You are on page 1of 15

Creativity Research Journal Copyright 2003 by

2003, Vol. 15, No. 1, 91–105 Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.

Creativity in the Moral Domain: Integration and Implications


Mark A. Runco
California State University, Fullerton, and the University of Hawaii, Hilo
Jill Nemiro
Claremont Graduate School

ABSTRACT: Specific domains of talent have been area but unremarkably in others. Howard Gruber has
increasingly recognized by educators. Howard Gru- done all of us a great service by directing attention to
ber has done a great deal to direct attention to what what may be the most important domain. This is the
may be the most critical domain, namely, moral cre- moral domain.
ativity. The intent of this article is to honor Gruber’s Why look to creativity in the moral domain, and
genius in our own humble fashion, by reviewing and why now? Several answers to these questions have re-
integrating the recent work on moral creativity. Spe- cently been proposed; the intent of this article is to re-
cial attention is directed to points of agreement view those answers and to integrate them with the ex-
found in the literature to implications for studies of isting creativity literature, with special attention
creativity and education. This is not merely a review, given to points of agreement and implications for
however; we make every effort to compare and con- studies of creativity and education. This is not merely
trast the various theories and highlight the contro- a review, however; we make every effort to compare
versies in this area. One of the more surprising con- and contrast the various theories and highlight the
troversies involves the concept of adaptation, which controversies in this area. One of the more surprising
is often associated with creativity and would seem to controversies involves the concept of adaptation,
have great potential for addressing creativity in the which is often associated with creativity and would
moral domain and the resolution of moral dilemmas. seem to have great potential for addressing creativity
We also explore the arguable theories that writing is in the moral domain and the resolution of moral
the more useful domain for the resolution of creative dilemmas. There are, however, often-overlooked lim-
dilemmas, that art for art’s sake is ethical, and that its to the applicability of adaptation. We also explore
general knowledge should be targeted in moral edu- the arguable theories that writing is the more useful
cation. We begin and end with the question, Why is domain for the resolution of creative dilemmas, that
creativity in the moral domain more important now art for art’s sake is ethical, and that general knowl-
than ever before? edge should be targeted in moral education. First we
address the question mentioned previously: Why is
creativity in the moral domain more important now
One of the most significant and useful of the concep-
than ever before?
tual breakthroughs in creative studies is that of
domain specificity. Albert (1980), for example, initi-
ated a longitudinal study of two groups of excep-
tional boys, each representing a different kind of Geir Kaufmann served as the Action Editor for this article. The au-
ability; Gardner (1983) described the unique devel- thors wish to express their appreciation to Abraham Tannenbaum for
comments on early drafts of this article.
opmental histories of symbolic, logical, bodily, mu-
Correspondence and requests for reprints should be sent to Mark
sical, spatial, intrapersonal, and interpersonal poten- Runco, Department of Child Development, EC 105, California State
tials; and Runco (1987) demonstrated empirically University–Fullerton, PO Box 6868, Fullerton, CA 92834–6868.
how gifted children might perform creatively in one E-mail: runco@exchange.fullerton.edu

Creativity Research Journal 91


M. A. Runco & J. Nemiro

The Need for Creative Morality dom thought of by those whose reflections on creativity
have as their frame of reference the artist’s studio, the con-
cert hall, or the quiet groves of literary contemplation. Oth-
The reasons for devoting attention to creativity in erwise the dark side will prevail, and we will have “created”
the moral domain are related to both individual growth for ourselves our own oblivion. (p. 143)
and societal well-being. Stein (1993), for example, ar-
gued that recent technological advances have brought There is, then, an obvious need for creativity in the
us to a point where many societal and scientific prob- moral domain—especially if you assume that creativ-
lems can only be solved with creative efforts. He de- ity is a kind of problem solving,1 and if you feel that
scribed advances in organ transplants and bioengi- the world has an ever-increasing supply of pressing
neering (cloning) as illustrating the need for linking problems. The question then becomes, How can we en-
morality and creativity, and he claimed that “we may sure that creativity is at the service of human survival?
be on the brink of a conflict in which we must master
technology or technology masters us . . . [we need
specific] guidelines to solve the countless moral Intermediaries and Social Processes
dilemmas we are bound to encounter” (p. 200).
McLaren (1993) also looked to science and tech- It would no doubt help if we paid more attention to
nology, describing dilemmas arising from progress in social dynamics and what Stein (1993) called interme-
new methods of surgery, transplants, DNA research, diaries in the creative process. Intermediaries are per-
and atomic energy, which have clarified the need for sons who “play supportive and gatekeeping roles be-
creative morality. McLaren suggested that so-called tween the creative individual and the public” (p. 197).
advances often “haunt those who are concerned for Intermediaries for artists share problems and supply
environmental integrity, and even the continued exis- emotional and financial support. Outside the arts, inter-
tence of life on earth” (p. 141). He noted that when mediaries include peer review committees, profes-
one problem is solved, a new problem is frequently sional publications and societies, foundations, govern-
created. mental agencies that grant funds, critics, and the press
McLaren (1993) extended this argument in his de- and media. Intermediaries often help to maintain moral
scription of “the dark side of creativity” (p. 137). He standards, being in a position to “uphold the ethical
cited Plato in this regard, and the idea that “artists” and moral standards of their science and profession”
were seen as a “threat to the integrity of the mind and (p. 197). (Later we will extrapolate and suggest that
spirit . . . [because] creativity apart from moral con- educators can be considered intermediaries in the
cern loses its soul” (pp. 138–139). In The Republic, moral and creative development of their students. They
Plato emphasized that creativity “must always have certainly should consider their responsibility as an in-
rationality as its goal, so that pleasure, to be accept- terpreter and guide of society’s values.)
able, must be judged in terms of its moral quality” Stein (1993) offered two examples to illustrate how
(p. 138). McLaren applied this reasoning to creative intermediaries have been called on to maintain moral
accomplishment. In his words, “if we are to be honest standards in creative endeavors. One example con-
in our quest for understanding creativity, we cannot cerned specific professional societies that were trying
evade acknowledging that, like all human endeavors, to monitor the exchanges occurring between ethno-
it too has its dark and even, to use Plato’s word, its botanists and persons in Third World countries from
daemonic side” (p. 137). whom they profited. The second example illustrates
The existence of this “dark side” highlights the how the New England Journal of Medicine was con-
need to carefully consider possible bridges between
morality and creativity. As McLaren (1993) sug-
gested, if we are naive about the dark side of creativ- 1
This assumption has been questioned, especially by those who
ity, we court disaster. In his own words, creativity focus on the creativity of artists (Dudek & Cote, 1994). The creativ-
should be ity of artists is easily interpreted as self-expression more than prob-
lem solving, though obviously artists might be solving problems as
at the service of human survival. . . . Now we must organize they work to capture what they wish or need to express. The debate
on a global scale, though it will require a mobilization of seems to hinge on one’s definition of problem (for a review, see
political will, international cooperation, and sacrifice sel- Runco, 1994b).

92 Creativity Research Journal


Creativity in the Moral Domain

fronted with the decision of whether to publish Nazi agency. However, an individual utilizing a broader vi-
research on hypothermia. The editors took a moral sion might see this child as an indication of a larger
stand and refused to publish this research, stating, “the social problem and attempt to tackle the problem at its
Journal has taken the position that it will not publish source. In Haste’s view, a truly morally creative act
reports of unethical research, regardless of their scien- must involve an “unusual vision of the moral serious-
tific merit. . . . Knowledge, although important may ness of the situation” and fuel “the individual’s own
be less important to a decent society than the way it is sense of efficacy and personal responsibility” (p. 3).
obtained” (Angell, 1990, pp. 1463–1464). This sug- Vision is thus not sufficient, or in Haste’s own words,
gests that intermediaries serve not only as emotional “it is not enough to have the inspiration or insight if
and financial supporters to creative individuals, but one does not have the psychological equipment to
also as interpreters, contributors, and protectors of so- carry through to performance” (p. 2). This description
ciety’s values. They clarify “for the society the func- makes it easy to tie responsibility (and intentions) to
tion and role of its science and teaches the society how creativity, for creativity is often explained in terms of
its contribution should be regarded and evaluated” inspiration or insight (see Gruber, 1981; Wallace,
(Stein, 1993, p. 200). The Nazi issue suggests that cre- 1991; Weisberg, 1993), but what good is an idea or in-
ative efforts must be evaluated in terms of their poten- sight unless it is somehow used?
tial effects, in terms of their background, and in terms Runco (1993b) also argued that intentions are criti-
of their intentionality. cal for creative morality, and he suggested that inten-
Intentionality is without a doubt one of the key tionality is more important than other dimensions that
concepts in studies of creative morality (Gruber, 1985, often attract more attention in the creativity literature,
1993; Haste, 1993; Runco, 1993a, 1993b).2 Haste was such as conformity and conventionality. Creativity is
aware of this when she defined moral creativity in terms often associated with “nonconformity, rebelliousness,
of three components—vision, efficacy, and responsibil- and unconventional tendencies,” whereas morality is
ity. The last of these is entirely compatible with inten- thought to involve “traditional, dogmatic, and conven-
tions, though Haste put it in the context of outcomes tional tendencies” (p. 17), but this distinction implies
and described how, because of vision and efficacy, an that morality and creativity are contradictory and oxy-
individual is personally moved to moral action. Vision moronic, or at least opposite ends of the continuum of
refers to an ability to look beyond convention, and ef- conventionality. However, Runco argued that creativity
ficacy refers to an individual’s awareness that he or is not entirely unconventional. Rules, procedures, and
she could act alone or with others on some important traditions are important in many artistic domains, for
issue. These three components characterize individu- instance, and morality is not always conventional.
als who are “perceived as acting with moral responsi- Runco cited examples of original and useful work that
bility or commitment” (p. 2). As an illustration, Haste extended the existing order (rather than breaking it)
predicted that most individuals who see a child who is and the view that morality is always conventional, cit-
deprived, hungry, or suffering would feel compelled to ing Gandhi, Confucius, Mohammed, and Jesus as
give financial support or call a child protection moral rebels. The exemplars described by Colby and
Damon (1992), Gardner (1993a), and Piechowski
(1993) demonstrate unconventional morality. The
2
Appropriateness is also related to both morality and creativity. problem is, then, that an either/or relationship is too
Moral conventions define what is appropriate behavior, for exam- often assumed, with individuals possessing either con-
ple, and most definitions of creativity mention some sort of appro-
ventionality or nonconventionality. When creativity is
priateness (e.g., fit, social value, adequacy) in addition to originality
or novelty (Rothenberg & Hausman, 1976; Runco & Charles, viewed as unconventional, there is a tendency to ignore
1993). The difficulty arises because creative solutions to moral the fact that creative performance can be conventional
problems may be viewed as inappropriate by some standards or cri- and involve rules and fixed procedures. The realistic
teria. Consider in this regard the fasting by UCLA students in 1993 view has creativity and morality representing two dif-
as a means for urging the administration to develop a Hispanic stud-
ferent continua. In this view, an individual could utilize
ies department. It would seem that creativity, appropriateness, and
morality are each relativistic concepts (Runco, 1993b, p. 24), both creativity and morality to solve ethical dilemmas.
though Johnson (1993) described several qualifications to such a What limited empirical evidence exists seems to be
view of morality. consistent with the idea of separate continua. Andreani

Creativity Research Journal 93


M. A. Runco & J. Nemiro

and Pagnin (1993), for example, found that tests of cre- century art, “for all its transgressive drive, is intrinsi-
ative potential were not correlated with tests of moral cally moral, as all great art always is” (p. 145).
reasoning. Admittedly, as Gruber (1993) pointed out, Family (1993) seemed to think that artists should
when two variables do not correlate with one another, make systematic efforts and intentionally apply their
it does not indicate that one has nothing to do with the skills. She called on the artist to take a leadership role
other. It only indicates that variations in one did not in bringing about changes for the benefit of this planet
correlate with variations in the other. As Gruber put it, and to assist in the return to equilibrium. For Family,
“any individual—or social group—must still work out artists are ideal leaders for creativity in the moral do-
a coherent and adaptive way of using all of his or her or main because they are not likely to be tied to conflict-
their capabilities, correlated or not” (p. 6). ing business interests. Family wrote that the artist’s
Are creativity and morality necessarily inten- work should
tional? Gruber (1993) seemed to think so, with his
incite enough pride and joy as well as openness of spirit, so
claim that “ought implies can implies create” (p. 3).
as to mobilize the confidence and assertiveness needed for
The idea here is that when something ought to be art to assume leadership and show people the possibility of
done and, further, it can be done, then “a moral im- liberating their inner resources from the materialistic con-
perative arises, we must do it” (p. 3). Piaget seemed sumerism and competitiveness and orienting them to coop-
to believe that intentions are important for morality eration and spiritual growth. Since the artist may be the per-
when he distinguished subjective moral reasoning son farthest removed from the utility functions in society
(such as being the owner of a polluting manufacturing busi-
and objective moral reasoning. The primary differ- ness), he or she is the best person to do this. (p. 86)
ence is that the former takes intentions into account.
With respect to creativity, Wolf and Larson (1981) Family (1993) described Leonardo da Vinci as a
suggested that children’s behavior must be intentional concrete example of an artist who assumed the role of
and cannot be spontaneous or accidental to be classi- moral leadership. Da Vinci was responsible, through
fied as creative. In fact, they argued that the sponta- his art, for leading the world into a new age, the Re-
neous behaviors of children, which frequently appear naissance, which stood for freedom from the church
to adults to be creative, are actually slightly inappro- and stressed both individualism and the dignity of hu-
priate or even bizarre behaviors that are simply unex- mankind.
pected by mature persons. Another part of the creativ- Many studies of artistic personalities show that
ity research that is very pertinent to this issue of they tend toward individuality and nonconformity (Al-
intentionality focuses on motivation and the possibil- bert & Runco, 1989; Crutchfield, 1962), and this
ity of creating art for art’s sake. might be taken as support for Family’s (1993) choice
of artists as leaders. Alternatively, it might imply that
artists will not be all that eager to take on roles that re-
Art for Art’s Sake quire leadership. Perhaps because of this second pos-
sibility, Family implored artists to see the ultimate
Runco (1993b) quoted a number of artists (e.g., goal of their work as a means of achieving happiness
Ayn Rand, Albert Camus, Ezra Pound, Mark Twain) without regret. She wrote, “the ultimate purpose of art
who clearly intended to convey their thoughts on is that it be enjoyed. . . . Beauty and joy are a function
morality through their art. This intention is incompati- of art and that is what we need in the world today”
ble with the position that art is an end in itself. Dudek (pp. 86–87). She thus saw the artist as crucial in creat-
(1993) emphasized the latter view—of art for art’s ing a fundamental reorientation toward the human
sake—when she described transgressive art. This was value of enhancement of happiness, a happiness with-
defined as work that breaks boundaries and presents out a regrettable side. Artists are the best individuals
“an image of . . . degradation, chaos, and ugliness.” to accomplish this reorientation because
What is most relevant is Dudek’s proposition that “a
basic moral principle is that all persons treat each if there is a clear example of enjoyment without spoilage,
pollution, exploitation, and debt, it is the enjoyment of art.
other as ends and never as means” (p. 145). This leads And with the help of modern communication technology,
to the idea that worthy art is true to the work itself as the artist is no longer the isolated, powerless, and poor non-
an end, never as a means. Dudek concluded that 20th- conformist, but together, all artists represent a powerful

94 Creativity Research Journal


Creativity in the Moral Domain

influence on public thought. It is from this power that defined more by what artists express rather than how.
derives the moral responsibility of the artist. (p. 84) Schwebel cited Picasso’s Guernica as an example of
Studies of aesthetics and judgment suggest that art such conscious moral communication. The agony of
has impact at least in part because it creates a catharsis war and a vision of doom were portrayed for viewers
through which a viewer can identify and empathize. to share and experience. Schwebel wrote this of Pi-
That should allow art to communicate human values casso’s Guernica:
and norms to members of society. Confronting his own abhorrence of this first demonstration
Like Family (1993), McLaren (1993) held high of the use of saturation bombing to terrorize and destroy
hopes for artists. He felt that the artist, rather than the civilians, he did not vocalize his condemnation through lec-
ture or give vent to his feelings through preachment, nor did
politician or military, “enjoys a higher esteem as a
he suppress them as something alien to the work of the
noble measure of accomplishment than the military artist. Instead, through his own language, he transformed his
genius which is measured by the extent of destruction, own cognitive and affective experience into symbols that
or political savvy measured by the number of failed others could identify with and thus gave the world an appre-
opponents, or economic prowess counted in dollars” ciation of what fascism, unchecked, had in store for
humankind. (p. 68)
(p. 85). McLaren also criticized “art for art’s sake.”
Thus both McLaren and Family hold views that are in For Schwebel, when the old way of thinking mani-
contrast to that of Dudek (1993), outlined earlier. Re- fested in normative art is no longer effective for new
call that Dudek claimed that art for its own sake (as an issues or challenges, artists are propelled into new so-
end) is intrinsically moral and suggested that the true lutions. This is one impetus for moral creativity.3 In
artist never takes an official stand. Rather, in her eyes, this sense, his view is not all that different from the
the artist’s responsibility is to view and portray truth- boundary breaking of transgressive art (Dudek, 1993).
fully the world as it actually is. Dudek wrote, “If the Significantly, Schwebel (1993) suggested that an
world must end the artist has at least decided to see it artist’s past experiences, values, and personality con-
as it is—and in the face of it to let out a full, heart- tributed to his or her interpretation, emotional experi-
rending howl: That howl we see in all the transgres- ence, and reaction to societal problems. They also de-
sive arts of our time and our place” (p. 146). For termined whether or not he or she engaged in morally
Dudek, this truthful portrayal of the world is one of creative artistic endeavors. The artist’s past experience
the most powerful moral activities in contemporary determined whether or not an external dilemma led to
society. Dudek described how this portrayal can assist moral creative behavior, a safer outlet, or denial and
in the development of moral action in others. suppression and thus lack of awareness of a moral
dilemma. Schwebel presented a model of moral cre-
Art is by its nature a symbol system which must inevitably
carry a message (nothing is without some meaning). By its ative development in which the artist progressed from
novelty and freshness it effects a new presentation of the no awareness (of a moral issue), to awareness on first
world as constructed by the consciousness of the artist. It is an interpersonal and then intrapersonal level. As a re-
therefore an attempted communication, a concretized sult of this awareness, the artist either began to recog-
thought, and as such a message, it may change the vision or
nize and express some of the moral conflicts or denied
the ideas about the world as currently experienced. Novel
and original art will by its nature not uphold the “state” but and thus suppressed this awareness. If this awareness
is more likely to effect some change in it, if not completely was not denied, reflection led to artistic expression in-
undermine it. . . . Art can be interpreted as acting in the ser- tegrating the human experience at the intrapsychic, in-
vice of human growth and welfare and is therefore moral in terpersonal, and social levels.
the highest sense of the term. (p. 147)
An artist who has wide experience and has re-
Schwebel (1993) seemed to think that intentions flected on the meaning or art follows one of three
are very important when he defined moral creativity as
“the conscious transformation of moral values and
3
their associated affect into artistic products” (p. 68). Interestingly, Schwebel (1993) noted that time plays a different
role in scientific versus artistic revolutions. In science, once a dis-
Unlike those already discussed, however, he focused covery is made and verified, the revolution is complete. In art, revo-
on the content of artistic revolutions rather than lution is never complete. Because artistic revolutions are never com-
method. He stated that moral creativity in the arts is plete, new issues and thus new revolutions arise.

Creativity Research Journal 95


M. A. Runco & J. Nemiro

courses: “(a) full integration at the conscious and un- tion and security when considering change. Religious
conscious levels of experience of using one’s creative language as a transitional object allows adults to re-
powers in the moral domain; (b) full integration at the main connected to a familiar base while taking risks.
conscious and unconscious levels of experience of This ability to establish and maintain a relational
using one’s creative powers for pure art, perhaps focus with a transitional object facilitates creative
achieving aesthetic refinements of dehumanized ab- adaptation in the world. Miller and Karl wrote, “We
stractions; or (c) after suffering the consequences . . . are suggesting that religious language, by offering
retreat from a consciousness of moral creativity to ready access to a sense of continuity, at times facili-
focus on the interpersonal and intrapsychic” (p. 71). In tates movement, change, and creative resolution of
some sense, these stages parallel those contained in Pi- conflict” (p. 109).
aget’s (1976) theory of cognitive development and in Various examples of the transitional nature of reli-
Kohlberg’s (1987) theory of moral development. With gious language were described in various religious
each new stage, the artist experiences moral dilemmas contexts. In addressing the familiar words that accom-
more deeply, comprehensively, and abstractly. pany the Catholic confession, Miller and Karl (1993)
In the development of moral creativity, individuals wrote, “These and other similar statements point to
may reach different levels at different times, ranging the way in which the ritual words allow a depth of ex-
from alienation to social consciousness. Schwebel perience, and particularly a taking of risks, in relation
(1993) suggested that “the alienated artists—they of to one’s self and to one’s moral dilemmas” (p. 103).
the empty selves or hyperreflexive consciousness—by Ritual union songs and songs of political struggle
the nature of their inclinations deny themselves the op- (such as those sung by the marchers in the civil rights
portunity for moral creativity through artistic transfor- movement), were also characterized as transitional ob-
mation” (p. 78). Schwebel acknowledged that artists jects and providing assistance in change by establish-
vary in the degree to which they communicate moral ing a connection with those who had struggled in the
values in their art. This variation occurs because of past. In the words of Miller and Karl, “There are times
(a) the nature of the artist’s personal development; when the inspiration needed, which is provided by the
(b) the artist’s understanding of the broader social con- transitional object, is simply the courage to go on.
text; and (c) the artist’s reaction to a violation of moral . . . These children sang songs—on the picket line,
values (Does the artist articulate his or her values and as they were taken off to jail—to help them feel
through his art, or is the artist afraid to make a moral the presence of their parents” (pp. 106–107).
stand?). Artists may react to moral dilemmas and be In sum, one link between creativity and morality
moral but not morally creative. To incorporate one’s re- lies in the use of a transitional object, such as religious
action into one’s art and send those values to the viewer language, to assist the individual in maintaining a fa-
is the gage specifically of moral creative behavior. miliar connection while taking the risk to creatively
solve moral dilemmas.
Moving from religion to hard science, Goswami
Outside the Arts (1993) used quantum theory to illustrate the possible
contribution of physics to ethics, morality, and values.
Several other theories emphasize personal and sub- He suggested that the creative freedom fundamental in
jective experiences and their role in creative work. ethics is also fundamental in quantum physics. He de-
Miller and Karl (1993), for example, examined the scribed how in physics, the creation of a double-bind
role of religious language in individual and social doubt state occurs when two competing situations are
change. They suggested that an individual needs to presented. The resolution occurs not through a flip of
learn to take the risks that may be necessary for moral a coin, but through creativity. Doubt may arise from
action. In their view, religious language can function that fact that there is no logical solution. Goswami
as a transitional object (cf. Winnicott, 1971), allowing suggested that the same holds true of moral dilemmas.
an individual to stay connected to his or her parents or He wrote,
origins while taking risks. Just as a child who tries to When logic is insufficient to reach an ethical answer, it can
go away from his or her parents and then turns to see if only be reached by a creative quantum leap. Even when
they are still there, adults may have a need for connec- logic can be stretched to reach a parsimonious solution, a

96 Creativity Research Journal


Creativity in the Moral Domain

creative approach often yields a richer solution that actually can only occur through maturation and the awareness
revolutionizes the context of the problem itself. Ethics in its of the individual as part of humanity” (Benchoam,
essence seems to involve inner creativity, an encounter with
our quantum self with the idea of transformation firmly
1993, p. 113). Again, a Piagetian assumption is appar-
established in our minds. . . . We avoid preconceived ent, because Benchoam’s cycle ends with a return to
answers; creativity is the goal. To remain open to more Phase 1, though now at a higher level of moral reason-
expansive possibilities without automatically (e.g., as an act ing and creative ability, in which awareness spreads to
of classical conditioning) taking the shortcut of a precon- new arenas.
ceived ethical formula is what empowers people occasional-
ly to find “miraculous” solutions. (p. 195)
The moral obligation for Benchoam as a political
prisoner was “to preserve the physical and psycholog-
ical integrity of the self” (Benchoam, 1993, p. 113).
Individual Cases To achieve this, Benchoam relied heavily on creative
activity. She described how
Much of what we know about the interplay of cre-
ativity and morality comes from case studies (Ben- art became a necessity for me in my functioning as a human
being because it provided me with a calm environment, that
choam, 1993; Colby & Damon, 1992; Gardner, of the inner self. Both of these enterprises—my human-
1993b; Piechowski, 1993). Admittedly, these have bi- rights commitment and the arts—have shaped my life and
ases (Runco, 1993c), but they are suggestive, rich and given meaning to my existence. . . . The constant interaction
in depth, and at the very least suggest hypotheses that of both enterprises has served as a source of refuge and
can be tested. Consider Benchoam’s report of her ex- protest at different stages of my life. (pp. 116–117)
periences in a life-threatening condition—being a
The creation of art with a moral content thus served
prisoner of war. In 1977, when she was only 16, mem-
as a survival strategy. It allowed freedom in an envi-
bers of the First Army Corps of Buenos Aires came to
ronment of total governmental control. Part of the ef-
her home, killed her 17-year-old brother, and took her
fect may have been escapism. Through the creation of
as a political prisoner, where she remained for 4 1/2
art, Benchoam could place herself in “the outside
years. In order to survive, she developed many psy-
world.” Again quoting Benchoam (1993),
chological strategies, and creative activity was pri-
mary among them. In the 7 years following her re- Would my attempts to reconstruct the beauty of the outside
lease, she developed a model of five phases of moral world keep me from insanity and help me to regain self-
consciousness that she felt she passed through during control under those extreme conditions? At first I did not
the time as a political prisoner. These phases can be have the answer, but later I realized that creative action of an
active mind was indeed what made a great deal of difference
summarized as (a) socialization with the environment in my psychological states, and that my moral responsibility
and culture (knowledge); (b) awareness of the self and was to maintain my humanity under such conditions. (p. 119)
of others as part of the world (comprehension); (c)
awareness of self as having the power to change the During her imprisonment, Benchoam produced
state of affairs through spontaneous creative acts two kinds of drawings—one in which she expressed
(analysis, reflection, confrontation, and experimenta- her feelings about the experience and surroundings,
tion); (d) consolidation of one’s personal values with the other in which she established a connection with
those of the majority, and refinement of one’s personal the outside world. Interestingly, these creative expres-
creative style (reflection, application, and beginning sions were so crucial to her preservation of self that
stage of synthesis); and (e) creation of work that ex- she (and other prisoners) continued to create despite
presses moral responsibility (synthesis, application, the fact that such creative actions were seen as a form
and re-evaluation), and a return to Phase 1, to repeat of resistance and prohibited.
the process at a higher level. Benchoam’s drawings (several of which are pub-
During the first three phases, individuals form lished in a 1993 issue of Creativity Research Journal)
moral responsibilities and become aware of their cre- changed as she passed through the five phases of moral
ative capacity. Spontaneous experimentation often consciousness. In phase 1, her drawings centered on
questions the status quo. A period of introspection and portraying elements of daily life. Drawings in the sec-
reflection characterizes Phase 4, and in Phase 5, cre- ond phase were used to divert her attention from the
ative works with moral content are created, “which jail conditions. In the third phase, she experimented

Creativity Research Journal 97


M. A. Runco & J. Nemiro

and created drawings that expressed her feelings about harmlessness, finding ways of being of service in a selfless
the conditions of jail. Drawings became more reflec- way, and striving for greater acceptance of others and of
themselves. . . . But the principal task for Peace Pilgrim,
tive in the fourth phase. Here, observation and analysis Etty, and Ashley, was to give a new meaning to their lives
were important before actually creating a drawing. Fi- and to discover their true selves. One could interpret this as
nally, in phase 5, drawings were “the concretizing on problem-finding in the intrapersonal domain: the self as the
paper and canvas of my thoughts” (Benchoam, 1993, object of discovery and creation. (p. 96)
p. 123).
Benchoam’s (1993) theory was constructed from her Especially interesting in this argument is the recog-
own experiences, which raises the question of general- nition of intentions, problem finding, and interper-
ity. In fact, similar concerns apply to all case studies sonal ability. Intentions were discussed in detail ear-
(Gardner, 1993b; Runco, 1993c). Often the question is lier. Runco (1993b) included problem finding in his
not one of the external validity of autobiography, as in suggestions about creativity in the moral domain
the case of Benchoam, but concerns generalizability: (more on that later), and Gardner (1993b) had quite a
When unambiguous cases of creative morality are stud- bit to say about the distinctiveness of intrapersonal
ied, do findings apply to everyday cases? talents.
Piechowski (1993) illustrated the development of Like Benchoam (1993), Piechowski (1993) pre-
inner transformation with three case studies—Etty sented a stage model. He described the levels as fol-
Hillesum, a Dutch woman whose inner growth led her lows: (a) Level 1, in which the main concern is with
to volunteer for deportation by the Nazis (Levels 3 and oneself, one’s own protection and survival; (b) Level
4); Ashley, a university professor who kept a diary of 2, in which there is a lack of inner direction, a sense of
her moral inner struggle (Level 4); and the Peace Pil- inner fragmentation in which one is submissive to the
grim, a woman who covered 25,000 miles on foot, values of the group and in which the focus is on ful-
propounding peace along the way (Level 5). Two prin- filling the expectations of others; (c) Level 3, in which
ciples emerged in these individuals—nonseparate- a person possesses moral concerns and a sense of the
ness, in which individuals were not seen in isolation ideal, but has not yet reached it, and in which moral
but as a part of a larger whole; and inner peace as a questions become important and are deeply felt;
necessary condition for world peace. (d) Level 4, which shows self-actualization, and in
Piechowski (1993) concluded that for self-actualiz- which ideals and actions agree and one develops a
ing and unambiguously ethical individuals, moral strong sense of responsibility; and (e) Level 5, which
truths may be entirely self-evident. After all, these in- is inspired by a powerful ideal such as equal rights,
dividuals live with these truths, so perhaps there is less world peace, or universal love. Importantly, Pie-
creativity required for them to be meaningful. After chowski’s cases were not artists. This may help gener-
some debate, Piechowski concluded that “one could alizations, at least to other nonartists.
consider the process of advanced inner growth as a Rappoport and Kren (1993) also focused on indi-
process of creating a new self. . . . If we can assume viduals outside the artistic domain. Their work is es-
that discovering a truth is a creative process, then dis- pecially interesting because they found two individu-
covering one’s true self must be one too” (p. 89). Thus als who performed moral actions without being
Piechowski concluded that inner transformation is in- altruistic. More specifically, the two individuals were
deed a creative process. altruistic at one point, but had histories lacking altru-
Note Piechowski’s (1993) connecting inner moral ism. This may seem contrary to assumptions about
transformations to creativity via truth. He wrote, special developmental backgrounds of moral exem-
plars. In fact, the personal histories suggested to Rap-
What characterizes them is that they live moral truth. But poport and Kren that their two cases were motivated
moral truth is achieved only as a result of advanced inner primarily by narcissism. Both individuals were active
transformation. Can one be creative in regard to moral truth? in their protection of Jews during the Holocaust.
These individuals engaged in an intense and deliberate
Much of the past literature on the Holocaust sug-
process of inner transformation which presented many indi-
vidual problems to be solved, for example, finding ways of gests that rescuers were autonomous, self-reliant, had
coping with emotional pain and tasks of self-discipline, free- strong moral values, and had a history of concern with
ing oneself from possessiveness and jealousy, practicing problems of the oppressed. Individuals involved in

98 Creativity Research Journal


Creativity in the Moral Domain

rescue activities were thought to be good. Rappoport Gardner (1993b) acknowledged the problems asso-
and Kren (1993) attempted to explain the rescue activ- ciated with the singling out of one moment in
ities of Oskar Schindler and Siegfried Jagendorf, two Gandhi’s life. Gardner put it this way:
amoral individuals who saved thousands of Jews from
death. Rappoport and Kren suggested that what On so many dimensions, Gandhi was a prototypically cre-
ative master. He was prototypical in his precocity in his cho-
caused them to be involved in these rescue activities sen (moral) domain; his obsessive search for opportunities
was not their invisible altruism, but their narcissistic and his capacity to exploit them; his studied marginality; his
personalities. In playing out savior roles, both oscillation between attachments to the many and the need
Schindler and Jagendorf “gained the ultimate narcis- for isolation; his essential selfishness; his Faustian ascetism;
sistic gratification of high admiration and respect from and the persistence of many childlike features in his philos-
ophy and in his person. (p. 44)
those they helped” (p. 135). This notion about narcis-
sism is interesting, particularly given Gardner’s Although not all children will reach the level of
(1993a) argument that eminent creators are self- moral responsibility attained by Gandhi, teachers and
promoters who often use other people. parents probably can assist in the moral development
Gardner (1993b) himself chose Mahatma Gandhi, of all children by providing opportunities to develop
who had a long history of altruism and moral activ- such interest and skills. Morality may be one of the
ity. (Gardner described Gandhi as precocious in the domains (such as philosophy or physics) that requires
moral domain.) Gardner argued for a focus on unam- huge investments and mature motivations. As Gardner
biguous cases, and he felt Gandhi was the “exemplar (1993b) cautioned,
par excellence in our time of creativity in the moral
domain” (p. 29). Gandhi’s moral creativity was There are certain domains of experience in which precocity
demonstrated through his work to mobilize others to or prodigiousness can be readily recognized. Provided that
service and wider goals and his own creative solu- the society provides opportunities for the advancement of
tions to moral dilemmas. Gandhi’s most creative young children, one is not surprised to learn of a child of 5
or 10 who is notably outstanding in numerical or mathemat-
moral solution may have been the invention of satya- ical power, in musical performance, in playing chess, or in
graha, a process of nonviolent resistance to injustice. displaying mechanical or spatial prowess. When it comes to
This process involved several stages, which included an understanding of other persons, and an ability to deal
efforts to persuade through discussion and reason; effectively with them, however, the markers are elusive.
persuasion through suffering (fasting); and as a last Limitations in size, power, emotional breadth and subtlety,
worldly experience, and knowledge of motivation all serve
resort, nonviolent coercion, noncooperation, or civil to limit the capacity of the young child to appear precocious
disobedience. Instead of confrontation or violence, in the social, political, religious, or ethical realms. (p. 30)
“a proponent of satyagraha mobilized the reasons
and conscience of one’s opponent by inviting suffer- Yet Gandhi’s parents saw his capacity for moral au-
ing on oneself. The satyagraha hoped thereby to thority and allowed him to function as a moral arbiter
convert the opponent and make him a willing ally” between his parents and other elders. Fortunately for
(p. 41). Gandhi, his parents gave him the freedom to explore
A concrete example of Gandhi’s morally creative social and ethical problems and develop his own re-
solutions lies in the situation called “The Event,” a sponses. As Gardner (1993b) stated, “Gandhi had re-
labor dispute between textile workers and mill own- peated opportunities to ‘test himself’ as a moral
ers. Gandhi first asked the workers to refrain from vi- agent” (p. 31).
olence or begging. After Gandhi arrived at a solution We are encouraged by developmental histories such
he felt was fair to both sides, he began a fast. After as Gandhi’s and think they offer optimism for educa-
three days of the fast, the mill owners were ready to tors. Further encouragement is seen in the evidence
work to reach a settlement. The mill owners insisted suggesting that developmental histories have an impact
they would give no more than a 20% raise, whereas on creativity (Albert & Runco, 1986; Runco & Charles,
workers wanted a 35% raise. Gandhi’s solution satis- 1997) and on creative morality in particular (Ben-
fied both parties. The workers received a 35% raise choam, 1993; Schwebel, 1993). Apparently a great deal
one day, and a 20% the next day, and a perpetual in- can be done today for tomorrow’s morality. In the fol-
crease of 27 1/2% (the arithmetical compromise). lowing section, we focus on possible educational goals.

Creativity Research Journal 99


M. A. Runco & J. Nemiro

Education a recurrent interaction with a conflictive environment”


(p. 112). From this we might infer that students are
Benchoam (1993) suggested that educators should challenged. That in turn indicates that educators
reinforce children’s exploration of moral issues by not might use Kohlbergian dilemmas in the classroom
quelling their “activistic” actions. From an early age, (see Duska & Whelan [1975] and Mattox [1975] for
she herself was involved in activist activities (as well classroom dilemmas). We will only add that this idea
as art). Benchoam wrote: “My mother and a sixth should not be taken too far. Readers may know of
grade history teacher provided greater meaning for my Goertzel and Goertzel’s (1962) findings about con-
activism by encouraging the involvement of young flict in the family background of highly creative in-
children and adolescents in the making of policies dividuals (see Runco, 1994a, for a review). The
which affected us as students” (p. 115). Benchoam Goertzels were careful to avoid recommending the
also suggested that facilitating general cognitive de- systematic introduction of trauma, and the same con-
velopment will help creative morality, and that educa- clusion no doubt applies to suggestions about hard-
tors should take special care to reinforce feelings of ship and conflict (Runco, 1994a). Perhaps Kohlberg’s
self-efficacy. As noted earlier, the individual must (1987) dilemmas-as-exercises will be useful because
view him- or herself as capable of effecting change. they challenge, but in an impersonal and nonthreaten-
This is reinforced by what Haste (1993) suggested ing fashion.
about efficacy. An assumption underlying the use of such dilemma
Although creativity and moral perspective no doubt exercises is that of the value of problem solving. Re-
will benefit from a large knowledge base, there may call Piechowski’s (1993) comment about problem
be a question about the influence of general cognitive finding for moral reasoning. With this in mind, Runco
development, given the lack of correlations reported (1993a) asked that educators take care to include more
by Andreani and Pagnin (1993). Perhaps instead of a than problem solving in exercises that are given to stu-
general knowledge base, educators should target dents. He pointed out that problem finding—which
metaphorical thinking skills. This is implied by John- represents a range of actions, including the identifica-
son’s (1993) theory that metaphorical thinking under- tion of problems and their definition—is critical for
lies moral imagination, and it is intimated by creative thinking and may be particularly important in
Bronowski’s (1977, p. 12) theory of how and why in- the attainment of moral creativity. Moreover, problem
dividuals are connected with society. Bronowski finding sets the stage for problem solving; a high-
(1977) quoted William Blake in this regard: quality problem probably has a high likelihood of a
high-quality solution.
A dog starv’d at his Master’s gate
Predicts the ruin of the State. (p. 12)
Of course, problem finding by itself is also insuffi-
cient. As Runco (1993b) described it, “If an artist in-
Blake apparently felt strongly about minute partic- tends to have a moral impact, he or she should define
ulars, which included details about individuals that are problems in such a way as to facilitate their solution”
indicative of society, such as the “starv’d dog.” (p. 24). In other words, with moral issues, problem de-
Bronowski discussed this as a kind of metaphor, and finition is probably more important than problem
metaphoric skills could be targeted in the classroom, identification. You need to go beyond awareness of the
although once again we should keep in mind Haste’s problem and actually suggest a direction for its solu-
(1993) example of “a child who is deprived, hungry, tion. Educators should therefore use a particular kind
or suffering” and how an awareness of social prob- of problem-finding task—one that encourages stu-
lems is not enough. Creative morality, in this view, re- dents to both identify the problem and a direction for
quires vision (which may come from metaphorical solution. Educators might use real-world moral dilem-
reasoning) and responsibility. mas to encourage the development of problem defini-
Colby and Damon (1992) reported that the moral tion and solution evaluation.
exemplars in their studies “treasure the chance to take This brings up one of the controversial hypotheses,
[risks and hardships] on” (p. xii), and Benchoam alluded to early in this article. The hypothesis is that
(1993) similarly argued that “moral responsibility and creative writing has advantages over other creative
its need for creative action . . . flourish where there is work. Runco (1993b) proposed that writing allows in-

100 Creativity Research Journal


Creativity in the Moral Domain

dividuals to explore problems and potential solutions, Haste (1993) offered the following guidelines for
and to do so in great depth. The visual arts may not educating for vision, efficacy, and responsibility: For
allow the same informational depth, though of course vision, “we need individuals to be able to question re-
they might make up for it in the emotional reactions ceived truths, to get below the surface of assumptions,
they can elicit. Those emotional reactions might en- and to arrive at some understanding of principles”
sure that viewers or other consumers persist in their (p. 10). A teacher can begin by recognizing moral cre-
efforts. The visual arts might thus make up in motiva- ativity as a desirable characteristic. That may sound
tion what they lack in range of opportunity for explo- obvious, but educators can value creativity in general
ration and expression. This is one reason we men- but not the specific components (e.g., autonomy) or
tioned the possibility of catharsis in the arts (also see expressions (e.g., moral reasoning) of it. Moreover, as
Csikszentmihalyi, 1988; Wakefield, 1994). Haste noted, often educators discuss historical figures
Haste (1993) evaluated two different educational such as Florence Nightingale or Joan of Arc, but their
programs already in existence that emphasize moral struggles and confrontations with authority are down-
action. One is the National Curriculum Council played, and the virtues of patience and quiet determi-
(NCC) program for citizenship education, and the sec- nation are stressed. According to Haste, these em-
ond is aimed at stimulating “green awareness” in phases should be changed. Vision requires questioning
young people. The NCC program identified eight and confronting the status quo. Thus,
components of citizenship, with an information and
action component to illustrate each. The Blue Peter reducing the achievements of heroes and heroines to spuri-
ous or misleading virtues, or alternatively, using their stories
Green Book illustrates ways in which a child can both as dubious evidence that the democratic system eventually
help with conservation and care of the environment allowed the desired changes to occur, is not going to lead to
and exercise influence on public offices. Twenty-eight an appreciation of the need for and operation of vision. Yet a
issues are covered. Each section contains an action more accurate account of their real virtues, and the bloody
box with suggestions for acts to aid greenness and nature of their struggle, might engender vision. (p. 11)
campaign for change. Haste (1993) recommended involvement in com-
Recall here that Haste (1993) described the impor- munity activities, classroom debates, and real-life ac-
tance of vision and of taking what we called a broad tion for fostering efficacy. These suggestions are, of
view. In a sense, Haste did this herself, noting a large course, consistent with Kohlberg’s (1987) ideas about
overlap between moral action and citizenship. She introducing dilemmas into the classroom (also see
suggested that children learning about citizenship via Duska & Whelan, 1975; Mattox, 1975). Other evi-
a program similar to The Blue Peter Green Book have dence for challenging the status quo was presented by
a better chance at development of moral creativity Benchoam (1993), Runco (1993b), and Stein (1993).
than those exposed to the NCC program. This is be- To assist in encouraging responsibility, teachers
cause the NCC program emphasizes education for must help children understand and be aware of the en-
conformity to roles and community helpfulness, emies of moral creativity, the pressures and dangers of
whereas The Blue Peter Green Book emphasizes edu- conformity placed on them through advertising and
cation for confronting the system to effect change, or media. Although schools have been reluctant to play
what she called “full participatory democracy” (p. 10). this role, Haste (1993) argued for teaching children
Further, The Blue Green Peter Book focuses on skills not only how their bodies work, but their minds as
in knowledge gathering and debate and discussion in well,
real-life contexts. Thus, children believe in their po-
tential to affect change. The NCC program used role so that they can see the enemies of participatory democracy are
playing and more “safe” projects. This would imply not just the “baddies” out there, but the perfectly normal work-
ings of ordinary social and cognitive life. . . . To effect both cit-
that to help develop moral creativity in children, they
izenship and moral creativity, we must confront the darker side
must be involved in real-life actions in which they feel of the system, and the darker side of the self. (p. 11)
their efforts do make a difference, and this is entirely
consistent with the trend in the creativity research to Here, we see a parallel, on the individual level, of
utilize realistic and real-world exercises and assess- McLaren’s (1993) theory of the dark side of creativity
ments (Renzulli, 1982; Runco & Chand, 1994). (cf. Schmid, 1967).

Creativity Research Journal 101


M. A. Runco & J. Nemiro

Schwebel (1993) was particularly concerned about In the words of Richards, “If it happens quick-
the elimination of art education programs that we are ly, we tend to catch it. But, if the scale is years,
currently experiencing in our school systems. He em- then watch out, because it just might catch us”
phasized that “those who wish to encourage inner (p. 168).
freedom could support such programs of education in • False boundaries of fearfulness: It is hard for
the arts” (pp. 79–80). As further support, Schwebel individuals to comprehend dangers that they
wrote cannot concretely imagine or have not person-
ally experienced. Slowly evolving dangers,
Society needs its artists to help its people understand what is
occurring two centuries after the American and French revo-
such as nuclear war or environmental deteriora-
lutions. It needs them, for their creativity, but especially for tion, are examples of dangers to which one may
their moral creativity. A still life of a bountiful harvest, a be blind.
young love in Bohemia, a humorous set of couplets about • Restricted view of community: This refers to
sex, clever repartee on stage about social customs—these seeing only the needs of one’s reference group,
are all the good pleasures we humans enjoy, interpretations
of nature and social relations that give deeper meaning to
not those of the species as a whole. Richards
life. But if art is to serve humankind in the most essential felt it was crucial for individuals to get past
ways, it must also do what it has accomplished in some of its these narrow frameworks. Again quoting her,
greatest moments: interpret the underlying social struggles
for power—with all their social, political, racial, ethnic, and
our survival has become strongly dependent upon our com-
sexual implications—that would otherwise be withheld
monalities as human beings, not on the differences between
from public consciousness. (p. 80)
each other as individuals and as members of narrow refer-
ence groups. We must seek to make all of humanity our
Those concerned that too much emphasis is being band. . . . We need not abandon our individual and group
placed on creative morality as problem solving may be identities and efforts, but instead need to supplement them
comforted by the suggestion that educational efforts with a much broader consciousness, becoming more aware,
include the arts. solicitous, and protective of our “species self.” (pp. 168–169)
The same individuals may also be encouraged by
the focus on the development of the personality traits • Psychic numbing: This involves the use of psy-
that are associated with creative thinking. Richards chological defenses such as denial to avoid
(1993) argued that the characteristics of creative per- awareness of discomforting problems. When
sons may give them an edge in pursuing moral respon- individuals feel discomfort, they instigate
sibility and awareness and should therefore be encour- efforts to erase or eliminate it.
aged. The critical characteristics include “a sustained
cognitive–affective moral awareness, the courage and Richards (1993) argued that creative individuals
confidence to act, and the vision to look outward to is- can assist in constructing a new vision because they
sues on a species scale” (p. 180). Richards felt a moral may have characteristics that make it easier for them
vision grew “out of individual empathetic concern on not to fall prey to the four major blindnesses. But
an everyday level, to ultimately embrace universal again, creative abilities alone do not guarantee that
principles” (p. 180). This fits well with Haste’s (1993) creative individuals will, in fact, be motivated to take
tripartite model and with Benchoam’s (1993) idea on moral responsibility. To achieve moral responsibil-
about empathy for creative morality. ity, one must have a universal perspective, have an em-
Educational efforts should encourage the good— pathic concern for others, and make a commitment
the arts and those important traits mentioned earlier— (Colby & Damon, 1992).
but it should also eliminate the bad. To this end, Escapism and avoidance should also be discour-
Richards (1993) identified the following areas of po- aged (Benchoam, 1993; Richards, 1993). As Richards
tential blindness that limit an individual from honestly argued,
appreciating societal problems:
one dares to have a look, despite the difficulties this may
entail. . . . [An] adult faces an initial small problem and
• Time frames and contrasts: An individual reacts takes a small creative risk. It is successful. The child rides
to only sudden or major changes and overlooks out the uncertainty, sees the result, gets a pat on the back
the gradual, perhaps more dangerous, situations. from a parent perhaps, and becomes aware of a tiny feeling

102 Creativity Research Journal


Creativity in the Moral Domain

that is savored. The message for the future: “Examine the to culture and society. Creative morality involves a
situation—and then do something.” (p. 175) clear sense of self—one in clear contact with social
and cultural context. This is striking in the case studies
Thus, a teacher can encourage a child to be morally of Colby and Damon (1992). They suggested that
responsible by helping students become interperson- moral endeavors may lead to the flow states described
ally aware, competent, and assertive, with a sense of earlier by Csikszentmihalyi (1990) and in particular to
personal power and a valuing of peaceful and cooper- the transcendence of self. This may explain why cer-
ative solutions over those that are aggressive. Educa- tain creative individuals are self-promoters (Gardner,
tors should work to discourage blindnesses and should 1993a). Perhaps what they accomplish and can even-
actively model and otherwise encourage an empa- tually share in the larger social arena is dependent on
thetic and socially responsible style of living. their first devoting time and energy entirely to them-
selves and their work.
The context of self is apparent in Benchoam’s
Discussion and Conclusions (1993) ideas about “the awareness of the individual as
part of humanity.” Similarly, Piechowski (1993) de-
Even in this fledgling area of study, there are points scribed the nonseparateness of the individual, and
of agreement and disagreement among theorists. Richards (1993) described an “abstract [interpersonal]
There is some question, for example, about the role of relatedness and mutuality.” As Richards described it,
intentions and the value of art for art’s sake (Dudek, “helping may come increasingly to be viewed not just
1993) and questions about the educational value of as an aid for the other, the self, or one’s group, but for
general knowledge, in comparison to specific (e.g., the all-inclusive ‘us.’ Increasingly, then, one’s ‘band’
metaphorical) skills. There were even questions about can become humanity and the viewpoint part of one’s
the social and objective facets of moral creativity and ‘species self’ ” (p. 179).
development. Benchoam captured the personal and the social in
Stein (1993) and Schwebel (1993) emphasized the two different purposes for art:
social, communicable aspects of creative morality.
These were also given great weight by other authors, On one hand, it is a relation with my inner self, like a love of
freedom, often illustrated in my work by representations of
who suggested that creative morality is a matter of ac-
nature, human solitude, and meditation. On the other hand, I
tual action and accomplishment. Haste (1993), for ex- have used my art work as a means of communicating ideas to
ample, seemed to think that something must get done people; usually some political or social concept. (1993)
for it to be called moral, and that it wasn’t enough to
simply think or consider moral options. Similarly, A subtle but critical point of disagreement involves
Richards (1993) said, “Examine the situation—and the concept of adaptation. Numerous theorists have
then do something” (p. 175). Benchoam (1993) and tied creativity to adaptation (e.g., Cohen, 1989; Flach,
Piechowski (1993), in contrast, emphasized personal 1990; Rothenberg & Sobel, 1980), the basic idea
and subjective aspects of creative morality. These lat- being that creative thinking allows an individual to be
ter views seem very important to us, and for the same flexible, and that this flexibility in turn supplies op-
reasons subjective aspects of other kinds of creativity tions for effective coping. Not surprisingly, the adap-
seem to be important (Runco, 1993c). Perhaps most tiveness of creative thinking is often used to justify its
important is that the personal facets may precede the role in resolving moral problems. Still, care must be
social. An individual must have an insight before he or taken with the concept of adaptation. This is because
she can explore or share the idea or solution. an individual—and society as a whole—might be too
The personal side of creative morality was implied adaptive, or at least too adaptive for creativity. This
in that the self was included in many theories. Self- would occur when an environment elicits stable and
discipline, self-awareness, and self-actualization were thus unoriginal behaviors. An individual or society
each emphasized. Creativity is also quite personal might be too traditional to be creative, and yet fit well
(Runco, in press-b), but of course neither morality nor into the immediate environment.
creativity are self-centered. On the contrary. The theo- This view might seem to be incompatible with that
ries reviewed in this article emphasize self in relation proposed by Gruber (1993) and Miller and Karl

Creativity Research Journal 103


M. A. Runco & J. Nemiro

(1993) and especially with Rothenberg and Sobel’s Andreani, O. D., & Pagnin, A. (1993). Moral judgment in creative
(1980) position that “creativity is the highest form of and talented adolescents. Creativity Research Journal, 6, 45–64.
Angell, M. (1990). The Nazi hypothermia experiments and unethi-
human adaptation” (p. 370). It is thus vital to keep in cal research today. New England Journal of Medicine, 322,
mind that our species can consciously direct evolu- 1462–1464.
tion. Richards (1993) referred to this as conscious Benchoam, E. D. (1993). Art refuge and protest: Autobiography of a
evolution and recommended that the schools, media, young political prisoner in Argentina. Creativity Research Jour-
and other institutions teach individuals “to circumvent nal, 6, 111–128.
Bronowski, J. (1977). A sense of the future. Cambridge, MA: MIT
our perceptual limitations and distinguish what is still Press.
‘natural’ in our evolution from what has now become Bruner, J. (1965). The growth of mind. American Psychologist, 20,
dangerous and needs to be altered” (p. 168). 1007–1017.
Bronowski (1977), Ornstein and Ehrlich (1989), and Cohen, L. (1989). A continuum of adaptive creative behaviors. Cre-
Runco (in press-a) also emphasized conscious evolu- ativity Research Journal, 2, 169–183.
Colby, A., & Damon, W. (1992). Some do care: Contemporary lives
tion. Bruner (1965) put the issue very aptly when he of moral commitment. New York: Free Press.
suggested that we must prepare our children “for the Crutchfield, R. (1962). Conformity and creative thinking. In
unforeseeable future” (p. 115), and Stein (1993) was H. Gruber, G. Terrell, & M. Wertheimer (Eds.), Contempo-
quoted earlier in this article as suggesting that we rary approaches to creative thinking. New York: Atherton.
must “master technology or it will master us” (p. 199). Csikszentmihalyi, M. (1988). The dangers of originality: Creativity
and the artistic process. In M. M. Gedo (Ed.), Psychoanalytic
The adaptability supplied by creativity should allow perspectives on art (pp. 213–224). Hillsdale, NJ: Analytic.
us to control our own fate and to cope with the unfore- Csikszentmihalyi, M. (1990). Flow: The psychology of optimal ex-
seeable future, but it must be consciously directed. It perience. New York: Harper & Row.
must be, in Heinzen’s (1994) terms, proactive rather Dudek, S. Z. (1993). The morality of 20th century transgressive art.
than reactive creativity. Creativity Research Journal, 6, 145–152.
Dudek, S. Z., & Cote, R. (1994). Problem finding revisited. In
This is one reason we explored educational implica- M. A. Runco (Ed.), Problem finding, problem solving, and
tions; education is a kind of proactive morality. And creativity (pp. 130–150). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
importantly, many of the educational recommenda- Duska, R., & Whelan, M. (1975). Moral development: A guide to
tions apply equally well to informal as well as formal Piaget and Kohlberg. New York: Paulist Press.
education (Benchoam, 1993; Piechowski, 1993; Family, G. (1993). The moral responsibility of the artist. Creativity
Research Journal, 6, 83–88.
Schwebel, 1993), and most apply well beyond child- Flach, F. (1990). Disorders of the pathways involved in the creative
hood. In fact, many of the changes and insights re- process. Creativity Research Journal, 3, 158–165.
ported by the case studies took place well into adult- Gardner, H. (1983). Frames of mind: A theory of multiple intelli-
hood. Consider also the behavior of Schindler and gences. New York: Basic Books.
Jagendorf (Rappoport & Kren, 1993). All this is quite Gardner, H. (1993a). Creating minds. New York: Basic Books.
Gardner, H. (1993b). Mahatma Gandhi: A hold upon others. Cre-
consistent with the idea of conscious evolution, though ativity Research Journal, 6, 29–44.
here we apply that idea to ontogenic evolution, rather Goertzel, V., & Goertzel, M. G. (1962). Cradles of eminence.
than phylogenic evolution. Individuals can direct their Boston, MA: Little, Brown.
own development and do so in a creative and moral Goswami, A. (1993). An idealist theory of ethics. Creativity Re-
fashion. What a wonderfully optimistic prospect. search Journal, 6, 185–196.
Gruber, H. E. (1981). On the relation between “a ha” experiences
and the construction of ideas. History of Science, 19, 41–59.
Gruber, H. E. (1985). Giftedness and moral responsibility: Creative
References thinking and human survival. In F. Horowitz & M. O’Brien (Eds.),
Gifted and talented: Developmental perspectives (pp. 301–330).
Albert, R. S. (1980). Exceptionally gifted boys and their parents: Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
Basic educational, cognitive, and creative similarities. Gifted Gruber, H. E. (1993). Creativity in the moral domain: OUGHT implies
Child Quarterly, 24, 174–179. CAN implies CREATE. Creativity Research Journal, 6, 3–16.
Albert, R. S., & Runco, M. A. (1986). The achievement of emi- Haste, H. (1993). Moral creativity and education for citizenship.
nence: A model of exceptionally gifted boys and their families. Creativity Research Journal, 6, 153–164.
In R. J. Sternberg & J. E. Davidson (Eds.), Conceptions of gift- Heinzen, T. (1994). Situational affect: Proactive and reactive cre-
edness (pp. 332–357). New York: Cambridge University Press. ativity. In M. P. Shaw & M. A. Runco (Eds.), Creativity and af-
Albert, R. S., & Runco, M. A. (1989). Independence and cogni- fect (pp. 127–146). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
tive ability in gifted and exceptionally gifted boys. Journal of Johnson, M. (1993). Moral imagination: Implications of cognitive
Youth and Adolescence, 18, 221–230. science for ethics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

104 Creativity Research Journal


Creativity in the Moral Domain

Kohlberg, L. (1987). The development of moral judgment and Runco, M. A. (Ed.). (1994b). Problem finding, problem solving, and
moral action. In L. Kohlberg (Ed.), Child psychology and child- creativity. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
hood education: A cognitive developmental view. New York: Runco, M. A. (in press-a). Creativity and the future. In Encyclope-
Longman. dia of the future. New York: Macmillan.
Mattox, B. A. (1975). Getting it together: Dilemma for the class- Runco, M. A. (in press-b). Creativity need not be social. In A. Mon-
room. San Diego, CA: Pennant. tuori & R. Purser (Eds.), Social creativity (vol. 1). Cresskill, NJ:
McLaren, R. (1993). The dark side of creativity. Creativity Re- Hampton.
search Journal, 6, 137–144. Runco, M. A., & Chand, I. (1994). Problem finding, evaluative
Miller, & Karl, S. (1993). Religious language as a transitional phe- thinking, and creativity. In M. A. Runco (Ed.), Problem finding,
nomenon. Creativity Research Journal, 6, 99–110. problem solving, and creativity (pp. 40–76). Norwood, NJ:
Ornstein, R., & Erlich, P. (1989). New world, new mind: Moving to- Ablex.
wards conscious evolution. New York: Touchstone. Runco, M. A., & Charles, R. (1993). Judgments of originality and
Piaget, J. (1976). To understand is to invent. New York: Penguin. appropriateness as predictors of creativity. Personality and Indi-
Piechowski, M. (1993). Is inner transformation a creative process? vidual Differences, 15, 537–546.
Creativity Research Journal, 6, 89–98. Runco, M. A., & Charles, R. (1997). Developmental trends in cre-
Rappoport, L., & Kren, G. (1993). Amoral rescuers: The ambigui- ative potential and creative performance. In M. A. Runco (Ed.),
ties of altruism. Creativity Research Journal, 6, 129–136. Creativity research handbook (Vol. 1, pp. 115–152). Cresskill,
Renzulli, J. S. (1982). What makes a problem real: Stalking the illu- NJ: Hampton.
sive meaning of qualitative differences in gifted education. Schmid, K. (1967). Aspects of evil in the creative. In J. Hillman
Gifted Child Quarterly, 26, 147–156. (Ed.), Studies in Jungian thought. Evanston, IL: Northwestern
Richards, R. (1993). Seeing beyond: Issues of creative awareness University Press.
and social responsibility. Creativity Research Journal, 6, Schwebel, M. (1993). Moral creativity as artistic transformation.
165–183. Creativity Research Journal, 6, 65–82.
Rothenberg, A., & Hausman, C. (1976). The creativity question. Stein, M. I. (1993). Moral issues facing intermediaries between cre-
Durham, NC: Duke University Press. ators and the public. Creativity Research Journal, 6, 197–200.
Rothenberg, A., & Sobel, R. S. (1980). Adaptation and cognition. Wakefield, J. (1994). Problem finding and empathy in art. In M. A.
Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 68, 370–347. Runco (Ed.), Problem finding, problem solving, and creativity
Runco, M. A. (1987). The generality of creative performance in (pp. 99–115). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
gifted and nongifted children. Gifted Child Quarterly, 31, Wallace, D. B. (1991). The genesis and microgenesis of sudden in-
121–125. sight in the creation of literature. Creativity Research Journal,
Runco, M. A. (1993a, August). Creativity in the moral domain. Dis- 4, 41–50.
cussant for symposium at the meeting of the American Psycho- Weisberg, R. W. (1993). Creativity: Beyond the myth of genius.
logical Association, Toronto, Ontario, Canada. New York: Freeman.
Runco, M. A. (1993b). Moral creativity: Intentional and unconven- Winnicott, D. W. (1971). Playing and reality. New York: Routledge.
tional. Creativity Research Journal, 6, 17–28. Wolf, F. M., & Larson, G. L. (1981). On why adolescent formal op-
Runco, M. A. (1993c). On reputational paths and case studies. Cre- erators may not be creative thinkers. Adolescence, 62, 345–348.
ativity Research Journal, 6, 487–488.
Runco, M. A. (1994a). Creativity and its discontents. In M. P. Shaw
& M. A. Runco (Eds.), Creativity and affect (pp. 102–123). Nor-
wood, NJ: Ablex.

Creativity Research Journal 105

You might also like