbledon. We instead have
most small cities do not have a professional to make an inductive inference, a predic-
sports team, this could be one of the first tion about the future, based on observations
cues checked - i.e., one of the first slots and knowledge we have acquired in the past.
that the cities roll past). To estimate a city's Clearly, by using prior experience we can
size, the QuickEst heuristic looks through often make better than chance predictions
the cues or features in order until it comes about future events in the world. This would
to the first one that the city does not pos- not be possible if the world were unstruc-
sess, at which point it stops searching for tured and behaved randomly. Fortunately,
any further information (e.g., if a city pos- most environments we face are highly struc-
sesses the first several features in order but tured, so that principled decision making
lacks a convention center, the city falls into serves us well. But what principles should
that bin and search will stop on that cue). guide our decision making? Many theories
QuickEst then gives the rounded mean cri- take what we will term classical rationality as
terion value associated with the absence of a source of answers. This is to say that for the
that cue as its final estimate (e.g., the mean task of reasoning under uncertainty, clear
size of all entries in the bin for cities without normative principles such as Bayesian infer-
an exposition site). Thus, in effect, QuickEst ence and variants of Occam's razor based on
uses features that are present to eliminate algorithmic information theory tell us what
all smaller criterion categories, and absent the rational course of action is (e.g., Chater,
features to eliminate all larger criterion cat- 1999; Hutter, 2005; Pearl, 1988). Yet humans
egories, so that only one criterion estimate often deviate from the classically rational:
remains. No cue combination is necessary, we make errors in a sometimes-systematic
and no adjustment from further cues is pos- fashion and appear to only partially adhere
sible. to normative ideals. This view of occasion-
QuickEst proves to be fast and frugal, as ally error-prone human behavior is most
well as accurate, in environments character- forcefully argued within the heuristics-and-
ized by a distribution of criterion values in biases tradition, which proposes that peo-
which small values are common and big val- ple rely on a limited number of heuristic
ues are rare (a so-called J-shaped distribu- principles that reduce the complex tasks of
tion, where the J is seen on its side). Such assessing probabilities and predicting values
distributions characterize a variety of natu- to simpler judgmental operations. In gen-
rally occurring phenomena, including many eral, these heuristics are quite useful, but
formed by accretionary growth. This growth
289 henry b r i g h t o n a n d peter m. t o d d

sometimes they lead to severe and system- strengths as weaknesses. Neither humans
atic errors (Tversky, 1972, p. 1124). nor animals uniformly adhere to overarch-
In this section we develop and justify ing principles because, as we will argue, such
why the classical view of rationality, when principles make cognitive demands that can-
adopted as a concept with which to under- not always be met. Furthermore, the gener-
stand human decision making and infer- ality of rational principles is in large part due
ence, fails to capture significant aspects of to abstractions away from specific aspects of
the inference task. We will contrast classi- the task. Sometimes specific considerations
cal rationality with ecological rationality and such as response time, are significant and
argue that the latter offers a far more pro- may outweigh more general considerations
such as predictive accuracy. We suspect that
ductive concept with which to understand
no single and universal measurement can
human decision making, as it bounds ratio-
characterize what is functional for an organ-
nality to the world rather than treats the
ism for all tasks, and in this sense we should
two as fundamentally separate (Todd &
be weary of proposals that collapse the prob-
Gigerenzer, 2003). Thus, the ecological
lem characterizing rational choice down to
approach differs significantly from both clas-
a single yardstick. The concept of ecological
sical rationality and the heuristics-and-biases
rationality accepts the deep problems that
tradition, and it offers what we consider
arise with universal and abstract principles
another way of thinking about rationality:
of rationality and works with them.
There is a third way to look at inference, First of all, an important distinction to
focusing on the psychological and ecolog- consider is that rational principles of infer-
ical rather than on logic and probability ence are normative vehicles for judging
theory. This view questions classical ratio- inductive inferences. As such, they are inert
nality as a universal norm and thereby with respect to how, in processing terms,
questions the very definition of good rea-
organisms should arrive at inferences. Her-
soning on which both the Enlightenment
and heuristics-and-biases views were built. bert Simon (1990, chap. 2) made the dis-
(Gigerenzer Si Goldstein, 1996, p. 651) tinction between substantive and procedural
rationality. Although some formulations of
But in what sense does ecological ratio- rational behavior consider procedural ratio-
nality differ from classical rationality? The nality, rational theories of inductive infer-
apparent strength of rational principles of ence are typically claims about substantive
inference stem from their generality and rationality. Substantive rational principles
their formal justification by way of prob- are yardsticks for judging inferences; they
ability theory, and ultimately information do not tell us, in mechanistic terms, how
theory (Li & Vitânyi, 1997). For example, to arrive at inductive inferences. It is use-
Occam's razor tells us to prefer simpler ful, therefore, to distinguish between the
explanations over complex ones, and this substantive problem of induction and the
principle proves productive when fitting a procedural problem of induction. This dis-
polynomial to a set of data points, choos- tinction is essential when we come to con-
ing between scientific theories, or describ- sider fundamental computational limits that
ing the behavior of human visual percep- make realizing rational norms in process-
tion (Sober, 1975). That such principles hold ing terms often intractable, if not provably
across diverse tasks that are seemingly unre- uncomputable. Note that this problem -
lated in their formulation, their physical the dichotomy between what is rational
characteristics, and importantly, the envi- and what is computationally achievable -
ronmental context, is seen as evidence of extends beyond the particular details of the
their strength. cognitive system. It is an issue for all com-
However, if our concern is the study of putational processes carrying out inductive
human and animal cognition, then there inferences. We mention the processing issue
are good reasons to view these apparent here because, if what is deemed rational is
situating rationality
f u n d a m e n t a l l y unobtainable by organisms,
against others. By considering the problem
of procedural rationality, we are taking one
then p e r h a p s our motives for adopting such
a concept of rationality should be ques- step toward situating the task of human
tioned. decision making. Constraints on realization
Another distinction we will draw con- can transform the nature of the problem,
trasts the substantive problem of induc- or, as Herbert Simon (1990) put it: "at each
tion and the cognitive-ecological problem of step toward realism, the problem gradu-
induction. This distinction will lead us to ally changes from choosing the right course
consider how behaving rationally in the of action (substantive rationality) to find-
classical sense (the substantive problem) ing a way of calculating, very approximately,
and behaving adaptively (a species-specific where a good choice of action lies (procedu-
cognitive-ecological problem) are not neces- ral rationality)" (pp. 26-27). In stressing this
sarily the same endeavor. For instance, the difference between substantive and proce-
inference suggested by the most probable dural rationality in this way, we do not want
prediction (and therefore the most rational give the impression that substantive theo-
one) may require expending considerable ries of rationality are wrong. The issue is
time, memory, and processing resources how appropriately a given notion of rational-
compared with an inference arrived at ity fits the question at hand. Simon's point,
quickly and on the basis of a cognitively and the point we are developing here, is
undemanding decision process requiring that, for the task of understanding cogni-
minimal information; moreover, the latter tion, procedural rationality is more appro-
may be only marginally inferior in proba- priate than substantive rationality. Again,
bilistic terms. Adaptive behavior, that which this does not imply that substantive theo-
fits the functional requirements of an organ- ries of rationality, such as Bayesianism, are
ism, is unlikely to be characterized using the wrong tool for studying cognition, but
probability theory and logic given that "peo- rather that such principles are inherently
ple satisfice - look for good enough solu- limited because they neglect the fact that
tions - instead of hopelessly searching for organisms are constrained in their ability to
the best" (Simon, 1990, p. 17). Put differ- process information.
ently, the payoff function with which we Some tasks, because of their inherent dif-
measure the efficacy of a decision maker ficulty, lack a clear notion of substantive
is not simply how accurate inferences are; rationality. For example, choosing which of
it also must consider ecological factors that two candidate moves in chess is most likely
take into account the structure of the task, to lead to a win can, in the general case, be
the criticality of response time, and factors only an estimate. Unsurprisingly, this inher-
contributing to cognitive effort. Now, in this ent difficulty makes the procedural prob-
section the question we ask is, Does one lem of playing chess even harder. In other
rationality fit all tasks? words, if we lack a clear formulation of ratio-
nal choice in the first place, then we can-
not expect that procedural solutions con-
4.1. Living Up to Expectation: From
form to this rational expectation. Although
Substantive to Procedural Rationality
chess is a supremely unenlightening exam-
Substantive rationality refers to rational prin- ple of human inference that, at best, may
ciples such as Bayesian inference or Occam's tell us about the fringes of human cogni-
razor. Procedural rationality, in contrast, tion (Chomsky, 2000, p. 161), there are many
considers what can be accomplished when other common human decisions that are
one takes into account the processing steps similarly difficult - or impossible - to ratio-
required to arrive at an inference. Once an nally analyze fully, such as deciding which of
inference has been made, the role of sub- two potential mates to woo (Gigerenzer &
stantive rationality is clear: it provides a cri- Todd, 1999). Furthermore, there are tasks
terion with which to judge this inference for which we do have a clear notion of
291 henry b r i g h t o n a n d peter m. t o d d

substantive rationality, yet procedural ratio- another. Given a series of observations


nality still forces us to rethink what is achiev- these criteria tell us, for any two candidate
able firom the perspective of the organism. category explanations, which is the "best"
This is the issue we will focus on. category description. Stepping back from
Consider the modem formulation of any specific solutions that the cognitive sys-
Occam's razor: hypotheses that recode tem may employ, it will prove useful to con-
observations in such a way to minimize sider first the more general class of computa-
encoding length should be chosen over oth- tional procedures for performing inductive
ers (Griinwald, 2005; Hutter, 2005; Li & inferences. Machine learning is the study
Vitinyi, 1997; Rissanen, 1989). Such a for- of procedural solutions to inference prob-
mulation has been proposed as a unifying lems (Mitchell, 1997), and therefore offers
principle of the cognitive system (Chater 8c a useful source of insight into the rela-
Vitinyi, 2003; see also Feldman, 2003) and tionship between substantive and procedu-
"suggests a possible (although of course par- ral rationality (which is sometimes termed
tial) account of the remarkable success of approximate rationality within artificial intel-
the cognitive system in prediction, under- ligence; see Russell 8c Norvig, 1995). |j|e
standing, and acting in an uncertain and economic and psychological research, artifi-
complex environment: that cognitive pro- cial intelligence and, in particular, machine
cesses search for simplicity" (Chater, 1999, learning often appeal to classical notions of
p. 283). Yet paradoxically, adherence to rational behavior (Goodie, Ortmann, Davis
simplicity principles can be so complex in Bullock, 8c Werner, 1999). For example,
processing terms that it "will not be possible using algorithmic information theory to fix
in general" (Chater, 1999, p. 283). As another a universal (i.e., problem independent,
example of the substantive-procedural gap, parameterless, and rationally motivated by
in both perception and action it is pro- way of Occam's razor) prior probabil-
posed that a "striking observation... is the ity distribution on the hypothesis space
myriad ways in which human observers (Solomonoff, 1964), Bayesian-inspired mod-
act as optimal Bayesian observers" (Knill 8c els of inductive reasoning have led some to
Pouget, 2004, p. 712). Once again, however, explore "a theory for rational agents act-
it is acknowledged that, "owing to the com- ing optimally in any environment" (Hutter,
plexity of the task, unconstrained Bayesian 2005, p. 24). Unfortunately, when realized
inference is not a viable solution for com- in procedural terms, such theories partly
putation in the brain" (Knill & Pouget, 2004, assume the "availability of unlimited com-
p. 718). Here we see the struggle between putational resources" (Hutter, 2005, p. v).
the desire to find concise universal laws of Even with extremely liberal constraints on
rational behavior and the processing diffi- resources, universally applicable laws of
culties that accompany these principles. To rationality, in processing terms, are difficult
see why this problem occurs, and how the or even impossible to achieve.
concept of ecological rationality can help In practice, machine-learning research
to clarify issues, we will consider the cog- places more conservative bounds on what
nitive task of categorization. Categorization is considered practical by often narrowing
requires making inductive inferences, it is a its interests to the class of computation-
ubiquitous ability of humans and other ani- ally tractable algorithms. Computationally
mals, and it offers a useful example for illus- tractable algorithms are those that place
trating the dichotomy between procedural computational demands on time and stor-
and substantive rationality. age space resources that grow as polynomial
For the categorization task, Bayesian function of the size of the problem (e.g.,
inference and modern castings of Occam's sorting a series of n numbers into ascend-
razor provide well-defined and precise ing order is deemed tractable because it can
rational criteria with which to compare be achieved by an algorithm requiring time
one potential category judgment against and space polynomial in n). Under these
situating rationality

constraints, a widespread realization, and well across domains. Induction may be the
arguably an axiom within machine learn- name of the game, but constraints are the
ing is that procedural adherence to rational rules that we play by. (Elman, 2003, from
ms.)
eXpectation breaks down. One useful con-
cept in thinking about ad hoc adherence to
the rational ideal is inductive bias, which Because uniform adherence to a norma-
refers to any basis on which one explana- tive criterion is taken as a goal, alleviating
tion is chosen over another, beyond simple the discrepancy between this goal and what
adherence to the observations (Gordon & can be achieved in practice can partially
Desjardins, 1995; Mitchell, 1997).1 An appro- be overcome through the selective choice
priately formalized Occam's-razor principle of learning algorithms, dependent on the
is a bias, for example, but typically bias task structure. For example, given knowl-
occurs as a result of restrictions on the rep- edge of the tasks for which some learning
resentational power of the hypothesis space algorithm A performs better any other algo-
(the set of explanations the algorithm can rithm, then A could be chosen over all oth-
consider] and how thoroughly the hypoth- ers when such a task is encountered. This
esis space can be searched (the manner in problem is known as the selective superior-
which the search for the optimal hypothesis ity problem. It remains largely unexplored,
is approximated). and only limited practical progress has been
The important point here is that the made in addressing it (e.g., Kalousis, Gama,
inductive bias of an algorithm typically & Hilario, 2004). Unfortunately, for anything
reflects concrete issues of realization such other than trivial tasks, machine learning
as the particular characteristics and assump- tells us that there is a gap between sub-
tions imposed by the implementation of stantive and procedural rationality. This gap
the algorithm (e.g., the nature of hypothe- exists because tractable algorithms tend to
sis space) rather than a rationally motivated focus their performance on some problems
normative bias, such as Occam's razor. Con- at the expense of others. Crucially, most
sequendy, and as a result of tractability and tasks are not trivial in the sense we mean
computability constraints, the procedural here and require the expenditure of con-
problem of induction has a different charac- siderable computational effort to find good,
ter from that suggested by the rational prob- let alone optimal, solutions. For example,
lem. The combination of considering non- the apparently trivial task of recognizing a
trivial tasks in conjunction with tractability face is extremely difficult from a computa-
constraints limits researchers to a vaguer tional standpoint: a full integration of the
adherence to rational expectations, where many facial properties that need to be con-
algorithms "should process the finite sample sidered is computationally intractable. In the
to obtain a hypothesis with good general- study of artificial intelligence, which seeks
ization ability under a reasonably large set engineering solutions for tasks like these,
of circumstances" (Kearns, 1999, p. 159). For optimal solutions are almost always unob-
machine learning, this breakdown in adher- tainable (for discussion, see Reddy, 1988).
ence to the rational, or optimal, outcome is Likewise, the study of cognition rarely
simply a well-established fact. Algorithmic reduces to the study of computationally triv-
solutions are, to varying degrees, focused ial problems.
rather than general, and their performance This brief discussion of machine learning
is adequate rather than normative: provides us with some conceptual tools with
which to consider the cognitive problem.
The cognitive problem of induction is a par-
Induction is not unbridled or uncon-
ticular instance of the procedural problem
strained. Indeed, decades of work in
machine learning makes abundantly clear of achieving rationality, and one that is sub-
that there is no such thing as a general pur- ject to hard biological/cognitive constraints
pose learning algorithm that works equally rather than the more abstract notion of
340
henry b r i g h t o n a n d peter m. t o d d

computational tractability encountered pre- tional structures present in the environment


viously. As for machine learning's algorith- (Hertwig & Todd, 2003; Todd, Billari, &
mic rationality problem, the general human Simao, 2005). In this sense, the cognitive sys-
cognitive problem is also broken down into tem does pull a neat trick: its limitations can
tasks with particular characteristics. For become enablers once we consider the eco-
instance, tasks spanning low-level aspects or logical side of problem.
the visual system and high-level tasks such Until now we have focused on internal
as concept learning and categorization are aspects of the organism. The previous sec-
commonly viewed as inductive tasks (e.g., tion highlighted how, by coupling limita-
Chater & VitSnyi, 2003; Sober, 1975). How- tions in cognitive structure to environment
ever, unlike a general constraint such as structure, simple mechanisms can match
computational tractability, these cognitive or exceed the performance of more com-
tasks are likely to work within very different plex mechanisms. For instance, the simplic-
and more stringent constraints, such as the ity of Take the Best can be interpreted as
physical limitations of the underlying bio- an inability to consider intercue correlations
logical machinery; constraints imposed by because Take the Best is restricted to act-
other cognitive systems also using resources ing on conditionally independent ecological
in the mind; and limits on attention, working cue measurements. For some environments
memory, and the like. Thus, different cog- this inability actually acts as an enabler as
nitive tasks are likely to yield to processing conditional information can be highly mis-
solutions of different forms. leading and unstable. In fact, among twenty
natural environments tested by Brighton
4.2. Situating Decision Making: (2005), over half reveal this property within
Confronting the Cognitive-Ecological the paired comparison task. In the same
Problem study, these characteristics of the environ-
ment posed serious problems for five classic
Processing makes demands on computa- machine-learning algorithms because they
tional resources. Placing constraints on these all carry out complex computations that
resources limits the degree to which ratio- consider conditional cue dependencies. As a
nal expectations can be met, and in partic- result of their reliance on noisy cue relation-
ular, processes tend to be focused on some ships, they performed worse than Take the
instances of the task with respect to their Best. Constraints that act as enablers illus-
ability to adhere to the demands set by sub- trate how the adaptive-toolbox metaphor
stantive rationality. Specific kinds of con- exploits the strengths of simplicity. This
straint impose specific kinds of focus and, trick is worth considering in more depth.
as Simon argued (1990, 1996), a full consid- For a specific task, the environment can
eration of cognitive limitations leads us to be viewed as set of structures to be exploited
consider boundedly rational processes. On by multiple simple processes. This perspec-
the one hand, constraints beyond those of an tive differs from the more traditional view,
abstract computational nature would appear where a single task is often seen in terms of
to limit even further the degree to which a single-process solution that is assumed to
rational expectations are likely to be met, possess a general competence on a diverse
and, as a result, the human cognitive system range of environmental structures. Decom-
needs to pull a neat trick if it is to measure posing the problem space into structurally
up to the demands of rationality under these distinct subproblems, according to this view,
terms. On the other hand, we will argue is not the principle objective because we
that there are good reasons to view cognitive assume the competence of a single pro-
limitations not as barriers but as enablers of cess to be sufficient for all relevant prob-
robust inference. Limitations can be viewed lems. For example, the paired comparison
as adaptive constraints in the sense that task addressed by the Take the Best heuris-
they may lead an agent to exploit informa- tic can be viewed as a special case of the
SITUATING RATIONALITY
337

te g 0 rization task. Within this task, Take E in comparison to some other mechanism
the Best is one process among several possi- M' when M outperforms M' on some cri-
ble candidates tuned to particular instances terion, or currency, of comparison. There
of this problem. In contrast, both in machine are two components to statements such as
learning and in psychological modeling, the these. First, such statements are compara-
categorization task is often v i e w e d from the tive rather than absolute: heuristics must
perspective of a single process, applied inde- be judged in comparison to other mod-
pendently of the precise nature of the task els. For example, Take the Best is ecologi-
environment. For example, P R O B E X is pre- cally rational compared to other models of
sented as "a model of probabilistic inference inference (Brighton, 2006; Czerlinski et al.,
and probability judgments based on generic 1999), and the recognition heuristic is eco-
knowledge" (Juslin & Persson, 2002, p. 563), logically rational compared to those models
yet such a claim cannot be sustained in any that do not consider, and therefore cannot
meaningful sense, as the inductive bias of exploit, recognition information (Goldstein
PROBEX, like any other process, will lead & Gigerenzer, 2002). Second, statements
to good performance on some instances of about the ecological rationality of a heuris-
the problem at the expense of others. Such tic appeal to some criterion of comparison.
single-process approaches often neglect the For instance, models of inference are often
structure of the environment, and therefore compared using cross-validation, which con-
the models are general only in the sense that siders the criterion of zero-one loss pre-
no clear understanding of their focus exists. dictive accuracy (e.g., Browne, 2000), or
using a criterion that measures the degree
Simple heuristics can w o r k extremely
to which a heuristic compresses the obser-
well because they are focused and tailor
vations (Griinwald, 2005).
their inductive bias to match specific infor-
mation structures in the environment. To For some, performance measures such as
support this view, our experiments show these call into question the concept of eco-
that in comparisons across twenty different logical rationality due to an ultimate appeal
natural environments, T a k e the Best more to rational criteria, which in the final analy-
often than not outperforms all competitors sis are used to justify and explain the perfor-
drawn from a collection of neural networks, mance of heuristics (Chater et al., 2003). But
exemplar models, and decision-tree induc- this argument misses a fundamental dimen-
tion models (Brighton, 2006). sion of the concept of ecological rationality
These simulation results strengthen the that we mentioned briefly at the start if this
claim that, when faced with a varied set of section. Given some criterion, the rational
environments, one approach toward achiev- course of action is defined as the one that
ing adaptive behavior is to rely on an maximizes the criterion. Cross-validation
adaptive toolbox, from which ecologically tells us to prefer the model that yields the
rational heuristics are selected contingent highest predictive accuracy, and Occam's
on the task and the ecological context. razor tells us to prefer the model that com-
This notion of contingent application is the presses the observations most succincdy.
crucial difference between the adaptive- Both these rational criteria consider only a
toolbox metaphor and the more widespread single perspective, which we might dub "raw
approach of focusing on a single general- inductive performance," as they constitute
purpose processing system. Thus, the per- perhaps the most basic and assumption-free
formance of heuristics must always be con- rational criterion. For this reason their use is
sidered conditional on the task, and in the widespread in the comparison of machine-
study of adaptive behavior, understanding learning algorithms (Kearns, Mansour, Ng,
environmental context is just as important as & Ron, 1997} and between models of cog-
understanding processing mechanisms. To nition (Pitt, Myung, & Zhang, 2002). How-
be more precise, we say that a mechanism ever, these criteria ignore crucial aspects of
M is ecologically rational in environment the ecological problem. Mechanisms that
295 henry b r i g h t o n a n d peter m. t o d d

blindly maximize the rational criteria may gent human behavior as engaged, socially
ignore marginally less predictive solutions and materially embodied activity, arising
that can be found using, for example, less within the specific concrete details of par-
information search and fewer processing ticular (natural) settings, rather than as an
steps. Thus, it is apparent that general and abstract, detached, general-purpose process
universal measures can abstract the prob- of logical or formal ratiocination" (Smith
lem away from significant factors influenc- 1999, p. 769). As we argued in the previ-
ing the adaptive function of the mechanism. ous section, the concept of ecological ratio-
Put differently, the appropriate payoff func- nality is called for precisely because formal
tion with which to assess human decision and generally applicable visions of rational
making is likely to be both multidimensional behavior fail to consider significant aspects
and task specific. Rational criteria, because of human decision making. These aspects
of their generality, necessarily sidestep this range from the algorithmic constraints on
ecological aspect of the problem. Although what can plausibly be achieved by the cog-
rational criteria widely used to judge induc- nitive system to ecological considerations
tive performance are often also used to com-
that affect the potential difference between
pare heuristics, their use in statements about
adaptive (and ecologically rational) deci-
ecological rationality is more a matter of
sions and classically rational decisions. Thus,
practical factors than a reflection of con-
the concept of ecological rationality bears
ceptual necessity. For this reason, heuristics
some of the hallmarks that characterize sit-
are often additionally compared using multi-
ple criteria, such as cross-validation and fru- uated approaches.
gality of information use (Czerlinski et al., At this point we lay down what we take
1999). Although substantive theories of to be some key characteristic features of
rationality could, in principle, be elaborated situated approaches to studying cognition
to consider further costs and more complex and how they apply to ecological rationality.
payoff functions, issues of processing must, The dimensions we consider are taken from
at some point, be considered. In the limit, Smith's (1999) characterization of situated
such a refined notion of substantive ratio- approaches in terms of six key dimensions:
nality could become procedural rationality, located, concrete, engaged, specific, embod-
the approach that we are advocating here. ied, and social.
Thus, there are varying degrees of abstrac-
tion when formulating a rational theory, and 4.4. Located
ecological rationality is a form of rationality
The significance of being located arises
tailored to understanding cognitive process-
when we adopt the view that "context-
ing in its ecological context.
dependence is a central and enabling fea-
ture of human endeavor" (Smith, 1999,
p. 769). Using Simon's metaphor of the scis-
4.3. Ecological Rationality as a Form
sors, context dependence is the environ-
of Situated Cognition
mental blade. In particular, Simon (1956)
Ecological rationality depends on intelli- makes the point that "we might hope to
gent agents deploying their various deci- discover, by a careful examination of some
sion strategies in particular situations, sen- of the fundamental structural characteristics
sitive to the structure of the environment of the environment, some further clues as
in which they are embedded. This sounds to the nature of the approximating mech-
like cognition situated in specific settings - anisms used in decision making" (p. 130).
but can we say more precisely in what way As we have shown, characteristics of the
the study of ecological rationality is related environment indeed represent a central and
to the situated movement in cognitive sci- enabling feature when we consider their role
ence? In broad terms, and to varying degrees, in supporting cognitively simple heuristics.
situated-cognition approaches view "intelli- For example, some environmental contexts
situating rationality

"enable" frugality in information use: in non-


4,6. Engaged
coinpensatory environments, where the best
cues outweigh the combined strength of all The property of engagement considers how
other cues, there is no reason to consider "ongoing interaction with the surround-
any but the first discriminating cue found,
ing environment is recognized as primary"
which is just the strategy adopted by lexi- (Smith, 1999, p. 769). Because heuristics are
cographic decision strategies like Take the specialized - tuned to specific environmen-
Best. It is the precise context that the envi- tal contexts - the adjustment of the decision
ronment presents that provides the trac- mechanism contingent on the structure of
tion enabling simple cognitive heuristics to the task environment demands that a deci-
perform so well. In these terms, location sion maker consider the inference task as an
ongoing rather than a static activity. Further-
is everything when considering ecological
more, because most of the heuristics in the
rationality. Without the enabling aspects of
adaptive toolbox involve search for informa-
each precise context, ecological rationality
tion in the environment, these mechanisms
cannot get off the ground.
are of necessity engaged in a process of envi-
ronmental interaction. This can happen on
4,5. Concrete
a moment-to-moment basis, as when a con-
The issue of concreteness refers to the view sumer deciding which good to buy checks
that "constraints of realization and circum- the packaging for information until he or
stance are viewed as of the utmost impor- she finds enough to make a choice, or when
tance" (Smith, 1999, p. 769). Constraints on a fielder trying to catch a ball adjusts her
realization, again using Simon's metaphor running speed so as to maintain a constant
of the scissors, correspond to the cognitive gaze angle (McLeod & Dienes, 1996), or at
blade. There are two degrees of concrete- longer time spans, as when a person encoun-
ness we have considered. First, at a purely tering different decision tasks or environ-
computational level, there are hard con- ments must choose or adapt the decision
straints on what can be achieved by com- mechanism he or she is using. Precisely how
putationally tractable processes (e.g., prob- decision makers react to environments is
lems that cannot be solved in polynomial the subject of ongoing research. For exam-
time). Second, moving f r o m an abstract con- ple, Todd and Dieckmann (2005) describe
sideration of issues of computability to the a process by which individuals may learn
more concrete issue of cognitive limitations, an order in which to use cues with Take
there are constraints arising f r o m the cog- the Best, and they show how this learned
nitive system as a biologically realized com- order itself influences the decisions made
puting device that further limit w h a t can be and the subsequent learning that an indi-
achieved. The vagaries of the human m e m - vidual can perform. Strong path dependen-
ory system, for example, f o r m a set of cog- cies - a hallmark of an engaged process -
emerge in the application of this learning
nitive constraints that influence h o w infor-
mechanism as it is intertwined with ongo-
mation is processed. Y e t constraints can also
ing decision making. Rieskamp and Otto
be important because they can enable some
(2005), in contrast, explore the changing
capabilities - continuing the m e m o r y exam-
use of particular fixed, simple heuristics in
ple, the role of forgetting can be seen as an
a reinforcement-leaming scenario. Here, a
enabler for heuristic inference, as it affects
balance between exploration and exploita-
the capacity for name recognition and there-
tion is struck by integrating feedback from
fore the ability to use the recognition heuris-
the decision-making process, which in turn
tic (Schooler & Hertwig, 2005). In a nutshell,
allows the agent to learn when to apply
the details of the concrete realization of
which strategy. This line of research is
cognitive mechanisms matter because cer-
particularly promising, as there are poten-
tain constraints enable the exploitation of
tial connections with other psychological
context.
HENRY BRIGHTON AND PETER M. TODD

research into strategy selection (Erev & Bar- dent on both the specific nature of the task
ron. 2005; Gonzalez, Lerch, & Lebiere, 2003) and the particularities of the individual cog-
and with attempts within machine learning nitive system.
to use human problem solving as inspiration
for systems that learn to learn, where the
4.8. Embodied
relationship between multiple tasks is con-
sidered an enabling feature of human induc- The importance of embodiment refers to the
tive performance (Thrun & Pratt, 1998). fact that "material aspects of agents' bodies
are taken to be both pragmatically and theo-
retically significant" (Smith, 1999, p. 769]. In
4.7. Specific other words, the particular physical instan-
Considerations of specificity refer to the fact tiation of the agent's body is taken to have
that "what people do is seen as varying, a strong impact on how the problem is both
dramatically, depending on contingent facts conceived of and solved. The gaze heuris-
about their circumstances" (Smith, 1999, tic for ball catching mentioned earlier, for
p. 769). For ecologically rational infer- example, is a process that relies on a par-
ence, the particular circumstances a decision ticular morphology: an eye and a bipedal
maker faces are paramount. The discussion locomotion system. Embodiment is impor-
earlier of the importance of being located tant, as an agent with a different morpholog-
highlights how circumstance can act as an ical design may solve the problem of catch-
enabling feature in decision making. We ing the ball using quite different processes:
take specificity to capture a slighdy different being equipped with wings and echolo-
set of contingencies of the tasks that people cation would open up entirely different
face, such as are evident from experimental ball-catching solutions. Ecological rational-
studies of when people use heuristics. For ity has, to date, been studied in an embodied
example, circumstances in which subjects form mostly in the field of behavior-based
are required to act under time pressure show robotics (e.g., Brooks, 1991; for a discus-
how the choice of decision strategy changes sion, see Goodie et al., 1999), where simple
as a result, with subjects showing a strong heuristics are used to help physically embod-
tendency to prefer simple sequential, cue- ied agents navigate through environments
based decision mechanisms (Edland, 1994; and solve different (usually rather simple)
Payne et al., 1993). The costs of information tasks. Despite these low-level investigations
search also have a strong bearing on which of embodied ecological rationality so far, we
strategy is used. For instance, when subjects nevertheless take issues of embodiment to
are required to search for information from have significant impact on high-level cogni-
memory, rather than on screen, they are tion. In particular, these issues are important
far more likely to use fast-and-frugal deci- for considering the sensory and propriocep-
sion strategies like Take the Best (Broder & tive origins of the cues going into the deci-
Shiffer, 2003). If subjects are required to esti- sion process, as well as the bodily and motor-
mate the values of associated with different system consequences of the decisions being
choices, rather than simply make a choice, made.
different decision strategies are, again, likely
to be used (Westenberg & Koele, 1992).
These studies not only highlight how sub- 4.9. Social
tleties in the specific nature of the task (in
Being social means "being located in hu-
contrast to the statistical structure of the
manly constructed settings among human
environment) can lead to quite different
communities" (Smith, 1999, p. 769). In
cognitive tools being used but also reveal
studying ecological rationality, we must
that individual differences are often at play.
acknowledge that a significant part of envi-
Information processing, from the perspec-
ronment structure will often be made up
tive of the adaptive toolbox, is highly depen-
of other individuals and the results of
situating rationality

their actions, whether in choosing a mate but we do not see this as the key issue at
(Todd et al., 2005)1, selecting a parking stake in this discussion. In short, we should
space (Hutchinson, Fanselow, & Todd, sound a note of caution. As Clancey (1997,
forthcoming), negotiating a fair division p. 345) points out, it is often tempting and all
of resources (Takezawa, 2004), reaching a too easy to present an either-or message. In
group decision (Reimer & Hoffrage, 2005; our case, this would amount to claiming that
Reimer & Katsikopoulos, 2004), deciding existing principles of rationality are irrele-
how to communicate important information vant to the study of human cognition. How-
(Kurzenhauser & Hoffrage, 2002), and many ever, this is not the point we wish to make.
other situations. T h e social rationality called When it comes to theorizing about situated
for in all of these cases is a special form cognition, we view ecological rationality as
of ecological rationality specifically dealing "adding new tools to cognitive science's tool
with social environments. kit" (Clark, 1997, p. 175) rather than replac-
ing the existing ones (see also Vera & Simon,
4.10. Summary: The Role of Situatedness lfft§
in High-Level Cognition Ecological rationality speaks to the rela-
tionship between mechanisms and envi-
It is clear that the concept of ecological
ronments and, in particular, how simple
rationality is closely allied and in strong
and cognitively plausible mechanisms that
agreement with the six defining character-
exploit the environment provide a produc-
istics of situated approaches to understand-
tive basis on which to explore human deci-
ing cognition proposed by Smith (1999).
sion making. Thus, the adaptive-toolbox
However, it is worth pointing out that the
vision of decision making has less to do
approach we advocate here is conservative
with what Smith (1999) terms "situatedness
in comparison with other more radical sit-
with a vengeance" (p. 770) and more to
uated positions. As the preceding sections
do with recasting, rethinking, and adding to
have demonstrated, ecologically rational
familiar concepts of cognition and situated-
heuristics are uniformly described in terms
ness. Mental representations, for instance,
of symbolic process models operating on
are not abandoned, but the fact that simple
representations. These processes draw on
processing solutions exploit structure in the
the classical notions of search, satisficing,
environment does suggest the possibility of
and decision rules. In contrast to more
a weaker reliance on internal models of the
radical positions, the concept of ecological
world. In Brooks's (1991) terms, we are sym-
rationality is agnostic with respect to, for
pathetic to the view that it is "better to use
example, issues of antirepresentationalism
the world as its own model" (p. 139). Fur-
(Slezak, 1999; Varela, T h o m p s o n , & Rosch,
thermore, in contrast to other frameworks
1991), dynamic systems theory (van Gelder,
with a focus on the relationship between
1995), or more philosophical rethinkings of
rational principles and the role of the envi-
the nature of cognition (Winograd & Flores,
ronment, such as Anderson's (1990) rational
1996). These issues are certainly significant
analysis (see also Oaksford 81 Chater, 1998),
dimensions of some theories of situatedness,
ecological rationality - realized through the
but we take the concept of ecological ratio-
adaptive toolbox - has a strong bottom-up
nality to be orthogonal to, for example, what
orientation to model construction reminis-
level and in what terms one describes pro-
cent of Brooks's subsumption architecture
cesses (for a related discussion, see V e r a &
for behavior-based robotics (Brooks, 1991).
Simon, 1993). To be clear on this point, we
In this sense, ecological rationality draws on
could note that simple heuristics could be
concepts that are more often associated with
implemented just as well using connection-
situated approaches to lower-level aspects of
ist networks or cognitive architectures such
cognition and demonstrates their productiv-
as ACT-R (Anderson & Lebeire, 1998; for
ity in studying higher-level aspects of human
an example, see Schooler & Hertwig, 2005),
decision making and inference.
299 346 henry b r i g h t o n a n d peter m. t o d d

5. Conclusion of rationality when seeking to understand


decision making and inference in humans
Ecological approaches to understanding the First of all, ecological rationality treats the
mind focus on the relationship between cognitive task as both located and con-
mind and environment. We have explored crete in the sense that the particular struc-
one form of this relationship, in which sim- ture making up the task environment can
ple mental mechanisms can make adap- be exploited by the concrete limited struc-
tive decisions by exploiting the character- ture of the processor. This relationship the
istics of environments. As such, the concept match between cognitive limitations and
of ecological rationality proves closely tied environment structure, is the core concept
with the key dimensions that characterize behind ecological rationality. Conventional
situated approaches to understanding the notions of rationality consider neither aspect
mind. To examine this connection, we and instead seek universally applicable prin-
began by considering three metaphors that ciples that are independent of both the capa-
have been used to characterize the relation- bilities of the actor and the structure of the
ship between mind and environment: mir- task. Part of the motivation for consider-
rors, lenses, and scissors. Mirrors reflect fun- ing ecological rationality, as we have dis-
damental features of the world such that cussed, is that the cognitive system needs
aspects of mind are shaped by the exter- to solve the procedural problem of arriv-
nal environment. Here, minds represent use- ing at inferences. This task is notoriously
ful and ubiquitous properties of the world, difficult, and we drew on machine-learning
and these properties help the mind to func- research to show h o w conventional notions
tion in environments. A lens projects rather of rationality cannot be universally adhered
than reflects, and reconstructs a representa- to. Faced with a fundamental dichotomy
tion of a distal stimulus on the basis of the between procedural and classical visions of
current proximal cues. Again, by projecting rationality, we question how appropriate
aspects of the environment into the mind, these classical visions of rationality are when
the environment can be acted on by process- seeking to understand the cognitive system.
ing this information. Scissors are different. T h e approach of ecological rationality
The scissors metaphor captures a relation- also turns on the engaged and specific nature
ship in which properties of the environment of cognition. T h e use of simple heuristics
are exploited by, rather than represented by, changes over time and as a reaction to
the capabilities of the agent. It is only in cir- changes in the environment. Although few
cumstances in which mind and environment cognitive theories w o u l d deny such a state
fit together like the blades of a pair of scissors of affairs, this reactive aspect of cognition is
that this relationship works. We have argued far more pivotal w h e n considering a toolbox
that the scissors metaphor is often appro- of ecologically rational heuristics, because of
priate when considering high-level cognitive their highly situation-specific nature. Eco-
processing tasks such as decision making and logical rationality also treats as highly sig-
inference. The concept of ecological ratio- nificant the social and (to a lesser extent)
nality, realized using an adaptive toolbox of embodied aspects of cognition. Humans
simple mechanisms, builds on this scissors inhabit environments constructed and occu-
metaphor. pied by other humans, and social heuristics
exploit the structure of environments con-
Simple decision heuristics that exploit
structed by the behavior of other humans.
features of natural environments perform
Similarly, the concrete details of sensor and
very well and sometimes better than more
muscle morphology are likely to be sig-
conventional and complex models of infer-
nificant in defining h o w simple heuristics
ence. Mechanisms such as these are termed
exploit body-environment interactions.
ecologically rational, and we have argued that
the concept of ecological rationality is far Despite the widespread adoption of ratio-
more productive than conventional notions nal principles as normative laws governing
SITUATING RATIONALITY
343
the cognitive system, we have argued that Barrett, H. C. (2005). Adaptations to predators
there are solid grounds for questioning this and prey, in D. M. Buss (Ed). The hand-
assumption. Rather than being rooted in book of evolutionary psychology (pp. 200-223).
probability theory, information theory, and Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
logic, the concept of ecological rationality Brighton, H. (2006). Robust inference with sim-
provides an alternative vision of rationality ple cognitive models. In C. Lebiere & B.
rooted in the concrete constraints of the cog- Wray (Eds.), Between a rock and a hard place:
nitive system and the structure of natural Cognitive science principles meet Al-hard prob-
lems (pp. 17-22). Menlo Park, CA: AAAI
environments. Behaving in line with classi-
Press.
cal rational principles and behaving adap-
Broder, A. (2000). Assessing the empirical valid-
tively, as we have argued, are not necessar-
ity of the "Take The Best" heuristic as a model
ily the same endeavor. Ecological rationality,
of human probabilistic inference. Journal of
by taking a situated perspective, provides a Experimental Psychology: Learning Memory,
vision of rationality bounded to the world in and Cognition, 26,1332-1346.
such a way that the limitations of the cogni- Broder, A., 8c Schiffer, S. (2003). "Take The
tive system and the specific context of cog- Best" versus simultaneous feature matching:
nition are viewed as significant and enabling Probabilistic inferences from memory and
features of adaptive cognition. If we are to effects of representation format. Journal of
understand the adaptive nature of high-level Experimental Psychology: General, 132(2), 277-
cognition, then the cognitive system needs 293.
to be viewed more as an ecologically ratio- Brooks, R. A. (1991). Intelligence without repre-
nal bag of tricks and less in terms of a for- sentation. Artificial Intelligence, 47,139-160.
mally motivated calculating device adhering Browne, M. W. (2000). Cross-validation meth-
ods. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 44,
to general principles of classically rational
108-132.
inference.
Brunswik, E. (1955). Representative design and
probabilistic theory in a functional psychol-
ogy. Psychological Review, 62,193-217.
Note Buss, D. M. (Ed.). (2005). The handbook of evolu-
tionary psychology. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
i The use of the term inductive bias differs both Chater, N. (1999). The search for simplicity:
from (a) the term bias in the heuristics and A fundamental cognitive principle? Quarterly
biases literature and (b) the term estimation Journal of Experimental Psychology, 52^(2),
bias in statistics (although inductive bias is 273-302.
connected to the latter; see Mitchell, 1997). Chater, N., 8c Brown, G. D. A. (1999). Scale
invariance as a unifying psychological princi-
ple. Cognition, 69, B17-B24.
References Chater, N., Oaksford, M, Nakisa, R., 8c Red-
ington, M. (2003). Fast, frugal and rational:
Anderson, J. R. (1990). The adaptive character of How rational norms explain behavior. Orga-
thought. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. nizational Behavior and Human Decision Pro-
Anderson, J. R., & Lebeire, C. (1998). The atomic cesses, 90, 63-86.
components of thought. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Chater, N., 8c Vitanyi, P. (2003). Simplicity: A
Erlbaum. unifying principle in cognitive science? Trends
Ariely, D., & Levav, J. (2000). Sequential choice in Cognitive Sciences, 7,19-22.
in group settings: Taking the road less trav- Chomsky, N. (1995). The minimalist program.
eled and less enjoyed. Journal of Consumer Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Research, 27(3), 279-290. Chomsky, N. (2000). New horizons in the study
Bak, P. (1996). How nature works. New York: of language and mind. Cambridge: Cambridge
Springer-Verlag. University Press.
Barkow, J. H., Cosmides, L., 8c Tooby, J. (Eds.). Clancey, W. J. (1997). Situated cognition: On
(1992). The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychol- human knowledge and computer represen-
ogy and the generation of culture. New York: tations. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Oxford University Press. Press.
3 0 1 henry b r i g h t o n a n d peter m . t o d d

Clark, A. (199-). Being there: Putting brain, body, heuristics in artificial intelligence, behavioral
and world together again. Cambridge, MA: ecology, and economics. In G. Gigerenzer
MIT Press. P. M. Todd, & the A B C Research Group
Czerlinski, J., Gigerenzer, G., & Goldstein, D. (Eds.), Simple heuristics that make us sman
G. (1999). How good are simple heuristics? (pp. 327-355). New York: Oxford University
In G. Gigerenzer, P. M. Todd, & the A B C Press.
Research Group (Eds.), Simple heuristics that Gordon, D. F., 8c Desjardins, M. (1995). Evalua-
make us smart (pp. 97-118). New York: Oxford tion and selection of biases in machine learn-
University Press. ing. Machine Learning, 20, 5-22.
Edland, A. (1994). Time pressure and the appli- Griinwald, P. (2005). Minimum description
cations of decision rules: Choices and judge- length tutorial. In P. Griinwald, I. J. Myung,
ments among multiattribute alternatives. 8c M. A. Pitt (Eds.), Advances in minimum
Scandinavian Journal of Psychology, 35,281-291. description length (pp. 23-79). Cambridge, MA:
Elman, J. L. (2003). Generalization from sparse MIT Press.
input. In Proceedings of the 38th Annual Meet- Hamilton, W. D. (1996). Narrow roads of gene
ing of the Chicago Linguistic Society. Chicago: land: Evolution of social behaviour (Vol. 1],
Chicago Linguistic Society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Erev, I., & Barron, G. (2005). On adapta- Hammond, K. R., 8c Stewart, T. R. (Eds.). (2001).
tion, maximization, and reinforcement learn- The essential BrunsuAk: Beginnings, explica-
ing among cognitive strategies. Psychological tions, applications. New York: Oxford Univer-
Review, 112(4), 912-931- sity Press.
Feldman, J. (2003). The simplicity principle in Hertwig, R., Hoffrage, U., & Martignon, L.
human concept learning. Current Directions in (1999). Quick estimation: Letting the environ-
Psychological Science, 12(6), 227-232. ment do some of the work. In G. Gigeren-
Gigerenzer, G., & Goldstein, D. G. (1996). Rea- zer, P. M. Todd, 8c the A B C Research Group
soning the fast and frugal way: Models of (Eds.), Simple heuristics that make us sman
bounded rationality. Psychological Review, 103, (pp. 209-234). N e w York: Oxford University
650-669. Press.
Gigerenzer, G., & Selten, R. (Eds.). (2001). Hertwig, R., 8c Todd, P. M. (2003). More is not
Bounded rationality: The adaptive toolbox. always better: The benefits of cognitive limits.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. In D. Hardman 8c L. Macchi (Eds.), Thinking:
Gigerenzer, G., & Todd, P. M. (1999). Fast and Psychological perspectives on reasoning, judg-
frugal heuristics: The adaptive toolbox. In G. ment and decision making (pp. 213-231). Chich-
Gigerenzer, P. M. Todd, & the ABC Research ester, UK: Wiley.
Group (Eds.), Simple heuristics that make us Hutchinson, J., Fanselow, C., 8c Todd, P. M.
smart (pp. 3-34). New York: Oxford Univer- (forthcoming). Car parking as a game between
sity Press. simple heuristics. In P. M. Todd, G. Gigeren-
Gigerenzer, G, Todd, P. M., & the A B C zer, 8c the A B C Research Group (Eds.), Eco-
Research Group (Eds.). (1999). Simple heuris- logical Rationality: Intelligence in the World.
tics that make us smart. New York: Oxford New York: Oxford University Press.
University Press. Hutter, M. (2005). Universal artificial intelligence:
Goldstein, D. G., & Gigerenzer, G. (1999). The Sequential decisions based on algorithmic prob-
recognition heuristic: How ignorance makes ability. Berlin: Springer.
us smart. In G. Gigerenzer, P. M. Todd, & the Juslin, P., 8c Persson, M. (2002). PRObabilities
ABC Research Group (Eds.), Simple heuristics from EXemplars (PROBEX): A "lazy" algo-
that make us smart (pp. 37-58). New York: rithm for probabalistic inference from generic
Oxford University Press. knowledge. Cognitive Science, 26(5), 563-607.
Goldstein, D. G., & Gigerenzer, G. (2002). Mod- Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., 8c Tversky, A. (Eds).
els of ecological rationality: The recognition (1982). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics
heuristic. Psychological Review, 109, 75-90.
and biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Gonzalez, C., Lerch, J. F., & Lebiere, C. (2003).
Press.
Instance-based learning in dynamic decision
Kalousis, A., Gama, J., 8c Hilario, M. (2004). On
making. Cognitive Science, 27,591-635.
data and algorithms: Understanding induc-
Goodie, A. S., Ortmann, A., Davis, J., Bullock,
tive performance. Machine Learning, 54,275-
S., & Werner, G. M. (1999). Demons versus
312.
situating rationality

Kearns, M. (1999)- Computational learning the- Pitt, M. A., Myung, I. J., & Zhang, S.
ory. In R- A. Wilson & F. C. Keil (Eds.), The (2002). Toward a method of selecting among
MIT encyclopedia of the cognitive sciences (pp. computational models of cognition. Psycholog-
159-160). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ical Review, 109(3), 472-491.
Kearns, M., Mansour, Y., Ng, A. Y., & Ron, D. Ramachandran, V. S. (1990). Interactions
(1997)- experimental and theoretical com- between motion, depth, color and form: The
parison of model selection methods. Machine utilitarian theory of perception. In C. Blake-
Learning, 27, 7-50. more (Ed.), Vision: Coding and efficiency (pp.
KniU, D- C., & Pouget, A. (2004). The Bayesian 346-360). New York: Cambridge University
brain: The role of uncertainty in neural cod- Press.
ing and computation. Trends in Neurosciences, Reddy, R. (1988). AAAI presidential address:
27(12), 712-719. Foundations and grand challenges of artificial
Kiirzenhauser, S., & Hoffrage, U. (2002). Teach- intelligence. AI Magazine, 9(4), 9-21.
ing Bayesian reasoning: An evaluation of a Reimer, T., 8c Hoffrage, U. (2005). Can simple
classroom tutorial for medical students. Med- group heuristics detect hidden profiles in ran-
ical Teacher, 24(5), 516-521. domly generated environments? Swiss Journal
Li,M., & Vitinyi, P. M. B. (1997). An introduction of Psychobgy, 64(1), 21-37.
to Kolmogorov complexity and its applications. Reimer, T., 8c Katsikopoulos, K. V. (2004). The
New York: Springer. use of recognition in group decision-making.
Makse, H. A., Havlin, B., & Stanley, H. E. (1995). Cognitive Science, 28(6), 1009-1029.
Modeling urban growth patterns. Nature, 377, Rieskamp, J., 8c Hoffrage, U. (1999). When do
608-612. people use simple heuristics and how can we
Markman, A. B., & Dietrich, E. (2000). Extending tell? In G. Gigerenzer, P. M. Todd, 8c the
the classical view of representation. Trends in A B C Research Group (Eds.), Simple heuristics
Cognitive Sciences, 4(12), 470-475. that make us smart (pp. 141-167). New York:
Martignon, L., 81 Hoffrage, U. (1999)- Why Oxford University Press.
does one-reason decision making work? In G. Rieskamp, J., 8c Otto, P. (2005). SSL: A theory of
Gigerenzer, P. M. Todd, & the A B C Research how people learn to select strategies. Manuscript
Group (Eds.), Simple heuristics that make us submitted for publication.
smart (pp. 119-140). N e w York: Oxford Uni- Rissanen, J. J. (1989). Stochastic complexity and
versity Press. statistical inquiry. Singapore: World Scientific.
McLeod, P., & Dienes, Z. (1996). Do fielders Rozin, P., 8c Fallon, A. E. (1987). A perspective
know where to go to catch the ball or only on disgust. Psychobgical Review, 94(1), 23-41.
how to get there? Journal of Experimental Psy- Russell, S., 8c Norvig, P. (1995). Artificial intelli-
chology, 22(3), 531-543. gence: A modern approach. Englewood Cliffs,
Mitchell, T. M. (1997). Machine learning. New NJ: Prentice Hall.
York: McGraw-Hill. Schooler, L. J., 8c Hertwig, R. (2005). How for-
Newell, B. R., & Shanks, D. R. (2003). Take getting aids heuristic inference. Psychobgical
the best or look at the rest? Factors influ- Review, 112, 610-628.
encing "one-reason" decision-making. Journal Shepard, R. N. (1987). Towards a universal law of
of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, generalization for psychological science. Sci-
and Cognition, 29, 53-65. ence, 37(4820), 1317-1323.
Oaksford, M., 8c Chater, N. (1998). Rational mod- Shepard, R. N. (2001). Perceptual-cognitive uni-
els of cognition. Oxford: Oxford University versal as reflections of the world. Behavioral
Press. and Brain Sciences, 24(4), 581-601.
Pachur, T., 81 Biele, G. (2007). Forecasting by Simon, H. A. (1956). Rational choice and struc-
ignorance: The use and usefulness of recogni- ture of the environment. Psychobgical Review,
tion in lay predictions of sports events. Acta 63,129-138.
Psychobgica, 125(1), 99-116. Simon, H. A. (1990). Invariants of human behav-
Payne, J. W., Bettman, J. R., 8c Johnson, E. J. ior. Annual Review of Psychobgy, 41,1-19.
(1993). The adaptive decision maker. N e w York: Simon, H. A. (1996). The sciences of the artificial
Cambridge University Press. (3rd ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Pearl, 1 (1988). Probabilistic reasoning in intel- Slezak, P. (1999). Situated cognition: Empir-
ligent systems. San Francisco: Morgan Kauf- ical issue, "paradigm shift" or conceptual
mann. confusion? In J. Wiles 8c T. Dartnall (Eds.),
3 5 0 henry b r i g h t o n a n d peter m . t o d d

Perspectives on cognitive science (Vol. 2, pp. 69- In L. K. Saul, Y. Weiss, 81 L. Bottou (Eds.)
9S). Stamford, CT. Ablex. Advances in neural information processing sys-
Smith, B. C, (1999). Situatedness/embeddedness. tems 17 (pp. 1393-1400). Cambridge, MA: MIT
In R. A. Wilson & F. C. Keil (Eds.), The MIT Press.
encyclopedia of the cognitive sciences (pp. 769- Todd, P. M., & Gigerenzer, G. (2001). Shepard's
770). Cambridge. MA: MIT Press. mirrors or Simon's scissors? C o m m e n t a r y on
Sober, E. (1975). Simplicity. Oxford, UK: Claren- R. N. Shepard: Perceptual-cognitive univer-
don Press. sals as reflections of the world. Behavioral and
Solomonoff, R. J. (1964). A formal theory of Brain Sciences, 24(4), 704-705.
inductive inference, part 1 and part 2. Infor- Todd, P. M., & Gigerenzer, G. (2003). Bounding
mation and Control, 7(1-2), 224-254. rationality to the world. Journal of Economic
Stenning, K, & van Lambalgen, M. (2004). A lit- Psychology, 24(2), 143-165.
tle logic goes a long way: Basing experiment Todd, P. M„ Hertwig, R., & Hoffrage, U. (2005).
on semantic theory in the cognitive science of The evolutionary psychology of cognition. In
conditional reasoning. Cognitive Science, 28(4), D. M. Buss (Ed.), The handbook of evolution-
481-529. ary psychology (pp. 776-802). Hoboken, NJ:
Takezawa, M. (2004). Developing a new frame- Wiley.
work of adaptive concession-making strategies:Tversky, A. (1972). Elimination by aspects: A the-
An approach to behavioral game theory from ory of choice. Psychological Review, 79(4), 281-
psychology. Manuscript submitted for publica- 299.
tion. van Gelder, T. J. (1995)- What might cognition
Tanner, C., 8t Medin, D.L. (2004). Protected val- be, if not computation? Journal of Philosophy,
ues: No omission bias and no framing effects. 91, 345-381.
Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 11(1), 185-191. Varela, F., Thompson, E., &. Rosch, E. (1991).
Thrun, S., & Pratt, L. Y. (1998). Learning to learn. The embodied mind: Cognitive science and
Boston: Kluwer Academic. human experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Todd, P. M. (1999). Simple inference heuristics Press.
versus complex decision machines. Minds and Vera, A. H., 81 Simon, H. A. (1993). Situated
Machines, 9(4), 461-477. action: A symbolic interpretation. Cognitive
Todd, P. M. (2001). Fast and frugal heuristics Science, 17, 7-48.
for environmentally bounded minds. In G. Westenberg, M. R. M., & Koele, P. (1992).
Gigerenzer & R. Selten (Eds.), Bounded ratio- Response modes, decision processes and deci-
nality: The adaptive toolbox (pp. 51-70). Cam- sion outcomes. Acta Psychologica, 80, 169-
bridge, MA: MIT Press. 184.
Todd, P. M., Billari, F. C., & Simao, J. (2005). Winograd, T., & Flores, F. (1996). Understanding
Aggregate age-at-marriage patterns from indi- computers and cognition: A new foundation for
vidual mate-search heuristics. Demography,
design. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
42(3)' 559-574- Zahavi, A., & Zahavi, A. (1997). The handicap
Todd, P. M., & Dieckmann, A. (2005). Heuristics principle: A missing piece of Darwin's puzzle.
for ordering cue search in decision making. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
C H A P T E R 18

Situativity and Learning

R. Keith Saivyer and James G. Greeno

i. Introduction among many educators that learning is an


individual mental process.
In the past two decades, education research The situative perspective emerged during
has been transformed by cognitive science. the 1980s, when some social scientists began
Cognitive scientists have been interested to analyze cognitive processes as aspects of
in educational applications since the interaction, and some cognitive scientists
1970s, when several artificial intelligence began to consider the social arrangements
researchers began to develop intelligent of learning as fundamental in determin-
tutoring systems (Bobrow & Collins, 1975; ing what is learned. Lucy Suchman (1987)
Sleeman & Brown, 1982; Wenger, 1987). T h e argued that the cognitive concept of action,
annual Carnegie Symposium in Cognition a process governed by plans with adap-
in 1974 provided a collection of early contri- tations to unanticipated aspects of situa-
butions on cognition and instruction (Klahr, tions, is inferior to an account in which
1976). In the 1980s, increasing numbers of "plans are resources for situated action, but
cognitive scientists began to apply their do not in any strong sense determine its
research to learning. In 1987, John Seely course" (p. 52). Suchman and others (e.g.,
Brown, David Kearns, and James Greeno Winograd & Flores, 1986) argued for a per-
cofounded the Institute f o r Research on spective in which "the organization of sit-
Learning. In 1989, Roger Schank was uated action is an emergent property of
recruited by Northwestern University to moment-by-moment interactions between
lead its new Institute f o r Learning Sciences. actors, and between actors and the envi-
During this early period, the educational ronments of their action" (1987, p. 179).
impact of cognitive science emphasized the Sylvia Scribner (1984), Jean Lave (Lave, 1988;
internal mental processes of learning - this Lave, Murtaugh, & de la Rocha, 1984), and
was consistent with the mentalist focus of Terezina Nunes, Annalucia Schliemann, and
early cognitive science, and with a belief David Carraher (1993), analyzed problem

347
r . keith s a w y e r a n d james g . g r e e n o

solv ing in everyday (i.e., nonlaboratory) set- commitment of all of these is to analyze
tings and argued that solutions of problems performance and transformations of activity
involving mathematical reasoning were bet- systems that usually comprise multiple peo-
ter understood as emerging from interac- pie and a variety of technological artifacts
tions between people and resources in the Analyses can include studying how these
setting than as products of mental oper- aggregate performances and transformations
ations with and on symbolic representa- correspond to and facilitate individual per-
tions. Another influential analysis of cogni- formance and learning, which are consid-
tive processes as aspects of social practice ered as participation and changes in partic-
were Hutchins's (1995a) studies of reason- ipation in the activity system. The situative
ing and representational practices by navy approach acknowledges that individual per-
ship-navigation teams, and of remembering formance and learning can also be analyzed
by the system of people and technologi- and explained in terms of individual mental
cal resources in an airplane cockpit (1995b). structures. However, the situative perspec-
Even color perception has been analyzed as a tive conceptualizes knowledge as distributed
process embedded in social practices (Good- across people and artifacts, and the focus
win, 2000; Goodwin & Goodwin, 1996). is on understanding activity and changes in
In the 1990s, researchers in the learn- activity systems in which knowledge is con-
ing sciences founded a new disciplinary tributed and used in joint actions by the peo-
field, with international meetings and the ple and other resources that participate col-
Journal of the Learning Sciences (JLS). The laboratively.
idea of situativity was adopted early on by A guiding principle of this new com-
some of these researchers. The term situ- munity is that learning is always situated.
ated cognition was first used, in discussions of School learning is situated in a setting of
research on learning, by John Seely Brown, a complex social organization that con-
Allan Collins, and Paul Duguid (1989) and tain learners, teachers, curriculum materials,
by Greeno (1989). Barbara Rogoff (1990) software tools, and the layout of the physi-
studied learning in family interactions and cal environment. Other learning is situated
emphasized children's participation in activ- in a setting of an individual reading a book
ities. The term situated learning was intro- or just thinking. Although the adjective sit-
duced by Jean Lave and Etienne Wenger uated w h e n applied to learning implies that
(1991), who argued that Brown et al.'s idea of there might be such a thing as nonsituated
cognitive apprenticeship should be replaced learning, learning scientists of the situative
by a concept they called "legitimate periph- persuasion generally believe that all learning
eral participation," referring more generally is situated. For this reason, we refer to a sit-
to a learner's opportunities to participate uative approach or situative perspective on
meaningfully as a member of a community learning rather than to situated learning or
of practice rather than to a learner's social situated cognition.
designation as an apprentice. Within traditional individualist cognitive
The situative perspective on learning science, the study of learning involves how
brings together parts of cognitive sci- mental structures change within the mind
ence with parts of educational psychol- of the learner. Traditionally, cognitive sci-
ogy, computer science, anthropology, soci- entists focus on the activities of individuals
ology, information sciences, educational as they answer questions, solve problems,
design studies, instructional design, and study texts, or respond to stimuli. Most
other fields. The approach we call "situative" often, they e x a m i n e performance on exper-
has gone by many names, including socio- imental tasks or school assessments. Cog-
cultural psychology (Rogoff, 1990; Wertsch, nitive explanations are models of the pro-
1991), activity theory (Engestróm, Miettinen, cesses that individuals use to construct store,
& Punamáki, 1999), and distributed cognition retrieve, and m o d i f y patterns of informa-
(Hutchins, 1995a). We consider that the core tion. C o n c e p t s and methods for analyzing
situattvity and learning 306

these knowledge structures are the main lems equivalent to those solved in these
focus of traditional individualist cognitive real-world systems are given to the partici-
science. pants in school-like tests, they generally per-
The cognitivist study of problem solving form poorly, as documented particularly by
is an example. Individual problem solvers Nunes et al. (1993). One implication of this
are hypothesized to have constructed cogni- research is that it is meaningless to assess
tive structures called "problem spaces" that whether someone has learned a particular
represent the task, including objects of the topic of mathematics without taking into
problem, arrangements of the objects in dif- account the kind of activity system in which
ferent states, operators, goals, and strategies. the person's knowledge is to be evaluated.1
Problem solving is understood as a process For example, a paper-and-pencil test is a
of searching in the problem space for a path specific type of activity system, and a per-
from the initial state to the goal. In their son's performance within that activity sys-
activity, problem solvers construct addi- tem is situated participation in a social prac-
tional structures of subgoals, evaluations of tice, just as any other performance.
changes in the problem state, memories of The claims and challenges of situative
past attempts, and so on (e.g., Newell & researchers were subjects of controversy in
Simon, 1972). cognitive science. Alonzo Vera and Herbert
Lave (1988) provided an analysis of rea- Simon (1993) responded to the claim that
soning and problem solving that contrasts behavior in complex settings requires a sit-
with the standard cognitivist view. Her anal- uative analysis, with examples such as fight-
yses support a conclusion that the problem ing forest fires and highway driving that have
space is not a stable information structure, been simulated or instantiated in computa-
as it is assumed to be to analyze problem tional systems, arguing that complex situa-
solving as a search. She showed that rea- tions do not, in principle, require departing
soning by grocery shoppers was a process from a symbol-processing account. Several
in which their decisions and the goals they situative researchers responded to Vera and
eventually achieved were shaped jointly by Simon (1993) in a special issue of Cognitive
their initial goals and preferences along with Science. Greeno and Joyce Moore's (1993)
the objects and symbols in the aisles of the response focused on conceptualizations of
supermarket. This implies that the problem symbols, noting that in situative analyses,
space is dynamically co-constructed by the symbols are assumed to be material or men-
problem solver in collaboration with mate- tal entities that are interpreted as having ref-
rial resources, sources of information, and erence. In standard cognitive theory, accord-
(very often) other people in the situation. ing to the physical-symbol hypothesis, all of
In another seminal analysis, Scribner (1984) a person's activity is assumed to be mediated
showed that problem solving by workers in a by symbolic representations. In the situative
dairy warehouse was a process in which their perspective, symbolic mediation is hypoth-
performance of placing the requested num- esized to occur in some, but not all, activity.
bers of items in containers for delivery was Objections were also raised against the
jointly determined by the workers' reading situative view by John Anderson, Lynne
of forms showing the numbers needed and Reder, and Herbert Simon (1996), who dis-
the visible numbers of items and open spaces puted claims they attributed to the situa-
in containers in the situation. tive perspective, including the claim that if
The decisions made and the solutions learning is situated it cannot transfer, and
produced in these two activity systems were the claim that learning can be effective only
generally optimal; that is, the shoppers gen- if it occurs in groups. In response, Greeno
erally chose products that had the best unit (1997) argued that they were attacking a
straw man: the situative perspective's com-
prices, and the dairy product loaders gen-
mitment to analyzing learning at the level of
erally filled orders by moving the minimum
activity systems does not preclude learning
number of items. When mathematical prob-
350 R. KEITH SAWYER AND JAMES G. GREENO

bv individuals that transfers to other activity 2. Settings of Learning and


systems, nor effective learning by an individ- Learning Research
ual in an activity system consisting of that
individual with other resources (e.g., a text- Traditionally (until the 1980s), there were
book) and without other people participat- two programs of research in the scientific
ing. study of learning. In one of the programs
Situative research provides an alternative in the purview of experimental psychology
to the mentalist idea that considers cogni- research was conducted mainly in controlled
tion as an internal mental process - one laboratory settings, arranged to provide
that may be influenced by the surround- data to advance the theoretical programs of
ing context but that is, at its root, inter- behaviorism and associationism. The other
nal. The situative approach shifts the focus: program, in educational research, was con-
situated action within activity systems is ducted mainly in classrooms, comparing dif-
central, with individuals and their actions ferent methods of teaching some topic in
considered constituents of the activity sys- the curriculum. Scientists who conducted
tem. Analyses at the system level do not fundamental learning research in laborato-
preclude analyses that focus on an individ- ries considered education research that was
ual participant, in which the other partici- focused on what occurred within classrooms
pants and resources are considered the con- unsuitable for discovering fundamental con-
text. Analyses at either the system level or cepts and principles of learning, because
the individual level can include hypotheses both the contents and situations of learning
about information structures. At the system were too complex. These studies of learning
level, hypotheses are about shared informa- in educational research were informed by
tion, the common ground that participants general theoretical issues, such as the merits
have and construct in their interaction. At of discovery learning or the value of using
the individual level, hypotheses are about concrete manipulative materials in mathe-
what an individual knows, and what he or matics, but the relation between experimen-
she perceives and understands in the activ- tal treatments and theories was not detailed
ity setting. In the situative view, learning at enough to support substantive theoretical
an individual level involves transformation advances (Sowder, 1989).
of the individual's participation in an activ- T h e development of information-pro-
ity system and occurs as part of a transfor- cessing theory in cognitive science enabled
mation of that activity system. Focusing on formal analyses of subject-matter content
only individual learning, as traditional cog- of learning, and this research program was
nitive scientists do, requires an assumption active beginning in the 1970s (e.g., Klahr,
that the cognitive processes of the activity 1976). In this cognitivist perspective, learn-
system can be decomposed in such a way ing is considered the acquisition of informa-
that specific elements can be associated with tion structures that support improvement
specific individual participants. But situative in tasks used in instruction. Empirical
researchers have shown that activity systems research used in developing and evalu-
differ in whether they are organized in ways ating cognitive models of learning has
that support such decomposition. The inter- mainly been done in laboratory studies in
actions of some activity systems, such as jazz which participants engaged in tasks like
or improvisational theater groups (Sawyer, those used in classroom instruction (e.g.,
2003a, 2003b), are not decomposable in this Anderson, 1982; Kintsch, 1998). Concepts
way with our current methods of analy- and principles developed and supported in
sis, and for these activity systems, isolating this research have informed instructional
the learning of any one individual would systems, including curricula for reading (Pal-
require more powerful analytical concepts incsar & Brown, 1984), mathematics (Ander-
and methods (see the discussion on com- son, Boyle, Corbett, & Lewis, 1990; Carpen-
plexity in section 7). ter & Fennema, 1992), and physics (diSessa
355
situattvity and learning

Table 18.1: Some Idealized Characteristics of Informal and Formal Education


™j a pted from Greenfield & Lave, 1982)

Informal Education Formal Education

E m b e d d e d in daily life activities Embedded in a context specialized for learning


Learners responsible for obtaining knowledge Teacher responsible for imparting knowledge
and skill, often in collaborative activity and skill, primarily to individuals
personal; relatives are appropriate teachers Impersonal; teachers should not be relatives
Little or no explicit pedagogy or curriculum Explicit pedagogy and curriculum
Learning by observation and imitation Learning by verbal interchange and questioning
Teaching by demonstration Teaching by verbal presentation of general
principles

& Minstrell, 1998; V a n L e h n et al., 2005], and sized specific procedures for accomplishing
these have been used and evaluated in school concrete tasks. Second, the procedures were
settings. used to accomplish meaningful real-world
As researchers using the situative ap- tasks, unlike formal schooling, where chil-
proach increasingly studied cognitive pro- dren learn knowledge that is not meaningful
cesses in settings of everyday activity, they in the real world outside of school. Third,
took up studies of learning in a wide range apprenticeship learning was embedded in a
of socially organized activities. rich practical social context, unlike school-
These studied included cross-cultural ing, where the contexts for learning skills
research by developmental psychologists and knowledge are abstracted from their use
and anthropologists, often in nonindustrial in the nonschool world.
cultures where formal schooling was not
universal. Of course, all cultures have learn-
3.1. Cognitive Apprenticeship
ing environments within w h i c h to support
learning by the young effectively; after all, Most of us think of very traditional trades
formally institutionalized schooling is a rela- when we hear the term apprenticeship - like
tively recent, modern invention. In the early shoemaking, silversmithing, or farming.
stages of this program, researchers proposed John Seely Brown, Allan Collins, and their
a distinction between formal and informal colleagues argued that the concept of
learning environments in terms of some apprenticeship had to be updated to make
characteristics that seemed to contrast learn- it relevant to modern subjects like reading,
ing in school and learning in nonschool set- writing, and mathematics; they called this
tings (see Table 18.1). updated concept of apprenticeship "cogni-
tive apprenticeship" (Brown et al., 1989;
Collins, Brown, f| Newman, 1989). It is
3. Considering L e a r n i n g cognitive because the focus is on cogni-
as Apprenticeship tive skills and processes rather than physical
ones. Traditional apprenticeship evolved to
In these early discussions, learning in teach domains in which the process of car-
apprenticeship was taken as a paradigmatic rying out a complex task can be observed,
alternative to learning in school (e.g., Brown by both learner and expert, and the rela-
et al., 1989). In her study of a traditional tai- tionship between the task and the resulting
lor shop in Africa, L a v e identified the central product is relatively obvious. Because the
features of the productive f o r m of appren- apprentice's practice on the task is observ-
ticeship she found in that setting (Lave & able, the expert can comment on it, and they
Wenger, 1991). First, apprenticeship empha- can work together to refine and correct the
r. keith sawyer a n d james g. g r e e n o

apprentice's performance. But with a lot of earlier. Even Lave's (Lave & Wenger, îg^j
knowledge taught in schools, teachers can- example of apprentice tailors is an imper-
not see the cognitive processes that are going fect fit to the then-prevalent characteriza-
on in students' heads, and it is difficult for tion of informal learning shown in Table 18
them to comment on how the student is Although the context of learning was a tai-
applying knowledge to problems and tasks. lor shop, where the everyday work of manu-
By the same token, students cannot see the facturing clothing was the main occupation
cognitive problem-solving processes of their the activities of the apprentices were orga-
instructors; thus, they cannot leam through nized to support their learning; they did not
observation and imitation. Before appren- simply absorb skills and knowledge inciden-
ticeship methods can be applied to learn tally from their presence in the tailor shop
cognitive skills, the learning environment Lave also reported that there was an explicit
has to be changed to make these internal
curriculum in which apprentices progressed
thought processes externally visible. Cogni-
from simpler to more complex tasks.
tive apprenticeship is designed to bring these
Lave and Wenger (1991) reviewed stud-
cognitive processes into the open, where stu-
ies of apprenticeship learning, intending to
dents can observe, enact, and practice them
identify major characteristics of this form of
(Collins, 2006).
learning. T h e y f o u n d that uses of the term
There are two additional differences
apprenticeship in practice are very hetero-
between cognitive apprenticeship and tra-
geneous, and they concluded that it would
ditional apprenticeship. First, because tra-
be more appropriate to focus on a concept
ditional apprenticeship is set in the work-
that refers to a central feature of appren-
place, the problems and tasks that are given
ticeship that is productive for learning, such
to learners arise not from pedagogical con-
as the apprentice tailors that Lave stud-
cerns but from the demands of the work-
ied (Lave & Wenger, 1991), but not present
place. Because the job selects the tasks for
in many examples of apprenticeship and
students to practice, traditional apprentice-
present in many learning arrangements that
ship is limited in what it can teach. Cogni-
are not apprenticeship. They referred to
tive apprenticeship differs from traditional
this concept as "legitimate peripheral par-
apprenticeship in that the tasks and prob-
ticipation," w h i c h acknowledges that new-
lems are chosen to illustrate the power of
comers in a community of practice are not
certain techniques and methods; to give stu-
positioned to participate with full entitle-
dents practice in applying these methods in
ments and accountability, but their par-
diverse settings; and to increase the com-
ticipation can be organized so that they
plexity of tasks slowly, so that component
become more knowledgeable and skilled,
skills and models can be integrated.
changing along a trajectory toward full
Second, whereas traditional apprentice- participation.
ship emphasizes teaching skills in the con-
text of their use, cognitive apprenticeship
emphasizes generalizing knowledge so that 4. Considering Learning
it can be used in many different settings. as C u i d e d Participation
Cognitive apprenticeship extends practice
to diverse settings and articulates the com- Although apprenticeship turned out not to
mon principles, so that students leam how be a useful organizing concept for learn-
to apply their skills in varied contexts. ing research and design, aspects of pro-
ductive versions of apprenticeship have
been identified as productive characteris-
3.2. Legitimate Peripheral Participation
tics of learning environments. In Laves
In retrospect, the concept of apprentice- study (Lave & Wenger, 1991)1 appren"
ship is less apt as an alternative to formally tices learned these domain-specific meth-
institutionalized schooling than was thought ods through a combination of what Lave
situattvityandlearning310

ailed observation, coaching, and practice. In the situative approach, learning and
In this sequence of activities, the appren- development are reconceptualized as appro-
tice repeatedly observed the master and his priation of tools and practices of the com-
of her assistants engaged in a complex task.
munity rather than internalization of a
The apprentice then attempted to execute body of facts and procedures (Wertsch,
some components of this task with coach- 1998). Practices are always situated - always
¡jjg _ guidance and help from the master, stretched across multiple participants, work-
ing together with complex designed and
i key aspect of coaching was guided par-
technological artifacts. Learning as appro-
ticipation: the close responsive support that
priation emphasizes that the individual is
the master provided to help the novice com-
learning how to participate in the socially sit-
plete an entire task, even before the novice uated activity by appropriating the ability to
had acquired every component skill. As the perform a role within the system. The inter-
learner mastered more of the component nal mental knowledge that may be required
skills, the master reduced his participation, to support that participation is a question of
providing fewer hints and less feedback to secondary interest.
the learner. The master faded away com-
pletely when the apprentice had learned to
smoothly execute the whole task. This con- 5. What Is Learned?
cept of guided participation or scaffolding
has been widely influential in the situative From the situative perspective, all socially
approach [Wood, Bruner, & Ross, 1976) and organized activities provide opportunities
has frequently been connected to Vygotsky's for learning to occur, including learning that
concept of the zone of proximal develop- is different from what a teacher or designer
ment (Rogoff, 1990). might wish. In an ethnographic study of
Rogoff (1990), who adopted the appren- math lessons in a bilingual Spanish-English
ticeship metaphor in her book Appren- third-grade classroom, Lave and Hass (Lave,
ticeship in Thinking, studied child-rearing 1997) focused on eleven children in the
practices among Guatemalan Mayans and upper math group for a three-week unit
found that much of their learning occurred on multiplication and division. During the
through guided participation that shared three weeks, the children gave no evidence
many features with the apprenticeships of having adopted any of the specific strate-
studied by Lave. Her research revealed the gies demonstrated by the teacher in her
importance of joint attention and inter- instruction, even though during group and
subjectivity, and emphasized that learning individual work, the students worked hard
involved a transformation in patterns of par- on the math problems, and even though
ticipation in an activity system. all eleven students turned in almost-perfect
These two research projects demonstrate daily worksheets. But instead of using the
key properties of learning that are found in procedures they were taught, they collab-
every culture: learning occurs through sit- orated and invented new procedures that
uated social practices that have emerged were easier. For example, they discovered
in the culture to facilitate learning. Indi- that the multiplication table printed in
vidual learning is almost impossible to
the book could be used to solve division
understand apart from these situated social
problems. However, essentially all of the
practices. Learning always occurs in his-
problems were solved using counting and
torically unique social and cultural set-
regrouping strategies, which were not pre-
tings, with historically and culturally cre-
sented in the lessons and were not sup-
ated social practices. Even formal classrooms
posed to be used. The children used their
are constructed social practices - they have
own invented procedures so as to produce
emerged relatively recently in history, and
the appearance of having used the teacher's
they may not always exist in their current
procedures - by getting correct answers
form.
r . keith s a w y e r a n d j a m e s g . g r e e n o

on the worksheets. After getting the cor- tive, learning is the continual accumulate
rect answers using their own methods, they of more and more knowledge - conceived
translated them into appropriate classroom of as representations that are possessed by
form on the worksheets. Interviews with the individual mind. From a situative per-
the teacher revealed that she was unaware spective, learning is the gradual approprj.
of these interactive, collaboratively invented ation, through guided participation, of the
procedures. ability to participate in culturally defined
The teacher and the textbook described socially situated activities and practices. And
in detail the procedures the children were because every culture has its own unique
supposed to use I but the children devel- set of practices, learning outcomes will be
oped a different set of practices. They knew different within each culture. Thus, the
they had to get the right answer, but instead situative approach contrasts with universal-
of learning the new procedure they learned ist developmental models traditionally asso-
how to draw on familiar known techniques. ciated with developmental psychology _
Even though they did not learn the mate- for example, Piaget's four-stage model in
rial, they performed well on the tests and which the pinnacle of development is for-
worksheets. Lave (1997) argues that rather mal, abstract thought.
than learning math, the children were learn-
ing how "to produce proper appearances of
successful problem solving" (p. 31). 6. T h e K e y Role of Communication
An individualist approach that relied only
on tests and worksheets would not have Group learning always involves human com-
revealed what was actually being learned munication, both verbal and nonverbal. To
in this classroom. The tests and the work- study group learning, situativity researchers
sheets seemed to provide evidence that the use the methods of interaction analysis
intended learning was occurring. However, (Chi, 1997; Jordan & Henderson, 199c;
the situative approach - which analyzed the Sawyer, 2006a). These methods evolved
complex activity systems of the classroom, from several disciplinary strands, includ-
including the collaboration among the stu- ing ethnomethodology, discourse analysis,
dents and the ways they interacted with symbolic interactionism, and sociocultural
textbooks, tables, and worksheets - revealed psychology. This research focuses on how
that a different set of transformations was people talk to one another as they plan,
occurring. evaluate, and coordinate their interactions
The situative approach also provides a with the material and technological sys-
framework for research that studies the hid- tems in their environment. The goal is to
den curriculum - learning practices that are identify patterns of interaction in which
not explicitly taught, but that students need the people in the group coordinate their
to know to participate effectively in learning behaviors as they participate in their joint
activities. It is a mistake to think that school activity. Such patterns have been called
learning is decontextualized. Instead, school "participation structures" (e.g., Erickson &
learning, like all learning, is situated activity. Mohatt, 1982; Philips, 1972). Each culture
It is also a mistake to contrast school learn- and each group develops its own distinc-
ing with everyday learning; school is the tive participation structures, and learning to
activity setting that students and teachers become more effective in one's participa-
engage in every day (see Lave, 1997). Prac- tion corresponds to achieving fuller partici-
tices include patterns of discourse commu- pation in a community's practices (Lave &
nication, such as those we discuss in the next Wenger, 1991). For example, the participa-
section. tion structure of a traditional school class-
This perspective helps researchers to room imposes specific roles on the teacher
understand cultural differences in the goals and the students, and provides a set of
of learning. From an individualist perspec- expected practices for each of those roles.
siTUATivrrv a n d l e a r n i n g
355

Students can talk only when given per- telling. For example, literacy researchers are
mission by the teacher, and even then the now examining how children learn to read
teacher determines the content of their talk. by focusing on preliteracy or emergent lit-
In contrast, the teacher has greater speaking eracy: how their informal interactions with
rights; for example, he or she can interrupt a parents and others prepare them for their
student if necessary, but students are rarely first encounters with the printed word. One
permitted to interrupt the teacher. of the most important activities that fami-
Interaction analysis studies the whole lies participate in collectively is telling sto-
activity system, without yet having com- ries. But this research is showing that chil-
plete understanding of the individual com- dren do not learn how to tell a story through
ponents - particularly the individual human explicit, formal instruction. Rather, they
participants in the system. However, sit- learn by engaging in joint storytelling inter-
uativity researchers are interested in both actions with their parents. At first, the par-
group learning in activity systems and ent may provide most of the detail, with
learning by individuals that advances their the child filling in only occasionally; grad-
effectiveness in participation. The tension ually, through a process of appropriation
between the individual- and group-level through guided participation, the child takes
approaches thus represents a general diffi- over increasing responsibility for telling the
culty facing scientists who study complex story. Through these complex activity sys-
systems: whether to proceed by reduction tems, a storytelling duet (Falk, 1980), a child
to study of the components or by holistic learns what a story is. (In fact, the narra-
study of the entire system (Sawyer, 2005). tive genre is subtly different in different cul-
Interaction analysis has identified impor- tures; there is no such thing as a univer-
tant patterns of conversational interaction - sal narrative competence that all children
patterns of turn taking, opening and clos- uniformly develop toward. Michaels [1981]
ing of topics, and mechanisms of repair showed that even in the United States, Euro-
in response to apparent misunderstanding pean American and African American sto-
have been reported and discussed (Sawyer, rytelling genres are substantially different -
2006a). Patterns of differential participation with negative impacts on students whose
by different individuals can be analyzed; for cultural background does not match that of
example, in many classroom settings, stu- the teacher. Again, the situative perspective
dents' contributions almost always respond provides a framework that allows us to bet-
directly to a question by the teacher (e.g., ter understand cultural differences in learn-
Bellack, Kliebard, Hyman, Frank, & Smith, ing outcomes.)
1966; Mehan, 1979); discourse in other class-
room settings is arranged so that students
also respond to one another's presentations 7. The Emergence of Complex
and ideas (e.g., Cazden, 2001; O'Connor & Social Mechanisms
Michaels, 1993).
Communication includes not only what is The situative perspective within education
said but also how it is said and how it comes is part of a broad recent trend in the social
to be interpreted. In addition to character- sciences, a trend that goes by many names
istic participation structures, each culture but that is generally referred to as "com-
has its own distinctive discursive practices. plexity." The paradigm of complexity has
These practices include genre, style, catch- primarily been applied to physical and bio-
phrases, wordplay, and joint routines. One logical systems, with the observation that
of the speech genres most studied by edu-
theoretical analyses of some systems in terms
cation researchers is storytelling, or narra-
of their components are so complex that an
tive; narrative scholars have discovered that
analysis in holistic terms provides a more sat-
different cultures often have very different
discursive practices associated with story- isfactory understanding than a reductionist
analysis of the parts and then working back
R. KEITH SAWYER AND JAMES G. GREF.NO

up from the parts in interaction to the whole These characteristics have been found
system. a variety of complex systems that have
Many cognitive scientists have drawn on resisted reductionist explanation, from bi
complexity concepts to analyze the human logical organisms to human minds to eco
mind (e.g., Bechtel & Richardson, 1993). nomic systems. To the extent that the activ
The brain is undeniably composed of indi- ity systems associated with learning share
vidual neurons and their interactions, and these properties, their explanation is more
understanding the brain can contribute to likely to benefit from a situative approach
understanding mental processes. These facts (Sawyer, 2005).
have led several neuroscientists to pursue
the usual reductionist approach in science:
to understand the mind, first understand 8. Decomposition and
the behavior of individual neurons and col- Functional Localization
lections of neurons, then understand the
ways that neuronal structures interact, and Bechtel and Richardson (1993) described the
then work upward to understand cognitive strategy of mechanistic explanation, which
functions. However, many cognitive scien- explains the behavior of a system in terms
tists and philosophers of mind are skeptical of the behaviors and interactions of the sys-
about the prospective reduction of analyses tem's components. Mainly using examples
of mental states to analyses in terms of neu- from biology, they identified ways in which
rons and their interactions. And many who such explanations are similar and different.
accept the possibility of eventual reduction All mechanistic explanations involve the
still believe that the best way for current behavior of some system and hypotheses
science to proceed is to continue analyses at about the system's decomposition into com-
both the neuronal and the mental levels. ponents. The hypotheses of a mechanis-
The issues involved in the situative tic explanation include a decomposition of
approach are analogous to these debates functions, along with a decomposition into
within the philosophy of mind, but moved components and a functional analysis that
up a level of analysis from the mind to hypothesizes ways that the behaviors of
the activity system. As in the philosophy components and their interactions accom-
of mind, there are reductionist scientists - plish functions that, together, account for
the individualist cognitive scientists - who behaviors of the system as a whole.
believe that study of activity systems should Bechtel and Richardson's analyses show
proceed by first analyzing individual men- that mechanistic explanations differ in im-
tal states and processes of the people in portant ways. In some analyses, behavior of
the system, and then analyzing the peo- a system is explained as a simple aggregation
ple's interactions, thus working upward to of functions, each of which is accomplished
an understanding of the entire activity sys- by one of its components. According to such
tem. Situativity researchers are analogous an analysis, the system is simply decompos-
to the nonreductionist position in the phi- able.
losophy of mind: activity systems may not
be reducible to individual minds and their
interactions, or at least the best scientific 9. Decomposability
strategy for the field at this point in time
is to include work at both the individual and Simply decomposable systems are modu-
the activity-system levels. lar, with each component acting primar-
In this section, we list a few well- ily according to its own intrinsic principles.
established characteristics of complex sys- Each component is influenced by the others
tems that have been identified by complex- only at well-defined input points; its func-
ity scientists over the past two decades, tion (its internal processing of those inputs)
is not itself influenced by other components
especially by Bechtel and Richardson (1993).
SITUATTVITY AND LEARNING

fSirnon, 1969)- In such a system, the behav- on the function of any component; thus,
ior of any part is intrinsically determined: component function is no longer intrinsi-
•tis possible to determine the component's cally determined. Dependence of compo-
roperties in isolation from the other com- nents on one another is often mutual and
ponents, despite the fact that they interact. may even make it difficult to draw firm
The organization of the entire system is criti- boundaries between components (Bechtel &
cal for the function of the system as a whole. Richardson, 1993, pp. 26-27). Functions that
For example, one component's behavior constitute the system's performance are not
may depend on products of other compo- accomplished locally, by individual com-
nents. However, that organization does not ponents or definable sets of components.
provide constraints on the internal function- Rather, their accomplishments are the result
ing of components. of interactivity in the system as a whole.
Contemporary complexity theory has Examples of integrated-system explanations
also argued that in functionally localizable include connectionist models of cognitive
systems, it is easier to reduce the analysis processes such as pattern recognition (e.g.,
of the system to analysis of its compo- Bechtel 8c Richardson, 1993; McClelland &
nents. A system is localizable if the func- Rumelhart, 1986). Each component of a con-
tional decomposition of the system corre- nectionist system is a unit with the sim-
sponds to its physical decomposition, and ple property of being more or less active.
each property of the system can be identi- Connections between units transmit either
fied with a single component or subsystem. activation or inhibition; that is, one unit
If system functions or properties cannot be causes either an increase or a decrease in
identified with components, but are instead the activity level of another unit, with the
distributed spatially within the system, that amount of the change depending on its cur-
system is not functionally localized (Bechtel rent activity level. Running a connectionist
¿Richardson, 1993, p. 24). model involves computing the activity levels
Some examples of explanations that of its units over many cycles, starting with
hypothesize simple decompositions and some initial values, and with increased acti-
functional localizations are production sys- vation of some units because of an external
tems (e.g., Anderson, 1983; Newell, 1990). event, such as the appearance of a stimu-
Each component of a production system is lus. The collection of activation levels even-
a production rule, composed of a condition tually converges to some configuration, and
and an action. Conditions test patterns in the some configurations correspond to patterns.
database and actions add or change patterns The system recognizes a pattern by set-
in the database. On each cycle of its opera- tling into the configuration that corresponds
tion, the system tests the patterns of all the to it. Unlike a production-system model,
production rules, selects one that matches, the function of recognizing a pattern by a
and performs its actions. The behavior of connectionist network cannot be associated
each production rule depends on what other with a single unit or limited set of units.
rales do, only in that they produce pat- Instead, the configuration of activation for
terns that determine whether that produc- any recognizable pattern is achieved through
tion rule's condition is in the database. the connections between units throughout
There also are mechanistic explanations the network.
of what Bechtel and Richardson called Between the poles of simply decompos-
"integrated systems," in which compo- able systems and integrated systems, Bech-
nents behave very simply and functions are
tel and Richardson (1993) identified interme-
explained by hypotheses about the organi-
diate cases. Some explanations hypothesize
zation of the system; that is, by hypothe-
ses about interactions between components. nearly decomposable systems, with com-
In an integrated system, the overall sys- ponents whose behavior is mainly deter-
tem organization is a significant influence mined intrinsically, but with some nonneg-
ligible interactions (cf. Simon, 1969). Other
R. KEITH SAWYER AND JAMES G. GREf.NO

explanations hypothesize minimally decom- of processes of individual problem solvin


posable systems, in which the behavior of could be counterproductive.
the s y s t e m and its components is mainly Those individualist scientists who would
determined by interactions between compo- pursue the study of activity systems by
nents, but with some nonnegligible intrinsic focusing on individual minds are mak-
characteristics of components. ing a factoring assumption: the assumption
that activity systems are decomposable and
functionally localizable in the way Bech-
10. Deeomposability and Localizability tel and Richardson (1993) described. How-
of Activity Systems ever, studies by situativity researchers con-
clude that some activity systems are only
A fundamental strategic issue for situative minimally decomposable. This is the crux
researchers is whether we should assume of the controversy between situativity the-
that explanations of behavior of activity sys- orists and individualist cognitive scientists'
tems characterize them as decomposable or its resolution will ultimately rest on better
nearly decomposable systems, or whether understanding the nature of the composi-
we should assume that explanations of activ- tion of activity systems - a question that can
ity systems turn out to require treating them only be addressed by studying the behavior
as minimally decomposable or integrated of activity systems and evaluating the suc-
systems. cess of alternative explanatory accounts.
The most obvious decomposition of an
activity system treats its individual partic-
ipants as components, along with other u. Functional Localizability
material and informational systems that con-
tribute to the system's functioning. If an When individualist cognitive scientists ana-
activity system is decomposable or nearly lyze activity systems by focusing on one par-
decomposable into those components, then ticipant in the system, they typically assume
progress toward a mechanistic explanation functional localizability. For example, a
of its behavior can be made by studying the complex team activity is easier to reduce to
properties of individuals in the kinds of sit- an individual-level analysis if each member
uations that the activity system encounters. of the team handles only one information-
For example, the large body of research on processing function in the context of the
individuals solving problems has developed team. But when information functions are
concepts and principles that account for diffused and stretched across multiple mem-
many aspects of individual problem-solving bers of the team, explaining even one activ-
performance and learning. If the problem- ity system function requires explanations of
solving behavior of a group in an activity multiple participants' mental structures and
system is nearly decomposable into its indi- of their interactions over time.
vidual components, we can expect that the
In some activity systems, work is arranged
concepts and principles developed by study-
so that the distribution of cognitive func-
ing individual problem solving could pro- tions complies approximately with simple
vide the basis for explaining problem-solving decomposition and functional localization.
performance and learning by the group. For example, Hutchins's (1995a) study of
On the other hand, if the behavior of the navy ship-navigation teams showed that in
group is minimally decomposable or inte- its normal operation, each team member
grated in solving problems, then principles had a single function in which he took an
of interaction between individuals are essen- observation and reported it or received some
tial for explaining the group's performance information, performed a well-defined oper-
and learning, and attempting to explain per- ation on it, and passed the results along.
formance and learning by a group in terms We expect that an explanation of this
situa'nvlty and learning

activity as a nearly decomposable and func- gence (Sawyer, 2005). In contrast to the nat- |
tionally localized system could be devel- ural systems studied by most complexity I
oped successfully. However, in an incident theorists - gases or biological systems - the |
where there was a breakdown of the elec- additional complexity of human language, J
trical system, the team's cognitive function- with its complex symbolic interaction, is
ing became improvisational and distributed another characteristic that contributes to the 9
across several team members. When each irreducibility of activity systems.
component of team information process- In mechanical and biological systems, I
ing was associated with a single individual, component relations are relatively w H
the factoring assumption would hold true understood and well defined. Interactions |9
and the activity system could potentially between gas molecules in a container can
be understood by beginning with individual be characterized using a few variables, such 1
cognitive analysis and then working up to as mass, direction, and velocity. In con-
the team level. But when each step of infor- trast, human communication is qualitatively
mation processing was diffused across multi- more complex for many reasons; for exam-
ple participants and accomplished by a pro- ple, people are capable of metacommuni-
cess involving significant interaction, then cating about their ongoing interaction whde
the factoring assumption would not hold, it is under way, a property not found in the
and a valid information-processing analy- interactions of any other complex system.
sis, such as the one Hutchins (1995a) pro- And the nature of peoples' interactions with
vided, has to be done at the activity-system technological artifacts is equally complex.
level. The complex nature of interaction in activ-
ity systems makes them difficult to reduce
to individual cognitive analysis.
12. Complex C o m m u n i c a t i o n
among Units
13. Implications of Distributed
In complexity theory, notions of emer- Cognition for Decomposability
gence are based on interactions and relations and Functional Localization
among the component parts. For example,
the criteria of nondecomposabdity and non- Situativity researchers within education
localizability are all defined in terms of the begin by observing that learning occurs
complex systemic relations among compo- in complex social situations, often with a
nents. In many-bodied physics, the inter- wide variety of designed and technolog-
actions are between molecules of a gas; in ical artifacts (e.g., textbooks, lab equip-
neuroscience, the interactions are synaptic ment, tools of the trade, computer soft-
transfer between neurons. Whether such ware). Most learning environments contain
a system is decomposable or functionally multiple individuals - particularly environ-
localizable is always determined by the ments that are explicidy designed to facd-
nature of the interactions among units. Gen- itate learning, such as school classrooms
erally speaking, more simplistic interactions or apprenticeship interactions. And even
are more likely to result in reducible sys- when an individual is apparendy learning
tems, because simplistic interactions are not alone, that learning always requires inter-
capable of supporting the high information action with complex designed artifacts that
transfer among components required to sup- resulted from a historical and social pro-
port functional diffusion or nondecompos- cess; for example, an individual may leam
ability. Consequently, several complexity from reading a book in solitude, but that
theorists have suggested that the complexity book was written and published through a
of each interaction among components may complex and multistage organizational pro-
be another variable contributing to emer- cess, and the individual chose and acquired
r. keith sawyer a n d james g. gref.no

that particular hook through another com- pected task. Instead of planning it first th
plex and social process. Although situativ- team improvised a response, one that turned
ity researchers assume that all learning is out to be quite effective. Two team mem-
situated - in the sense that even when an bers evolved a new way to interact during
individual is alone, that solitude itself is the sixty-six location fixes that were taken
socially constructed according to historically during this tense time. When he analyzed
and culturally contingent norms - in empiri- his videotapes later, Hutchins found that the
cal practice, they almost always study learn- team had explored at least thirteen different
ing in groups, and typically in groups that are organizational structures until, after about
working with a variety of complex designed thirty fixes had been taken, an effective
artifacts. structure emerged. Hutchins (1995a) was so
Hutchins (1995a) reported an influential impressed that he began to think of the team
study of group learning that we consider as if it had its own brain: "the solution was
instructive regarding prospects for develop- clearly discovered by the organization itself
ing explanations of learning in activity sys- before it was discovered by any of the par-
tems. Hutchins analyzed a navigation team ticipants" (p. 351).
working on a navy ship. He found that the Many learning environments are complex
navigation task was cognitively distributed social systems that contain multiple peo-
among the members of the team, in what ple, some more knowledgeable than oth-
he referred to as "distributed cognition." The ers; a wide range of physical and techno-
official training manuals and training courses logical artifacts; and emergent and evolving
specified procedures for interaction and for cultural practices that bring together people
how to use the complex technical devices and artifacts. These activity systems share
on the bridge, but what actually happened properties w i t h other complex systems that
on the navigation bridge very often diverged are not explained simply by intrinsic prop-
from the official, documented practice. In erties of their components: they are not sim-
several cases, no one actually knew exactly ply decomposable or directly functionally
how the entire system was operating, even localizable, at least according to current con-
though Hutchins was able to demonstrate ceptual resources and methods, but possi-
that the system's emergent group practice bly because activity systems may be inher-
was optimal. ently integral or minimally decomposable
Throughout his study, Hutchins exam- systems. 2 It is in this sense that learning
ined how newcomers learned to participate environments are complex social systems,
in this complex activity system. But he also w i t h emergent group properties that can-
found that it was not only the newcomers not be reduced to the mental structures of
who were learning; in some cases, the entire the individual participants without taking
team was engaged in distributed learning. account of communicative and other inter-
For example, in one very tense situation actions between the individuals.
when the team's equipment broke down, T h e situative approach to learning ana-
which we mentioned earlier, the entire team
had to collectively improvise and figure out lyzes learning environments as complex
a new way to distribute the cognitive task social systems. In keeping with the com-
on the fly. plexity project more generally, the situa-
tive approach resists reduction of learning
There was no official procedure for deter- environments to individual mental knowl-
mining the ship's exact location when the edge structures. T h e preferred method is to
equipment failed, and it turned out to be a analyze the interactional mechanisms occur-
complicated design problem to calculate ring w i t h i n the learning system by using
the best way to distribute tasks among the the methodologies of interaction analysis.
group. The team had no time for com- Sawyer (2005) has argued that the key fea-
plicated design; they had only minutes to ture of collaborative groups that results
reconfigure the group to handle the unex- in irreducible emergent properties is the
srruATivrry a n d u a r n i n c

¡ eX communication enabled by human as interacting with a computer program, 1


exchanging e-mail messages, conversing on
language-
The key to understanding learning in th e telephone, or performing scripted drama 4
complex social groups is to analyze the pro- or scored music, need to be analyzed to 1
cesses of communication and to simulta- determine the kinds of functional decompo^fl
neously analyze (1) how these processes give sition and localization that provide the most 1
rise to emergent social properties, (2) to satisfactory explanations.
what extent those processes result in indi- As learning scientists, we are especially 1
vidual knowledge, and (3) to what extent concerned with the nature of explanatiol^H
that individual knowledge can be marshaled of activity in learning environments; t h a t M l
by the learner for use in a different complex in activity systems that are organized d d i ^ H
social group (i.e., a different situation). erately for learning to occur. We expect t h a f j a
explanations of learning environments d i n |
fer in the kinds of explanations that can M
u. Explanations D i f f e r D e p e n d i n g be developed, depending on the social prac- 8
on Activities a n d S o c i a l P r a c t i c e s tices of their activity systems. For example, 1
in classrooms that are organized iliilu l i J
Not all activity systems are alike, and the cally, with a teacher making extensive pre- I
kind of explanation that can be developed sentations, with discourse mainly consist-
for some activity systems may not be achiev- ing of initiation-response-evaluation (IRE)
able for others. More specifically, we expect exchanges, and with most of the students'
that aspects of a group's social practices - the learning activity consisting of individual J
regularities of the group's interactive behav- seatwork and homework, it seems plausible
ior as it functions as an activity system - to expect successful explanations that char- 1
determine the degree of decomposability acterize the activity as nearly decomposable 9
and functional localizability that can be and functionally localized systems. On the
assumed in explaining the group's activities. other hand, in classrooms that are organized
For example, an individual reading a page primarily for collaborative learning activities
of printed text is an activity system that has with discourse patterns that include revok-
been explained successfully w i t h local func- ing and other exchanges between students,
tionality and simple decomposability. T h e we expect that successful explanations will 1
physical text, after all, does not change in require assuming minimal decomposability
the process of its being read. This does not and achievement of functions by interaction
contradict our assertion that reading a text rather than intrinsic properties of the indi-
should be understood as an activity embed- vidual teachers and students.
ded in a social context, but while the person
is alone, interacting with a text, the mean-
ings that he or she attributes to the text are 15. B r i n g i n g T o g e t h e r Individual
a function of the physical t e x t and charac- Learning and G r o u p Learning
teristics of the person. In contrast, we are
confident that the activity system of a face- Although situativity researchers emphasize
to-face conversation needs to be analyzed as that learning environments always contain
a minimally decomposable system in which complex activity systems, they nonethe-
functions are achieved through joint action, less are interested in the learning associ-
not localized in the contributions of individ- ated with individual participants, as well
ual participants (Clark, 1996; S a w y e r , 2005). as the learning that corresponds to trans-
Sawyer's (2003a, 2003b) studies of improvi- formations in the entire activity system.
sational theater and jazz p e r f o r m a n c e also But unlike traditional cognitive psychology,
provide clear cases requiring analyses as min- individual cognition is considered in relation
imally decomposable and functionally non- to transformations of the activity system. For
localized systems. Intermediate cases, such example, in inquiry classrooms, students'
r. keith sawyer a n d james g. g r e f . n o

understandings are shared as they f o r m u - 16. Example 1: A Study of Learning


late and evaluate questions, and propose a Classroom Practice
and debate alternative meanings of con-
cepts and explanations. Analyses can con- To illustrate h o w learning scientists can
sider whether the actions of individual stu- study t h e learning of practices using the situ
dents contribute to the class's progress in ative perspective, we describe two case stud
achieving shared understanding, rather than ies. In this section, we summarize Hall and
simply being displays of the understandings R u b i n ' s (1998) analysis of how a new rep.
they have already constructed cognitively resentational practice became established in
in their prior interactions with textbooks, a classroom (following Greeno, 1998). They
teachers, and computers. d o c u m e n t e d h o w the practice originated in
Developing a situative explanation re- an individual's w o r k , expanded through that
quires a simultaneous consideration of both student's small group, and then was broad-
the transformations of the entire activity sys- cast to t h e class.
tem and of participants' knowledge struc- T h e teacher, Magdalene Lampert, devel-
tures that are used in the activity. These o p e d innovative practice-oriented teaching
analyses often use many of the concepts m e t h o d s and e x a m i n e d the processes of her
that are standard in cognitive science; they teaching f o r several years. Lampert often
differ in that they are based on records of had t h e students w o r k in groups of four
conversation between participants (rather or five students to discuss challenging prob-
than laboratory experiments or think-aloud lems. E a c h student kept a journal in which
protocols). Situative studies bring cognitive he or she r e c o r d e d problem solutions and
science and interaction analysis together by explanations. Hall and Rubin (1998) ana-
providing analyses of interaction in activity lyzed v i d e o t a p e d records of several segments
systems and including hypotheses about of class activity that illustrate Lampert's
structures of information used and con- approach to teaching about distance, time,
structed in the activity. These analyses in- and s p e e d of m o t i o n - all key concepts in ele-
clude representing contributions of the mentary mathematics. They analyzed sev-
material and technological tools and arti- eral incidents in the development and use
facts of the system. The goal is to under- of a kind of representational practice that
stand cognition as the interaction among they called a "journey line," which repre-
participants and tools in the context of an sents t w o quantities - time and distance -
activity. For this reason, it is often said that by marking units along the line that are
the situative perspective studies distributed labeled w i t h distances above the line and
cognition: problem solving, planning, and times b e l o w the line. T h e journey-line rep-
reasoning are accomplished by a group of resentation w a s used by a student, Karim,
people, working together with complex to explain to another student, Ellie, why
technological artifacts and with external one of the p r o b l e m s should be solved using
representations they generate during the multiplication. Later, Lampert asked Karim
task (e.g., diagrams, figures, models). to explain the representation to the class.
A f t e r K a r i m ' s presentation, Lampert had
Thus, an analysis in the situative per-
Ellie explain t h e representation to the class,
spective can analyze three levels simulta-
affirming that it was a resource to be used
neously: starting with the symbolic interac-
generally in t h e class's practice.
tion among members of the group, working
up toward an analysis of the emergent group Hall and R u b i n (1998) distinguished
properties that result, and working down between three levels of activity: private
toward an analysis of the thinking pro- activity (writing in the journal), local activ-
cesses and knowledge structures perceived ity (small-group conversation), and public
and constructed by one or more of the indi- activity (presentations and discussions with
viduals participating in the group. the w h o l e class). T h e y identified several
s1tuativity and learning

•flteractions in which the representational this laboratory, they had to expand the tra-
oractice of the journey line played a key ditional cognitive science notions of prob- §
roje - it functioned as a resource in the lern space and mental representation to con- 1
class's practices of problem solving and sider these distributed across the people j
mutual sensemaking. Learning-sciences re- and the technology in the laboratory - a I
search often examines the role of represen- defining feature of situative research. The
tational forms as resources for collaborative problem space comprises models and arti-
sensemaking and reasoning. It also exam- facts together with a repertoire of activities 1
ines the ways that students talk about their in which simulative model-based reasoning
developing understanding. plays a key role (Lehrer & Schäuble, 2006).
The problem-solving processes of the lab
are distributed throughout the cognitive sys- M
17. Example 2: A Study of Learning tem, which comprises both the researchers
in a Scientific W o r k Environment and the cognitive artifacts that they use.
They used a mixed-method approach,
The second case study we describe was a combining cognitive analyses of the prob-
study by Nersessian and her colleagues of lems and models used by researchers with an
how laboratory groups develop over time ethnographic analysis of the situative activ-
towards increasing understanding (Nerses- ities and tools and how they are used in
sian, 2005; Nersessian, Kurz-Milcke, New- the ongoing activity of the laboratory. Their
stetter, & Davies, 2003). They found it pro- close ethnographic analysis allowed them to
ductive to consider activity in the scientific document temporary and transient arrange-
laboratory they studied as an evolving ments of the activity system - the laboratory
distributed cognitive system. For example, routines, the organization of the workspace,
Nersessian et al. (2003) gave a situative the cultural artifacts being used, and the
interpretation of several aspects of learning social organization of the team members.
in a bioengineering lab that was trying to Their cognitive analysis allowed them to
develop artificial blood vessels: the evolu- document how people and their relation-
tion of artifacts and methods, the evolution ships changed over time - as they evaluated
of relationships between individuals, and the and revised problem definitions (often work-
evolution of relationships between individ- ing closely with technological artifacts), as
uals and artifacts. they revised models of phenomena, and as
Biomedical engineering is a new combi- their concepts changed over time.
nation of disciplines in which new knowl- Because it is impossible to test artificial
edge and practices are emerging continually, blood vessels in a live human body, model-
and the researchers are constantly learning ing practices are critical to the work. The
during their problem-solving activities. The researchers have to design working mod-
laboratory team included undergraduates, els to use for experimentation. Each iter-
doctoral students, and postdocs, and all of ation of a model represents the lab's col-
these participants learned over time and lective understanding of the properties and
transformed their participation in the activ- behaviors of the human body. For example,
ity system. Much of the equipment used the flow loop is a device that emulates the
in the laboratory is designed and built by shear stresses experienced by cells within
the team, and the members of the team the blood vessels. The flow loop originated
often modify the technological artifacts dur- in the research of the senior scientist and
has been passed down through generations
ing their practice - such that not only the
of researchers, enabling each to build on the
people but also the tools undergo change
research of others, as it is reengineered in the
over time.
service of model-based reasoning. The flow
Nersessian et al. (2003) found that to loop is constructed so that the test fluid will
understand how problems were solved in
r. keith s a w y e r a n d james g. g r e f . n o

create the same lands of mechanical stresses 18. C o n c l u s i o n


as a real blood vessel. But because the model
is a mechanical system, its design is subject Education research has contributed substan-
to engineering constraints, and these often tially to the situated cognition approach
require simplification and idealization of the beginning in the 1980s, when cognitive scien-
target biological systems being modeled. For tists first began to realize the situated nature
example, in the body arterial wall, motion of cognition and learning. Most of the semi-
is a response to the pulsating blood flow, nal empirical studies that contributed to the
but in the flow-loop simulation, known as a emergence of the situated approach were
bioreactor, the fluid does not actually flow; conducted in learning environments. The
but it does model the pulsating changes situative approach has increased in influence
in pressure experienced by the arterial in education research, from the late 1980s
wall. to the present. It is a core element of the
In scientific laboratories, collaboration is new interdisciplinary field of the learning
often mediated by external representations sciences (Sawyer, 2006b).
such as these mechanical models, as well In this chapter we have written about the
as diagrams and sketches. In this lab, devices situative approach to learning rather than
are external representations of the collective situated learning. Even if the researcher is a
knowledge of the group. Model-based rea- traditional cognitive psychologist, interested
soning is a distributed phenomenon, involv- exclusively in how individual mental struc-
ing both the internal mental models that a tures change during learning, that individ-
researcher holds, as well as the shared exter- ual's learning will nonetheless be situated.
nal model manifested in devices and other The laboratory settings used by experimen-
models. tal cognitive psychologists are situations -
A situative analysis focuses on this dis- complex activity systems - and the learning
tributed nature of cognition in the labo- that occurs in such experiments is just as sit-
ratory, treating it as a distributed process uated as a tailor's apprenticeship or a child's
involving multiple people and the techno- learning a first language.
logical artifacts that they create and modify Researchers taking a situative perspective
together. In the situative view of an activity generally accept that individuals do, in fact,
system, learning is conceived of as transfor- learn in these situations; and that individual
mations over time in the nature of the inter- mental structures certainly change as part of
actions among people and between people this learning. T h e situative approach is com-
and their constructed artifacts. For example, plementary and compatible with traditional
when newcomers to the lab are first intro- cognitive psychology, and both approaches
duced to a device like the bioreactor, they contribute important pieces of the puzzle
assume that its design is fixed. As they begin of how people learn. However, the situ-
to interact with these devices, they quickly ative approach changes the way we think
leam the many problems: tubes leak, sutures about and use the findings of experimental
do not keep, reservoirs overflow, pumps psychology. It problematizes the decompos-
malfunction. The newcomers soon realize ability assumption typically made by tradi-
that everyone else, including the most expe- tional psychologists and suggests that, before
rienced old-timer, is always struggling to get scientists can really understand what these
things to work, always revising and modify- experiments have taught us, we first have to
ing the devices. The newcomer's learning is a analyze the experiment itself as a complex
process of coming to understand the contin- activity system - in other words, apply the
gent and changing nature of these devices - situative approach to experimental settings.
the newcomers build a relationship with the
devices that Nersessian et al. (2003) called a The situative approach will continue to
"cognitive partnership." be central to the learning sciences, because
this new interdisciplinary field is increasingly
s r r u A T i v r r y AND l e a r n i n g

demonstrating that learning is most effec- theories) that provides strong explanation*
tive when students work collaboratively to activity systems as nearly decomposable and
solve authentic problems in rich, real-world localizable systems.
tasks. In these new learning environments, it
is extremely difficult to be misled into think-
ing that individual students learn in isola- References
tion - whereas in the traditional method of
instructionist teaching, when students sat in Anderson, J. R. (1982). Acquisition of cognitive
rows at desks and were expected to inter- skill. Psychological Review, 89, 396-406.
nalize the teacher's pronouncements, one Anderson, J. R. (1983). The architecture of cog-
could more easily assume that learning was nition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University M
about internalizing the knowledge struc- Press.
Anderson, J. R., Boyle, C. F., Corbett, A. T., g
tures being explained by the teacher. A situ-
Lewis, M. W. (1990}. Cognitive modeling and
ative approach can make an important con-
intelligent tutoring. Artificial Intelligence, 42,
tribution to understanding how these new
7-50.
forms of learning take place and how we Anderson, J. R., Reder, L. M., & Simon, H. A
can design learning environments to be most (1996). Situated learning and education. Edu-
effective. cational Researcher, 25(4), 5-11.
Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (1993). D i s c o v e r ' §
ing complexity: Decomposition and localization
Notes as strategies in scientific research. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
i An analogy with physics is instructive. Mea- Bellack, A. A., Kliebard, H. M., Hyman, R. T,
surement of a moving object's velocity only Frank, L., & Smith, J. (1966). The language of
makes sense if a frame of reference is the classroom. New York: Teacher's College
specified. Assessment situations for assessing Press.
knowledge are akin to frames of reference for Bobrow, D. G., 8c Collins, A. (1975). Represen-
measuring properties of motion. Of course, tation and understanding: Studies in cognitive
the complexity of assessing what a person science. New York: Academic Press.
knows is much greater than the complexity Brown, J. S., Collins, A., 8c Duguid, P. (1989).
of measuring how an object is moving, but Situated cognition and the culture of learning.
the need to interpret findings of assessment Educational Researcher, 18(1), 32-42.
in ways that take account of the frame of Carpenter, T. P., 8c Fennema, E. (1992). Cog-
reference involved in the assessment is anal- nitively guided instruction: Building on the
ogous. knowledge of students and teachers. Interna-
| The two of us differ in the strengths of tional Journal of Educational Research, IJ, 457-
our pessimism about the prospects of devel- 470.
oping a reductionist or mechanistic expla- Cazden, C. B. (2001). Classroom discourse: The
nation of cognitive processes in groups. In language of teaching and learning (2nd ed.).
R. K. S.'s view, reduction of those activity Portsmouth, NH: Heinemann.
systems that are highly integrated, even if Chi, M. T. H. (1997). Quantifying qualitative
one day possible in principle, might not add analyses of verbal data: A practical guide.
to the scientific knowledge of those systems Journal of the Learning Sciences, 6(3), 271-
that we had already acquired through analysis 3J5-
at the activity-system level and could require Clark, H. H. (1996). Using language. Cambridge:
a vastly greater investment of resources (see Cambridge University Press.
Sawyer, 2005). In J. G. G.'s view, simple Collins, A. (2006). Cognitive apprenticeship. In
reduction of activity systems is out of reach R. K. Sawyer (Ed.), The Cambridge handbook
now, given the theoretical resources that of the learning sciences (pp. 47-60). New York:
are available. However, future developments, Cambridge University Press.
such as better understanding how individu- Collins, A., Brown, J. S., 8c Newman, S. E.
als are sensitive to one another's communica- (1989). Cognitive apprenticeship: Teaching
tive intentions, could result in a theory (or the craft of reading, writing, and mathematics.
R. keith s a w y e r a n d james g. g r e f . n o

In L B Resnick (Ed.), Knowing, learning, and In J. G. Greeno 8c S. V. Goldman f£ds 1


instruction: Essays in honor of Robert Glaser Thinking practices in mathematics and science
(pp. 455-494). Mahwah, N,I: Lawrence learning (pp. 189-235). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence
EHbaum. Erlbaum.
diSessa, A. A., & Minstrell, J. (1998). Cultivating Hutchins, E. (1995a). Cognition in the wild Cam
conceptual change with benchmark lessons. bridge, MA: MIT Press.
In J. G. Greeno & S. V. Goldman (Eds.), Hutchins, E. (1995b). How a cockpit remembers
Thinking practices in mathematics and science its speeds. Cognitive Science, 19, 265-288.
learning (pp. 155-187). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Jordan, B., & Henderson, A. (1995). Interaction
Erlbaum. analysis: Foundations and practice. Journal of
Engestrom, Y., Miettinen, R., & Punamaki, R. the Learning Sciences, 4(1), 39-103.
(Eds.). (1999). Perspectives on activity theory. Kintsch, W. (1998). Comprehension: A paradim
New York: Cambridge University Press. for cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press.
Erickson, F., & Mohatt, G. (1982). Cultural orga-
nization of participation structures in two Klahr, D. (Ed.). (1976). Cognition and instruction
classrooms of Indian students. In G. Spindler Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
(Ed.), Doing the ethnography of schooling Lave, J. (1988). Cognition in practice: Mind, math-
(pp. 152-174). New York: Holt, Rinehart 8c ematics, and culture in everyday life. New York-
Winston. Cambridge University Press.
Falk, J. (1980). The conversational duet. In B. R. Lave, J. ( 1 9 9 7 ) . The culture of acquisition and
Caron (Ed.), Proceedings of the Sixth Annual the practice of understanding. In D. Kirshner
Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society 8c J. Whitson (Eds.), Situated cognition: Social
(pp. 507-514). Berkeley: University of Califor- semiotic, and psychological perspectives (pp. n-
nia, Berkeley. 35). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Goodwin, C. (2000). Practices of color classi- Lave, J., Murtaugh, M., 8c de la Rocha, 0. (1984),
fication. Mind, Culture, and Actiinty, 7, 1 9 - The dialectic of arithmetic in grocery shop-
36. ping. In B. Rogoff 8c J. Lave (Eds.), Every-
Goodwin, C., & Goodwin, M. H. (1996). Seeing day cognition: Its development in social context
as situated activity: Formulating planes. In Y. (pp. 6 7 - 9 4 ) . Cambridge, MA: Harvard Uni-
Engestrom & D. Middleton (Eds.), Cognition versity Press.
and communication at work (pp. 61-95). New Lave, J., 8c Wenger, E. (1991). Situated learning:
York: Cambridge University Press. Legitimate peripheral participation. New York:
Greenfield, P., 8c Lave, J. (1982). Cognitive Cambridge University Press.
aspects of informal education. In D. Wagner 8c Lehrer, R., 8c Schauble, L. (2006). Cultivating
H. Stevenson (Eds.), Cultural perspectives on model-based reasoning in science education.
child development (pp. 181-207). San Francisco: In R. K. Sawyer (Ed.), The Cambridge hand-
W. H. Freeman. book of the learning sciences (pp. 371-387). New
Greeno, J. G. (1989). Situations, mental mod- York: Cambridge University Press.
els and generative knowledge. In D. Klahr McClelland, J., Rumelhart, D., 8c Parallel Dis-
& K. Kotovsky (Eds.), Complex information tributed Research Group (Eds.). (1986). Par-
processing: The impact of Herbert A. Simon allel distributed processing: Explorations in the
(pp. 285-318). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence microstructure of cognition. Cambridge, MA:
Erlbaum. MIT Press/Bradford.
Greeno, J. G. (1997). On claims that answer Mehan, H. ( 1 9 7 9 ) . Learning lessons. Cambridge,
the wrong questions. Educational Researcher, MA: Harvard University Press.
26(1), 5-17. Michaels, S. (1981). "Sharing time": Children's
Greeno, J. G, (1998). The situativity of knowing, narrative styles and differential access to lit-
learning, and research. American Psychologist, eracy. Language in Society, 10, 423-442.
53' 5-z6- Nersessian, N. J. (2005). Interpreting scientific
Greeno, J. G., & Moore, J. L. (1993). Situativity and engineering practices: Integrating the cog-
and symbols: Response to Vera and Simon. nitive, social, and cultural dimensions. In
Cognitive Science, 17,49-59. M. Gorman, R. Tweney, D. Gooding, & A.
Hall, R., & Rubin, A. (1998). There's five little Kincannon (Eds.), Scientific and technological
notches in here: Dilemmas in teaching and thinking (pp. 17-56). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence
learning the conventional structure of rate. Erlbaum.
s1tuativity and learning

Mersessian, N. J-, Kurz-Milcke, E., Newstet- Sawyer, R. K. (Ed.). (2006b) The Cambridf |
,er W. C., & Da vies, J. (2003). Research handbook of the learning sciences. New Y o r k l s
laboratories as evolving distributed cogni- Cambridge University Press.
tive systems. Proceedings of the Cognitive Sci- Scribner, S. (1984). Studying working i n U n S
ence Society 25 (pp. 857-862). Hillsdale, NJ: gence. In B. Rogoff & J. Lave (Eds.), Every- I
Lawrence Erlbaum. day cognition: Its development in social contBOeM
Newell, A. (1990). Unified theories of cognition. (pp. 9 - 4 0 ) . Cambridge, MA: Harvard UmvqjM
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. sity Press.
Newell, A., 8c Simon, H. A. (1972). Human prob- Simon, H. A. (1969). The sciences of the artificial. 1
lem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Hall. Sleeman, D., 8c Brown, J. S. (Eds.). (1982). Intel- 1
Nunes, T., Schliemann, A. D., 8c Carraher, D. W. ligent tutoring systems. New York: Academic
(1993)- Street mathematics and school math- Press.
ematics. New York: Cambridge University Sowder, J. T. (1989). Research agenda for math- '
Press. ematics education: Vol. 5. Setting a research, 1
O'Connor, M. C., 8c Michaels, S. (1993). Align- agenda. Reston, VA: National Council of I
ing academic task and participation status Teachers of Mathematics.
through revoicing: Analysis of a classroom dis- Suchman, L. A. (1987). Plans and situated actions: |
course strategy. Anthropology and Education The problem of human-machine communication. %
Quarterly, 24(4), 318-335. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Palincsar, A. S., 8c Brown, A. L. (1984). Recipro- VanLehn, K., Lynch, C., Schulze, K_, Shapiro,
cal teaching of comprehension-fostering and J. A., Shelby, R., Taylor, L., et al. (2005). The
comprehension-monitoring activities. Cogni- Andes physics tutor: Five years of evaluations. 5
tion and Instruction, l, 117-175. In G. McCalla 8c C. K. Looi (Eds.), Proceedings
Philips, S. U. (1972). Participant structures and of the nth International Conference of Artificial
communicative competence: Warm Springs Intelligence and Education (pp. 678-685). Am-
children in community and classroom. In C. B. sterdam: IOS Press.
Cazden, V. P. John, 8c D. Hymes (Eds.), Func- Vera, A. H., 8c Simon, H. A. (1993). Situated
tions of language in the classroom (pp. 370-394). action: A symbolic interpretation. Cognitive
New York: Teacher's College Press. Science, Special Issue: Situated Action, 17(1),
Rogoff, B. (1990). Apprenticeship in thinking: Cog- 7-48.
nitive development in social context. New York: Wenger, E. (1987). Artificial intelligence and
Oxford University Press. tutoring systems: Computational and cognitive
Sawyer, R. K. (2003a). Group creatiinty: Music, approaches to the communication of knowledge.
theater, collaboration. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence San Francisco: Morgan Kaufmann.
Erlbaum. Wertsch, J. V. (1991). Voices of the mind: A sotioM
Sawyer, R. K. (2003b). Improvised dialogues: cultural approach to mediated action. Cam-
Emergence and creativity in conversation. West- bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
port, CT: Greenwood. Wertsch, J. V. (1998). Mind as action. New York;
Sawyer, R. K. (2005). Social emergence: Societies as Oxford University Press.
complex systems. New York: Cambridge Uni- Winograd, T., 8c Flores, F. (1986). Understand-
versity Press. ing computers and cognition. Norwood, NJ:
Sawyer, R. K. (2006a). Analyzing collabora- Ablex.
tive discourse. In R. K. Sawyer (Ed.), The Wood, D., Bruner, J., 8c Ross, G. (1976). The
Cambridge handbook of the learning sciences role of tutoring in problem solving. Journal
(pp. 187-204). New York: Cambridge Univer- of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 17, 8 9 -
sity Press. 100.
CHAPTER 19

Language in the Brain, Body, and World

Rolf A. Zwaan and Michael P. Kaschak

i. Introduction guage. For example, understanding a sen-


tence about removing an apple pie from the
Language is a uniquely human tool. It helps oven would involve the retrieval of traces
us situate ourselves in the world around us of motor experience (lifting the pie and
by directing our attention to people, objects, feeling its weight) and perceptual experi-
events, and possibilities for action. Language ence (seeing and smelling the pie, feeling
also situates us in worlds separate from our the heat coming out of the oven). The rel-
immediate environment. Through descrip- evant memory retrieval occurs by probing
tions of real or imagined events, it serves the same sensorimotor processing mecha-
to draw our attention to people, objects, nisms that would be involved if one were
events, and possibilities for action that are actually lifting, seeing, and smelling the pie
not present in the here and now. This situ- (Barsalou, 1999). In a very literal sense, the
ating of oneself in events outside of the here comprehension of a sentence about remov-
and now takes place through a process of ing the pie from the oven relies on much
mental simulation. the same machinery that would be involved
Mental simulation can be considered a in actually carrying out the action. Under-
vicarious experiencing of the events being standing the sentence also involves the reso-
described. Language is a sequence of stimuli nance of experiential traces of having heard,
that orchestrate the retrieval of experiential read, spoken, and written the words in the
traces of people, places, objects, events, and sentence.
actions. This retrieval occurs in part via a A number of recent studies have pointed
rapid, direct, and passive memory process to the conclusion that the ability to mentally
similar to the resonance process described simulate actions (and their consequences)
by Hintzman (1986). The experiential traces is crucial to our ability to plan and exe-
reflect the comprehenders' past experience cute actions, and to understand the actions
with particular objects, actions, and events, of others (e.g., Flanagan & Johansson, 2003;
as well as their previous experience with lan- Wolpert, Doya, & Kawato, 2003). These data

368
ROLF A. 7.WAAN AND MICHAEL P. KASOIAK

form the basis of our claims about the role of ing next in the story) can facilitate language fa
mental simulation in language comprehen- comprehension (e.g., Hess, Foss, & Carroll, J
sion Just as we understand the actions of 1995). More broadly, knowledge about par-
^ers by internally simulating their actions, ticular genres of language use allows COÊÊ^K
can understand the actions of people prehenders to anticipate the content and
described in language through an internal structure of a text, and thus tailor their
simulation of their actions (e.g., Glenberg & reading strategies in appropriate ways (e.g.,
Kaschak, 2002; Zwaan & Taylor, 2006). Thus, Zwaan, 1994). This anticipation is guided aj
language comprehension is grounded in the both by one's experience with real actions m
same knowledge and processes that are used and events in the world and by one's previ- 1
to support comprehension and conceptual-
ous experiences with language.
ization in many other domains (Barsalou,
The claim that language processing
1999,2005).
involves the rapid use of information that
The ability to experience situations vicar- points toward likely next states in the lin-
iously is adaptive. It allows us to learn from guistic input is consistent with constraint-
(and empathize with) others' past experi- satisfaction views of language processing
ences and to coordinate future actions. This (e.g., Jurafsky, 1996; MacDonald, Pearlmut-
provides the basis for anticipating future ter, 8c Seidenberg, 1994; McRae, Spivey-
states within ourselves (or others) and in the Knowlton, 8c Tanenhaus, 1998). On this
environment. We call the process through view, sentence processing proceeds by acti- g
which this anticipation arises "presonance." vating many possible interpretations for the I
Presonance captures the idea that the quick- sentence. These interpretations compete for
acting and passive memory retrieval posited activation on the basis of probabilistic infor-
in theories such as Hintzman's (1986) does mation from the comprehender's experi-
more than simply bring forth past experi- ence with language. The likelihood of a
ences; it also brings forth experiential m e m - particular word being used in a particular
ory traces that facilitate the processing of syntactic function (MacDonald et al., 1994),
likely changes to the self or the environment. the likelihood of a particular syntactic
The ability to anticipate such changes to structure being used (Jurafsky, 1996), the
the self or the environment is crucial to the preceding context (e.g., Spivey 8c Tanen-
ability to plan and take action in the world haus, 1998; van Berkum, Brown, Zwitser-
(for a discussion of the role of trajectories lood, Kooijman, 8c Hagoort, 2005), and other
of events in memory and m e m o r y retrieval, such factors are simultaneously considered
see Glenberg, 1997). For example, w h e n we as the language-processing system works to
see a barking dog charge t o w a r d us, previ- develop the most likely interpretation of the
ous experience with similar situations tells sentence. When the language refers to ele-
us that the dog will continue its approach. ments of the here and now (rather than a
Thus, we can prepare f o r this future state displaced situation), additional factors (e.g.,
(approaching dog) by taking action to pro- the affordances of the objects present in
tect ourselves. It is important to stress that the environment; Chambers, Tanenhaus, 8c
presonance should be v i e w e d as an auto- Magnuson, 2004) also exert an influence
matic and fast process and not as deliberative on on-line sentence comprehension (see
Spivey 8c Richardson, this volume). There is
prediction.
now considerable evidence that these
In the context of language processing,
sources of information are used as soon as
presonance operates on m a n y levels. Antic-
they are available to the language-compre-
ipating the next elements in the linguis-
hension system.
tic input - be they phonemes, words, or
syntactic constructions - serves to facilitate Closer to our notion of mental simula-
the processing of those elements. Anticipat- tion, presonance may be based on a covert
ing subsequent changes in the events being use of the language-production system
described (on a basic level, w h a t is com- (Pickering & Garrod, 2004; Townsend 81
LANGUAGE IN THE BRAIN, BODY, AND WORLD

a c c o m p a n y a stick shift. Instead of this


Bever, 2001). On the most basic level, there
sequence of sensorimotor activations, the
is evidence to suggest that our perception of
automatic-shift driver might only activate an
speech sounds involves the activation (res-
auditory representation of the sound associ-
onance) of the motor programs that would
ated with a stick shift.
be used to produce those sounds ourselves
A n o t h e r m a j o r factor in the depth of
(e.g., Porter & Lubker, 1980; for a brief
one's vicarious experience is the compre-
review and discussion, see Fowler, 1996).
The use of one's language-production sys- hender's language comprehension skill. On
tem while processing language also takes the v i e w outlined here, language compre-
place on higher levels of analysis. The gen- hension skill reflects one's sensitivity to
eral idea behind this premise is that com- linguistic constructs, as reflected in the
prehended would continuously but subcon- strength of t h e links between linguistic con-
sciously ask the question, What would I say structions - experiential traces themselves -
or write here if I were the speaker or writer and nonlinguistic experiential traces (Gold-
(for a discussion, see van Berkum et al., berg, 1995; Z w a a n , 2004; Zwaan & Madden
2005)? This mimicry approach might be an 2004). E v e n if a comprehender has relevant
effective mechanism of lexical and syntac- experiential traces, if the reader fails to bring
tic anticipation depending on the degree of these to bear, the ensuing mental simula-
common ground and common experience tion will not be coherent. For example, in
between the producer and the recipient of a second-language learner of English who
the message. has experience w i t h shift sticks, the relevant
Language-based presonance is a largely experiential traces will not be activated if he
automatic and effortless process in which or she does not k n o w the meaning of shifting
the retrieval of experiential traces is trig- gear (i.e., has no links between shifting gear
gered by the perception of linguistic struc- and the relevant experiential traces).
tures. Activation of these traces allows the T h e notion that language processing in-
comprehender to vicariously experience the volves perceptual and motor simulations of
described situation. The depth of the vicari- the described situation cannot be derived
ous experience is subject to the effectiveness f r o m traditional theories of comprehension.
of presonance, which is subject to a num- T h e s e theories conceptualize comprehen-
ber of factors. As just noted, one major fac- sion as the construction of a mental rep-
tor is the comprehender's own experience. resentation of t h e described situation, a
Presonance is presumably greatest when the situation m o d e l (van Dijk & Kintsch, 1983).
comprehender's experiential traces closely Various studies have demonstrated that
match those of the described situation. For comprehenders are sensitive to aspects of
example, a sentence about shifting a car the referential situation, as evidenced by
from second gear into third gear will yield reading times and the activation and deacti-
a more specific mental simulation in a per- vation of concepts (for reviews, see Zwaan
son experienced in driving a stick-shift car & Radvansky, 1998; Z w a a n & Rapp, 2006).
than in a person who has only driven an O n e limitation of this earlier work is that
automatic-shift car. Specifically, one might it makes t h e (often-tacit) assumption that
predict that the former would show acti- comprehension involves the activation and
vation in the motor area for the right leg, integration of abstract mental representa-
releasing the leg from the gas pedal, followed tions. This assumption derives from a basic
by activation of the left leg area, as this is tenet of the cognitive revolution; namely,
used to push down the clutch right before
that cognition can be studied as a system of
the shift is made by a right-hand power grip
abstract rules and representations, separated
of the shift stick and by subsequently mov-
f r o m the brain and the world. The idea that
ing the hand forward, away from the body.
abstract rules and representations can form
The expert might furthermore activate audi-
the basis of cognition has been called into
tory and vestibular traces that typically
question on t h e basis of what has been called
ROLF A. ZWAAN AND MICHAEL P. KASCHAK
17* J

the "symbol-grounding problem." Because process. When one is talking about a spe» M
bstract, arbitrary symbols and rules are not cific table (e.g., your coffee table), the range
perly grounded in the world, they cannot of relevant experiential traces will be much m
form the basis of meaning (linguistic or oth- smaller.
erwise; for discussion, see Glenberg, 1997; The link between word forms and senso-
Hamad, 1990; Searle, 1980). rimotor memory traces reflects a process of
Contrary to this mind-as-computer view grounding language in the surrounding envi- I
of cognition, the mental simulation view ronment that begins in the earliest stages j
that we discuss in this chapter is based of language acquisition. Much of the lan-
on the view that cognition is grounded in guage that very young children hear is about I
the systems of perception and action plan- the people, objects, and events that sur-
ning m one's own body (see also Spivey 8c round them (e.g., Tomasello, 2003). Care-
Richardson, this volume). A s a consequence, givers use gestures and other paralinguistic I
it should be possible to observe that the devices to direct children's attention toward
performance of cognitive tasks (e.g., com- elements of the environment that are being
prehending language) involves the recruit- discussed in an effort to ground new lin- §
ment of one's systems of perception and guistic terms in the external world (Masur,
action planning (as evidenced by priming 1997). Although the linking of linguistic
and/or interference that arises between lan- forms to experiential memory traces is only
guage processing on the one hand, and the a part of the important work that goes into
performance of perceptual or motor tasks language acquisition, it provides the basis for
on the other hand). This prediction is now the child's growing ability to use language
supported by a number of empirical obser- to describe the world around them and
vations involving psycholinguistic tasks. We (later) worlds separate from the here and
review this literature, moving f r o m the word now.
level to the discourse level by means of the
sentence level.
2.1. Perceptual Traces

There is a great deal of evidence that read-


2. Experiential T r a c e s at t h e ing or listening to isolated words activates
Word Level perceptual representations. One experiment
examined whether perceptual information,
Central to the mental simulation view of specifically the shape of objects, is acti-
language comprehension is the claim that vated during semantic processing (Zwaan 8t
individual words (linguistic constructs) are Yaxley, 2004). Subjects judged whether a
linked to sensorimotor m e m o r y traces that target word was related to a prime word.
form the basis of the mental simulation. Prime-target pairs that were not associ-
For example, when one processes the w o r d ated, but whose referents had similar shapes
table, the linguistic f o r m resonates with per- (e.g., ladder-railroad), yielded longer "no"
ceptual traces (e.g., the shape, size, color, responses than unassociated prime-target
and other features of tables one has seen) pairs, suggesting that shape information
and motor traces (e.g., actions that one has had been activated. A visual-field manip-
taken involving tables in the past) f r o m one's ulation showed that, in right-handed sub-
experiences with tables. In the absence of a jects, this effect was localized in the left
sharply defining context, the specific m e m - hemisphere. This finding is consistent with
ory traces that contribute to the retrieval behavioral, brain imaging, and lesion data,
process will be varied and m a y vary across which suggest that object shape at the
time (Barsalou, 2005). T h u s , w h e n one is category level is represented in the left hemi-
talking about tables in general, there is a sphere (for a detailed review, see Damasio,
wide range of experiential traces that are Tranel, Grabowskia, Adolphs, 8c Damasio,
relevant, and these will a f f e c t the retrieval 2004).
l a n g u a g e i n t h e brain, b o d y , a n d w o r l d

In further support of the view that for a review, see Pulvermuller, 1999). As
words activate perceptual representations, expected on the mental simulation view
verifying the properties (denoted by adjec- the patterns of activation that arise when
tives) of objects (denoted by nouns) is faster processing words are somatotopically orga-
when subsequent items remain in the same nized. The processing of words about hand
sensory- modality. For example, verifying actions, leg actions, and mouth actions acti-
that a lemon is sour is faster after verifying vated different parts of the premotor cortex
that an apple is tart than after verifying that each of which had been previously identified
a lime is green, just as switching between as responsible for executing hand, leg, and
modalities incurs processing costs in percep- mouth actions.
tual tasks (Pecher, Zeelenberg, & Barsalou,
2003). If words activate traces of perceptual
2.3. Other Traces
experience, then exposure to words should
lead to the activation of the neural substrates The resituating power of words extends
that are also active when their referents are beyond the activation of perceptual and
perceived. Neuroimaging research has pro- motor traces. For example, threat words
duced just such evidence (e.g., Martin & such as destroy and mutilate, presented as
Chao, 2001). part of a modified Stroop task, have been
shown to activate bilateral amygdala regions
to a greater extent than do neutral control
2.2. Motor Traces words, thus implicating subcortical struc-
The processing of words denoting objects tures in semantic processing (Isenberg et al.,
makes available the affordances (i.e., pos- 1999). The amygdala's role in emotional pro-
sibilities for interaction) of those objects cessing is well documented (e.g., LeDoux,
(Tucker & Ellis, 2004). Subjects viewed a 1995). In addition, activation was found
series of pictures and judged whether the in sensory-evaluative and motor-planning
objects in the pictures were natural or man- areas, areas that are normally activated
made. The judgment was made by produc- when the organism senses danger. This is
ing a power grip or a precision grip. Parti- all the more noteworthy given that the sub-
cipants responded more quickly to objects jects' ostensive task was not comprehending
that would be used with a power grip when words but naming the color in which they
their judgment response required a power were shown.
grip, and they responded more quickly to
objects that would be used with a precision
grip when the judgment response required a 3. Experiential Traces at
precision grip. In a subsequent experiment, the Sentence Level
Tucker and Ellis (2004) asked participants
to perform the same task, except that they As noted earlier, the experiential traces acti-
responded to the words that label each of vated by individual words can be quite het-
the objects rather than a picture. As before, erogeneous. Words may have several mean-
participants responded to the wbrds more ings, and traces relevant to each of these
quickly when the grip they used in making meanings are activated when the word is
the response matched the grip they would processed in the absence of a constraining
use in interacting with the object. context. For example, the word nail refers
Converging evidence for the activation both to a body part (fingernail, toenail) and
of motor information on the processing of a metal fastener, and the processing of the
words comes from recent work in neuro- word nail likely involves the activation of
science. Regions of the brain responsible traces relevant to both senses of the word
for the production of actions are active (at least initially). Sentences provide a con-
during the comprehension of action words straining context that hones the retrieval of
(Hauk, Johnsrude, & Pulvermuller, 2004; experiential traces for a given word (e.g.,
r o l f a. z w a a n and michael p. kaschak

Tabossi, Colombo, & Job, 1987; V u , Kellas, & and colleagues showed that language com-
Paul, 199®)- Thus, in the sentence, " H e used prehenders represented both the orientation
hammer to drive the nail into the wall," and the shape of the objects described in the
Ml wo rds hammer and drive create a par- sentence.
ticular context in which experiential traces The preceding experiments show that
relevant to nail will be retrieved. Under such static perceptual information is retrieved
conditions, the comprehender is likely to during language comprehension. More
retrieve only those traces of nail that are rel- recent studies have shown that the percep-
evant to the "metal fastener" sense of the tual simulations that arise during language
word- processing have dynamic components as
The preceding example highlights the well. Zwaan, Madden, Yaxley, and Aveyard
fact that mental simulations evolve across (2004) asked participants to read sentences
rime. As sensorimotor m e m o r y traces are about objects moving towards them ( T h e
retrieved, they produce a mental context first baseman threw you the ball") or away
that shapes the outcome of subsequent from them ("You threw the first baseman
memory retrieval operations. For example, the ball"). After each sentence, participants
when one encounters the verb throw, many saw two images presented in rapid succes-
potential motor traces are activated. These sion, and had to decide whether the images
traces are narrowed down w h e n subsequent were the same. For example, the partici-
information in the sentence indicates which pants saw two dots presented in succession.
object is being thrown, w h e r e it is being On critical trials, the second dot was either
thrown, and so on. In this sense, the con- slighdy larger (simulating motion toward
struction of a mental simulation is akin to a the participant) or slightly smaller (simulat-
constraint-satisfaction process. ing motion away from the participant) than
the first dot. The change was small enough
M. Perceptual Traces that it was not reliably detected by the par-
ticipants. Responses were faster when the
There is a growing b o d y of evidence sug- direction of motion implied by the dots
gesting that perceptual information f o r m s matched the direction of motion described
an important basis for the comprehension of in the sentence.
sentences. In a series of studies, Z w a a n and A more recent set of experiments has
colleagues (Stanfield 81 Z w a a n , 2001; Z w a a n , shown that the actual mechanisms involved
Stanfield, &. Yaxley, 2002) asked participants in auditory and visual processing are engaged
to perform a sentence-picture verification during language comprehension. Kaschak
task. Participants w o u l d read sentences such et al. (2005) asked participants to listen to
as "John put the pencil in the c u p . " Sub- sentences describing motion in one of four
sequent to the sentence, participants saw directions: toward ("The car approached
a picture of a pencil and h a d to decide you"), away ("The car left you in the dust"),
whether the object pictured appeared in up ("The rocket blasted off"), and down
the sentence (on critical trials, the answer ("The confetti fell on the parade"). At the
was always "yes"). Participants respond to same time, participants viewed black-and-
white stimuli depicting motion in either the
the picture more quickly w h e n its orienta-
same direction as that described in the sen-
tion matched the orientation that the object
tence (e.g., viewing a toward percept while
would have in the situation described by the
hearing a toward sentence) or in the opposite
preceding sentence. For e x a m p l e , if the pen-
direction as that described in the sentence
cil was described as being in a c u p , partici-
(e.g., viewing an away percept while hearing
pants were faster to respond to a picture of a
a toward sentence). Participants made sensi-
pencil oriented vertically t h a n to respond to
bility judgments more quickly for the criti-
a picture of a pencil oriented horizontally. If cal sentences when the direction of motion
the pencil was described as lying on a table, in the percept mismatched the direction
the opposite pattern w a s o b s e r v e d . Z w a a n
language in the brain, body, a n d w o r l d

of motion in the sentence. Kaschak et al. the percept (for discussion, see Lavie, 2005)
(2005) explained this pattern as the result of Consequendy, there is no competition for
a competition for resources within the visual resources; instead, the direction of motion
system. The toward percept is engaging the in the percept primes the comprehension
parts of the visual system that respond to of sentences describing motion in the same
toward motion, and thus it is difficult to direction.
use these parts of the visual system to sim-
ulate the toward motion described in the 3.2. Motor Traces
sentence. When the direction of motion in
The comprehension of sentences also in-
the percept and sentence mismatch, there is
volves the retrieval of motor traces. Klatzky
no such competition, and comprehension is
Pellegrino, McCloskey, and Doherty (1989)
more facile.
demonstrated that producing bodily pos-
These findings have been extended to the
tures (e.g., pinching the thumb and index
auditory modality. Kaschak, Zwaan, Ave-
finger together) facilitated the processing of
yard, and Yaxley (2006) asked participants
sentences describing actions that required
to read sentences describing motion toward,
a similar body posture ("Aim a dart").
away, up, or down while simultaneously lis-
Thus, motor information can facilitate the
tening to white noise manipulated to give
comprehension of sentences. Glenberg
the impression of motion in one of those
and Kaschak (2002; see also Borreggine
four directions. As before, the direction of
& Kaschak, 2006) showed that the con-
motion in the sound was either the same
verse is also true: processing sentences can
as the direction of motion in the sentence
facilitate motor responses. Participants read
(toward-toward), or the opposite direction
sentences describing an action that requires
as that described in the sentence (toward-
moving the arm toward the body ("Open
away). Again, responding was faster when
the drawer") or away from the body ("Close
the direction of motion in the percept mis-
the drawer"). The participants' task was to
matched the direction of motion in the sen-
decide whether the sentences made sense.
tence.
On critical trials, participants had to respond
Interestingly, this pattern of data is re-
"yes" by making an arm motion either
versed when the sentence and percept are
toward their body or away from their body.
presented in the same modality. The preced-
Half of the time the direction of the response
ing experiments (in which responding was
matched the direction of motion in the sen-
fastest in the mismatching conditions) all
tence, and half of the time the direction of
presented the linguistic input in a different
the response was the opposite of the direc-
modality than the percept. However, when
tion of motion in the sentence. Participants
participants processed auditorily presented
responded more quickly when the direction
sentences while also listening to the audi-
of the "yes" response matched the direction
tory motion stimuli, they responded more
of the action described by the sentence.
quickly when the direction of motion in the
Glenberg and Kaschak (2002) refer to this as
sentence matched the direction of motion in
the action-sentence compatibility effect (ACE).
the percept. One explanation for this rever-
sal in the pattern of response times is that Glenberg and Kaschak (2002) reported a
presenting the sentences and percepts in reliable A C E across many kinds of sentences.
a different modality allows both kinds of Imperative sentences ("Open the door") and
stimulus to be processed at the same time. sentences about the transfer of concrete
This makes it possible to observe the com- objects ("You gave Mike a pen") showed the
petition for resources described previously. A C E , as did sentences about abstract kinds
However, when the sentence and percept of transfer ( " Y o u told Bill the story"). This
are presented in the same modality, the latter finding suggests that the sensorimo-
attentional demands of processing the sen- tor simulations underlie the comprehension
tence temporarily block the processing of not only of sentences about literal actions
i n n j M K s

ROLF A. ZWAAN AND MICHAEL P. KASCHAK


375

n(j events but also of sentences that involve Buccino et al. (2005) have provided fur-
ther insight into the role of motor traces
' t h e preceding studies used relatively in sentence processing. Using a combination
coarse measures (e.g., whole sentence read- of transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS)
• times) to assess the role of motor and behavioral measures of sentence pro-
information in sentence processing. More cessing, Buccino and colleagues report that
recently, Zwaan and Taylor (2006) have the processing of sentences about action
begun investigating the motor resonance using a particular effector (e.g., the hand)
that occurs during on-line sentence process- interferes with making responses with that
ing In one of their experiments they pre- same effector. Thus, when a hand motion
sented subjects with sentences such as "He / must be programmed while comprehend-
realized / that / the music / was / too loud / ing a sentence about hand motions, there
so he / turned down / the / volume." The appears to be a competition for resources
sentences were presented in segments and that slows the execution of the hand motion.
subjects progressed through the sentence Although this matter needs to be investi-
by turning a knob, with each five degrees gated in more detail, it puts the A C E and
of rotation producing a new segment. Half related effects in a different perspective.
the subjects turned the knob clockwise and Simulating a sentence about hand motions
the other half counterclockwise. Zwaan and appears to interfere with the production of
Taylor found that when the direction of hand motions. However, the interference
rotation implied by the sentence (e.g., turn- may be less when the motion described in
ing down the volume implies counterclock- the sentence is congruent with the motion
wise rotation) matched the rotation the sub- that needs to be produced.
jects themselves were making to read the
sentence, reading times were shorter than 3.3. Other Traces
when the two directions mismatched. To
our knowledge, this is the first experiment Glenberg, Havas, Becker, and Rinck (2005)
to report on-line effects of motor resonance have reported experiments suggesting that
in language comprehension. systems involved in emotional responses are
An interesting aspect of Z w a a n and Tay- engaged during language comprehension. In
lor's (2006) results is that motor reso- a series of experiments, Glenberg et al.
nance was constrained to the so-called tar- (2005) used the Strack procedure (Strack,
get region in the sentence (i.e., the segment Martin, 8l Stepper, 1988) to induce a partic-
at which the rotation was being described). ular mood in their participants. This proce-
This was the verb region in all critical dure involves either holding a pen in your
sentences. This finding has two important teeth to force the face into a smiling pos-
implications. First, motor resonance occurs ture or holding a pen in your lips to force
immediately upon encountering the rele- the face into a frowning posture. While
vant word or phrase. Second, it is short lived. in these emotion-inducing postures, par-
The immediacy of motor resonance is con- ticipants read sentences that were positive
sistent with constraint-based models of sen- or negative in emotional valence. Glenberg
tence processing (MacDonald et al., 1994; et al. (2005) report that participants respond
McRae et al., 1998). T h e finding of motor more quickly to sentences when the emo-
resonance being short lived could be due to tional valence of the sentence matches their
the nature of the sentences. T h e verb phrase induced mood.
is followed by a noun phrase, which shifts
the focus away from the action toward its
result. It is possible that this attentional shift
is responsible for the limited duration of 4. Resituating at the Discourse Level
motor resonance (e.g., MacWhinney, 2005).
We are currently investigating this issue. Although it is useful to study the process-
ing of words and sentences presented in
language in the brain, body, a n d w o r l d

isolation, most language-comprehension sit- the way we anticipate actual events, then
uations involve connected discourse. There violations of temporal continuity should
is very little research on discourse com- negatively affect on-line language compre-
prehension from an embodied perspective. hension. This has indeed been shown to be
Just as motor resonance has been demon- the case; reading times for sentences that
strated at the word and the sentence level, violate chronology and continuity are longer
it has been shown to occur at the level than reading times for sentences that do
of discourse. Spivey and Geng (2001) had not (e.g., Mandler, 1986; Zwaan, 1996; for
subjects listen to stories describing events extensive reviews, see Zwaan, 2004; Zwaan
that involved vertical or horizontal motion. 8c Radvansky, 1998). These findings can be
They surreptitiously tracked the subjects' interpreted as consistent with the notion
eye movements and found that vertical of presonance. On the basis of their expe-
events tended to be associated with verti- rience with actual events, comprehenders
cal eye movements and horizontal move- expect by default that linguistically medi-
ments with horizontal eye movements, as ated events occurred chronologically and
if the subjects were directly observing these contiguously. Because this expectation is
events (for an in-depth discussion of eye violated, there is a momentary slowdown of
movements, see Spivey & Richardson, this the comprehension process. However, given
volume). its exposure to violations of this expecta-
Just as comprehenders use eye move- tion in language, the comprehension system
ments to trace the actions described in a dis- quickly gets back on track.
course, they also use gestures to keep track The mental simulation view of language
of discourse entities across time. McNeil comprehension also predicts that the con-
(1998) has shown that, in cases where a con- tents of the comprehender's working mem-
versation involves events that occur in differ- ory should reflect the accessibility of objects
ent times and places, interlocutors use their and events in the real world given our
gestures to indicate which events are being human sensory, attentional, and action-
discussed. For example, events taking place related limitations. For example, when
in the present would be accompanied by ges- observing objects and events in the real
tures that are produced direcdy in front of world, objects that are occluded are not as
the speaker's body, whereas events taking available for processing as objects that are
place in the past would be accompanied by not occluded. This leads to the prediction
gestures that are produced off to one side that working memory should contain the
of the speaker's body. The spatial location following:
of the gestures thus provides a reliable cue
as to which set of events is being described | Present objects rather than absent objects
in the current utterance. The gestures also § Present features rather than absent fea-
facilitate transitions between talking about tures
the past and present. • Close objects rather than distant objects
Another line of research has focused on i Ongoing events rather than past events
cases in which the discourse structure devi- • Current goals rather than past goals
ates from everyday experience. If compre- I Visible entities rather than occluded enti-
henders process events conveyed though ties
language the way they process actual events,
then these deviations should bring about Actions in the real world should also be
momentary disruptions of the comprehen- affected by the information that is retrieved
sion process. For example, language allows
in the service of mentally simulating a refer-
us to deviate from the chronological and
ent world. Several predictions follow from
continuous flow of events we experience in
this claim. These predictions principally fol-
real life. If we anticipate described events
low from the idea that the performance of
^¡jgm — IUI w i l l — O H

r o l f a. z w a a n and m i c h a e l p. kaschak
377

erceptual and motor systems should be • A visible entity rather than an occluded
ff ted by the requirements of the men- one (Horton & Rapp, 2002).
1 simulation. Evidence that the processing
f words affects perceptual processes was As mentioned earlier, there is also evi-
° orted by Richardson, Spivey, Barsalou, dence that comprehenders assume the spa-
re!
j^cRae (2003). Evidence that motor pro- tial perspective of a protagonist in the story
311
ses are affected by sentence comprehen-
(Bower, Black, & Turner, 1979; Bryant, Tver-
Q been reported by Glenberg and sky, 8c Franklin, 1992; Franklin 8c Tversky,
Kaschak (2002), Zwaan and Taylor (2006), 1990; Morrow 8c Clark, 1988; Rail 8c Harris,
nd Buccino et al. (2005). Additionally, we
2000).
expect that when not otherwise engaged
the actual situation (e.g., when one is
reading or deliberately trying to maintain 5. Conclusions and Outlook
eye contact with someone), eye movements
should reflect the vicarious experience of theThere is a good deal of evidence that lan-
referent situation. guage processing brings about the preso-
The assumptions that are generally made nance of perceptual, motoric, and expe-
in discourse comprehension research are riential traces in the comprehender. This
¿at (a) information that is currently in evidence has been found at the word, sen-
working memory is more accessible (i.e., tence, and discourse levels. We argue that
more highly activated) than information this evidence can be coherendy explained
that is not, and (b) when probed, more by assuming that language comprehension
accessible information will yield faster is grounded in the same neural systems that
responses than less accessible information. are used to perceive, plan, and take action in
Therefore, the presentation of probe words the external world. In this way, the compre-
associated with the contents of work- hension of language involves the vicarious
ing memory should facilitate responses. In experiencing of the people, objects, emo-
accordance with this logic, various stud- tions, and events that are described in the
ies have demonstrated that the contents text. More broadly, just as our ability to
of working memory during comprehension plan and take action in the world relies on
reflect the nature of the described situation. the ability to anticipate likely changes that
Probe-word responses are faster when the will occur in the environment, we argue
probe refers to that an essential part of the language com-
prehension process is the ability to antici-
• A present entity rather than an absent pate what is coming next, both in the lin-
entity (Anderson, Garrod, & Sanford, guistic input and in the situations that are
1983; Carreiras, Carriedo, Alonso, & Fer- being described. This process of presonance
nandez, 1997). is immediate and effortless. It allows us to
' A present rather than an absent feature resituate ourselves and vicariously experi-
(Kaup & Zwaan, 2003). ence (and learn from) events that have hap-
• A present object rather than a distant pened in situations other than the one we
object (Glenberg, Meyer, & Lindem, currendy find ourselves in.
1987; Morrow, Bower, & Greenspan, Whereas we find much promise in this
1989; Morrow, Greenspan, & Bower, 1987; general approach to language comprehen-
Rinck & Bower, 2000). sion, significant research remains to be done
I An ongoing event rather than a past event on virtually all fronts. There is a relative
(Zwaan, 1996; Zwaan, Madden, 8r Whit- dearth of research on how sensorimotor
ten, 2000). information is retrieved and used during on-
I A current goal rather than an accom- line sentence comprehension. There has also
plished one (Trabasso 8c Suh, 1993). been little work considering how known
language in t h e brain, body, a n d w o r l d

elements of perceptual or motoric pro- book of categorization in cognitive science


cessing systems can be integrated with an (pp. 619-650). St. Louis: Elsevier.
account that explains the moment-by- Borreggine, K. L., & Kaschak, M. P. (2006). The
moment comprehension of sentences. Fi- action-sentence compatibility effect: It's all
nally, very little effort has been put forth in the timing. Cognitive Science, 30(6), iem~
to determine how and when sensorimotor 1112.
information might be retrieved and used Bower, G. H„ Black, J. B., & Turner, T. J. (i9?9)
during the comprehension of language in Scripts in memory for text. Cognitive Psychol-
ogy, a, 177-220.
more naturalistic tasks (e.g., tasks in which
Bryant, D. J., Tversky, B., & Franklin, N. (1992)
reading does not involve twisting a knob or
Internal and external spatial frameworks for
moving one's arm or viewing some sort of
representing described scenes. Journal of Mem-
percept). These questions highlight the fact
ory and Language, 31, 74-98.
that we are only at the beginning of the Buccino, G., Riggio, L., Mellia, G., Binkofski
process of building a sensorimotor account F., Gallese, V., & Rizzolatti, G. (2005). Lis-
of language processing. As we look to the tening to action-related sentences modulates
future, we see the development of a the- the activity of the motor system: A combined
ory that firmly grounds the comprehension TMS and behavioral study. Cognitive Brain
of language in our ability to plan and act Research, 24, 355-363.
and that views language not as something Carreiras, M., Carriedo, N., Alonso, M. A., & Fer-
that is special and distinct from the rest of nandez, A. (1997). The role of verbal tense and
cognition but as something that is a natural verbal aspect in the foregrounding of infor-
extension of the cognitive processes needed mation in reading. Memory and Cognition, 23,
to act successfully in the external world. 438-446.
Chambers, C. G., Tanenhaus, M. K., & Mag-
nuson, J. S. (2004). Actions and affordances
in syntactic ambiguity resolution. Journal of
Acknowledgments
Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory,
and Cognition, 30, 687-696.
We thank Michael Spivey for helpful comments Damasio, H., Tranel, D., Grabowskia, T.,
on a previous version of this chapter. Rolf Zwaan Adolphs, R., & Damasio, A. (2004). Neural
was supported by National Institutes of Health systems behind word and concept retrieval.
grant MH-63972. Both authors were supported by Cognition, 92,179-229.
Grant No. BCS-0446637 from the National Sci- Flanagan, J. R., & Johansson, R. S. (2003). Action
ence Foundation. Please address correspondence plans used in action observation. Nature, 424,
regarding this chapter to Rolf Zwaan, Depart- 769-771.
ment of Biological and Cognitive Psychology, Fowler, C. A. (1996). Listeners do hear sounds,
Erasmus University, Rotterdam, The Nether- not tongues. Journal of the Acoustical Society of
lands, zwaan@fsw.eur.nl. America, 99,1730-1741.
Franklin, N., 8t Tversky, B. (1990). Searching
imagined environments. Journal of Experimen-
References tal Psychology: General, 119, 63-76.
Glenberg, A. M. (1997). What memory is for.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 20,1-19.
Anderson, A., Garrod, S. C, & Sanford, A. J.
Glenberg, A. M., & Kaschak, M. P. (2002).
(1983). The accessibility of pronominal
Grounding language in action. Psychonomic
antecedents as a function of episode shifts in
Bulletin SS Review, 9, 558-565.
narrative text. Quarterly Journal of Experimen-
Glenberg, A. M., Havas, D., Becker, R., & Rinck,
tal Psychology, jçA, 427-440. M. (2005). Grounding language in bodily
Barsalou, L. W. (1999). Perceptual symbol sys- states: The case for emotion. In R. A. Zwaan
tems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22, 577- 8t D. Pecher (Eds.), The grounding of cognition:
660. The role of perception and action in memory, lan-
Barsalou, L. W. (200;). Situated conceptualiza- guage, and thinking (pp. 115-128). Cambridge:
tion. In H. Cohen & C. Lefebvre (Eds.), Hand- Cambridge University Press.
* mm mm m m m . t i j ^ : ' ^ * - ^

ROLF A. ZWAAN AND MICHAEL P. KASCHAK


379

rleiiberg, A. M., Meyer, M . , & Lindem, Lavie, N. (2005). Distracted and confused? Selec-
K (1987)- Mental models contribute to tive attention under load. Trends in Cognitive
foregrounding during text comprehension. Sciences, 9,75-82.
Journal of Memory and Language, 26, 6 9 - LeDoux, J. E. (1995). Emotion: Clues from the
g,
brain. Annual Review of Psychology, a6, 209-
2
Goldberg, A. E. (1995). Constructions: A construc- 35-
jgn grammar approach to argument structure. MacDonald, M. C., Pearlmutter, N. J., & Seiden-
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. berg, M. S. (1994). Lexical nature of syntac-
Hamad, S. (1990). T h e symbol grounding prob- tic ambiguity resolution. Psychological Review,
lem. physica D, 42, 335~34 6 - 101,676-703.
Hauk, 0., Johnsrude, I., & Pulvermuller, MacWhinney, B. (2005). The emergence of gram-
p (2004). Somatotopic representation of mar from perspective taking. In D. Pecher &
action words in the motor and premotor cor- R. A. Zwaan (Eds.), Grounding cognition: The
tex. Neuron, 41, 301-307. role of perception and action in memory, lan-
Hess, D. J., Foss, D. J., & Carroll, P. (1995). guage, and thinking (pp. 198-223). Cambridge:
Effects of global and local context on lex- Cambridge University Press.
ical processing during language comprehen- Mandler, J. M. (1986). On the comprehension of
sion. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Gen- temporal order. Language and Cognitive Pro-
eral, 124,62-82. cesses, 1, 309-320.
Hintzman, D. L. (1986). "Schema-abstraction" in Martin, A., & Chao, L. L. (2001). Semantic mem-
a multiple trace model. Psychological Review, ory and the brain: Structure and process. Cur-
93,411-428. rent Opinion in Neurobiology, 11,194-201.
Horton, W. S., & Rapp, D. N. (2002). Occlu- Masur, E. F. (1997). Maternal labeling of
sion and accessibility of information in nar- novel and familiar objects: Implications
rative comprehension. Psychonomic Bulletin & for children's development of lexical con-
Review, 10,104-109. straints. Journal of Child Language, 24, 427-
Isenberg, N., Silbersweig, D., Engelien, A., 439-
Emmerich, K., Malavade, K., Benti, B., et al. McNeill, D. (1998). Speech and gesture integra-
(1999). Linguistic threat activates the human tion. In J. M. Iverson & S. Goldin-Meadow
amygdala. Proceedings of the National Academy (Eds.), The nature and functions of gesture in
of Sciences, 96,10456-10459. children's communication: New directions for
Jurafeky, D. (1996). A probabilistic model of lex- child development (No. 9, pp. 11-27). Sail Fran-
ical and syntactic access and disambiguation. cisco: Jossey-Bass.
Cognitive Science, 20,137-194. McRae, K., Spivey-Knowlton, M. J., & Tanen-
Kaschak, M. P., Madden, C. J., Therriault, D. haus, M. K. (1998). Modeling the influence of
J., Yaxley, R. H., Aveyard, M., Blanchard, A. thematic fit (and other constraints) in on-line
A., et al. (2005). Perception of motion affects sentence comprehension. Journal of Memory
language processing. Cognition, 94, B 7 9 - and Language, 38, 283-312.
B89. Morrow, D. G., Bower, G. H., & Greenspan,
Kaschak, M. P., Zwaan, R. A . , Aveyard, M., & S. L. (1989). Updating situation models dur-
Yaxley, R. H. (2006). Perception of auditory ing narrative comprehension. Journal of Mem-
motion affects language processing. Cognitive ory and Language, 28, 292-312.
Science, 30(4), 733-734. Morrow, D. G., & Clark, H. H. (1988). Interpret-
Kaup, B., & Zwaan, R. A. (2003). Effects of nega- ing words in spatial descriptions. Language
tion and situational presence on the accessibil- and Cognitive Processes, 3, 275-291.
ity of text information. Journal of Experimental Morrow, D. G., Greenspan, S. E., & Bower, G. H.
Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, (1987). Accessibility and situation models in
23,439-446. narrative comprehension. Journal of Memory
Klatzky, R. L., Pellegrino, J. W., McCloskey, B. and Language, 26,165-187.
P., & Doherty, S. (1989). Can you squeeze Pecher, D., Zeelenberg, R., & Barsalou, L. W.
a tomato? The role of motor represen- (2003). Verifying the properties of object
tations in semantic sensibility judgements. concepts across different modalities produces
Journal of Memory and Language, 28, 56- switching costs. Psychological Science, 14, 119-
77- 129.
LANGUAGE IN THE DRAIN, BODY, AND WORLD

Trabasso, T., 8t Suh, S. [1993). Understand-


Pickering, M. J., & Garrod, S. (2004). Toward
ing text: Achieving explanatory coherence
a mechanistic psychology of dialogue. Behav-
through on-line inferences and mental opera-
ioral and Brain Sciences, 27,169-226.
Porter, R., & Lubker, J. (1980). Rapid repro- tions in working memory. Discourse Processes,
duction of vowel-vowel sequences: Evidence 16, 3-34-
for a fest and direct acoustic-motoric link- Tucker, M., & Ellis, R. (2004). Action priming
age in speech. Journal of Speech and Hearing by briefly presented objects. Acta Psychologica,
Research, 23, 593-602. 116, 185-203.
Pulvermuller, F. (1999). Words in the brain's lan- van Berkum, J. J. A., Brown, C. M., Zwitser-
guage. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22, 253- lood, P., Kooijman, V., & Hagoort, P. (2005).
336. Anticipating upcoming words in discourse:
Rail, J., & Harris, P. L. (2000). In Cinderella's slip- Evidence from ERPs and reading times. Jour-
pen? Story comprehension from the protago- nal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Mem-
nist's point of view. Developmental Psychology, ory, and Cognition, 31, 443-467.
36,202-208. van Dijk, T. A., & Kintsch, W. (1983). Strategies of
Richardson, D; C., Spivey, M. J., Barsalou, L. W., discourse comprehension. New York: Academic
& McRae, K. (2003). Spatial representations Press.
activated during real-time comprehension of Vu, H., Kellas, G., & Paul, S. T. (1998). Sourcesof
verbs. Cognitive Science, 27, 767-780. sentence constraint on lexical ambiguity reso-
Rinck, M., & Bower, G. H. (2000). Temporal and lution. Memory and Cognition, 26, 979-1001.
spatial distance in situation models. Memory Wolpert, D. M., Doya, K. ( 81 Kawato, M.
and Cognition, 28,1310-1320. (2003). A unifying computational framework
for motor control and social interaction. Phil-
Searle, J. R. (1980). Minds, brains, and pro-
osophical Transactions of the Royal Society, 358,
grams. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 417- 593-602.
457- Zwaan, R. A. (1994). Effect of genre expectations
Spivey, M. J., & Geng, J. J. (2001). Oculomotor on text comprehension. Journal of Experimen-
mechanisms activated by imagery and mem- tal Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cogni-
ory: Eye movements to absent objects. Psycho- tion, 20, 920-933.
logical Research, 65, 235-241. Zwaan, R. A. (1996). Processing narrative time
Spivey, M. J., & Tanenhaus, M. K. (1998). Syntac- shifts. Journal of Experimental Psychology:
tic ambiguity resolution in discourse: Model- Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 22, 1196-
ing the effects of referential context and lexi- 1207.
cal frequency. Journal of Experimental Psychol-Zwaan, R. A. (2004). The immersed experiencer:
ogy: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 24,1521- Toward an embodied theory of language com-
•543- prehension. In B. H. Ross (Ed.), Thepsychology
Stanfield, R. A., & Zwaan, R. A. (2001). The of learning and motivation (Vol. 44, pp. 35-62).
effect of implied orientation derived from ver- New York: Academic Press.
bal context on picture recognition. Psycholog- Zwaan, R. A., & Madden, C. J. (2004). Updating
ical Science, 12(2), 153-156. situation models. Journal of Experimental Psy-
Strack, F., Martin, L., & Stepper, S. (1988). chology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 30,
Inhibiting and facilitating conditions of the 283-288.
human smile: A nonobtrusive test of the facial Zwaan, R. A., Madden, C. J., 8l Whitten, S. N.
feedback hypothesis. Journal of Personality and (2000). The presence of an event in the nar-
Social Psychology, 54, 768-777. rated situation affects its activation. Memory
Tabossi, P., Colombo, L., & Job, R. (1987). and Cognition, 28,1022-1028.
Accessing lexical ambiguity: Effects of con- Zwaan, R. A., Madden, C. J., Yaxley, R. H.,
text and dominance. Psychological Research, & Aveyard, M. E. (2004). Moving words:
49,161-167. Dynamic mental representations in language
Tomasello, M. (2003). Constructing a language: comprehension. Cognitive Science, 28, 611-619.
A usage-based theory of language acquisi- Zwaan, R. A., & Radvansky, G. A. (1998). Situ-
tion. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University ation models in language comprehension and
Press. memory. Psychological Bulletin, 123,162-185.
Townsend, D. J., & Bever, T. G. (2001). Sen- Zwaan, R. A., & Rapp, D. N. (2006). Discourse
tence comprehension: The integration of habits comprehension. In M. A. Gernsbacher & M.
and rules. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
r o l f a. z w a a n a n d michael p. kaschak

i CEds ) Handbook of psycholinguistics Zwaan, R. A., & Taylor, L. (2006). Seeing, acting,
P § | | 725-764)- San Diego, C A : Else- understanding: Motor resonance in language
comprehension. Journal of Experimental Psy-
vier
' RA._ Stanfield, R. A., & Yaxley, R. chology: General, 135,1-11.
l^l j-j Language comprehenders mentally Zwaan R. A., & Yaxley, R. H. (2004). Lateraliza-
esent the shapes of objects. Psychological tion of object-shape information in semantic
¡¡©8 processing. Cognition, 94, B35-B43.
CHAPTER 20

Language Processing Embodied


and Embedded

Michael Spivey and Daniel Richardson

A language fractionated from all its referents The ability of language to convey infor-
is perhaps something, but whatever it is, it is mation about objects, people, and ideas that
neither a language nor a model of a language. have no immediate physical presence, or
have never even existed before, would seem
- Robert Rosen, Essays on to mark it out as a prime example of a
Life Itself representation-hungry (Clark, 1997) cogni-
tive task that is not situated in the world.
Even if the mental representations underly-
1. Introduction ing language are grounded in past perceptual
or motor experiences of the world (Barsalou,
While driving in England recently, the sec- 1999; Glenberg, 1997; Zwaan & Kaschak, this
ond author was listening to a play on the volume), this does not require that when it
radio. A Roman senator was telling another is spoken, an utterance has any deep con-
how Cicero had insulted him in court. In nection to the environment in which it is
moments like those, it seems that language heard, as the case of the radio play clearly
could not be less situated in the world. demonstrates.
The senators were in Rome, not the English Such unembedded communication about
countryside; the events took place in the dis- objects and events that are not in the here
tant past; even within the play, the senator and now is obviously possible, but it is
listening had not been in the courtroom or not always successful. After all, how many
had ever met Cicero. Despite these many times have you heard someone try to tell
degrees of separation between the words of a funny story and end up saying, "I guess
the Roman senator and the world of the you had to be there." Being there is exactly
radio listener, the play was perfecdy under- what embedded language is about, and it is
standable. Indeed, at one further degree of arguably our primary form of language use.
separation, you as a reader are perfecdy able It is somewhat ironic, of course, that we are
to understand what happened in the car. using the medium of unidirectional scripted

382
language processing embodied and embedded
language to make our arguments, but in this to encoding facts and understanding figu-
chapter we will argue that, for the bulk of rative phrases. In recent work, conversa-
everyday language use by most people, lan- tion appears as jointly situated cognition, in
guage processing is inextricably embedded which conversants coordinate one another's
in die world. Production and comprehen- visual attention around the external world.
sion display many of the hallmarks of situ- Our review of the literature suggests that
ated cognition discussed in this volume and fine-grained behavioral measures such as e y e
can often be understood best in terms of tracking convincingly demonstrate language
agents acting within a particular environ- use to be a prime example of situated cog-
nition.
ment.
The situated and nonsituated aspects of Embedded language processing involves
language map onto a distinction made by complex situational variables imposing im-
Clark (1992) between t w o separate traditions mediate influences on word recognition,
within language research. T h e language-as- syntactic parsing, and discourse comprehen-
product tradition has lauded the nonsitu- sion. This means that language processing
ated virtues of language: spoken language is is an interdisciplinary activity in the brain,
an evanescent auditory signal, yet it can be involving visual perception, auditory per-
used to refer to objects, people, and events ception, motor processing, and reasoning, in
that are not present. This tradition, which addition to linguistic computations. Impor-
has dominated psycholinguistics, studies the tandy, however, the purview of embedded
processes by w h i c h listeners f o r m internal language processing not only is coexten-
linguistic representations. Experimentally, sive with other internal cognitive processes
this tradition seeks to decontextualize lin- but also extends beyond the language user's
guistic stimuli w h e r e possible to isolate pro- brain. That is, the very cognitive operations
cesses and representations. In contrast, the involved in embedded language processing
language-as-action tradition has character- are themselves coextensive among speaker,
ized language use as a f o r m of joint action listener, and environment. We lay out these
that is embedded in the world. This tra- arguments at the computational level before
dition stems f r o m the school of ordinary- offering empirical evidence at the behavioral
language philosophy (Austin, 1962; Grice,
level.
1989; Searle, 1969). Experimentally, this tra-
dition has observed and analyzed the con-
versations of individuals in real-world social
2. C o m p u t a t i o n a l A r g u m e n t s
interactions and tasks.

In the past decade, attempts have been Language has been held up as the best case in
made to bridge these t w o traditions (see the argument for cognitive modules that are
Trueswell & Tanenhaus, 2004). Following isolated from one another and from exter-
early work by C o o p e r (1974), eye-tracking nal variables (Fodor, 1983). In contrast, situ-
technology has been used during task- ated cognition is about the inextricability of
oriented language use in rich contexts, fol- cognition from key situational variables in
lowing the language-as-action tradition, and the environment. A particular mathemati-
has provided a fine-grained measurement cal distinction becomes especially important
of linguistic processing in the language-as- when discussing the separabdity of cogni-
product tradition (e.g., Tanenhaus, Spivey- tion from the environment, as well as the
Knowlton, Eberhard, & Sedivy, 1995). We separability of individual cognitive processes
use the term embedded language to refer to from one another. Cognitive psychology's
this bridge between the language-as-product traditional information-processing approach
and language-as-action traditions. In this (e.g., Neisser, 1967; Sternberg, 1969) relies
chapter, we will present evidence that the heavily on an assumption of component-
external world is involved in a wide range dominant dynamics, whereas a more con-
of linguistic processes, from parsing syntax tinuous and interactive situated cognition
MICHAEL SPIVEY AND DANIEL R I C H A R D S O N

approach (e.g., Greeno, 1998; Neisser, 1976) psychology (Turvey & Carello, 1995; Turvey
steers the mathematical description more 8n Shaw, 1999), has the necessary explana-
toward interaction-dominant dynamics. In tory tools for dealing with an account of
component-dominant dynamics, most of the cognition that is not limited to the individual
important functional processes are carried organism's brain but also includes situational
out inside each subsystem (e.g., a language variables as part and parcel of cognition.
subsystem, a vision subsystem, a memory In what follows, we will review a vari-
subsystem). And when those subsystems ety of real-time experimental evidence from
share information with one another, the psycholinguistics that is gradually accruing
transmission is extremely limited and con- support for rich interaction between cog-
strained. The transmission process itself does nitive subsystems as well as rich interac-
not contribute significandy to the func- tion between the biological substrate and
tional computational result. In contrast, the environmental substrate. These find-
interaction-dominant dynamics are when ings indicate that language processes rely
most of the important functional processes heavily on situational variables at a very fine
are carried out via the interactions between time scale, and therefore exhibit the kind
subsystems, not inside each of them. That of interaction-dominant dynamics that are
is, each subsystem's behavior is substantially more consistent with the developing situ-
described by parameters external to it, and ated cognition approach to psychology than
only partly described by its own internal with the traditional information-processing
state-transition parameters. In such a cir- approach.
cumstance, the openness of these subsys-
tems requires that the level of analysis be
zoomed out a notch so that the larger sys- 3. Spoken-Language Processing
tem being described (which comprises those Embedded in a Situational Context
subsystems) is a bit more closed (not rely-
ing so much on parameters external to it), Put simply, language is not processed by
and therefore more scientifically analyzable. language processors; it is processed by peo-
If internal mental processing is a sufficiendy ple. Much like J. J. Gibson's (1979) ecolog-
open system that proper analysis requires ical psychology, where the level of analysis
describing the larger system in which inter- is the organism-cum-environment, a proper
nal mental processing is embedded, then the understanding of how language processing
appropriate level of analysis is the organism- works requires attention to the perceptual-
environment dyad, not just the organism motor patterns that interface the organism
(Gibson, 1979; Turvey & Shaw, 1999). with its environment (see Zwaan & Kaschak,
When a system exhibits interaction- this volume) and those environmental prop-
dominant dynamics, the traditional feed- erties in which the language use is embed-
forward linear-systems analysis borrowed ded. Without the many different environ-
from electrical engineering no longer suf- mental constraints that situate language
fices. That is, the popular divide-and- processing - too often lumped together
conquer scientific paradigm endorsed by the under the monolithic term context - lan-
modularity framework is no longer valid guage as we know it would not exist.
for such a system. Instead, what is needed Eye movements are a particularly com-
is a dynamical-systems framework that pelling example of how component-
applies continuous mathematical descrip- dominant dynamics do not provide a good
tions to the functional interactions that description of how the brain and body
emerge between subsystems (e.g., Kelso, interface with their environment and how
1995; Port & van Gelder, 1995; van Orden, interaction-dominant dynamics may pro-
Holden, & Turvey, 2003; Ward, 2002). vide a more appropriate description. Con-
The dynamical-systems framework, which is siderable evidence (e.g., Gold & Shadlen,
becoming increasingly popular in ecological 2000; Spivey 8l Dale, 2004; van der Heijden,
LANGUAGE PROCESSING EMBODIED AND EMBEDDED

1996) supports the observation that the brain tion, it is natural that we first report on
does not achieve a stable percept, then make evidence for embedded language processing
a n eye movement, then achieve another sta- that comes from eye-tracking experiments.
ble percept, then make another eye move- For a decade now, eye-tracking studies
ment, and so forth. The eyes often move have been demonstrating the wide vari-
during the process of achieving a stable per- ety of ways in which the visual world is
cept. As a result, before perception can fin- continuously accessed and integrated with
ish settling into a unitary interpretation of spoken-language processing, at the level
its input, oculomotor output changes the of word recognition (Allopenna, Magnu-
perceptual input by placing new and dif- son, & Tanenhaus, 1998), reference resolu-
ferent visual information on the foveas. For tion (Eberhard, Spivey-Knowlton, Sedivy,
example, an initial eye fixation may cause & Tanenhaus, 1995), syntactic processing
certain dynamical perceptual processes to (Tanenhaus et al., 1995), and thematic role
be set in motion, which then (before they assignment (Altmann & Kamide, 1999).
become stable) cause a new eye movement, For example, even during the few hun-
which then allows for different environmen- dred milliseconds it takes to hear a spoken
tal properties to cause different dynamics in word, situational constraints provided by the
the perceptual process, which then cause visual context can influence the activations
yet another eye movement, and so forth. of lexical representations that result from
Thus, perception is simultaneously influ- processing those first few phonemes. When
enced by sensory input (caused by envi- sitting in front of a table with real objects
ronment properties reflecting light onto the (see Figure 20.1) and being instructed, "Pick
retinas) and by oculomotor output (caused up the candy," about one-third of the time
by intermediate products of perception's participants initially fixate the candle for
own analog computations). Because eye a couple hundred milliseconds before then
movements tend to operate at a slightly fixating the candy to pick it up (Spivey-
finer time scale than does perceptual stabi- Knowlton, Tanenhaus, Eberhard, 8t Sedivy,
lization, the perception-action cycle in this 1998). They do this because that object's
case becomes a circular causal loop - for name shares several initial phonemes with
which distinguishing the chicken from the caruiy (i.e., it is a cohort of the word;
egg, so to speak, becomes moot. This kind Marslen-Wilson, 1987). In a control condi-
of loop is called "impredicative" (Poincare, tion, if you deliver the same spoken instruc-
1906) because it comprises elements that tion with a visual display that does not
can be defined only with reference to the contain a candle, participants quickly land
larger system of which they are members their eyes on the candy and rarely fixate
(Rosen, 2000; Turvey, 2004). With impred- the other objects. (Similar results are found
icative systems, such as a continuously flow- in the graded curvature of computer-mouse
ing perception-action loop, there can be movements, with instructions like "Click the
no context-independent definition of each candle"; see Spivey, Grosjean, & Knoblich,
computational element, followed by a lin- 2005.) If you ask them whether they noticed
ear, feed-forward, componentwise integra- having looked at the candle, they will deny
tion of those elements. In this loop, per- having done so. Thus, in the right visual
ceptual and cognitive parameters, motor environments, eye movements can be used
parameters, and environmental parameters as an early strategy-proof measure of par-
are so causally intertwined with one another tially active representations that can be sam-
that the system can be adequately studied pled without interrupting normal task per-
only as a whole: a mind situated in its envi- formance.
ronment. To further strengthen this linking hy-
As the time scale of eye movements pothesis between multiple lexical activa-
brings into sharp relief this insight into tions and the probability of fixating various
the real-time situated character of cogni- objects, Allopenna et al. (1998) replicated
HAF.L SPIVEY AND DANIEL RICHARDSON
,86

Figure 20.1. When instructed, "Pick up the candy," participants


frequently look first at the (similar sounding) candle, and then
quickly move their eyes to the candy to pick it up. At the time scale
of the delivery of individual phonemes, linguistic and visual
information is being integrated to drive saccadic eye movements
(Tanenhaus et al., 1995) and continuous hand movements (Spivey
et al., 2005).

the cohort effect, extended it to rhymes recognition that influences the comprehen-
(looking at a handle when instructed, "Pick sion process, but more specifically how
up the candle"), and demonstrated a close actionable the situational constraints allow
correspondence between the eye-movement that copresent object to be. For example,
data and the lexical activations of McClel- Chambers, Tanenhaus, Eberhard, Filip, and
land and Elman's (1986) T R A C E model of Carlson (2002) gave participants instruc-
spoken word recognition (see also Dahan, tions like, "Put the cube inside the can,"
Magnuson, & Tanenhaus, 2001; Spivey et al., when there were two cans in the display.
2005). Similar eye-movement cohort effects They found that situation-specific afford-
have been observed in French (Dahan, ances (of one of the cans in the display
Swingley, Tanenhaus, 8t Magnuson, 2000), being large enough to contain the cube
in Russian (Marian & Spivey, 2003), and and the other can being too small to con-
even across two languages (Ju & Luce, 2004; tain the cube) immediately constrained the
Spivey & Marian, 1999). referential domain of "the can," such that
Notably, it is not just the mere visual participants looked only at the appropri-
copresence of an object during spoken-word ately actionable object - despite the glaring
l a n g u a g e p r o c e s s i n g embodied a n d embedded 3*7

corner of the display to begin planning the


manual action. Thus, the eyes are linking
referring expressions from the spoken lin-
guistic input to their potential referents in
the world about as quickly as they arrive.
Interestingly, when such prepositional-
phrase structures contain syntactic ambigu-
ities, the visual and situational context can
be used immediately to resolve them. For
example, if participants are presented with
a display of real objects like that in Figure
20.3A, and instructed, "Put the spoon on
the napkin in the bowl," they first look at
the spoon and then frequendy fixate the
upper-right napkin, before finally fixating
Figure 20.2. W h i l e listening to t h e instruction, the bowl and carrying out the proper action
"Put the q u e e n of hearts that's b e l o w the j a c k of (Spivey, Tanenhaus, Eberhard, & Sedivy,
diamonds a b o v e t h e king of spades," participants 2002; Tanenhaus et al., 1995). This suggests
concurrently m a k e anticipatory fixations of that participants are often initially parsing
various cards on t h e basis of partial input. S e e "on the napkin" as syntactically attached
text f o r details. to the verb phrase (i.e., temporarily treat-
ing it as the goal for the spoon's "putting"
referential ambiguity in the speech signal. event). The brief fixation of the irrelevant
Thus, speech input alone does not deter- napkin is evidence of this incorrect parse
mine spoken-word recognition. The situa- because it does not happen in the control
tional context, constrained by what relevant condition, where the spoken instruction is
objects are visible and actionable, plays an syntactically unambiguous (e.g., "Put the
immediate role in driving the processes that spoon that's on the napkin in the bowl").
map phonemes onto lexical representations The critical demonstration that visual and
and lexical representations onto referential situational context can intervene during
operations. real-time syntactic processing comes from
In fact, the temporal continuity with the condition where the same syntactically
which the speech stream is integrated with ambiguous instruction was delivered with
visual and situational constraints can be sys- the visual display in Figure 20.3B. In this
tematically illustrated by tracking the com- context, participants hardly ever looked at
prehension of complex clause structures. the irrelevant goal (e.g., the other napkin).
Because there are two spoons in this con-
Eberhard et al. (1995) gave participants
text, upon hearing "the spoon," the par-
instructions like, "Put the queen of hearts
ticipant does not yet know which spoon
that's below the jack of diamonds above the
is being referred to, and both spoons tend
king of spades." In Figure 20.2, a schematic
to get fixated briefly. Then, on hearing
example of a scan path shows the eye posi-
"on the napkin," the referential uncertainty
tion starting at the central cross and jump-
introduced by having two potential spoons
ing to the queen of clubs soon after hear-
causes the comprehension process to parse
ing "queen." After hearing "of hearts," the
"on the napkin" as syntactically attached to
eyes move down to the distracter queen of
the noun phrase rather than to the verb
hearts and flit around there until hearing
phrase, thereby discriminating which spoon
"that's below the jack of diamonds" causes
is being referred to (cf. Crain & Steedman,
them to fixate the target queen of hearts. 1985). Thus, even syntactic processing (once
After a quick check of that jack of dia- thought to be the poster child of encapsu-
monds, and once "king of spades" is heard, lated modularity; cf. Frazier & Clifton, 1996)
the eyes finally move up to the upper-left
MICHAEL SPIVEY AND DANIEL RICHARDSON
>88
these situational constraints combine with
the verb's frequency-based biases in arm,
ment structure (e.g., h o w strongly it p r e fe
a prepositional phrase) to determine tlT
likelihood of a misparse. Most important'
for demonstrating the importance of situ
ated context in language processing, the re"
ative affordances of the objects being moved
around play a crucial role in defining th
situated constraints in which comprehend
sion takes place. Chambers, Tanenhaus, and
Magnuson (2004) gave participants instruc-
tions like, "Pour the egg in the bowl over the
flour." W h e n the second of the two referents
(an egg in a glass) was compatible with the
action (i.e., it was in liquid form and thus
could be poured), the context functioned
like the previous two-referent contexts and
prevented the misparse associated with fix-
ating the incorrect goal (an extra bowl that
was empty). However, when that second
egg was in shell form (and thus not able to
be poured), participants immediately k n e w
which egg was being referred to on hearing
"pour the egg," and thereby fell into the trap
of parsing "in the b o w l " as a goal rather than
a noun-phrase modifier.
Thus, as suggested by McRae, Ferretti,
and A m y o t e (1997), individual verbs, such
as pour, may activate rather complex sets
of semantic features regarding the thematic
roles (e.g., agents, patients, themes, goals)
that are likely to participate in the event
being described. For example, Altmann and
Figure 20.3. W h e n instructed, "Put the spoon on Kamide (1999) presented participants with
the napkin in the bowl," participants often computer-screen displays containing pic-
misparse the syntactic attachment of the initial tures of a man, a woman, a newspaper, and
prepositional phrase when there is only one a cake. As evidence of anticipations from
visible referent for spoon (panel A ) , b u t not a verb's thematic role preferences, when
when there are t w o such referents (panel B). the spoken instruction was "The woman
will read the newspaper," participants often
fixated the newspaper shortly before hear-
is fluidly integrated in real time with the ing the word newspaper - immediately after
situated context in which language compre- hearing the word read, moreover, which is
hension takes place. consistent with the notion of mental ani-
Similar eye-movement evidence for the mation (Hegarty & Just, 1993; Matlock &
immediate use of situational context during Richardson, 2004). W h e n Altmann (2004)
syntactic parsing has been found with partic- showed the pictures and then took them
ipants as young as eight years old (Trueswell, away before presenting the sentence, he
Sekerina, Hill, & Logrip, 1999). Moreover, observed the same basic results, with partic-
Snedeker and Trueswell (2004) showed that ipants fixating the appropriate blank regions
LANGUAGE PROCESSING EMBODIED AND EMBEDDED

that used to contain the relevant objects. form of dynamic visuospatial simulation
This blank-screen paradigm illustrates how is generated when comprehending fictive
the external environment alone is not what motion descriptions (Barsalou, 1999; Zwaan,
imposes the situated constraints; rather, it 2004), and this simulation even incorpo-
is the time-dependent relationship between rates information about terrain maneuver-
the environment and the internal men- ability.
tal representations that creates the situated A typical information-processing account
character of language processing. might suppose that a linguistic figurative
Even when two sentences describe iden- description is processed into a set of spatial
tical referents in the world, aspects of fig- relations, and if necessary, the result is later
urative meaning are detectable in how a passed on for comparison with the output
visual scene is inspected. When static refer- of a visual process. At odds with this view is
ents in the visual scene are best understood the fact that traces of nonliteral content can
by mentally animating them, eye move- be found in the earliest moments of visuo-
ments can provide evidence of that men- motor processing. Comprehension of figu-
tal animation (cf. Hegarty & Just, 1993; rative language can produce mental repre-
Rozenblit, Spivey, & Wojslawowicz, 2002). sentations that are distinct from equivalent
literal counterparts. These representations
Matlock and Richardson (2004) contrasted
are immediately integrated with visual pro-
literal descriptions of scenes ("The road is
cessing, such that various forms of dynamic
in the valley") with descriptions using Ac-
spatial information can drive eye move-
tive motion ("The road runs through the val-
ments around a scene. In this way, even
ley"). Fictive motion descriptions are a type
comprehension of nuances of figurative
of figurative language because they employ
meaning appears to be embedded in the
a verb of motion (runs) but no motion takes
world.
place. Norming results show that fictive and
nonfictive spatial descriptions are equivalent
in meaning. Participants heard one of these 3.1. Semantic Memory
descriptions while looking at a schematic
drawing of a scene. Matlock and Richardson We have seen that during language process-
(2004) found that participants spent more ing, the external world is interrogated con-
time fixating the path when it was described tinuously throughout the course of incre-
using fictive motion. mental linguistic input. This embedded
In that experiment, it is as if the eyes nature can be seen at multiple time scales of
were acting out the subtie figurative spatial language comprehension, even in the way
dynamics implied by the road "running" (cf. that semantic information is encoded and
Madock, 2004), and Richardson and Mat- recalled. In a series of experiments, Richard-
lock (2007) demonstrated that such fictive son and colleagues (Richardson & Kirkham,
motion descriptions affect eye movements 2004; Richardson & Spivey, 2000) found
specifically by evoking mental representa- that when listening to spoken information,
tions of motion. When participants heard relevant spatial locations are encoded and
information about terrain that would affect accessed with a saccade when relevant.
actual motion across the scene, it influenced These experiments can be seen as a linguis-
how they viewed a picture if it was described tic case of situated cognition, related to epi-
with fictive motion. Looking times and stemic actions (Kirsh & Maglio, 1994) and
eye movements scanning along the path deictic pointers (Ballard, Hayhoe, Pook, &
increased during fictive motion descrip- Rao, 1997).
tions when the terrain was first described Figure 20.4 shows a schematic of Richard-
as difficult ("The desert is hilly") as com- son and Spivey's (2000) first experiment.
pared to easy ("The desert is flat"); there Participants watched a video clip of a talk-
were no such effects for descriptions with- ing head delivering a short piece of infor-
out fictive motion. It appears that some mation such as, "Shakespeare's first plays
Yfo MICHAEL SPIVEY AND DANIEL RICHARDSON

In the presentation phase of


each trial, four video clips of
actors making short factual
statements appeared in each
of four ports on the screen.

In the test phase, the ports were empty and an


audio clip relating to one of the four facts was
played. Subjects judged whether the statement
was true or false while their eye movemet
recorded.

Each trial was analysed by


'dock coding* the ports. The
critical port was numbered 0,
and other ports 1 - 3 in
clockwise rotation.

Ports
Figure 20.4. Design and results of Richardson and Spivey (2000,
experiment 1).

were romantic comedies. His last was The video clips were replaced by four identical
Tempest." These talking heads appeared in spinning crosses (Spivey & Richardson, 2000,
turn in each of four ports of a two-by-two experiment 2), when the ports moved to
grid. After presentation, the participants the center of the screen during presentation
looked at a blank grid and heard a state- (Spivey & Richardson, 2000, experiment 5),
ment that related to one of the facts (e.g., and when the ports moved independently
"Shakespeare's last play was The Tempest'). to different locations on the screen before
They answered out loud whether it was the answer period (Richardson & Kirkham,
true or false. As they answered, participants' 2004). Moreover, in all experiments, par-
eye movements were recorded. The port ticipants' accuracy in answering the factual
that had previously contained the talking question was not related to whether they
head that conveyed the relevant information looked at the critical port. Why, then,
was termed the critical port. It was found that do participants continue to spatially index
there were almost twice as many fixations information — encoding location of an event
to the critical port than to each of the other and refixating that location when recalling
ports. This result was replicated when the its properties?
LANGUAGE PROCESSING EMBODIED AND EMBEDDED 39>

A first attempt to explain this spatial- the experiments of Richardson and Spivey
indexing behavior might cite the phe- ( 2 0 0 0 ) and of Richardson and Kirkham
nomenon of context-dependent memory, in ( 2 0 0 4 ) were treating pieces of evanescent
which memory is improved if the conditions auditory semantic information as if they
that were present during encoding are rein- were stable physical objects in the world
stantiated during recall (e.g., Bradley, Cuth- there to be reinspected whenever the need
bert, & Lang, 1988; Godden & Baddeley, arose. Richardson and Kirkham ( 2 0 0 4 ) found
>975'' Winograd & Church, 1 9 8 8 ) . This expla- that despite the fragility of infants' spatial
nation falls short on two counts, however. abilities around that age (Colombo, 2001;
Memory was not improved in this paradigm, Gilmore 8c Johnson, 1 9 9 7 ) , infants as young
because looks to the critical port did not as six months of age showed the same
produce more correct answers. In several of spatial-indexing behavior: they encoded the
the experiments, the conditions that were location of a toy that danced to a tune inside
present during encoding were not reinstan- a port, tracked the location of the port as
tiated during recall, because the ports were it moved, and refixated the port when the
in different locations between presentation tune was heard again. These results sug-
and test phases. gest that the embedded nature of linguistic
The more fitting explanation draws on semantic memory has roots in early develop-
the notion of external memory (Brooks, 1991; ment.
Clark, 1997; O'Regan, 1992). In everyday
life (Simons 8c Levin, 1997) and carefully
circumscribed experimental tasks (Ballard, 3.2. Conversation
Hayhoe, 8c Pelz, 1995; Hayhoe, Bensinger, A stream of speech is processed by a lis-
8c Ballard, 1 9 9 8 ) , it appears that partici- tener, moment by moment, in reference to
pants do not encode many properties of the the external world. In this sense, language
visual world. Instead, as and when informa- comprehension is embedded. But of course,
tion is needed, it is accessed from external in the main, language use is an interac-
memory via an eye movement. As every tion between people. What does the embed-
system of information storage needs a sys- ded nature of language entail for the inter-
tem of information retrieval, perhaps spatial play of comprehension and production that
indexing stores the addresses for a content- occurs during naturalistic conversation? The
addressable memory that exists in the exter- language-as-action tradition has long seen
nal environment rather than in the brain. conversation as a form of joint action that
It could be argued that participants in is situated in the world (Clark, 1 9 9 6 ) . And
the experiments of Richardson and Spivey recent technological advances have allowed
( 2 0 0 0 ) and of Richardson and Kirkham the time course of conversation and linguis-
( 2 0 0 4 ) were tacitly behaving as if the fac- tic processing to be studied in fine detail, and
tual information they had heard could be thus have formed a bridge to the language-
accessed from external memory. When a as-product tradition (Trueswell 8c Tanen-
fact was heard, participants associated the haus, 2 0 0 4 ) .
information with a port on the computer In this section, we draw three broad con-
screen. As the information was needed dur- clusions firom the current literature that
ing the question period, the association was speak to the embedded nature of conversa-
activated and a saccade was launched to tion. First, participants in a conversation are
retrieve that information. Of course, in this aware of how the other is cognitively situ-
case, there was no useful information there ated in the world. H. Clark ( 1 9 9 6 ) describes
at all, and so accuracy in answering the ques- this as knowledge of the common ground,
tion did not increase with fixations to the and recent evidence supports his notion that
empty critical port. linguistic processing is intimately affected by
This interpretation suggests that, in terms assumptions about an interlocutor's visual
of their looking behavior, participants in perspective, past experience, and beliefs.
MICHAEL. SPIVEY AND DANIEL RICHARDSON
V)1
Initial results from other collaborative
Second, interlocutors actively manipulate
tasks, however, suggested that listeners do
the common ground for communicative
not extend very far into a consideration of
purposes. Just as an individual may alter his
the speaker's mental states (Keysar, Barr,
or her environment during a situated cogni-
Balin, & Paek, 1998). Keysar, Barr, Balin, and
tive task (Hutchins, 1995; Kirsh & Maglio,
Brauner (2000) used a referential communi-
1994), or two participants may anticipate
cation task (Krauss & Weinheimer, 1964) ;n
one another's task constraints during joint
which two people are seated on either side
action (cf. Knoblich & Jordan, 2003; Sebanz,
of an array of pigeonholes containing vari-
Knoblich, & Prinz, 2003), so two conver-
ous objects and the director (a confederate)
sants will use actions and gestures, con-
instructs the matcher to move objects. Some
currendy with their speech, to coordinate
of the array is blocked so that the director
their interaction and update the common
cannot see some of the objects. Keysar et al.
ground. Last, the degree to which interlocu-
(2000) found that when the matchers hear,
tors are able to coordinate their visual atten-
"Pick up the smallest candle," they fixate
tion moment by moment across a shared
(and sometime pick up) the smallest can-
visual display is causally related to the suc-
dle they can see, even though that candle
cess with which they communicate.
is occluded from the directors' view, and
Listeners are certainly sensitive to some
hence could not possibly be the intended
facts about a speaker. For example, Fitneva
referent. It was argued that during such a
and Spivey (2004] showed that knowledge of
conversation, the matcher initially takes an
the author of a spoken statement influences
egocentric interpretation of the director's
lexical ambiguity resolution. Although the
instruction and can take into consideration
word case is ambiguous between a court
only the director's knowledge state at the
case and a container case, when a judge says
end of the process, as an error correction.
the word, listeners immediately resolve it as
meaning court case, and when a store owner Later studies (Hanna, Tanenhaus, &
says it, listeners immediately resolve it as a Trueswell, 2003) argue that the Keysar
meaning a container case. et al. (2000) result misses the pervasive effect
Metzing and Brennan (2003) showed that of common-ground information by swamp-
the identity of speakers is also impor- ing it with typicality effects. In short, when
tant when parsing novel forms of refer- the matchers hear "the smallest candle," the
ence known as conceptual pacts (Brennan object that is occluded from the speaker's
& Clark, 1996). In their task, a participant perspective happens to be the most typi-
and a confederate repeatedly referred to cal referent of the statement, and hence it
a novel object as, for example, the "shiny attracts a higher proportion of fixations than
cylinder." This is an example of lexical a completely unrelated item. Using a similar
entrainment (Garrod & Anderson, 1987). design, Hanna et al. (2003) deconfounded
At a later stage the object was referred these variables. In the key condition, the
to again, either by the old or a new con- director instructs the matcher, "Put a trian-
federate, or by the old or a new name gle on top of the red one," when two red
(e.g., the "silver pipe"). Although partici- triangles are in view. One of these red tri-
pants fixated the correct object equally fast angles is not known to the speaker, how-
regardless of which confederate used the ever, and so could not be the intended ref-
old name, participants were relatively slow erent. In this case, when the target and the
when the old confederate used the new competitor are identical, matchers make a
name. This momentary confusion shows higher proportion of fixations to the cor-
that speaker identity is linked to particular rect target from the very moment they
conceptual pacts and that listeners expect hear the word red. Therefore, rather than
terms within common ground to be reliably act solely as a late source of error correc-
used. tion, common-ground information acts as a
LANGUAGE PROCESSING EMBODIED AND EMBEDDED

constraint (among many) on reference reso- see the builder at work, this visual com-
lution at the earliest stages of linguistic pro- mon ground was exploited and continually
cessing (Hanna & Tanenhaus, 2004; see also updated as a joint activity. For example,
Nadig & Sedivy, 2002). while the director was describing the next
In the matching studies discussed so far, block to pick up, the builder might find
common ground was investigated by manip- it in a pile and exhibit it to the director,
ulating whether a director had knowledge of who would interrupt or alter his description
the physical presence of a particular item. midsentence to confirm whether it was the
Conversants appear to keep track of changes correct piece. Similarly, the builder would
in common ground brought about by lin- poise a block just above where he or she
guistic manipulations as well. In an exper- believed it should be attached to the model
iment by Brown-Schmidt, Campana, and or turn the model to face the director so
Tanenhaus (2004), a speaker instructed a lis- that the director simply had to acknowledge
tener to move various blocks on a grid. Both whether the move was correct. These ges-
were naive participants. Sometimes during tures were precisely timed and coordinated
this task, the speaker referred to "the red with the director's speech. When a visual
one" even though there were several red common ground is available, participants
blocks in sight. The listener was able to fixate situate their dialog by engaging in complex
the correct block, however, because what joint activities that support and even sup-
the speaker had said previously had implic- plant verbal communication (see also Bren-
idy identified a smaller set of objects that nan, 2004).
included only one of the red blocks. In this In a classic case of situated cognition,
way, linguistic context can circumscribe the Kirsch and Maglio (1994) found that expert
referential domain. Tetris players would rotate shapes using
Our second claim regarding the embed- a button press, as it was a faster way to
ded nature of conversation is that partici- view different orientations than using men-
pants not only are aware of how one another tal rotation. They termed this button press
have situated their dialogue in the world an epistemic action because participants take
but also actively manipulate that common action in the world to manipulate knowl-
ground as a coordinated joint activity that edge rather than use purely mental oper-
uses pointing, placing, and gestures (Clark, ations. The external world was acted on
1996, 2003; Clark & Brennan, 1991; Schober, to process information. Similarly, in situ-
1993). For example, Bangerter (2004) exam- ated communication, conversants take joint
ined how participants discussed pictures action in the world rather than use purely
when they could or could not point. At long linguistic communication. In this way, the
distances, where they would be ambigu- physical gestures and actions that conver-
ous, there were fewer pointing gestures. At sants use can be thought of as joint epistemic
closer ranges, pointing increased and lin- actions.
guistic description of location decreased. In But is it the case that these situated
this way, pointing gestures were used oppor- strategies and dynamic coordination of com-
tunistically as part of a composite signal with mon ground are actually more efficient
speech. than unembedded one-way communication
Clark and Krych (2004) analyzed other (as in reading or listening to the radio)?
forms of physical action that are employed Research quantifying the degree of coordi-
to manipulate common ground. In their nation between conversants' visual attention
task, a director participant instructed a suggests that this is true. Richardson and
builder participant how to construct a Lego Dale (2005) analyzed the statistical patterns
model. When the director could not see of eye movements as a fine-grained index of
what the builder was doing, performance how speakers and listeners deployed their
suffered. When the director was able to attention within a visual common ground.
394 MICHAEL SPIVEY AND DANIEL R I C H A R D S O N

Rather than study speakers and listeners sep- of this time frame suggests that speakers
arately, and asking them to produce or com- and listeners may keep track moment by
prehend short sentences, they tracked eye moment of a subset of the depicted people
movements of both speakers and listeners who are relevant, just as listeners in Brown-
who were engaged in a spontaneous, com- Schmidt et al. (2004) were able to linguis-
plex discourse. They quantified the tempo- tically circumscribe the referential domain.
ral coupling (or entrainment) between con- Richardson and Dale (2005) found that the
versants' eye movements and examined its overlap between speaker and listener eye
relationship to the success of the discourse. movements peaked at about 2000 ms. In
First, the speech and eye movements of other words, two seconds after the speaker
one set of participants were recorded as they looked at a cast member, the listener was
looked at pictures of six cast members of most likely to be looking at the same cast
a TV sitcom (either Friends or The Simp- member. The timing of this peak roughly
sons). They spoke spontaneously about their corresponds to results in the speech produc-
favorite episode and characters, or described tion and comprehension literatures. Speak-
what had happened in a scene they had just ers will fixate objects 800 ms to 1000 ms
watched. One-minute segments were cho- (Griffin & Bock, 2000; Meyer, Sleiderink,
sen and used unedited, with all the devia- & Levelt, 1998) before naming them, and
tions, hesitations, and repetitions of just a listeners will typically take 500 ms to 1000
minute of normal speech. These segments ms to fixate an object from the word's
were then played back to a separate set onset (Allopenna et al., 1998). These fig-
of participants. The listeners looked at the ures include cases of proper-noun produc-
same visual display of the cast members, tion and comprehension, but this peak in
and their eye movements were recorded as overlap between speaker and listener eye
they listened to the segments of speech. movements was still present in the data
They then answered a series of comprehen- when all names of the cast members, and
sion questions about what was said by the associated speaker fixations, were removed
speaker. from the analysis. (Of course, no such peak
Listener and speaker eye movements was observed in any of the speaker x
were coded as to which of the six cast mem- randomized-listener analyses.) The coupling
bers (if any) was being fixated during every between speaker and listener eye move-
33-ms time slice. Cross-recurrence analysis ments was pervasive, suggesting that plan-
(Zbilut, Giuliani, & Webber, 1998; Zbilut ning diverse types of speech will influence
& Webber, 1992) was used to quantify the the speaker's eye movements, and a few sec-
degree to which the speaker and listener eye onds later, hearing them will influence the
positions overlapped at successive time lags. listener's eye movements.
This speaker x listener distribution of fix- Importantly, this entrainment of eye-
ations could be compared to a speaker x movement patterns between speaker and
randomized-listener distribution, which was listener was not merely an epiphenome-
produced by shuffling the temporal order of nal by-product of the conversation process.
each listener's eye-movement sequence and It played a functional role in comprehen-
then calculating the cross-recurrence with sion. When the overall proportion of cross-
the speakers. This randomized series serves recurrence between individual speaker-
as a baseline of looking at chance at any given listener pairs was quantified, the strength
point in time, but with the same overall dis- of the relationship between speaker and
tribution of looks to each picture as the real listener eye-movement patterns reliably
listeners. predicted how many of the comprehen-
From the moment a speaker looks at a sion questions the listener answered cor-
picture, and for the following six seconds, a rectly. This correlation was supported by a
listener was more likely than chance to be follow-up study that experimentally manip-
looking at that same picture. The breadth ulated the relationship between speaker and
LANGUAGE PROCESSING EMBODIED AND EMBEDDED 395

Time of lag (ms)

Figure 20.5. Average cross-recurrence of eye position at different


time lags for forty-nine speaker-listener pairs (Richardson & Dale,
2005). See text for details.

listener eye movements. When a low-level haps cognitive psychology's long-standing


perceptual cue made the eye movements of preoccupation with circumstances of unidi-
a listener more or less like the speaker's, rectional unembedded language use, such as
the listener's performance on comprehen- reading experiments and listening to decon-
sion questions was correspondingly affected. textualized, prerecorded oration, was a mis-
Despite the fact that conversants could leading way to begin developing theories
not interact with each other in Richardson about language (cf. Spivey et al., 2002). The
and Dale's (2005) experiments, their visual rarified ability to represent things that are
attention was coupled at the millisecond res- not present or ideas not thought before,
olution of eye movements. Moreover, this in the absence of immediate environmen-
coupling determined listeners' comprehen- tal support, might be better understood as
sion performance. Thus, cross-recurrence the special peculiarity of language, not the
analysis shows that looking around the core of its everyday function. For exam-
common ground in step with each other ple, across developmental time, children
appears to drive the process of conversants' take much longer to understand references
mutual understanding, and so provides a to objects when they are absent, gaining
quantitative data visualization of the notion competence in comprehension and then
of embedded language and situated dis- production throughout the second year of
course. life (Huttenlocher & Smiley, 1987; Saylor,
2004; Swingley & Fernald, 2002). Interest-
ingly, caregivers usually anchor their ref-
4. Conclusion erences to absent objects via objects that
are present, asking, for example, "Where's
Perhaps the case of a B B C radio play about Daddy?" and gesturing to his briefcase (Hut-
Roman senators is actually a misleading tenlocher, 1974; Saylor & Baldwin, 2004).
place to start in an analysis of language. Per- Similarly, one could speculate that across
MICHAEL SPIVEY AND DANIEL RICHARDSON

evolutionary time, language might well have a programmed list of conceptual features,
first emerged situated in cooperative activi- but rather is composed of the sensorimotor
ties such as hunting and tool use (Barsalou, experiences that it expects to be situated in
1999; Corballis, 1992) rather than as a way to the world on hearing the word apple. Per-
refer to abstract concepts and objects that haps, so with humans, our understanding of
were not present. language is c o m p o s e d not of amodal logi-
Regardless of the ontogeny and phy- cal symbols that are divorced from the real
togeny of language, it is clear that the study world, but instead of perceptual-motor sim-
of adult language use in naturalistic con- ulations and of situated actions in the envi-
texts reveals a rich interaction with the ronment and w i t h other language users.
world. Language processing is not some-
thing that happens just in the individual
brain of the speaker or the listener. In Acknowledgments
many circumstances, the proper analysis of
language processing is at the level of the We are grateful to Rolf Zwaan and the editors
organisms and the environment in which for helpful comments that improved the exposi-
they are situated. The phenomena that arise tion, and to the two Sams for giving their fathers
enough free time to write this chapter. Work on
at such a level of analysis clearly exhibit
this chapter was supported by NIMH-R01-63961
interaction-dominant dynamics, rather than
to M. J. S.
component-dominant dynamics, thus obvi-
ating the linear module-based analysis com-
mon to the information-processing frame- References
work. As part of the linguistic process of
recognizing words or parsing syntax, par-
Allopenna, P. D., Magnuson, J. S., & Tanenhaus,
ticipants make saccades to referents in the
M. K. (1998). Tracking the time course of spo-
world that are phonetically, semantically, ken word recognition using eye movements:
or pragmatically appropriate. In conversa- Evidence for continuous mapping models.
tion, the degree to which a listener follows a Journal of Memory and Language, 38(4), i a -
speaker's gaze around the world is an indica- 439-
tion of their understanding, and in face-to- Altmann, G. T. M. (2004). Language-mediated
face conversation, eye movements can serve eye movements in the absence of a visual
as linguistic cues. Language comprehension world: The "blank screen paradigm." Cogni-
could even be called "stubbornly situated" tion, 93, 79-87.
cognition, because several paradigms have Altmann, G. T. M., & Kamide, Y. (1999). Incre-
found that participants look systematically mental interpretation at verbs: Restricting the
at entirely blank regions of space (that used domain of subsequent reference. Cognition,
to contain the referents) during linguistic 73, 247-264.
processing. Austin, J. L. (1962). How to do things with words.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Although they are logically separable, Ballard, D., Hayhoe, M., & Pelz, J. (1995). Mem-
the perspectives of embedded language and ory representations in natural tasks. Journal of
embodied language (see Zwaan & Kaschak, Cognitive Neuroscience, 7, 66-80.
this volume) have an interesting synergy. For Ballard, D., Hayhoe, M., Pook, P., & Rao, R.
example, these ideas have been combined in (1997). Deictic codes for the embodiment of
the conversational robot Ripley (Roy, 2005; cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 20,
Roy & Mukherjee, 2004), which represents 723-767.
the meanings of objects by multimodal sen- Bangerter, A. (2004). Using pointing and describ-
ing to achieve joint focus of attention in dia-
sory expectations at certain locations (sim-
logue. Psychological Science, 15(6), 415—419.
ilar ideas have been developed in theories
Barsalou, L. W. (1999). Language comprehen-
of perception; Noe, 2004; O'Regan & Noe,
sion: Archival memory or preparation for sit-
2001). That is to say, for the robot, the uated action? Discourse Processes, 28(1), 61-
meaning of the word apple is not merely 80.
39?
l a n g u a g e p r o c e s s i n g embodied a n d embedded

Bradley, M. M., Cuthbert, B. N., & Lang, P. J. ing. Journal of Memory k. Langua&, ;o(i), 62-
(1988). Perceptually driven movements as con- 81.
textual retrieval cues. Bulletin of the Psycho- Colombo, J. (2001). The development of visual
nomic Society, 26, 541-553. attention in infancy. Annual Review of Psychol-
Brennan, S. (2004). How conversation is shaped ogy, s2> 337-367-
by visual and spoken evidence. In J. Trueswell Cooper, R. M. (1974). The control of eye fixation
& M. Tanenhaus (Eds.), Approaches to study- by the meaning of spoken language: A new
ing world-situated language use: Bridging the methodology for the real-time investigation
language-as-product and language-as-action tra- of speech perception, memory, and language
ditions (pp. 95-129). Cambridge, MA: MIT processing. Cognitive Psychology, 6{i), H4-
Press. 107.
Brennan, S. E., & Clark, H. H. (1996). Concep- Corballis, M. C. (1992). On the evolution of lan-
tual pacts and lexical choice in conversation. guage and generativity. Cognition, 44(3), 197-
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning,
226.
Memory, &s Cognition, 22(6), 1482-1493.
Crain, S., & Steedman, M. (1985). On not being
Brooks, R. (1991). Intelligence without represen-
led up the garden path. In D. Dowty, L. Kart-
tation. Artificial Intelligence, 47,139-159.
tunen, 8c A. Zwicky (Eds.), Natural language
Brown-Schmidt, S., Campana, E., & Tanen-
parsing (pp. 320-358). Cambridge: Cambridge
haus, M. K. (2004). Real-time reference
University Press.
resolution by naïve participants during a
Dahan, D., Magnuson, J. S., 8c Tanenhaus, M. K.
task-based unscripted conversation. In J. C.
(2001). Time course of frequency effects in
Trueswell & M. K. Tanenhaus (Eds.), World-
spoken-word recognition: Evidence from eye
situated language processing: Bridging the
movements. Cognitive Psychology, 42, 317-367.
language-as-product and language-as-action tra-
ditions (pp. 153-172). Cambridge, MA: MIT Dahan, D., Swingley, D., Tanenhaus, M. K., &
Press. Magnuson, J. S. (2000). Linguistic gender and
Chambers, C. G., Tanenhaus, M. K, Eberhard, spoken-word recognition in French. Journal of
K. M., Filip,. H., & Carlson, G. N. (2002). Memory and Language, 42, 465-480.
Circumscribing referential domains during Eberhard, K., Spivey-Knowlton, M., Sedivy, J.,
real-time language comprehension. Journal of 8c Tanenhaus, M. (1995). Eye movements as a
Memory &É Language, 47(1), 30-49. window into real-time spoken language com-
Chambers, C. G., Tanenhaus, M. K., & Mag- prehension in natural contexts. Journal of Psy-
nuson, J. S. (2004). Actions and affordances cholinguistic Research, 24, 409-436.
in syntactic ambiguity resolution. Journal of Fitneva, S., 8c Spivey, M. (2004). Context and lan-
Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, 8É guage processing: The effect of authorship. In
Cognition, 30(3), 687-696. J. Trueswell 81 M. Tanenhaus (Eds.), World
Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, situated language use: Psycholinguistic, linguis-
and world together again. Cambridge, MA: tic and computational perspectives on bridging
MIT Press. the product and action traditions (pp. 317-327).
Clark, H. H. (1992). Arenas of language use. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cam-
Clark, H. H. (1996). Using language. Cambridge: bridge, MA: MIT Press.
Cambridge University Press. Frazier, L., 8c Clifton, C. (1996). Construal. Cam-
Clark, H. H. (2003). Pointing and placing. In S. bridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kita (Ed.), Pointing: Where language, culture, Garrod, S., 8c Anderson, A. (1987). Saying what
and cognition meet (pp. 243-268). Mahwah, NJ: you mean in dialogue: A study in conceptual
Lawrence Erlbaum. and semantic co-ordination. Cognition, 27,181—
218.
Clark, H. H., & Brennan, S. E. (1991). Ground-
Gibson, J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual
ing in communication. In L. B. Resnick, J. M.
perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Levine, 8c S. D. Teasley (Eds.), Perspectives on
Gdmore, R. O., 8c Johnson, M. H. (1997). Ego-
socially shared cognition (pp. 127-149). Wash-
ington, D C : American Psychological Associa- centric action in early infancy: Spatial frames
tion. of reference for saccades. Psychological Science,
8, 224-230.
Clark, H. H, 8L Krych, M. A. (2004). Speaking Glenberg, A. (1997). What memory is for. Behav-
while monitoring addressees for understand- ioral and Brain Sciences, 20,1-55.
598 MICHAEL SPIVEY AND DANIEL R I C H A R D S O N

Godden, D. R., & Baddeley, A. D. (1975). Kirsh, D., & Maglio, P. ( 1 9 9 4 ) , On distinguish-
Context-dependent memory in two natu- ing epistemic from pragmatic action. Cognitive
ral environments: On land and underwater. Science, 18, 5 1 3 - 5 4 9 .
British Journal of Psychology, 66(3), 325-331. Knoblich, G., &. Jordan, J. (2003). Action coor-
Gold, J., & Shadlen, M. (2000). Representation dination in groups and individuals: Learning
of a perceptual decision in developing oculo- anticipatory control. Journal of Experimental
motor commands. Nature, 404, 390-394. Psychology: Learning, Memory, & Cognition, in
Greeno, J. (1998). The situativity of knowing, 1006-1016.
learning, and research. American Psychologist, Krauss, R. M., 8c Weinheimer, S. (1964). Changes
5?, 5-26- in reference phrases as a function of frequency
Grice, P. (1989). Studies in the way of words. Cam- of usage in social interaction: A preliminary
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press. study. Psychonomic Science, 1, 113-114.
Griffin, Z. M., & Bock, K. (2000). What the eyes Marian, V., 8c Spivey, M. (2003). Competing
say about speaking. Psychological Science, 11(4), activation in bilingual language processing:
274-279. Within- and between-language competition.
Hanna, J. E., & Tanenhaus, M. K. (2004). Prag- Bilingualism: Language and Cognition, 6, 97-
matic effects on reference resolution in a 115.
collaborative task: Evidence from eye move- Marslen-Wilson, W. (1987). Functional paral-
ments. Cognitive Science, 28(1), 105-115. lelism in spoken word recognition. Cognition1
Hanna, J. E., Tanenhaus, M. K., & Trueswell, 25, 71—102.
J. C. (2003). The effects of common ground Matlock, T. (2004). Fictive motion as cognitive
and perspective on domains of referential simulation. Memory & Cognition, 32, 1389—
interpretation. Journal of Memory Si Language, 1400.
49W. 4J-&- Matlock, T. M., 8c Richardson, D. C. (2004). Do
Hayhoe, M., Bensinger, D., & Ballard, D. (1998). eye movements go with fictive motion? In
Task constraints in visual working memory. Proceedings of the 26th Annual Meeting of the
Vision Research, 3 8 , 1 2 5 - 1 3 7 . Cognitive Science Society (pp. 909-914). Mali-
Hegarty, M., & Just, M. A. (1993). Construct- wall, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
ing mental models of machines from text and McClelland, J., & Elman, J. (1986). The TRACE
diagrams. Journal of Memory 86 Language, 32, model of speech perception. Cognitive Psychol-
ogy, 18,1-86.
7I7~"742-
McRae, K., Ferretti, T., 8c Amyote, L. (1997).
Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cam-
Thematic roles as verb-specific concepts.
bridge, MA: MIT Press.
Language and Cognitive Processes, 12, 137-
Huttenlocher, J. (1974). The origins of language
176.
comprehension. In R. Solso (Ed.), Theories
Metzing, C., 8c Brennan, S. E. (2003). When
in cognitive psychology: The Loyola symposium
conceptual pacts are broken: Partner-specific
(pp. 331-388). Potomac, MD: Erlbaum.
effects on the comprehension of referring
Huttenlocher, J., & Smiley, P. (1987). Early word
expressions. Journal of Memory & Language,
meanings: The case of object names. Cognitive
49(2), 201-213.
Psychology, 19(1), 63-89.
Ju, M., & Luce, P. (2004). Falling on sensitive Meyer, A. S., Sleiderink, A. M., 8c Levelt, W. J.
ears: Constraints on bilingual lexical activa- M. ( 1 9 9 8 ) . Viewing and naming objects: Eye
tion. Psychological Science, 15, 314-318. movements during noun phrase production.
Kelso, J. (1995). Dynamic patterns: The self- Cognition, 6 6 ( 2 ) , B 2 5 - B 3 3 .
organization of brain and behavior. Cambridge, Nadig, A. S., 8c Sedivy, J. C. (2002). Evidence
MA: MIT Press. of perspective-taking constraints in children's
Keysar, B., Barr, D. J., Balin, J. A., 81 Brauner, on-line reference resolution. Psychological Sci-
J. S. (2000). Taking perspective in conversa- ence, 1 3 , 3 2 9 - 3 3 6 .
tion: The role of mutual knowledge in com- Neisser, U. ( 1 9 6 7 ) . Cognitive psychology. EastNor-
prehension. Psychological Science, 11(1), 3 2 - 3 8 . walk, CT: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Keysar, B., Barr, D. J., Balin, J. A., & Paek, T. S. Neisser, U. ( 1 9 7 6 ) . Cognition and reality: Princi-
(1998). Definite reference and mutual knowl- ples and implications of cognitive psychology. San
edge: Process models of common ground in Francisco: W. H. Freeman.
comprehension. Journal of Memory &! Lan- Noe, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge,
guage, 39(1), 1-20. MA: MIT Press.
L A N G U A G E PROCESSING E M B O D I E D A N D E M B E D D E D 3 9 ?

O'Regan, J. K. (1992)- Solving the "real" mysteries Saylor, M. M., 8c Baldwin, D. A. (2004). Dis-
of visual perception: T h e world as an outside cussing those not present: Comprehension
memory. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 46, of references to absent caregiver». Journal of
461-488. Child Language, 31, 537-560.
O'Regan, J. K., 8c Noë, A. (2001), A sensorimo- Schober, M. F. (1993). Spatial perspective-taking
tor account of vision and visual conscious- in conversation. Cognition, 47(1), 1-24.
ness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 939- Searle, J. (1969). Speech acts: An essay in the philos-
1031. ophy of language- N e w York: Cambridge Uni-
Poincaré, H. (1906). Les mathématiques et la versity Press.
logique. Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, Sebanz, N., Knoblich, G . , & Prinz, W. (2003).
14, 294-317. (Translated in W. Ewald (Ed.), Representing others' actions: Just like one's
1996, From Kant to Hilbert: A source book in the own? Cognition, 88, B11-B21.
foundations of mathematics (Vol. 2). Oxford: Simons, D. J., 8c Levin, D. (1997). Change
Oxford University Press.) blindness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 1, 2 6 1 -
Port, R., 8c van Gelder, T. (Eds.). (1995). Mind as 267.
motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cogni- Snedeker, J., 8c Trueswell, J. (2004). The develop-
tion. Cambridge, M A : M I T Press. ing constraints on parsing decisions: The role
Richardson, D . , 8c Dale, R. (2005). Looking to of lexical-biases and referential scenes in child
understand: T h e coupling between speakers' and adult sentence processing. Cogtitwe Psy-
and listeners' eye movements and its relation- chology, 49, 238-299.
ship to discourse comprehension. Cognitive Spivey, M., 8c Dale, R. (2004). On the continu-
Science, 29, 39-54. ity of mind: Toward a dynamical account of
Richardson, D., 8c Kirkham, N. (2004). Multi- cognition. In B. Ross (Ed.), The psychology of
modal events and moving locations: Eye learning and motivation (Vol. 45, pp. 87-142).
movements of adults and 6-month-olds reveal San Diego, C A : Elsevier.
dynamic spatial indexing. Journal of Experi- Spivey, M., Grosjean, M., & Knoblich, G.
mental Psychology: General, 133, 46-62. (2005). Continuous attraction toward phono-
Richardson, D. C., 8c Matlock, T. M. (2007). The logical competitors. Proceedings of the National
integration of figurative language and static Academy of Sciences, 102,10393-10398.
depictions: An eye movement study of fictive Spivey, M., 8c Marian, V. (1999). Crosstalk
motion. Cognition, 102(1), 129-138. between native and second languages: Partial
Richardson, D., 8c Spivey, M. (2000). Represen- activation of an irrelevant lexicon. Psychologi-
tation, space and Hollywood Squares: Looking cal Science, 10, 281-284.
at things that aren't there anymore. Cognition, Spivey, M., Tanenhaus, M., Eberhard, K, 8c
76, 269-295. Sedivy, J. (2002). Eye movements and spo-
Rosen, R. (2000). Essays on life itself. N e w York: ken language comprehension: Effects of visual
Columbia University Press. context on syntactic ambiguity resolution.
Roy, D. (2005). Grounding words in perception Cognitive Psychology, 45(4), 447-481.
and action: Computational insights. Trends in Spivey-Knowlton, M., Tanenhaus, M., Eberhard,
Cognitive Sciences, 9, 389-396. K, Sedivy, J. (1998). Integration of visuospa-
Roy, D., 8c Mukherjee, N. (2004). Towards sit- tial and linguistic information in real-time and
uated speech understanding: Visual context real-space. In P. Olivier 8c K G a p p (Eds.),
priming of language models. Computer Speech Representation and processing of spatial expres-
and Language, 19, 227-248. sions (pp. 201-214). Mahwah, N J : Lawrence
Rozenblit, L., Spivey, M., 8c Wojslawowicz, J. Erlbaum.
(2002). Mechanical reasoning about gear-and- Sternberg, S. (1969). The discovery of processing
belt systems: Do eye movements predict per- stages: Extensions of Donders' method. Acta
formance? In M. Anderson, B. Meyer, 8c P. Psychologica, 30, 276-315.
Olivier (Eds.), Diagrammatic representation Swingley, D., & Femald, A. (2002). Recogni-
and reasoning (pp. 223-240). Berlin: Springer- tion of words referring to present and absent
Verlag. objects by 24-month-olds. Journal of Memory
Saylor, M. M. (2004). Twelve- and sixteen- &! Language, 46(1), 39-56.
month-old infants recognize properties of Tanenhaus, M . K , Spivey-Knowlton, M . J., Eber-
mentioned absent things. Developmental Sci- hard, K. M., 8c Sedivy, J. C. (1995). Integration
ence, 7(5), 599-611. of visual and linguistic information in spoken
400 MICHAEL SPIVEY AND DANIEL RICHARDSON

language comprehension. Science, 268(5217), selection, selection for action, and actio
1632-1634. for perception. Visual Cognition, 3,
Trueswell, J., Sekerina, I., Hill, N., & Logrip, M. 361.
(1999). The kindergarten-path effect: Study- van Orden, G., Holden, J., & Turvey, M. (2003)
ing on-line sentence processing in young chil- Self-organization of cognitive performance
dren. Cognition, 73, 89-134. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General
Trueswell, J., & Tanenhaus, M. (Eds.). (2004). 132, 33 1- 35°-
Approaches to studying world-situated lan- Ward, L. (2002). Dynamical cognitive science
guage use: Bridging the language-as-prvduct and Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
language-as-action traditions. Cambridge, MA: Winograd, E., & Church, V. (1988). Role of spa-
MIT Press. tial location in learning face-name associa-
Turvey, M. T. (2004). Impredicativity, dynamics, tions. Memory and Cognition, 16(1), 1-7.
and the perception-action divide. In V. K. Jirsa Zbilut, J. P., & Webber, C. L., Jr. (1992). Embed-
& J. A. S. Kelso (Eds.), Coordination dynamics: dings and delays as derived from quantifica-
Issues and trends (Vol. 1, pp. 1-20). New York: tion of recurrence plots. Physics Letters A, 171
Springer-Verlag. 199-203.
Turvey, M., & Carello, C. (1995). Some dynam- Zbilut, J. P., Giuliani, A., & Webber, C. L.,
ical themes in perception and action. In R. Jr. (1998). Detecting deterministic signals in
Port & T. van Gelder, Mind as motion: Explo- exceptionally noisy environments using cross-
rations in the dynamics of cognition (pp. 373- recurrence quantification. Physics Letters A
401). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 246, 122-128.
Turvey, M., & Shaw, R. (1999). Ecological foun- Zwaan, R. A. (2004). The immersed experiencer:
dations of cognition: I. Symmetry and speci- Toward an embodied theory of language com-
ficity of animal-environment systems. Journal prehension. In B. Ross (Ed.), The psychology of
of Consciousness Studies, 6,111-123. learning and motivation (Vol. 44, pp. 35-62).
van der Heijden, A. (1996). Perception for New York: Academic Press.
C H A P T E R 21

Situated Semantics

Varol Akman

It is perhaps worth while saying that situations (e.g., the sort of roles they play
semantics.. .is a sober and modest discipline and the views they hold).' Following Mil-
which has no pretensions of being a universal ton Rokeach (1998), we define an attitude
patent-medicine for all the ills and diseases of as a relatively lasting organization of beliefs
mankind, whether imaginary or real. You around an object or situation preparing a
will not find in semantics any remedy for person to respond in some preferential man-
decayed teeth or illusions of grandeur or class ner. We care about attitudes because we
conflicts. Nor is semantics a device for think that we can use them to predict behav-
establishing that everyone except the speaker ior. This requires that social agents maintain
and his friends is speaking nonsense. considerable uniformity to act in a certain
(more or less consistent) way in situations.
ï Alfred Tarski (1944) It was Erving Goffrnan's (2002) idea to look
behind situations to discover the structures
1. Situations and Context that implicidy govern them. These struc-
tures he called "frames." Where a situation
What is it that we really want to convey is given by its contents, a frame is described
when we say "situated semantics"? We begin by its components having a definite arrange-
with a brief digression and then proceed ment and stable relations (Gonos, 1977,
toward the main concern of this chapter, p. 860). Each of the forms of daily activities
semantics. scrutinized by Goffman has names (e.g., one
Stage works in which the humor derives is at a birthday party or a fund-raiser). On
from the situations the characters are placed the other hand, situations are describable
in (sitcoms) make one thing clear. Placed in but nameless (e.g., a shareholders' meeting
social situations, people construct the mean- that ended in a fistfight; Goffman, 2002).
ing of these situations in a subjective way. Situated semantics can be regarded as
This affects the way they behave in these an attempt at placing situational context

401
VAROl. AKMAN
402

(context of situation) at the center of all dis- dom has full and precise information about
cussions of meaning. The word situation (or the relevant circumstances.
more properly, context of situation) was used Context has long been a salient issue
by John Rupert Firth to cover all the rele- in social studies of language; namely, how
vant circumstances in which a specific act of human beings employ language to build the
speech takes place. Also termed extralinguis- social and cultural organizations that they
tic context, this referred to the entire situa- inhabit. Lyons (1995) finds this inevitable:
tion in which an utterance is made (e.g., who "In the construction of a satisfactory the-
is the speaker, who is the addressee, whether ory of context, the linguist's account of the
the delivery is formal or informal, the aim of interpretation of utterances must of neces-
utterance, the time of utterance, the loca- sity draw upon, and will in turn contribute
tion of utterance). In the analysis of a lan- to, the theories and findings of social sci-
guage, Firth (1957) thought, features recur- ences in general: notably of psychology,
ring in individual utterances will be related anthropology and sociology" (p. 292). Influ-
to types of situation and to specific features enced by Firth, Goodwin and Duranti (1992)
in them.2 judge context as basic in ethnographical
Blackburn (1994) offers a similar defini- studies of language use. They claim that con-
tion: "In linguistics, context is the parts of text "stands at the cutting edge of much
contemporary research into the relationship
an utterance surrounding a unit and which
between language, culture, and social orga-
may affect both its meaning and its gram-
nization, as well as into the study of how lan-
matical contribution" (p. 80). He then adds
guage is structured in the way it is" (p. 32).
that context also refers to "the wider situ-
ation, either of the speaker or of the sur-
roundings, that may play a part in deter-
mining the significance of a saying." Angeles 2. Enter S T A S S
(1981) regards context as the totality of asso-
ciations, preconceptions, and so forth that Situation theory is a theory of information
are closely related to a thing and influence content that takes context very seriously
one's perspectives, judgments, and knowl- (Akman 8c Surav, 1996,1997). Groundbreak-
edge of that thing. Accordingly, if something ing work on situation theory is due to the
is seen in context (or put into context), it late Jon Barwise, noted logician, and John
is considered with all the factors that are Perry, prominent philosopher of language.
related to it rather than just being considered Barwise and Perry were the founders of
on its own, so that it can be properly under- Stanford University's Center for the Study
stood.5 of Language and Information (CSLI), which
Clark and Carlson (1981) take context as became almost synonymous with situation-
information that is available to a person theoretic research.6
on a given occasion. Their intrinsic context The theory matured over the years. It
(sometimes called the "common ground") was applied to a number of linguistic issues,
refers to the totality of knowledge, beliefs, resulting in what is commonly known as sit-
and suppositions that are shared by the uation semantics. Situation semantics aims
speaker and the hearer.4 Adopting a stance to construct a mathematically rigorous the-
attributable to Leech (1981), we can say ory of meaning and the application of
that "the specification of context has the such a theory to natural language.7 One
effect of narrowing down the communica- is engaged in situation semantics if one is
tive possibilities of [a] message as it exists using situation-theoretic ideas - mathemat-
in abstraction from context" (p. 66). Thus, ical theories of information content - to
context has a disambiguating function,5 for study meaning in natural language. In fact,
a so-called fleshing-out strategy - converting the two areas are not clearly separable, as the
statements into decontextualized (eternal) still-popular acronym STASS (situation the-
sentences - cannot always be used. One sel- ory and situation semantics) neady shows.
s i t u a t e d semantics 4°5

Situation semantics is based on the fol- work of Donald Davidson, knowledge of


lowing general observation: in evaluating a meaning of a sentence coincides with knowl-
certain statement, one needs not only certain edge of truth conditions (i.e., what the world
indices like times and worlds (of possible- is to be like if the sentence is true). (It is
world semantics). As Recanati (2004) noted that actual knowledge of truth condi-
notes: tions is not required.) Compositionality fas-
tidiously maneuvers to determine the mean-
Why not also, for example, locations? If I ing of the sentence in terms of the meanings
say "It's raining," the location is unarticu- of its constituents (Pietroski, 2003; Pulman,
lated, but it is relevant q u a feature of the 1997)-
circumstance of evaluation: what I say (or
The ordinary-language approach, on the
think) is true [if and only if] it's raining at
other hand, studied the activity of saying
the contextually provided location. Why
not also consider the agent of the speech things. 10 Thus, one has speech acts to ana-
act (the speaker) or the thought act (the lyze and as one could no more ignore irony,
thinker) as (part of) the circumstance of metaphor, implicature, and so on, one has
evaluation, to handle cases in which the to consider the so-called speaker's mean-
content to be evaluated is a property of ing. Communication succeeds as soon as the
agents which the speaker or thinker self- intentions (the m-intentions of Paul Herbert
attributes? Why not extend [this approach] Grice) of the speaker are recognized by the
also to ordinary objects? If, talking about
hearer.
my car, the mechanic tells me "The car-
buretor is in good condition but there is Idealized approaches to semantics under-
a problem with the front wheels," my car estimated the role played by context; they
is a crucial feature of the circumstance of ignored factors such as intentions and cir-
evaluation. It is true (or false) of my c a r cumstances of the individuals involved in
that the carburetor is in good condition, the communicative process. (Or rather, they
and so on. The same thing could have placed them in the pragmatics wastebas-
been said of another car, but as things ket.) But linguistic devices like indexicals,
turn out it is my car which figures in
demonstratives, and tenses rely heavily on
the [content] of the mechanic's utterance,
context for interpretation and are funda-
(p. 122)
mental to the way language carries infor-
mation. A sentence can be used over and
Situation semantics does not impose man-
over again in different situations to say
made assumptions on our conceptual
different things (the so-called efficiency
scheme. 8 This makes it enticing for a new-
of language)." Its interpretation (i.e., the
comer to the realm of semantics. It is bur-
class of situations described by the sen-
densome for someone to embrace, say, Mon-
tence) is therefore subordinate to the sit-
tagovian intensions (Dowty, Wall, & Peters,
uation in which the sentence is used. This
1981), but situations have a certain concep- context-providing situation (discourse situ-
tual clarity. Actually, situation semantics is ation) is the speech situation, including the
a fine exemplar of what a naturalized theory speaker, the addressee, the time and place
of semantics should be like. of the utterance, and the expression uttered.
In the history of natural language seman- Because speakers are always in different sit-
tics, there was a period when it was con- uations, having different causal connections
sidered bon ton to distinguish meticulously to the world and different information, the
between formal semantics and pragmatics. 9 information conveyed by an utterance will
If you w o r k e d on the former, you counted be relative to its speaker and hearer (the
as doing idealized - as opposed to ordi- so-called perspectival relativity of language).
nary - language philosophy. T w o impor- T h e insistence of situation semantics on con-
tant desiderata - truth conditions and com- textual interpretation makes it compatible
positionality - w e r e crucial to the meaning with speech-act theory and discourse prag-
of a declarative sentence. Originating in the matics.
VAROL. AKMAN

Situation theory starts with a fundamen- Consider a certain mountain. Keefe (2000)
tal observation: reality consists of situations. notes that
A situation is a rich object consisting of
individuals having various properties and any sharp spatio-temporal boundaries
drawn around the mountain would be
standing in a variety of relations. It is, in
arbitrarily placed, and would not reflect a
a sense, a small world. We always find our-
natural boundary. So it may seem that [the
selves in situations. J. J. Gibson (1979) fa- mountain] has fuzzy boundaries, and so
mously argued that perception was regu- given the common view that a vague object
lated by response to properties in the visual is an object with fuzzy, spatio-temporal
world. He thus embraced the position that boundaries, that it is a vague object, (p. 15)
most thinking depends on suitable responses
to environmental demands (Turvey & It is not hard to generalize the approach
Carello, 1986). Deep down, the Barwise- briefly outlined a b o v e to situations of any
Perry stance is also an ecological one. u kind. A l t h o u g h the description "last night's
Although situations are commonsensical football g a m e " does s u c c e e d in picking out
entities on the one hand, they can be quite a unique object, it is evident that that
problematical as soon as we start asking object (situation) has blurry spatiotemporal
probing questions about their fundamental boundaries. S u p p o s e J o h n says, "The game
nature. Devlin (1991a, pp. 31-32) exemplifies was w a t c h e d (in the stadium) by an even
this by imagining a dialogue between t w o n u m b e r of spectators." Because the woolly
participants (John and David) about a par- boundaries of the g a m e situation, this should
ticular football game they have both seen. c o m e out to be neither true nor false (hence
John and David can have an extended dis- indeterminate). N o t e that, in general, John
cussion about this game while maintaining and D a v i d w o u l d hardly ever argue about
informativeness and avoiding disorientation the truth of such statements. They are more
or puzzlement. How is that possible? Nei- likely to talk a b o u t matters regarding the
ther John nor David can enumerate every bit C o k e bottles t h r o w n at the players or the
of information that this particular game sit- colorful shirts w o r n by referees. In both of
uation supports. Actually, this would make these cases, there can be little disagreement
their postgame discussion superfluous and as to the truth value of the propositions
not very enjoyable. Thus, the following under discussion.
query of Devlin (1991a) becomes vital: Barwise and Perry w e r e the first to formu-
late a full-fledged proposal about the use of
[I]f you were to interrupt John and David situations f o r semantics, b u t it is worth men-
in the middle of their conversation and ask tioning that A u s t i n (1979) saw the need for
them what they were talking about, they situations in his f a m o u s 1950 paper on truth.
would reply "Last night's football game. " In this w o r k , A u s t i n makes key observations
Are we then to conclude that they were in about statements. He notes that the making
fact talking about nothing; or that neither of a statement is a historic event: a speaker
was really sure what it was they were dis- is uttering certain w o r d s (a sentence) to an
cussing? [p. 32) audience w i t h r e f e r e n c e to a historic situ-
ation. Usually these w o r d s are used to talk
"Clearly not," Devlin replies, and mentions about the w o r l d ("something other than the
our inability to reduce situations to an amal- words"). T h i s w o r l d exhibits similarities and
gam of more familiar entities. Devlin con- dissimilarities; in an extremely chaotic or
siders the latter as one good explanation for perfectly ordered w o r l d , there would be lit-
people's disinclination to regard situations tle to say. A u s t i n then makes a fundamen-
as bona fide objects. Devlin's question is in tal distinction (1979, p p . 121-122) between
some sense relatively old. In discussions of descriptive and demonstrative conventions.
vagueness in philosophy, vague objects have T h e f o r m e r correlate the words (sentences)
received considerable attention (Tye, 1990). with the types of situation, thing, or event
SITUATED SEMANTICS

present in the world. The latter correlate the notions of individual, relation, and spatio-
words (statements) with the historical situ- temporal location depend on this. In other
ations and so on present in the world. The words, the basic constituents of the the-
truth of a statement then simply reduces to ory are determined by the agent's schema
this: the historical state of affairs with which of individuation. Formal representation of
the statement is correlated by the demon- these uniformities yields types. Situation
strative conventions is of a type with which theory provides a collection of basic types
the sentence used in making the statement for individuating or discriminating uniformi-
is correlated by the descriptive conventions. ties of the real world: situation, infon, indi-
As a simple illustration of the idea, take vidual, n-place relation, temporal location,
a signpost that reads "Checkpoint ahead." spatial location, type, and parameter. (We
This says that there is checkpoint ahead choose not to count polarities as types.)
(descriptive conventions). The word ahead Parameters are generalizations over
probably means something like a couple of classes of nonparametric objects (e.g., indi-
hundred yards. The sign makes a true state- viduals, spatial locations). Parameters can be
ment if there is indeed a checkpoint ahead associated with objects that, if they were
(at a reasonable distance). It would be mak- to replace the parameters, would yield one
ing a false claim if one encounters no such of the objects in the class that paramet-
checkpoint. ric object abstracts over. Hence, allowing
parameters in infons results in parametric
infons. __ For example, <see,g,Alice,i> and
7. Ontology <see,J;,h,i> are parametric infons where g
and h stand for individuals. These infons
Individuals, properties, relations, and spa- are parametric on the first, and the first and
tiotemporal locations are basic constructs of second, argument roles of the relation see,
situation theory. Individuals are conceived respectively. (Their meaning can be ren-
as invariants; having properties and standing dered as "someone sees Alice" and "some-
in relations, they tend to persist in time and one sees someone," respectively.) Anchor-
space. ing (binding) parameters of an infon to
Infons (Devlin, 1992) are discrete items objects yields parameter-free infons. For
of information. They are denoted as example, given <see,g,Alice,i>, if F(g) =
<R,a,,... ,a n ,p>, where R is an n-place rela- Bob, then we obtain the parameter-free
tion, a , , . . . ,an are objects appropriate for infon <see,Bob,Alice,i>.
the respective argument places of R, and Given a situation s, a parameter g, and a
p is the polarity (o or 1). If p = 1 (respec- set of infons I (involving g), one can define
tively, o) then a„ . . . ,an stand (respectively, [g|s [=1] to denote the type of all objects for
do not stand) in relation R. 1? A situation is which the conditions imposed by I hold in
a structured part of the reality that an agent s. This process of obtaining a type is type
manages to pick out. Situations are inten- abstraction. Here g is the abstraction param-
sional objects. For this reason, abstract situ- eter and s is the grounding situation.
ations are proposed to be their counterparts A situation s' is part of another situation
amenable to mathematical manipulation. s just in case for all infons i, s' t=i—>• s
An abstract situation is defined as a set This relation is antisymmetric, reflexive, and
(Devlin, 1991c). Given a real situation s, the transitive, and consequendy provides a par-
set {i|s )=i}, where i is an infon, is the corre- tial ordering of situations.
sponding abstract situation. Here, s is said to Situations in which a constituent
support an infon i (denoted as s (=i above) sequence is assigned both polarities are
just in case i is true of s. incoherent. For instance, a situation s
A scheme of individuation - a way of is incoherent if <has,Alice,A#,o> and
carving the world into uniformities - is <has,Alice,A#,1> are both supported by s.
an essential aspect of situation theory. The Although there cannot be a real situation
VAROL AKMAN

s validating this, the constituent sequence not shouting" are logically equivalent in the
<has,Alice,A*> may be assigned these classical sense. In situation semantics, these
polarities for spatiotemporally distinct sit- two sentences will not have the same inter-
uation types (say, s and s'). pretation. A situation s describing the cir-
Situation semantics makes simple cumstance in which Bob is only angry will
assumptions about the way natural lan- not contain anything about Bob's shouting
guage works. Primary among them is the (i.e., s will be silent on Bob's shouting).
assumption that language is used to convey However, another situation s' obtained as
information about the world (the so-called the union of two situations ("Bob is angry
external significance of language). Even and Bob is shouting" plus "Bob is angry and
when two sentences have the same inter- Bob is not shouting") will contain something
pretation (i.e., describe the same situation), about Bob's shouting.
they can carry different information. To recap, in Tarskian semantics, state-
Suppose Alice was eating ice cream yes- ments that are true in the same models con-
terday. She is eating ice cream now. Both of vey the same information. Situation seman-
these situations share the same constituent tics takes the view that logically equivalent
sequence <eat,Alice,ice cream>. These two sentences need not have the same subject
events, occurring at different times, have matter, for they need not describe situations
the same situation type. Situation types can involving the same objects and properties.
be more general. For example, a situation The notion of partiality leads to a more fine-
type in which someone is eating something grained notion of information content and a
at home contains the situation in which stronger notion of logical consequence that
Alice is eating ice cream at home. If Alice does not lose track of the subject matter.
is not present in the room where this chap-
ter is being written, then "Alice is eating ice
cream" is not part of the room situation s 4. Constraints
and hence gets no truth value in s. Thus,
situation theory allows partiality. Intelligent agents generally make their way
To see this more clearly, imagine two in the world by being able to pick up cer-
games that are going on, one across town tain information from a situation, process
from the other. Alice is playing cards with it, and react accordingly. Being in a situ-
Bob, and Carol is playing cards with David. ation, such an agent would have informa-
Elwood, watching the former game, mis- tion about the situations it sees, hears about,
takes Alice for Carol, and mutters: "Carol believes in, and so on. Thus, on hearing
has the ace of clubs." According to the clas- Bob's utterance "A wolf is running toward
sical theory, if Carol indeed has the ace, his you," Alice would have the information that
claim would be true since "Carol" and "the her friend is addressing her with you. More-
ace of clubs" are used to pick, among all over, by relying on the situation described
the things in the world, the unique objects by the utterance, she would know that there
satisfying the properties of being someone is a wolf fast approaching her. Alice would
named Carol and being the ace of clubs, run away, having in possession the acquired
respectively. In contrast, situation seman- knowledge that wolves are hazardous. She
tics identifies these objects with respect to would activate this knowledge from the sit-
some limited situation - the resource situ- uation she finds herself in via a constraint -
ation exploited by Elwood. Elwood's claim the link between wolves and their reputa-
would then be false even if Carol held the tion as life-threatening creatures.
ace in the other game.
A network of abstract links between high-
Partiality makes it possible to distinguish order uniformities (i.e., situation types) pro-
between logically equivalent statements. For vides such information flow. The statement
example, the statements "Bob is angry" and "Smoke means fire" expresses the lawlike
"Bob is angry, and Bob is shouting or Bob is relation that links situations where there is
situated semantics
smoke to situations where there is a fire. If cares about the second situation, not the
s is the type of smoky situations and f is first. Situation semantics differs from other
the type of fire situations, then having been approaches in that in attitude reports we do
attuned to the constraint s ^ f , an agent can not describe our mind directly (by referring
pick up the information that there is a fire in to states of mind, ideas, senses, thoughts,
a particular situation by observing that there and whatnot) but indirectly (by referring
is smoke.' 4 Anchoring plays a major role in to situations that are external). To appre-
the working of constraints. Cognitively, if ciate this point, consider the sentence "The
the preceding constraint holds, then it is a wolf is approaching." Understanding what
fact that if s is realized (i.e., there is a real situations this sentence describes is essen-
situation s 0 of type s), then so is f (i.e., there tial to grasping its meaning. One such con-
is a real situation f Q of type f ) . To invoke crete situation is the one Bob is currently
the constraint, we have to use an anchoring facing. But there are coundess other (poten-
function that binds the location parameters tial) situations that can be described in the
to appropriate objects present in the ground- same way. In other words, on hearing this
ing situation (i.e., we have to first find a place sentence in our mind's eye are evoked all
and time at which there is smoke). those situations accurately described by it.
It is possible to identify three forms of Now take the sentence "Bob wants a big
constraints. Necessary constraints are those stick," expressing a certain wish of Bob. It
by which one can define or name things may be possible to understand this by trying
(e.g., every dog is a mammal). Nomic con- to imagine all those private (internal) men-
straints are patterns that are usually called tal states of Bob correctly described by it.
natural laws (e.g., blocks fall unless they are However, it is much more meaningful (less
supported). Conventional constraints are baffling) to resort to public situations for
those arising out of the customs that hold an explanation. Thus, Bob wants to achieve
within a community (e.g., the first day of the (arrive at) a situation in which he is holding
month is payday). These are neither nomic a big stick. This he normally does by look-
nor necessary (i.e., they can be violated). All
ing around to find something like that or by
types of constraints can be conditional or
(creatively) crafting one - say, by breaking a
unconditional. Conditional constraints can
tree branch - when he is not able to locate
be applied to situations that fulfill some con-
one lying on the forest floor.
dition, and unconditional constraints can be
In situation semantics, propositions are
applied to all situations.' 5
conceived as situations, and propositional
attitudes are characterized as relations to
such situations. To believe that a particu-
5. Meaning lar wolf is dangerous is then to stand in a
relationship to that wolf and the property of
Meaningful expressions are used to con- being dangerous. Several researchers concur
vey information not only about the exter- that major difficulties threaten the situation-
nal world but also about our minds (the theoretic rendering of propositional atti-
so-called mental significance of language). tudes. Davis (2003, pp. 351-352) cites what he
Clearly, language could not work if it did calls Frege's and Russell's problems: "Frege's
not have information significance - if it were problem arises from the intensionality of
not about matters in a public world. Return- propositional attitude contexts, the fact that
ing to an earlier example, consider the sen- substitution of coextensive terms in such
tence "A wolf is running toward you" uttered contexts does not always produce equiva-
by Bob. It can give Alice information about lent statements. Someone can believe that
two different situations. The first one is the Cary Grant is famous, for example, with-
situation that she is located in. The sec- out believing that Archibald Leach is.' 6 Rus-
ond one is Bob's belief situation. If Alice sell's problem arises from the intentional-
is certain that he is hallucinating, then she ity of propositional attitudes, the fact that
4 0 j v a r o l akman

people can think about nonexistent objects about u - such as its speaker and time of
and have other prepositional attitudes con- utterance - are determined by the discourse
cerning them. Many children believe that situations. The ties of the mental states of
Santa Claus brings presents at Christmas, the speaker and the hearer with the world
even though Santa Claus does not exist." constitute c.
Davis notes that common responses to A discourse situation involves the expres-
the former problem typically dispose of the sion uttered, its speaker, the spatiotemporal
view that prepositional attitudes are rela- location of the utterance, and the addressee
tions between individuals and situations. Each of these defines a linguistic role: the
Rather, such attitudes are assumed to be role of the speaker, the role of the addressee
relations connecting individuals, situations, and so on. T h e utterance situation u con-
and modes of presentation (i.e., ways of strains the world in a certain way, depend-
believing).'7 ing on h o w the roles for discourse situations
In their thorough account of preposi- connections, and described situations are to
tional attitude reports, McKay and Nelson be filled. For instance, an utterance of "I am
(2005) make similar claims: trembling" defines a meaning relation:

Recall that one of the problems facing naive d, c || I am trembling || e.


RusseUianism was that
Lois believes that Superman is stronger than Given a discourse situation d, connec-
tions c, and a described situation e, this holds
Clark Kent,
just in case that there is a location L and a
threatens to entail speaker s such that s is speaking at L, and in
Lois believes that Superman is stronger than
e, s is trembling at L.
Superman,
Besides discourse situations, the inter-
which in turn threatens to entail pretation of an utterance depends on the
Lois believes that Superman is stronger than speaker's connections with objects, proper-
himself. ties, times and places, and on the speaker's
ability to exploit information about one sit-
Because the situation that Superman is uation to obtain information about another.
stronger than Clark Kent just is the situa- Therefore, context supports not only facts
tion that Superman is stronger than him-
about speakers, addressees, and so on
self, these are the same beliefs. The situa-
but also facts about the relations of dis-
tion semanticist cannot appeal to the dif-
ference between the property of being taller course participants to other contextually rel-
than Superman and the properly of being evant situations such as resource situations.
taller than oneself, as the neo-Russellian Resource situations are contextually avail-
can, to distinguish the properties. This is able and provide entities for reference and
because a difference in structure doesn't quantification.
correspond, for the situation semanticist, to In interpreting the utterance of an expres-
a difference in proposition. But then the sit- sion S in context, there is a flow of informa-
uation semanticist, as opposed to the naive tion, partly f r o m the linguistic form encoded
Russellian, is committed to the claim that
in S and partly f r o m contextual factors pro-
Lois believes that Superman is stronger
vided by the utterance situation u. These are
than himself. But surely that is irrational!
combined to f o r m a set of constraints on the
According to situation semantics, mean- described situation e. This situation is not
ings of expressions reside in systematic rela- uniquely determined; there may be others
tions between different types of situations. satisfying the constraints. T h e meaning of
They can be identified with relations on dis- an utterance of S and hence its interpreta-
tion are influenced by other factors such as
course situations d, (speaker) connections
stress, modality, and intonation. However,
c, the utterance situation u itself, and the
the situation in w h i c h S is uttered and the
described situation e. Some public facts
situated semantics 4°5

situation e described by this utterance seem to understand this is as follows. If the only
to play die most influential roles. kind of information available to an agent is
In the remainder of this chapter, we give that supplied by G, then O(G.s) cannot be
two applications of situation semantics. The distinguished from tu.
first application is situated inference. This As an illustration, consider the Jerry
application is presented after the following Fodor oracle 0 ( G , F odor), for an appropri-
section, which introduces some background ate G. Stretching back in time to include
material. The second application is literary his granny, and forward in time to include
interpretation. his grandchildren, it will contain Fodor's
birthplace, his favorite books (including The
House at Pooh Corner, of course!), positions
6. Oracles he has held, students he has taught, and so
on. One key observation has to do with the
Let G be a collection of parametric infons. extent of this oracle. Different people at
G provides one with a framework for con- different times may have access to differ-
versing about some part of the world (or the ent information about it. Ernie Lepore must
whole world). By anchoring the parameters surely know more about it than I do, for I
in an infon belonging to G, an item of infor- never met Fodor but am familiar, to some
mation is obtained. degree, with his oeuvre. Fodor himself will
Given an individual or a situation s, the know considerably more about it, though a
G-oracle of s, denoted as 0(G,s), is the situ- biographer of this philosopher may unearth
ation comprising that part of the world and facts that could be news even to Fodor.
the entire body of knowledge that concerns Various observations regarding oracles
s. This is relative to a set of issues (i.e., it can be stated (Devlin, 1991b):
is understood to be meaningful within the
framework provided by G). Thus, differ- • Oracles are situations. This necessitates
ent sets will enable one to talk - and glean that an agent would have only partial
information - about different aspects of the information about a particular oracle.
world.'8 » Oracles (ipso facto, situations) make little
Oracles were invented by Devlin (1991a): sense if one tries to specify them in terms
of which infons they support. The right
Just as various kinds of number (e.g., com- way to specify an oracle is in terms of a
plex numbers) 'exist' because we postu- description that is less primitive.
late their existence (in the mathematical • In natural language, a single word or
realm), so too with oracles. u>ith dif-
phrase can bring into focus an entire ora-
ferent kinds of number system, oracles are
cle situation corresponding to an indi-
intended to provide a theoretical construct
vidual.
that corresponds to a certain feature in the
world being studied. In this case, the 'fea- i The more information two agents share
ture' concerned is the situation compris- about an oracle, the more efficient is the
ing precisely those objects and facts of rel- communication between them.' 9
evance to a given individual or situation,
(p. 48)
7. Situated Inference
If we stick to the classical assumption
that among the situations available there is As noted in the preceding section, a set
a unique, maximal situation co - in ST ASS, of issues is a collection of parametric
to is commonly known as the world 1 then infons that provide us with an information-
the following can be stated. For any G-infon theoretic framework for discussing the
i in which only objects that are the con- world or some part of it. By anchoring the
stituents of 0 ( G , s ) occur, 0(G,s)|=i if and parameters in this set, we obtain an item of
only if a)^=i. One particularly natural way information. Clearly, using different sets of
40J 40jv a r o lakman

issues, we can talk about different aspects Sperber and Wilson talk about degrees 0f
of the world. For example, when talking relevance. Clearly, one piece of information
about Bob in the context of a colloquium in may be more relevant to a particular con
Hawaii (PHIL '05), we may include stuflflike text. Their following definition does the job
his being the organizer of the colloquium, "An assumption is relevant in a context t
things that happened to him around the the extent that its contextual effects in tbi$
time of the colloquium, the personal charac- context are large. An assumption is rele
teristics of Bob that help one recognize him, vant in a context to the extent that th
and so on. However, what happened to Bob effort required to process it in this context i
when he was five years old is probably not small" (Sperber & Wilson, 1986, p. pg||| *
included in the set of issues (unless his col- estimate relevance, we can try to measure
loquium talk is about his experiences in his the relevance of i to G. Here, we use the
early youth). criterion proposed by Sperber and Wilson'
For example, O(G.Bob) contains (this is namely, maximum contextual effect and
a very brief list): minimum processing effort. 22 We interpret
the effects of i on G as contextual effects
An infon is relevant to a context if it has
«organize,Bob.PHIL 05,1 >
some contextual effects on the context with
< go, Bob, Hawaii, 2005,1 > a small-sized anchoring. It is irrelevant to a
< male. Bob, i> context if either it has no contextual effect
on the context or otherwise some contextual
G is, in some sense, a template of infor- effects with a large-sized anchoring.
mation which determines what portion of Let us consider a context that contains
0(G,Bob) is to be considered. OfBob) may the regularity "Birds fly." We represent this
contain a large amount of information about
the medical state of Bob, but if G does not
discuss these issues, 0(G,Bob) would not b = [s|s f = < b i r d , y , i > ]
include such information.
f = fs|s j= < fly,y,i >]
Because we need a notion of relevance
here, we consider Sperber and Wilson b*f
(1986), in which relevance is psychological
relevance of a proposition to a context. Their The infon i = <bird,Tweety,i> is relevant to
assumption is that people have intuitions of this context, as with the anchoring F(y) =
relevance (i.e., they can consistently distin- Tweety we can conclude that Tweety flies.
guish relevant from irrelevant information). The size of anchoring is 1, and thus the pro-
A proposition is relevant to a context if it cessing effort is minimal.
interacts in a certain way with the (con- Consider now the following dialogue
text's) existing assumptions about the world between Carol and Bob:
(i.e., if it has some contextual effects that are
accessible). These contextual effects include Carol: D i d you see the fight in the base-
the following20: ball game on Foo TV last night?
Bob: I always watch Foo T V .
1. Contextual implication: a new assump-
tion can be used together with the exist- Did Bob see the fight? We begin by not-
ing rules to generate new assumptions. ing that Carol's utterance carries the fol-
2. Strengthening: a new assumption can lowing presupposition: A baseball game was
strengthen some of the existing assump- shown on Foo TV last night. Additionally,
tions. we are aware of the (commonsense) rule:
!- Contradicting or eliminating: a new If some event is broadcast on a TV chan-
assumption may change or eliminate nel and someone watches that channel, then
some of the existing assumptions. he or she also sees the event. The encoded
SITUATED SEMANTICS 4°5

versions of the first three items of informa- faced with one equation in three u n k n o w n s :
tion are, respectively, <see,Bob,the fight,?>, R, c, and P. Usually, the solution is not
<watch,Bob,Foo T V , i > , and <show,Foo unique. T h e task of literary interpretation
TV the baseball g a m e , i > . T h e constraint is to use the available information a b o u t
suggested by the commonsense rule is b ^ e , the unknowns (e.g., biographical material,
where b = [sis | = < s h o w , w , f i , i > & $ [= <watch, information about the culture in w h i c h t h e
y,\V,i>] and e = [Sl§ ^=<see,y,iV,i>]; using writing took place, etc.) to circumscribe the
the anchoring F(y) = Bob, F(w) = Foo T V , range of their possible values. 2 3
and F(<i) = the baseball game, we achieve a Let the right-hand side of Barwise's e q u a -
contextual e f f e c t (i.e., the invocation of the tion be a set of possible intended meanings.
constraint) and conclude that Bob saw the These are clear to the author - we p r e s u m e -
fight (i.e., the polarity denoted with ? above during the writing activity but m a y be c u m -
is 1). (Clearly, the fight situation is a part of bersome to discover later. 24 An author of fic-
the game situation.) Notice that the size of tion creates an artificial circumstance at first
the anchoring is 3 this time. and builds his or her work around that. T h e
author has something in mind and wants
to share this with readers; the author has
8. Interpretation an intended meaning P. To achieve P, the
author determines the elements of circum-
In his w o r k on literary criticism, Barwise stance that fit best to his or her needs. Here,
(1989a) suggests a m o c k equation (a con- the author can choose to play with the rules
straint C) to relate the basic constituents of of language. This is also the point where
the author makes either implicit or explicit
content:
assumptions about the language conventions
C ( R , S , c ) I P. (Percy, 1975).
A reader, picking up the written material
Here, S is a sentence and c is the situation in in his hand, normally reads it from begin-
which S is used. R is defined as the language ning to the end. Therefore, ideas frequendy
conventions holding between an author and descend on him as they are written (sequen-
a reader (or better yet, his readership). P is tially). A n d more often than not, a reader
the content of S (i.e., the intended mean- understands the text at first pass; the reader
ing). We assume that the communication does not go through the text over and over
between an author and a reader is limited again to bind variables, rewrite portions,
only to written text. Thus, it is not feasible to reorder passages, make optimizations, and
ask the author about his intention for writ- so on.
ing S; that will have to be discovered by a From the perspective of a reader, the
reader. For many kinds of written material, P author could have intended almost any
is a single intended meaning (attributable to meaning. This can be denoted with the car-
a determinate author). H o w e v e r , in most lit- dinality of intention space being large. If a
erary works and especially in poetry, authors reader is familiar with the language conven-
may aim, for assorted reasons, at more than tions, we assume that he or she can read
one intended meaning. T h e richness of a say, a book. Here, if the text is accessi-
literary w o r k m a y be rooted in its being ble, we can claim that the world the b o o k
ambiguous or multifaceted. All the param- presents can be budt in the intention space
eters in the previous constraint are at the of the reader. T h e reader may read sequen-
writer's disposal. He or she can play with tially, may skip pages or chapters, or m a y
them, as long as the constraint is satisfied.
choose to browse. T h e intention space, w i t h
(Obviously, if the writer experiments with
every element that is added, acquires n e w
R - a fitting e x a m p l e w o u l d be Finnegans
restrictions. T h e reader in turn begins to
Wake - he has less chance of being under-
understand what the author is saying in the
stood.) Thus, the reader of a literary text S is
book.
4 0 jv a r o lakman

Ambiguity comes in two kinds. The first reader of Eco) or writer oriented and follow
is due to large intention spaces and the other the rules of the author.
to incompatible intentions. The former can
be exemplified by the so-called open texts
{Eco, 1979]. In such texts, the openness 9. Brief G u i d e to the Literature
stems from size: the intention space cannot
be fully circumscribed in a reader's mind. Two book-length treatments of STASS are
The author does not write something to Barwise and Perry (1983) and Devlin (1991a).
mean something definite in an open text. Although somewhat dated, the former is
Rather, the author writes to keep his or her packed with excellent semantic common
intention space large so that reader can con- sense.25 The latter proposes a standard
sume only a portion of that. (And just what vocabulary and pays close attention to the
that portion might be is up to the reader.] foundations; it is the only modem intro-
The second kind of ambiguity is in fact an duction to S T A S S , together with the most
incompatibility problem. In general, being a recent (Devlin, n.d.). Devlin also wrote
reader makes one divide the intention space accounts of S T A S S , mostly oriented toward
into parts and discard irrelevant parts. The the layperson (cf. Devlin, 1998, 2001). Selig-
criterion to discard some part in favor of man and Moss (1997) is a survey of situation
another seems to be the exact problem of theory that is mathematically demanding;
understanding texts. it also has a good bibliography of technical
Authors must also assume some familiar- papers.
ity on the part of a reader with the concepts Various versions of situation theory have
they write about, and this assumption lies been applied to a number of linguistic issues
between the borders of R and c. Because arising in English (Stucky, 1989). Barwise
this kind of familiarity is usually counted (1986,1987) has written especially important
among the language knowledge, there will papers in that they study classical areas of
not be a clear distinction between c and semantics such as conditionals, quantifiers,
R in these cases. If the author is telling us and anaphora. The ideas emerging from
about some planet and assumes that a reader research in situation semantics have also
knows the meaning of the word planet, does been combined with well-developed linguis-
he or she assume something for R, as the tic theories, leading to rigorous formalisms
author assumes the reader must know what (Fenstad, Halvorsen, Langholm, 8t van Ben-
a planet is? Or does the author assume some- them, 1987).
thing about c, that is, if the reader knows Indexicals, demonstratives, referential
what a planet is, the reader must be able uses of definite descriptions, deictic uses
to infer some knowledge about the circum- of pronouns, tense markers, and names
stances mentioned in the work? all have technical treatments in situation
To cope with this problem, we can accept semantics. Gawron and Peters (1990) focus
R and c as mutually exclusive, and define on the semantics of pronominal anaphora
c as the special part of circumstances that and quantification. They argue that the
are used in the work and R as the remain- ambiguities of sentences with pronouns can
ing part of the language. This is a hard-and- be resolved with an approach that repre-
fast solution but does not present us with sents anaphoric relations syntactically. They
a standard about separating c and R. (Thus, use a relational framework that consid-
the assumptions underlying children's books ers anaphoric relations as relations between
and Shakespeare's plays are not the same.) utterances in context. Cooper (1991, 1996)
To produce some standard about the sep- offers detailed studies of linguistic prob-
aration of c and R, one must come up lems to which situation semantics has been
with explicit definitions. Definitions may be applied with some success. Tin and Akman
reader oriented and follow the rules in the (1996) show how situation theory can be
mind of a generic reader (i.e., the model given a computational twist. They offer
SITUATED SEMANTICS 4'3

a prototype to study practical problems, Linguistics (2nd ed), published by Elsevier in


including anaphora resolution. Devlin and 2006.
Rosenberg (1996) explore applications of
situation theory to human-computer inter-
action. Notes
Three early conference proceedings spe-
cifically devoted to developments in STASS 1 William Isaac Thomas argued that so-called
are Cooper, Mukai, and Perry (1990), Bar- social reality is essentially the totality of these
wise, Gawron, Plotkin, and Tutiya (1991), constructions. He thought that social situa-
and Aczel, Israel, Katagiri, and Peters (1993). tions never repeat themselves. Every situa-
tion would be more or less novel in that it
Today it is possible to find situation-
would include new human activities differ-
theoretic work dispersed in conferences
ently put together.
on logic, language, and information. Thus,
2 Not surprisingly, the word situated has also
despite what Partee (2005) asserts in her been used in artificial intelligence. Humans,
intellectual autobiography, today STASS is delivery robots, and automated factories are
alive and well. all systems that have an intelligent, ongo-
ing interaction with environments that are
dynamic and imperfectly predictable. Such
10. Conclusion systems are often called "situated agents"
(Rosenschein & Kaelbling, 1995). Rosen-
For an expression to have meaning, it should schein and Kaelbling present a particular
convey information. On the basis of this fun- approach to the design of situated agents. The
damental insight, situation semantics devel- approach is based on situated-automata the-
ops a theory of meaning that is based on ory and permits designers to use high-level
language constructs to describe the informa-
relations between situations. In analyzing a
tional content of agents.
speech act S, situation semantics looks at 3 Conversely, if a remark, statement, and so on,
various situations (e.g., discourse situations, is taken or quoted out of context, it is consid-
resource situations) that contribute to the ered only on its own and the circumstances
meaning of S. Doing so makes it possible in which it was said are ignored. It, therefore,
to describe the meaning of both expressions seems to mean something different from the
and mental states in terms of the informa- meaning that was intended.
tion they carry about the external world. 4 Manfred Pinkal says this about the potential
Situation semantics provides a funda- size of a context:
mental framework for realistic semantics.
The ideas emerging from research into sit- Aside from the surrounding deictic coor-
dinates, aside from the immediate lin-
uation semantics have been combined with
guistic co-text and accompanying gestural
linguistic work and have led to numerous
expressions at closer view, the following
useful proposals. This chapter gave only a determinants can influence the attribu-
glimpse of this exciting activity. Interested tion of sense: the entire frame of inter-
readers should consult the literature for a action, the individual biographies of the
deeper appraisal. participants, the physical environment,
the social embedding, the cultural and
historical background, and - in addition
Acknowledgments to all these - facts and dates no matter
how far removed in dimensions of time
The author gratefully acknowledges the moral and space. Roughly speaking, 'context'
support of the editors and insightful comments can be the whole world in relation to an
of the referees. T h e improved readability of this utterance act. (Asher Sd Simpson, 1994,
chapter is due to the able efforts of Katherine P i iH
Faydash. A compressed article (two thousand
words) using material from this chapter appeared 5 Leech (1981): "The effect of context is to
in K. Brown (Ed.), Encyclopedia of Language and attach a certain probability to each sense (the
44 VAROL AKMAN

complete ruling-out of a sense being the lim- expressions are syntactically analyzed using
iting case of nil probability)" (p. 67). a categorial grammar. Then the outcome of
6 In the beginning, the development of sit- this analysis is massaged into expressions in
uation theory was hampered by a lack of a tensed intensional logic. Finally, the lat-
appropriate modeling tools. Later, the theory ter expressions are interpreted with respect
assembled its foundations from innovations to a model. The oft-cited problem with this
coming from nonstandard set theory (for a approach is that the truth conditions of a sen-
clear account, see Barwise & Etchemendy, tence are relative — to an interpretation, a
1987). Barwise and Seligman (1997) further world, and a time (Lepore, 1982).
advanced the theory by introducing the idea 10 Newcomers to linguistics are frequently sur-
of an information channel, which preserves prised that linguists regard language as a living
information as it is transmitted through a sys- organism and thus invariably prefer to study
tem. Historically, this idea can be said to orig- spoken language.
inate from Dretske's (1981) groundbreaking 11 Ambiguity is another aspect of the efficiency
work on information content. of language. Some natural language expres-
Devlin (2004) gives a general appraisal of sions have more than one meaning. There are
STASS. This work may be consulted to get factors such as intonation, gesture, the place
a better feel of the historical developments of an utterance, and so on, which may play
that shaped STASS. Many of the papers key roles in the interpretation of an utter-
cited by Devlin can be found in Barwise ance. Instead of downgrading ambiguity as
(1989b). an impurity of natural languages, situation
7 In the rest of this chapter, we will use "sit- semantics tries to build a full-fledged theory
uated semantics" and "situation semantics" of linguistic meaning.
interchangeably. 12 Butterworth (1998):
8 Barwise and Perry (1983) thought that
On the ecological view, perception is nec-
"notions like logical form, logical constant,
essarily situated within the ecology since
proper name, quantifier, variable, quantifier
it consists in obtaining information from
scope, opaque or transparent contexts, de
dicto and de re readings, sense and reference, the active relation between the organism
intension and extension, meaning postulate, and a structured environment. Indeed, it
possible world, rigid designator, truth con- is a process of perception that situates the
ditions and T-sentences, and tense operator organism in the environment. The evi-
are all technical or pseudo-technical notions dence from infancy suggests that percep-
introduced by philosophers and logicians" tion is a 'module' or component of the cog-
(pp. xi-xii). nitive system that is antecedent to thought
and language and that may contribute to
9 When Alfred Tarski invented model-
theoretic semantics for first-order logic, he the mastery of reasoning, (p. 29)
in a way opened the road to the semantics of 13 If R is an n-place relation and a„ . . . ,am, m <
natural language. In the Tarskian approach, n, are objects appropriate for the argument
logical sentences are interpreted in terms of places R, and if the filling of these argument
a model. Because of the nature of classical places is sufficient to satisfy the minimality
logic, this implies that sentences come out conditions for R, then <R,a,,... ,am,p> is
true or false in such a model. Richard Mon- a well-defined infon. Minimality conditions
tague believed that the techniques of formal for a particular relation are the collection of
semantics, as applied to systems oflogic, were conditions that determine which particular
also suitable to ordinary language. In Mon- groups of argument roles need to be filled to
tague's theory, syntax of language is modeled produce an infon. If m < n, the infon is said
via a grammar. Syntactic rules are then asso-
to be unsaturated; if m — n, it is saturated.
ciated with semantic rules that deliver the
interpretation of a sentence from the inter- 14 We are slightly abusing the notation here.
pretations of its parts (Kamp & Reyle, 1993). In fact, s^f is shorthand for the factual,
The Montagovian approach is a three-stage parameter-free infon <involve,s,f,i>.
process (the upcoming description is some- 15 Consider a man meeting with a real-estate
what crude but not incorrect). First, language agent who is going to show him an apartment
for rent. When they enter the building, he
SITUATED SEMANTICS 4°5

smells gas and w a r n s the agent, a smoker, not Logical: the inference rules (according to
to light a cigarette. W h a t happened? This sce- Sperber and Wilson, these rules are
nario is taken from H u n t (1999): deductive)
Encyclopedic: information about objects,
My brain contained an internal represen- properties, and events
tation of the physical state of the room Lexical: rules that allow us to interpret the
and the habits of my companion. Pro- natural language utterances and sen-
cesses internal to the brain constructed tences.
a second brain state that depicted a
potential explosion. For each brain state 21 T h e measurement of contextual e f f e c t s and
there was an interpretation in terms of processing effort is difficult ( S p e r b e r &
correspondence between properties of the Wilson, 1986):
brain state and a property of the external
world. Further brain processes operated The problems involved in measuring con-
on the first and second states to produce textual effects and processing effort are,
a third state that initiated the external of course, by no means specific to rele-
warning to my companion, (p. 9) vance theory or to pragmatics. They affect
psychology as a whole. However, for rel-
We can restate the story in terms of situated evance theory these problems take on a
cognition. W h e n something is situated, it is more specific form. Within relevance the-
put in a certain position or circumstances. ory, the problem is not so much to assess
Conversely, to situate something is to estab- contextual effects and processing effort
from the outside, but to describe how the
lish or indicate t h e place of it, or to put
mind assesses it own achievements and
in a context. T h u s , H u n t was placed in a
efforts from the inside, and decides as a
particular circumstance w h e r e his thinking
result to pursue its efforts or relocate them
clearly d e p e n d e d on a specific response to the
in different directions, (p. 130)
demands of t h e environment.
16 In making this claim, Davis (2003) offers the
22 Mental operations of humans are, in general,
caveat that he is interpreting belief descrip-
similar to what an anchoring function does:
tions opaquely (rather than transparently).
humans individuate relations and objects and
17 Davis (2003, p p . 352-353) is also careful to
fill the gaps in the relations with appropriate
point out that Frege's and Russell's problems
individuals, and reason over them. On the
still arise in classical possible-world seman-
other hand, finding an appropriate anchoring
tics, w h e r e propositional attitudes are charac-
function that creates the desired contextual
terized as relations b e t w e e n individuals and
effects might be difficult.
sets of possible worlds (and where proposi-
tions are defined as w o r l d sets). 23 This approach can be generalized to coher-
ent multisentence discourse. Allen (1995)
18 Using j=;> a technical definition of oracles is
explains:
possible. L e t the term G-infon denote any
infon that results from anchoring the param- A discourse is coherent if you can easily
eters in an infon in G. T h e n 0 ( G , s ) is the determine how the sentences in the dis-
minimal situation s such that sf=i for any fac- course are related to each other. A dis-
tual, parameter-free G - i n f o n i that genuinely course consisting of unrelated sentences
involves s. would be very unnatural. To understand
19 This is crucial in the case of celebrities, as a discourse, you must identify how each
Crimmins (1992) observes: "Agents w h o are sentence relates to the others and to the
normal m e m b e r s of our society are almost discourse as a whole. It is this assumption
certain to have notions of very famous indi- of coherence that drives the interpretation
viduals" (p. 92). process, (p. 465)
20 Here, context is a psychological construct
that represents an individual's assumptions The idea is that each new sentence should
about the world at any given time and place be interpreted (as a minimum) in the con-
and is supposed to include information of the text provided by the sentences neighbor-
following kinds: ing it.
416 VAROL AKMAN

14 This applies even to an author himself. Many (Ed.), Generalized quantifiers (pp. 1-29).
of us have suffered in those situations where drecht, The Netherlands: Reidel.
we see a note we have scribbled a month ago Barwise, J. (1989a). On the circumstantial relatic
and spend a lot of time just to recover our between meaning and content. In J. Barwis
original intention in writing it. The situation in logic, CSLI Lecture Notes (N
25 Lindstrom (1991) offers a thorough critique of 17, pp. 59-77)- Stanford, CA: CSLI Public
this book. tions.
26 We thus find the following claim in Partee Barwise, J. (1989b). The situation in logic. Star
(2005) unnecessarily harsh: ford, CA: CSLI Publications.
Barwise, J., & Etchemendy, J. (1987). The liaj
Barwise and Perry's work, on the other An essay on truth and circularity. New Yori
hand, while starring off from some very Oxford University Press.
interesting uleas about "scenes" and "sit- Barwise, J., & Perry, J. (1983). Situations andatt]
uations" as ontologically important cat- tudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
egories to include in the foundations of Barwise, J., & Seligman, J. (1997). Informatu»
semantics... suffered from... problems flow: The logic of distributed systems. Cam
that made it become less attractive to bridge: Cambridge University Press.
many of us than it seemed like it was Barwise, J., Gawron, J. M., Plotkin, G., &
going to be Some scholars have con- Tutiya, S. (Eds.). ( 1 9 9 1 ) . Situation theory and
tinued to develop Barwise and Perry's its applications (Vol. 2). Stanford, CA: CSLI
situation semantics, and certain of its Publications.
ideas were readily borrowed into other Blackburn, S. (1994). The Oxford dictionary
approaches, but it soon became periph- of philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University
eral as a wholesale theory. Press.
Butterworth, G. (1998). Context and cognition
in models of cognitive growth. In A. C. Quel-
References has & F. Pereira (Eds.), Cognition and context
[Special issue of Artálise Psicológica] (pp. zj-
Aczel, P., Israel, D., Katagiri, Y . , & Peters, S. 44). Lisbon: Instituto Superior de Psicología
(Eds ). (1993). Situation theory and its appli- Aplicada.
cations (Vol. 3). Stanford, C A : C S L I Publica- C l a r k , H. H . , & C a r l s o n , T. B. (1981). Context
tions. f o r c o m p r e h e n s i o n . In J. L o n g & A. Baddeley
Akman, V., & Surav, M. (1996). Steps toward (Eds.), Attention and performance IX (pp. 313-
formalizing context. A1 Magazine, 17, 5 5 - 330). Hillsdale, N J : L a w r e n c e Erlbaum.
72. C o o p e r , R. (1991). T h r e e lectures on situation-
Akman, V., & Surav, M. (1997). The use of sit- theoretic g r a m m a r . In M. Filgueiras, L.
uation theory in context modeling. Computa- D a m a s , N. M o r e i r a , & A. P. Tomás (Eds.),
tional Intelligence, 13, 427-438. Natural language processing (pp. 102-140).
Allen, J. (1995). Natural language understanding. Berlin: Springer.
Redwood City, C A : Benjamin/Cummings. C o o p e r , R. (1996). T h e role of situations in
Angeles, P. A. (1981). Dictionary of philosophy. generalized quantifiers. In S. Lappin (Ed.),
New York: Harper & Row. The handbook of contemporary semantic theory
Asher, R. E., & Simpson, J. M. Y. (Eds.). (1994). (pp. 65-86). C a m b r i d g e , M A : Blackwell.
The encyclopedia of languages and linguistics C o o p e r , R., M u k a i , K . , & Perry, J. (Eds.). (1990).
(Vol. 2). Oxford: Pergamon. Situation theory and its applications (Vol. 1).
Austin, J. L. (1979). Truth. In J. O. Urmson & Stanford, C A : C S L I Publications.
G. J. Wamock (Eds.), Philosophical papers Crimmins, M. (1992). Talk about beliefs. Cam-
(pp. 117-133). Oxford: Clarendon. bridge, M A : M I T Press.
Barwise, J. (1986). Conditionals and conditional Davis, W. A. (2003). Meaning, expression and
information. In E. C. Traugott, C. A. Fer- thought. Cambridge: C a m b r i d g e University
guson, &. J. S. Reilly (Eds.), On conditionals Press.
(pp. 21-54). Cambridge: Cambridge Univer- Devlin, K. (n.d.). Situation theory and situation
sity Press. semantics. Retrieved M a r c h 28, 2008, from
Barwise, J. (1987). Noun phrases, generalized http://www.stanford.edu/~kdevlin/HHL_
quantifiers, and anaphora. In P. Gardenfors SituationTheory.pdf
a

wantics 4*7

Devlin, K. (îgyia). Logic and information. New Goodwin, C., & Duranti, A. (1992). Rethinking
York: Cambridge University Press. context: An introduction. In A. Duranti & C.
Devlin, K. (1991b). Oracles in situation semantics. Goodwin (Eds.), Rethinking context: Language
In J. Barwise, J. M. Gawron, G. Plotkin, & S. as an interactive phenomenon (pp. 1-42). New
Tutiya (Eds.), Situation theory and its applica- York: Cambridge University Press.
tions (Vol. 2, pp. 41-49). Stanford, CA: CSLI Hunt, E. (1999). What is a theory of thought? In
Publications. R. J. Sternberg (Ed.), The nature of cognition
Devlin, K. (1991c). Situations as mathematical (pp. 3-49). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
abstractions. In J. Barwise, J. M. Gawron, G. Kamp, H., & Reyle, U. (1993). From discourse to
Plotkin, & S. Tutiya (Eds.), Situation theory logic: Introduction to model-theoretic semantics
and its applications (Vol. 2, pp. 25-39). Stan- of natural language, formal logic, and discourse
ford, C A : CSLI Publications. representation theory, Parts I and II. Dordrecht,
Devlin, K. (1992) . Infons as mathematical objects. The Netherlands: Kluwer.
Minds and Machines, 2,185-201. Keefe, R. (2000). Theories of vagueness. Cam-
Devlin, K. (1998). Goodbye, Descartes: The end of bridge: Cambridge University Press.
logic and the search for a new cosmology of the Leech, G. (1981). Semantics: The study of meaning.
mind. New York: Wiley. Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin.
Devlin, K. (2001). Infosense: Turning information Lepore, E. (1982). What model theoretic seman-
into knowledge. New York: W. H. Freeman. tics cannot do. Synthese, 54,167-187.
Devlin, K. (2004). Jon Barwise's papers on natural Lindstrom, S. (1991). Critical study: Situations
language semantics. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, and attitudes. Nous, 25, 743-770.
10, 54-85. Lyons, J. (1995). Linguistic semantics: An introduc-
Devlin, K., & Rosenberg, D. (1996). Language at tion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
work: Analyzing communication breakdown in McKay, T., & Nelson, M. (2005). Prepositional
the workplace to inform systems design. Stan- attitude reports. Retrieved March 28, 2008,
ford, C A : C S L I Publications. from http://plato .Stanford, edu/entries/prop-
Dowty, D., Wall, R., | Peters, S. (1981). Intro- attitude-reports
duction to Montague semantics. Dordrecht, The Partee, B. H. (2005). Reflections of a for-
Netherlands: Reidel. mal semanticist as of Feb. 2005. Retrieved
Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of infor- March 28, 2008, from http://people.umass.
mation. Cambridge, M A : MIT Press. edu/partee/docs/BHP_Essay_Febo5.pdf
Eco, U. (1979). The role of the reader: Explorations Percy, W. (1975). The message in the bottle: How
in the semiotics of texts. Bloomington: Indiana queer man is, how queer language is, and what
University Press. one has to do with the other. New York: Farrar,
Fenstad, J. E., Halvorsen, P.-K., Langholm, T., Straus 8c Giroux.
& van Benthem, J. (1987). Situations, lan- Pietroski, P. M. (2003). The character of natu-
guage, and logic. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: ral language semantics. In A. Barber (Ed.),
Reidel. Epistemology of language (pp. 217-256). Oxford:
Firth, J. R. (1957). Papers in linguistics, 1934-1951. Oxford University Press.
London: Oxford University Press. Pulman, S. G. (1997). Semantics. In R. Cole, J.
Gawron, J. M., 81 Peters, S. (1990). Anaphora and Mariani, H. Uszkoreit, A. Zaenen, 8c V. Zue
quantification in situation semantics. Stanford, (Eds.), Survey of the state of the art in human
CA: CSLI Publications. language technology (pp. 105-111). Cambridge:
Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to Cambridge University Press.
visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Recanati, F. (2004). Literal meaning. Cambridge:
Goffman, E. (2002). Definition of the situation. Cambridge University Press.
In C. Calhoun (Ed.), Dictionary of the social Rokeach, M. (1998). Attitudes. In G. Marshall
sciences. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Ed.), A dictionary of sociology. Oxford:
Retrieved June 13, 2008, from http://www. Oxford University Press. Retrieved June 21,
oxfordreference.com/views/ENTRY. 2008, from http://www.oxfordreference.com/
html?subview=Main&entry=ti04.e425 views/ENTRY.html?subview=Main8centry=
Gonos, G. (1977). "Situation" versus "frame": The t88.en6
"interactionist" and the "structuralist" analyses Rosenschein, S. C., 8c Kaelbling, L. P. (1995). A
of everyday life. American Sociological Review, situated view of representation and control.
42, 854-867. Artificial Intelligence, 73,149-173.
v a r o l akman
41S

losophy and Phenomenological Research, 4,


Seligman, J., & Mciss, L. S. (1997). Situa-
tion theory. In J. van Benthem & A. ter 376. , ,
Metilen (Eds.), Handbook of logic and lan- Tin, E., 8t Akman, V. (1996). Information-
guage (pp. 239-309). Amsterdam: Elsevier oriented computation with BABY-SIT. In J
Science. Seligman 8t D. WesterstShl (Eds.), Logic, lan-
Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1986). Relevance: guage, and computation (Vol. 1, pp. 19-34)
Communication and cognition. Cambridge, Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.
MA: Harvard University Press. Turvey, M., & Carello, C. (1986). The equation
Stucky, S. (1989). The situated processing of sit- of information and meaning from the perspec-
uated language. Linguistics and Philosophy, 12, tives of situation semantics and Gibson's eco-
347-357- logical realism. Linguistics and Philosophy, 8,
Tarski, A. (1944). The semantic conception of 81-90.
Tye, M. (1990). Vague objects. Mind, 99,535-557.
truth and the foundations of semantics. Phi-
CHAPTER 22

Is Consciousness Embodied?

Jesse Prinz

i. Introduction T h e radicalism of embodied and embed-


ded approaches has been taken too far, but
Consciousness is trendy. It seems that more people w h o are prepared to dismiss these
pages are published on consciousness these approaches may be missing out on a catalog
days than on any other subject in the phi- of helpful resources. I do not think embodi-
losophy of mind. E m b o d i m e n t and situated ment and situated cognition hold the basic
cognition are also trendy. T h e y mark a sig- key to explaining consciousness, but some-
nificant departure from orthodox theories, thing in this ballpark may help us explain
and are thus appealing to radicals and rene- certain aspects of conscious experience. We
gades. It is hardly surprising, then, that con- should resist the most seductive theories but
sciousness, e m b o d i m e n t , and situated cog- pay close attention to more modest ones. In
nition have coalesced (see, e.g., Cotterill, general, I think the great promise of e m b o d -
1998; Hurley, 1998; Mandik, 1999; Noe, 2004; ied and situated cognition will emerge as
O'Regan & N o e , 2001; T h o m p s o n & Varela, the excitement dies down. As with connec-
2001). Both topics are exciting, and being tionism, the value of these approaches is
exciting is an additive property. An embod- harder to see if we focus on h o w radical they
ied or situated theory of consciousness is are. Radicalism may be good for politics,
the philosophical equivalent of a block- but it is bad for science. In science, I pro-
buster. But excitement is not always cor- mote middle-of-the-road liberalism. A f t e r
related with truth, and the embodied and critically evaluating some radical theories,
situated approach to consciousness may be I will advance four moderate proposals that
easier to sell than to prove. take embodiment seriously.

In this chapter, I assess situated and Before proceeding, it will be u s e f u l to


embodied approaches to consciousness. This offer some working definitions. T h e t e r m
is neither an exculpation nor an execution, embodied is most genetically used to m e a n
but an exploration. My verdict is tempered. involving the body (compare discussion in

4*9
JESSE PRINZ
4*5

Gallagher, 2005). To say that a mental capac- where we are located. Someone who held
ity is embodied can mean one of two things. this view might suppose that, if two people
It can mean that the capacity depends on with the same internal state were in different
the possession and use of a body, not just a environments, their conscious experiences
brain. I exclude the brain, because the brain would be different. Defenders of situated
is part of the body, and all materialists (and cognition, like defenders of radical embodi-
some dualists) believe that mental capaci- ment, would deny that a brain in a vat has
ties involve the brain. Some embodiment conscious states like our own; a brain in a
theorists think other parts of the body are vat has no body and does not interact with
important as well. Other embodiment the- the environment in the way that we do.
orists do not go quite this far. Instead, they I will now argue that many of the stan-
say that embodied mental capacities are ones dard ways of defending these hypotheses
that depend on mental representations or about consciousness do not enjoy adequate
processes that relate to the body (see, e.g., support (see also Prinz, 2000a, 2006). After
Glenberg & Kaschak, 2003). Such represen- that, I will get more concessive. I think that
tations and processes come in two forms: certain aspects of consciousness may depend
there are representations and processes that on systems involved in perceiving and con-
represent or respond to the body, such as a trolling the body. The brand of embodiment
perception of bodily movement, and there I favor may not be as sexy as other varieties
are representations and processes that affect on the market, but I think the brand I favor
the body, such as motor commands. We can may capture what is true and important
call the first class "somatic" and the second about this trend in consciousness studies. I
class "enactive." On this use of the term think defenders of more radical views have
embodiment, everyone agrees that, say, pro- ultimately done a great service by drawing
prioceptive states of the central nervous sys- our attention to the relationship between
tem are embodied. The controversy con- experience and action, and understanding
cerns whether other forms of perception that relationship will prove essential for an
and cognition are embodied. For example, adequate theory of consciousness.
only an embodiment theorist would say
that vision is embodied in any of the ways
described here. To say that consciousness 2. Situated Experience
is embodied is to say that consciousness
depends either on the existence of processes People who advocate situated cognition
in the body outside the head or on somatic tend also to advocate embodiment. This is
or enactive processes that may be inside the not surprising. If you think that the envi-
head. ronment makes an important contribution
Colloquially, the term situated means to mental capacities, then you might be dis-
located somewhere. On this definition, all posed to accept the idea that the body makes
materialists and many dualists think that a contribution. For one thing, the body can
mental states and processes are situated. be regarded as part of the environment of
The thoughts you are currently having are the mind or brain - it is just a very local
in your brain, and your brain is in a spe- part. And, for another thing, we need a body
cific geographical location. We could locate to explore the environment, and for fans
your thoughts if we affixed a GPS device of situated cognition, interactions between
to your cranium. Defenders of situated cog- the environment and the body are often
nition mean something stronger, of course. regarded as crucial for intelligent behavior.
They mean that being located in a physi- For example, catching a baseball involves
cal environment makes an essential contri- moving one's body in a way that keeps the
bution to our mental capacities. Conscious- ball in the center of the visual field. Never-
ness is situated if being conscious in the theless, it is useful to discuss situated cog-
way that we are depends on whether and nition and embodiment separately, because
•i-o
isc o n s c i o u s n e s sembodied?•i-o

the proposals that have been advanced with causally coupled if the equations describing
respect to consciousness are dissociable. the dynamics of one include variables that
It is possible, for example, to think that quantify over states of the other, and con-
versely. Almost everyone agrees that mind
consciousness is embodied in some sense
and world are causally coupled. What pro-
without accepting strong versions of the
ponents of situated consciousness add to this
hypothesis that consciousness is situated. In
platitude is the claim that conscious expe-
this section, I will focus on situated con- riences arise only when certain dynamical
sciousness. relations are instantiated; the dynamical pro-
At the outset, it is important to distin- cesses are essential for consciousness. If one
guish three ways in which conscious expe- thinks that consciousness depends on the
riences may be dependent on the external instantiation of certain dynamical systems,
environment. One form of dependency is and those systems are coupled with the envi-
semantic. Externalists about mental content ronment, then one might conclude that con-
argue that content does not supervene on scious experiences would not arise were it
what is in the head (e.g., Fodor, 1994; Wil- not for causal interactions with things in the
son, 2004). Intentional content, in particular, environment.
depends on relationships between mind and Presented in this way, the situated view
world, where those relationships are usually still locates consciousness in the head. T h e
understood as causal, teleological, or infor- hypothesis is that consciousness depends on
mational. Some people think that the char- processes in the head that simply could not
acter of conscious experiences depends on arise in the way that they do if it were
their intentional content; this is one ver- not for steady causal interactions with the
sion of the view known as representation- world. An even more radical suggestion is
alism (e.g., Dretske, 1995; Lycan, 1996; Tye, that consciousness has a constitutive depen-
1995). If y o u are a representationalist and dency on the environment. One might think
an externalist, then you are committed to that consciousness supervenes on features of
the view that conscious experience depends the environment along with internal states.
on the external environment. But this is not On this view, conscious states are realized by
the kind of dependency that proponents dynamical systems that extend beyond the
of situated cognition are after. Externalists skin. Thus, we have two situated conscious-
think that the relevant environment is the ness hypotheses: causal and constitutive.
world that an agent resides in, or perhaps Both of these hypotheses come in stronger
some merely possible world. Proponents of and weaker versions. On the stronger ver-
sion, we could not have conscious states
situated cognition think that conscious
at all were it not for being hooked up to
states depend on the local environment cur-
the environment in a particular way. On
rently surrounding and impinging upon the
the weaker version, consciousness can arise
agent. This dependency usually is not con-
without environmental hookups, but the
strued as semantic.
character of conscious experience is differ-
The second kind of dependency is causal.
ent in such circumstances; environmental
The experiences y o u are having might be
hookups affect the character of experience.
causally dependent on the environment you
As Block (2005) and Adams and A i z a w a (this
are in. On one formulation, this hypothe-
volume) point out, these views are some-
sis is uncontroversial. T h e environment can
times conflated by defenders of situated con-
causally stimulate our sensory receptors and
sciousness.
bring about experiences. Proponents of sit-
uated cognition d e f e n d a m u c h more inti- I think we can reject the stronger ver-
mate link. First, they tend to suppose that sions of the situated approach outright. C o n -
conscious states are causally coupled with scious states arise w h e n we are dreaming or
the environment (e.g., T h o m p s o n & Varela, hallucinating despite the fact that, in those
2001). Coupling is a term f r o m dynamical cases, the contents do not reflect causal
systems theory. R o u g h l y , t w o systems are
4m JESSE P R I N Z

interactions with the external environment. deprivation chamber), we have reason to


Even more dramatically, people have rich think that consciousness does not have envj.
conscious experiences when they are put in ronmental substrates on some occasions.
sensory-deprivation chambers, suspended in Why, then, should we think the environ-
liquid with their eyes, ears, and chemical ment is ever a substrate of experience?
senses cut off (e.g., Feynman, 1997). Peo- On the face of it, hallucinations provide
ple in sensory-deprivation chambers report reason to reject situated consciousness. If
visual hallucinations, and there is no reason veridical perceptions are just like halluci-
to suppose that the content of those halluci- nations, and hallucinations are independent
nations is dictated by the environment they of the environment, then veridical percep-
are in. tions are probably independent as well. But
What about the weaker suggestion that defenders of situated consciousness reject
the character of conscious experiences is the first premise. They argue that halluci-
affected by the environment? I think the nations are not like veridical perceptions. I
causal version is perfecdy plausible. Every- think that is a very hard nut to chew. Many
one agrees that the environment can influ- hallucinations may be unlike real experi-
ence our experiences. It may turn out ences in various respects, but given the fact
that the specific character of an experi- that hallucinatory experiences (including
ence depends on how internal states unfold dreams, mirages, phantom limbs, and psy-
dynamically over time, and such unfolding chotic experiences) are frequendy mistaken
can be influenced by the environment. The for reality, it seems overwhelmingly likely
causal situated hypothesis is really contro- that there can be hallucinations that are
versial only on stronger versions. It is con- qualitatively indistinguishable from veridi-
troversial to say that we could not be con- cal perceptions.
scious at all if we were not hooked up to the Let me offer here what I consider the
environment in a specific way, but it is rel- best argument for a situated view of con-
atively uncontroversial to say that the char- sciousness. It is loosely inspired by sugges-
acter of the experiences we actually have tions made by Alva Noe (2004) and, follow-
results from how we are dynamically hooked ing Noe, I will focus on vision. The argument
up to the environment. I will leave this rel- begins with a premise that is axiomatic for
atively uninteresting suggestion to one side. situated cognition enthusiasts: the world is
Much more contentious is the constitutive its own best model (Brooks, 1991). Propo-
view. Proponents of situated consciousness nents of situated cognition argue that if we
like to suggest that, when we are not dream- form internal representations of the world
ing or hallucinating, our experiences are at all, they are sparsely detailed; we do
constituted by an interaction between inter- not internally represent the external envi-
nal states and the environment. (I use con- ronment in all its rich splendor. There is
stitution broadly to cover relations of iden- no need to. If we need more information
tity, realization, constituency, and so on.) than we have currently encoded at any given
Views of this kind have been defended by moment, we can always consult the world.
James (1904) and Noe and Thompson (2004), Our senses can sample the environment at
among others. Noe (2004) says it is one way any given moment. The environment is triv-
to cash out the idea of direct perception: ially a more accurate source of information
perception is not mediated by an internal about itself than any internal representa-
representation that stands between mind tions we happen to form, so we might as
and world, but rather is constituted by a well save processing power and represent
mind-world interaction. as little of it as possible. This is what fans
It is difficult to defend a view like this. of situated cognition like to say, but, when
Given that consciousness can arise in sit- it comes to conscious experience, a puzzle
uations that are indifferent to the exter- immediately arises. Conscious experiences
nal world (hallucination in a sensory- seem to be richly detailed; the visual field,
is c o n s c i o u snessembodied?•i-o

for e x a m p l e , seems to have shapes and colors cut across the b r a i n - b o d y - w o r l d divisions"
in every corner. S o m e p e o p l e think this is an (p. 26).
illusion. D e n n e t t (1969), f o r e x a m p l e , says T h e argument that I just s k e t c h e d f o r
that it is an introspective trap caused by the conclusion that consciousness is partially
the fact that, w h e n e v e r we try to e x a m - constituted by the w o r l d rests on t w o as-
ine a part of the visual field, we sample sumptions. It rests on the assumption t h a t
the corresponding part of the environment experiences are rich and that internal r e p r e -
and retrieve the relevant details. But this sentations are not. I will not take issue w i t h
explanation is slightly unsatisfying. W h e n the first assumption. A d m i t t e d l y , e x p e r i -
I am watching T V , I can, at any m o m e n t , ence seems sparse under certain c i r c u m -
flip the channels and see w h a t is happen- stances. For example, if y o u try to c o u n t t h e
ing on every n e t w o r k , b u t I have no illu- serifs in this letter P you might briefly lose
sion that I am experiencing multiple chan- awareness of the surrounding letters (see t h e
nels at once. In response, defenders of the discussion of inattentional blindness herein).
view that richness in an illusion might argue B u t experience is not always sparse. If y o u
that saccades are faster than channel switch- stare at this w h o l e page rather than a sin-
ing on a TV set, and the speed is w h a t makes gle P, it will look like a rich field of clus-
the image seem so rich. B u t I do not see tered letters. Y o u probably will not be able
why speed should m a k e a difference here. to read those letters (they are not all in f o c u s ,
If each visual instant w e r e lacking in detail, and it is hard to read multiple letters simul-
then we should e x p e r i e n c e a flickering bar- taneously), b u t y o u will experience them,
rage of sparse images. A rapid sequence of lined up in neat rows spanning across y o u r
sparse images should engender an experi- visual field. Under such circumstances, it
ence of a unified image only if the brain inte- is difficult to deny that experience seems
grates the successive snapshots into a single rich. I am not suggesting that the visual field
rich composite. If y o u still think the sac- seems uniformly detailed. W h e n staring at a
cade story can explain w h y the visual field scene, many objects m a y be out of focus or
seems rich, then try to stare at the scene unidentified, b u t we still seem to experience
in front of y o u keeping y o u r eyes fixed. a field that is filled rather than sparse. T h a t
Much of w h a t y o u experience may be blurry is w h a t I mean w h e n I say that experience
(sharp f o c u s is restricted to the fovea), b u t seems rich.
the visual field will still seem very rich. T h e
If richness is hard to challenge, w h a t
richness of e x p e r i e n c e seems to reside in
about the second premise in the argu-
the present, not in any capacity I have to
m e n t f o r situated consciousness? S h o u l d we
get more information a m o m e n t f r o m now.
accept the claim that the richness of e x p e -
That aspect of p h e n o m e n o l o g y needs to be
rience is not a consequence of rich inter-
explained. A n d here is w h e r e the situated
nal representations? A l v a N o e (2004) thinks
cognition thesis arises. If conscious experi-
that we must accept this claim. He thinks
ence is not restricted to w h a t is in my head
there is empirical evidence demonstrating
but includes the environment around me,
that internal representations are not rich. In
then the richness of experience is not an illu-
particular, he cites studies on change blind-
sion. E x p e r i e n c e really is rich, even though
ness. In these experiments, subjects are pre-
internal representations are sparse. It is rich
sented with t w o consecutive images that d i f -
because experience is partially composed
fer in some respect. For e x a m p l e , a pair of
by the world, and the world is rich. T h e
people in the first image might s w a p hats, a
idea that the w o r l d is literally a component
parrot might change color, a building m i g h t
of conscious experience m a y sound bizarre,
shrink in size, an aircraft engine m i g h t dis-
but it has been proposed as a serious possi-
appear, and so on. T h e s e large changes in
bility. N o e and T h o m p s o n (2004) say, " T h e
the pictures often go unnoticed. M a n y sub-
substrates of consciousness - in particular of
jects cannot see any d i f f e r e n c e b e t w e e n t h e
visual perceptual consciousness - seem to
t w o pictures. T h a t suggests that t h e y are
jesse p r i n z
•P4

not encoding every detail. Noe uses these cued recall. Noe himself acknowledges this
findings to conclude that internal represen- when he notes that people in change blind-
tations are sparse. ness experiments are above chance at cued
But Noe's conclusion does not hold up on recall for objects whose disappearance they
scrutiny. Another hypothesis is that people failed to notice. But this concession under-
encode pictures in very rich detail but do mines the argument for situated conscious-
not store all those details from moment to ness. That argument was premised on the
moment (Simons & Levin, 1997). On this idea that the apparent richness of experi-
interpretation, subjects form internal rep- ence can be explained only by the richness
resentations that change when the pictures of the environment, because internal rep-
are swapped, but they do not keep track of resentations are not sparse in detail. The
these changes; there can be changing rep- studies just reviewed refute this premise by
resentations without representations of the establishing that internal representations are
fact that a change has taken place. There rich. If so, then one can explain the appar-
is strong evidence suggesting that this inter- ent richness of experience without making
pretation of change blindness is right; peo- the radical claim that the external world is a
ple form rich representations and simply do substrate of experience.
not store all the details in memory long Other arguments for the view that con-
enough to make comparisons from moment scious experiences are constituted, in part,
to moment. Consider priming studies. Sil- by the environment can surely be imagined,
verman and Mack (2001) have shown that but I do not think any argument for that
information that people fail to notice dur- conclusion will be convincing. Such an argu-
ing change blindness experiments can prime ment would need to show that there can
information processing. For example, if you be aspects of phenomenal experience that
show subjects an array of letters and then are not explained by events in the head. In
change some, they will not always notice this spirit, proponents of situated conscious-
that some have changed. But the letters from ness argue that there are no neural correlates
the initial array that went unnoticed must be of consciousness (Noe & Thompson, 2004),
internally represented, because when sub- Without taking up this issue, let me just
jects are given a subsequent test in which comment that the attempts to correlate con-
they need to complete a picture of a letter sciousness experiences with brain states has
than has been distorted, the letters that they been amazingly productive (Jack & Prinz,
were shown in the change blindness task 2003; Koch, 2004; Metzinger, 2000). We can
influence their responses. In a more recent find brain states that encode the same infor-
study, Mitroff, Simons, and Levin (2004) mation as conscious states and occur at the
showed subjects consecutive pairs of images same time. We find line detectors in visual
depicting an array of objects. Subjects were areas active when we see illusory contours,
often unable to tell when one of the objects and we find motion detectors active when
had changed, but when asked to confirm we see illusory motion. Neuroscience is still
which objects they had seen on a subse- a young field, but every phenomenal feature
quent probe, they were well above chance that we investigate seems to have a system-
in recalling the objects whose disappear- atic correlate. Of course, we do not know
ance had gone unnoticed. This suggests that why neural events give rise to phenomenal
those objects were internally represented. qualities (the hard problem), but that mys-
On the sparse representation interpretation tery will not be solved by assuming that con-
of change blindness, unnoticed features are sciousness supervenes on items in the envi-
not internally represented. The Silverman ronment. The bottom line is that there is no
and Mack study and the Mitroff et al. study serious reason at this time to suppose that
contradict this hypothesis. Unnoticed fea- the correlates of consciousness will include
tures must be represented because they anything outside the head. Indeed, given
cause priming, and they are available for how far we have come in neuroscience,
•i-o
is c o n s c i o u s n e s s embodied? •i-o

it is hard to take that suggestion very seri- mental representations. (This characteriza-
ously- tion is loose, because some embodiment
theorists reject the representational theory
of mind. I address antirepresentationalism
- Radical E m b o d i m e n t elsewhere; Prinz & Barsalou, 2000.) If men-
tal representations are located in the brain,
When interpreted as a thesis about constitu- then this approach to embodiment does not
tion, situated consciousness is a very radical carry exorbitant metaphysical costs. It is less
hypothesis; it says that the environment is extravagant than the constitution version
a component of our conscious experiences. of the situated approach and worth taking
To accept this is to give up a central plank more seriously.
of modern materialism - the supposition Embodied approaches are less metaphys-
that consciousness supervenes on the brain. ically extravagant, but they are often radi-
I have yet to encounter an argument that cal in other respects. As Hurley (1998) puts
is nearly p o w e r f u l enough to consider giv- it, she and other defenders of embodiment
ing up the brain doctrine. T h e claim that want to dispose of the "classical sandwich"
consciousness is embodied is sometimes pre- model of the mind, which dominates in con-
sented as a version of situated consciousness. temporary philosophy and cognitive science.
Just as proponents of situated conscious- In the classical sandwich model, the mind
ness locate experience partially in the world, divides neatly into input systems, which
some proponents of embodied conscious- receive sensory information; cognitive sys-
ness locate experience partially in the body tems, which engaging in thinking; and out-
(outside the brain). S o m e combine these put systems, which execute motor actions.
views, suggesting that consciousness super- On this approach, thinking is a proprietary
venes on interactions between body and class of capacities nestled between input and
world. T h e claim that consciousness extends output systems and largely independent of
into the body is only marginally more plau- both. I am skeptical of the classical sandwich
sible than the claim that consciousness leaks myself, because I believe that thinking incor-
out into the world. We have never found porates representations used for perception
any cells outside the brain that are candi- and motor control (Prinz, 2002) But Hurley
dates as correlates for experience. Such cells and others want to go even further. They
want to demolish the border between inputs
would have to co-vary with conscious states
and outputs. I believe that the senses and
in content and time course. Every compo-
motor systems interact, but they are nev-
nent of the b o d y that we can experience is
ertheless distinct; they use different repre-
represented in the brain, and when the cor-
sentational codes, follow different rules, can
responding brain areas are damaged experi-
function independently, and often reside in
ence is lost. Conversely, bodily experience
different parts of the brain. Hurley and some
can continue after the body is damaged, as
other radical embodiment theorists believe
in the case of p h a n t o m - l i m b pain. There is,
either that there is no division between input
in short, little reason to think the correlates
and output systems (instead we have unified
of experience e x t e n d b e y o n d the cranium.
sensorimotor systems) or, to the extent that
Fortunately, one can defend the view that
such a division exists, input systems causally
consciousness is e m b o d i e d without aban-
depend on output systems to do any seri-
doning the assumption that consciousness
ous work. In other words, embodiment the-
resides in the brain. As we saw in the intro- orists like to defend either a constitution
duction, the t e r m embodiment sometimes thesis or a strong causal thesis about percep-
refers to v i e w s according to which mental tion and action; perceiving is either partially
capacities involve internal states and pro- constituted by processes that are motoric
cesses that control or respond to the body. in nature or causally d e p e n d on those pro-
Put loosely, on o n e use of the term, a mental cesses for normal operation. I will not d w e l l
capacity is e m b o d i e d if it depends on bodily
JESSE PRINZ

on this distinction. Following O ' R e g a n a n d a s o p e r a t i v e p o s s i b i l i t i e s f o r a c t i o n , and, pro-


Noe (2001J, I will refer to all versions of this p o n e n t s o f t h e e n a c t i v e a p p r o a c h believe,
genera) approach as "the enactive v i e w . " t h i s i s a p r e c o n d i t i o n f o r n o r m a l perceptual
The enactive view should be distin- c o n s c i o u s n e s s . T o s e e n o r m a l l y , f o r exam-
guished from less controversial h y p o t h e s e s ple, w e m u s t k n o w h o w a v i s i b l e surface
about the relationship between inputs a n d w o u l d c h a n g e i f w e w e r e t o a l t e r t h e position
outputs. Everyone agrees that there can be o f o u r e y e s o r b o d i e s . O ' R e g a n a n d N o e are a
causal interactions between the t w o . For e x - l i t t l e v a g u e a b o u t w h e t h e r w e c o u l d see a t all
ample, everyone agrees that w h e n a p e r s o n w i t h o u t p i c k i n g u p o n s e n s o r i m o t o r contin-
looks at a hammer, she might s p o n t a n e o u s l y g e n c i e s , b u t t h e y c l e a r l y t h i n k t h a t ordinary
generate a motor command consistent w i t h e x p e r i e n c e , i n c l u d i n g t h e d i s t i n c t i v e quali-
grasping the hammer. In G i b s o n ' s terms, we ties o f c o l o r s a n d t h e d i f f e r e n c e s between
can see what actions an object affords. B u t t h e senses, r e q u i r e s m o t o r dispositions. In
seeing affordances is understood, in o r t h o - his b o o k N o e (2004) is m o r e explicit; he
dox views, as an associative process. V i s u a l s e e m s t o s u g g e s t t h a t w e w o u l d literally b e
states bring motor responses to m i n d . L i k e - b l i n d w i t h o u t h a v i n g d i s p o s i t i o n a l motoric
wise, everyone agrees that m o t o r states can r e s p o n s e s t o v i s u a l i n p u t s . T h a t i s a fasci-
have some impact on perception. To t a k e n a t i n g h y p o t h e s i s . I t h i n k it is f a l s e , b u t it
a trivial example, shifting your eyes a f f e c t s certainly is n o t o b v i o u s l y false.
what you see. It is even likely that a m e r e l y T o a s s e s s t h e e n a c t i v e v i e w , w e need t o
imagined shift of gaze can a f f e c t visual p e r - g e t a b i t c l e a r e r o n w h a t i t s d e f e n d e r s claim.
ception by shifting the focus of visual atten- I w i l l d i s t i n g u i s h t h r e e e n a c t i v e hypotheses.
tion. Thus, motor representations can c a u s e A l l a r e c o m p a t i b l e , b u t t h e y a r e potentially
changes in visual representations. D e f e n d e r s d i s s o c i a b l e , a n d t h e y c a l l o n d i f f e r e n t evi-
of the enactive view have something m o r e d e n c e . T h e f i r s t e n a c t i v e h y p o t h e s i s i s devel-
radical in mind. They suppose that m o t o r opmental. O n e m i g h t t h i n k t h a t ordinary
representations are (causally or constitution- c o n s c i o u s p e r c e p t i o n c a n n o t d e v e l o p with-
ally) essential to perceiving; we w o u l d be o u t t h e e x e r c i s e o f m o t o r s k i l l s . T h e devel-
blind, in some sense, without t h e m . o p m e n t a l h y p o t h e s i s i s c o m p a t i b l e w i t h the
Applied to consciousness, t h e e n a c t i v e supposition that perceptual consciousness
view holds that the conscious e x p e r i e n c e s d o e s n o t d e p e n d o n m o t o r r e s p o n s e s later
caused by sensory encounters with t h e w o r l d i n l i f e . I n t h i s r e s p e c t , i t i s a m o r e moder-
depend on motor responses. For e x a m p l e , a t e h y p o t h e s i s t h a n t h e n e x t t w o t h a t I will
visual experience may depend on m o t o r c o n s i d e r . B u t s h o u l d w e t h i n k i t i s true?
representations that control e y e position. T h e m a i n i t e m of e v i d e n c e advanced in
O'Regan and N o e (2001) say that seeing f a v o r o f t h e d e v e l o p m e n t a l e n a c t i v e view
involves a skillful engagement w i t h t h e i s a s t u d y c o n d u c t e d i n 1 9 6 3 b y H e l d and
world. More specifically, they say that e v e r y - H e i n ( s e e C o t t e r i l l , 1 9 9 8 ; M a n d i k , 1999; Noe,
thing that we can distinguish in perception 2004). H e l d a n d H e i n p e r f o r m e d a n exper-
affords different potential motor interac- iment with t w o y o u n g kittens, reared i n
tions, and that perceiving involves t h e reg- d a r k n e s s . F o r t h r e e h o u r s a d a y , t h e kittens
istration of these sensorimotor contingen- w e r e b r o u g h t i n t o a n i l l u m i n a t e d r o o m and
cies. As I understand it, t h e idea is t h a t we p l a c e d o n e i t h e r s i d e o f a h a r n e s s , which
have various action-dispositions associated a l l o w e d o n e k i t t e n t o w a l k a r o u n d a room
with the stimuli that we encounter, and e a c h w h i l e t h e o t h e r h u n g s u s p e n d e d i n a cra-
of these dispositions, if carried out, w o u l d d l e . T h e s e c o n d k i t t e n w a s a b l e t o see the
alter the sensory inputs; sensorimotor dispo- r o o m a s t h e o t h e r k i t t e n r o a m e d around,
sitions constitute implicit k n o w l e d g e of h o w b u t i t w a s n o t a b l e t o m o v e o n its own.
stimuli would change if we w e r e to m o v e in A f t e r t e n d a y s i n t h i s a p p a r a t u s , t h e kittens
some way. When a stimulus impinges on o u r w e r e f r e e d a n d t h e i r v i s i o n w a s t e s t e d . Held
senses, those dispositions b e c o m e available a n d H e i n f o u n d t h a t v i s i o n i n t h e active cat
is c o n s c i o u s n e s s e m b o d i e d ? 4*7

was normal, b u t vision in the passive cat was for the thesis that moving around one's envi-
abnormal in three respects: it did not blink ronment is necessary for the development of
when objects loomed toward it, it had diffi- conscious perception, and there seems to be
cult guiding its p a w s visually, and it did not plenty of evidence against that hypothesis.
avoid visual cliffs. T h e y concluded that phy- Radical inferences from the Held and Hein
sical interaction with the world is necessary cat studies should be put to rest.
for development of vision. Applied to con- Let me turn to a second radical enactive
sciousness, one might be tempted to con- view. Some enactive theorists imply that
clude that visual consciousness will not de- there can be no conscious perceptual e x p e -
velop in the absence of physical interaction. riences in the absence of internal states that
The Held and Hein result is fascinating, register sensorimotor contingencies - the
but it cannot be used to support a strong motor responses that the perceptual states
version of the hypothesis that consciousness afford. This would be a stunning fact if true,
depends developmentally on action. First, but why should we believe it? Defenders of
the passive cat was not blind. It was able enactive consciousness are sometimes a bit
to move about successfully using vision; it unclear about what evidence is supposed to
just suffered f r o m very specific behavioral support this necessity claim, but let me con-
deficits. Second, these deficits are unsurpris- sider one argument. Noe (2004) is impressed
ing. T h e cat failed to assign motoric sig- by results from the study of prism lenses
nificance to its visual episodes. It did not that either invert or shift the visual field.
understand that an object rapidly filling its When people wear these lenses, the senso-
visual field was looming toward it (perhaps rimotor contingencies that they have mas-
the object just appeared to be growing); tered no longer apply. Normally, if an object
it had difficulty with visually coordinating appears in front of us when we stare straight
its paws, because it did not have experi- ahead, we can grasp it by reaching straight
ence calibrating kinesthetic feedback with forward. If we are wearing lenses that shift
visual feedback; and it did not avoid visual the visual field to the left, a forward reaching
cliffs, because experience may be needed to motion will miss the object. Over a period
learn that surfaces that look a certain way of time, people wearing the lenses adjust
are farther away. But, for all that, the pas- to the new contingencies, and they report
sive cat's visual experiences may have been being very disoriented when they first put
just like the active cat's visual experiences; the lenses on. N o e is struck by the reports
the difference was that the passive cat did of disorientation. As he describes it, peo-
not assign the same action-related signifi- ple are temporarily blinded when they first
cance to those experiences. This is utterly wear the glasses. This is just what the enac-
unsurprising. Deprive a cat of action, and tive hypothesis under consideration w o u l d
it will not learn what actions various visual predict. When we realize that the expected
experiences afford. Third, the passive cat contingencies are wrong, we need to dis-
attained normal visual abilities quickly after pense with them, and as we do so, per-
the experiment. Fourth, the experiment has ceptual experience should be dramatically
not been replicated. Fifth, lessons from cats affected or lost.
may not apply to us. Riviere and Lecmyer
T h e trouble is that Noe's characteriza-
(2002) recendy studied visuospatial abilities
tion of what happens when people w e a r
in young children w h o suffer from congen-
inverting lenses is misleading. People do not
ital motor atrophy. These children had no
experience blindness and, as long as they
experience moving around in the world but
do not try to move, the visual world will
their visual abilities were the same as healthy
remain unaffected (I get this f r o m first-hand
children.
reports by Fred Dretske, w h o has tried the
These points raise serious doubts about lenses). Disorientation arises w h e n people
the developmental embodied consciousness try to physically interact with the objects
hypothesis. I am aware of no good evidence they see. It is very disorienting to reach for
jesse prtnz

an object and miss! I am even willing to myasthenia gravis (Cassell, Billig, & Randall
grant tiiat inverting lenses can alter percep- 1998). In addition, p e o p l e with damage to
tual response. For example, I would not be parietal cortex can s u f f e r f r o m disruptions
surprised if receptive fields in visual areas of in visually guided action, saccade control
the brain shift as one adapts to the lenses; we and the allocation of attention to multiple
know that receptive fields change with shifts objects, but they are not blind (Milner &
of attention (Moran & Desimone, 1985)1 But Goodale, 1995). In summary, I am aware of
those changes do not support the enac- no insult to any brain system involved in
tive view. Everyone agrees that the senses motor control that results in blindness.
interact and that events in one sense can To deal with the clinical findings, enac-
alter another. For example, ventriloquists tive theorists might argue that the relevant
can cause us to shift the location of speech motor responses are located in the visual
sounds in auditory space by making us watch pathway and other sensory systems, not
the lips move on a dummy. In the McGurk in areas traditionally associated with motor
effect, the visual appearance of moving lips control. I hope it goes without saying that
actually alters the sound that we hear, and responses of this kind are ad hoc. Damage
the effect is instantaneous (McGurk & Mac- to visual pathways does not cause motor
Donald, 1976). Likewise, we should not be deficits, and there is no theory-independent
surprised if misalignments of vision and reason to say that motor dispositions are
action cause changes in visual experience. encoded therein. If one retreats to dispo-
Such causal effects fall far short of the sitions and anachronistic definitions of the
hypothesis that motor responses are neces- motor areas in the brain, there is a danger
sary for perceptual experience. By analogy, that the enactive v i e w will become unfal-
the fact that vision affects hearing does not
sifiable. Enactive theorists should identify
entail that we cannot hear without seeing.
and test precise predictions of their theories.
To establish that motor representations They should tell us w h i c h motor systems are
are necessary for conscious perceptual expe- involved in vision, and they should predict
rience, it would be useful to show that that insult to those systems w o u l d have seri-
damage to motor systems results in per- ous repercussions f o r visual experience.
ceptual deficits. There is little evidence for Enactive theorists should also provide
this in the clinical literature. For exam- evidence for the claim that motor systems
ple, patients with amyotrophic lateral scle- are necessarily active w h e n we have con-
rosis (Lou Gehrig's disease) suffer from scious visual experience. T h e y often empha-
a degeneration of premotor neurons. This size the importance of eye-movements for
profoundly disrupts motor response, but it experience, but there is little evidence for
leaves perceptual consciousness intact (Kan- the claim that visual perception depends
dell, Schwartz, & Jessel, 2000). Likewise, on saccades. We perceive both during and
paralysis of the ocular muscles, which con- between saccades, and w h e n we keep our
trol eye movements, does not prevent peo- eyes fixed, we do not b e c o m e blind. Defend-
ple having conscious visual experience. For ers of the enactive v i e w might respond
example, Land, Furneaux, and Gilchrist
by saying that, under these circumstances,
(2002) describe an individual who has rel-
motor responses are available disposition-
atively normal vision despite the fact that
ally. Perhaps they are right, but this must
she had lifelong congenital ocular fibrosis,
be established empirically, and it must also
which prevents her eyes from moving. Peo-
be established that if the dispositions were
ple with paralyzed eyes often report dou-
disrupted or eliminated, experience would
ble vision, because their eyes come out of
change. Suppose you train yourself to sac-
alignment, but they can certainly see. This is
cade to the right w h e n you see a certain
the case even when the paralysis of the eyes
shade of blue, and then, after firmly estab-
results from the elimination or receptors in
lishing that disposition, you retrain your-
the nerves that control eye movement, as in
self to saccade to the left. Will the visual
is c o n s c i o u s n e s s embodied? •I-O

experience of that blue change after retrain- phenomenally different in virtue of differ-
ing? I doubt it. Is this a prediction of the ences in sensorimotor contingencies. The
theory? If not, why not? two senses can register the same feature of
Let me turn now to one final enactive the environment, but, because they have
hypothesis. Suppose the enactive theorists different implications for action, they feel
were to concede that motor responses are different. One item of evidence used to
not necessary for perceptual consciousness. defend this claim comes from Bach-y-Rita's
They might still argue that motor responses, (1972) research on prosthetic vision (Noe,
when available, affect the character of per- 2004; Mandik, 1999). Bach-y-Rita developed
ceptual experiences. N o w , to avoid trivial- an apparatus that converts visual informa-
ity, this hypothesis cannot just be a causal tion (acquired from video cameras affixed
claim. As noted, everyone can agree that to a pair of eyeglasses) into tactile informa-
motor responses can causally affect percep- tion by pressing tiny pins configured in the
tual responses. To advance a substantive same pattern as the visual signal into the
proposal, enactive theorists might defend torso or tongue. People who wear this appa-
a version of the constitution thesis. They ratus come to report that the tactile inputs
might claim that when motor responses are have visual significance. For example, they
available, they are constituent parts of per- can use the tactile inputs to avoid loom-
ceptual experiences. When we see some- ing objects, grasp, and navigate between
thing, on this proposal, the conscious visual obstacles. On the enactive interpretation,
experience is partially constituted by the the tactile information has come to have
fact that we are registering sensorimotor the motor contingencies normally associated
contingences. Put differently, the enactive with vision, and that results in the tactile
theorists might say that the phenomenal sensations actually feeling as if they were
character of perceptual states is comprised visual (see also Dennett, 1991). In this way,
in part by the motor consequences of those sight can be restored to the blind.
states. I am not persuaded by these lines of evi-
This thesis is usually taken to have two dence for the enactive view. First consider
implications. T h e first has to do with distin- the claim that we distinguish different qual-
guishing phenomenal experiences within a ities within a sense modality by distinguish-
single sense modality. Enactive theorists sug- ing sensorimotor contingencies. That seems
gest that t w o different experiences within intuitively wrong. If you see a stick in the
the same modality differ in virtue of being water, it looks curved, but if you know it is
associated with different motor responses. a stick, you know that you can grasp it the
For example, the experience of seeing a same way you would grasp a straight object.
curved line and a straight line afford differ- Sticks in the water and out of the water look
ent kinds of grasping, and, more controver- different, but they afford the same actions.
sially, the experience of two colors affords The color case is even less plausible for the
different movement of the eyes and pupil enactive view than the shape case. Suppose
aperture. N o e (2004) argues for the latter you compare the experience of staring at
thesis by suggesting that color constancy - two uniformly colored and uniformly bright
our capacity to recognize a color as the same fields, one red and the other blue. It is obvi-
under very different luminance conditions - ous that these look different but unlikely
might be achieved by keeping track of the that they afford different eye movements.
ocular affordances that each hue has under Of course red and blue may afford different
multiple conditions. eye movements under other conditions, but
that fact is irrelevant; the colors look dif-
The second implication of the enactive
ferent here and now. Conversely, imagine
constitution view has to do with our capac-
staring at a giant field of red first with your
ity to distinguish different senses (Noe, 2004;
eyes to the left, and then to the right. Under
Hurley & Noe, 2003). T h e proposal implies
these two conditions, the red looks the same,
that vision and hearing, for example, are


4*° jesse prinz

but the sensorimotor contingencies differ; in lier, 1 also raised doubts about the situated
one case you are able to shift gaze back to the approach. Those w h o have been tempted by
right, and in the other you are able to shift these views tend to be radical. Some of them
gaze back to the left. Differences in senso- entertain the view that consciousness does
rimotor contingencies are neither necessary not reside entirely inside the head. Some
nor sufficient for differences in perceptual argue that conscious experience could not
qualities. occur in the senses without the activation of
The same conclusion follows for distin- motor representations. Some maintain that
guishing between modalities. Enactive the- motor representations are constituent parts
orists would have us believe that people of our sensory experiences and an essen-
using the prosthetic vision device experi-
tial contributor to ordinary perceptual qual-
ence visual qualities. That does not seem to
ities, such as color experiences. These views
be the case. Instead, they just learn to use
are exciting, to be sure, but they do not
tactile properties as a distance sense. Over
enjoy much empirical support. We should
time, they may stop focusing on the surface
resist gratuitous radicalism. But that does
of their bodies and direct attention outward,
not mean we should reject embodied and
but they are not having visual experiences.
The blind do not suddenly see. Touch func- situated approaches entirely. There may be
tions like vision in this case, but it does not aspects of conscious experience that will
feel like vision. By comparison, imagine feel- ultimately be explained by appeal to our
ing the surface of a street using a walking nature as embodied and embedded agents.
stick. Like Bach-y-Rita's device, this turns Some authors have been developing theo-
touch into a distance sense, but it does not ries of perception that emphasize the influ-
result in a visual experience. Seeing a street ence of action systems without arguing for
and feeling it with a cane are phenome- strong forms of dependency (e.g., Findley
nally different. Indeed, there are many cases & Gilchrist, 2003; Matthen, 2005). I will not
in day-to-day life where different senses review this literature, but I will indicate four
afford the same behavioral responses. Com- avenues for future exploration.
pare hearing something to the left and see- The first possibility that I want to con-
ing something on the left. Both cases afford sider is that embodiment contributes to
head shifting and alternations in auditory self-consciousness (see Bermudez, Marcel,
and visual attention. When we see some- & Eilan, 1995; Boyer, Robbins, & Jack, 2005;
thing on the left, we look and listen; and Gallagher, 2005; Jeannerod & Pacherie, 2004;
when we hear something on the left, we do Roessler & Eilan, 2003). There is a notion
the same. Despite these similarities in sen- of the self that is bodily in nature. On one
sorimotor contingencies, the experience of use of first-person concepts, I am my body.
seeing is qualitatively different from that of If you kick my body, you are kicking me.
hearing. The enactive account of how we To have a conscious experience of the self
distinguish between the senses seems to be includes awareness of the body. It includes
false. It is also unnecessary. There are plenty awareness of actions, posture, and the inter-
of differences in how our perceptual sys- nal patterns of bodily changes that we expe-
tems represent the world; they use different rience as emotions and moods. Arguably, a
rules and representations. There is no need person lacking experience of a body would
to appeal to motor processes to explain how lack an important kind of self-consciousness.
we differentiate the senses. Such a person w o u l d experience the exter-
nal world, but not a self. Of course, such a
person could observe her own body through
vision, but that would be like observing the
4. Moderate Embodiment
body of another person; it would not be
an experience of the body as a self. Such
I have been raising doubts about the enac-
a person would experience the world from a
tive approach to conscious experience. Ear-
specific vantage point, of course; the senses
IS C O N S C I O U S NESS EMBODIED? •I-O

deliver information from a perspective. But neously, it is not as if I had two separate
perspectival does not entail personal. By streams of consciousness, like the two hemi-
analogy, a movie camera captures the world spheres in a split-brain patient. Both sensory
from a point of view, but that does not streams are part of a single coherent expe-
imbue the camera's image with a self-like rience. What allows for such phenomenal
quality. Cameras provide a view from some- unity?
where, not necessarily a view from someone.
Without body experiences, perception and One popular answer is that the modali-
perceptual memories might feel like self-less ties are bound together by some neural pro-
sequences of film. cess; perhaps they fire at the same rate (e.g.,
Crick & Koch, 1990; Singer & Gray, 1995).
The second possibility builds on the first. The physiological evidence for neural syn-
If perception of the body constitutes a form chrony theories of binding is not very strong
of self-consciousness, then it is also plausi- (Reilly, Busby, & Soto, 2003), but let's sup-
ble that experiences of the body contribute pose that bound experiences do fire at the
to the sense of ownership that inheres in same rate. Would that explain the unity of
ordinary perceptual experience. When I per- experience? Decidedly not. After all, cells
ceive the world, the perceptual experiences in your brain may fire at the same rate as
that I have seem to be mine. Experiences cells in my brain, but there is no unified
have a subject. One tempting explanation consciousness encompassing our two heads.
is that the experience of ownership comes Simultaneous firing is, at best, a computa-
from the fact that my experiences occur in tional marker that allows a system to inte-
my body and I can initiate and experience grate experiences in some other way (for
bodily responses to what I perceive. If an other objections, see LaRock, 2006). Perhaps
object looms towards me, I duck. Such sen- embodiment holds the key.
sorimotor contingencies may link percep- Here is a highly speculative proposal. Per-
tion of the external world to perceptions of haps I experience unity in my senses because
the embodied self in a way that makes the they are all available to a common locus of
embodied self feel like a subject of expe- agency. Perhaps unity consists in my capac-
rience. The phenomenology of ownership ity to act on information in each of my
may consist in my felt reactions to the world senses. Notice that the two streams of con-
I perceive. sciousness in a person with a split brain
These two proposals leave various issues both contribute to control of the same body,
unsettled. Can one have a conscious expe- but they are not available to a common
rience of oneself and of ownership without locus of agency. The information process-
bodily experiences? Does the bodily com- ing resources that use inputs from the right
ponent of self-consciousness involve both hemisphere to select behavioral responses
the experience of motor responses and the left cannot avad themselves of inputs from the
hemisphere, and conversely. Thus, there
perception of bodily changes (motor and is no transhemispheric unity in the split-
somatic components), or is just one of these brain patient. For the rest of us, inputs from
components enough? These are questions both hemispheres are unified, and that unity
for future research. may derive from the fact that both hemi-
I want to move now to a third pos- spheres feed to the same action control cen-
sible role for embodiment in conscious ters. Unity across the senses may work in the
experience. Sense modalities are indepen- same way. This is certainly an avenue worth
dent from each other; they process differ- exploring.
ent information, have different phenomenal
Let me turn now to a fourth and final
qualities, are vulnerable to selective deficits, avenue
and reside in different parts of the brain. most vexing for future research. One of the
Despite this profound division between the ies concerns the questions in consciousness stud-
senses, conscious episodes seem unified. What purpose does function of consciousness.
When I experience sight and sound simulta- consciousness serve? I
jesse prinz

suspect that there is no special function alike. In 1987, Jackendoff took this theory
of consciousness as such; an unconscious of perception as a point of departure and
creature could do what we do. But there asked, Where in the hierarchy does con-
is undoubtedly a particular functional role sciousness arise? T h e obvious answer is that
played by the mental states that happen to conscious arises at the intermediate level
be conscious in us. To identify that role, We see whole objects, not constellations of
we can first determine which of our mental edges, and we see them from a particular
states are conscious and then see whether point of view. We hear words and melodies
those states make any distinctive contribu-
not isolated tones, and we hear their specific
tion to information processing. Toward this
acoustic properties, rather than categorical
end, I will briefly sketch a theory of con-
invariants.
I think Jackendoff is right about where
sciousness that I have defended more fully
in information processing consciousness is
elsewhere (Prinz, 2000b, 2005, forthcoming).
located, but his theory of consciousness is
The theory begins with a question about incomplete in a crucial respect. Mere activa-
the locus of consciousness. Perceptual sys- tion of an intermediate-level representation
tems have many components, and these are is not sufficient for consciousness. After all
organized hierarchically. Marr (1982) pre- we can perceive things subliminally. Con-
sented a general theory of how these hier- sciousness requires something more. I think
archies are organized, which is still widely the missing ingredient is attention. When
accepted today; Marr got details wrong, but attention systems are damaged, as in cases of
he correctly distinguished three levels of unilateral neglect, consciousness of the unat-
perceptual processing. Low-level perception tended regions is lost (Bisiach, 1992). This
extracts the local features that impinge on suggests that attention is necessary for con-
the surfaces of our sensory receptors. Typi- sciousness. Cases of subliminal perception
cally, these features are sampled piecemeal may be explained by supposing that sub-
and not bound into unified spatiotempo- liminal stimuli are presented too quickly to
ral wholes. Low-level vision delivers a con- become objects of attention.
stellation of edges, and low-level audition
To directly test whether attention is nec-
gives us individual tones. At an interme-
essary for consciousness, researchers give
diate level these parts are bound together
subjects tasks that demand a lot of atten-
into more coherent representations. Edges
tion, and they see what effect this has on
become shapes and tones become melodies
consciousness. For example, Mack and Rock
or word sounds. High-level perception pro-
(1998) asked subjects to determine which
duces categorical representations by extract-
of the two lines comprising a crosshair was
ing invariants from the intermediate level.
longer. This is difficult to do, and while sub-
An intermediate-level visual representation
jects were intensely examining the crosshair,
of a cow will present it from a particu-
they briefly flashed a word, a face, or a
lar vantage point; it will be a bound con-
geometrical shape. Many subjects failed to
tour assembled from the edges detected at
notice the flashed object. Attention pre-
the low level. High-level visual representa-
tions extract away from the vantage point vented them f r o m seeing. Most, Scholl,
and produce a representation of the basic Clifford, and Simons (2005) have shown
form of a cow that remains constant across that subjects can fail to notice an object
a wide range of viewing positions. Marr calls that slowly moves across the center of a
this a structural description. In audition, cat- computer screen if they are attending to
egorical representation may abstract away movements of other objects on the screen.
from specific acoustic properties. For exam- This phenomenon is called "inattentional
ple, if two people say the word cow there blindness." It differs f r o m change blind-
will be differences in the sound captured at ness because in cases of change blindness
the intermediate level, but the high level we probably do experience the stimuli pre-
may treat the two sounds as if they were sented to us in rich detail, we just fail to keep
is c o n s c i o u s n e s s embodied? 433

track of h o w those stimuli change f r o m one for representations that are v i e w p o i n t spe-
m o m e n t to t h e n e x t . In inattentional blind- cific?
ness, we do not e x p e r i e n c e t h e unattended T h e natural answer to this question is
stimuli. Indeed, w h e n attention is very nar- that viewpoint-specific representations are
rowly f o c u s e d , t h e visual field loses m u c h e x t r e m e l y valuable for making decisions
of its richness, as if it contained only those about action. S u p p o s e y o u encounter a b e a r
objects that are currently being attended. while hiking through the w o o d s . Y o u n e e d
Ordinary we are not engaged in tasks that to m a k e a quick decision about w h a t to
require highly f o c u s e d attention, so we allo- do. To make that decision, it is e x t r e m e l y
cate attention resources d i f f u s e l y over the important to k n o w several facts: Is the b e a r
space in f r o n t of us, allowing us to experi- facing y o u or facing away? Is it close to
ence m a n y things simultaneously. O n e can y o u or in the distance? Is it staring at
think of t h e visual field as a p h e n o m e n a l l y y o u or looking elsewhere? T h e s e questions
varied landscape, w i t h s o m e things vividly can be answered by consulting visual infor-
present in consciousness, other things less mation that is encoded at the intermedi-
vivid, and still others not consciously pro- ate level, b u t probably not encoded at the
cessed at all. T h i s variation seems to be high level, which abstracts away f r o m such
determined by t h e varied allocation of atten- details of vantage point. T h e best explana-
tion. T h e s e observations suggest that con- tion f o r w h y working m e m o r y gains access
sciousness arises only w h e n we attend, and to intermediate-level representations is that
t o the e x t e n t w e attend. C o m b i n e d w i t h those representations are privileged with
J a c k e n d o f P s hypothesis, w e e n d u p w i t h respect to deciding h o w to act.
what I call the A I R theory: conscious states L o w - l e v e l representations are too frag-
are A t t e n d e d Intermediate-level Represen- m e n t e d to be especially useful for decision-
tations. making; in responding to the bear, we have
T h e A I R theory allows us to address to see it as a coherent object, not as a dis-
the question of f u n c t i o n . First, we can ask, connected group of edges. High-level repre-
what p u r p o s e do intermediate-level repre- sentations can be useful for decision making,
sentations serve? O b v i o u s l y , they allow us but they facilitate decisions that are differ-
to derive high-level representations. N o t e ,
ent in kind f r o m the decisions that d e p e n d
however, that they serve this purpose even
on the intermediate level. If y o u encounter a
when they arise unconsciously. To under-
bear, it is important to k n o w it is a bear; if it
stand w h a t f u n c t i o n consciousness serves,
w e r e a bush or a pony or your uncle Charlie,
we need to ask w h y intermediate-level rep-
then there w o u l d be no need to flee. High-
resentations e v e r b e c o m e targets of atten-
tion. T h i s question can be addressed by level representations are p r e s u m e d to be the
reflecting on h o w attention works. A t t e n - primary tools f o r making such categorical
tion is essentially a tool for directing infor- judgments. It is at the high level, then, that
mation access. W h e n w e attend, perceptual we establish category-related goals. If y o u
information gains access to working m e m - see a bear, your goal might be to get a w a y
ory. T h e t e r m working memory refers to sys- f r o m it s o m e h o w . But that is an end, not a
tems that store information f o r a brief period means. Y o u cannot decide h o w to achieve
of time. W o r k i n g m e m o r y is not a passive y o u r goal without knowing h o w y o u are sit-
storehouse, h o w e v e r . As the n a m e implies, uated. If the bear is close by, looking at
working m e m o r y works. It is w h e r e we m a k e you, and approaching f r o m the right, then
decisions (as o p p o s e d to responding auto- y o u should flee to the left. If the bear is
matically). So the question of w h a t con-
far off or facing another direction, then y o u
sciousness is f o r boils d o w n to the question
should freeze. V i e w p o i n t - s p e c i f i c i n f o r m a -
of w h y intermediate-level representations
tion is needed to determine h o w y o u r goal
become available f o r decision making. W h y
can best be realized; it is information that
do the centers of decision have special need
provides a means to the end. It is in that
respect that the intermediate level is tightly
jesse prinz

linked t o a c t i o n . I f y o u h a v e t o d e c i d e w h a t s a m e d i r e c t i o n . I f t h e s e f o r e c a s t s are right


t o d o w i t h y o u r body, r a t h e r t h a n just w h e r e a c o m p l e t e t h e o r y of c o n s c i o u s n e s s will be
y o u w a n t t o e n d up, t h e n t h e i n t e r m e d i a t e an e m b o d i e d t h e o r y , in a m o d e r a t e sense
l e v e l b e c o m e s crucial. o f t h e t e r m . A c o m p l e t e t h e o r y will impli-
I will n o t d e v e l o p this r o u g h p r o p o s a l c a t e s y s t e m s t h a t a r e i n v o l v e d i n represent-
h e r e . I m e n t i o n it to suggest t h a t c o n s c i o u s - ing a n d c o n t r o l l i n g t h e b o d y . T h e contribu-
ness a n d a c t i o n m i g h t b e closely r e l a t e d a f t e r t i o n s of t h e s e s y s t e m s are, I suspect, highly
all. If I am right, c o n s c i o u s n e s s arises w h e n significant. T h e y g i v e us a s e n s e of agency,
decision c e n t e r s gain a c c e s s t o t h e r e p r e s e n - o w n e r s h i p , a n d u n i t y . T h e s e a r e pervasive
t a t i o n s t h a t a r e especially useful f o r d e c i d i n g a s p e c t s o f c o n s c i o u s e x p e r i e n c e . Moreover
h o w to act. Consciousness m a y not require t h e m e c h a n i s m s t h a t g i v e r i s e t o conscious-
m o t o r responses, b u t i t w o r k s i n t h e ser- ness m a y h a v e e v o l v e d i n t h e service o f
v i c e of s u c h responses. T h i s is a m o r a l v i c - a c t i o n . If so, c o n s c i o u s n e s s is n o t a b o u t sens-
t o r y for t h e e n a c t i v e a p p r o a c h , e v e n i f m a n y ing; w e c a n d o t h a t w i t h o u t consciousness.
authors currently exploring t h e relationship N o r is c o n s c i o u s n e s s a b o u t m a k i n g life more
b e t w e e n consciousness and action are h o p - p l e a s a n t o r m o r e m i s e r a b l e ; t h e s e are just
ing to identify a m o r e i n t i m a t e link. T h o s e side e f f e c t s . R a t h e r c o n s c i o u s n e s s is about
authors want action to be s o m e h o w c o n - a c t i n g - it e m e r g e s t h r o u g h processes that
stitutive of consciousness. I w a n t t o sug- m a k e t h e w o r l d a v a i l a b l e t o t h o s e systems
gest t h a t c o n s c i o u s n e s s is a p r e c o n d i t i o n for t h a t a l l o w u s t o s e l e c t b e h a v i o r a l means t o
d e c i d i n g h o w t o act, a n d t h e r e p r e s e n t a t i o n s o u r e n d s . In r e s i s t i n g r a d i c a l situated and
t h a t b e c o m e c o n s c i o u s a r e ideally s u i t e d for e m b o d i e d t h e o r i e s , w e m u s t n o t lose sight
this p u r p o s e . It is a c e n t r a l f u n c t i o n of c o n - o f this f u n d a m e n t a l f a c t .
sciousness t o p r o v i d e a c t i o n s y s t e m s w i t h
t h e information needed to make real-time
decisions. Acknowledgments

Philip R o b b i n s and W a y n e Wright each gave


5. Conclusions
me c o m m e n t s on an earlier draft of this chap-
ter. T h e i r editorial corrections, bibliographical
Situated and embodied approaches have a guidance, t h o u g h t f u l suggestions, and challeng-
t e n d e n c y t o drift t o w a r d e x c e s s i v e radical- ing questions l e d to n u m e r o u s improvements
ism. P r a c t i t i o n e r s a r g u e t h a t o r t h o d o x c o n - throughout. I am e x t r e m e l y grateful.
c e p t i o n s o f t h e m i n d will b e c o m p l e t e l y
u n d e r m i n e d o n c e w e r e c o g n i z e a p l a c e for
b o d y a n d w o r l d i n m e n t a l life. I t h i n k w e References
s h o u l d resist s u c h e x t r e m e s . I n issuing t h a t
w a r n i n g , t h e b u l k o f this discussion has b e e n Bach-y-Rita, P. (1972). Brain mechanisms in sen-
critical, b u t t h a t w a s n o t m y u l t i m a t e p u r - sory substitution. N e w Y o r k : Academic Press.
pose. I think the situated and e m b o d i e d B e r m u d e z , J . , M a r c e l , A . , & Eilan, N. (Eds.).
a p p r o a c h h a s m u c h t o offer. R a t h e r t h a n (1995). The body and the self. Cambridge, MA:
focus on d e b u n k i n g o r d e f e n d i n g radical M I T Press.
claims, we should look for t h e ways in which Bisiach, E. (1992). U n d e r s t a n d i n g consciousness:
a n e m b o d i e d o r i e n t a t i o n c a n lead t o g e n u i n e C l u e s f r o m unilateral neglect and related dis-
orders. In A. D. M i l n e r & M. D. Rugg (Eds.),
insights a b o u t t h e n a t u r e o f c o n s c i o u s n e s s .
The neuropsychology of consciousness (pp. 113-
I t h i n k this a p p r o a c h is leading to e x c i t i n g
139). L o n d o n : A c a d e m i c Press.
and promising views which might have been
Block, N. (2005). R e v i e w of A l v a Noe's Action in
n e g l e c t e d o t h e r w i s e . R e c e n t w o r k o n self-
Perception. Journal of Philosophy, 102, 259-272.
c o n s c i o u s n e s s has f o c u s e d o n a w a r e n e s s o f
Boyer, P., R o b b i n s , P., & J a c k , A. (1995). Varie-
t h e acting body, and work on t h e unity and ties of self-systems w o r t h having. Conscious-
function of consciousness m a y m o v e in t h e ness and Cognition, 14, 647-660.
IS CONSCIOUSNESS EMBODIED? 435

Brooks, R. A. (1991). Intelligence without repre- Kandell, E. R., Schwartz, J. H., & Jessel, T. M.
sentation. Artificial Intelligence, 47, 139-159. (2000). Principles of neural science (4th ed.).
Cassel, G. H„ Billig, M. D„ & Randall, H. G. New York: McGraw-Hill.
(1998). The eye book: A complete guide to eye Koch, C. (2004). The quest for consciousness:
disorders and health. Baltimore: Johns Hop- A neurobiological approach. Denver, CO:
kins University Press. Roberts.
Cotterill, R. (1998). Enchanted looms: Conscious Land, M. F., Furneaux, S. M., & Gilchrist, I. D.
networks in brains and computers. Cambridge: (2002). The organization of visually mediated
Cambridge University Press. actions in a subject without eye movements.
Crick, F., & Koch, C. (1990). Towards a neurobi- Neurocase, 8, 80-87.
ological theory of consciousness. Seminars in LaRock, E. (2006). Why neural synchrony fails
Neurosciences, 2, 263—275. to explain the unity of visual consciousness.
Dennett, D. (1969). Content and consciousness. Behavior and Philosophy, 34, 39-58.
London: Routledge 8l Kegan Paul. Lycan, W. (1996). Consciousness and experience.
Dennett, D. (1991}. Consciousness explained. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Boston: Little, Brown. Mack, A., & Rock, I. (1998). Inattentional blind-
Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. Cam- ness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
bridge, MA: MIT Press. Mandik, P. (1999). Qualia, space, and control.
Feynman, R. (1997). Surely you're joking, Mr. Philosophical Psychology, 12, 47-60.
Feynman! Adventures of a curious character. Marr, D. (1982). Vision: A computational investi-
New York: W. W. Norton. gation into the human representation and pro-
Findlay, J. M., 8l Gilchrist, I. D. (2003). Active cessing of visual information. New York; W. H.
vision. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Freeman.
Fodor, J. A. (1994). The elm and the expert: Men- Matthen, M. (2005). Seeing, doing, and knowing.
talese and its semantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT New York: Oxford University Press.
Press. McGurk, H., & MacDonald, J. (1976). Hear-
Gallagher, S. [2005). How the body shapes ing lips and seeing voices. Nature, 264, 746-
the mind. New York: Oxford University 748.
Press. Metzinger, T. (Ed.). (2000). Neural correlates of
Glenberg, A. M., & Kaschak, M. P. (2003). The consciousness: Empirical and conceptual ques-
body's contribution to language. In B. Ross tions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
(Ed.), The psychology of learning and motivation Milner, D., & Goodale, M. (1995). The visual brain
(Vol. 43, pp. 93-126). New York: Academic in action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Press. Mitroff, S. R., Simons, D. J., & Levin, D. T.
Held, R., & Hein, A. (1963). Movement-produced (2004). Nothing compares two views: Change
stimulation in the development of visually blindness can occur despite preserved access
guided behavior. Journal of Comparative and to the changed information. Perception S6 Psy-
Physiological Psychology, 56, 872-876. chophysics, 66, 1268-1281.
Hurley, S. (1998). Consciousness in action. Cam- Moran, J., & Desimone, R. (1985). Selective atten-
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press. tion gates visual processing in the extrastriate
Hurley, S., & Noe, A. (2003). Neural plasticity cortex. Science, 229, 782-784.
and consciousness. Biology and Philosophy, 18, Most, S. B., Scholl, B. J., Clifford, E., & Simons,
131-168. D.J. (2005). What you see is what you set: Sus-
Jackendoff, R. (1987). Consciousness and the tained inattentional blindness and the capture
computational mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT of awareness. Psychological Review, 112,217-242.
Press. Noe, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge,
Jack, A., & Prinz, J. (2003). Searching for a scien- MA: MIT Press.
tific experience. Journal of Consciousness Stud- Noe, A., & Thompson, E. (2004). Are there neu-
ies, it, 51—56. ral correlates of consciousness? Journal of Con-
James, W. (1904). Does "consciousness" exist? sciousness Studies, 11, 3-28.
Journal of Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific O'Regan, J. K, & Noe, A. (2001). A sensorimo-
Methods, 1, 477-491. tor account of vision and visual consciousness.
Jeannerod, M., & Pacherie, E. (2004). Agency, Behavioural and Brain Sciences, 24(5), 939-1011.
simulation and self-identification. Mind & Prinz, J. (2000a). The ins and outs of conscious-
Language, 19, 113-146. ness. Brain and Mind, 2, 245-256.
jesse prinz

Ptinz, J. (iooob). A neurofunctiona! theory of tion (pp. 168-192). Oxford: Oxford University
visual consciousness. Consciousness and Cog- Press.
nition, 9, 243-259. Rivière, J., & Lécuyer, R. (2002). Spatial cognition
Print, J. (2002) Furnishing the mind: Concepts and in young children with spinal muscular atro-
their perceptual basis. Cambridge, MA: MIT phy. Developmental Neuropsychology, 21, 273-
Press. 283.
Prinz, J. (2005). A neurofunctional theory of con- Roessler, J., 8c Eilan, N. (Eds.). (2003). Agency
sciousness. In A. Brook & K. Akins (Eds.), Cog- and self-awareness. Oxford: Oxford University
nition and the brain: The philosophy and neu- Press.
rosaence movement (pp. 381-396). Cambridge: Silverman, M., 8c Mack, A. (2001). Priming from
Cambridge University Press. change blindness [Abstract]. Journal of Vision
Prinz. J. (2006). Putting the brakes on enac- 1,13a.
tive perception. PSYCHE, 12(1). Retrieved Simons, D. J., & Levin, D. T. (1997). Change
June 13, 2008, from http://psyche.cs.monash. blindness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 1, 261-
edu .au/symposia/noe/Prinz.pdf 267.
Prinz, J. (forthcoming). The conscious brain. New Singer, W., 8c Gray, C. (1995). Visual feature inte-
York: Oxford University Press. gration and the temporal correlation hypothe-
Prinz, J., & Barsalou, L. (2000). Perceptual sym- sis. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 18, 555-586.
bols and dynamic systems. In A. Markman & Thompson, E., 8c Varela, F. (2001). Radical
E. Dietrich (Eds.), Cognitive dynamics. Dor- embodiment: Neural dynamics and conscious-
drecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer. ness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5, 418-425.
Reffly, R., Busby, R., & Soto, R. (2003). Three Tye, M. (1995). Ten problems of consciousness.
forms of binding and their neural sub- Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
strates: Alternatives to temporal synchrony. Wilson, R. (2004). Boundaries of the mind: The
In A. Cleeremans (Ed.), The unity of con- individual in the fragile sciences. Cambridge:
sciousness: Binding, integration, and dissocia- Cambridge University Press.
CHAPTER 23

Emotions in the Wild

The Situated Perspective on Emotion

Paul Griffiths and Andrea Scarantino

x. Introduction tions (Prinz, 2004a), his contribution does


not emphasize the role of the environment,
Many theoretical traditions have contrib- assimilating emoting to perceiving actual or
uted to the scientific elucidation of emotion, as-if changes of one's own body (Damasio,
but philosophers facing the question, W h a t 1999). In a further parallel with traditional
is an emotion? h a v e concentrated on t w o views of cognition, both cognitivists and
of these in particular. 1 Philosophical cog- neo-Jamesians focus on the contributions
nitivism is inspired by the appraisal tradi- that emotions make to the organism's inter-
tion in p s y c h o l o g y (e.g., Arnold, i960, 1970; nal psychological economy. T h e primary
Scherer, 1999), T h e alternative neo-Jamesian function of emotions, on both accounts, is
approach is inspired by the somatic marker to provide the organism's decision-making
hypothesis in a f f e c t i v e neuroscience ( D a m a - systems with information about the signifi-
sio, 1996; Panksepp, 1998). Cognitivists iden- cance of a stimulus situation.
tify emotions w i t h representations of the This chapter describes a very different
stimulus situation, or evaluative judgments perspective on emotion, according to w h i c h
(Solomon, 1976, 1993). Neo-Jamesians iden- emotions are the following:
tify emotions w i t h states of bodily arousal,
which are detected by the brain as affect 1. Designed to function in a social context:
(Prinz, 2004b). Both these views of emo- an emotion is often an act of relationship
tion parallel t h e v i e w of cognition that has reconfiguration brought about by deliv-
been called into question by situated cog- ering a social signal;
nition research (Smith, 1999; Clark, 1997). 2. Forms of skillful engagement w i t h t h e
In both theories, emotions are conceived world that need not be mediated by con-
as internal states or processes and the role ceptual thought;
of the e n v i r o n m e n t is confined to pro- 3. Scaffolded by the environment, b o t h
viding stimuli and receiving actions. Thus, synchronically, in the unfolding of a
although Prinz advocates embodied e m o - particular emotional p e r f o r m a n c e , a n d

437
paul g r i f f i t h s a n d a n d r e a s c a r a n t i n o

diachronicallv, in the acquisition of an appraisal, the organism receives information


emotional repertoire; from the environment and uses it to deter-
4. Dynamically coupled to an environ- mine the emotional significance of the sit-
ment that both influences and is influ- uation that confronts it. In contrast, the
enced by the unfolding of the emotion. situated perspective envisages organisms
probing their environment through initial
We draw heavily on transactional accounts emotional responses and monitoring the
of emotion proposed by some contemporary responses of other organisms to determine
psychologists (Fridlund, 1994; Parkinson, how the emotion will evolve (see section 5).
1995; Parkinson, Fischer, & Manstead, 2005;
Russell & Fernandez-Dols, 1997). Although
these authors do not, to our knowledge, con- 2. Social Situatedness
ceive of their work as a contribution to the
situationist literature that is the focus of A situated perspective on the mind recog-
this volume, we contend that their propos- nizes that it is designed to function in an
als constitute a fairly exact, affective paral- environmental context and that aspects of
lel to situationist ideas about cognition. The the environment m a y be causal components
primary aim of this chapter is to demon- of mental mechanisms (Clark & Chalmers,
strate that a situated approach to emotion 1998). Research on situated cognition has
already exists and is backed by a substantial often emphasized the reliable physical prop-
experimental literature. This body of theory erties of the environment, properties that
and data could make a major contribution can be exploited to reduce cognitive load. In
to fleshing out the general situationist per- contrast, a situated perspective on emotion
spective on the mind. emphasizes the role of social context in the
We emphasize that adopting the situa- production and management of an emotion,
tionist perspective does not require deny- and the reciprocal influence of emotion on
ing the results produced by other theoret- the evolving social context. Behaviors that
ical traditions in psychology, such as the have traditionally been viewed as involun-
affect-program tradition, or even the heuris- tary expressions of the organism's psycho-
tic value of alternative theoretical perspec- logical state are instead viewed as signals
tives. Instead, the situated perspective shifts designed to influence the behavior of other
our theoretical focus to neglected phenom- organisms, or as strategic moves in an ongo-
ena and questions. The situated approach ing transaction between organisms. 2
to emotion is at its most compelling when One of the most important experimen-
applied to exemplars like anger in a marital tal paradigms for a situated perspective on
quarrel or embarrassment while delivering emotion is the study of audience effects -
a song to an audience. These are cases in differences in emotional response to a con-
which the emotion has a temporal course stant stimulus which reflect differences in
of development and involves an ongoing the expected recipient(s) of the emotion.
exchange of emotional signals (e.g., facial Among the most dramatic effects are those
actions, tones of voice). This switch in the obtained for the production of the so-called
focus of emotion theory parallels the way in Duchenne smile - the pattern of move-
which situated cognition research switches ment of mouth and eyes generally accepted
the focus of cognitive science from exem- as a pancultural expression of happiness
plars like theorem proving to engaged, real- (Ekman, 1972). Ten-pin bowlers are presum-
time exemplars like navigation in a cluttered
ably happiest w h e n they make a full strike
environment.
and less happy w h e n they knock down a
Finally, the situated perspective on emo- few pins. H o w e v e r , bowlers rarely smile
tion has some points in common with active- after making a full strike when facing away
vision accounts of situated perception (Noe, from their bowling companions and smile
2004). In traditional models of emotional very often after knocking down a few pins
e m o t i o n s i n t h e wii.d 439

when they face their companions (Kraut & a valuable morsel of food, but only if there
Johnston, 1979)- Spanish soccer fans show are female chickens in the vicinity (Marler &
a similar pattern in their facial response Evans, 1997). There is, presumably, no point
to goals and issue Duchenne smiles only in demonstrating foraging ability to other
when facing one another (Fernandez-Dols males! Results like these suggest that the
& Ruiz-Belda, 1997). Fernandez-Dols and social situatedness of emotion is not a spe-
Ruiz-Belda also demonstrate that at the 1992 cial human achievement mediated by con-
Barcelona Olympics, although gold medal- ceptual thought but a fundamental aspect of
ists produced many signs of emotion dur- emotion (see section 3).
ing the medal ceremony, they produced Socially situated emotions have a strate-
Duchenne smiles almost exclusively when gic aspect neglected in cognitivist and neo-
interacting with the audience and officials. Jamesian accounts of emotion. Emotions
These results suggest that smiles are not have been seen as more or less accurate
outpourings of happiness that are merely responses to how things are, but they are
witnessed by other people but affiliative ges- also, and perhaps primarily, more or less
tures made by one person to another with effective goal-oriented responses. For exam-
respect to something good that has occurred. ple, one study in which people were asked
This fits the model of emotions as strategic to describe situations in which they had
moves in the context of a social transaction. become angry found that the prospect of
Obviously, people do smile and produce obtaining compensation is a significant fac-
other classical emotional expressions when tor determining whether a loss elicits anger
they are alone, but studies suggest that they or sadness (Stein, Trabasso, & Li wag, 1993).
do so far less often than one might expect. This is puzzling if anger is merely a response
Even such apparently reflexive displays as to having been wronged, but makes good
facial expressions produced in response to sense if anger is a strategy to obtain restitu-
tastes and smells appear to be facilitated by tion.
an appropriate social setting, and the same
Embarrassment is an emotion that wears
appears to be the case for pain expressions
its social situatedness on its face, as most
(Russell, Bachorowski, & Fernandez-Dols,
theories of embarrassment acknowledge
2003). Furthermore, it would be a mistake
(Parkinson et al., 2005, pp. 188-192). The
to conclude that audience effects are absent
finding that observers evaluate people who
when a physical audience is absent. Solitary
behave in a socially inappropriate manner
subjects who mentally picture taking part
more favorably if they show embarrassment
in a social interaction produce more emo-
suggests that one function of embarrassment
tional facial signals than subjects who focus
may be to indicate knowledge of a violated
on the emotional stimulus without an imag-
norm and acceptance of its validity (for more
ined audience. Fridlund (1994; Fridlund et
on embarrassment elicitors, see section 3).
al., 1990) has described this as implicit social-
In a study in which subjects were asked
ity and remarked that his experimental sub-
to record a karaoke-style performance of
jects display to the audience in their heads.
a notoriously embarrassing love song, the
The sensitivity to social context mani- singer's subsequent level of embarrassment
fested in audience effects can be imple- was reduced if he or she was given rea-
mented by very simple mental mechanisms, son to believe that the experimenter knew
as is evident from the prevalence of audi- the subject was embarrassed by the per-
ence effects in animals. This is important formance (Leary, Landel, & Patton, 1996).
because it helps to explain how the emo- The authors take this result to suggest that
tions can be produced strategically with- embarrassment functioned as a signal: the
out becoming mere pretences of emotion singer needed to convey to the audience that
(see also Griffiths, 1997, chap. 6; 2004b). he or she had a low opinion of the song, thus
Male Golden Sebright chickens, for exam- confirming the singer's knowledge of, and
ple, make a fuss when they find and consume desire to conform to, community standards.
44° paul g r i f f i t h s a n d a n d r e a s c a r a n t 1 n o

Some emotional behavior simply cries are overlooked when they are assimilated to
out for a transactional analysis. Sulking is the traditional exemplar cases.
normally thought of as a manifestation of
emotion, but traditional theories of emo-
tion do little to illuminate it. This is perhaps 3. N o n c o n c e p t u a l Emotional Content
why there has been so little research on a
phenomenon of such obvious importance to Most situationist literature opposes the idea
human relationship dynamics. Sulking sabo- that the primary medium of cognition is
tages mutually rewarding social transactions conceptual thought. Although not denying
and rejects attempts at reconciliation. Tra- that conceptual thought exists, situationists
ditional appraisal theory can identify sulking see it as only the icing on the cognitive cake.
as a manifestation of anger, but does noth- Other forms of cognition explain most of the
ing to explain the specifics of sulking, which practical abilities of organisms to negotiate
must be handed off to a separate theory of their environments (Smith, 1999; Cussins
emotion management or emotion coping. It 1992). In this section we explore a similar
is also implausible that all (or even most) perspective on emotional content.
people who sulk sincerely judge themselves To be credited with conceptual thought
to have been wronged, so an ancillary theory a creature must fulfill requirements of max-
of self-deceit is needed as well. In contrast, imal inferential promiscuity with respect
viewing an emotion as a strategy of rela- to its thought contents (Hurley, 2003). A
tionship reconfiguration (Parkinson, 1995, p. popular way to state this requirement is
295) provides a compelling perspective on Evans's (1982) generality constraint, accord-
sulking. Sulking is a behavioral strategy for ing to which a mental state qualifies as a
seeking a better deal in a relationship - an "thought that a is F" just in case it is possible
emotional game of chicken in which trans- for the subject to decompose that state into
actions that benefit both parties are rejected recombinable ingredients and form with
until appropriate concessions are obtained. such ingredients mental states of two sorts:
The question confronting an agent deciding states that predicate of "a" any property G
whether to become upset in this way is not the subject can conceive of, and states that
whether they have been slighted simpliciter, predicate F of any object "b" the subject
but whether taking what has happened as can conceive of. T h e ability to entertain the
a slight and withdrawing cooperation will thought "a is F" is therefore "a joint exer-
give them leverage. Once again, this strate- cise of two abilities" (Evans, 1982, p. 104),
gic appraisal of the situation may be realized namely, the ability to have the concept of a
by a relatively simple mental mechanism. particular object "a" and the ability to have
The situated perspective on emotion can the concept of a particular property F. These
be seen as an attempt to refocus discussion abilities underlie the higher-order ability to
on a new set of examples. Rather than taking think productively and systematically, sensu
the meeting between a man and a bear in a Fodor (1975 and elsewhere).
lonely wood as a paradigm of fear, attention Situationists argue that skillful activities
is focused on displays of fear produced by a such as navigating an environment or cook-
child when her caregiver is at hand. Rather ing a meal can be conducted without con-
than taking righteous anger at the injustices ceptual thought in this sense, and that these
of the world to be the paradigm of anger, abilities are at least as important a part
anger is studied in the context of its devel- of cognition as abilities that require con-
opment in a marital confrontation. The aim ceptual thought (Smith, 1999). In a sim-
of this refocusing is twofold: first, to illumi- ilar fashion, the situated perspective on
nate the aspects of emotional life that are emotion views emotions as forms of skill-
arguably most relevant to practical issues of ful engagement with the world and resists
emotion management; second, to reveal the the view that they either are or essentially
social aspects of many other emotions that involve conceptual thought. The ability to
EMOTIONS IN THE WILD 44»

emote is not to be explained in terms of intuitive (monkeys are never really afraid)
prepositional attitudes and their use in prac- but also deprives us of two of the most fruit-
tical and theoretical inferences. Instead, the ful avenues for the study of emotions: com-
contentfulness of emotions emerges from parative animal studies and the exploration
the fact that they enable dexterous inter- of ontogenetic emotional development. It is
actions with the environment. Importantly, also inconsistent with the phenomenon of
when ascribing this form of emotional con- affective primacy (Ohman, 1999), in which
tent to an organism, we are entitled to use emotion systems display some of the prop-
concepts not possessed by the organism hav- erties of a Fodorian module (Fodor, 1983):
ing the emotion, a standard condition for they are fast, mandatory, cognitively impen-
labeling a form of mental content as non- etrable, and have limited central accessi-
conceptual (Bermúdez, 2003).' bility. The case of phobias is exemplary
Although there is no room here to elabo- in this respect, as a phobic can reconcile
rate on the specifics of nonconceptual emo- the conceptual thought that the object of
tional representation, what appears to be their phobia is completely harmless with
crucial is that it is an action-oriented form of utter terror toward it. The traditional cog-
representation (Griffiths, 2004b; Scarantino, nitivist must assimilate phobias either to
2005). Emotional content has a fundamen- inconsistent beliefs or to self-deceit. In the
tally pragmatic dimension, in the sense that case of fear at least, there is good scien-
the environment is represented in terms of tific reason to believe that phobias result
what it affords to the emoter in the way neither from logical error nor from self-
of skillful engagement with it. To get a deceit, but from the neural architecture of
more vivid intuitive grip on this, imagine the emotion system. By means of ingenious
the world-as-perceived (Ümwelt) of an ante- lesion studies, LeDoux (1993) has demon-
lope suddenly confronted by a lion. The strated that fear can be elicited in a reflex-
dominant elements of the antelope's Ümwelt like fashion through a neural low road that
are escape affordances (Scarantino, 2003), as projects along a subcortical pathway directly
all of its cognitive, perceptual, and motoric to the amygdala and bypasses the neocor-
abilities are recruited to discover and exe- tex. Because full-blown conceptual thought
cute an action sequence that evades the is generally assumed to involve the neocor-
predator. This representation of the world tex, this appears to be strong evidence that
in goal-oriented terms is required by the conceptual thought is not essential for fear. 4
urgency of the situation, which demands The biggest hurdle for a situated perspec-
selectively transforming inputs into oppor- tive on emotions is constituted by the so-
tunities for life-saving output rather than called higher cognitive emotions (for skep-
generating a multipurpose representation of ticism about this label, see section 6). Guilt,
the environment. shame, resentment, envy, and embarrass-
A situationist, action-oriented approach ment, for example, seem connected by their
to emotional content is diametrically very definitions to a range of sophisticated
opposed to classic cognitivist theories of conceptual abilities. This perspective is sup-
emotions, which take emotions to be eval- ported by the psychological literature on
uative judgments or combinations of beliefs emotional appraisal. The influential account
and desires (Marks, 1982; Nussbaum, 2001; of Lazarus (1991) suggests that each emo-
Solomon, 1993). Although this approach tion is caused by an appraisal whose con-
may give an accurate account of some forms tent can be captured by a core relational
of sophisticated human emotionality, it falls theme. Guilt is caused by the appraisal that
short as a general theory of emotions. In one has transgressed a moral imperative and
particular, the assumption that conceptual shame by the appraisal that one has failed
thought is essential for emotion prevents us to live up to an ego ideal. These appear
from making sense of emotions in infants to be paradigmatically conceptual thoughts,
and animals. This not only is wildly counter- which demand possession of concepts such
4 4 ° paul g r i f f i t h s a n d a n d r e a s c a r a n t 1 n o

as moral imperative, self, and ideal. Con- When someone we care about accuses us
ventional appraisal theory thus seems to tie even unjustly, a need to repair the relation-
these emotions to conceptual thought. But ship emerges. Guilt is often a good strategy
this not only would imply that emotions like to meet this need, because it conveys a mes-
guilt, shame, and even anger cannot con- sage of sympathetic suffering and the inten-
ceivably occur in children and animals, it tion to avoid future involvement in harmful
would also be inconsistent with the appar- events affecting the accuser.
ent occurrence of emotions such as victim The transactionalist perspective makes
guilt (Parkinson et al., 2005, and see next sense of many otherwise mysterious forms
paragraph) or shame generated by merely of higher cognitive emotion. For example
interacting with a higher-ranking member of although embarrassment has usually been
the community (Fessier, 1999).5 Confronted associated with the recognition of personal
by these and other difficulties, appraisal the- failure with respect to relatively unimpor-
orists have come to accept that even such tant norms of conduct, embarrassment can
apparendy conceptually complex appraisals be elicited simply by being pointed at in
as Lazarus's core relational themes can be public (Lewis, 2000) or being deservedly
made (1) without the information evalu- praised in public (Parrott 8c Smith, 1991).
ated being available to other cognitive pro- Parkinson et al. (2005) interpret this as evi-
cesses, (2) before perceptual processing of dence that embarrassment can be a simple
the stimulus has been completed, and (3) response to public attention, which does not
using only simple sensory cues to define the presuppose negative self-evaluation. Embar-
property that has to be identified. The resul- rassment can thus occur as a result of mere
tant multilevel appraisal theories (Teasdale, unwanted attention, which may or may not
1999) suggest that the same content can be be the result of having committed a faux pas.
possessed at different levels of appraisal, a From this perspective, embarrassment may
view consistent with the idea that some lev- be available to prelinguistic children. Reddy
els of appraisal involve nonconceptual con- (2000) reports the combination of coy smiles
tent. and gaze aversion in two-month-old infants,
The situated perspective on emotions which suggests the possibility that primitive
identifies emotions like guilt and shame in forms of embarrassment may emerge much
a way that leaves open the extent to which earlier than the cognitive capacities gener-
they involve conceptual thought. The ques- ally assumed to underlie them: "the dynam-
tion becomes whether the social transaction ics of interpersonal interaction may produce
corresponding to the emotion can occur in emotion without the internal cognitive rep-
the absence of the appropriate conceptual resentation of those dynamics. All that is
thoughts. Parkinson et al. (2005) offer us rea- required is a basic perception of self in rela-
sons to think that this is indeed the case tion to others, which may well be present at
for many higher cognitive emotions. They a very early age" (Parkinson et al., 2005, p.
report a study by Kroon (1988) in which 210). This idea will be enlarged upon in the
only 28 percent of experimental subjects next section.
reporting guilt experiences deemed them-
selves causally related to the event that pro-
voked their guilt. Parkinson (1999) further 4. C u l t u r a l S c a f f o l d i n g
supports the view that it is not necessary
to engage in thoughts of moral transgres- The concept of environmental scaffold-
sion to feel guilty by documenting instances ing has been central to situated cogni-
of guilt generated by unwarranted accusa- tion research: intelligent behavior is guided
tions from relevant others. These forms of and supported by the context in which it
guilt can be explained from a transaction- unfolds. The emphasis here is on the active
alist perspective if guilt is a form of skillful contribution of the environment to the cog-
social engagement aimed at reconciliation. nitive process (Clark 8c Chalmers, 1998).
EMOTIONS IN THE WII.D 443

To disregard the enabling properties of the includes socialization and exposure to all
environment is to lose sight of the fact those factors that make up a culture (Cos-
that the causal structure underlying a great mides, Tooby, & Barkow, 1992). Hence a
many cognitive achievements projects into feature of the emotional phenotype may be
the relational space between cognizer and both a (phylogenetic) product of evolution
environment. and an (ontogenetic) product of a rich con-
A situated perspective on emotion recog- text of socialization. A fully adequate reso-
nizes that the environment plays an active lution of the nature-versus-nurture debate,
role in structuring and enabling emotional however, requires the additional recogni-
engagements, which like cognitive engage- tion that the role of the developmental con-
ments are scaffolded by their natural con- text is not restricted to activating alterna-
text of occurrence. 6 T h e environment scaf- tive outcomes prefigured in a disjunctive
folds emotion in t w o ways. Synchronically, genetic program (Griffiths, 1997; Griffiths
the environment supports particular emo- & Stotz, 2000). Developmental systems are
tional performances - particular episodes usually competent to produce viable pheno-
of, say, anger or sadness (see section 5). types outside the specific parameter ranges
Diachronically, the environment supports in which they have historically operated.
the development of an emotional phe- This may even be an important source of
notype or repertoire of emotional abili- evolutionary novelty (Schlichting & Pigli-
ties. Thus, the provision of confessionals ucci, 1998; West-Eberhard, 2003).
in churches enables certain kinds of emo- In our view, an adequate perspective
tional performance (synchronic scaffolding), on the relationship between evolution and
and the broader Catholic culture supports social construction must recognize (1) that
the development of the ability to engage the way developing humans respond to
in the emotional engagements of confession inputs from the social environment and
(diachronic scaffolding). Synchronic scaf- the fact that the social environments pro-
folding has received more attention than vide those inputs may both be subject to
diachronic scaffolding in the literature on evolutionary explanation, and (2) that the
situated cognition (but see Thelen & Smith, biological endowment of a healthy human
1994). In contrast, there is more research infant determines a norm of reaction that
on the diachronic, developmental role of includes a large range of emotional pheno-
affective culture than on its synchronic role. types, not all of which have been specifi-
This is a by-product of the longstanding cally selected for nor need to have occurred
debate over nature versus nurture in emo- before in human history (for similar per-
tion theory. spectives, see Bjorklund & Pellegrini, 2002;
To appreciate the potential interest of Parkinson, forthcoming). That said, we hope
the extensive body of research on emo- that we can go on to discuss the role of
tional development, we need to diffuse the the environment in the genesis of emotions
heated but ultimately sterile debate over without being accused of ignoring biology.
nature and nurture. Situated perspectives Parkinson et al. (2005, p. 224) formu-
on emotion have traditionally been aligned late a useful framework for the study of
with social constructionism because of the the environment's many roles. They dis-
simplistic view that evolved features of the cuss both how the development of an emo-
mind must develop in ways that are insen- tional repertoire is diachronically scaffolded
sitive to the social environment — they by the cultural context in which an indi-
are programmed in the genes (e.g., Rat- vidual grows up and how specific emo-
ner, 1989). Fortunately, it is increasingly rec- tional performances are synchronically scaf-
ognized that evolution does not construct folded by the social and cultural context
genetic homunculi but developmental sys- in which they occur. They explore the
tems designed to function in a develop- potential social influences on emotion under
mental context that, in a species like ours, the two broad areas of ideational factors
4+4 TAI IT GRIFFITHS AND ANDREA SCARANT1NO

and material (actors, offering an adaptation When the child is about one year old
of Markus and Kitavama's (1994) model. Parkinson et al. (2005) envisage the emer-
Ideational factors include normative stan- gence of secondary intersubjectivity, charac-
dards about when emotions should be expe- terized by the recognition not only of people
rienced or expressed (e.g., American wed- and objects but also of the relations existing
ding guests are normatively required both to between them. A classic example of emo-
be happy for the couple and to convey their tional engagement emerging at this stage is
happiness), emotion scripts (shared internal- social referencing. Infants learn to engage
ized understandings of the standard unfold- objects emotionally in light of the emo-
ing of an emotional episode), and ethnothe- tional responses other people have to them.
ories (culture-specific belief systems about For example, if toddlers observe a disgusted
the nature and value of emotions). Material expression on their mother's face when they
factors include emotional capital (e.g., the are handling a toy, they are less inclined to
emotional resources associated with having play with it (Hornik, Risenhoover, 8t Gun-
a specific social status, gender, etc.), venues nar, 1987).
in which certain emotional performances are Finally, infants articulate their emotions
favored (e.g., a confessional, a stadium, a with the help of their emerging concep-
temple), and a range of emotional technolo- tual resources (cultural articulation). Draw-
gies for the management of emotions, from ing on symbolic resources in the surround-
prayer beads to Prozac. ing culture, most important those afforded
Parkinson et al. (2005) draw on exist- by language, the child organizes its experi-
ing work on emotional development to ence of emotional transactions in concep-
construct a model of the development of tual form. 7 It is at this stage that ideational
a culturally situated emotional phenotype factors, such as emotion scripts and display
(pp. 235-248). They distinguish three main rules, and material factors, such as emotional
ontogenetic stages: primary intersubjectiv- capital and emotional technologies, have
ity, secondary intersubjectivity, and cultural their greatest impact on emotional develop-
articulation. ment.
Primary intersubjectivity emerges in the It is in their understanding of cultural
first few months of a child's life, when pat- articulation that Parkinson et al. (2005)
terns of attraction and aversion are estab- depart from traditional social construction-
lished with objects and relevant others, most ism. Articulation does not simply cause
prominently caregivers. One form of emo- emotions to take on the form suggested
tional engagement emerging at this stage by the local affective culture. While the
involves struggling in response to a tight articulated, concept-mediated emotion is a
embrace (Camras, Campos, Oster, Miyake, real component of the emotion system, it
& Bradshaw, 1992). Parkinson, Fischer, and is superimposed on an existing emotional
Manstead identify this as the ontogeneti- repertoire grounded in primary and sec-
cally earliest form of anger, despite the fact ondary intersubjectivity: "We don't learn to
that the concepts that make up the core get angry in the first place by following cul-
relational theme of anger are not available tural rules, even if those rules are applied to
at this point. This identification is made our anger after the fact" (Parkinson et al.,
possible by thinking of anger as a type of 2005, p. 247). T h e conceptual articulation
social transaction rather than as a conceptual of the emotion allows for the emergence
thought embodying a core relational theme of tensions between emotional engagements
(see section 3). The primary anger reac- reflecting different ontogenetic stages (e.g.,
tion in infants is developmentally continu- some episodes of anger may not fit norma-
ous with episodes of adult anger in which tive rules for their appropriate elicitation, as
the core relational theme is not instantiated, in the case of the j a m m e d door). In such
such as anger elicited by repeated failure to cases the subject will often struggle to inter-
open a jammed door. pret a spontaneous emotional response so as
emotions in the wild 445

to fit the cultural articulation of an appro- appraisal, in which an individual's appraisal


priate emotion. of a situation is linked to that of others. The
Parkinson et al.'s (2005) account of most famous experiment on social appraisal
the ontogeny of emotion allows individ- (more precisely, social referencing) demon-
uals raised in different affective cultures strated that the willingness of infants to
to develop different emotional phenotypes. crawl over a visual cliff reflected whether
This could happen in either of two ways. their waiting mother produced a positive
First, individuals do conform to a significant or negative facial expression (Sorce, Emde,
degree with the norms and scripts that they Campos, & Klinnert, 1985). Similar processes
have internalized. Second, all sorts of cul- occur in adults. A tactless remark can be
tural differences - physical child-care prac- shrugged off when the other members of
tices, common toys, and so forth - may a social gathering treat it as a nonevent, or
affect emotional development. It is worth when they laugh it off, whereas it may be
noting, however, that these latter influ- appraised as a deadly insult if bystanders
ences need not necessarily increase the fit meet it with silence or with a sharp intake of
between emotion as experienced and emo- breath. Such distributed appraisal provides
tion as articulated. It is perfectly conceiv- an emotional correlate to distributed cogni-
able that some element of the upbringing of tion (e.g., Hutchins, 1995).
children in an affective culture might make Real-time socialization is perhaps the
it harder for them to conform to its norms closest parallel in emotion research to the
as adults than would otherwise be the case. forms of scaffolding that have been the focus
In any case, even when cultural articulation of much philosophical discussion of situa-
has had its full effect on the development of tionism, such as the notorious notebook of
the emotional repertoire, a gap remains that Clark and Chalmers (1998). In our view,
allows emotions to occur in the absence of too much attention has been devoted to
the conceptual conditions taken to define whether such cognitive aids imply that cog-
them. nition is literally spread out into the world.
We now turn from the cultural scaffold- Similar claims have been made in the liter-
ing of emotional development (diachronic ature on the emotions, with emotions said
scaffolding) to the cultural scaffolding of to exist in the social space between trans-
emotional performances (synchronic scaf- actants, and so forth, but we believe it
folding). For society to function smoothly, would be a mistake to focus on these ques-
individuals must have the right emotions at tions, which are largely semantic. The real
the right times, and it is not left to individual interest of situationist accounts of emotion
psychological processes to ensure that this lies in their methodological prescriptions for
occurs. It is hardly necessary to describe the future psychological study of the emotions.
emotional technologies used to ensure that We will return to this theme in section 6.
soldiers hate the enemy, feel loyalty to their
unit, and are not overwhelmed by fear in
combat. Parkinson et al. (2005) use the more 5. Dynamic C o u p l i n g
cheerful example of the wedding ceremony,
in which ritual, music, and setting scaffold A situated perspective on cognition includes
participants' performances of their comple- the realization that cognition is dynamically
mentary affective roles. It is not left to shaped by the context in which a cognitive
chance to make a wedding a big day for all episode takes place. This context changes
concerned. Such real-time socialization is an over time, sometimes as a consequence
alternative to inducing conformity with local of the cognitive activity. Context depen-
affective norms via diachronic socialization dence generates a system of reciprocal cau-
(Parkinson et al., 2005, p. 226). sation that classic approaches to the mind
Another real-time process inducing con- tend to neglect, as they abstract from the
formity to emotional norms is social local properties of the environment (Smith,
PAUL GRIFFITHS AND ANDREA SCARANTINO

1999). A situated perspective on emotion threat displays " w e r e given when the bird
explores some of the same themes, focus- was uncertain w h a t to do" and that "which
ing on the temporal dynamics of skillful of the several possible responses it showed
emotional engagement, exploring the way next depended on the behavior of the rival."
in which the emotional episode shapes the Hence threat expressions should be under-
context of its development and is in turn stood as "signals in a process of negotiation
shaped by it. Because the context of emo- between individuals" (Hinde, 1985a, p. 109)
tional episodes is largely social, understand- Hinde cast d o u b t on the assumption that
ing the dynamic coupling between emoter "emotional behavior is the outward expres-
and environment amounts to understanding sion of an emotional state, and that there is a
how the unfolding of an emotion episode one-to-one correspondence between them "
affects the behaviors of other organisms and an assumption he associated with Darwin
is in turn shaped by their behavior. Emotion (1872). He also noted that the assumption of
is a form of skillful engagement with the a one-to-one correspondence between emo-
social environment that involves a dynamic tional states and emotional behaviors does
process of negotiation mediated by recipro- not make evolutionary sense, as it may be
cal feedback between emoter and interac- adaptive for an organism to mislead others
tants. This feedback is provided by recipro- about its motivational state. Natural selec-
cal emotional signals. tion will o f t e n f a v o r sending nonveridical
Researchers on situated cognition have or ambiguous messages, a point that has
been strongly influenced by the dynami- also impressed transactional psychologists
cal cognitive science approach featured in (Fridlund, 1994,1997). H i n d e acknowledged,
the collection Mind as Motion [Port & van however, that signals do not always serve
Gelder, 1995). The dynamicist ideas pre- negotiating purposes. His conclusion was
sented here have a rather different pedi- that we should e x p e c t emotional behaviors
gree, as they are primarily grounded in the to lie on a c o n t i n u u m b e t w e e n expressing
study of relationship dynamics (Hinde, 1979, and negotiating:
1981). This large body of work on topics such
Such considerations suggest the view that
as infant attachment and romantic relation-
emotional behavior may lie along a con-
ships starts from the premise that relation-
tinuum from behaviour that is more or
ships are not an immediate function of the less purely expressive to behaviours con-
properties that individuals bring to a rela- cerned primarily with a process of negoti-
tionship, but emerge as a result of specific ation between individuals.... In animals,
interactions between those individuals and bird songs lie nearer the expressive end,
inputs from a changing environment. threat postures nearer the negotiation end.
The ethologist Robert Hinde (1985a, In man, spontaneous and solitary laugh-
ter are primarily expressive, the ingratiat-
1985b) was the first to articulate the idea
ing smile primarily negotiating. However
that emotional behavior can be a form of
most emotional expressions involve both.
negotiation. He noticed that several kinds (Hinde, 1985b, p. 989}
of emotional expressions, in both humans
and animals, are issued only when a recip- We consider this an important insight.
ient is there to be influenced by them, and Hinde's suggestion is that m a n y emotional
that it is the responses of the recipient that expressions have a nonarbitrary relation to
determine the subsequent behavior of the the organism's motivational states, but at the
individual exhibiting the initial emotional same time are a i m e d to m a k e a move in a
behavior rather than the presumed emotion negotiation w h o s e o u t c o m e is open ended
expressed by that behavior. Hinde noted and crucially d e p e n d e n t on the recipient's
that birds often flee after having issued a responses.
threat expression. Indeed, the threat dis- T h e first thing that is left open by an
play may be a better predictor of flight expressive action is w h e t h e r the emoter
than of attack. His interpretation was that will manifest the action tendency associated
EMOTIONS IN THE WILD 447

with that emotion. This will depend on what lost if anger is understood only as a
affordances are available to the emoter in response to a certain class of stimulus sit-
the local context in which the emotional uations, ignoring the temporal dynamics of
episode unfolds. Notably, neither the avail- its unfolding and the strategy of relationship
able affordances nor the emoter's intention reconfiguration it embodies.
to act on a particular one of them are pre- An emotional expression may also be
ordained at the beginning of the episode, open ended in a more radical way: in some
but instead are partially determined by the cases the identity of the initial emotion is
interactant's responses, which are in turn shaped by the ongoing process of negotia-
influenced by the ongoing emotional signals tion. We are accustomed to think of anger
received. Consider, for example, an episode as brought about by the appraisal of being
of anger in the context of a marital con- slighted, and this is certainly what hap-
frontation, and assume that an action ten- pens in many cases of anger. But on occa-
dency of retribution is associated with anger. sion this appraisal is best understood as
There are many ways in which the retribu- the outcome of negotiation in an episode
tive action tendency could be manifested: that already has the marks of the emotional
sulking, insulting, leaving the house, ask- (e.g., physiological arousal, focused atten-
ing for a divorce, and so on. Conversely, tion, an urgent tendency to realign one's role
the retributive tendency could be inhibited. in the context of a relationship). What is
Anger can be diffused by emotion manage- left partially undetermined and in need of
ment techniques or redirected at another context-dependent disambiguation is what
object (e.g., the poverty that may be the exact emotion one is experiencing. Many
external driver of marital discord), or the marital quarrels begin from small matters
aroused state of either party could facilitate of contention, which engage the partners
the emergence of another emotion (e.g., fear emotionally, but that general emotionality
of losing one's partner). This flexibility is can develop into a variety of distinct emo-
one of the trademark properties of a large tions. This idea of emotional uncertainty
class of emotions, which distinguishes them echoes some of the dynamics of threat dis-
from reflexlike responses like startle, and plays described by Hinde (1985a, 1985b). The
perhaps affect programs, whose behavioral bird's confrontation with a rival activates an
consequences are relatively indefeasible. emotional engagement that is open ended in
What determines how a particular the sense that at the beginning of the process
episode of anger unfolds is a feedback mech- of negotiation it is undetermined whether
anism that involves the reciprocal exchange the bird is angry or afraid. The identity of
of signals delivered by expressions and other the emotion will be shaped through time
behavior in the course of time. The currency by the responses received to the threat dis-
of this communication includes fixed stares, play. The appraisal that type identifies the
loud and high-pitched tones, brisk gestures, emotion does not occur at the beginning
a confrontational demeanor, tears, firm dec- of the emotional episode but in the course
larations, forceful movements, and their of it, depending on whether the interaction
strategic opposites (e.g., amicable stares, affords the advantageous manifestation of
low-pitched tones, smiles) that will deter- one emotion rather than the other.
mine if and how anger manifests. At first blush, a situated perspective on
This is where the metaphor of negotiation emotions is in tension with the affect-
comes to full fruition, as the anger episode is program conception of emotions in the
not exhausted by the interactant's reception Darwin-Tomkins-Ekman tradition (Darwin,
of a one-shot message, but is dynamically 1872; Ekman, 1972; Tomkins, 1962). In this
shaped by how the interactant responds theoretical tradition, a low-level (modular)
to the initial message, by how the emoter appraisal occurs on exposure to certain stim-
responds to the interactant's response, and uli and is followed by a cascade of responses,
so on. This context dependence is entirely including physiological, expressive, and
PAUL GRIFFITHS AND ANDREA SCARANTINO

behavioral ones, which follow the appraisal uated perspective and try to diffuse some
quickly and automatically. A specific expres- possible misunderstandings. Let us begin
sion is associated with each basic emotion with what we are not saying. We are not
and consequendy carries veridical informa- claiming that, because the social environ-
tion about what emotion is unfolding. The ment provides dynamic scaffolding for the
apparent conflict between affect-program unfolding of emotional episodes, an emo-
theory and a situated approach, however, tion literally extends into the environment.
can be at least partly defused by noticing This sort of ontological claim may be inter-
that the two approaches operate on differ- esting in principle, but we do not think that
ent temporal scales. The situated approach its possible heuristic value for the psychol-
focuses on longer emotional episodes that ogy of emotion is likely to be worth the
may comprise the activation of affect pro- fuss it causes. An extended-emotion thesis
grams as proper parts. For example, a young potentially confuses the claim that the envi-
man who is suddenly poked in the back ronment makes a causal contribution to a
while standing in a line will automatically mental process with the more ontologically
undergo affect program anger, manifested demanding claim that it is a constituent
in a reflexlike fashion through forceful turn- part of it (see A d a m s & Aizawa, this vol-
ing around, baring of the teeth, and an ume). Therefore, until it proves impossible
aggressive action tendency. But there is no to phrase the substance of the situated per-
obstacle to conceiving of this execution spective in any other w a y , we will remain
of the anger affect program as part of a neutral on the extended-emotion thesis.
longer episode, which includes what hap- There are other potentially interesting
pens after the identity of the offender has questions we wish to remain neutral about,
been determined. It is at this stage that because we do not think the value of the
the idea of negotiation acquires explana- situated perspective on emotions hinges on
tory purchase. If the offender is a good- how we answer them. For example, it may
looking young woman who profusely apolo- be debated what sort of externalism about
gizes, the agonistic action tendency is likely emotions is supported by the data and the-
to be prompdy substituted by an affiliative ory we have presented, or whether group
action tendency. If the offender is another emotions arising through mutual social ref-
young male, however, a different dynamic erencing challenge methodological individ-
emerges, which may lead to an exchange of ualism in the psychology of emotion. We
anger displays and ultimately escalate into a leave it to others to take definitive positions
physical fight. on these issues.
Moreover, a situated approach is not It may forestall another misunderstand-
committed to the view that all things we ing if we state explicitly that the plausibility
call emotions in ordinary language are social of the perspective we propose is not hostage
engagements with a negotiating dimension. to the success of the wider situationist pro-
What we have described are emotions lying gram. The situated perspective on emotion
toward the negotiating end of the contin- is supported, in so far as it is currently sup-
uum discussed by Hinde, and the vernacu- ported, by experimental data and theoretical
lar emotion domain contains states and pro- considerations about the emotions.
cesses on which a situated approach sheds T h e real theoretical payoff of the situ-
no light, as we discuss subsequently. ated perspective on emotions is method-
ological. By shifting theoretical focus from
the intrapsychic to the interpersonal, from
6. What Is the Value of the Situated the unbidden to the strategic, from the short
Perspective on Emotion? lived to the long lived, from the context
independent to the context dependent, from
In this final section, we illustrate what we the static to the dynamic, the situated per-
take to be the theoretical payoff of a sit- spective points the attention of the research
emotions in t h e w i l d 449

community to aspects of emotions that have the ground rules of the activity of explicat-
been unduly neglected and that may hold ing.
the key to understanding the nature and We have suggested that the situated per-
function of a large class of emotions. These spective on emotions affords new theoret-
aspects of emotion have not been entirely ical leads for the explication of the so-
ignored, of course (e.g., Frijda, 1986, and called higher cognitive emotions (e.g., guilt,
elsewhere; Solomon, 1998), but we think shame, embarrassment). Although these are
they would have become more central if the emotions involved in phenomena we are
a broader perspective on the mind suit- most eager to understand (e.g., morality, art,
able to encourage them had been available. mental disorders, daily emotional manage-
We believe that the situated approach can ment), they are also among the most com-
offer such a perspective: the aspects of emo- plex and challenging of emotional states.
tion we have highlighted as worthy of the- Although one of us made extensive use of
oretical exploration largely correspond to the phrase "higher cognitive emotions" in
those the situationist movement has sin- earlier work (Griffiths, 1997), we now regard
gled out as neglected in classical cognitive it as potentially confusing (Griffiths, 2004a).
science. First, it suggests that the occurrence of these
We emphasize once again that the sit- emotions necessarily involves conceptual
uationist perspective is not, in principle, thought, a view we have strongly ques-
incompatible with other existing theoretical tioned. Second, it seems almost irre-
approaches (e.g., neo-Jamesianism, affect- sistible to align the distinction between
program theory). In part this is a matter basic emotions and higher cognitive emo-
of temporal scale of resolution, as outlined tions with a distinction between two sets
in section 5. More importantly, we believe, of vernacular emotion categories - anger,
and have argued extensively in earlier work, disgust, and surprise being paradigmatically
that the plurality of states and processes that basic, and guilt, shame, and embarrassment
form the domain of emotion leave emotion being paradigmatically higher. We believe,
theorists with no viable alternative to theo- however, that there is as much need for plu-
retical pluralism. Griffiths (1997, 2004a) has ralism in the theoretical treatment of subor-
argued that it is unlikely that all the psycho- dinate categories of emotion as there is in the
logical states and processes that fall under treatment of the superordinate category of
the vernacular category of emotion are suffi- emotion: some instances of anger, disgust, or
ciently similar to one another to allow a uni- surprise may be adequately accounted for in
fied scientific psychology of the emotions. the affect program framework, but others
The psychological, neuroscientific, and bio- may require other theoretical perspectives,
logical theories that best explain any partic- and the same holds for episodes of guilt,
ular subset of emotions will not adequately shame, or embarrassment. The situated per-
explain all emotions. In a slogan, emotion spective on emotion, and the transactional
is not a natural kind. Scarantino (2005) has psychology on which we have drawn in
argued that the scientific project of answer- describing it, is just one of these theoretical
ing questions of the form, What is an emo- approaches, and it is meant to cut across the
tion? or W h a t is anger? is best understood as dichotomy between basic and higher cogni-
a project of explication. Explication involves tive emotions as generally understood.
offering a theoretically motivated precisifi- In a nutshell, the situated perspective sug-
cation of an existing concept. Explications gests that certain forms of emotion cannot
are not good or bad simpliciter but relative be understood without expanding our field
to the theoretical objectives that motivate of view. By confining our attention to neu-
them. Where there is more than one sen- ral circuitry or conceptual thought alone,
sible theoretical objective, quarreling about we risk focusing on the proverbial tail of
which explication should replace the origi- the emotional elephant. Its trunk and body
nal concept is simply not to have understood may lie further afield, in the social and
PAUL GRIFFITHS AND ANDREA SC AR ANTINO

cultural environment in which emotional shame in the culture he studied, was fre-
episodes untold and emotional phenotypes quently manifested under these circum-
develop. stances.
6 The term engagement has been previously
used to characterize emotions, for example
Acknowledgments by Parkinson (forthcoming) and by Solomon
(2004). This similarity may be explained by
the presence in Solomon's cognitivism of
Authors' names are in alphabetical order. We a social constructionist strand, related to
thank Franco and Adriana Scarantino for their Sartre's theory of emotions, which empha-
hospitality at Pinetina while this chapter was sizes the active side of emotions along broadly
written. Griffiths's work was supported by an transactionalist lines.
Australian Research Council Federation Fellow- 7 There is an evident parallel here with Annette
ship. Edouard Machery provided useful feedback Karmiloff-Smith's (1992) theory of represen-
on an earlier draft. tational redescription.

Notes References

1 For the breadth of current psychological Arnold, M. B. (i960). Emotion and personality.
research, see Dalgleish and Power, 1999; New York: Columbia University Press.
Ekman and Davidson, 1994; and Lewis and Arnold, M. B. (Ed.). (1970). Feelings and emotions.
Haviland-Jones, 2000. Recent philosophical San Diego, C A : Academic Press.
work on emotion is surveyed in Griffiths Bermudez, J. (2003). Nonconceptual mental con-
(2003) and collected in Solomon (2004). tent. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclope-
2 The strategic role of the emotions has long dia of philosophy. Accessed July 9, 2005, from
been noticed by economists [Frank, 1988; http://plato.stanford.edu
Hirshleifer, 1987). Until recently, however, Bjorklund, D. F., & Pellegrini, A. D. (2002). The
this recognition was not linked to a new origins of human nature: Evolutionary develop-
account of the nature of emotions themselves mental psychology. Washington, D C : Ameri-
(but see Ross & Dumouchel, 2004). Not sur- can Psychological Association.
prisingly, behavioral ecologists have also been Camras, L. A., Campos, J. J., Oster, H., Miyake,
sensitive to the strategic role of emotions in K., & Bradshaw, D. (1992). Japanese and
social interaction (e.g., Fessler & Haley, 2003). American infants' responses to arm restraint.
3 The nonconceptual content literature has Developmental Psychology, 28, 578-583.
so far focused primarily on nonconceptual Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body,
perceptual states, nonconceptual subdoxas- and world together again. Cambridge, MA:
tic states, and nonconceptual representa- MIT Press.
tional states of creatures without language Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended
(Bermudez, 2003). We think emotional phe- mind. Analysis, 58, 7-19.
nomena constitute a representational domain Cosmides, L., Tooby, J., &. Barkow, J. H. (1992).
of their own, which embodies a yet-to-be- Introduction: Evolutionary psychology and
understood brand of nonconceptual content conceptual integration. In J. H. Barkow, L.
(Griffiths, 2004a, 2004b; Scarantino, 2005). Cosmides, & J. T o o b y (Eds.), The adapted
f The view that emotions are evaluative judg- mind: Evolutionary psychology and the genera-
ments has been extensively criticized for tion of culture (pp. 3-15). Oxford: Oxford Uni-
these reasons. Its defenders have replied versity Press.
that judgment need not involve full-blown Cussins, A. (1992). Content, embodiment and
conceptual thought (Nussbaum, 2001, 2004). objectivity: T h e theory of cognitive trails.
This risks collapsing cognitivism into the Mind, 101, 651-688.
uncontroversial view that emotions are in Dalgleish, T., & Power, M. J. (Eds.). (1999).
some sense or other directed at the world Handbook of cognition and emotion. Chi-
(Scarantino, 2005). chester, UK: John Wiley.
Fessler (1999) reports that malu, the emo- Damasio, A. R. (1996). T h e somatic marker
tion most closely corresponding to Western hypothesis and the possible functions of the
EMOTIONS IN THE WILD 45j

prefrontal cortex. Philosophical Transactions of Frijda, N. H. (1986). The emotions. Cambridge:


the Royal Society of London B, 351(1346), 1413- Cambridge University Press.
1420. Griffiths, P. E. (1997). What emotions really
Damasio, A. R. (1999). The feeling of what hap- are: The problem of psychological categories.
pens: Body and emotion in the making of con- Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
sciousness. New York: Harcourt Brace. Griffiths, P. E. (2003). Emotions. In S. Stich &
Darwin, C. (1872). The expression of the emotions T. Warfield (Eds.), The Blackwell guide to the
in man and animals. N e w York: Philosophical philosophy of mind (pp. 288-308). Oxford and
Library. New York: Blackwell.
Ekman, P. (1972). Emotion in the human face. New Griffiths, P. E. (2004a). Is emotion a natural kind?
York: Pergamon Press. In R. C. Solomon (Ed.), Thinking about feeling:
Ekman, P., & Davidson, R. J. (Eds.). (1994). The Contemporary philosophers on emotions (pp.
nature of emotion: Fundamental questions. New 233-249). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
York: Oxford University Press. Griffiths, P. E. (2004b). Towards a Machiavellian
Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford: theory of emotional appraisal. In P. Cruse &
Oxford University Press. D. Evans (Eds.), Emotion, evolution, and ratio-
Fernändez-Dols, J. M., & Ruiz-Belda, M.-A. nality (pp. 89-105). Oxford: Oxford University
(1997). Spontaneous facial behavior during Press.
intense emotional episodes: Artistic truth Griffiths, P. E., 8c Stotz, K. (2000). How the mind
and optical truth. In J. A. Russell 81 J. M. grows: A developmental perspective on the
Fernändez-Dols (Eds.), The psychology of facial biology of cognition. Synthese, 122(1-2), 29-51.
expression (pp. 255-294). Cambridge: Cam- Hinde, R. A. (1979). Towards understanding rela-
bridge University Press. tionships. London: Academic Press.
Fessler, D. M. T. (1999). Toward an under- Hinde, R. A. (1981). The bases of a science of
standing of the universality of second-order interpersonal relationships. In S. W. Duck &
emotions. In A. L. Hinton (Ed.), Biocultural R. Gilmour (Eds.), Personal relationships 1;
approaches to emotions (pp. 74-116). Cam- Studyingpersonal relationships (pp. 1-22). Lon-
bridge: Cambridge University Press. don: Academic Press.
Fessler, D. M. T., 8c Haley, K. J. (2003). The Hinde, R. A. (1985a). Expression and negotiation.
strategy of affect: Emotions in human coop- In G. Zivin (Ed.), The development of expressive
eration. In P. Hammerstein (Ed.), The genetic behavior (pp. 103-116). New York: Academic
and cultural evolution of cooperation (pp. 7-36). Press.
Cambridge, M A : M I T Press. Hinde, R. A. (1985b). Was "the expression of
Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought. New emotions" a misleading phrase? Animal Behav-
York: Crowell. ior, 33, 985-992.
Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind: An Hirshleifer, J. (1987). On the emotions as guar-
essay in faculty psychology. Cambridge, MA: antors of threats and promises. In J. Dupre
Bradford Books/MIT Press. (Ed.), The latest on the best. Cambridge, MA:
Frank, R. H. (1988). Passions within reason: The Bradford Books/MIT Press.
strategic role of the emotions. N e w York: W. W. Hornik, R., Risenhoover, N., 8c Gunnar, M. R.
Norton. (1987). The effects of maternal positive, neu-
Fridlund, A. J. (1994). Human facial expression: tral and negative affective communications on
An evolutionary view. San Diego, C A : Aca- infants' responses to new toys. Child Develop-
demic Press. ment, 58, 937-944.
Fridlund, A. J. (1997). The new ethology of Hurley, S. (2003). Animal actions in the space of
human facial expressions. In J. A. Russell 81 reasons. Mind and language, 18(3), 231-256.
J. M. Fernändez-Dols (Eds.), The psychology Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cam-
of facial expression (pp. 103-129). Cambridge: bridge, MA: MIT Press.
Cambridge University Press. Karmiloff-Smith, A. (1992). Beyond modularity: A
Fridlund, A. J., Schaut, J. A., Sabini, J. P., developmental perspective on cognitive science.
Shenker, J. I., Hedlund, L. E., 81 Knauer, M. J. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
(1990). Audience effects on solitary faces dur- Kraut, R. E., & Johnston, R. E. (1979). Social and
ing imagery: Displaying to the people in your emotional messages of smiling: An ethologi-
head. Journal of Nonverbal Behaviour, 14(2), cal approach. Journal of Personality and Social
113-137. Psychology, 37,1539-1553.
4+4TaIITgriffithsandandreas c a r a n t 1 n o

Kroon, R. M. (1988). Aanleidingen en structuur Parkinson, B. (1995). Ideas and realities of emotion
van schtddgn<oel. Unpublished master's thesis, London: Routledge.
University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam. Parkinson, B. (1999). Relations and dissociations
Lazarus, R. S. (1991)- Emotion and adaptation. between appraisal and emotion ratings of rea-
New York: Oxford University Press. sonable and unreasonable anger and guilt
Lean, M. R., Landel, J. L., & Patton, K. Cognition and Emotion, 13, 347-385.
M (1996). The motivated expression of Parkinson, B. (forthcoming). The heart of emotion.
embarrassment following a self-presentational Unpublished manuscript.
predicament. Journal of Personality, 64(3), 619- Parkinson, B., Fischer, A. H., & Manstead, A. S.
636. R. (2005). Emotions in social relations: Cultural
LeDoux, J. E. (1993). Emotional networks in group, and interpersonal processes. New York:
the brain. In M. Lewis & J. M. Haviland Psychology Press.
(Eds.), Handbook of emotions (pp. 109-118). Parrott, W. G., & Smith, S. F. (1991). Embarrass-
New York: Guilford Press. ment: Actual vs. typical cases, classical vs. pro-
Lewis, M. (2000). The emergence of human emo- totypical representations. Cognition and Emo-
tions. In M. Lewis & J. M. Haviland-Jones tion, 5, 467-488.
(Eds.), Handbook of emotions (2nd ed., pp. 265- Port, R. F., & van Gelder, T. (Eds.). (1995). Mind
280). New York: Guilford Press. as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cog-
Lewis, M.j & Haviland-Jones, J. M. (Eds.). (2000). nition. Cambridge, M A : MIT Press.
Handbook of emotions (2nd ed.). New York: Prinz, J. (2004a). Embodied emotions. In R. C.
Gudford Press. Solomon (Ed.), Thinking about feeling: Con-
Marks, J. (1982). A theory of emotions. Philosoph- temporary philosophers on emotions (pp. 44-59).
ical Studies, 42, 227-242. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Markus, H. R., & Kitayama, S. (1994). The cul- Prinz, J. (2004b). Gut reactions: A perceptual the-
tural construction of self and emotion: Impli- ory of emotion. Oxford: Oxford University
cations for self and behavior. In S. Kitayama Press.
& H. R. Markus (Eds.), Emotion and culture: Ratner, C. (1989). A social constructionist cri-
Empirical studies of mutual influence (pp. 89- tique of the naturalistic theory of emotion.
130). Washington, DC: American Psychologi- Journal of Mind and Behavior, 10(3), 211-230.
cal Association. Reddy, V. (2000). Coyness in early infancy. Devel-
Marler, P., & Evans, C. (1997). Animal sounds opmental Science, 3, 186-192.
and human faces: Do they have anything in Ross, D., & Dumouchel, P. (2004). Emotions as
common? In J. A. Russell & J. M. Femindez- strategic signals. Rationality and Society, 16(3),
Dols (Eds.), The psychology of facial expression 251-286.
(pp. 133-226). Cambridge: Cambridge Univer- Russell, J. A., Bachorowski, J.-A., & Fernández-
sity Press. Dols, J. M. (2003). Facial and vocal expressions
Noe, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, of emotions. Annual Review of Psychology, 54,
MA. MIT Press. 349-359-
Nussbaum, M. C. (2001). Upheavals of thought: Russell, J. A., & Femández-Dols, J. M. (1997).
The intelligence of emotions. Cambridge: Cam- The psychology of facial expression. Cambridge:
bridge University Press. Cambridge University Press.
Nussbaum, M. C. (2004). Emotions as judgments Scarantino, A. (2003). Affbrdances explained.
of value and importance. In R. C. Solomon Philosophy of Science, 70, 949-961.
(Ed.), Thinking about feeling: Contemporary Scarantino, A. (2005). Explicating emotions.
philosophers on emotions (pp. 183-199). Oxford: Unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, University of
Oxford University Press. Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh.
Ohman, A. (1999). Distinguishing unconscious Scherer, K. R. (1999). Appraisal theory. In T. Dal-
from conscious emotional processes: Method- gleish 81M. J. Power (Eds.), Handbook of emo-
ological considerations and theoretical impli- tion and cognition (pp. 637-663). Chichester,
cations. In T. Dalgleish & M. J. Power (Eds.), UK: John Wiley.
Handbook of emotion and cognition (pp. 321- Schlichting, C. D., & Pigliucci, M. (1998). Phe-
352). Chichester, UK: John Wiley. notypic evolution: A reaction norm perspective.
Panksepp, J. (1998). Affective neuroscience: The Sunderland, M A : Sinauer.
foundations of human and animal emotions. Smith, B. C. (1999). Situatedness/embededness.
Oxford: Oxford University Press. In R. A. Wilson & F. C. Keil (Eds.), The MIT
EMOTIONS IN THE WILD

encyclopedia of the cognitive sciences (pp. 769- The representation and organization of emo-
771). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. tional experience; Unfolding the emotion
Solomon, R. C. (1976). The passions. New York: episode. In M. Lewis & J, M. Haviland (Eds ),
Doubleday. Handbook of emotions (pp. 279-300). New
Solomon, R. C. (1993). The passions (2nd ed.). York: Guilford Press.
New York: Hackett. Teasdale, J. D. (1999). Multi-level theories of
Solomon, R. C. (1998). The politics of emotion. cognition-emotion relations. InT. Dalgleish 8c
In P. A. French & H. K. Wettstein (Eds.), Mid- M. J. Power (Eds.), Handbook of cognition and
west Studies in Philosophy, 22,1-20. emotion (pp. 665-681). Chichester, UK: John
Solomon, R. C. (Ed.). (2004). Thinking about feel- Wiley.
ing: Contemporary philosophers on emotions. Thelen, E., 8c Smith, L. (1994). A dynamic systems
Oxford: Oxford University Press. approach to the development of cognition and
Sorce, J. F., Emde, R. N., Campos, J. J., & Klin- action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
nert, M. D. (1985). Maternal emotional sig- Tomkins, S. S. (1962). Affect, imagery, and con-
nalling: Its effect on the visual cliff behaviour sciousness. New York: Springer.
of 1 year olds. Developmental Psycholog, 21, West-Eberhard, M. J. (2003). Developmental plas-
195-200. ticity and evolution. Oxford: Oxford Univer-
Stein, N. L., Trabasso, T., 8c Liwag, M. (1993). sity Press.
The Social Context of Cognition

Eliot R. Smith and Frederica R. Convey

Cognition almost invariably occurs in the the half dozen or so main subdisciplines of
context of other people: the web of face-to- psychology (e.g., cognitive, clinical, per-
face encounters, personal relationships, and sonality, developmental, social, biological).
social group memberships that make us who As such, it has its o w n scientific journals,
we are. These social entities not only very conferences, textbooks, traditions, and
frequendy constitute the content of our distinctive foci of interest. T h e conceptual
thoughts and feelings but also fundamen- focus of social p s y c h o l o g y is the study of
tally shape the processes underlying our cog- human behavior in its social context, or to
nition and behavior as well. To detail some put it slightly less concisely, the study of
of the evidence for this broad claim, this how people's thoughts, feelings, and actions
chapter describes the interface of situated are influenced by the actual or implied
cognition with social psychology. We make presence of other people. S o m e specific
the case that these two fields focus on many areas of research interest that fall within
of the same empirical and conceptual issues, this definition include the following:
though sometimes taking different perspec-
tives. Following a brief section that intro-
• Social perception: H o w p e o p l e perceive
duces the field of social psychology, the main
body of the chapter is organized under four other individuals, interpret their behav-
broad principles that we believe capture iors, and infer their intentions; the role
major areas of overlap and common interest of social group m e m b e r s h i p s and group
between situated cognition and social psy- stereotypes in this process; h o w people
chology. perceive themselves and the influence of
the self-concept on thoughts, emotions,
and social behavior.
x. W h a t Is Social P s y c h o l o g y ? • Social influence: H o w people's opinions
and behavior are influenced by persua-
Social psychology is a discrete area of sive messages f r o m others or by confor-
theory and research that represents one of mity processes; h o w social groups form

454
the social context of cognition 455

norms that in turn regulate group mem- Asians) inevitably led to activation of mental
bers' behaviors. representations of generally shared and well-
• Social relationships: How people form learned stereotypes associated with those
close relationships (friendships, roman- groups, just as perception of words nam-
tic attachments) and how relationships ing common concepts automatically leads to
affect thoughts, feelings, and behavior; activation of those concepts. The activation
how people cooperate with others in and application of a stereotype is considered
groups that interact to make decisions or an autonomous cognitive process involving
perform concrete tasks; when and how the access and modification of mental rep-
people help others or aggress against resentations, taking place within a perceiver
them. who functions as an uninvolved information
processor, never actually behaving in the
world but simply reporting his or her judg-
Social psychology has been greatly influ-
ments and opinions. This caricature repre-
enced by its disciplinary neighbor, cogni-
sents an almost completely nonsituated pic-
tive psychology, both in its methodological
ture of human cognition.
preference for controlled laboratory exper-
iments as the most highly valued research On the other hand, other forces pull
method and in the focus of most com- social psychology in exacdy the opposite
mon theories. Social psychological theories direction, toward consideration of the sit-
for the most part (albeit with important uated nature of cognition and behavior. The
exceptions) are theories about mental pro- very definition of social psychology states
cesses that underlie the types of social that its ultimate concern is with effects of
phenomena outlined previously, such as the social situation or context on cognition
person perception, social influence, and rela- and behavior. This focus has kept the field
tionship formation. Of course, mental pro- from going too far down the road of focus-
cesses relevant to social psychology include ing on autonomous inner processes. The ten-
not only narrowly cognitive processes such dency to boxologize the mind has been tem-
as language comprehension, causal ascrip- pered by a constant focus on the ways in
tion, and problem solving, but also the emo- which personal relationships, group mem-
tional and motivational processes that loom berships, and our self-perceptions constrain
large when people interact either in friendly and facilitate our cognition. In its empha-
or conflictual ways. sis on flexible processing in a social context,
With these characteristic interests and social psychology parallels the situated cog-
approaches, social psychology frequendy nition approach in its focus on cognition as
finds itself pulled in two opposing direc- the underpinning of adaptive behavior, and
tions. On the one hand, social psycholog- its acknowledgement that thought is pro-
ical theories have frequently been formu- duced by the interaction between the organ-
lated as abstract, disembodied stories about ism and its environment. Social psychol-
autonomous mental processes, expressed as ogy already embraces many of the central
"boxologies" with little or no concern for tenets of the situated cognition approach, so
adaptiveness in, or even interfaces with, research in social psychology can inform the
real social environments. This is the very study of situated cognition more broadly.
approach whose shortcomings, whether In the domain of stereotyping, for instance,
realistically portrayed or caricatured and recent research has demonstrated, in con-
exaggerated, are so frequently the starting trast to the earlier picture of autonomous
point for rationales and justifications of the and automatic processes, that stereotype
situated cognition approach. As an example, activation depends on the perceiver's active
consider social psychological research on the goals and motives. When perceivers have
effects of stereotypes on person perception. specific reasons to want to know in depth
Theorists had long assumed that perception about the other person (Fiske, Neuberg,
of members of social groups (e.g., women, Beattie, & Milberg, 1987), or when they
EUOT R. SMITH AND FREDERICA R. CONREY
456

are motivated to think well or ill of that of close c o n n e c t i o n s a m o n g cognition, moti-


person (Sinclair & Kunda, 1999), activated vation, and action, c o n n e c t i o n s that have
stereotypes can be profoundly altered or b e e n core t o p i c s of s t u d y in social psychol-
suppressed. Person perception can thus be ogy. W e o f f e r t h r e e e x a m p l e s .
viewed as socially adaptive (e.g., Gilbert, j. Motivation shapes cognition. Cognition
1998) and a product of the motivational is generally n o t n e u t r a l a n d detached but
context. Stereotyping and other processes biased by t h e i n d i v i d u a l ' s m o t i v e s and goals.
unfold in ways that facilitate ongoing social C o n s i d e r a p e r s o n ' s u n d e r s t a n d i n g of the
interaction, relationship maintenance, and meaning of traits ( s u c h as reliable, hon-
the accomplishment of the perceiver's social est, or intelligent), w h i c h are basic compo-
goals in a given social context rather than nents of o u r i m p r e s s i o n s of o t h e r people as
in fixed and invariant style. This line of well as ourselves. R e s e a r c h s h o w s that our
research demonstrates the movement in definitions of s u c h traits are not objective
social psychology toward a model of human and invariant b u t are s h a p e d in self-serving
social cognition as both situated and adap- w a y s by o u r o w n p e r c e i v e d standings on
tive, and suggests ways in which research those traits ( D u n n i n g & C o h e n , 1992). As
on social cognition might inform our under- a second e x a m p l e , c o n s i d e r a person who
standing of situated cognition more broadly. is a m e m b e r of t w o social g r o u p s that are
stereotyped in o p p o s i t e w a y s , such as an
As a way of organizing our description of
A f r i c a n A m e r i c a n ( p o o r , unintelligent) and
theory and research within social psychology
physician ( a f f l u e n t , intelligent). If such an
that pertains to situated cognition, we adopt
individual delivers praise to a social per-
four major principles advanced by Smith
ceiver, research s h o w s t h a t features of the
and Semin (2004). These are intended to
positive s t e r e o t y p e are automatically acti-
capture four interrelated and partially over-
vated, w h e r e a s t h e d e l i v e r y of criticism trig-
lapping themes that are common to social
gers activation of t h e n e g a t i v e stereotype
psychology and situated cognition. T h e prin-
(Sinclair & K u n d a , 1999). In other words,
ciples are as follows: (1) Cognition is for the
the motivation to b e l i e v e praise and dispar-
adaptive regulation of action, and mental
age criticism tunes a n d constrains stereotype
representations are action oriented; (2) cog-
activation. A third e x a m p l e : C r o w e and Hig-
nition is embodied, both constrained and
gins (1997) d e m o n s t r a t e d that people in a
facilitated by our sensorimotor abilities as
p r o m o t i o n f o c u s , t h o s e p u r s u i n g achieve-
well as our brains; (3) cognition and action
ment, c o m m i t m o r e errors of commission
are situated in the sense of being contingent
than do p e o p l e in a p r e v e n t i o n focus, those
on specific aspects of the agent's social envi-
pursuing security a n d responsibility. That
ronment; (4) cognition is distributed across
is, p r o m o t i o n - f o c u s e d p e o p l e are m o r e will-
brains and the environment and across social
ing to c o m m i t errors of c o m m i s s i o n in pur-
agents (e.g., when information is discussed
suit of hits, and p r e v e n t i o n - f o c u s e d peo-
and evaluated in groups). With regard to
ple are m o r e willing to c o m m i t errors of
each of these themes, we briefly review
omission. Finally, t h e f u n d a m e n t a l human
and integrate relevant social psychological
need to belong shapes o u r social cognition.
research.
People experiencing a h e i g h t e n e d need to
belong, as after a social rejection, tune their
2. C o g n i t i o n Is A c t i o n O r i e n t e d attention and cognition to process social
information in the e n v i r o n m e n t more care-
Situated cognition offers the key insight that fully and thoroughly (Pickett, Gardner, &
cognition is for adaptive action. Our minds Knowles, 2004). T h e s e and n u m e r o u s other
evolved for the on-line control of behavior examples of biases in cognition caused by
under the demands of survival rather than the perceiver's motivational concerns effec-
for detached puzzle solving or abstract cog- tively illustrate h o w social cognition serves
itation. This principle implies the existence the needs of adaptive action (Brewer, 1991;
THE SOCIAL CONTEXT OF COGNITION 457

Brewer & Harasty, 1996; Gollwitzer 8c Bargh, have strong attitudes, the attitude is auto-
1996; Higgins 8c Sorrentino, 1990; Sorrentino matically activated to color the percep-
& Higgins, 1986). tion of the object and influence judgments
2. Time pressure shapes cognition. Because and actions (Fazio, Sanbonmatsu, Powell, &
cognition is for adaptive action, real-world Kardes, 1986).
pressures such as time constraints often Our impressions of other people are also
impinge on cognitive processes. Social psy- action-oriented representations, containing
chology has a strong tradition of dual- information about how we behave toward
process models, w h i c h specify h o w and or interact with those others (Baldwin, 1992;
when we use heuristics and biases to achieve Carlston, 1994; Holmes, 2000). In fact, differ-
cognitive goals with a minimum of effort, ent people with w h o m the perceiver has the
and how and w h e n we employ more effort- same type of relationship tend to be con-
ful processing (for a review, see Smith & De- fused with one another in memory - to a
Coster, 2000). Carrying on a conversation, greater extent even than different people
for example, is an instance of social cogni- w h o share important social characteristics
tion under time pressure - the pragmatic de- such as age or race - indicating that mental
mands of the situation may limit one's abil- representations of people are structured by
ity to ponder as deeply as might be desired. the types of actions they call for rather than
It is important to recognize that, though by their abstract traits or category member-
heuristic processing has sometimes been ships (Fiske 8c Haslam, 1996).
portrayed as sloppy or intrinsically error In summary, social psychologists have
prone, it is more fruitfully viewed as adap- enthusiastically endorsed the notion that
tive: yielding good-enough results that sat- cognition is oriented toward adaptive action
isfy pragmatic constraints of real-life, action- (Fiske, 1992), and much research has spelled
demanding situations (Gigerenzer, Todd, 8t out concrete implications of this principle
the A B C Research G r o u p , 1999). in such areas as motivated biases in cogni-
3. Mental representations are action-ori- tion, effects of time pressure on cognitive
ented. T h e situated cognition approach sug- processes, and the action-oriented nature of
gests that not only cognitive processing attitudes and other mental representations.
styles but also mental representations should
be action oriented, tuned to the effec-
tive and efficient control of action. Social 3. Cognition Is Embodied
psychological research has supported this
hypothesis as well. T h e attitude, a men- An emphasis on action as the goal of cogni-
tal representation specifying a perceiver's tive activity suggests the importance of the
positive or negative evaluation of an object body - the vehicle of all action - as a con-
or concept, has been considered perhaps straint on cognition. Thus, a second major
the most characteristic and central construct theme of situated cognition is that bodily
of the field (Allport, 1954). Examples of states and sensorimotor representations play
attitudes include antipathy toward specific an important role in all cognition. This issue
social groups (i.e., prejudice), liking for one- has been explored in at least two domains
self (i.e., self-esteem), and liking or dislik- within social psychology.
ing for consumer products, social policies, 1. Sensorimotor aspects of mental repre-
or abstract ideas (e.g., tax cuts, abortion sentations. Attitudes, mental representations
rights). Attitudes are fundamentally action- involving evaluations of objects, have close
oriented representations: their main func- connections to sensorimotor systems related
tion is to tell the perceiver how to relate to approach and avoidance. For instance,
to or interact with the object - whether to muscle movements involving approach and
approach or avoid it, praise or blame it, cher- avoidance have been shown to influ-
ish or damage it. Research shows that when ence evaluative judgments of novel objects
people encounter objects toward which they (e.g., Cacioppo, Priester, & Berntson, 1993).
EUOT R. SMITH AND FREDERIC A R. CONREY

Muscle movements associated with pulling about the perceptual experience of a cat's
an object closer lead to more positive judg- purr, the feeling of its fur, the appearance of
ments, while those associated with push- its movements, and so on, and can reproduce
ing away lead to negative judgments. Other the core aspects of these experiences in the
studies (Neumann & Strack, 2000) present mind to afford categorization, imagination
words on a computer screen over a back- planning, and so on. Barrett (2006) offers a
ground of a rotating spiral pattern. Rota- more detailed and specific account of how
tion in one direction gives an appearance embodied conceptual knowledge combines
that one is moving toward the screen, and with affective states to produce the expe-
rotation in the other direction generates rience of emotion, also applying Barsalou's
the appearance of moving away. When the model.
screen appears to be moving closer, peo- 2. Perception-behavior links. William
ple can classify positive words more quickly, James (1890) was among the first in psychol-
and when the screen appears to be moving ogy to study the ideomotor or perception-
farther away, negative words receive faster behavior link. Recent work in diverse areas
responses. These and similar findings suggest of psychology and neuroscience, at both
that attitudes or evaluations are not just in the neural (Rizzolatti & Arbib, 1998) and
the head but involve the perceiver's whole the behavioral (Dimberg, Thunberg, &
body, being linked to movement toward or Elmehed, 2000) levels, confirms that motor
away from objects in a real physical sense. processes are integral to perception. Within
Going beyond attitudes, Schubert (2004) social psychology, research suggests that
showed that making a fist influences peo- subtle activation of a concept such as polite-
ple's automatic processing of words related ness through reading words related to that
to the concept of power, suggesting that concept actually influences people's overt
even such a highly abstract concept involves behavior, making them act more polite. In a
motoric elements in its representation. similar way, exposure to the concept of the
Recent research by Livingston and Brewer elderly causes people to walk more slowly -
(2002) as well as by Blair, Judd, Sadler, and that is, to behave in a way that is consistent
Jenkins (2002) shows that stereotyping is not with stereotypes about that social group
purely a matter of the application of abstract (Bargh, Chen, & Burrows, 1996). People
knowledge about the characteristics of vari- naturally tend to imitate the expressive or
ous social groups but has strong perceptual incidental behaviors of other people when
elements as well. Stereotypes applied to a they interact with them, and this type of
given person are affected by that person's imitation generally leads to increased liking
continuously varying perceptual attributes (Chartrand & Bargh, 1999). All these effects
(e.g., skin tone, facial features) as well as by show that action-oriented representations
his or her discrete category membership. of behaviors are recruited as we perceive
other people. In other words, we use our
Finally, in a broad theoretical paper,
bodies in the process of social perception.
Niedenthal, Barsalou, Winkielman, Krauth-
Gruber, and Ric (2005) apply Barsalou's
(1999) model of perceptual symbol systems,
sensorimotor-based representations, to var- 4. Cognition Is Situated
ious types of representations studied in
social psychology, including attitudes, social Cognition has sometimes been understood
judgment, and emotions. The perceptual- as implemented by abstract, amodal infor-
symbol systems model proposes that knowl- mational processes that proceed within an
edge is represented by perceptual simula- organism, isolated from the larger context
tors: mechanisms in the mind that simulate except for a narrow set of defined inputs and
multiple variations on the perceptual expe- outputs. The situated cognition approach, of
rience associated with a cognitive object. course, rejects this picture of autonomous,
For instance, the system stores information context-free inner processes in favor of a
THE SOCIAL CONTEXT OF COGNITION 459

view of an organism as involved in intensive Research" (Norenzayan & Schwarz, 1999)-


moment-to-moment interaction with its These participants provided explanations
environment. As we discussed previously, that were relevant in the specific social con-
the physical body plays an important role in text: a communication with a particular type
constraining and affording social cognition, of researcher. The cooperative norms of
but other aspects of the immediate physi- communication (Grice, 1975) require a con-
cal and psychological environment are also stantly evolving representation of the goals
important. Again, social psychology, by def- of the self and of the other people in the
inition, is concerned with the influence of interaction. A smooth completion of the
the situation on cognition. However, a view interaction relies on the participants' abil-
of cognition as infinitely flexible and respon- ity to attend to the context and to select and
sive to the situation lacks predictive power, provide situationally appropriate contribu-
unless we can identify those features of tions.
the environment that are most important in 2. Relational context. Beyond general com-
determining the course of cognition. Social municative norms, our relationships with
psychology's perspective suggests that many specific individuals have important impli-
of the most important features of the cogni- cations for how we process social informa-
tive context are not physical but social. The tion. Research on close relationships, for
immediate, interactive conversational con- instance, reveals the somewhat unsurpris-
text, our relationships with other individu- ing result that we tend to idealize our close
als, and our broader memberships in social others. People's perceptions of their part-
groups represent three levels of interper- ners' attributes are closer to the attributes
sonal context in which cognition and action they believe would be ideal than to their
are situated. partners' actual attributes as indicated by
i. Communicative context. Because social the partner's own self-reports. This bias is
interaction is so complex and so fundamen- socially adaptive: the more we idealize our
tal to our experience, the immediate con- partners - the more inaccurate we are in per-
text, whether we are physically alone or ceiving their characteristics - the more sat-
with others, is often a communicative con- isfied we are with our relationships (Mur-
text. As a result, some of the most perva- ray, Holmes, & Griffin, 1996). We defend
sive and most impactful factors that shape our relationships not only by thinking of our
our cognition are norms of communica- partners as better than they are but also by
tion. Extremely subtle situational cues, if thinking of our alternatives as worse than
they signal communicative relevance of dif- they are. For example, students in commit-
ferent contents, have been found to influ- ted heterosexual relationships rate opposite-
ence behavior and cognition. In social psy- sex targets as less attractive than do their
chology, one well-replicated finding is that single counterparts (Simpson, Gangestad, &
people explain others' behavior in terms of Lerma, 1990).
the actors' inner personality characteristics, Personal relationships regulate cognitive
wants, or beliefs rather than in terms of the and behavioral processes in other ways as
demands of social situations (Gilbert, 1998). well. Just as owners come to resemble their
This tendency has been viewed as auto- dogs (Roy & Christenfeld, 2004), we come to
matic, fundamental, linked to the properties resemble our partners psychologically. Peo-
of abstract mental processes (Ross, 1977). ple tend to choose romantic partners and
Yet in one experiment, participants asked friends who are already similar to themselves
to provide causal explanations for a social (Luo & Klohnen, 2005), and they also tend
event on a questionnaire headed "Institute to grow closer to their significant others in
for Personality Research" provided more their attitudes (Davis & Rusbult, 2001). We
personal and fewer situational explanations are also much more likely to be persuaded
than did participants asked to explain the by people we like than by people we dislike
same phenomena for the "Institute for Social (Cialdini, 1993).
ELIOT R. SMITH AND FREDERICA R. C O N R E V

Although they have been intensively students who reported them when no photo
studied, romantic relationships are not the was present. Our important group member-
only relationships that influence cognition. ships, potentially activated by subtle situa-
In fact, all the people we interact with tional cues, regulate our social attitudes and
affect us in some way. Romantic relation- behavior.
ships are generally positive and lasting, but Social identities serve as much more than
more immediate and less positive relation- guides to our own appropriate behavior,
ships, such as power relationships, also however. Because an identity is a group
influence cognition. White women assigned membership that we share with some peo-
the role of superior in a group interaction ple but not others, it divides the world into
with African American women exhibit more us and them, and shapes how we think about
racial bias than do white women assigned to and behave toward other people. People on
the subordinate role (Richeson & Ambady, the "us" side of the line, fellow group mem-
2003). Positions in the power hierarchy with bers, become better liked (Mullen, Brown,
respect to other individuals affect not only & Smith, 1992). We make positive attribu-
how we think of them but also how we act tions for their behaviors (Pettigrew, 1979),
toward them. These findings illustrate how and we treat them better - more fairly and
cognition and action are influenced not only altruistically (Turner et al., 1987). Further-
by the physical context in which we per- more, just as we tend to think like our sig-
form them but also by the specific individu- nificant relationship partners, we tend to
als with whom we perform them. think like members of our in-groups. We
3. Group context. The point that our are more easily persuaded by in-group than
place in the social context is fundamental by out-group members (Mackie, Worth, 8t
to our cognition is further emphasized by Asuncion, 1990), and we share emotions
the extensive literature on effects of social (Smith, 1993) and attitudes (Norton, Monin,
group memberships. The social context is Cooper, & Hogg, 2003) with members of the
made up not only of our relationships with in-group. We also assume that they are sim-
specific others but also the groups we iden- ilar to us (Robbins 8c Krueger, 2005).
tify with (Turner, Hogg, Oakes, Reicher, People on the "them" side, out-group
& Wetherell, 1987), termed social identities. members, are seen as homogenous (Judd 8c
Social groups establish norms, or standards Park, 1988) and as quite different from us
for correct and appropriate beliefs, opin- (Robbins 8c Krueger, 2005). They are also
ions, and behaviors. For example, it may seen as competitors rather than coopera-
be appropriate to talk about one's salary tors and are likely to become the targets of
woes among a group of friends but not with discrimination (Brewer, 1979). Both being
coworkers. Other norms dictate that men a member of an in-group (Tesser, 1988),
and women ought to differ in their inter- and discriminating against an out-group can
est in sports or their emotional expressive- make us feel better about ourselves (Rubin 8c
ness. Such norms influence our behavior Hewstone, 1998). Thus, any activated social
all the time, whether or not other mem- identity is an aspect of the social situation
bers of the groups are physically present. that can have profound consequences for
When a social identity is activated by situ- how we think and behave, and how we treat
ational reminders of membership or by our the people we interact with. Importantly,
own intentional thought, we tend to con- other group members need not be physi-
form to that group's norms. For example, cally present for our in-group identities to
Baldwin, Carrell, and Lopez (1990) studied form an important, perhaps a fundamental,
Roman Catholic college students and found part of the social context in which our cog-
that their attitudes and behaviors reported nition and behavior are situated.
when a photo of the pope was visible on the Cognition is situated; sometimes this is
wall were more consistent with their reli- taken to mean that it is almost infinitely
gious norms, compared to those of similar flexible and responsive to the physical
t h e social contex t of cognition 421

and psychological context. This flexibil- distributed across objects and the physical
ity sometimes makes it difficult to predict environment, much of our distributed cog-
exactly how the infinitely variable context nition is actually distributed across other
w ill change how we think and behave. A people. Such a distribution occurs when-
social psychological perspective identifies ever people establish and maintain a socially
precisely which features of the environment shared system of meaning. Although this
are particularly important (those that are idea has taken many forms in social psychol-
relevant to immediate conversational con- ogy (for a review, see Thompson & Fine,
texts, ongoing interpersonal relationships,
1999), the idea that people use symbols such
or social group memberships) and allows
as language to facilitate interaction, and that
understanding of h o w those features shape
meanings are dynamically constructed and
cognition and action.
shared in groups, have been driving forces in
the study of group cognition in recent years.
1. Distributed cognition in groups. Mod-
c. C o g n i t i o n Is D i s t r i b u t e d
ern societies rely on committees such as
boards, juries, and management teams to
Our final t h e m e is that cognition is dis-
do a great deal of their important thinking:
tributed: not contained within minds, but
making decisions, managing projects, and
implemented by systems that link minds
developing new ideas. This reliance reflects
with aspects of the physical and social envi-
the idea that group cognition should always
ronment. In other words, cognition is often
be more effective than individual cogni-
enabled by information-processing loops
tion: members of a committee can correct
that pass through the outside world as
one another's errors, recall relevant infor-
well as the mind, via perceptual and motor
mation that others cannot, and in general
processes. O n e familiar illustration of dis-
reach more adaptive final decisions. Y e t
tributed cognition is the fact that most of
research shows that group performance is
us w o u l d have great difficulty multiplying
frequently worse than that of an equal num-
two three-digit numbers in our heads, but ber of individuals working independendy
do it w i t h ease given a pencil and paper. (Levine & Moreland, 1998). What proper-
As we manipulate symbols, these external ties of socially distributed cognition account
resources b e c o m e part of an overall cogni- for this pattern? Might distributed cognition
tive system, functioning as m e m o r y storage, offer advantages in any situation? In fact, the
offering cues f o r w h a t digits to process next, literature on group performance has demon-
and so on. strated that individual minds and interacting
Treatments of distributed cognition, like groups display many similar properties.
this e x a m p l e , have typically focused on One broad conclusion is that groups
how cognition is enabled and scaffolded by tend to show enhanced versions of the
features of the physical environment. For very same biases that affect individuals
example, Kirsch (1995) discussed ways in (Hinsz, Tindale, & Vollrath, 1997). Indi-
which we use space to facilitate cognitive viduals tend to ignore base rate informa-
performance, and Hutchins (1995b) focused tion, overrely on information about repre-
on h o w pilots' perceptual systems and minds sentativeness (Argote, Devadas, & Melone,
interact w i t h the design and layout of cock- 1990), and escalate commitment to an action
pit instruments to track the speed of air- once it has been chosen (Whyte, 1993), but
planes. A l t h o u g h s o m e w o r k arising from all of these effects tend to be even stronger
the situated cognition tradition has exam- in groups than in individuals. Individuals
ined t h e w a y cognition is shared across also tend to demonstrate a confirmation
teams (Hutchins, 1991), group interaction bias in information processing: they partic-
and decision making has b e e n a central focus ularly like and attend to information that
of research w i t h i n social psychology. A n d is consistent with the information or opin-
in reality, w h i l e cognition can certainly be ions they already have (e.g., Frey, 1986).
4<u ELIOT R. SMITH AND FREDERICA R. CONREY

Similarly, groups have a tendency to attend we might need. In e f f e c t , we keep much


more to members whose opinions are consis- of our m e m o r y in other people's heads.
tent with the group's existing opinion. T h e Wegner (1986) called this phenomenon
impact of each member's opinion decreases "transactive m e m o r y . " Transactive memory
as a function of the distance between that has been demonstrated to have important
opinion and the average opinion of the consequences for group performance. For
group (Davis, 1996). Ultimately this process example, training groups together so that
can lead to a destructive uniformity of opin- they form a robust transactive memory sys-
ions within the group, to the disregard of rel- tem tends to lead to better group perfor-
evant evidence, possibly leading to what has mance, compared to training group mem-
been termed grvupthink (Janis, 1997). The bers separately and then bringing them
difference between group thinking and indi- together (Moreland 8c Myaskovsky, 2000).
vidual thinking, then, is generally a matter of Transactive m e m o r y thus represents one
degree. Rather than groups being able to cor- potential mechanism by which groups might
rect individual biases, the general findings be able to attain better performance than
suggest that groups exaggerate those biases. a similar n u m b e r of isolated individu-
als, if its benefits outweigh the increased
Gigone and Hastie (1997) offer a differ-
processing biases characteristic of group
ent perspective that also suggests groups and
cognition.
individuals can be thought of in fundamen-
tally similar ways. In their model, individu- O u r understanding of group-level cogni-
als come to a group discussion with specific tion obviously owes much to our knowledge
items of evidence or information relevant to of individual-level cognition. But the reverse
a decision, and function as information inte- is equally true: distributed cognition, or cog-
grators, combining the implications of those nition in groups, has important implications
items to arrive at their individual opinions. for individual-level cognition. In humans,
In turn, group discussion of the issue allows conscious thought shares important features
the individual opinions to be integrated with group discussion. First, it is mediated
into the overall group decision. Gigone and and structured by language and therefore is
Hastie (1997) do not find that group discus- influenced by the socially shared meaning
sion adds any extra value or emergent qual- inherent in our linguistic structures. Second,
ity to the group decision, besides the sim- intrapersonal thinking, like conversation, is
ple integration of individual opinions. Their temporally constrained; just as only one per-
studies show that the effects of informa- son in a group can express an idea at once,
tional items on the final group decisions are we can only explicitly think one thing at
entirely mediated by the opinions of the a time. Finally and most important, it has
individual members before any discussion been argued that individual-level thought
took place. Like the research on biases dis- follows developmentally f r o m interpersonal
cussed previously, this research suggests that communication, which is prior and primary
there is little qualitative difference between (Vygotsky, 1962/1986). Socially distributed
individual and group-based cognition, with cognition precedes conscious reasoning, so
both functioning essentially as simple infor- thinking (holding conversations with our-
mation integrators. selves) owes m u c h to our ability to have
2. Distributed memory in groups. Despite conversations with other people. From this
the fact that cognition distributed across perspective, it is less insightful to say that
groups is not necessarily better or more group cognition is like individual cognition
accurate than individual cognition, there than it is to observe that individual think-
is no denying that we do distribute our ing is a lot like thinking in groups. Extend-
cognition across other people all the time. ing our understanding of how distributed
Rather than remembering things for our- cognition operates between people should
selves, many of us store information about inform our understanding of individual
w h o knows information or has skills that thought.
the social contextofcognition423

6. C o n c l u s i o n model of simulators as mental representa-


tions) are currently being applied within
\s we hope this chapter has made clear, social psychology (Barrett, 2006; Niedenthal
the topics studied by social psychologists et al., 2005). Increased interchange of this
overlap to a considerable degree with those sort seems highly desirable in view of the
that have interested researchers in the situ- two fields' similar substantive and concep-
ated cognition perspective. The four themes tual concerns.
that organized the discussion in this chap- Social psychology may offer one insight
ter reflect major points of convergence and above all others to readers interested in sit-
uated cognition. That is its emphasis on the
agreement between these two areas. The
social context of behavior - the fact that
two areas also share historical roots. The
human behavior in general takes place in,
fundamental ideas of the situated cogni-
and is adapted to, a rich and complex net-
tion movement go back in various forms
work of group memberships, personal rela-
to Dewey, Mead, and particularly William
tionships, social motives, and the socially
James and Frederick Bartlett. These same
constituted self. This view represents a valu-
individuals are considered as important fore- able supplement to the typical focus on
bears of social psychology, precisely because behavior as situated in the physical environ-
of the similar concerns of that field with the ment (e.g., Kirsh, 1995). Finally and more
social situation and its effects on cognition concretely, the bodies of empirical and the-
and behavior. oretical work in social psychology reviewed
Nevertheless, despite this convergence of in this chapter may be helpful in enriching
interests, it is striking how little interchange researchers' thinking about the nature of sit-
there has been between these two areas to uated cognition in general.
date. For example, Edwin Hutchins (a cog-
nitive anthropologist) insightfully described
distributed cognition in a navigation team References
(1995a), but totally without citations to
highly relevant work from social psychol- Allport, G. W. (1954). The nature of prejudice.
ogy on group processes, team performance, Oxford, UK: Addison-Wesley.
or transactive memory. Many similar exam- Argote, L., Devadas, R., & Melone, N. (1990).
ples exist of researchers from cognitive sci- The base-rate fallacy: Contrasting processes
ence, anthropology, or other disciplinary and outcomes of group and individual judg-
areas investigating topics such as those dis- ment. Organizational Behavior and Human
cussed in this chapter, evidently without Decision Processes, 46(2), 296-310.
realizing that extensive, highly applicable Baldwin, M. W. (1992). Relational schemas and
bodies of theory and empirical findings exist the processing of social information. Psycho-
logical Bulletin, 112(3), 461-484.
within social psychology. On the other side
Baldwin, M. W., Carrell, S. E„ & Lopez,
of the fence, social psychologists often con-
D. F. (1990). Priming relationship schemas:
tinue to develop and apply abstract, disem-
My advisor and the pope are watching me
bodied, nonsituated information processing
from the back of my mind. Journal of
models, with little evident awareness of the Experimental Social Psychology, 26(5), 435-
powerful critiques of such models that have 454-
been o f f e r e d within the situated cognition Bargh, J. A., Chen, M., & Burrows, L. (1996).
movement. Automaticity of social behavior: Direct effects
A f e w instances of productive inter- of trait construct and stereotype activation on
change b e t w e e n these fields are beginning to action. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
emerge. Semin and Smith (2002) and Smith chology, 71(2), 230-244.
and Semin (2004) offered descriptions of Barrett, L. F. (2006). Solving the emotion par-
the overlapping interests of the fields, and adox: Categorization and the experience of
as noted previously, specific models deriv- emotion. Personality and Social Psychology
ing f r o m situated cognition (e.g., Barsalou's Review, 10, 20-46.
ELIOT R. SMITH AND FREDERICA R. CONREY

Barsalou. L. W. (1999). Perceptual symbol sys- Dimberg, U., T h u n b e r g , M . , & Elmehed, K.


tems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22, 577— ( 2 0 0 0 ) . Unconscious facial reactions to emo-
600. tional facial expressions. Psychological Science
Blair. 1. V . , Judd, C. M., Sadler, M. S., & Jenk- 11(1), 86-89.
ins, C. (2002). The role of Afrocentric features Dunning, D . , 8c C o h e n , G. L. ( 1 9 9 2 ) . Egocentric
in person perception: Judging by features and definitions of traits and abilities in social judg-
categories. Journal of Personality and Social ment. Journal of Personality and Social Psychol-
Psychology, 83(1), 5-25. ogy, 6 3 ( 3 ) , 34 1- 355-
Brewer, M. B. (1979). In-group bias in the Fazio, R. H., Sanbonmatsu, D. M., Powell, M.
minimal intergroup situation: A cognitive- C., 8c Kardes, F. R. ( 1 9 8 6 ) . On the automatic
motivational analysis. Psychological Bulletin, activation of attitudes. Journal of Personality
86(2), 307-324. and Social Psychology, 5 0 ( 2 ) , 2 2 9 - 2 3 8 .
Brewer, M. B. (1991). The social self: On being Fiske, A. P., 8c Haslam, N. ( 1 9 9 6 ) . Social cognition
the same and different at the same time. Per- is thinking about relationships. Current Direc-
sonality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 17(5), tions in Psychological Science, 5 ( 5 ) , 1 3 7 - 1 4 2 .
475-482. Fiske, S. T. ( 1 9 9 2 ) . Thinking is for doing: Por-
Brewer, M. B., & Harasty, A. S. (1996). Seeing traits of social cognition from daguerreotype
groups as entities: The role of perceiver moti- to laserphoto. Journal of Personality and Social
vation. In R. M. Sorrentino & E. T. Higgins Psychology, 6 3 ( 6 ) , 8 7 7 - 8 8 9 .
(Eds.), Handbook of motivation and cognition: Fiske, S. T., N e u b e r g , S. L., Beattie, A. E.,
The interpersonal context (Vol. 3, pp. 347-370). & Milberg, S. J. ( 1 9 8 7 ) . Category-based and
New York: Guilford Press. attribute-based reactions to others: Some
Cacioppo, J. T., Priester, J. R., 8c Berntson, G. informational conditions of stereotyping and
G. (1993). Rudimentary determinants of atti- individuating processes. Journal of Experimen-
tudes: II. Arm flexion and extension have dif- tal Social Psychology, 2 3 ( 5 ) , 3 9 9 - 4 2 7 .
ferential effects on attitudes. Journal of Person- Frey, D. ( 1 9 8 6 ) . Recent research on selective
ality and Social Psychology, 65(1), 5-17. exposure to information. Advances in Exper-
Carlston, D. E. (1994). Associated systems theory: imental Social Psychology, 1 9 , 4 1 - 8 0 .
A systematic approach to cognitive represen- Gigerenzer, G . , T o d d , P. M., 8c the A B C
tations of persons. In R. S. J. Wyer (Ed.), Asso- Research G r o u p . ( 1 9 9 9 ) . Simple heuristics that
ciated systems theory: A systematic approach to make us smart. N e w Y o r k : O x f o r d University
cognitive representations of persons (Vol. 7, pp. Press.
1-78). Hillsdale, N J : Lawrence Erlbaum. Gigone, D., 8c Hastie, R. ( 1 9 9 7 ) . T h e impact of
Chartrand, T. L. & Bargh, J. A. (1999). The information on small group choice. Journal
chameleon effect: The perception-behavior of Personality and Social Psychology, 7 2 , 1 3 2 -
link and social interaction. Journal of Personal- 140.
ity and Social Psychology, 76, 893-910. Gilbert, P. ( 1 9 9 8 ) . T h e evolved basis and adap-
Cialdini, R. B. (1993). Influence: Science and prac- tive functions of cognitive distortions. British
tice (3rd ed.). New York: HarperCollins Col- Journal of Medical Psychology, 7 1 ( 4 ) , 4 4 7 - 4 6 3 .
lege. Gollwitzer, P. M., 8c Bargh, J. A. (Eds.). ( 1 9 9 6 ) .
Crowe, E., 8c Higgins, E. T. (1997). Regulatory The psychology of action: Linking cognition and
focus and strategic inclinations: Promotion motivation to behavior. N e w York: Guilford
and prevention in decision-making. Organiza- Press.
tional Behavior and Human Decision Processes, Grice, H. P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In P.
69,117-132. Cole 8c J. L. Morgan (Eds.), Syntax and seman-
Davis, J. H. (1996). Small-group research and the tics (Vol. 3, pp. 4 4 - 5 8 ) . N e w York: Academic
Steiner questions: The once and future thing. Press.
In E. H. Witte 8c J. H. Davis (Eds.), Under- Higgins, E. T., 8c Sorrentino, R. M. ( 1 9 9 0 ) . Hand-
standing group behavior: Consensual action by book of motivation and cognition: Foundations of
small groups (Vol. 1, pp. 3 - 1 2 ) . Hillsdale, NJ: social behavior (Vol. 2 ) . N e w York: Guilford
Lawrence Erlbaum. Press.
Davis, J. L., 8c Rusbult, C. E. ( 2 0 0 1 ) . Attitude Hinsz, V. B„ Tindale, R. S., 8c Vollrath, D.
alignment in close relationships. Journal of A. (1997). T h e emerging conceptualization of
Personality and Social Psychology, 81(1), 65- groups as information processes. Psychological
84 Bulletin, 121, 43-64.
the social contex t of cognition 465

Holmes, J- (2000). Social relationships: The illusions in romantic relationships: Love is not
nature and function of relational schemas. blind, but prescient. Journal of Personality and
European Journal of Social Psychology, 30,447- Social Psychology, 71(6), 1155-1180.
497- Neumann, R., 8c Strack, F. (2000). Approach and
Hutchins, E. (1991)- The social organization of avoidance: The influence of proprioceptive
distributed cognition. In L. B. Resnick & and exteroceptive cues on encoding of affec-
J. M. Levine (Eds.), Perspectives on socially tive information. Journal of Personality and
shared cognition (pp. 283-307). Washington, Social Psychology, 79(1), 39-48.
DC: American Psychological Association. Niedenthal, P, M., Barsalou, L. W., Winkiel-
Hutchins, E. (1995a). Cognition in the wild. Cam- man, P., Krauth-Gruber, S., 8c Ric, F. (2005).
bridge, M A : M I T Press. Embodiment in attitudes, social perception,
Hutchins, E. (1995b). H o w a cockpit remembers and emotion. Personality and Social Psychology
its speeds. Cognitive Science, 19(3), 265-288. Review, 9,184-211.
James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology. Norenzayan, A., 8c Schwarz, N. (1999). Telling
Oxford, UK: Holt. what they want to know: Participants tailor
Janis, I. L. (1997). Groupthink. In R. P. Vecchio causal attributions to researchers' interests.
European Journal of Social Psychology, 29(8),
(Ed.), Leadership: Understanding the dynam-
1011-1020.
ics of power and influence in organizations (pp.
Norton, M. I., Monin, B., Cooper, J., & Hogg,
163-176). Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre
M. A. (2003). Vicarious dissonance: Attitude
Dame Press.
change from the inconsistency of others. Jour-
Judd, C. M., 8c Park, B. (1988). Out-group homo-
nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 85(1),
geneity: Judgments of variability at the indi-
47-62.
vidual and group levels. Journal of Personality
Pettigrew, T. F. (1979). The ultimate attribution
and Social Psychology, 54(5), 778-788.
error: Extending Allport's cognitive analysis
Kirsh, D. (1995) • The intelligent use of space. Arti-
of prejudice. Personality and Social Psychology
ficial intelligence, 73, 31-68.
Bulletin, 5(4), 461-476.
Levine, J. M., 8c Moreland, R. L. (1998). Small
Pickett, C. L., Gardner, W. L., & Knowles, M.
groups. In D. T. Gilbert, S. T. Fiske, & G. (2004). Getting a cue: The need to belong and
Lindzey (Eds.), Handbook of social psychol- enhanced sensitivity to social cues. Personality
ogy (4th ed., Vol. 2, pp. 415-469). Boston: and Social Psychology Bulletin, 30,1095-1107.
McGraw-Hill. Richeson, J. A., 8c Ambady, N. (2003). Effects of
Livingston, R. W . , 8c Brewer, M. B. (2002). situational power on automatic racial preju-
What are we really priming? Cue-based ver- dice. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
sus category-based processing of facial stim- 39(2), 177-183.
uli. Journal of Personality and Social Psychol- Rizzolatti, G., & Arbib, M. A. (1998). Language
ogy, 82(1), 5-18. within our grasp. Trends in Neurosciences,
Luo, S., 8c Klohnen, E. (2005). Associative mating 21(5), 188-194.
and marital quality in newlyweds: A couple- Robbins, J. M., 8c Krueger, J. (2005). Social pro-
centered approach. Journal of Personality and jection to ingroups and outgroups: A review
Social Psychology, 88, 268-278. and meta-analysis. Personality and Social Psy-
Mackie, D. M., Worth, L. ¡g 8c Asuncion, A. G. cholog Review, 9, 32-47.
(1990). T h e processing of persuasive in-group Ross, L. (1977). The intuitive psychologist and his
messages. Journal of Personality and Social Psy- shortcomings: Distortions in the attribution
chology, 58, 812-822. process. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in
Moreland, R. L., 8c Myaskovsky, L. (2000). experimental social psychology (Vol. 10, pp. 174-
Explaining the performance benefits of group 221). New York: Academic Press.
training: Transactive memory or improved Roy, M. M., 8c Christenfeld, N. J. S. (2004). Do
communication? Organizational Behavior and dogs resemble their owners? Psychological Sci-
Human Decision Processes, 82,117-133. ence, 15(5), 361-363.
Mullen, B., Brown, R., 8c Smith, C. (1992). Rubin, M., 8c Hewstone, M. (1998). Social iden-
Ingroup bias as a function of salience, rele- tity theory's self-esteem hypothesis: A review
vance, and status: An integration. European and some suggestions for clarification. Person-
Journal of Social Psychology, 22(2), 103-122. ality and Social Psychology Review, 2(1), 40-
Murray, S. L., Holmes, J. G., 8c Griffin, D. W. 62.
(1996). T h e self-fulfilling nature of positive
e l i o t f t . smith a n d f r e d e r i c a r . c o n r f . v

Schubert, T. W. (2004). The power in your hand: Advances in Experimental Social Psychology,
Gender differences in bodily feedback from
making a fist. Personality and Social Psychology Sorrentino, R. M., S Higgins, E. T. (1986). Hand-
Bulletin, 50(6), 757-769. book of motivation and cognition: Foundations
Semin, G. R., & Smith, E. R. (2002) Interfaces of of social behavior. New York: Guilford Press.
social psychology with situated and embodied Tesser, A. (1988). Toward a self-evaluation main-
cognition. Cognitive Systems Research, 3, 385- tenance model of social behavior. In L.
396. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental
Simpson, J. A., Gangestad, S. W., & Lerma, M. social psychology (Vol. 21, pp. 181-227). San

i
(3990). Perception of physical attractiveness: Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Mechanisms involved in the maintenance of Thompson, L,, & Fine, G. A. (1999). Socially
romantic relationships. Journal of Personality shared cognition, affect, and behavior: A

I
and Social Psychology, 59(6), 1192-1201. review and integration. Personality and Social
Sinclair, L„ & Kunda, Z. (1999). Reactions to a Psychology Review, 3(4), 278-302.
black professional: Motivated inhibition and Turner, J. C., Hogg, M. A., Oakes, P. J., Reicher,
activation of conflicting stereotypes. Journal S. D., & Wetherell, M. S. (1987). Rediscover-
of Personality and Social Psychology, 77(5), 885- ing the social group: A self-categorization theory.
904. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.
Smith, E. R. (1993). Social identity and social Vygotsky, L. (1986). Language and thought. Cam-
emotions. Toward new conceptualizations of bridge, MA: MIT Press. (Originally published
prejudice. In D. M. Mackie & D. L. Hamilton 1962)
(Eds.), Affect, cognition, and stereotyping: Inter-Wegner, D. M. (1986). Transactive memory: A
active processes in group perception (pp. 297- contemporary analysis of the group mind. In
315). San Diego, CA: Academic Press. B. Mullen & G. R. Goethals (Eds.), Theories
Smith, E. R., & DeCoster, J. (2000). Dual-process of group behavior (pp. 185-208). New York:
models in social and cognitive psychology: Springer-Verlag.
Conceptual integration and links to under- Whyte, G. (1993). Escalating commitment in
lying memory systems. Personality and Social individual and group decision making: A pros-
Psychdogy Review, 4(2), 108-131. pect theory approach. Organizational Behav-
Smith, E. R., & Semin, G. R. (2004). Socially situ- ior and Human Decision Processes, 54(3), 430-
ated cognition: Cognition in its social context. 455.
C H A P T E R 25

Cognition for Culture

Felix Warneken and Michael Tomasello

Organisms inherit their environments as about and explore the environment while
much as they inherit their genes. Indeed, still under the protection of parents (Bruner,
biological adaptations come into existence 1972). Within this general learning-life-
ontogenetically "expecting" a certain envi- history strategy, some species also develop
ronment: fish are born with fins, expecting skills of social learning that enable individu-
water; bats are born with sonar, expecting als to take advantage of the knowledge and
caves. S o m e organisms even modify their skills of group mates when that is to their
environments, and then their progenitors benefit as well (Boyd &. Richerson, 1985).
biologically adapt to the new environment Humans rely on learning and social learning
(so-called niche construction; Odling-Smee, perhaps more than any other species, and
Laland, & Feldman, 2003). For example, ants this both enables their unique form of cul-
have evolved various skills for living in the tural organization and is an adaptation to it.
anthills that they (i.e., their forebears) have What all of this adds up to is an observa-
built. tion banal in behavioral biology but not suf-
H u m a n beings are big-time niche con- ficiendy appreciated in cognitive psychol-
structors, of course, with the added twist ogy: it makes no sense to speak of cognitive
that different groups of humans construct skills independent of the environmental con-
very different niches (a.k.a. cultures), and so texts within which they evolved and oper-
the species as a w h o l e cannot be adapted to ate. With specific reference to humans, our
a particular constructed environment ahead proposal here is that most, if not all, of the
of time. T h e solution is flexible learning unique features of human cognition evolved
and cognitive skills that enable individu- as adaptations to humans' unique form of
als to acquire information locally and to cultural organization, that is, as adaptations
make decisions based on that information to a self-constructed niche involving coop-
without m i c r o m a n a g e m e n t from Mother erative social practices with group mates
Nature. T h i s typically requires a long period and their material and symbolic artifacts.
of immaturity so that the young can learn Clearly this is not all there is to human

467
t i l 1\ w a r n i k f n a n d m i c h a e l TOMASELLO

cognition, «s many human skills evolved C h i m p a n z e e s a n d o t h e r primates have


in the context of such things as foraging failed all sorts of e x p e r i m e n t s testing their
(e.g., skills of object recognition, manipula- ability to d e t e r m i n e t h e perceptions, inten-
tions, and b e l i e f s of o t h e r s (for overviews
tion, categorization, and quantification), and
see Povinelli, Bering, & G i a m b r o n e , 2000-
other human skills evolved in the context of
T o m a s e l l o & C a l l , 1997). For e x a m p l e , they
competitive interactions with group mates did not s e e m to take t h e visual perception of
over food, mates, and other resources (e.g., others into a c c o u n t as t h e y indiscriminately
the understanding of goal-directed action). begged f o r f o o d f r o m h u m a n s w h o either
However, our argument is that humans have could or c o u l d n o t see t h e m (Povinelli &
also evolved some unique cognitive skills for Eddy, 1996), and t h e y did n o t understand a
cooperating and communicating with oth- human's c o m m u n i c a t i v e intention to indi-
ers culturally. That is, humans are adapted cate the location of h i d d e n f o o d by look-
ing and pointing at it ( f o r an overview, see
for special kinds of cooperative and com-
Call & T o m a s e l l o , 2005). Importantly, in all
municative interactions that require them
of these studies, t h e c h i m p a n z e e s interacted
to take multiple perspectives on things, and with a cooperative e x p e r i m e n t e r w h o would
ultimately, through some kind of internal- provide (rather than h i d e ) information and
ization process, to develop so-called per- act for (rather than against) them. How-
spectival cognitive representations - which ever, these c o o p e r a t i v e situations might not
are taken for granted in cognitive psychol- c o m e as naturally to t h e m as they come
ogy but are actually unique in the animal to humans. C o n s e q u e n t l y , H a r e (2001) pro-
kingdom (Tomasello, 1999). posed that t h e c h i m p a n z e e m i n d is espe-
cially adapted f o r c o m p e t i t i v e encounters
In this chapter, we argue and provide evi- and will thus d e m o n s t r a t e its peak perfor-
dence for this view of the evolution of the mance in c o m p e t i t i v e rather than cooper-
unique features of human cognition and cul- ative situations. T h u s , w h e n H a r e and col-
ture. After a brief evolutionary introduc- leagues placed a d o m i n a n t and a subordinate
chimpanzee in c o m p e t i t i o n over f o o d - with
tion, we do this, first, by looking closely
some pieces of f o o d visible to both individ-
at the process of human cognitive develop-
uals and some only to t h e subordinate - the
ment, especially in its early social and cul- subordinates w e r e m o r e likely to go for the
tural aspects, and then by comparing human f o o d that w a s hidden f r o m t h e dominant's
social-cognitive skills to those of our nearest view (Hare, Call, A g n e t t a , 8c Tomasello,
primate relatives, the great apes, who share 2000; Hare, Call, 8c T o m a s e l l o , 2001). Relat-
some but not all of our skills for navigating edly, chimpanzees also try to conceal their
through a complex social world. o w n approach to contested f o o d by select-
ing paths on w h i c h t h e competitor cannot
see or hear t h e m w h e n t h e y steal the food
1. Primate and Human Social (Hare, Call, Sl T o m a s e l l o , 2006; Melis, Call,
& Tomasello, 2006). T h u s , chimpanzees can
Cognition and Learning interpret w h a t others see and how that
affects their intentional actions (see also
Nonhuman primates are intensely compet- Call, Hare, Carpenter, & Tomasello, 2004)
itive creatures, and so they have evolved but mainly in the c o n t e x t of competitive
uniquely complex social-cognitive skills for social interactions. T a k e n together, these
competing with group mates for food, and a number of other studies provide evi-
mates, and other valued resources. Follow- dence that chimpanzees actually do under-
ing Humphrey (1976), the social cognition of stand important aspects of intentional action
primates has been characterized by appel- and perception (Tomasello, Call, & Hare,
lations such as primate politics (de Waal, 2003; but for a different v i e w , see Povinelli
1982) and Machiavellian intelligence (Byrne
& Whiten, 1988). This competitive orienta-
tion becomes especially clear when we look
at experiments aimed at testing nonhuman
primates' theory of mind.
cognitionf o rculture47»

& Vonk, 2003). The fact that the majority of facts": such entities as marriage, money, and
situations eliciting these skills are competi- government, which are of course uniquely
tive in nature reveals something fundamen- human and exist only through the shared
tal about the chimpanzee mind; namely, practices and beliefs of a group.
that it is mainly adapted for competitive The evolutionary processes for this
rather than for cooperative social interac- unique adaptation are still unclear, but it
tions. Accordingly, Tomasello, Carpenter, is possible that premodern humans devel-
Call, Behne, and Moll (2005) have proposed oped these skills of shared intentionality,
two distinct biological adaptations under- which enabled more complex forms of
lying human social-cultural cognition. The cooperation, ultimately leading to the cul-
first concerns the understanding of inten- tural organizations characteristic of mod-
tional action and perception, a pathway em humans. These cooperative motivations
that humans share to a large extent with might have originated in nuclear fami-
chimpanzees and that evolved in the con- lies (Wrangham, Jones, Laden, Pilbeam, &
text of intraspecific competition. The sec- Conklin-Brittain, 1999) and spread as selec-
ond concerns the skills and motivations to tion pressures favored individuals possess-
ing these skills because groups pooling their
share these psychological states with others,
individual efforts outcompeted other groups
which very likely is unique to humans and
(Richerson 8c Boyd, 2005; Sober 8c Wilson,
evolved in the context of intensely coopera-
1998).
tive social activities of a particular kind.
Our proposal is thus that the human Ontogenetically, human children grow
primate has evolved - on top of its com- up in the midst of all of these cooperative
petitive skills and propensities - additional activities. Their emerging understanding of
skills and motivations for interacting with shared intentionality enables them to partic-
others cooperatively. Specifically, humans ipate in an increasing number of interactions
engage with one another in cooperative involving joint attention, cooperative com-
activities characterized by shared intention- munication, the use of artifacts and sym-
ality (Bratman, 1992; Gilbert, 1989; Searle, bols, as well as normative social practices
1990, 1995; Tuomela, 1995). Shared inten- (the way we "ought" to do it). This under-
tionality refers to activities in which partici- standing cannot be taken for granted, and
pants have a shared goal and jointly coordi- indeed there are some individuals who are
nate their actions to pursue that goal (joint not equipped biologically to leam to partic-
intentions) - and both represent the entire ipate in cultural activities. These are indi-
interaction cognitively. This cognitive repre- viduals with autism. Children with autism
sentation reaches beyond an understanding grow up in essentially the same environment
of the intentions the other individual might as other children, but because of their bio-
have (she intends to do x by means of y) logical deficit, they cannot participate in the
in that so-called we-intentions are formed. cultural and symbolic activities around them
Specifically, in we-intentions the intentions in the species-typical manner. The develop-
of each participant include something of the ment of human cognitive skills thus depends
intentions of the other (we intend to do x both on a species-typical cultural environ-
by means of me doing y, and you doing y 2 ). ment and on biologically evolved skills for
This embedded intentional structure char- participating meaningfully in such an envi-
acterizes simple activities such as lifting a ronment.
heavy stone together, as well as complex
activities such as building a house or play-
ing a symphony. When people share inten-
tions with one another repeatedly in partic-
2. The Ontogeny of Cultural Cognition
ular social contexts, this results in habitual
Perhaps the best place to observe the
social practices and beliefs that create what
unique aspects of human cognition is in
Searle (1995) calls "social or institutional
human infants and young children, as their
f e l i x w a r n e k e n a n d michael t o m a s e l l o
47°

species-typical cognitive skills are first begin- participating (Ross & Lollis, 1987). Infants of
nine to emerge. Comparison to nonhuman this age also are able to reverse roles with
primates helps to identify what are indeed an adult in a joint activity, demonstrating
the species-unique aspects. their understanding of the different roles
involved (Carpenter, Tomasello, 8t Striano,
2005). In a set of more naturalistic observa-
Cooperative Activities in the Second i Bakeman and Adamson (1984) found
\ ear of Life that already in the first half of the second
Human children do not just go around pur- year, infants are active participants in joint
suing their own individual goals; they also activities. In a longitudinal study, they iden-
are interested in and concerned for others. tified a considerable increase of coordinated
Thus, starting at around their first birth- joint engagements in free-play situations at
days, infants show concern for others in home from fifteen to eighteen months of
distress and occasionally comfort them (for age. The category coordinated joint engage-
an overview, see Eisenberg & Fabes, 1998). ment denotes triadic interactions between
In experimental studies, infants at eigh- a child, an adult, and an external object
teen months of age - and to some extent or event, in which the child not only fol-
even fourteen-month-olds - perform spon- lows the adult's lead but also actively directs
taneous acts of helping (Warneken & the adult's attention. This shows that even
Tomasello, 2006) by, for example, helping before language acquisition has begun in
an adult retrieve an out-of-reach object or earnest, young children become increasingly
opening the doors of a cabinet for him or more active partners in joint activities in
her. To engage in these helpful acts, the which they conceive of their own and a part-
children had to both understand the other's ner's actions and attentions as directed at a
unachieved goal and be motivated to altruis- third object and each other,
tically help her to achieve it. This shows that However, in one-year-olds, coordinated
young children can use their understanding social actions remain restricted to rather rit-
of intentional action not only to learn from ualized games. W h e n approaching the sec-
others (imitation) or to predict the other's ond year of life, children begin to generate
next move in a competitive situation (as bouts of coordinated social actions also in
chimpanzees) but also to actually act altru- simple nonritualized contexts, as shown in
istically for another person. Young, human- a series of studies by Eckerman and col-
raised chimpanzees may also in some situ- leagues (for an overview, see Eckerman &
ations be helpful to humans (Warneken & Peterman, 2001). T h e y do this mainly by
Tomasello, 2006). what the authors called the "imitative pat-
But whereas in helping it is sufficient sim- tern," as the partners imitate each other's
ply to understand another individual's indi- actions in a turn-taking sequence. In a study
vidual goal, truly cooperative activities are by Warneken, C h e n , and Tomasello (2006),
based on shared intentionality, with partners children at eighteen to twenty-four months
coordinating interdependent roles directed of age were able to cooperate with an adult
at a shared goal. The first steps in this partner in both novel social games and
direction are taken when infants at around problem-solving tasks. For example, in one
one year of age engage in ritualized games task, the partners had to perform comple-
such as peekaboo or rolling a ball back and mentary roles like one person holding a con-
forth, which rely on scaffolding by an adult tainer open so that the other could retrieve
(Gustafson, Green, & West, 1979; Ratner & the object from inside. Interestingly, when
Bruner, 1978; Ross & Lollis, 1987). Infants the partner interrupted in the middle of the
appear to understand that these social inter- activity (as in the study of Ross 81 Lollis,
actions involve interdependent actions, as in 1987), children of both age groups frequently
one study they prompted their adult part- communicated to the partner in an attempt
ner to continue the game when she stopped to request his or her cooperation. All
cognition for culture 47»

children produced at least one such commu- comprehensible by the listener, even clar-
nicative attempt. This shows that the chil- ifying (helping) when necessary; and the
dren understood their own and their part- listener cooperates by making good-faith
ner's action as interconnected parts of a attempts to comprehend the speaker's com-
joint activity. On a generous interpretation, municative intention and ask for clarifica-
this can also be taken as evidence that they tions (help) where necessary. These two
were trying to redirect the partner toward a roles are actually directly embodied in
shared goal, insisting on the commitment to the main conventional devices that human
support each other's actions in a cooperative beings have created for the purpose of com-
activity. munication, linguistic symbols, which are
Between eighteen and twenty-four bidirectional in the sense that both speaker
months, children's behavioral skills in co- and listener can switch roles in using the
ordinating their actions with a partner in symbol to influence the other's behavior that
time and space improve remarkably, as they influence themselves (Mead, 1934).
shown by Eckerman (e.g., Eckerman, 1993) To comprehend and produce such con-
and Warneken et al. (2006). This also marks ventional communicative means, especially
the phase during which children become nonlinguistic ones such as pointing, inter-
able to solve problems cooperatively with actants have to create some shared frame
same-aged peers. In a study by Brownell of reference (common ground, joint atten-
and Carriger (1990, 1991), children at tional frame) in which these means become
eighteen months virtually always failed in meaningful in specific situations. A point by
problem-solving tasks with complementary itself means nothing. For instance, if I point
roles where one child had to manipulate an at a drawer, you will probably be confused,
apparatus so that the other could retrieve but if we both know together that you are
an object, but children at two years solved looking for your glasses, you would immedi-
the tasks successfully over repeated trials. ately comprehend my meaning. You under-
Thus, despite the small number of studies in stand that my communicative intention is
this age group, we may tentatively conclude to change your intentional act of searching
that in the first half of the second year of for the glasses by providing new informa-
life, children already understand the basic tion. Such comprehension depends not only
joint intentional structure of cooperative on the ability to grasp the embedded struc-
activities in social games and problem solv- ture of a communicative intention but also
ing, and their improving behavioral skills on the ability to understand the cooperative
during the second half of the second year motive behind it - that you are doing this
of life enable them to establish coordinated for me to help me find the object.
interactions in a wider array of contexts This cooperative structure becomes
with different social partners. apparent already in the preverbal commu-
nicative exchanges in which infants start
to participate shortly after their first birth-
Cooperative Communication day - in terms of both their comprehension
in the Second Year of Life and their production. On the comprehen-
Human communication is an inherendy sion side, infants begin to follow another
cooperative activity (Clark, 1996). When person's gaze direction and pointing ges-
tures, interpreting such cues as communica-
human beings converse with one another
tive means to inform them about objects
they are playing the complementary roles
and events in the world. For example, in
of speaker and listener, and each does his
one study Behne, Carpenter, and Tomasello
or her part toward the shared goal of the
(2005) played a hiding and finding game in
listener comprehending the speaker's com-
which the experimenter hid a toy in one
municative intention. The speaker cooper- of two locations and then, addressing the
ates by expressing his or her communica- infant through eye-contact, indicated the
tive intentions in ways that are potentially
454 felix warneken and michael t o m a s e l l o

correct location by either gazing or point- with a distracter object. When the adult
ing at it. Already at fourteen months of age, wanted to resume his action (e.g., picked
infants chose the correct location, indicating up his papers ready to staple), he discov-
that they used the experimenter's commu- ered the stapler missing and looked quizzi-
nicative cues to find the toy. Importantly, cally around. Twelve- and eighteen-month-
this was not an automatic gaze- or point- old infants pointed more often to the target
following response, but rather resulted from than the distracter object, presumably to
an actual understanding of the commu- help the adult find what he needed. In sum
nicative intentions behind it. Thus, when starting at one year of age, infants point for
the adult produced similar surface behav- three main reasons: imperatively, with the
iors, but without expressing the commu- goal of having the other do something for
nicative intent to inform them (e.g., the them; declaratively, to share attention to
index finger directed at the target, but only and interest in external objects and events1
because the experimenter was looking at and informatively, in which their pointing is
her wristwatch), infants searched randomly. directed at helping others with their goal.
The infant constructed with the adult a joint These acts of preverbal communication
activity in which he or she represented that can be seen as ontogenetic forerunners to
what we are doing together is playing a game fully linguistic communication in that the
in which I search for a toy and you help me basic structure of human communication
find it - and so the looking and pointing is is already in place. In comprehending and
taken as a communicative means to inform expressing communicative intentions, in-
me of the location. fants demonstrate an understanding of the
On the production side, it is in the same complementary roles of recipient and infor-
age range when infants make their first mant of a communicative act. In performing
nascent attempts to express their own com- either role, they can take the other person's
municative intentions in putatively simple role into account and can switch between
gestures such as pointing. First of all, infants them, at one time requiring information (see
point imperatively with the goal of having Behne et al., 2005) and at other times being
an adult do something for them, like hand the informant themselves (see Liszkowski
them an object. This has been described as et al., 2006). Linguistic communication adds
a situation in which they use the other per- in the perspectival component inherent in
son as a tool that can make certain things linguistic symbols as different choices for
happen (Bates, 1979; Bates, Camiaoni, & construing a situation.
Volterra, 1975). Second, they point declar- In general, human infants begin quite
atively to influence others' attention. When early to participate in cooperative activi-
they see something interesting happening, ties involving the sharing of psychological
they often point this out to adults and states with others (e.g., attention toward
seem to expect them to comment back: or information about aspects of the world).
they do not seem satisfied when the adult In some theories, these interactions then
attends only to the object or only to the become internalized in a Vygotskian fash-
infant, as they repeat their point under ion: comprehension of the external social
these circumstances (Liszkowski, Carpen- interaction leads to an internal cognitive rep-
ter, Henning, Striano, & Tomasello, 2004). resentation. Our proposal is that social inter-
Thus, these declarative points are aimed actions involving shared intentionality lead
at sharing attention and interest in exter- specifically to what we have called "dialogic
nal objects and events. Third, infants some- cognitive representations" (Tomasello et al.,
times point to provide information for oth- 2005; see also Fernyhough, 1996). In dia-
ers. In a study by Liszkowski, Carpenter, logic cognitive representations, each partici-
Striano, and Tomasello (2006), an adult was pant conceives the activity holistically, with
using some kind of instrument, for exam- the shared goal and both roles (including
ple, a stapler, which got misplaced together its perspective) in a single representational
cognition f o r culture 47»

format. These representations then enable isms observe others repeatedly in the same
children's full participation in cultural (me- situations, they can predict what they will
diated) practices such as linguistic commu- do next on the basis of simple association
nication and other forms of symbolic inter- and memory. But if they are to predict what
action with an interpersonal structure.
others will do in novel situations, they must
know what the others are trying to do (their
->. C h i l d r e n a n d C h i m p a n z e e s : F r o m goal) and what they can perceive in the
U n d e r s t a n d i n g to Sharing Intentions world around them.
With regard to the understanding of
Comparing the cognitive skills of human goals, the critical test involves exposing sub-
children and chimpanzees - one of two jects to a situation in which the environ-
closest relatives — is instructive because it mental outcome produced by an actor's
helps us to identify those aspects of human action does not match with his goal. For
cognition that were already present in the example, Meltzoff (1995) had young chil-
common evolutionary ancestor of the two dren observe an actor try but fail to put a
species from those aspects that developed ring on a hook. Eighteen-month-old infants
only in the human lineage. Such a com- attempted to bring about the desired but
parison might also enable us to identify the unobserved goal (ring on hook) rather than
social cognitive prerequisites for participat- the undesired but observed end state (ring
ing in a human culture, including in the falling down) (twelve-month-olds do not do
comparison here of chimpanzees that have this [Bellagamba & Tomasello, 1999] but
been raised by humans in a human envi- fifteen-month-olds do [Johnson, Booth, &
ronment, including exposure to artifacts and O'Hearn, 2001]). In the study of Tomasello
language. Interaction with humans may lead and Carpenter (2005), when the three young
chimpanzees to adopt some more human- chimpanzees were tested with the same pro-
like skills of social behavior than is typical for cedure with a set of several novel objects
their wild conspecies (the so-called encul- (including control conditions), they repro-
turation hypothesis; Call & Tomasello, 1996; duced the intended acts rather than the
Tomasello & Call, 2004). failed attempts, indicating that they were
actually able to interpret the demonstrator's
For making our summary comparison, we
actions in terms of his goals. The same three
will rely on data from three studies involv-
chimpanzees showed their understanding of
ing the same three human-raised chim-
goal-directed action also in a similar study in
panzees between one and five years of age:
which they successfully reproduced actions
Tomasello and Carpenter (2005), Warneken
an actor produced on purpose while basi-
and Tomasello (2006), and Warneken et
cally ignoring those he produced by accident
al. (2006). T h e tasks in these studies were
(signaled by the vocal marker "Whoops!"; for
generally modeled after experiments with
the original study with fourteen-month-old
human children and were focused on two
infants, see Carpenter, Akhtar, & Tomasello,
dimensions of social cognition: (1) the basic
1998).
understanding of goal-directed action and
Beyond the realm of social learning, there
perception, and (2) the ability to participate
is another context in which the understand-
in cooperative and communicative interac-
ing of unachieved goals is crucial: helping.
tions involving shared intentionality.
To successfully help another person, one
has to have not only an altruistic motiva-
tion but also an understanding of the goal
Understanding of Goal-Directed Action that the other cannot achieve. To test this,
and Perception the helping tasks developed for the human
Perhaps the most fundamental skill of pri- infant study were adapted for the three
mate social cognition is the understanding of human-raised chimpanzees (Warneken 8t
intentional action and perception. If organ- Tomasello, 2006). As it turned out, all three
454 FELIX WARNEKEN AND MICHAEL TOMASELLO

chimpanzees helped the human caregiver attend to specific aspects of things in their
by handing her objects she was unsuccess- perceptual field. Studies with human infants
fully reaching for - for example, after she have shown that from around twelve to
had accidentally dropped them on the floor fourteen months of age they know that oth-
(and did not bring them when she had dis- ers selectively attend to things that are new
carded them intentionally). However, the to them. For example, in a study by Moll
chimpanzees did not help in the other kinds Koring, Carpenter, and Tomasello (2006), an
of situations with more complex goals (e.g., adult looked at a single object and exclaimed
completing the stacking of objects, opening excitedly, "Oh, w o w , look at that!" When
a door for the other). These findings support the object was old for the adult - both
the interpretation that chimpanzees are able child and adult had played together with
to understand goal-directed action, at least the object - the children inspected the side
when the goal is easy to discern, as in situ- of the object or looked for something else
ations in which a person is reaching for an in the room, possibly because they assumed
object. that the adult could not refer in such an
excited way to the object as a whole that
Just to round out the picture, we
she already knew quite well. On the other
should also report that several other studies
hand, when the object was new to the
also demonstrate that other chimpanzees
adult, the children did not display such
can distinguish accidental from intentional
searching behavior presumably because they
actions and trying and failing from suc-
thought the adult was excited about the
ceeding (see Call et al., 2004; Call &
new object as a whole. When the three
Tomasello, 1998; Uller, 2004). Taken to-
chimpanzees were tested with essentially
gether, these results demonstrate that chim-
the same method, they inspected the object
panzees understand important aspects of
indiscriminately of whether it was new or
intentional action, and they even do this on
old to the experimenter.
some occasions outside of competitive sit-
uations - namely, when learning about the Overall, then, the three human-raised
properties of new objects and when helping chimpanzees demonstrated an understand-
another person to achieve a goal. ing of perception - they know what oth-
With regard to visual perception, it is well ers see even when that differs from what
known that many nonhuman primates fol- they themselves see - but they did not
low the gaze direction of others to targets understand that humans selectively attend
(Tomasello et al., 1998). As did the chim- to things depending on what is new to them.
panzees in the study of Tomasello, Hare, This failure might be because chimpanzees
and Agnetta (1999), the three human-raised simply do not understand that humans get
chimpanzees followed the gaze direction of excited about new rather than old things.
a human to hidden locations behind barriers. It is also possible, however, that human
When an experimenter was alternating gaze infants but not chimpanzees can distinguish
between the chimpanzee and an object that between aspects of the world that they have
the chimpanzee could not see because the and have not previously shared with others
view was obstructed by some kind of opaque in episodes of joint attention (see Moll &.
barrier, the chimpanzee locomoted behind Tomasello, 2004). Thus, their failure in this
the barrier to see what the experimenter was task might reflect their general lack of skills
looking at. Thus, these three chimpanzees and motivation for joint attention (see the
knew that others see things that they them- subsequent section).
selves cannot see, similarly to human infants
at twelve months of age (Moll 8t Tomasello,
Understanding Shared Intentionality
2004).
However, despite the understanding of Chimpanzees in the wild do many things
what others can or cannot see, the same sub- in small groups, including hunting for mon-
jects did not seem to understand that others keys (Boesch & Boesch-Achermann, 2000).
cognitionf o rculture47»
47»

In experimental studies, chimpanzees will 2005). The interpretation here is that human
work together, under some circumstances, children - but not chimpanzees - under-
to obtain food, demonstrating in the process stand joint activities from a bird's-eye view
an understanding that the partner is needed in which the shared goal and both roles are
and selecting the partners that work best part of one representational format, and so
(Melis et al., 2006). These behaviors from easily reversed if needed.
the wild and the laboratory could all be In terms of cooperative communication,
called "cooperative," in the general sense of it is very interesting that chimpanzees basi-
the term, but it is not clear whether they are cally never point out things to one another,
underlain more specifically by shared goals show things to one another, or instruct
and intentions; that is, by skills and motiva- one another intentionally (Tomasello, 2006).
tions for shared intentionality. Human infants do these things from around
Warneken et al. (2006) adapted the four their first birthdays, demonstrating a strong
cooperation tasks from their experiment motivation to share experience with oth-
with children to test the three human- ers. Chimpanzees do, however, sometimes
raised chimpanzees on their skills to engage point to things they want for humans. Thus,
in cooperative activities with their human Tomasello and Carpenter (2005) found
caregiver. The chimpanzees were able to that all three of their human-raised chim-
solve problem-solving tasks with food as tar- panzees produced communicative gestures
get object (e.g., by lifting a door so that the from early in life. However, all of the
partner could retrieve it for them), but they gestures by the three human-raised chim-
showed no interest in social games with no panzees were imperatives for action, such
external goal as such. Most important, when as pointing to distant objects to have the
the partner interrupted the activity by not human retrieve it for them. Similarly, all
performing her role, the chimpanzees never three chimpanzees used more proximal ges-
once attempted to reengage her actions. tures such as giving a closed container to
The chimpanzees instead tried to solve the their caregiver when they could not open
task alone or disengage from the task com- it themselves. By contrast, they never once
pletely, which suggests that they did not produced a declarative gesture such as show-
conceive of the activity as one involving two ing or pointing to share interest in an object
roles directed at a shared goal. This stands or an event, behaviors that are very com-
in stark contrast to the human children at mon in human infants from around twelve
eighteen and twenty-four months of age, months of age.
who reliably produced such reengagement With regard to comprehension of com-
attempts. municative gestures, there is no indication
Similarly, the three chimpanzees did not that the three chimpanzees understood that
show evidence for role-reversal in simple pointing can be used to inform others of
social games such as one person holding out things in the world. They were tested in
a plate and the other placing an object on top a situation very similar to the hiding and
(Tomasello & Carpenter, 2005). The chim- finding situation by Behne et al. (2005) used
panzees performed either action but did not with human infants. When a piece of food
perform it in a manner that could be inter- was placed under one of two opaque con-
preted as an overt invitation to the part- tainers, they randomly chose either one of
ner to take her turn. In contrast, human them, unable to use communicative cues
children at eighteen months - occasionally by the experimenter who indicated the cor-
already at twelve months - reverse roles rect location by pointing at it, or, in a vari-
spontaneously. When they start out with ation of this, placing a marker on top (for a
one role (e.g., placing the object on top), review of other studies coming to the same
they switch to the other role of holding out conclusion, see Call & Tomasello, 2005).
the plate for the partner, with an expectant Thus, in contrast to one-year-old infants, the
look to the other's face (Carpenter et al., chimpanzees were unable to interpret the
454 454felixwarnekenandmichaelt o m a s e l l o

cooperative communicative gestures of oth- others are situated in social interactions,


ens. One interpretation for this is, again, Our proposal is that primates, in general,
that they did not view the interaction as developed skills for understanding inten-
a cooperative activity in which the other tional action and perception in the context
expresses the communicative intention to of competitive social interactions, and this
inform them about something. enabled all kinds of new skills for predicting
Interestingly, when the situation was and manipulating the behavior of others,
framed as a competitive one, chimpanzees In addition, human beings also devel-
were suddenly successful. Hare and Toma- oped some additional skills of social cogni-
sello (2004) tested mother-reared chim- tion to create and participate in highly coop-
panzees by directly comparing a competitive erative social interactions involving shared
and a cooperative version of the task. When intentionality. These species-unique social-
they saw a competitor (human or chim- cognitive skills enabled the creation, over
panzee) unsuccessfully reaching for one of historical time, of all kinds of very differ-
two containers with a hand gesture very ent cultural practices and artifacts in whose
similar to pointing, they were able to infer midst human children in different cultures
that this was the one containing food and develop ontogenetically today. Following
chose accordingly when it was their turn. Vygotsky, we can posit that the internal-
However, when a cooperative experimenter ization of these interactions leads to some
pointed to the correct container, the same new forms of dialogic or perspectival cog-
subjects chose at random. Thus, they were nitive representations. These new forms of
able to read the competitor's intention to cognitive representation are fundamentally
snatch the food but did not understand social in nature, involving both shared and
the communicative intention to inform differentiated perspectives on a single set
them of the correct location. Once again, of entities, so that one and the same entity
one proposal to account for this difference may be simultaneously construed in differ-
is that this communicative situation is fun- ent ways, under different descriptions, for
damentally cooperative and therefore not different purposes. Such perspectival cogni-
mastered by the chimpanzees. Coopera- tive representations are taken for granted in
tive gestures involving sharing information cognitive science - all theories of knowledge
become meaningful only under the premise representation assume t h e m as a matter of
that the subject views the gesture as part of course - but in fact there is no evidence that
a joint activity, in which the gesturer is shar- any other species develops such representa-
ing information with them. Thus, although tions (Tomasello, 1999). O u r proposal is that
chimpanzees are able to read the perception perspectival cognitive representations are an
and goals of others, a critical skill in the con- ontogenetic product resulting f r o m humans'
text of competitive interactions, they seem unique biological adaptation for social inter-
evolutionarily less well prepared to partici- actions involving shared intentionality, and
pate in cooperative activities that are based that other species do not have such repre-
on sharing attention and intentions with sentations because t h e y are not adapted for
others. such social interactions.
Thus, we see here the basic human cul-
tural dialectic: biologically evolved skills for
4. C o n c l u s i o n social interaction enable the creation of cul-
tural artifacts and practices, which then
From an evolutionary perspective, cognition structure the ontogeny of each new gener-
is always situated. In the case of humans in ation of children. C h i l d r e n internalize the
particular, many cognitive skills are situated use of these cultural artifacts and practices,
in individual activities of locomotion, per- and the social interactions in w h i c h they are
ception of the physical and social worlds, mastered, resulting in the kinds of perspecti-
manipulation of objects, and so forth. But val cognitive representations that distinguish
47»
cognition for culture

human cognition from that of all other ani- intellect in monkeys, apes, and humans. New
mal species. A full understanding of any York: Oxford University Press.
aspect of h u m a n cognition thus requires an Call, J., Hare, B., Carpenter, M., 8c Tomasello,
understanding of the ecological contexts - M. (2004). Unwilling or unable: Chimpanzees'
in this case the social and cultural contexts - understanding of human intentional action.
within w h i c h it has evolved and developed. Developmental Science, 7, 488-498.
Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (1996). The effect of
humans in the cognitive development of apes.
In A. Russon, K Bard, & S. Parker (Eds.),
References Reaching into thought: The minds of the great
apes (pp. 371-403). Cambridge: Cambridge
Bakeman, R., & Adamson, L. B. (1984). Coor- University Press.
dinating attention to people and objects in Call, J., 8c Tomasello, M. (1998). Distinguish-
mother-infant and peer-infant interaction. ing intentional from accidental actions in
Child Development, 55(4), 1278-1289. orangutans [Pongo pygmaeus], chimpanzees
Bates, E. (1979). The emergence of symbols: Cogni- (Pan troglodytes), and human children (Homo
tion and communication in infancy. New York: sapiens). Journal of Comparative Psychology,
Academic Press. 112(2), 192-206.
Bates, E., Camiaoni, L., 8c Volterra, V. (1975). Call, J., 8c Tomasello, M. (2005). What do
The acquisition of performatives prior to chimpanzees know about seeing revisited: An
speech. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly, 21, 205- explanation of the third kind. In N. Eilan, C.
224. Hoerl, T. McCormack, 8c J. Roessler (Eds.),
Behne, T., Carpenter, M., 8c Tomasello, M. Joint attention: Communication and other
(2005). One-year-olds comprehend the com- minds (pp. 45-64). Oxford: Oxford University
municative intentions behind gestures in a Press.
hiding game. Developmental Science, 8(6), 492- Carpenter, M., Akhtar, N., 8c Tomasello,
499. M. (1998). Fourteen- through 18-month-old
Bellagamba, F., 8c Tomasello, M. (1999). Re- infants differentially imitate intentional and
enacting intended acts: Comparing 12- and 18- accidental actions. Infant Behavior Si Develop-
month olds. Infant Behavior &É Development, ment, 21(2), 315-330.
22(2), 277-282. Carpenter, M., Tomasello, M., 8c, Striano, T.
Boesch, C., 8c Boesch-Achermann, H. (2000). The (2005). Role reversal imitation in typically-
chimpanzees of the Tax forest: Behavioural ecol- developing infants and children with autism.
ogy and evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Infancy, 8, 253-278.
Press. Clark, H. (1996). Uses of language. Cambridge:
Boyd, R., 8c Richerson, P. (1985). Culture and Cambridge University Press,
the evolutionary process. Chicago: University de Waal, F. B. M. (1982). Chimpanzee politics:
of Chicago Press. Power and sex among apes. London: Jonathan
Bratman, M. (1992). Shared cooperative activity. Cape.
Philosophical Review, 101(2), 327-341. Eckerman, C. O. (1993). Toddlers' achievement
Brownell, C. A., 8c Carriger, M. S. (1990). of coordinated action with conspecifics: A
Changes in cooperation and self-other differ- dynamic systems perspective. In L. B. Smith 8c
entiation during the second year. Child Devel- E. Thelen (Eds.), A dynamic systems approach
opment, 61(4), 1164-1174. to development: Applications (pp. 333-357).
Brownell, C. A., & Carriger, M. S. (1991). Collab- Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
orations among toddler peers: Individual con- Eckerman, C. O., & Peterman, K. (2001).
tributions to social contexts. In L. B. Resnick, Peers and infant social/communicative devel-
J. M. Levine, 8c S. D. Teasley (Eds.), Per- opment. In G. Bremner 8c A. Fogel
spectives on socially shared cognition (pp. 365- (Eds.), BlackweU handbook of infant develop-
383). Washington, DC: American Psychologi- ment (pp. 326-350). Maiden, MA: Blackwell
cal Association. Publishers.
Bruner, J. (1972). The nature and uses of imma- Eisenberg, N., 8c Fabes, R. A. (1998). Proso-
turity. American Psychologist, 27, 687-708. cial development. In W. Damon 8c N. Eisen-
Byrne, R. W., 8c Whiten, A. (1988). Machiavellian berg (Eds.), Handbook of child psychology:
intelligence: Social expertise and the evolution of Social, emotional, and personality development
454 felix warneken and michael t o m a s e l l o

(5th ed., Vol. 5, pp. 701-778). New York: John Meltzoff, A. N. (1995). Understanding the inten-
Wiley & Sons. tions of others: Re-enactment of intended acts
Femvhough, C. (1996). The dialogic mind: A dia- by 18-month-old children. Developmental Psy-
logic approach to the higher mental functions. chology, 31, 838-850.
New Ideas in Psychology, 14, 47-62. Moll, H., Koring, C., Carpenter, M., &
Gilbert, M. (1989). On social facts. London: Rout- Tomasello, M. (2006). Infants determine what
ledge. others attend to by pragmatics and exclusion.
Gustafcon, G. E., Green, J. A., & West, M. J. Journal of Cognition and Development, 7(3),
(1979). The infant's changing role in mother- 411-430.
infant games: The growth of social skills. Moll, H., 8c Tomasello, M. (2004). Twelve- and
Infant Behavior Sd Development, 2(4), 301- 18-month-old infants follow gaze to spaces
308. behind barriers. Developmental Science, 7(1),
Hare, B. (2001). Can competitive paradigms F1-F9.
increase the validity of social cognitive exper- Odling-Smee, F. J., Laland, K. N., 8c Feldman,
iments on primates? Animal Cognition, 4,269- M. W. (2003). Niche construction. The neglected
280. process in evolution. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
Hare, B., Call, J., Agnetta, B., 8c Tomasello, M. University Press.
(2000). Chimpanzees know what conspecifics Povinelli, D. J., Bering, J., 8c Giambrone, S.
do and do not see. Animal Behavior, 59, 771- (2000). Toward a science of other minds:
785. Escaping the argument by analogy. Cognitive
Hare, B., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2001). Do Science, 24, 509-541.
chimpanzees know what conspecifics know? Povinelli, D. J., 8c Eddy, T. J. (1996). Chim-
Animal Behavior, 61,139-151. panzees: Joint visual attention. Psychological
Hare, B., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2006). Chim-| Science, 7,129-135.
panzees deceive a human competitor by hid- Povinelli, D. J., 8c Vonk, J. (2003). Chimpanzee
ing. Cognition, 101(3), 495~5H- minds: Suspiciously human? Trends in Cogni-
Hare, B., 8c Tomasello, M. (2004). Chimpanzees tive Sciences, 7,157-160.
are more skillful in competitive than in coop- Ratner, N., 8c Bruner, J. (1978). Games,
erative cognitive tasks. Animal Behavior, 68, social exchange and the acquisition of lan-
571-581. guage. Journal of Child Language, 5(3), 391-
Humphrey, N. (1976). The social function of 401.
intellect. In P. Bateson & R. A. Hinde (Eds.), Richerson, P. J., & Boyd, R. (2005). Not by genes
Growing points in ethology (pp. 303-321). Cam- alone: How culture transformed human evolu-
bridge: Cambridge University Press. tion. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Johnson, S. C., Booth, A., 8c O'Hearn, K. (2001). Ross, H. S., 8c Lollis, S. P. (1987). Communica-
Inferring the goals of a nonhuman agent. Cog- tion within infant social games. Developmental
nitive Development, 16, 637-656. Psychology, 23(2), 241-248.
Liszkowski, U., Carpenter, M., Henning, A., Stri- Searle, J. (1990). Collective intentions and
ano, T., 8c Tomasello, M. (2004). Twelve- actions. In P. Cohen, J. Morgan, 8c M.
month-olds point to share attention and inter- Pollack (Eds.), Intentions in communication
est. Developmental Science, 7, 297-307. (pp. 401-415). Cambridge, M A : MIT Press.
Liszkowski, U., Carpenter, M., Striano, T., 8c Searle, J. (1995). The construction of social reality.
Tomasello, M. (2006). Twelve- and 18-month- New York: Free Press.
olds point to provide information for others. Sober, E., 8c Wilson, D. S. (1998). Unto others: The
Journal of Cognition and Development, 7, 173- evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior.
187. Cambridge, M A : Harvard University Press.
Mead, G. H. (1934). Mind, self, and society. Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. human cognition. Cambridge, M A : Harvard
Melis, A. P., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2006). University Press.
Chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes) conceal visual Tomasello, M. (2006). W h y don't apes point?
and auditory information from others. Journal In N. Enfield 8c S. Levinson (Eds.), Roots
of Comparative Psychohgy, 120(2), 154-162. of human sociality (pp. 506-524). New York:
Melis, A. P., Hare, B., & Tomasello, M. (2006). Berg.
Chimpanzees recruit the best collaborators.
Tomasello, M., & Call, J. (1997). Primate cogni-
Science, 311(5765), 1297-1300.
tion. New York: O x f o r d University Press.
COGNITION FOR CULTURE 479

Tomasello, M., & Call, J. (2004). The role of direction geometrically. Animal behavior,
humans in the cognitive development of apes 5 (4). 769-777-
8

revisited. Animal Cognition, 7, 213-215. Tuomela, R. (1995). The importance of us: A philo-
Tomasello, M., Call, J., & Hare, B. (1998). Five sophical study of basic social notions. Stanford,
primate species follow the visual gaze of CA: Stanford University Press.
conspecifics. Animal Behavior, 55(4), 1063- Uller, C. (2004). Disposition to recognize goals
1069. in infant chimpanzees. Animal Cognition, 7,
Tomasello, M., Call, J., & Hare, B. (2003). Chim- 154-161.
panzees understand psychological states: Wameken, F., Chen, F., & Tomasello, M. (2006).
The question is which ones and to what Cooperative activities in young children and
extent. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, 153- chimpanzees. Child Development, 77(3), 640-
156. 663.
Tomasello, M., & Carpenter, M. (2005). The Wameken, F., & Tomasello, M. (2006). Altruis-
emergence of social cognition in three young tic helping in human infants and young chim-
chimpanzees. Monographs of the Society for panzees. Science, 311(5765], 1301-1303.
Research in Child Development, 70(1). Wameken, F., & Tomasello, M. (2007). Helping
Tomasello, M., Carpenter, M., Call, J., Behne, T., and cooperation at 14 months of age. Infancy,
& Moll, H. (2005). Understanding and sharing »(3)- 271-294.
intentions: The ontogeny and phylogeny of Wrangham, R. W., Jones, J. H., Laden, G., Pil-
cultural cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sci- beam, D., 8c Conklin-Brittain, N. (1999). The
ences, 28(5), 675-691. raw and the stolen: Cooking and the ecology
Tomasello, M., Hare, B., & Agnetta, B. (1999). of human origins. Current Anthropology, 40(5),
Chimpanzees, Pan troglodytes, follow gaze 567-594.
CHAPTER 26

Neuroethology

From Morphological Computation to Planning

Malcolm A. Maclver

Introduction As a combination of the laboratory sci-


ence of neurobiology and the field observa-
Neuroethology is a field devoted to under- tion science of ethology, neuroethology has
standing the nervous system through the significant challenges, including determining
broader contexts of evolution, natural his- how much of the ecological context of an
tory, ecology, and everyday behavior; in animal is necessary or practical to import
other words, it is the study of situated ner- into the laboratory (for a review, see Pfluger
vous systems. Its focus is on how neural sys- & Menzel, 1999). Once the animal and its
tems subserve behaviors that an animal per- reduced environment are in the laboratory,
forms in its natural habitat, such as capturing another problem to be solved is how to
prey and evading predators, finding a mate, extract, from its continuous and highly irreg-
and navigating through its domain. Often ular activity, a particular behavior to focus
the nervous system is examined in animals on. One way that this issue has been dealt
that exhibit extraordinary specializations in with historically (Pfluger & Menzel, 1999)
behavior, such as sonar-emitting bats and is through avoidance of learned behaviors in
fish that hunt by detecting changes in a favor of highly stereotyped innate behaviors.
weak, self-generated electric field, because More recently, neuroethology has embraced
such specializations result in specialized model systems for studying limited forms of
neural circuitry, making neuron-level anal- learning, such as the zebra finch (Marler,
yses more tractable. These experimentally 1991), which learns its song from a tutor
tractable animals are sometimes referred to only during the first thirty-five days of life.
as "model systems." People generally prefer After this period, the song is "crystallized"
to work with an established model system and does not vary.
so that they can build on a body of knowl- With a behavior identified and character-
edge that has already been gathered about ized, the next step is to uncover its puta-
the system. tive neural basis. Here a new set of issues
neuroethology 4&1

comes into play, centered on the technical work in the first instance? Even if you do
difficulty of obtaining reliable recordings of not believe that the properties of interest in
the electrical activity of the animal's ner- neuroethology relate to cognition, how the
vous system. Often this may not be fea- tension between the outside-the-body ten-
sible unless the animal is under anesthe- dencies of ethology and the inside-the-head
sia. Options include working on a "reduced tendencies of neurophysiology plays out
prep," in which slices of brain, dissociated in neuroethology is alone instructive. That
cells, or whole parts of the nervous system these aspects can be in tension needs further
may be placed into a chamber where they explanation; otherwise one might think that
can be perfused with oxygen, nutrients, or this is simply a matter of groups of scientists
neuroactive drugs and stabilized for record- working on different parts of a big problem,
ing. A better approach, comparatively rare where everyone recognizes that a division of
because of its technical difficulty, is implant- labor is practical and necessary. Neurophys-
ing one or more permanent recording elec- iological approaches often implicitly suggest
trodes in the brain, mounted on a platform that many, perhaps most, components of
that is glued to the head with the signals sent the nervous system can be understood with-
out via cables or wirelessly; this technique out examining an animal's larger context,
is called "chronic recording." Such tools at be it behavioral, biomechanical, or evolu-
best monitor the ongoing activity of one to tionary. In contrast, neuroethologists believe
hundreds of cells in networks that can con- that unless the larger context is understood
sist of millions of cells (and only the electri- - for example, by quantifying the profile
cal activity, at that). Larger-scale properties, of sensory signals that an animal is subject
spanning multiple networks, biomechan- to in its habitat or by placing neural char-
ics, and behavior, are sometimes examined acters of related animals into phylogenetic
through the development of computer mod- trees ("neurocladistics") - many aspects of
els of individual components that are then neural function will not be understood.
recombined in computo in simulation envi- Exemplifying this point, in several model
ronments, an endeavor sometimes referred systems neuroethologists have found that
to as "computational neuroethology" (Chiel neural circuits involved in sensory process-
& Beer, 1997; Cliff, 1995). This then is the ing exhibit very different response proper-
neuroethologist's modus operandi: find an ties when they are subjected to naturalistic
animal offering certain experimental conve- stimuli than to the nonnaturalistic stim-
niences such as behavioral specializations, uli more commonly used in neurobiology,
identify and quantify a behavior, and mea- because these are easier to generate and
sure its neural correlates, if possible in the manipulate experimentally (see Sharpee
"awake, behaving animal," or if not, in some et al., 2006, and references therein).
reduced preparation while delivering stimuli In view of these considerations, in the first
similar to those occurring during the identi- part of the chapter I will discuss how the
fied behavior. tension between the inward- and outward-
Neuroethology has several aspects that looking approaches of neuroethology may
will be of interest to the situated cognition be resolved through excising bits of the
community. Because ethology is all about world and encapsulating them into virtual
what goes on when an animal is embedded reality apparatuses in the laboratory. In the
in its environment (consider the title of an second part of the chapter I will argue that
important monograph of one of its founders: results from neuroethology do, in fact, relate
The Animal in Its World [Tinbergen, 1972]), to cognition. Here I will first detail results
and neurobiology is all about what goes on in from studies of morphological computation
the brain, often with only cursory attention that expose the computational role of shape
to matters beyond the periphery of the head, and structure in animal bodies in adaptive
how can the enterprise of neuroethology behavior, and then I will describe some
soo malcolm a. mac1ver

recent results concerning the neuroethol- animals that - like miners wearing head-
ogy of prey-capture behavior that may give lamps - provide their own source of illu-
insight into the origin of the paradigmat- mination for perceiving their dark envi-
ically cognitive faculty of planning. I will ronments: sonar-emitting bats and electric
argue that the evolution of sensing systems field-emitting fish (Figure 26.1a and 26.1c).
that enable animals to perceive their envi- For both model systems a substantial part
ronment far beyond the bounds of where of the sensory system exists in the interplay
they are immediately moving, possessing a between generated signals and objects in
buena vista, if you will, is key to the origin of the environment (Nelson & Maclver, 2006).
planning. I call this the Buena Vista Sensing
Thus, a fundamental part of the literature is
Club hypothesis. Through planning, mem-
devoted to describing and analyzing how the
bers of the Buena Vista Sensing Club are
self-generated signals propagate and interact
able to make better use of this space in the
with the environment - characterizing the
guidance of their behavior than their more
sensory system as it operates outside of the
reactive mala vista brethren.
body of these animals (on bats, see Boonman
& Jones, 2002; Ghose & Moss, 2003; Hartley
8c Suthers, 1989; Miller & Surlykke, 2001; Par-
1. Internalism, Externalism, a n d sons, Thorpe, 8c. Dawson, 1997; Schnitzler,
V i r t u a l W o r l d s in N e u r o e t h o l o g y Moss, 8c Denzinger, 2003; on fish, see Assad,
Rasnow, 8c Stoddard, 1999; Chen, House,
The methodological and philosophical basis Krahe, 8c Nelson, 2005; Rasnow, 1996; Ras-
of neuroethology takes the situatedness of now 8c Bower, 1996). Recently, this work has
organisms as a basic fact and works forward been referred to as research into the sensory
from there. Both traditional cognitive sci- ecology of an animal (Barth 8c Schmid, 2001;
ence and much of neurobiology differ in Dusenbery, 1992). In these studies, the ner-
emphasis, focusing on what goes on in the vous system of the animal may hardly be
head (Clark, 1997; Hutchins, 1995; Noe, 2004; mentioned.
Rowlands, 1999; Wilson, 1995). This cran- Whereas the externalist tendencies of
iocentric approach often goes by the label neuroethology have their most literal form
of "internalism." What is variously called in the context of this work on the active-
"situated cognition," "embodied cognition" sensing model systems of bats and weakly
(Ballard, Hayhoe, Pook, & Rao, 1997; Hauge- electric fish, the focus on the relevant
land, 1998), "distributed cognition," "senso- aspects of the external world in behavior is
rimotor accounts of perception" (O'Regan pervasive in the discipline, from characteri-
& Noe, 2001), "active externalism" (Clark zation of odor plumes for studies of moths
& Chalmers, 1998), "enactive externalism" (Murlis, Willis, 8c Carde, 2000) to recon-
(Noe, 2004), and "wide computationalism" struction of what a fly sees while it is buzzing
(Wilson, 1994) all share the view that the around in an open field (van Hateren, Kern,
properties of interest can depend on the Schwerdtfeger, 8c Egelhaaf, 2005). As point-
head plus body plus environment. I will refer ed out by James J. Gibson (1979, p. 57), the
to these different approaches as "external- pioneer of ecological approaches to percep-
ism." tion, mechanical signals in the environment
Although situatedness is basic to neu- (stress, strain, pressure, inertia, gravity, fric-
roethology, as alluded to in the introduc- tion, drag) are no less important in under-
tion, it is true that its two contributing dis- standing behavior than are sensory signals
ciplines pull in different directions: ethology in the environment. Neuroethologists there-
to externalism and neurobiology to inter- fore have an increasing stake in investigat-
nalism. H o w is this tension resolved in ing mechanical factors with respect to both
neuroethology? Consider investigations into the animal and the environment (e.g., Chiel
the sensory systems of two popular model 8c Beer, 1997; Dickinson, 1996; Full 8c T u ,
systems in neuroethology, both nocturnal 1991; Maclver, Fontaine, 8c Burdick, 2004).
NEWROETHOLOGY
483

Figure 26.1. Sensory volumes of different active sensing animals,


a. Bat echolocation beam; the illustrated range is the estimated
detection range for small prey (mosquitoes) averaged across several
bat species, b. Dolphin; the illustrated range is the estimated
detection range for a prey-sized, water-filled sphere, c. Weakly
electric fish; the illustrated range is the estimated detection range
for small prey (water fleas), d. Rat whisker system. Reproduced
with permission from Nelson and Maclver (2006).

In parallel with sensory ecology, I refer to case. My argument is not that the important
this as an animal's "mechanical ecology." properties of interest depend on the brain
Those with internalist leanings should not alone, which internalism would insist on (at
fear, however. First, there is the safe refuge least for cognitive properties). Instead, often
of the cognitive; to take this refuge, the the properties very definitely do depend
internalist would argue that what we are on the brain plus body plus environment,
considering here are not cognitive proper- but the elements of the causal chain that
ties in the first instance, whereas only the are most resistant to being understood are
notion that cognition depends on the brain largely in the brain and body alone, in part
was at issue. I will return to this point later. for mundane technical reasons such as acces-
Aside from this defense from the irrelevance sibility to measurement. Evidence for this
of neuroethology, recall that the modus claim is that, in some cases, we have the
operandi of the neuroethologist is to even- capability to mimic the animal's world in
tually relate natural behaviors to neuronal such a way that the animal does not know
structures. This is done by recording neu- any better. I will present three examples
ral activity either in awake, behaving ani- of virtual worlds used in neuroethologi-
mals or, more often, in fixed and anes- cal research that exemplify this point (Fig-
thetized, or otherwise drastically reduced, ure 26.2) for studies of insects, fish, and
forms (e.g., brain slices). "Aha!" our internal- mammals. These virtual worlds pass the
ist interlocutor will exclaim, "Now we get to embodiment Turing test - animals situated
the important business: what you are really in them happily converse with the proxy as
interested in is what goes on in the brain; if it were the real deal.
you're not stuffing recording electrodes into The first example is from work at the
the environment, are you?" There is some Max Planck Center for Biological Cybernet-
sense to the internalist's intuition in this ics, in Tübingen, Germany, in the late 1960s.
Figure 26.1. Three virtual worlds in neuroethology. a. Reichardt's
closed-loop apparatus for the study of optomotor responses in
house flies (Reichardt & Wenking, 1969). The fly is tethered on a
rigid rod that senses the torques generated by the fly as it steers left
or right and moves the surrounding visual panorama
complementary to the motions that would naturally result from
those torques. Modified from Reichardt and Poggio (1976). b. A
closed-loop apparatus for the study of electromotor responses in
weakly electric fish. The fish is held in the center of the tank either
by mechanical constraint (not shown) or paralyzed by a drug and
placed into a holder (not shown). Two graphite rods parallel to the
fish deliver an electric field similar to what a nearby fish would
emit. By bringing the frequency of the delivered field close to that
of the fish in the tank (monitored via the vertical graphite rods), an
electromotor behavior, the jamming-avoidance response, is
triggered and sustained by following the fish's frequency changes.
Similar to the apparatus in Watanabe and Takeda (1963). c. A
closed-loop apparatus for studying the behavior of rats, based on
Dahmen's (1980) similar device for insects and Götz and Gambke's
(1968) servosphere. The ball is suspended by an air cushion. The
animal walks while tethered to a force and torque sensor, whose
signals are measured to alter the real time video projected onto the
rat's visual surround. From Holscher et al. (2005) with permission.

During that time, Werner Reichardt used a control of the stimulus and quantification of
preexisting system for recording the turn- behavior.
ing torque generated by flies that are fly- The second example involves the elicita-
ing while rigidly affixed to the end of a thin tion of an interesting electromotor behavior
rod (Figure 26.2a}. In his apparatus, the mea- in weakly electric fish. These fish discharge
sured turning torque was transformed into a their weak electric field at a particular fre-
rotation of the surrounding visual panorama quency that is both species specific and indi-
with an angular velocity proportional to the vidual specific. When two fish happen across
torque (Figure 26.2a; Reichardt & Poggio, each other in their native habitat while dis-
1976; Reichardt & Wenking, 1969), so that charging within a f e w hertz of each other,
when the fly turned to the left or right, the they will shift their discharge frequencies
surrounding visual scene changed appropri- (via a motor nucleus in the brain) to avoid
ately. This approach has been heavily used jamming their electrolocation systems. To
in studies of fly behavior, from the neu- study this behavior, a fish is placed in a
ral basis of optomotor behaviors to learning tank and fixed in place either mechanically
and flight mechanics, as it enables precise or by paralysis, using a drug (Figure 26.2b).
NEUROETHOLOGY 4»5

The fish's electric field is recorded, and plus the given part of the world. Neverthe-
a field that is slightly higher or lower in less, the externalist may be given pause by
frequency than its field is introduced into considering the success of virtual-reality sys-
the tank, eliciting the jamming-avoidance tems in neuroethology. These demonstrate
response (Watanabe & Takeda, 1963). The that we understand the relevant couplings
approach used here is again closed loop, to the external world in select cases in a suf-
because any changes in output frequency ficient - not to say complete - way, whereas
by the fish are monitored and used to ad- we have a long way to go to understand the
just the frequency of the jamming stimu- internal goings-on of the brain and body.
lus so that the behavior can be continuously
elicited. Using this method combined with
neurophysiology, the jamming avoidance 2. Is Neuroethology Relevant
response became the first vertebrate behav- to Situated Cognition?
ior whose complete neural circuit from sen-
sory input to motor output was understood I had mentioned that one way a cogni-
(Heiligenberg, 1991). tively inclined person might assert that
The third example, also originally devel- neuroethology is not relevant to cognition
oped in the late 1960s at the Max Planck is by arguing that the processes under con-
Center, is from studies by Karl Götz and sideration are not cognitive. That is, given
others: an insect would walk on a sphere that many cognitive scientists hold that the
that counterrotates in such a way that the extension of cognition itself outside of the
animal is always in one place, again greatly usual human case is controversial (Wilson
simplifying the measurement of behavior & Clark, this volume), how can results on
with video and the delivery of controlled the zoo of small animals that neuroethol-
stimuli. The original version, called a "ser- ogy studies provide insight into situated
vosphere," tracked the animal's location and cognition? The difficulty of bridging these
fed the movement back to two motors that two domains is exemplified by the mis-
rotated the sphere so that the animal stayed match between the cognitive capacities we
roughly at the apex of the sphere (Götz & attribute to humans with those attributes
Gambke, 1968; Kramer, 1975; Vaijü, 1975). A of nonhuman animals that are sanctioned
more recent variation (Figure 26.2c) does not by neuroethology. The attributions of neu-
use motors but instead has the animal teth- roethologists have a distinctly mechanistic
ered above the apex of a hollow sphere that flavor, such as "encodes stimulus amplitude
is suspended by an air cushion and rotated with neuron spike rate" or "rotates head
by the animal's own movements (Dahmen, to zero azimuth to target by comparing
1980; Holscher, Schnee, Dahmen, Setia, 81
the intensity of sounds between the ears"
Mallot, 2005). It comes as no surprise that
or, on a behavioral level, "advertises fit-
two of these three examples stem from an
ness to a potential mate by the complex-
institute devoted to cybernetics. For more
ity of the song." Cognitive faculties, such
details on this tradition see Eliasmith (this
as remembering, planning, and deliberating,
volume).
have their clearest form in conscious, occur-
One response to these examples would rent thought processes in humans, and their
be that this proves the internalist's point - presence in nonhuman animals is not often
the world does not matter; all one needs is broached by neuroethologists.
to synthesize and input the right kind of Nonetheless, an attraction of external-
signals. However, Alva Noe (2004, p. 224) ist approaches such as situated cognition
makes a convincing case that far from being a is their ecumenical approach to all kinds
triumph of internalism, the success of virtual of phenomena that have been previously
reality scenarios is precisely what an exter- barred from the tent of cognition. Accord-
nalist should hope for: it demonstrates that ing to Adams and Aizawa (this volume), this
the elicited behavior depends on the brain more open approach is confused and results
gg MALCOLM A. MACIVER

from externalists (i) making the error of slid- dencies on the external world and causal
ine from "x is causally coupled to a cognitive proximities to the cognitive. I should state
act" to "cognition is constituted by x," and (2) at the outset that this is not meant to be
failing to dearly differentiate cognitive from a representative set of results; most of neu-
noncognitive processes. An example they roethology consists of detailing the opera-
give of the first error is to make the jump tion of neuronal circuits that support natural
from the fact that the reading of a ther- behaviors, and these will not be discussed,
mostat is causally coupled to room temper- Even the preceding virtual-world examples
ature to the notion that the thermostat is are not representative of neuroethology as a
constituted by the room-thermostat system. whole because the discipline has a strong
Similarly, they would argue, the fact that bias toward sensory systems and sensory
the cognitive act of long division with paper acquisition, with only a f e w active systems
is causally coupled to the piece of paper for the study of motor function apart from
is a fallacious basis for asserting that cog- the ones presented, such as research into the
nition is constituted by the human-paper neural network responsible for chewing in
system. However, unless one leaves cogni- crustaceans. This bias may be in part due
tion as an unanalyzed whole, it will have to there being too f e w closed-loop appa-
causally coupled subcomponents. Of these ratuses like those described previously, all
parts it would be correct, presumably, to of which require a considerable amount of
make the move from causal coupling to con- engineering expertise. For a more represen-
stitution; in a case like this, the thermostat tative sampling of neuroethology, I refer the
really would be constituted by the room- reader to Web sites of neuroethology courses
thermostat system. The key issue, therefore, (Hopkins, 2005; Maclver & Nelson, 1996),
is the proper characterization of what counts surveys (Barth & Schmid, 2001; Carew, 2000;
as cognition. Because this is poorly defined Hughes, 1999; Land & Nilsson, 2002; Zupanc,
at present, I will take the strategy of consid- 2004), and conference proceedings of the
ering causal proximity to cognition, in the International Society of Neuroethology.
hope that although we may not have a clear Under the rubric of morphological com-
definition of cognition, we have some intu- putation, I will give the example of how
ition about when we are closer to it or fur- the ears of bats perform a signal processing
ther away from it. We have clear intuition, function by dint of their convoluted shape,
for example, that the central processing unit and how the geometry of the fly compound
in a computer is more proximal to a com- eye may allow for the efficient extraction of
putation performed by the computer than is self-motion from the optic-flow field. These
the table on which the computer is resting. two examples concern how the earlier men-
Sinularly, the most compelling examples of tioned sensory ecology of an animal, the
situated cognition are examples in which ambient set of behaviorally relevant signals
some bit of the world plays a central role: in an animal's habitat, is interwoven with
for example, the use of external objects such preneuronal signal processing. I then briefly
as maps during navigation (Hutchins, 1995), discuss bilateral symmetry, a ubiquitous fea-
racks of letter tiles in Scrabble to remember ture of animal body plans, and the passive
words (Maglio, Madock, Raphaely, Cher- walker, a robotic model of human walking
nicky, & Kirsh, 1999), and paper and pen to that consists of only rigid links and joints and
manipulate numbers (Zhang & Wang, 2005). yet is able to walk with a human gait. Both
In these cases, one can reasonably argue that are examples of how the mechanical ecology
drawing the boundary of the cognitive at the of an animal (the ambient inertia, stiffness
skin is arbitrary (Clark & Chalmers, 1998). and compliance, drag or contact friction, and
With these considerations in mind (if not, so on, of the animal and its coupling to the
perhaps, in the head), I will present results habitat) is interwoven with locomotion and
from neuroethology with a range of depen- control of position.
NEUROETHOLOGY

Figure 26.3. A potpourri of bat pinnae. Ear-shape data and


rendering courtesy of Rolf Mueller. The pinna is the outer ear; the
tragus is the small pointed flap of tissue coming up from the base of
the pinna.

These two examples of morphological esis may also be a useful step in articulating
computation highlight the importance of an empirical approach to the evolution of
transneuronal processes in sophisticated sig- consciousness.
nal processing and mechanical capabilities.
However, the capabilities at issue are distant
2.1. Morphological Computation
from more familiar examples of cognition.
Following the section on morphological 2 . 1 . 1 . BAT EARS
computation, I try to partially close the gap Bats have been a staple model system of
by exploring how recent work on the neu- neuroethology since Galambos and Griffin
roethology of prey capture may give insight (1940) first elucidated the role of self-
into one potential origin of the paradigmat- generated acoustic emissions in their noc-
ically cognitive faculty of planning. On the turnal hunting behavior. In the intervening
basis of this work, I will argue that the sen- years, a host of laboratories have investi-
sory transcendence of the space of imme- gated how bats are able to perform their
diate movement provides a core basis of high-precision, high-speed prey-capture
planning, an idea that I call the Buena Vista maneuvers in total darkness by using acous-
Sensing Club hypothesis. Given prior dis- tic pulses, emitted from either the nose or
cussions of the relationship between plan- mouth. The bat is a very successful example
ning and consciousness (Bridgeman, 1992, of an active-sensing system (eight hundred
2003), the Buena Vista Sensing Club hypoth- echolocating species worldwide), in which
mal.col.m a. macivgr
an animal perceives the world via a self- formation of skin and supporting tissue of
generated signal source (Nelson & Maclver, the ear in the bat f o r m s a computational
2006}. From a signals perspective this is a device that solves a key p r o b l e m in the local-
remarkable feat, because all active-sensing ization of prey in three-dimensional space,
animals must overcome spherical spread-
ing ( r ) losses as a signal propagates away 2.1.2 THE GEOMETRY OF THE FLY EYE
from diem, as well as spherical spreading Movement through space creates a pattern
losses from the target back to the source, of visual information called "optic f l o w . " As
resulting in quartic attenuation of the signal you m o v e f o r w a r d through space, things to
with distance. Thus, to double their sensing the side seem to m o v e b a c k w a r d . T h e rate at
range, active-sensing animals need to gen- which they m o v e b a c k w a r d is a function of
erate a signal at least sixteen times more your distance to t h e m , t h e horizontal angle,
powerful (Nelson & Maclver, 2006). As they and your velocity: things l o o m i n g directly
hunt for prey, bats emit pulses of acous- ahead seem to hardly m o v e at all. If y o u are
tic energy at frequencies of thirty kilohertz rolling around the axis of f o r w a r d motion,
and above. The spectral composition of the rather than translating ( s u p p o s e y o u are fly-
signal varies greatly with species and habi- ing in an ultralight airplane near t h e ground
tat (Schnitzler et al., 2003). For example, and a gust of w i n d hits so t h a t o n e w i n g goes
bats that hunt in cluttered environments up and the other d o w n ) , a d i f f e r e n t optic-
generate a call that has two components: a flow pattern occurs. Flies d e t e c t self-motion
constant frequency (CF) portion followed to help stabilize flight, a n d neuroethological
by a downward frequency-modulated (FM) evidence is emerging that t h e g e o m e t r y and
sweep. T h e CF portion of the call gives wiring of the p h o t o r e c e p t o r s on t h e e y e of
the bats better distance acuity, whereas the the fly m a k e c o m p u t i n g o p t i c flow a trivial
FM portion gives them multispectral cues problem (Egelhaaf et al., 2002). A k e y finding
concerning fine details of target shape and has been that t h e orientations of t h e r o w s of
movement (Suga, 1990). During the final photoreceptors along w h i c h t h e o p t i c flow
phase of a prey-capture sequence, called is c o m p u t e d , a f u n c t i o n of t h e e y e ' s geom-
the "terminal buzz" phase, the bat rapidly etry, coincide w i t h t h e p r e f e r r e d directions
increases the pulse rate (Ghose & Moss, of the neuron that t h o s e sensors c o n n e c t to
2003; Kalko, 1995) and switches exclusively (Figure 26.4). A n e u r o n d e d i c a t e d to detect-
to FM sweeps. ing a rolling m o t i o n of t h e fly connects to
T h e bat is able to detect its horizontal a r o w of sensors, o m m a t i d i a , t h a t he paral-
angle (left-right bearing, or azimuth) to tar- lei to the o p t i c - f l o w p a t t e r n t h a t o c c u r s on
gets by analyzing both intensity and time the e y e w h e n t h e fly rolls. A c t i v a t i o n of that
differences in the sounds arriving at the t w o neuron w o u l d then be a reliable indicator
ears: if the target is to the left, the sound will that the corresponding o p t i c flow, and thus
arrive slighdy earlier and with more intensity rolling self-motion, is o c c u r r i n g ,
at the left ear than the right. However, an T h e e x a m p l e s of b a t ears a n d fly eyes
object's vertical position is not detectable in show h o w t h e physical c o n f i g u r a t i o n of
this manner. Instead, the intricate shapes of the b o d y p e r f o r m s a s o p h i s t i c a t e d c o m p u -
the bat's ear (pinnae) and tragi (Figure 26.3) tational role in t h e life of t h e s e animals,
provide cues to vertical elevation (Wotton, O t h e r e x a m p l e s i n c l u d e s p e c t r a l filtering
Haresign, & Simmons, 1995; Wotton & Sim- through p i g m e n t e d oil d r o p s in t h e e y e s of
mons, 2000). Returning sonar cries follow birds (Varela, Palacios, & G o l d s m i t h , 1993),
different pathways through the pinna-tragus distinct filtering p r o p e r t i e s of a m p u l l a r y
c o m p l e x according to their angle of entry, versus tuberous e l e c t r o r e c e p t o r s in elec-
inducing spectral cues that vary systemati- trie fish b e c a u s e of t h e p r e s e n c e of tightly
cally with t h e elevation angle. T h e bat can packed skin cells in t h e l u m e n ( S z a b o ,
then simply listen to these spectral cues to 1974), p h o n o t a x i s in c r i c k e t s t h r o u g h reso-
detect the elevation of the target. T h e con- nance in their f o r e l i m b s ( M i c h e l s e n , 1998;
NEUROBTHOLOOV
4%

Figure 26.4. Computing optic flow through eye geometry.


a. Self-motion generates optic flow over the eyes. Arrows on the
left plane represent the local motion vectors on the eye when the
animal rolls around its longitudinal body axis. The local response
properties of a neuronal tangential cell, the VS6 cell, are adapted to
detect this particular self-rotation. It is assumed that with its large
dendrite, this cell integrates signals from local input elements whose
preferred directions (arrows on second-from-left plane) correspond
to the direction of local motion vectors in roll-induced optic flow.
b. Head of a female blowfly. White lines over the right eye indicate
the course of ommatidial rows in the eye lattice, c. Organization of
the receptive field of a VS6 cell. Orientation and length of arrows at
different angular positions indicate the neuron's local preferred
direction and motion sensitivity in the right visual hemisphere. o°
azimuth and 0° elevation corresponds to the point direcdy in front
of the animal. Lines in the upper-left quadrant indicate the course
of ommatidial rows, which are oriented vertically in the equatorial
region of the eye (v-row). The direction of visual motion is thought
to be analyzed mainly by interactions between ommatidia along the
rows in the hexagonal eye lattice (cf. orientation of rows and
arrows). In the dorsofrontal eye region, the course of the v-rows
strongly shifts toward a horizontal orientation. This change in
orientation is reflected by the change in local preferred directions of
VS6 cells in corresponding regions of its receptive field. Text
verbatim from Egelhaaf et al. (2002). Reproduced with permission.

Michelsen, Popov, & Lewis, 1994), and the adaptive behavior occur, in part, outside
role of cochlear micromechanics in hear- of the nervous system, a useful prelimi-
ing ( G u m m e r , Hemmert, & Zenner, 1996; nary step toward the argument that cog-
Russell & Kossl, 1999). In these cases, a nition can depend on processes outside of
significant amount of signal processing has the body. An important issue holding up
been completed prior to entry of the sig- acceptance of these points is how to relate
nal into the nervous system. These examples the somewhat incommensurate form of ana-
show that key computations subserving log computation apparent in these cases to
Jj^o MALCOLJ 1 A. MACIVER

the more mature notions of computation on the body, making the animal yaw (turn
and algorithm complexity with digital rep- left or right) from the trajectory that is
resentations (for an insightful discussion of the shortest distance between t w o points.
the distinction between analog and digital, According to one theory of its origins, bilat-
see Haugeland, 1981). This question, how eral symmetry arose w h e n a jellyfishlike
computabilitv over discrete spaces relates to ancestral form migrated from a midwa-
computabilitv over continuous spaces such ter existence to crawling along the seafloor
as real numbers, has become a topic of inter- (Trochaea theory, Nielsen, 2001). Even when
est over the past few years, and metrics such they are not moving on an aquatic or terres-
as the log of condition in the case of linear trial surface, however, given their presence
systems have been proposed (see reviews by in volumes of water or air close to surfaces,
Blum, 2004; Braverman & Cook, 2006]. all animals are more than two-dimensional
creatures but not fully three-dimensional
2.1.3 BILATERAL SYMMETRY IN ANIMAL ones - even birds and fish typically move
BODY PLANS far less up and down than horizontally. As
The bat and fly examples concern exploita- two-and-a-half-dimensional creatures, ani-
tion of structure in the sensory ecology mals can exploit their bilaterally symmet-
of those animals. How do animals exploit rical sensory structures, such as ears, for
structure in their mechanical ecology? A control of horizontal bearing by simple
deep pattern connecting sensory processing comparisons b e t w e e n them, as in the bat
and locomotion can be read in the bilat- (termed tropotaxis, and achieved by com-
eral symmetry of animals. All animals but missural fibers connecting bilaterally paired
sponges, jellyfish, comb jellies, and placo- sensory nuclei in the brain; f o r m o r e details,
zoans are bilaterally symmetrical. The bila- see Braitenberg, 1965, 1984; Hinde, 1970;
terian animal body plan, which appeared Maclver et al., 2004). T h u s , fundamental
contemporaneously with the appearance of needs of efficient locomotion, and sim-
multicellular animals between 0.5 and 1.5 bil- ple sensor-based control algorithms for the
lion years ago, often includes high forward important decisions of l e f t w a r d versus right-
mobility along the midline axis (Grabowsky, ward m o v e m e n t via bilaterally paired sen-
1994) and is closely coupled to cephaliza- sory organs, appear to have b e e n entrenched
tion, an adaptation that complements such in the structure of animals since the dawn of
mobility with a clustering of sensory organs their multicellular origins.
around the anterior end of the organism. All
vertebrates and most other highly mobile 2.1.4 T H E PASSIVE WALKER
animals such as insects feature this neurome- Another observation concerning the impor-
chanical complementarity. With this neu- tance of mechanical structure in subserv-
romechanical template (Full 8c Koditschek, ing behavior comes f r o m outside of neu-
1999) came the active feeding behaviors and roethology, in the field of robotics. O v e r
agile locomotion that correlate with the evo- the past several years, building on the work
lution of advanced nervous systems needed of M c G e e r (1992), A n d y R u i n a and oth-
to control these behaviors (Conway, 1998; ers have been working on passive walk-
Dewel, 2000; Koob & Long, 2000; North- ers. These robots, designed to be models
cutt, 2002; Paulin, 2005). I will return to these of human bipedal walking, are able to walk
issues below when I discuss why the ability with no energy other than t h e small amount
to sense objects distant from the body origi- imparted by an inclined plane, and nothing
nated. other than rigid links and joints. M o r e recent
Consider what would happen during for- versions use a very small a m o u n t of energy,
ward movement in a fluid were it not similar to the a m o u n t u s e d by humans,
for symmetry around the midsagittal plane to walk on flat surfaces (Collins, Ruina,
along which animals propel themselves: Tedrake, 8c Wisse, 2005). T h e implication
there w o u l d be an imbalance of drag forces of this w o r k is that m u c h of t h e efficiency
neuroethoi.ogy
49 1

Figure 26.5. From reactivity with a mala vista to planning with a


buena vista. Control and planning in prey-capture behavior as a
function of the ratio between the sensory volume (SV) and the
stopping motor volume (MVst0p) for two Active animals: one (left)
with the near unity ratio characteristic of many passive sensing
animals that have poor acuity and active-sensing animals and
another (right) with a large ratio to illustrate the rarer situation of
long-range passive-sensing systems such as vision, a. With
near-unity SV:MVst0p ratios, search proceeds in a raster-scan-like
fashion through the environment. If a prey is close enough to be
within one of these search tracks, it is detected and possibly
captured, b. With large SV:MVstop ratios, there is the possibility
that multiple trajectories to a detected prey (dashed lines) can be
assessed prior to action. After assessing multiple paths, one path is
chosen (bi) that is longer than a path that may disclose the position
of the predator to the prey too early p>i§ or result in reaching an
untraversable obstacle (bj).

of human movement may arise through hav- derived commonly observed gaits in bipeds
ing a skeletal structure and mass distribution (Srinivasan & Ruina, 2006) and movements
that makes walking as energetically favor- in fish (Maclver et al., 2004).
able to the body as swinging is to a pendu-
lum. Such efficiency is enormously impor-
tant: if we were as inefficient as the Honda 2.1.5 T H E BONE-BRAIN CONTINUUM
bipedal robot Asimo, which requires at least A general pattern emerging from the work
ten times more energy per unit distance and above is that regularities existing over dis-
weight (Collins et al., 2005), then with a parate timescales in an animal's environ-
full day's walking we would need to eat ment are absorbed by different systems of
ten times more food than we typically eat. the body. The longest timescale regularities,
Further evidence of mechanical efficiency such as the need for a balance offerees along
comes from computational studies using the the axis of travel to move in straight lines,
technique of optimal control to find move- are encapsulated at the level of structural tis-
ments that minimize energy. These have sues (bones, cartilage, chitin) in a bilaterally
soomalcolma.mac1ver

symmetrical body plan. The maintenance lar animals, and 1.6 billion years ago, the esti-
costs of these tissues are the lowest of any mated time of the last common ancestor of
body material. The shortest timescale reg- plants and animals, all animals were unicel-
ularities, such as the current state of self- lular and thus lacking a nervous system (Car-
motion, are encapsulated at both the struc- roll, 2001; Meyerowitz, 2002). It seems likely
tural level of sensor geometry and through that the nervous system is a solution to the
energetically expensive neuronal process- problem of controlling the body when it is
ing, tissue which requires forty times more composed of more than a f e w cells (Nielsen,
power per unit mass than bone (Martin & 2001), at which point diffusion breaks
Fuhrman, 1955). The computations that an down as an effective communication system.
animal needs to move through space are Much of the nervous system is concerned
spread across these systems. At this level of with problems that arise from being mobile,
description, there is no basis for an invidious and it appears that its evolution was greatly
distinction between bone and brain. accelerated after animals discovered an
appetite for eating other animals (Conway-
2.2 The Buena Vista Sensing Club Morris, 1998; Northcutt, 2002; Paulin, 2005).
Consider the example of the tunicate, which
The Buena Vista Sensing Club hypothesis has a mobile, bilaterally symmetrical lar-
suggests that the expansion of the range with val stage, and a stationary (fixed to a sub-
which animals can monitor external space, strate), asymmetrical adult phase: once it
relative to their usual velocity, has been has reached its final resting spot, the tunicate
one - perhaps the dominant - driving force digests much of its nervous system. Whether
for the evolution of the ability to plan. In or not ignorance is bliss, for a sessile crea-
most environments, distant goals cannot be ture a brainless existence at least reduces the
effectively reached by single behaviors but amount of grub it has to come by!
instead require the sequencing of multiple Let us consider the problem of sensory-
behaviors. Although the sequencing could signal-based movement guidance in some
be purely reactive, it is clear that multiple detail, because it appears central to the gen-
approaches are possible when our percep- esis of nervous systems. O u r ancestors are
tual world extends to a large expanse of unicellular animals for which, by dint of
heterogeneous space (Figure 26.5b); thus, at their small size, inertial forces on the body
are dominated by drag forces (the ratio of
the very least, there is a basis for selection
these two is quantified by the Reynolds
pressures that would lead to a capacity for
number). The simple consequence of this
evaluating multiple possible trajectories to a
is that as soon as you stop generating forces
goal. The number of animals with the req- to move, you will stop. Think of walking
uisite sensory-mechanical balance conserva- on normal ground versus skating on ice. In
tively includes cephalopods (squids, cuttle- the former, as soon as you stop generat-
fish, octopus), raptors such as hawks and ing forces through your contact with the
eagles, and many of the mammals. Before ground, you stop moving; in the latter, even
proceeding, I would like to address the ques- after you stop pushing off the ice, you are
tion of why sensation jumped beyond the still moving. In water, our ancestral envi-
boundaries of animals in the first instance. ronment, animals are in the viscous regime
when they are below around a millime-
2.2.1 A BRIEF HISTORY OF TELECEPTIVE ter in size. As an animal grows larger, it
SENSATION enters the inertial regime, and now in the
absence of active braking forces the ani-
In his Opticks, Newton remarked, "Infinite
mal will coast along through space for some
space is the sensorium of the deity." In what
time after cessation of force production. The
ways is finite space the sensorium of lesser relationship between control signals, such as
creatures? First, a bit of evolutionary back- those required to w h i p a flagellum to move
ground. Between 700 million years ago, the
date of the earliest trace fossils of multicellu-
NEIJROETHOLOGY 493

forward, and the point in space that the ani- about five hundred milliseconds for an eva-
mal needs to reach, perhaps some tasty bac- sive action such as braking or swerving to
terium, is not straightforward in the inertial occur after you have initiated it (although
regime. T h i s is because the animal cannot actually it will be a function of, e.g., your
simply halt motion at the point of contact velocity, mass, friction of the roadway-tire
with the bacterium but needs to perform interface, braking power, speed of muscle
state estimation to predict h o w soon before contraction), that means you need to sense
the bacterium is reached it will need to shut the moose around seven hundred millisec-
off the generation of force as a function of onds before contact, or ten or more meters
its current dynamics (Paulin, 2005). Con- away if you are going fifty kilometers per
tact sensors such as mechanoreceptors are hour. In short, the neuromotor delay time
not sufficient: y o u need a teleceptive sen- plus the action time determine an effec-
sory system - one that can detect targets tive horizon of reactivity; if you sense things
s o m e distance away f r o m your body with- inside of that horizon, you are powerless; if
out contact. T h e r e are several of these, most you sense things outside of the horizon, you
obviously the visual system, but also audi-
will at least have time for the most basic of
tory, chemosensory, electrosensory, and the
actions. This example gives a sense of the
mechanosensory lateral line, which detects
dynamic considerations involved in deter-
f l o w disturbances in water at a distance.
mining how far the sensory volume should
For a given object, the maximal distance
extend in the direction of movement. As
at w h i c h it can be detected using one of
you extend your sensory volume beyond the
these teleceptive systems - as one moves
horizon of reactivity, you allow for more
the object in all directions around the body -
than simple reactive control strategies, such
f o r m s a surface we will refer to as the sensory
as braking or swerving. With a buena vista,
volume (SV).
you can look far ahead and execute long-
duration plans such as multiple lane changes
2.2.2 TELECEPTIVE SENSATION prior to an exit. However, note that these
AND CONTROL considerations only apply to less predictable
W h a t determines h o w far away from the features of the space - a situation where,
b o d y , and in w h a t directions, the sensory as Haugeland (1998) nicely puts it, "percep-
v o l u m e should extend to allow for effective tion is cheap, representation expensive" (p.
control of the body in space? Consider the 219). In less dynamic contexts, such as long-
f o l l o w i n g scenario: y o u are driving along in range navigation, and where perception is
t h e fog, able to only see a short distance in cosdy, guiding movement through internal-
front of the car. Suddenly, a huge lumber- ized spatial maps may be more effective.
ing m o o s e appears through the fog, stand- If, for example, that moose on the road in
ing in the roadway. Y o u now have several front of you is actually stuffed, and has been
options: step on the brakes, swerve, run into inconveniently installed in the center of the
the m o o s e , or some combination of these. road, you could eventually learn to avoid
Unfortunately, any action y o u take will it early on, on the basis of your recognition,
be at least t w o hundred milliseconds after say, that it is just past the hairpin turn before
the moose-related sensory signals hit your Crazy Bob's Taxidermy and Pedicure. This
retina, because of conduction and processing represents the internalization of space in a
delays b e t w e e n the surface of your retina form that, other than issues of changes in
and t h e contraction of muscles in your lower the space and the need to localize your posi-
or u p p e r limbs. N o w , if y o u see the moose tion in the space, may be interchangeable
three m e t e r s in front of the car, and you with sensation. I will return to this point to
are going fifty kilometers per hour (four- discuss reports that active-sensing animals
teen meters per second), by the time you possess highly accurate spatial maps.
step on the brake, the moose is already Whereas we have the concept of sensing
going through your windshield. If we allow range for discussing how the sensory v o l u m e
soomalcolma.mac1ver

relates to control, there is no analogous con- in the field are analyzed and used to direct
cept for movement. In control theory, a dis- subsequent behavior. Using the electric field
cipline of engineering, where something can and sensors as a teleceptive active-sensing
move over a given time span is called the system, the fish is able to hunt at night in
"small-time reachable set," and I propose the muddy rivers of the A m a z o n basin.
that this concept provides a usable motor We quantified the three-dimensional
system analogue to sensing range. To define shape and size of the electric fish's prey
it we begin with a mechanical system char- SV using a combination of behavioral and
acterized by a set of time-varying control computational techniques that allowed us
inputs (e.g., for a car it could be rear-wheel to estimate when the live prey could be
rotational position and front-wheel steering detected (Snyder et al., 2007). T h e omni-
angle). For this mechanical system one can directional SV for prey is s h o w n in Figure
estimate the small-time reachable set to be 26.6. The MV varies as a function of the
the region of space that the mechanical sys- time interval being examined, the fish's ini-
tem can reach over a given time interval tial state, and the control inputs of the
for all feasible control inputs (i.e., inputs fish's musculoskeletal system over the time
that do not exceed the capacity of the sys- interval being considered. Because we do
tem, such as a ninety-degree turning angle not have access to these control inputs, we
or acceleration beyond the power of the estimated the M V empirically b y analyz-
engine). The original work in this area con- ing motion capture data of these fish hunt-
cerns reachable sets of a kinematic car (e.g., ing for prey. T h e strategy we used was to
Vendittelli, Laumond, & Nissoux, 1999), but look at all body displacements that occurred
more recent work treats the computation over a given time interval across multiple
of reachable sets for continuous dynami-
trials. We quantified the MV by placing a
cal systems (Mitchell, Bayen, & Tomlin,
surface over the m a x i m a l displacements in
2005).
all directions; thus, for each t i m e interval,
With the concept of the small-time we obtained a particular M V . A fascinat-
reachable set, along with the notion of the ing and unexpected finding w a s that, similar
sensory volume, I can address how the rela- to the S V , the MV is also omnidirectional,
tive sizes of movement and sensing volumes a testament to the remarkable morphology
relate to behavioral control. I will do this and maneuverability of these animals. Figure
in the context of one popular model system 26.6 shows the MV for three d i f f e r e n t time
for the study of sensory processing in ani- intervals, showing that it b e c o m e s larger
mals, the weakly electric fish. and changes shape as the interval increases
from over one hundred to seven hundred
2.2.3 MOVEMENT AND SENSING SPACES milliseconds.
IN WEAKLY ELECTRIC FISH W e can n o w q u a n t i f y h o w closely
For studies of the weakly electric fish matched these t w o spaces are by c o m i n g up
Apteronotus albifrons, the black-ghost knife with a convenient m e a s u r e of this match;
fish, my colleagues and I have applied the we use the intersection of t h e t w o v o l u m e s
concept of the small-time reachable set divided b y their union. W h e n w e exam-
(hereafter termed the motor volume, M V ) ine this measure versus t h e t i m e interval of
to determine the extent of the overlap movement, we find that t h e m a t c h is maxi-
between the motor volume and the sensory mal at a time interval of a b o u t 432 millisec-
volume for detection and capture of prey onds. T h e importance of this t i m e interval is
(Snyder, Burdick, Nelson, & Maclver, 2007). that it is close to the s u m of t h e n e u r o m o t o r
delay and stopping times f o r t h e fish; it takes
As an object enters the weak electric field
one hundred milliseconds f o r a detectable
that the fish continually emits, distortions
signal indicating prey to reach t h e brain and
in the electric field are picked up by around
produce a behavioral reaction, and another
fourteen thousand electroreceptors covering
two hundred milliseconds are required for
the entire body surface. These distortions
NEURQETHOtOCV
495

Figure 26.6. Sensory volume and motor volumes of a weakly


electric fish. The prey SV (for a typical prey, the water flea
Daphnia magna) and MVs of a weakly electric fish as a function
of the indicated movement time. Adapted from Snyder et al.,
(2007).

the animal to come to a halt from stan- with coining to a stop as an animal's stop-
dard hunting velocities and capture the prey. ping motor volume (MVstop).
In other words, in an active-sensing animal, When an animal needs to emit sixteen
which has to invest metabolic energy to pro- times more power to double its sensing
duce a sensing field, just enough energy is range, we expect selection pressure against
emitted for the animal to be able to detect making the SV any larger than it needs to be.
the prey far enough out to stop. (Like many Here is where the great advantage of passive-
animals, these electric fish simplify the con- sensing systems, such as vision, becomes
trol problem of engulfing small prey by being apparent: now the only cost associated with
nearly stationary at the point of ingestion.) having a longer sensing range is having
From an analysis of previously published a larger eyeball and associated visual sig-
data on bat prey capture we find evidence nal processing circuitry (Brooke, Hanley, &
of a similar pattern: the echolocation SV Laughlin, 1999; Land & Nilsson, 2002). With
(Figure 26.1a) is close to the MV at the sum the resolution of our high-acuity visual sys-
of the neuromotor delay and the stopping tems, about one-sixtieth of a degree under
time (Snyder et al., 2007). For convenience, ideal conditions, we can resolve a thirty-
I will refer to the particular MV associated centimeter-long rabbit at one kilometer - a
SOO malcolm a. mac1ver

distance that takes us more than ten min- low SV:MV s t 0 p ratio has little ability to eval-
utes to walk at a good clip and about four uate different trajectories toward or away
minutes at a fast run. At night, and when from the sensed object because of time and
our mechanical abilities are augmented by space constraints. With a large ratio, there
a vehicle, the relationship between our SV will be multiple feasible trajectories to a
and MVstop is not necessarily intuitive: we distant goal. If these different trajectories
are strapping on a massive, fast mechanism vary in their likelihood of success, we would
that expands our M V ^ p , while operating expect selection pressure to favor animals
with low light levels, which shrinks our that are able to evaluate these different pos-
S V . The two factors combined with our sibilities and then select the one most likely
considerable neuromotor latency result in to lead to success.
surprisingly slow recommended night driv- Returning to the scene of C r a z y Bob's
ing speeds from highway safety agencies Taxidermy and Pedicure, it is important to
(less than fifty kilometers per hour when note that the preceding claims about control
using low-beam headlights; U.S. National and planning are qualified by "with respect
Traffic Highway Safety Administration, to something sensed." This is because we
2004). know that the ability to navigate through
foraging areas far larger than the SV and
2.2.4 CONTROL AND PLANNING return h o m e is c o m m o n among animals,
How does this relate to control and plan- whether they possess short- or long-range
ning? If the ratio of the SV to MV s f o p is sensing systems. It appears that m a n y ani-
near one (Figure 26.5a), the set of behav- mals develop a cognitive m a p of the larger
ioral options with respect to something just territory over which they live, and they can
sensed is very small, limited to stopping, index their position in this space either by
turning, and other behaviors that have sim- using local landmarks or through path inte-
ple relationships between sensory input and gration, where current position is estimated
neuromotor output. We refer to these sim- by updating some initially k n o w n position
ple behaviors as "reactive" because there with each subsequent m o v e m e n t the ani-
is only time for simple reflexive reactions. mal makes (Hafting, Fyhn, M o l d e n , Moser,
With simple mappings between inputs and & Moser, 2005). Provided that the features
movement, animals can embed control laws of interest in the space are not significantly
in parts of the nervous system like the spinal altered between visits, it is quite conceivable
cord and hindbrain that feature minimal that such animals could plan to revisit these
processing and conduction delays. As we features while relying only on path integra-
increase the ratio of SV to MV^op, an ani- tion or on sensing of nearby landmarks.
mal has the capacity to examine a larger In this way, a representation of space plus
space beyond that which it will immedi- path integration or localization m a y be a
ately move several behavioral cycles into the good proxy for sensation. H o w e v e r , there
future, where a behavioral cycle is the neu- are clear differences. E a c h unit of space con-
romotor delay time plus the time it takes tains potential harms and benefits f o r a typ-
to perform a simple action like stopping. ical animal. T h e s e fall into t w o categories:
T h e first consequence is that when targets of those items that are stable e n o u g h through
future behavior come into range, the animal time that their presence or absence can be
has many options, and dynamics and neu- internalized into an infrequently u p d a t e d
romotor delays do not dominate potential m a p of space, and those items that are not.
response modes (Figure 26.5b). For example, In the former category are things such as
an animal could sequence multiple behav- environmental obstructions, t h e location of
iors to reach a goal, such as trotting over to home, the level of the tide, w h e r e f o o d has
a barrier, jumping over it, and then crouch- been cached for use during t h e winter, the
ing under an obstruction. An animal with a location of flowering plants, a n d so forth.
NEUROETHOLOGY 497

Into the latter category is the present on structures such as the hippocampal
location of predators and prey and cur- formation that appears to be central to spa-
rent weather conditions. Although there are tial cognition (Cohen & Eichenbaum, 1993;
clear advantages to being able to plan over O'Keefe 8t Nadel, 1978; Hafting et al., 2005).
stable features of the environment, planning An example of this is the seasonal expan-
over the SV is critical for predation and sion and shrinking of related brain struc-
avoiding being preyed on. Because the shift tures in food-caching birds (Krebs, Sherry,
to a mobile-predator lifestyle in the early Healy, Perry, & Vaccarino, 1989; Sherry,
Cambrian (more than five hundred million Vaccarino, Buckenham, & Herz, 1989; Smul-
years ago) likely led to the innovation of the ders, Sasson, 8c Devoogd, 1995). The shrink-
vertebrate head and related sensory struc- ing and expansion of brain tissue with spatial
tures f r o m headless ancestors (Northcutt & memory load in these animals suggests that
Gans, 1983), any capacity that affects preda- memory can be quite costly (Dukas, 1999).
tory ability has the potential to be a source of Quantification of this cost would allow us
significant selection pressure on the nervous to assess the trade-off between maintaining
system of animals. a rapidly updated representation of space
It is nonetheless interesting to consider through sensation, with the associated costs
some of the complex relationships among of sensing (Laughlin, 2001), and a slowly
sensing range, rate at which the habitat updated representation that requires path
changes over time, size of foraging area, integration or localization with the associ-
animal speed, and accuracy of landmark- ated costs of spatial memory.
based guidance systems. For example, bats Ultimately, the tipping point between the
appear to prefer linear landmark features effectiveness of single control laws versus
between roost and foraging area (Schnit- planning (be it over internalized space or
zler et al., 2003). This preference probably through sensing) may have to do with how
facilitates their observed reduced reliance densely occupied space is with behaviorally
on echolocation along bat flyways (preferred relevant contingencies, relative to move-
paths f r o m roost to hunting grounds), as well ment speed and to the size of the MVstop.
as allowing a cruder spatial map (e.g., less This is similar to Levins's (1968) notion of
frequent location updates) than would be environmental grain. Living in a very sparse
necessitated if the bat were to follow a more environment and possessing long-range sens-
fractal landmark structure at their high fly- ing systems, long reaction times, and a large
ing speed. Active sensing animals in general amount of inertia (being massive and/or fast)
seem to have particularly accurate spatial is similar to living in a cluttered environ-
maps (on electric fish, see Cain, 1995; Cain, ment and having short-range sensing sys-
Gerin, &. Moller, 1994; on rodents, see Haft- tems, short reaction times, and low inertia.
ing et al., 2005; O ' K e e f e St. Burgess, 2005; The rain forest is not equivalent to a bar-
on bats, see Schnitzler et al., 2003). Clearly, ren desert under equal sensory and move-
however, there are many different ways ment conditions, but if the clutter of the
that space can be internalized. For exam- rainforest contracts the SV or the desert
ple, internalization could be as rudimentary increases speed, they could possess similar
as following a trail of chemical laid down planning loads in this framework. In birds,
by a fellow traveler, such as occurs with it has been shown that flight speed increases
ants, or as complicated as the hippocampus- with (body mass)0 ' 67 , and visual resolution
dependent distributed spatial-cue binding increases with (flight speed)' 33 , so larger
f o u n d in mammals (Cohen & Eichenbaum, birds with more inertia resolve objects at
19933• longer times to contact than do smaller birds
A further difference between planning (Brooke et al., 1999). In bats, prey detection
over sensed space and internalized space is range is matched to the wingbeat interval,
that the latter may place significant demands which in turn has a power law relationship
soo malcolm a. mac1ver

to body mass and flight speed (Holderied & hive. Given these considerations, compar-
von Helversen, 2003). ing nonhuman primates, which as a group
have larger eyes than other mammals (Ross,
2.2.5 PUTTING BUENA VISTA TO THE TEST 2000), to other vertebrates may be more
To test the Buena Vista Sensing Club informative. Along these lines, it is known
hypothesis, ideally we would start with that mammals (which appear to make up
behavioral correlates of planning in a wide the bulk of the members of the Buena
range of animals and relate them to their Vista Sensing Club) have greatly increased
sensory and motor capacities. Unfortu- the complexity of the forebrain over
nately, adequate behavioral data on planning other vertebrates (Figure 26.7; Striedter,
behavior are not available. Quantitative data 2005).
on the motor and sensing spaces of a vast One further point should be made to but-
array of animals other than more modern tress the Buena Vista Sensing C l u b against
vertebrates are also lacking. Cognitive neu- complaints from members of the Mala Vista
roscientists, however, have been investigat- Sensing Club - all those animals with puny
ing the neural locus of planning in humans sensing ranges. They could argue that if any-
for some time. Thus, in lieu of the missing one should have been pressured into having
behavioral data, we will consider some of an ability to plan, it should have been them,
this evidence. because they would benefit even more from
In humans, cognitive neuroscience has this ability than a Buena Vistite. There are
shown that the prefrontal cortex is impor- three primary ways in which selection pres-
tant for planning (Damasio, 1985). Within sure to plan can be manifested. O n e is to
primates, we know that humans have nearly evolve long-range sensing abilities, thus join-
doubled the volume of Brodmann's area 10, ing the Buena Vista Sensing Club. Another
a prefrontal cortical area considered impor- is through symbol use, such as language or
tant for planning, over the closest nonhuman waggle dances. The third is through an inter-
primate (Semendeferi, Armstrong, Schle- nal map plus path integration to determine
icher, Zilles, 8t van Hoesen, 2001), whereas where one is in that map, as discussed above.
human visual acuity is not significandy bet- The first, joining the Buena Vista Sensing
ter than that of other primates (Ross, 2000). Club, is inapplicable, as we are address-
This may be an exception to the Buena ing members of the Mala Vista Club. We
Vista Sensing Club hypothesis. However, will not consider the second, as symbolic
the ability to plan without the help of sym- approaches are rare. T h e third approach
bolic methods such as language may have is possible, but we return to our previous
reached saturation in early primates. It is point, that a capacity to plan over internal-
possible that with language and other sym- ized space will not help with prédation and
bol systems, hominids took planning to a avoiding being preyed on, both of which are
new level. Although language is thought to significant sources of selection pressure on
be a more recent innovation than is com- the nervous system. W h e t h e r other sources
patible with increased frontal lobe volume, of selection pressure are sufficient to lead to
given recent evidence concerning the audi- planning is unclear. T h e presence of accu-
tory capacity of early hominids, language use rate spatial maps, and perhaps planning, in
may be quite ancient (Martinez et al., 2004). active-sensing animals w o u l d seem to sug-
Symbolic approaches can effectively extend gest the answer is yes. H o w e v e r , t w o of
a perceptual system to encompass an in- the active-sensing modalities, echolocation
definite amount of space for planning and electrolocation, are in animals that have
through the reports from fellow symbol relatively recent, non-active-sensing ances-
users; one example of this is the bee's waggle tors. The ability to internalize large maps
dance, which allows individual bees to com- may be a holdover f r o m long-range passive
municate the location and richness of a for- sensing habits and the exploitation of corre-
aging patch far beyond the SV of bees at the spondingly large foraging areas - an echo of
neuropathology

Figure 26.7. Toward a comparative biology of planning.


Phylogenetic tree depicting the relationships of major vertebrate
groups. Numbers across the top indicate the number of cell groups
experts have described in the forebrains of representative species.
The symbols indicate approximately where forebrain complexity is
likely to have increased (squares) or decreased (circles). Modified
with permission from Striedter (2005).

an ancestral condition when perception was are encapsulated in the animal at a host
cheaper. of levels from structural tissues to neural
responses, according to the temporal band-
width of these regularities and associated
3. Conclusion energy trade-offs. For the second step, I elu-
cidated how work on one model system in
I began with a précis of how neuroethology neuroethology, the weakly electric fish, may
navigates the sometimes contested realm of give insight into relationships among con-
its own externalist and internalist leanings. trol, planning, and the ratio between the SV
In excising a piece of the world with an ani- and MVstop. I put forth the hypothesis that
mal and coupling these together in closed- sensing beyond the M V ^ p may be central to
loop apparatuses, neuroethology recognizes the evolution of planning. If true, the Buena
the unity of the external and internal in Vista Sensing Club hypothesis naturalizes a
adaptive behavior. The virtual world exam- formerly largely human faculty in a way that
ples also show that in some cases we under- makes it approachable in more experimen-
stand the relevant external factors needed to tally accessible animals.
elicit natural behaviors, whereas the neural Adams and Aizawa (this volume) raise
and biomechanical underpinnings of these the issue of the motivation for an exter-
behaviors are still largely not understood; nalist redefinition of cognition. As part of
this in some measure supports an internalist the effort to understand the intelligence
bias in effort if not in philosophy. of nonhuman animals, for neuroetholo-
As the first of two steps from neu- gists the redefinition is driven by pragmatic
roethology to situated cognition, I showed needs. Craniocentrism simply does not
how present research on situated nervous work for understanding the kinds of quite
systems within neuroethology is indicating sophisticated behaviors that neuroetholo-
the important computational role of non- gists are working on. As suggested by the
neuronal sensory and mechanical structures three virtual-world examples, the instances
in supporting adaptive behavior. Regular- of morphological computation, and the
ities in the world at multiple timescales relationships among behavioral control,
soo malcolm a. mac1ver

sensing, and mechanics i have discussed, sciousness, was only necessary o n c e percep-
they arise out of a tight inteiplay of body, tual systems delivered choices at such a dis-
brain, and environment, with deep ties to tance that reactive (nonconscious) control
an animal's environment and evolutionary schemes for action w e r e no longer advanta-
history. geous. T h e lead-up to consciousness could
I will end with some points about the therefore have been a gift of s p a c e wrought
implications of the Buena Vista Sensing by passive teleceptive sensation in a niche
C l u b hypothesis as it relates to extended where such acuity p a i d fitness dividends.
mind issues and consciousness. In Clark and T h e need to sequence b e h a v i o r s over this
Chalmers's (1998) paper on the extended space w o u l d then h a v e given rise to execu-
mind, they give the example of Otto the tive control structures in t h e brain, including
Alzheimer's patient and Inga - whose mem- working m e m o r y and attention, f o r carrying
ory is unimpaired - determining the address out these sequences, in a case s t u d y of h o w
of a museum. They argue that the address of "it is not the animal's brain t h a t organizes its
the museum in Otto's address book, always world, but the evolutionary e c o l o g y of the
with him, is functionally identical to Inga's animal that organizes its b r a i n " ( R e e d , 1996,
(nonoccurrent) belief that the museum has p. 69).
some particular address. I would argue that Neuroethology, w i t h its c o m p a r a t i v e
the realm of readily interrogable space deliv- approach and close attention to evolu-
ered by a long-range teleceptive sensory tionary, ecological, b e h a v i o r a l , a n d neural
system can be equivalendy thought of as aspects of animal life, m a y at first s e e m an
an extended belief system; there as well, unlikely contributor to t h e field of situated
all potential subjects of perceptual fixation cognition. H o w e v e r , as I h o p e t h e preceding
have the status of some type of belief in the examples have suggested, it is w e l l p o i s e d to
extended cognitive system. The idea of the push f o r w a r d our u n d e r s t a n d i n g o f h o w sim-
environment serving as an external memory ple and direct b e h a v i o r a l r e s p o n s e s to sen-
story has been around since the 1970s, begin- sory input can give w a y t o abilities w e m o r e
ning with Dreyfus's work and later nicely readily recognize as cognitive.
encapsulated by Brooks in his "let the world
be its own best model" (see Noe, 2004, p. 234,
ni4). Specific proposals as to how percep-
Acknowledgments
tual fixation via long-range sensing systems is
I thank Andy Barto, Heather Eisthen, Kevin
important to cognition have been put forth
Lynch, Mark Nelson, and Rob Wilson for com-
by Dana Ballard and colleagues (Ballard
ments on earlier drafts, and Michael Dickinson,
et al., 1997). The need for members of the
Mike Paulin, and Georg Striedter for useful dis-
Buena Vista Sensing C l u b to manipulate this cussions. Thanks to Rolf Mueller for images of bat
extended information space (LaValle, 2006) pinnae from microcomputed tomography. This
of beliefs to achieve distant goals would have work was supported by National Science Foun-
gone quite beyond the capacity of reactive dation Grant No. IOB-0517683.
control strategies.
Bridgeman (1992) wrote, "Consciousness
is the operation of the plan-executing mech- References
anism, enabling behavior to be driven by
plans rather than immediate environmen-
Assad, C., Rasnow, B., & Stoddard, P. K. (1999).
tal contingencies." Similar ideas were put Electric organ discharges and electric images
forth by H u m p h r e y (1992, p. 42). Conscious- during electrolocation. Journal of Experimental
ness, Prinz argues (this volume), is con- Biology, 202(10), 1185-1193.
cerned with attention to intermediate-level Ballard, D. H., Hayhoe, M. M, Pook, P. K,
representations that are useful f o r action. & Rao, R. P. N. (1997). Deictic codes for
W h a t I h a v e presented here is a suggestion the embodiment of cognition. Behavioral and
that planning, and perhaps therefore con- Brain Sciences, 20, 723-767.
n e u r o e t h o l o g y4 & 1

Barth, F. G., & Schmid, A. (Eds.). (2001). Ecology Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended
of sensing. Berlin: Springer. mind. Analysis, 58, 7-19.
Blum, L. (2004). Computing over the reals: Cliff, D. (1995). Neuroethology, computational.
Where Turing meets Newton. Notices of the In M. A. Arbib (Ed.), The handbook of brain
AMS, 51(9), 1024-1034. theory and neural networks (pp. 626-630).
Boonman, A., & Jones, G. (2002). Intensity con- Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
trol during target approach in echolocating Cohen, N. J., & Eichenbaum, H. (1993). Memory,
bats: Stereotypical sensori-motor behaviour in amnesia, and the hippocampal system. Cam-
Daubenton's bats, Myotis daubentonii. Journal bridge, MA: MIT Press.
of Experimental Biology, 205(18), 2865-2874. Collins, S., Ruina, A., Tedrake, R., & Wisse,
Brakenberg, V. (1965). Taxis, kinesis, and decus- M. (2005). Efficient bipedal robots based on
sation. Progress in Brain Research, 17, 210-222. passive-dynamic walkers. Science, 307(5712),
Braitenberg, V. (1984). Vehicles: Experiments in 1082-1085.
synthetic psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Conway-Morris, S. (1998). The crucible of cre-
Press. ation: The Burgess Shale and the rise of animals.
Braverman, M., 8L Cook, S. (2006). Computing Oxford: Oxford University Press.
over the reals: Foundations for scientific com- Dahmen, H. J. (1980). A simple apparatus to
puting. Notices of the AMS, 53(3), 318-329. investigate the orientation of walking insects.
Bridgeman, B. (1992). On the evolution of Experientia, 36(6), 685-687.
Damasio, A. R. (1985). The frontal lobes. In K.
consciousness and language. Psycoloquy, 3(15).
Heilman & E. Valenstein (Eds.), Clinical neu-
http://www.cogsci.ecs.soton.ac.uk/cgi/psyc/
ropsychology (pp. 339-375). Oxford: Oxford
newpsy?3.i5, accessed May 17, 2008.
University Press.
Bridgeman, B. (2003). Psychology and evolution:
Dewel, R. A. (2000). Colonial origin for Eumeta-
The origins of mind. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
zoa: Major morphological transitions and the
Brooke, M. D., Hanley, S., 8c Laughlin, S. B
origin of bilaterian complexity. Journal of Mor-
(1999). The scaling of eye size with body mass
phology, 243(1), 35-74.
in birds. Proceedings of the Royal Society of Lon-
Dickinson, M. H. (1996). Unsteady mechanisms
don Series B, 266(1417), 405-412.
of force generation in aquatic and aerial loco-
Cain, P. (1995). Navigation in familiar envi- motion. American Zoologist, 36(6), 537-554.
ronments by the weakly electric elephant- Dukas, R. (1999). Costs of memory: Ideas and
nose fish, Gnathonemus petersii L. (Mormyri- predictions. Journal of Theoretical Biology,
formes, Teleostei). Ethology, 99(4), 332-349.
Cain, P., Gerin, W., & Moller, P. (1994). «97(0, 41~5°-
Short-range navigation of the weakly elec- Dusenbery, D. B. (1992). Sensory ecology: How
tric fish, Gnathonemus petersii L. (Mormyri- organisms acquire and respond to information.
dae, Teleostei), in novel and familiar environ- New York: W. H. Freeman.
ments. Ethology, 96(1), 33-45. Egelhaaf, M., Kern, R., Krapp, H. G., Kretzberg,
Carew, T. J. (2000). Behavioral neurobiology: The J., Kurtz, R., & Warzecha, A. K. (2002). Neu-
cellular organization of natural behavior. Sun- ral encoding of behaviorally relevant visual-
derland, M A : Sinauer. motion information in the fly. Trends in Neu-
Carroll, S. B. (2001). Chance and necessity: The rosciences, 25(2), 96-102.
evolution of morphological complexity and Full, R. J., & Koditschek, D. E. (1999). Templates
diversity. Nature, 409(6823), 1102-1109. and anchors: Neuromechanical hypotheses of
Chen, L., House, J. L., Krähe, R., & Nelson, M. E. legged locomotion on land. Journal of Experi-
(2005). Modeling signal and background com- mental Biology, 202(23), 3325-3332.
ponents of electrosensory scenes. Journal of Full, R. J., & Tu, M. S. (1991). Mechanics of a
Comparative Physiology A, 191(4), 331-345. rapid running insect: 2-legged, 4-legged and
Chiel, H. J., & Beer, R. D. (1997). The brain has a 6-legged locomotion. Journal of Experimental
body: Adaptive behavior emerges from inter- Biology, 156, 215-231.
actions of nervous system, body, and envi- Galambos, R., 8c Griffin, D. R. (1940). The super-
ronment. Trends in Neurosciences, 20, 553- sonic cries of bats. Anatomical Record, 78, 95.
557- Ghose, K., 8c Moss, C. F. (2003). The sonar
beam pattern of a flying bat as it tracks teth-
Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body,
ered insects. Journal of the Acoustical Society of
and world together again. Cambridge, MA:
America, 114(2), 1120-1131.
M I T Press.
SOO malcolm a. MAC1ver

Gibson, J. J. (197g). The ecological approach to Kalko, E. K. (1995). Insect pursuit, prey capture
visual perception. Mahwah. NJ: Lawrence Erl- and echolocation in pipistrelle bats (Microchi-
baum roptera). Animal Behavior, 50, 861-880.
Götz, K. G.. & Gambke, C. (1968). Zum bewe- Koob, T. J., 8c Long, J. H. (2000). The vertebrate
gungssehen des Mehlkäfers Tenebrio molitor. body axis: Evolution and mechanical function.
Kybernetik, 4, 225. American Zoologist, 40(1), 1-18.
Grabows ky, G. L. [1994). Symmetry, locomotion, Kramer, E. (1975). Orientation of the male silk-
and the evolution of an anterior end: A lesson moth to the sex attractant bombykol. In D. A.
from sea-urchins. Evolution, 48(4), 1130-1146. Denton 8c J. P. Coghlan (Eds.), Olfaction and
Gummer, A. W., Hemmert, W., 8c Zenner, H. P. taste (Vol. 5, pp. 329-355). New York: Aca-
{1996). Resonant tectorial membrane motion demic Press.
in the inner ear: Its crucial role in frequency Krebs, J. R., Sherry, D. F., Healy, S. D., Perry, V.
tuning. Proceedings of the National Academy of H., 8c Vaccarino, A. L. (1989). Hippocampal
Sciences, 93(16), 8727-8732. specialization of food-storing birds. Proceed-
Hafting, T., Fyhn, M., Molden, S., Moser, M. ings of the National Academy of Sciences, 86(4),
B., 8c Moser, E. I. (2005). Microstructure of a 1388-1392.
spatial map in the entorhinal cortex. Nature, Land, M. F., 8c Nilsson, D.-E. (2002). Animal eyes.
436(7052), 801-806. New York: Oxford University Press.
Hartley, D. J., 8c Suthers, R. A. (1989). The Laughlin, S. B. (2001). The metabolic cost
sound emission pattern of the echolocating of information: A fundamental factor in
bat, Eptesicus fuscus. Journal of the Acoustical visual ecology. In F. G. Barth 8c A. Schmid
Society of America, 85(3), 1348-1351. (Eds.), Ecology of sensing {pp. 169-185). Berlin:
Haugeland, J. (1981). Analog and analog. Philo- Springer.
sophical Topics, 12, 213-226. LaValle, S. M. (2006). Planning algorithms. New
Haugeland, J. (1998). Mind embodied and York: Cambridge University Press.
embedded. In J. Haugeland (Ed.), Having Levins, R. (1968). Evolution in changing environ-
thought: Essays in the metaphysics of mind (pp. ments: Some theoretical explorations. Princeton,
207-238). Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univer- NJ: Princeton University Press.
sity Press. Maclver, M. A., 8c Nelson, M. E. (1996). Top-
Heiligenberg, W. (1991). Neural nets in electric ics in neuroethology. Retrieved October 17,
fish. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 2005, from http://nelson.beckman.uiuc.edu/
Hinde, R. A. (1970). Orientation. In Animal courses/neuroethol/
behavior: A synthesis of ethology and com- Maclver, M. A., Fontaine, E., 8c Burdick, J. W.
parative psychology (pp. 146-192). New York: (2004). Designing future underwater vehicles:
McGraw-Hill. Principles and mechanisms of the weakly elec-
Holderied, M. W., 8c von Helversen, O. (2003). tric fish. IEEE Journal of Oceanic Engineering,
Echolocation range and wingbeat period 29(3), 651-659.
match in aerial-hawking bats. Proceedings of Maglio, P., Matlock, T., Raphaely, D., Cher-
the Royal Society of London Series B, 270(1530), nicky, B., 8c Kirsh, D. (1999). Interactive skill
2293-2299. in Scrabble. In Proceedings of the Twenty-first
Holscher, C., Schnee, A., Dahmen, H., Setia, L., Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Soci-
& Mai lot, H. A. (2005). Rats are able to navi- ety. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
gate in virtual environments. Journal of Exper- Marler, P. (1991). Song-learning behavior: The
imental Biology, 208(3), 561-569. interface with neuroethology. Trends in Neu-
Hopkins, C. D. (2005). Projects in rteu- rosciences, 14(5), 199-206.
roethology. Retrieved September 18, 2005, Martin, A. W., 8c Fuhrman, F. A. (1955). The rela-
from http://instructi.cit.cornell.edu/courses/ tionship between summated tissue respiration
bionb^/ and metabolic rate in the mouse and the dog.
Physiological Zoology, 28, 18-34.
Hughes, H. C. (1999). Sensory exotica: A world
Martinez, I., Rosa, M., Arsuaga, J. L., Jarabo, P.,
beyond human experience. Cambridge, MA:
Quam, R., Lorenzo, C., et al. (2004). Auditory
MIT Press.
capacities in Middle Pleistocene humans from
Humphrey, N. (1992). A history of the mind. New
the Sierra de Atapuerca in Spain. Proceedings
York: Simon & Schuster.
of the National Academy of Sciences, 101(27),
Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cam- 9976-9981.
bridge, MA: MIT Press.
n e u r o e t h o l o g y4 & 1

McGeer, T. ( i g g 2 ) . Principles of walking and run- bat: A quantitative analysis of types of calls.
ning. In R. M. Alexander (Ed.), Advances in Journal of Mammalogy, 7 8 ( 3 ) , 9 6 4 - 9 7 6 .
comparative and environmental physiology u: Paulin, M. G. (2005). Evolutionary origins and
Mechanics of animal locomotion (pp. 1 1 3 - 1 3 9 ) . principles of distributed neural computation
Berlin: Springer-Verlag. for state estimation and movement control in
Meyerowitz, E. M. (2002). Plants compared to vertebrates. Complexity, 1 0 ( 3 ) , 5 6 - 6 5 .
animals: The broadest comparative study of Pfluger, H. J., 8c Menzel, R. (1999). Neuroethol-
development. Science, 295(5559), 1482-1485. ogy, its roots and future. Journal of Compara-
Michelsen, A. ( 1 9 9 8 ) . The tuned cricket. News in tive Physiology A, 185(4), 3 8 9 - 3 9 2 .
Physiological Sciences, 1 3 ( 1 ) , 3 2 - 3 8 . Rasnow, B. (1996). The effects of simple objects
Michelsen, A., Popov, A. V., & Lewis, B. (1994). on the electric field of Apteronotus. Journal of
Physics of directional hearing in the cricket Comparative Physiology A, 178(3), 3 9 7 - 4 1 1 .
Gryllus bimaculatus. Journal of Comparative Rasnow, B., 8c Bower, J. M. (1996). The electric
Physiology A, 1 7 5 ( 2 ) , 1 5 3 - 1 6 4 . organ discharges of the gymnotiform fishes: I.
Miller, L. A., 8c Surlykke, A. (2001). How some Apteronotus leptorkynchus. Journal of Compar-
insects detect and avoid being eaten by bats: ative Physiology A, 178(3), 3 8 3 - 3 9 6 .
Tactics and countertactics of prey and preda- Reed, E. S. (1996). Encountering the world: Toward
tor. Bioscience, 5 1 ( 7 ) , 5 7 0 - 5 8 1 . an ecological psychology. Oxford: Oxford Uni-
Mitchell, I. M., Bayen, A. M., 8c Tomlin, C. versity Press.
J. (2005). A time-dependent Hamilton-Jacobi Reichardt, W., & Poggio, T. ( 1 9 7 6 ) . Visual con-
formulation of reachable sets for continuous trol of orientation behavior in the fly. Part I.
dynamic games. IEEE Transactions on Auto- A quantitative analysis. Quarterly Reviews of
matic Control, 50(7), 947-957. Biophysics, 9(3), 3 1 1 - 3 7 5 .
Murlis, J., Willis, M. A., 8c Carde, R. T. (2000). Reichardt, W., 8c Wenking, H. (1969). Opti-
Spatial and temporal structures of pheromone cal detection and fixation of objects by fixed
plumes in fields and forests. Physiological Ento- flying flies. Naturwissenschaften, 56(8), 4 2 4 -
mology, 2 5 ( 3 ) , 211-222. 425.
Nelson, M. E., 8c Maclver, M. A. (2006). Sensory Ross, C. F. (2000). Into the light: The origin of
. acquisition in active sensing systems. Journal Anthropoidea. Annual Review of Anthropology,
of Comparative Physiology A, 192, 5 7 3 - 5 8 6 . 29,147-194.
Nielsen, C. (2001). Animal evolution: Interrela- Rowlands, M. (1999). The body in mind: Under-
tionships of the living phyla (2nd ed.). Oxford: standing cognitive processes. Cambridge: Cam-
Oxford University Press. bridge University Press.
Noe, A. ( 2 0 0 4 ) . Action in perception. Cambridge, Russell, I. J., 8cKossl, M. (1999). Micromechanical
M A : MIT Press. responses to tones in the auditory fovea of
Northcutt, R. G. ( 2 0 0 2 ) . Understanding verte- the greater mustached bat's cochlea. Journal
brate brain evolution. Integrative and Compar- of Neurophysiology, 82(2), 676-686.
ative Biology, 4 2 ( 4 ) , 7 4 3 - 7 5 6 . Schnitzler, H. U., Moss, C. F., 8c Denzinger, A.
Northcutt, R. G., 8c Cans, C. ( 1 9 8 3 ) . The gene- (2003). From spatial orientation to food acqui-
sis of neural crest and epidermal placodes: A sition in echolocating bats. Trends in Ecology
reinterpretation of vertebrate origins. Quar- & Evolution, 18(8), 386-394.
terly Review of Biology, 5 8 ( 1 ) , 1 - 2 8 . Semendeferi, K, Armstrong, E., Schleicher, A.,
O'Keefe, J., 8c Burgess, N. ( 2 0 0 5 ) . Dual phase Zilles, K, 8c van Hoesen, G. W. (2001). Pre-
and rate coding in hippocampal place cells: frontal cortex in humans and apes: A com-
Theoretical significance and relationship to parative study of area 10. American Journal of
entorhinal grid cells. Hippocampus, 1 5 , 8 5 3 - Physical Anthropology, 114(3), 224-241.
866. Sharpee, T. O., Sugihara, H., Kurgansky, A. V.,
O'Keefe, J., 8c Nadel, L. ( 1 9 7 8 ) . The hippocampus Rebrik, S. P., Stryker, M. P., 8c Miller, K.
as a cognitive map. New York: Oxford Univer- D. (2006). Adaptive filtering enhances infor-
sity Press. mation transmission in visual cortex. Nature,
O'Regan, J. K., & Noe, A. ( 2 0 0 1 ) . A sensorimo- 439(7°79). 93^~942-
tor account of vision and visual consciousness. Sherry, D. F., Vaccarino, A. L., Buckenham, K.,
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 2 4 ( 5 ) , 9 7 7 . 8c Herz, R. S. ( 1 9 8 9 ) . The hippocampal com-
Parsons, S., Thorpe, C. W., 8c Dawson, S. M. plex of food-storing birds. Brain, Behavior,
( 1 9 9 7 ) . Echolocation calls of the long-tailed and Evolution, 3 4 ( 5 ) , 3 0 8 - 3 1 7 .
MALCOLM A. MACIVF.R

Smulders, T. V., Sasson, A. D., & Devoogd, T. J. H. J. Bischof (Eds.), Vision, brain, and behav-
(1095). Seasons! variation in hippocampal vol- ior in birds (pp. 77-98). Cambridge, MA: MIT
ume in a food-storing bird, the black-capped Press.
chickadee. Journal of Neurobiology, 27(1), 15- Varjvi, D. (1975). Stationary and dynamic
responses during visual edge fixation by walk-
Snvder. J. B„ Rurdick, J. W., Nelson, M. E., ing insects. Nature, 255(5506), 330-332.
& Maclver, M. A. (2007). Omnidirectional Vendittelli, M., Laumond, J. P., & Nissoux, C.
sensory and motor volumes in an electric (1999). Obstacle distance for car-like robots.
fish. PLoS Biology 5(11) ejoi doi: 10.1371/ IEEE Transactions on Robotics and Automation,
journal .pbio.0050301. >9(4l 678-691.
Srinivasan. M., & Ruina, A. (2006). Com- Watanabe, A., & Takeda, K. (1963). The change
puter optimization of a minimal biped of discharge frequency by A . C . stimulus in
model discovers walking and running. Nature, a weak electric fish. Journal of Experimental
4390?o-^), 72-75. Biology, 40, 57-66.
Striedter. G. F. (2005). Principles of brain evolu- Wilson, R. A. (1994). Wide computationalism.
tion. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer. Mind, 103(411), 351-372.
Suga, N. (1990, June). Biosonar and neural com- Wilson, R. A. (1995). Cartesian psychology and
putation in bats. Scientific American, 60-68. physical minds: Individualism and the sciences
Szabo, T. (1974). Anatomy of the specialized lat- of the mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University
eral line organs of electroreception. In A. Fes- Press.
sard (Ed.), Electroreceptors and other specializedWotton, J. M., 8c Simmons, J. A. (2000). Spectral
receptors in lower vertebrates: Handbook of sen- cues and perception of the vertical position
sory physiology (Vol. 3, pp. 13-58). New York: of targets by the big brown bat, Eptesicus fus-
Springer. cus. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America,
Tinbergen, N. (1972). The animal in its world: 107(2), 1034-1041.
Explorations of an ethologist, 1932-1972. Lon- Wotton, J. M., Haresign, T., 8c Simmons, J.
don: Allen & Unwin. A. (1995). Spatially dependent acoustic cues
U.S. National Traffic Highway Safety Admin- generated by the external ear of the big
istration. (2004). Driving at night can be brown bat, Eptesicus fuscus. Journal of the
deadly. Retrieved September 19, 2005, from Acoustical Society of America, 98(3), 1423-
http://ntl.bts.gov/lib/000/200/251/deadly.pdf H45-
van Hateren, J. H., Kern, R., Schwerdtfeger, G., Zhang, J., 8c Wang, H. (2005). The effect of
& Egelhaaf, M. (2005). Function and coding external representations on numeric tasks.
in the blowfly Hi neuron during naturalis- Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology,
tic optic flow. Journal of Neuroscience, 25(17), 58/1(5), 817-838.
4343~4352- Zupanc, G. K. H. (2004). Behavioral neurobiology:
Varela, F. J., Palacios, A. G., & Goldsmith, T. H. An integrative approach. Oxford: Oxford Uni-
(1993). Color vision of birds. In H. P. Zeigler & versity Press.
Index

abstract representations, 253 adaptive toolbox for rationality, 326


academic disciplines, 18 affective primacy, 441
A C E (action-sentence compatibility effect), 374 affordances, 11, 25, 39, 293, 426, 447
action agent-dependent instruction manuals, 244
adaptive, 456, 491 Agre, P., 280
as causal contribution to representation, 129 AIR theory, 433
as presupposing representation, 129 Aizawa, Kenneth
in problem solving, 293 on contingent intracranialism, 68,
observation of, 209 78
of visual sensation, 190 on coupling, 485
parallel competition of, 311 on externalism, 9, 71, 499
perception as form of, 44 on mark of the cognitive, 87
representation in, 130 on situated experience, 421
situated, 27 Akman, Varol, 401, 412
spatial thought in, 208 alerting capacity, 187,195,196
task-exogenous, 270 Allen, C., 158
action-object couplets, 209 Allopenna, P. D., 385
action-sentence compatibility effect (ACE), 374 Altmann, G. T. M., 388
activity localization in learning, 358 ambiguity, fallacies of, 172
activity theory, 348 American Medical Association, 180
Aczel, P., 413 Amyote, L., 388
Adams, Fred anatomical discontinuity in visual sensation, 186
on contingent intracranialism, 68, 78 Anderson, J. R, 328, 341, 349
on coupling, 485 Anderson, M. L., 142,144
on externalism, 9, 71, 499 Angeles, P. A., 402
on mark of the cognitive, 87 animal cognition
Adamson, L. B., 470 bilateral symmetry in body plans, 490
adapted proper functions, 122 primate vs. human, 468
adaptive action, 456, 491 studies in, 24
INDEX
$66

biology
animate vision, 61, 62,136
animal body plans, 490
anthropology, 26
cognitive extension and, 58
Anzai, V , j»o
applications of cognitive science, 19 connectionism and, 141
appraisal theories, interdisciplinary themes of cognition, 24
Appretiticeship in Thinking (Rogoff), 353 mechanisms in, 159
apprenticeship, cognitive, 24, 348, 351 biomedical engineering, 363
architecture. See cognitive architectures BioSLIE (Biologically plausible
Aristotle, 36,179 Structure-sensitive Learning Inference
articulatoiy-motor system, 323 Engine), 145
Ashby, W . R . , 13,26 Blackburn, S., 402
associationism, 350 Blair, I. V., 458
atemporal models, 140 blank screen paradigm, 389
attention, joint, 222 blended disciplines. See interdisciplinary themes
attitudes, 401, 457 of cognition
attract or networks, 141 blindness
attunement theory, 296 continuation, 281
audience effects, 438 inattentional, 188
Austin, J. L., 22,404 change, 188, 424
autobiographical memory, 221 Block, N., 421
autonomous systems, 163 Blumer, Herbert, 21
autopoesis, 25 body and spatiality, 195, 196, 202. See also
Avdede, Murat, 3 embodied mind
The Body in Mind (Rowlands), 91
Bach-y-Rita, Paul, 193,429 Bompas, A., 195
Bakeman, R . 470 Botvinick, M., 192
Baldwin, M. W., 460 boundaries
Ballard, Dana, 62,136,191, 500 control theory and, 149
Bamberger, J., 23 in complex systems, 14
Bangerter, A., 393 in problem solving, 268
Bar, M., 250 Boundaries of the Mind (Wilson), 81
Barclay, J. R., 248 Bransford, J. D., 22
Bargh, J. A., 252 Brennan, S. E., 392
Barrett, L. F., 458 Brewer, M. B., 458
Barsalou, Lawrence W. Bridgeman, B., 500
on situated concepts, 236 Brighton, Henry, 322, 336
perceptual symbol systems model of, Broca, Paul, 157
45s Brooks, R. A . , 6, 26, 89, 299, 341, 500
Bardett, F. C., 22, 218, 220 Brown, John Seely, 347, 348, 351
Barwise, Jon, 402,404,411,412 Brownell, C. A . , 471
Bateson, C . , 11,18,25, 26 Brown-Schmidt, S., 393, 394
Bayesian inference, 331 Bruner, J., 23
Bechtel, William, 149,155,160,164, 356 Brunswick, Egon, 25, 308, 324
The Bee's Language (Frisch), 25 Buccino, G . , 375, 377
behaviorism, 136, 350 Buena Vista Sensing C l u b hypothesis, 492
Behne, T., 471,475 Buhler, Karl, 25
Being and Time (Heidegger), 38 Burge, Tyler, 57
Bentley, A. F., 21 Burks, A. W., 13
Bergson, H., 42,224 Busemeyer, J e r o m e R., 307
Bernard, Claude, 159,165
Berzelius, J. J., 159 Campbell, John, 223
Biederman, I., 248 Campbell, Sue, 221
bilateral symmetry in animal body plans, canalization, 97
490 Cannon, Walter, 165
Bingham, G . , 64 Carlson, T. B., 402
INDEX f°7

Carnegie Symposium in Cognition, 347 cognitive collages, 207


Carpenter, M., 473,475
cognitive extension. See also extended mind, 55
Carraher, David, 347 articulating idea of, 62
Carraher, T. N., 272 critiques of, 68
Carriger, M. S., 471 historical roots, 56
Cartesian internalism, 8 in biology and computation, 58
categorization, 24g, 334 cognitive life of things, 227
causal dependence, 6, 421 cognitive maps, 207
cellular automata mechanisms, 26 cognitive off-loading, 6
Center for the Study of Language and cognitive partnership, 364
Information (CSLI), 402 cognitive psychology, 249, 311
Chalmers, D. Cognitive Science journal, 349
extension thesis of, 8 Cognitive Science Society, 16,27
on coupling, 84 Cohen, J., 192
on extended cognition, 66, 67, 69, 71,79, Cole, M., 2i, 27
500 collaborative inhibition, 226
on mark of the cognitive, 87 collaborative recall, 226
on scaffolding, 445 collective memory. See shared memory
Chambers, C. G., 386, 388 Collins, Allan, 348, 351
Chambers, D., 279 color
change blindness, 188, 424
chaos theory, 12, 19, 26 experience to action adaptation, 194
Chapman, D., 280 perception of, 348
Chomsky, Noam, 57 visual sensation and sensorimotor approach,
chronic recording, 481 194
Churchland, P. S., 140 combinatorial constraint, 118
circumspection, 39 common ground, 241, 350, 370, 391,402
Clancey, William J., 11, 22, 25, 341 communication
Clark, Andy cooperative, 475
cybernetics and, 19
on change blindness, 188 gestures as, 209
on cognition as information processing, 87 in groups, 354
on coupling, 84 learning role of, 354, 359
on decouplability, 127 situated context, 459
on embedding, 7 spatiality in, 209
on extended cognition, 8, 55, 79, 97, 500 diagrams, 211
on mark of the cognitive, 87 gestures, 209
on scaffolding, 228, 445 complex systems, 12
on situations in cognition, 242 adaptive, 12,13
Clark, H., 383, 391, 393, 402 boundaries in, 14
classical sandwich model of mind, 425 compositional networks in, 14
classical theory emergence in, 14
control, 137 features of, 13
problem solving, 265 feedback loops, 14
classroom learning, 362 in learning, 355, 359
closed-loop control, 137, 484 theory, 19
coaching. See guided participation; scaffolds component-dominant dynamics, 383
cognitive anthropology, 61 compositionality, 14, 403
cognitive apprenticeship, 24, 348, 351 computation
cognitive architectures, 136 as mark of the cognitive, 87
behaviorism in time, 136 extended mind and, 58, 60
challenges for, 142 in language processing, 383
connectionism, 140 in problem solving, 298
mind as motion, 139 morphological, 484
time constraints, 137 neural engineering framework (NEF), 144
cognitive augmentation, 63 Computation and Cognition (Pylyshyn), 57
INDEX
568

m o d e m theory, 1 4 3 , 1 4 8 , 1 4 9
concepts. Scr situated concepts and teleceptive sensation and, 493, 496
conceptualizations convenient group p r o b l e m solving, 272
conceptual pacts, 392 convergence zones, 238
conceptual systems, 236 conversation, 391. See also discourse level
conceptual-intentional system, 323 language processing
concreteness Cooke, E., 193
of cognition, 339 Cooper, R., 383, 412
of representations, 254 cooperative activities, 470
connectionism cooperative communication, 471, 475
biology and, 141 core relational themes, 442
cognitive architectures, 140 corporality, 4 4 , 1 9 5 , 1 9 6
development of, 13 Cosmides, L., 158
low-level models of, 141 coupling
memory and, 219 constitution fallacy, 81, 84
systems thinking and, 15 emotion and, 445
Conrey, Frederica R., 454 representation constraints o f , 126
consciousness, 419 resources, 68
constructivism and, 7 Cree, G. S., 243
moderate embodiment of, 430
cross-disciplines, 18. See also interdisciplinary
phenomenal, 7
themes of cognition
radical embodiment of, 425
cross-modal associations, 238
situated experience and, 420
cross-recurrence analysis, 394
constraint-satisfaction view of language
Crowe, E., 456
processing, 369
C S L I (Center f o r t h e S t u d y o f L a n g u a g e and
constructivism
Information), 402
consciousness and, 7
cultural articulation, 444
in systems thinking, 16
cultural cognition, 467
interdisciplinary themes of cognition, 20
cooperative activities, 470
language and, 23
cooperative c o m m u n i c a t i o n , 471
memory and, 218
radical, 25 goal-directed action, understanding o f , 473
context dependence, 105, 316, 338 in dependent hierarchy, 19
context-specific representation, 105 ontogeny of, 469
contextual effects on learning, 410 primate vs. h u m a n , 468
contingent intracranialism, 78 relativism in, 17
cognition as information processing, 87 shared intentionality, understanding o f ,
computation in, 87 474
coupling arguments, 81 cultural scaffolding, 442—444
Gibbs's interpersonal, 86 Cummins, Robert, 1 0 7 , 1 5 8 , 159
simple, 81 cybernetics, 8 , 1 3 , 1 5 , 2 4 , 1 3 7
system version of, 83 Cycles of Contingency ( O y a m a , G r i f f i t h s , &
evolutionary argument, 90 G r a y ) , 59
mark of the cognitive and, 86
meaning in, 88 Dale, R , 393
operationalizing in, 88 Darwin, Charles, 446
resources and, 68 Davidson, D o n a l d , 403
transcranialism vs., 78 Davidson, J. E., 275
continuation blindness, 281 Davis, W. A . , 407
continuity in experience of visual sensation, Dawkins, Richard, 59
186 decentralized procedural m o d e l , 16
control decision analysis, 308
feedback, 137 decision making, 307
in dynamic systems, 150 context-dependent p r e f e r e n c e s , 316
loci of, 164 decision-field t h e o r y , 314
metacognitive, 300 embedded, 106
INDEX

sequential sampling processes, 311 Donald, Merlin, 220, 228


situated, 307 double bind theory, 25
decomposability of mechanisms, 159 007 principle, 7, 62
distributed cognition and, 359 Dretske, F., 120,123
homuncular, 107 DST. See developmental systems theory
in learning, 356 dual component account of representation, 128
spatiality and, 202, 336 Duchenne smiles, 438
decouplability constraint, 126 Duguid, Paul, 348
deictic pointers, 389 Dummett, Michael, 173
Dennett, D. C., 79, 423 Dunbar, G., 242
dependency on external environment, 421 Duranti, A., 402
dependent hierarchy, 19 Durkheim, £., 21
derived proper functions, 122 Dynamic Memory (Schank), 22
Descartes, 41,159 dynamic systems, 134
detached databases view of concepts, 244 cognitive architectures, 136
developmental psychology, 102 behaviorism in time, 136
developmental systems theory (DST), 58, 59, challenges for, 142
98 connectionism, 140
Devlin, K., 404, 409, 412 mind as motion, 139
D e w e y , John time constraints, 137
as constructivist, 20, 23 control and, 150
influence of, 26 decision making in, 310
on language, 22 emotion and coupling, 445
on learning, 21 neural engineering framework (NEF),
on organism and environment, 36 142
on stimulus-response theory, 11 computation in, 144
theory of inquiry, 24 embedded mind in, 147
diachronic scaffolding, 443, 44; theory of, 8, 383
diagrams and spatiality of communication, 211
dialogic cognitive representations, 472 Eberhard, K. M„ 387
Dieckmann, A., 339 Eckerman, C. O., 470,471
differentiation in biological systems, 165 ecological psychology, 25
Dijksterhuis, A., 252 ecological rationality, 331
Dimperio, Eric, 307 as situated cognition, 338
direct proper functions, 122 concrete dimension of, 339
disciplinary perspectives, 18 constraints of, 336
discontinuity in visual sensation, 186 embodied dimension of, 340
discourse-level language processing, 355, 375, engaged dimension of, 339
39i located dimension of, 338
discrimination, out-group, 460 social dimension of, 340
dissipative structures, 26 specific dimension of, 340
distributed cognition economical vision, 190
development of, 15 Edelman, G. M., 26
functional localization and, 359 education. See learning
in memory, 227 egocentric spatial framework, 42
in social context, 461 Eliasmith, Chris, 134,142,144
situated perspective of, 348, 362 eliminativism, 99,128, 330
distributed memory in groups, 462 Ellis, R., 372
division of labor between mind and body, 37, Elman, J., 386
165 embedded mind
dogma of intrinsic unsuitability, 69 defined, 6
domains language processing and, 384
innateness specificity to, 105 nativism and, 105
mechanisms specific to, 326 neural engineering framework (NEF), 147
problem solving independence from, 268 rationality and, 171
Sio
extemalism
embodied mind in language, 46
as mechanism, 165 . in neuroethology, 482
as philosophical antecedent to situated memory and, 391
cognition, 42 representation and, 66, 227
consciousness and, 425 vehicle, 58,127,128, 130
defined, 5
ecological rationality and, 340 factoring assumption, 358
in social context, 457 fallacies of ambiguity, 172
emergence in complex systems, 14 feedback loops and control, 14,137
emergent literacy, 355 Feldman, M., 59
emotional capital, 444 felt location example of sensorimotor approach
emotions, 437-444 192
cultural scaffolding, 442-444 Ferretti, T., 388
dynamic coupling, 445
fictive motion descriptions, 389
negotiation of, 446
figurative language, 389
nonconceptual content, 440
Firth, John Rupert, 402
scripts, 444
Fischer, A. H., 442, 443-444
social situatedness, 438
Fitneva, S., 392
enactive processes and representations, 38, 420,
Fivush, R., 222
426
Flourens, J. P. M., 158
engaged dimension of cognition, 339
Fodor, Jerry
Engel, Susan, 220
on cognitive architecture, 144
entrainment, lexical, 392
on functionalism, 57
entrenched conceptualizations, 97,98, 245,
on methodological solipsism, 56,155
491
on modularity, 157,158
environment. See also extended mind;
extemalism; spatiality on symbolicist systems, 145
problem solving, 265, 280 framing
environmentalism, 58 concepts in situations, 242
episodic memory, 237 in problem solving, 271
epistemic actions in semantics, 401
cognitive off-loading, 6 of abstract concepts, 240
in language processing, 389 Franklin, N., 204
in problem solving, 281 Freeman, W. J., 26,128
equiavailability model, 204 Freud, Sigmund, 224
ethnoscience, 18 Fridlund, A. J., 439
ethology, 25 Frisch, Karl von, 25
Evans, G., 440 Fu, W.-T., 72
events, 208 functional localization

evolutionary perspective distributed cognition and, 359


in neuroscience, 492 in learning, 356, 358
mark of the cognitive, 90 functionalism, 57,108
of emotions, 443 Furneaux, S. M., 428
perception and cognition relationship,
241 Galambos, R., 487
psychology, 157 Gall, Franz Joseph, 1 5 7 , 1 5 8
exograms, 227 Gallagher, Shaun, 3, 5, 35
extended mind. See also cognitive extension, 7 Gallanter, E., 278
emotion and, 448 GAnti, Tibor, 163
extemalism and, 58 Gardner, H., 24
nati vism and, 96 Gawron, J. M., 412
representation and, 128 general semantics, 13, 22
T E C S and, 66 general systems theory, 11,12, 13
extended phenotype, 59 generality constraint, 440
extended systems and nativism, 102
generative entrenchment, 97, 98
INDEX 5"

genetic algorithms, 13, 28 Hall, R., 362


geographic spaces, 206 Hanna, J. E., 392
Gestalt theory of problem solving, 274 Hare, B., 468,476
gestures, 209 Hastie, R., 462
as communication, 209,47; Haugeland, J., 88, 493
in problem solving, 297 Head, H., 26, 42
in spatial descriptions, 210 HEC (hypothesis of extended cognition), 70,96,
language comprehension and, 371, 376 104
memory and, 210 Heidegger, M., 38
Gibbs, Raymond, 82, 86 Hein, A., 426
Gibson, J. J. Held, R., 426
ecological psychology of, 384 HEMC (hypothesis of embedded cognition),
influence of, 26 7°
on affordances, 11, 25, 39, 293,426 heuristic tools
on dynamics, 135 in rationality, 326
on mechanical signals in environment, QuickEst estimation, 330
482 recognition and paired comparison, 328
on perception and environment, 404 Take the Best, 329
on vision, 7 Hewitt, C., 16
Gick, M., 275 hidden curriculum, 354
Gigerenzer, G., 309, 329 Higgins, E. T., 456
Gigone, D., 462 Hinde, Robert, 446
Gilbert, Margaret, 225, 226 hints in problem solving, 291. See also scaffolds
Gilchrist, I D., 428 Hintzman, D. L., 368, 369
Glasersfeld, E. von, 20, 25 Hirst, William, 226
Glenberg, A. M., 242, 250, 374, 375, 377 historical kinds, 178
goal-directed action, understanding of, 473 Hoerl, Christopher, 223
Goffinan, E., 21, 401 Holmes, G., 42
Goodwin, C., 402 Holyoak, K., 275
Gotz, Karl, 484 homeostasis, 165
grabbiness of visual transients. See alerting homuncular decomposition, 107
capacity HRR vectors, 145
grain size factor of situations, 255 Hume, David, 195
Gray, W. D., 59, 72 Humphrey, N., 468, 500
Greeno, James G. Hurley, S. L., 4, 56, 79,425
on affordances, 293 Husserl, E., 42,195
on dynamical system models, 296 Hutchins, Edwin, 88, 348, 358, 461,463
on learning, 347 hypothesis of embedded cognition (HEMC), 70
on problem solving, 29; hypothesis of extended cognition (HEC), 70, 96,
on situated concepts, 242 104
Griffin, D. R., 487
Griffiths, Paul, 59, 73,100, 437, 449 iconic representations, 118
group dynamics ideational factors, 443
communication in, 354 imitation
distributed cognition in, 461 in decision process, 330
in-group and out-group, 460 learning pattern of, 470
learning in, 361 impredicative systems, 385
memory in, 462 inattentional blindness, 188
groupthink, 462 individual learning, 361
guided participation. See also scaffolds individualistic conception of mind, 56
learning as, 352 individuation scheme, 405
Gunderson, Keith, 155 induction, 332, 335
inferences
Halbwachs, M., 224 Bayesian, 331
pattern completion, 245
Hall, E. T„ 21, 26
INDEX
5*5

journey line representation, 362


inferences («mt.)
semantics, 409 Kahneman, D., 316
statistical character of, 246 Kamide, Y„ 388
infons, 405 Kamin, L. J., 16
informal learning, 352 Kaschak, Michael P., 250, 368, 373, 374, 377
information. See also knowledge Kauffmann, S. A . , 26
encapsulation of, 157 Keams, David, 347
processing, 87 Keefe, R., 404
relativity of, 119 Keysar, B., 392
representation constraints of, 119
Kirkham, N., 391
in-group preferences, 460
Kirsh, David, 218, 264, 281, 393, 461
inhibition, collaborative, 226
Kit ay am a, S., 444
insight problems, 291
Klatzky, R. L., 374
Institute for Research on Learning, 347
Klein, G. A., 309
instruction manuals, agent-dependent,
knowledge, n, 265, 269, 270, 289
244
Korzybski, A., 22
integrated systems, 357
Kroon, R. M., 442
integration, neural, 143
Krych, M. A., 393
intenders, 107
intentionality
Laland, K., 59
consciousness and, 38
Lampert, Magdalene, 362
content and, 421
Land, M. F., 428
in communication, 403
shared, 469 Langer, S., 22
interaction-dominant dynamics, 384 language, 368. See also semantics
interactivity comprehension, 253
computation and, 383
analysis of, 355, 360
in problem solving, 277 constructivism in, 23
intercorporeality, 44 discourse level, 375, 391
interdisciplinary themes of cognition in context of everyday life, 45
anthropology and cognition, 26 interdisciplinary themes of cognition, 21
biology and cognition, 24 memory and, 21, 389
constructivism, 20 processing, 382
education and cognition, 20 embedded in situational context, 384
language and cognition, 21 semantic memory, 389
memory, 217 sentence level, 372
neurology and cognition, 26 motor traces, 374
philosophy and cognition, 20 perceptual traces, 373
sociology and cognition, 21 word level, 371
internalism, 8, 482 motor traces, 372
interoceptive inferences, 244, 251 perceptual traces, 371
interpretation and semantics, 411 Language, Thought and Other Biological
intersubjectivity, 44, 444 Categories (Millikan), 121
intracranialism. See contingent intracranialism Larkin, J. H., 278
intrinsic intentionality, 69 Lashley, K. S., 26,158
intuitive knowledge, 273 Latour, B., 21
Isard, S. D., 248 Lave, J.
isomorphism of problem, 273 on apprenticeship, 351, 352
on contextual effects, 271
Jackendoff, R., 144, 432 on problem solving, 347, 349
James, W., 20, 422, 458 on situated learning, 27, 348, 353
Jenkins, J. J., 22 Lazarus, R. S., 441
Jessup, Ryan K., 307 learning, 347
joint attention, 222 activity localization, 358
Journal of the Learning Sciences, 348 as apprenticeship, 351
index

as guided participation, 352 sketch, 212


category, 249 spatiality of navigation, 205
communication role in, 354, 359 mark of the cognitive, 86
complexity in, 355, 359 as computational, 87
decomposability, 356 as meaningful, 88
distributed cognition and, 359 cognition as information processing, 87
educational theory, 23 evolutionary argument, 90
functional localization, 356, 358 operationalizing, 88
in classroom, study of, 362 Markus, H . R ., 444
in cultural context, 468 Marr, David, 57,432
in scientific work environment, study of, material factors, 443, 444
363 Matlock, T. M., 389
individual and group, 361 Matter and Memory (Bergson), 42
interdisciplinary themes of cognition, 20 Maturana, H. R., 24,128
legitimate peripheral participation, 352 Max Planck Center for Biological Cybernetics,
nature of, 19 483
outcomes, 353 maximal inferential promiscuity, 440
research on, 350 McClamrock, Ron, 79
situated, 27 McClelland, J. L., 219, 386
social context, 361 McCormack, Teresa, 223
Lécuyer, R., 427 McGeer, T., 490
Le Doux, J. E., 441 McKay, T., 408
Leech, G., 391 McNeill, D., 376
legitimate peripheral participation, 352 McRae, K., 243, 388
Leibniz, 100 Mead, G. H., 21, 26
less-is-more effect, 329 meaning
Levin, D. T., 424, 497 as mark of the cognitive, 88
lexical entrainment, 392 linguistic, 45
linguistic meaning, 4; semantics and, 407
Liszkowski, U., 472 meaningfulness factor of situations, 256
literacy and narrative language, 3 ; ; mechanical ecology, 486
lived body, 42 mechanisms
Livingston, R. W., 458 decomposability of, 159
localization division of mind and brain, 157
activity, 358 embodied cognitive, 165
functional, 356, 358, 359 modularity vs., 160
located dimension of cognition, 338 situated cognitive, 165
locational externalism, 57-58 mechanistic explanation, 356
loci of control, 164 Meltzoff, A. N., 473
Loft us, E., 22 memory, 217
Lorenz, Konrad, 25 as constructive activity, 218, 219
low-level connectionist models, 141 as interpersonal skill, 218, 219
Luchins, A. S., 275 as social interaction and joint attention to
Lyons, J., 402 past, 222
autobiographical, 221
Maclver, Malcolm A., 480 cognitive life of things, 227
Mack, A., 424, 432 collaborative recall, 226
distributed cognition and exograms, 227
MacKay, D., 188
episodic, 237
Maglio, P., 283, 301, 393
gestures and, 210
Magnuson, J. S., 388
group dynamics of, 462
Mandler, J. M„ 248
Halbwachs on, 224
Manstead, A. S. R., 442, 443-444 interdisciplinary framework for, 217
maps language and cognition in, 21
between representations, 299 plural subject of, 225
cognitive, 207, 212
w

natural kinds, 179


memory (com.)
naturalistic decision making, 309
semantic, 237
navigation, spatiality of, 205
shared, 134
near-decomposability, 161
visual sensation, 186
NEF. See neural engineering f r a m e w o r k
anatomical discontinuity, 186
negotiation of emotion, 446
experiential continuity, 186
Nelson, K., 222
world as outside memory hypothesis, 187
Nelson, M., 408
mental maps, 112
Nersessian, N. J., 363
mental transformation model, 204
neural engineering framework ( N E F ) , 142
Merleau-Ponty, M., 42, 1S5
computation in, 144
metabolic ignorance, 72
embedded mind in, 147
metacognitive control of discovery, 300, 302
neural network modeling, 15, 219, 310
methodological solipsism, 56,155
neuroethology, 480
Metzing, C., 392
bat ears example, 487
Michaels, S., 355
bilateral symmetry in animal b o d y plans,
Mill, J. S., 177
490
Miller, G. A., 248, 278
Buena Vista Sensing C l u b hypothesis, 492
Millikan, Ruth, 121,171
fly eye geometry e x a m p l e , 488
Minsky, M.. 14,15
intern alism and e x t e m a l i s m in, 482
misrepresentation constraint, 127
morphological computation, 484
Mitroff, S. R., 424
multiple timescales of adaptive
modality-specific representations, 4
entrenchment, 491
modality-specific simulations, 237
passive walkers, 490
modeling. See also specific models, 19, 364
relevance of, 484
modem control theory, 143,148,149
teleceptive sensation
modularity
control and, 493, 496
mechanisms vs., 160
history of, 492
of mind, 57,155
of semantic memory, 237 of movement and space, 494
Moll, H„ 474 neurology, 19, 26,135, 437
Moore, Joyce, 349 neuropsychology, 219
Moreno, Alvero, 163 Newell, A . , 14,16, 5 7 , 1 3 8 , 265
morphological computation, 484 Newton, Isaac, 492
Morrison, J. B , 203 niche construction, 58, 467
Moss, L. S., 412 Niche Construction: The Neglected Process in
Most, S. B., 432 Evolution (Laland & F e l d m a n ) , 59
motivation, 456 Niedenthal, P. M„ 458
motor experiential traces in language, 372, 374 Noe, A .
motor resonance, 375, 376 on causation and constitution, 82
multiagent systems modeling, 1 3 , 1 5 on eliminativism, 128
multi-level appraisal theories, 442 on enactive consciousness, 422, 427, 429
multimodal simulations, 244 on sensory perception, 3 8 , 1 3 0 , 195, 426
multiple-loop systems, 143 on virtual reality scenarios, 484
Murphy, K. M., 298 nominal kinds, 178
Myin, Erik, 185,195 nonconceptual emotional content, 440
norm following in decision process, 330
Nagel, T., 40 Norman, D. A . , 72
narrative, 21, 355 normativity
nativism, 96 of proper functions, 123
embedded cognition, 10; of representation, 1 2 0 , 1 3 1
extended cognition, 96 Nunes, Terezina, 347, 349
extended systems, 102
representations objective body, 42
context-specific, 105 objectivism, 15
persistent, 109 object-oriented thinking, 297
INDEX

Occam's razor, 331, 332, 334, 335 embodiment, 42


Odling-Smee, John, 59 interdisciplinary themes of cognition, 20
off-line sensorimotor processing, 4 language and, 45
off-loading, 6 organism-environment, 36
Olick, J. K., 226 spatiality, 38
on-line and on-demand attributes of vision, 190, phronesis, 36
191 physical transformation model, 205
on-line sensorimotor processing, 4 Piaget, J., 20, 23, 26
The Ontogeny of Information (Oyama), 59 Plato, 100,157
ontology and semantics, 405 Poincart, H., 192
open text ambiguity, 411-412 Polanyi, M., it, 21
open-loop control, 137 Port, R., 138
operationalizing cognition, 88 Povinelli, D. J., 223
optic flow, 488 pre-literacy, 355
Opticks (Newton), 492 presonance, 369
oracles in semantics, 409 Pribram, K. H., 278
O'Regan, J. Kevin Prigogine, I., 26
on eliminativism, 128 primary intersubjectivity, 444
on enactive visual perception, 130 primitivist view of innateness, 104
on sensory perception, 185, 426 Prinz, Jesse, 419, 437, 500
world as outside memory theme of, 6 problem isomorphism, 273
organizational closure, 2; problem solving, 264
Otto, P., 339 classical theory, 26;
outcomes, learning, 353
ill-defined problems in, 268
out-group discrimination, 460
Newell and Simon on, 265
Oyama, Susan, 59
objections to, 268
problem space, 266
paired comparison tool, 328 task environment, 265
Papert, S., 16, 23 environmental structure, 265, 280
parallel competition of actions, 311 epistemic actions, 281
parity claim, 71 external representations, 278
Parkinson, B., 442, 443-444 framing, 271
Partee, B. H., 413 gestures in, 297
partiality in situation semantics, 406 interactivity, 277
participation structures, 352, 354 positive theory on, 290
passive walkers, 490 affordances and activity, 293
path integration, 496 hints, 291
pattern completion inferences, 245 metacognitive control of discovery,
Peirce, C. S., 20, 37, 297 self-cueing, 300
perception thinking with things, 297
as f o r m of action, 44 process model of, 274
in language, 371, 373 registration, 276
Perceptions (Minsky), 16 resources and scaffolds, 284
perceptual symbol systems model, 458 spatiality in, 266, 349
peripheral participation, 352 special-case solutions, 286
problematic situation, 37
Perry, John, 402, 404
procedural memory, 219
persistent representations, 109
procedural rationality, 332, 333
personal derived proper functions, 125
process model of problem solving, 274
perspective inferences, 251
proper functions, 122
Peters, S., 412
adapted, 122
phenomenal consciousness, 7 derived, 122
phenotypes, extended, 59
Philipona, D., 192,194 personal vs. sub-personal, 124
philosophy relational, 122
antecedents to situated cognition, 35 protected values in decision process, 330
Si6
combinatorial constraint, 118
Putnam. Hilary, 57 decouplability constraint, 126
Pytyshyn, Zenon, 57, >44, H5 informational constraint, 119
misrepresentation constraint, 127
QuickEst estimation, 325, 330 teleological constraint, 121
teleosemantics stimulus and benefits, 123
radial categories, 254 dialogic cognitive, 472
radical constructivism, 25 dual component account of, 128
Ramachandran, V., 192
emotions and, 441
rationality, 322
enactive, 420
adaptive toolbox, 326
extended mind and, 128
ecological, 331
external, 227
as situated cognition, 338
frameworks, 19
concrete dimension, 339
iconic, 118
constraints of, 336
in action, 129, 457
embodied dimension, 340
in problem solving, 278
engaged dimension, 339
journey line, 362
located dimension, 338
mapping between, 299
social dimension, 340
modality-specific, 4
specific dimension, 340
normativity of, 120
heuristic tools, 326
of abstract, 253
QuickEst estimation, 330
of concepts, 247
recognition and paired comparison, 328
persistent, 109
Take the Best, 329
sensorimotor aspects of, 457
mind and environment relationships, 323
situated cognition and, 127
procedural, 333
somatic, 420
substantive, 333
spatiality and, 208
real kinds, 179
theory of mind, 425
real-time socialization, 445
vehicle, 119
recall, collaborative, 226
Wittgenstein on, 47
Recanati, F., 403
resonance process, 368, 370, 375, 376
recognition heuristic, 328
resources in problem solving, 284, 297. See also
recognition-primed decision model, 311
scaffolds
reconstructive memory retrieval, 245, 247
Richardson, Daniel, 149, 160, 164, 356, 377,
Reddy, V., 442
382
Reder, Lynne, 349
Rieskamp, J., 339
redescriptions in semantic memory, 237
Rivière, J., 427
Reese, Elaine, 223
Robbins, Philip, 3
reference objects, 206
robotics, situated, 18, 26, 61
reference point effect, 317
Rock, I., 432
registration in problem solving, 276
Rogers-Ramachandran, D., 192
Reichardt, Werner, 484
Rogoff, B., 27, 348, 353
Reid, Thomas, 157
Rokeach, Milton, 401
Reisberg, D., 279
Rosen, Robert, 382
relational proper functions, 122
Rosenberg, D., 413
relativism, cultural, 17
Rosenfield, I., 26
relativity of information, 119
rotation error, 206
relevance of proposition to context, 410
Rowlands, Mark, 46, 89, 90,117
remembering. See memory
rubber hand experiment, 192
Remembering: A Study in Experimental and Social
Rubin, A., 362
Psychology (Bartlett), 218
Ruina, Andy, 490
Rensink, R. A., 188
Rumelhart, D. E., 219
representation, 117
Rupert, Robert, 8, 68, 70, 96
clarification in visual sensation, 189
Russell, Bertrand, 173,175, 407
context-specific, 105
Ryle, G., 22
criteria of, 117
INDEX 5*7

Sacks, O., 26 sensory substitution, 193


sandwich model processing, 4 sentence-level language processing, 372
Savage-Rumbaugh, Sue, 67 sequential-sampling processes, 311
Sawyer, R. Keith, 347, 360 shared intentionality, understanding of, 469,473,
Sayeki, Y., 295 474
scaffolds shared memory, 224
cultural, 442-444 collaborative recall, 226
in problem solving, 284 Halbwachs on, 224
Scarantino, Andrea, 73, 437, 449 plural subject of, 225
Schacter, Daniel, 221 Shaw, R. E., 25
Schank, R. C., 22, 347 Shepard, Roger, 323, 327
scheme of individuation, 405 Shoben, E. J., 253
Schliemann, Annalucia, 347 signal-detection theory, 311
Schon, D. A., 23, 24 The Silent Language (Hall), 21
Schubert, T. W., 458 Silverman, ML, 424
Schuman, H., 226 Simon, H. A.
Schwanenflugel, D. J., 253 as anti-behaviorist, 14,16
Schwartz, B., 226 on complex situations, 349
Scientific Management (Taylor), 37 on coupling mind and environment, 324
Scribner, S., 27, 272, 347, 349 on external representations, 278
scripts, emotional, 444 on near decomposability, 161
search, 329, 340 on problem solving, 265, 309
secondary subjectivity, 444 on substantive and procedural rationality,
seeing. See visual sensation 332/ 333
Sejnowski, T., 140 physical symbol system of, 57,138
self-consciousness, 430 Simons, D. J., 424
self-cueing, 300 simulation theory, 44
The Selfish Gene (Dawkins), 59 situated action, 27
Seligman, J., 412 situated cognition
semantic memory, 237, 389 as cognitive extension, 55
semantics, 401 as mechanism, 165
constraints, 406 ecological rationality as, 338
context for, 401 in social context, 458
general, 13, 22 philosophical antecedents of, 3;
interpretation, 411 primer on, 3
literature on, 412 representation and, 127
meaning, 407 scientific antecedents to, 11
ontology, 405 systems thinking in, 16
oracles, 409 situated concepts and conceptualizations, 236,
representations, 118 244
situated inference, 409
conceptual systems, 236
S T A S S , 402
cumulative nature of, 256
Semin, G. R., 456, 463
defined, 243
sensorimotor approach
definitions, 242
color sensation, 194
dimensions of, 255
contingency theory, 192
entrenched, 245
embodied mind and, 4
evidence for, 246
felt location example, 192
from cognitive psychology, 249
rubber hand experiment, 192
from social psychology, 251
sensory consciousness, 19;
interoceptive and perspective inferences,
sensory quality and substitution, 193
251
visual sensation and, 191
sensory consciousness, 195 representation in memory, 247
sensory ecology, 486 representation of abstract, 253
sensory quality, 193 modality-specific simulations in, 237
multimodal simulations in, 244
INDEX

diagrams in, 211


situated concepts (amf.)
egocentric framework, 42
origins of, 241
gestures in, 209, 376
pattern-completion inferences, 245
grain size of situation and, 255
radial categories, 254
Heidegger on, 41
semantic memory, 237
in communication, 209
statistical character of inference, 246
in problem solving, 266, 349
situated inference and semantics, 409
in thought, 202
situated learning, 27, 348
situated perception, 185 action and, 208
situated robotics, 18, 26, 61 mental transformations, 208
situation theory and situation semantics situated mental space, 208, 213
(STASS), 402, 412 space around body, 204
situations, defined, 243 space for, 202
Skarda, C., 128 space of body, 202
sketch maps, 212 space of navigation, 205
Smith, B. C., 323, 338 mental framework, 204
Smith, E. E., 237 neuroscience and, 497
Smith, Eliot R., 128,454, 456,463 of representations, 208
Smithers, T., 128 teleceptive sensation and, 494
Snedeker, J., 388 specific dimension of cognition, 340
S O A R symbolicist cognitive model, 138, 293 Sperber, Daniel, 158, 410
social context, 454. See also social psychology Spivey, Michael, 51 382, 389, 391, 392
adaptive action in, 456 S T A S S (situation theory and situation
distributed cognition in, 461 semantics), 402, 412
embodied cognition in, 457 statistical character of inference, 246
emotions in, 438 Steels, L., 26
learning and, 353 Stein, N., 248
memory in, 218 Sterelny, K., 100
of cognition, 340 Sternberg, R. J., 275
situated cognition in, 458 stimulus-response theory, 11
social identities, 460 Stoicism, 36
social judgment theory, 307 stored program theory of mind, 14, 15
social psychology storytelling, 21, 355
defined, 454 structuralism, 23, 25
in learning, 348, 361 structure-specific mechanisms, 326
memory and, 218 subjectivity, secondary, 444
situated concepts and conceptualizations in, subpersonal derived proper functions, 125
2 substantive rationality, 333

Suchman, L. A., 27, 347
social stimuli, 252
Sutton, John, 217
social-interactionist theory, 223
symbol-grounding problem, 3, 371
Society for Neuroscience, 135
symbolic interaction, 21
Society of Mind (Minsky), 15,16
symbolicist cognitive model, 138, 145
sociocultural systems, 63, 222. See also cultural
synchronic scaffolding, 443, 445
cognition
syntactic processing, 387
sociology, 21
system dynamics, 12
solipsism, 56,155
systemic decomposition, 107
somatic marker hypothesis, 437
systems thinking
somatic processes and representations, 420
somatosensory feedback, 250 claims, challenges, and contributions to, 17
sparse vision, 190 constructivism in, 16
spatial indexing, 390 development of, 12
spatiality, 201 manifestation in situated cognition, 16
as philosophical antecedent to situated overview, 12
cognition, 38 theory, 1 1 , 1 2 , 1 3
continuity in, 186 transcranialism coupling argument, 83
INDEX 5'9

tacit knowledge, n Turing machines, 138,166


tactile visual sensory substitution device, 193 Turner, J. Scott, 59
Take the Best heuristic, 325, 329, 336 Turvey, M. T., 25
Tanenhaus, M. K., 388 Tversky, Barbara, 201, 203, 204, 210,
tangibility factor of situations, 256 3.6
Tarski, Alfred, 401
task-exogenous actions, 270 unidirectional scripted language, 382
task-specific device (TSD), 64, 73
task-dependent attribute of vision, 190,191 valid inference, 172
Tastevin, J., 192 Vallfe-Tourangeau, F., 250
taxonomic extemalism, 57 values in decision process, 330
Taylor, F. W., 37, 210 van Gelder, T., 128,138
Taylor, L., 375 Varela, F., 24, 128
TECSs (transient extended cognitive systems), vehicle extemalism, 58,127,128,130
65 vehicle representation, 119
teleceptive sensation veil of metabolic ignorance, 72
control and, 493, 496 Vera, Alonzo, 349
history of, 492 Virchow, Rudolf, 165
of movement and space, 494 visual sensation, 185
teleological constraint on representation, 121 action of, 190
teleofunctionalism, 108 change blindness, 188, 424
teleosemantics, 123 color experience, 194
temporality felt location example, 192
causal reasoning, 223 memory and, 186
continuity in, 186, 387 anatomical discontinuity, 186
embodied mind and, 43 continuity in experience, 186
grain size of situation and, 255 world as outside memory hypothesis, 187
tenet of computational promiscuity, 69 optic flow, 488
Thelen, E., 128 representation clarification, 189
theory of inquiry, 24 rubber hand experiment, 192
Thompson, E., 422, 423 sensorimotor approach, 191
time constraints sensory consciousness, 195
adaptive action and, 457 sensory quality and substitution, 193
dynamicism and, 137, 142 von Bertalanffy, L., 11,13
Von Foerster, H., 24
Tin, E., 412
von Hoist, Erich, 25
Tinbergen, Nikolaas, 25, 26
von Neumann, J., 13,14,135
Titchener, E. B., 23
von Wolff, Christian, 157
Todd, Peter M., 25, 309, 322, 339
Vygotsky, L. S„ 26, 285
Tomasello, Michael, 467, 469, 473
Tooby, J., 158
tools. See resources in problem solving; scaffolds Wameken, Felix, 467, 470, 471, 473,
T R A C E model of spoken word recognition, 475
386 Wason card task, 144
transactionalist perspective, 442 Webb, B, 128
transactive memory, 462 Wegner, D. M., 462
transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS), 375 Wenger, Etienne, 348, 352
transcranialism, 81 Wertsch, J. V., 21
transductions in semantic memory, 237 Wheeler, M., 128
transient extended cognitive systems (TECSs), wide computationalism, 58, 60
65 Wiemer-Hastings, K., 240, 243, 254
Trueswell, J., 388 Wiener, Norbert, 24,137
truth conditions, 403 Wilden, A., 17,18,19
T S D . See task-specific device Wilson, Robert A., 55, 81, 84,109, 225,
Tucker, M., 372 410
Tulving, E., 237 Wimsatt, William, 98

You might also like