You are on page 1of 18

Cognition 115 (2010) 207–224

Contents lists available at ScienceDirect

Cognition
journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/COGNIT

Mayan morality: An exploration of permissible harms


Linda Abarbanell a,*,1, Marc D. Hauser b,c,1
a
Graduate School of Education, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA 02138, United States
b
Department of Psychology, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA 02138, United States
c
Department of Human Evolutionary Biology, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA 02138, United States

a r t i c l e i n f o a b s t r a c t

Article history: Anthropologists have provided rich field descriptions of the norms and conventions gov-
Received 26 June 2008 erning behavior and interactions in small-scale societies. Here, we add a further dimension
Revised 11 December 2009 to this work by presenting hypothetical moral dilemmas involving harm, to a small-scale,
Accepted 16 December 2009
agrarian Mayan population, with the specific goal of exploring the hypothesis that certain
moral principles apply universally. We presented Mayan participants with moral dilemmas
translated into their native language, Tseltal. Paralleling several studies carried out with
Keywords:
educated subjects living in large-scale, developed nations, the Mayan participants judged
Moral psychology
Cross-cultural
harms caused as the means to a greater good as more forbidden than harms caused as a
Omission bias side-effect (i.e., side-effect bias). However, unlike these other populations living in large-
Means-side-effects scale societies, as well as a more educated and less rural Mayan comparison group, the tar-
Universals get rural Mayan participants did not judge actions causing harm as worse than omissions
Mayans (i.e., omission bias). A series of probes targeting the action–omission distinction suggest
Judgments that the absence of an omission bias among the rural Mayan participants was not due to
difficulties comprehending the dilemmas, using the judgment scale, or in attributing a
greater causal role for actions over omissions. Thus, while the moral distinction between
means and side-effect may be more universal, the moral distinction between actions and
omission appears to be open to greater cross-cultural variation. We discuss these results
in light of issues concerning the role of biological constraints and cultural variation in
moral decision-making, as well as the limitations of such experimental, cross-cultural
research.
Ó 2009 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.

1. Introduction moral relativist might argue that the rightness or wrong-


ness of slavery, war, or child abuse are to be determined
For decades, philosophers and psychologists have wres- by a culture, and open to change over time depending upon
tled with the distinction between moral relativism and culturally varying perspectives, a moral absolutist would
moral absolutism (Gowans, 2008; Harman & Thomson, argue that such issues are unquestionably immoral regard-
1996). Moral relativists claim that ethical standards are less of the culture’s beliefs or goals. In the face of this de-
culturally based and merely a matter of context and con- bate, it goes without saying that cultural groups, both
vention. Moral absolutists claim that there are absolute extinct and extant, have exhibited massive differences in
ethical standards, such that certain actions are either right what they believe are morally permissible actions, and
or wrong independently of context or culture. Whereas a how these beliefs are translated into behaviors and rules,
both explicit and implicit, that help or harm others.
(Brandt, 1954; Henrich et al., 2005; Ladd, 1957; Nisbett &
* Corresponding author. Fax: +1 617 496 7077.
Cohen, 1996; Westermarck, 1906–1908). On the other
E-mail addresses: abarbali@gmail.com (L. Abarbanell),
mdh102559@gmail.com (M.D. Hauser). hand, there also appear to be similarities across cultures,
1
Both authors contributed equally to this research. at least suggesting the possibility of universal principles

0010-0277/$ - see front matter Ó 2009 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2009.12.007
208 L. Abarbanell, M.D. Hauser / Cognition 115 (2010) 207–224

(Gert, 2004; Haidt, 2007; Hauser, 2006a; Henrich et al., strong, 2008; Cushman, Young, & Hauser, 2006; Fischer &
2005, 2006; Nisbett & Cohen, 1996). Ravizza, 1992; Greene, Nystrom, Engell, Darley, & Cohen,
The philosophical debate about moral relativism and 2004; Greene, Sommerville, Nystrom, Darley, & Cohen,
absolutism focuses largely on prescriptive claims, that is, 2001; Haidt & Baron, 1996; Hauser, Tonnaer, & Cima, in
whether different societies should have the kinds of free- press; Mikhail, 2007; Ritov & Baron, 1990; Spranca, Minsk,
dom they apparently have to decide moral cases. Most of & Baron, 1991).
these arguments tend to proceed without making signifi- Though the web-based studies have tapped variation in
cant contact with descriptive work, designed to character- age, gender, education, and religious background, and re-
ize the cross-culturally variable and universal principles vealed little to no influence of such factors on participants’
that guide moral judgment and behavior in different soci- moral judgments, it is clear that this internet sample is
eties (Doris & Plakias, 2008; Fraser & Hauser, in press). insufficient for testing questions of universality and
Anthropological approaches, on the other hand, have cross-cultural variation. In particular, although these stud-
mostly provided very general ascriptions of moral norms ies originally sampled thousands of individuals, most were
to the target population, based almost entirely on observa- from English-speaking countries, most were formally edu-
tions of how people act in different circumstances, and cated, and many had read books discussing moral issues.
sometimes on the basis of questionnaires concerning Further, all were technologically savvy, at least in terms
how they justify such actions (e.g., Evans-Pritchard, of their ability to find, log in, and navigate computer soft-
1969; Malinowski, 1922/1984; Mead, 1928/2001; Turn- ware designed to access the world wide web. And lastly,
bull, 1987). From the perspective of a Western industrial- though many studies have uncovered the distinctions
ized culture, this kind of work often leads to fairly noted above, not all do. This is especially the case with re-
surprising descriptions of violence, sexuality, and parent- spect to the action/omission distinction, where, depending
ing practices, actions that we think are immoral. They have on the manipulations, some studies show an omission bias
also led to the view that moral norms are fairly uncon- (see references above) whereas others do not (Connolly &
strained, free to vary depending upon the beliefs of the tar- Reb, 2003; Mandel & Vartanian, 2007; Patt & Zeckhauser,
get culture. It is possible, however, that underlying this 2000; Tanner & Medin, 2004). At present, there is no clear
variation in observed behavior are a common set of princi- consensus as to why some studies fail to find an omission
ples that dictate when harm is permissible, when help is bias in part because different studies use different presen-
obligatory, and the situations that mandate loyalty and re- tation methods (e.g., parallel vs. serial presentation of vign-
spect. To address this possibility, and compliment the ettes), modify different aspects of the scenarios (e.g.,
more traditional observational explorations, experimental familiar vs. unfamiliar individuals), use different permissi-
approaches targeting specific principles are necessary (Bar- bility scales (e.g., dichotomous yes/no acceptability vs. per-
on & Miller, 2000; Miller, 1994; Miller, Bersoff, & Harwood, missibility scales), and test either a small or large number
1990; Shweder, Mahapatra, & Miller, 1987). Though exper- of dilemmas varying narrowly (e.g., different versions of
imental approaches, by their nature, derive evidence under the trolley problem) or broadly (e.g., artificial and non-arti-
more artificial conditions, they can more readily zero in on ficial cases); for critical discussion of these issues, see (Bar-
particular parameters than standard ethnographies, and in on, 2009; Baron & Ritov, 2004). It is thus unclear, for
the present case, target factors that have been at the center example, whether failures to find an omission bias are
of philosophical, legal, and psychological debates (e.g., due to particular cases (e.g., only testing trolley problems),
Gert, 2004; Hauser, 2006b; Kamm, 2007; Mikhail, 2007; the use of different scales, or different modes of presenta-
Sunstein, 2005). Further, when this experimental approach tion (sequential vs. parallel).
is anchored in the rich ethnographies of the local culture, We tested a Mayan population in the Tenejapa region of
the assumptions can be checked, and the artificiality re- Chiapas, Mexico, using their native language Tseltal,
duced by contrasting the patterns obtained in experiments attempting to match previous studies with respect to sev-
with those obtained from observation. This is the approach eral methodological details (Cushman, 2008a; Cushman
adopted here. et al., 2006; Hauser, Cushman, Young, Jin, & Mikhail,
We presented moral dilemmas to a small-scale, rural, 2007; Hauser et al., in press): moral dilemmas pitting
and largely uneducated population of Mayan subjects. non-consequentialist rules against utilitarian-consequen-
We used dilemmas adapted from ones that previously tialist outcomes, sequential presentation of cases, Likert-
had been presented to subjects living in large-scale, highly scales for moral judgments, scenarios lacking information
industrialized, and educated societies, using the Moral about the identity of the individuals involved. We explic-
Sense Test, an online experimental environment itly contrasted the results from this population with a less
(www.moral.wjh.edu) designed to test a broad range of rural and more educated Mayan sample from the same
moral concerns. Previous studies with this web-based geographical region, also tested in Tseltal using the exact
technology, as well as other work in moral psychology, same methods. Based on this design, we hypothesized that
has revealed several central psychological distinctions. In any differences observed between the target Mayan popu-
particular, participants tend to judge harms caused as the lation and our comparison groups would be less likely to
means to a greater good as less permissible than those be accounted for by methodological differences, and more
caused as side-effects (i.e., side-effect bias), actions as less likely to be due to cultural factors; we also contrasted the
permissible than omissions (i.e., omission bias), and harms results from our target Mayan population with the internet
caused by contact as less permissible than non-contact studies, but with the caveat that many things differ be-
(Baron & Ritov, 2004; Cushman, Knobe, & Sinnott-Arm- tween these populations. We turn next to a brief descrip-
L. Abarbanell, M.D. Hauser / Cognition 115 (2010) 207–224 209

tion of social life in the Tseltal Mayan community where USD), reinforcing the closed nature of these communities
we worked, presenting only those details that we consider and their need for an intra-dependent social structure.
relevant to understanding their social structure and possi- While the municipal center resembles a small town, the
bly, sense of the moral domain. outlying parajes are decidedly rural, comprised of loosely
grouped family compounds surrounded by milpas (corn-
fields). Daily life revolves around the immediate and ex-
2. Mayan2 social life: a brief synopsis
tended family, however all members of the paraje know
one another and are engaged in an extended web of mutual
The municipality of Tenejapa is an indigenous Mayan
obligations and responsibilities; all adult community
community in the highland region of Chiapas, Mexico. Of
members are obliged to share in local governance, deci-
the approximately 38,000 residents, 99% are speakers of
sion-making, and community labor. While most parajes
the Mayan language Tseltal and are descendents of the
are today accessible by road, transportation is still scarce.
classical Mayan civilization that flourished from 600 to
Most individuals rarely leave their paraje.
900 AD. Although the culture has changed alongside and
The physical and familial structure of these parajes
in interaction with mainstream Mexican society, a long
helps to strengthen community bonds. Inheritance is patri-
history of apartheid together with the remarkable resis-
lineal, with a father’s land divided evenly among all of his
tance of the indigenous peoples has resulted in the mainte-
sons who will often build their homes on this land, forming
nance of a separate culture, with its own language, dress,
extended family complexes. Daughters generally leave the
and social, political and religious institutions, making this
family compound to live with their husbands; however,
a relevant population for exploring cross-cultural similari-
they may make frequent visits home and remain closely
ties and differences in the moral domain.
tied to their family of origin. As most families are fairly
The municipality is divided into 61 parajes, small rural
large (an average of 3 live births per woman 12 years and
hamlets that surround a more urban municipal center
older; INEGI, 2005), and individuals tend to marry young
and that maintain the structure of a small-scale agrarian
(as young as 15 years old), this quickly results in an ex-
society in daily life (INEGI, 2005). The center houses gov-
tended network of kin with the associated responsibilities
ernment offices, the main Catholic church, and a weekly
and obligations. All family members including young chil-
market, and is the primary site of political and ceremonial
dren share responsibilities for household chores such as
life. It is also home to a small but prominent ladino popu-
tending crops, gathering firewood, cooking and childcare.
lation (Spanish-speakers of mixed Spanish and indigenous
These close-knit networks of community and kin provide
descent), most of whose families have resided in Tenejapa
an important contrast from prior samples of industrialized
for generations and own small shops and businesses that
large-scale societies that could potentially affect moral
line the center’s three main streets. There is also regular
judgments, particularly with respect to perceived obliga-
transportation between the municipal center and the near-
tions and responsibilities toward others, and resulting in
est urban center of San Cristobal de Las Casas at a distance
a relatively rich understanding of what others do and do
of about 27 km. In contrast, the outlying parajes, which are
not do.
relatively isolated, are inhabited almost exclusively by
In addition to these characteristics which help bind
Tseltal Mayans who practice subsistence milpa (slash and
community members to one another, the political system
burn) agriculture. Despite the long-time coexistence of
in Tenejapa has a unique structure that helps reinforce
the ladino and the indigenous populations, contact be-
the traditional beliefs and practices of the community.
tween them is limited. Each group worships its own set
The Ayuntamiento, or city council, the central political
of saints and maintains its own religious festivals. And
power in the municipality, is comprised of two groups of
while indigenous and ladino children attend the same
functionaries – those who are part of the official institution
schools, most ladinos speak little to no Tseltal, and the
as recognized by Mexican law, and those who are not rec-
two groups rarely if ever intermarry.
ognized by law but by the social and cultural norms of the
While recent government incentives have resulted in
community (Medina Hernandez, 1991). The first group
most children now attending school, most adults
consists of a municipal president, a syndicate, nine regi-
(>35 years old) in Tenejapa have little to no formal school-
dores who function like local police, a judge, a treasurer,
ing and few opportunities to participate in the national
a secretary, and various directorates. The second group
economy, resulting in limited to no contact with the
consists of four alkal (from the Spanish, mayor), eight tatik
majority culture. Men may occasionally travel to lowland
martin (from San Sebastian martyr), and a larger group of
fincas or tourist centers like Cancun for seasonal employ-
minor regidores who serve largely as messengers and er-
ment, and a small number migrate to urban areas like Mex-
rand runners for higher political authorities.
ico City and even the United States and send earnings
The alkal together with the tatik martin have an espe-
home. About half the population earns no wages at all,
cially unique and important role: they serve to connect
while the other half earns less than the minimum wage
the official government with the traditional religious orga-
(at the time of testing, 48 pesos per day, or about $4.50
nization and social norms of the community (Medina Her-
nandez, 1991). The alkal select the head alfereces, or
2
For convenience, we use the term ‘‘Mayan” throughout this paper when captains who are in charge of carrying out traditional reli-
referring to the Tseltal Mayan community of Tenejapa where we worked.
We wish to emphasize, however, that there are various Mayan languages
gious festivals believed to be necessary for the well-being
and cultures and our findings may or may not generalize to other Mayan of the community. They also make sure that the alfereces
communities. carry out their duties in line with the socially sanctioned
210 L. Abarbanell, M.D. Hauser / Cognition 115 (2010) 207–224

rules, which include prohibitions such as fasting and absti- the household would like to participate. At the time of test-
nence from any sexual relations during certain festivals. ing, LA had worked in this community for over 4 years, and
Failure to observe such restrictions are believed to result with this particular research assistant for 2 years. There-
in the failure of the festival and perhaps even the death fore, both LA and her assistant were well known to most
of the transgressor, reinforcing a connection between indi- community members who readily participated in previous
vidual obligations and the well-being of the entire commu- tasks; none of this earlier work focused on issues of moral-
nity. The tatik martin have the special duty of instructing ity, or social norms more generally. In Pajaltón, recruit-
the members of the Ayuntamiento in a series of prayers ment was facilitated by the local authorities. An effort
that are recited by all political functionaries at the begin- was made to recruit participants who had little to no
ning and middle of the year. They also have the responsi- schooling and had not lived or worked outside of Tenejapa
bility of interceding if they feel the municipal authorities as our intention was to obtain a sample as distinct from
have strayed from traditional Tenejapan norms. prior samples and as representative of a small-scale agrar-
In addition to these two main groups localized in the ian society as possible. Because of social conventions, as
municipal center – one sanctioned by the law and the well as a limited adult population to select from, we did
other by the community – there is a third group, the tijwi- not have strict control over individual-level demographics.
nik, who serve to connect the Ayuntamiento with the out- Our final sample of participants therefore tended to mirror
lying parajes. While localized in their parajes where they the average adult demographics of the parajes where we
help maintain order, they meet weekly with the municipal worked.
president where they serve as a representative and mes- Due to the above mentioned limitations, and in particu-
senger for their community. lar, restrictions on the total available sample of partici-
The Mayan communities, therefore, while accountable pants that could be tested, some participants were tested
to Mexican national law, remain distinctly rooted in local on more than one condition. These individuals were later
social and religious customs and tied to the needs and identified using a highly conservative approach. Specifi-
norms of hamlet life. Such ties include both a heightened cally, given that many individuals in this community share
responsibility to both family and community, as well an the same first name, as well as their maternal and paternal
intimacy with the actions and relationships of others in last names, we compared all individuals with the exact
their community. same name and classified them as repeats if they provided
overlapping demographic information, allowing for ex-
pected variation in the self-report of factors such as age.
3. Methods
For example, as in many small-scale societies, many indi-
viduals have only a rough sense of their age, and thus,
3.1. Sample sites
when asked, will often give estimates that can fluctuate
by as much as 10 years for the same individual on different
Most of our participants were from the parajes of the
occasions. For example, we counted as the same individual
Cañada Chica (pop. 217), the Cañada Grande (pop. 550),
three entries sharing the same name and demographic
and for one condition, from Pajaltón (pop. 613; INEGI,
information (including places of residence and birth, years
2005). All three parajes lie outside of the municipal center.
of schooling, number of children and religious identifica-
While not randomly selected (these communities were se-
tion), but with reported ages of 30, 37 and 38 years. In
lected on the basis of prior fieldwork and relationships that
our analyses, we test for the effect of repeated sampling
facilitated testing), they have demographic profiles that
on moral judgments, noting that in previous work we have
place them close to the municipal average on many mea-
not found any such effects (Cushman et al., 2006; Hauser
sures of conservatism, such as illiteracy (Proportion of illit-
et al., in press; Huebner, Pettit, & Hauser, in preparation).
erate individuals 15 years and older: Cañana Chica
Participants were paid 40 pesos (about 4 USD) for their
(CC) = 42%, Cañada Grande (CG) = 36%, Pajalton (P) = 29%,
time, a rate that had previously been agreed upon in meet-
municipal average 31%), monolingualism (% monolingual
ings between LA, the local authorities and a gathering of
5 years and older: CC = 46%, CG = 39%, P = 33%, municipal
interested community members. Procedures for oral in-
average 31%), and level of schooling (average grade level:
formed consent were followed at all times, and all studies
CC = 4.3, CG = 4.4, P = 3.8, municipal average 4.3; INEGI,
were conducted with the consent of local authorities, as
2005). Moreover, these parajes adhere to the social, physi-
well as with the approval of Harvard University’s IRB. Test-
cal, and political description outlined in the previous
ing took place in a quiet room of a private dwelling in Ten-
section.
ejapa for participants from the Cañanda Chica and the
Cañada Grande and in an unused classroom of the local
3.2. Participant recruitment school in Pajaltón, with only LA, the research assistant,
and participant present. Most sessions lasted about 20 min.
We recruited participants in the Cañanda Chica and the
Cañada Grande with the help of LA’s research assistant, a 3.3. Translation of moral dilemmas
native-speaking Tseltal woman who was from the commu-
nity and resided in the same paraje (the Cañada Chica) as English-language versions of the dilemmas were trans-
many of the participants. The research assistant walked lated into Spanish by LA who is fluent in Spanish. These
from house to house, first explaining the general condi- were then translated into Tseltal with the assistance of a
tions of the study, and then asking whether anyone in native Tseltal-speaker (a former bilingual school teacher
L. Abarbanell, M.D. Hauser / Cognition 115 (2010) 207–224 211

and Tseltal instructor). LA, who is proficient in Tseltal, first did?” (Binti ya a’nop yu’un a te 0ye, jich te bit’il la spas te wi-
explained each dilemma in Spanish and then helped trans- nike?). To ensure that the participants (most of whom were
late it line-by-line alongside the translator. This collabora- nonliterate and unfamiliar with this type of task) under-
tive method allowed LA to question specific words and stood what they were supposed to be responding to, the
phrases, to check for fidelity to the original version, and question was followed by a quick, neutral summary (e.g.
to clarify any misunderstandings. The translated dilemmas ‘‘that he called the man over, thus the one man died and
were then back-translated into Spanish by the research the five men were saved”). Participants were then told about
assistant in Tenejapa who would be assisting with the task. the judgment scale. To concretize the scale, LA held up one
This was again done on a line-by-line basis followed by hand and pointed to each finger in turn while reading the
asking for a brief summary to check for overall comprehen- scale. If participants had difficulty responding, they were gi-
sion. The assistant, a woman from the community with a ven a choice between ma xtu’un or lek, followed by addi-
background similar to the participants, was also asked tional prompting with the intensifiers. Most participants,
whether she thought the stories would be comprehensible however, responded appropriately without simplification.
to the participants. Occasionally, lexical changes were
made to reflect local variations and artifacts were rendered
4. Condition 1
more culturally appropriate (e.g. a vase was replaced with
a ceramic water vessel or k’ib). However, every effort was
4.1. Methods
made to match the original structure of the dilemmas as
closely as possible (see Appendix A for back-translation
To determine whether the general methods used in pre-
of Tseltal into English).
vious studies of moral judgments among participants liv-
In collaboration with the research assistant, LA devised
ing in large-scale societies would work with our Mayan
a 5-point scale in Tseltal to mirror the 7-point forbidden–
population, we presented 30 adult participants (Fe-
permissible–obligatory scale used in the internet based
male = 23, Male = 7, mean age = 42.10 (SD = 13.18, range
studies (Cushman et al., 2006; Hauser et al., in press). First,
24–70), mean years of schooling = 2.33 (SD = 2.50, range
a dichotomy was drawn between actions that ‘‘won’t do”,
0–6)) with four moral dilemmas, each involving a potential
were ‘‘not possible” or ‘‘don’t answer”, ma xtu’un in Tseltal,
harm to one individual and the saving of five other individ-
and actions that were favorable or good, lek. Checking
uals. The dilemmas targeted killing by way of non-contact
these terms against the opinions of several native speakers,
means, a side-effect, an omission (letting die), and contact
they were found to be the closest in match in both defini-
(see Table 1). More specifically, we sought an initial test of
tions and use (for an analysis of the corresponding terms in
the hypothesis that, like participants on the Moral Sense
Tsotsil, a closely related language, see Haviland, 1977, p.
Test, the Mayan participants would perceive (1) means-
123). Intensifiers were then added to make a 5-point scale
based harms as worse than side-effects, (2) actions as
ranging from very impermissible to very good: ma xtu’un ta
worse than omissions, and (3) contact-based harms as
bayel (very impermissible), ma xtu’un jteb nax (a little
worse than non-contact (Cushman et al., 2006).
impermissible), lek jteb (a little good), lek nax (regular
The Mayan participants were read each story, one at a
good), and mero lek (very good).
time, randomized for order of presentation. A repeated
measures ANOVA was computed over the participants’ re-
3.4. Testing procedures
sponses to the 5-point Likert-scale.

After a brief background interview (including questions


about the participants’ age, marital status and number of 4.2. Results
children, places of residence and birth, work and school
history, knowledge of Spanish and literacy, and religious Overall, there was a significant difference in permissi-
affiliation), participants were told that they would be read bility judgments for these four dilemmas (F3,87 = 39.61,
two to four stories and after each, would be asked what p < 0.001, g2p ¼ 0:58). Paired t-tests showed that subjects
they thought about the protagonist’s behavior in the story, judged harms caused as a side-effect as more permissible
using the scale to provide their response. Participants were (MSIDE-EFFECT = 4.07, SE = 0.22) than means-based harms
assured that there were no right or wrong answers and caused by contact (MMEANS-CONTACT = 1.63, SE = 0.22;
that we were only interested in what they thought. The t(29) = 8.06, p < 0.001, d = 2.02) and non-contact (MMEANS-
stories were then read by LA to ensure that they were read NON-CONTACT = 1.90, SE = 0.21; t(29) = 7.86, p < 0.001,
in the same manner for each participant and for each story; d = 1.84), as well as by omission (MOMIT = 1.90, SE = 0.26;
however, the research assistant was present at all times to t(29) = 6.39; p < 0.001, d = 1.66). Critically, when harm
offer clarifications and support as needed, with LA moni- was caused in the absence of contact, subjects did not
toring for accuracy and bias. For example, if the research judge harms caused by action as worse than harms caused
assistant said ‘‘he called the man over and the one man by omission or letting die, nor did they judge contactful
died,” LA added ‘‘thus, the five men were saved.” The re- harm as worse than harm caused in the absence of contact.
search assistant was familiar with the need for experimen-
tal control and had excellent communication skills and 4.3. Discussion
rapport with the participants.
Following the presentation of each story, we asked par- These results license two preliminary conclusions con-
ticipants ‘‘What do you think about that, what the man cerning the specific dilemmas presented and the specific
212 L. Abarbanell, M.D. Hauser / Cognition 115 (2010) 207–224

Table 1
The first four dilemmas presented to Mayan subjects, testing for the distinctions of (i) means-side-effect, (ii) kill-let die, and (iii) contact-no contact. All
dilemmas started as follows: A man is sitting near the side of the road when he sees a truck speeding along. It is headed towards a group of five men, who do not hear
or see it, and if nothing appears in the road, it will certainly hit and kill them. . .

Side-effect, non-contact killing Means-based non-contact killing Non-contact omission, letting die Means-based contact killing
Across the road is another man Across the road is another man Across the road is another man Standing next to him is another
sitting in front of his house. If the sitting in front of his house. If the about to walk onto the road. If he man. If the man who is sitting by
man who is sitting by the road calls man who is sitting by the road calls walks onto the road, the truck will the road pushes the other man, the
out to the truck driver and says out to the man by his house and certainly hit and kill him, but if it other man will fall into the path of
‘watch out,’ the truck will swerve says ‘come here,’ the man will walk does, it will stop and not continue the truck, be killed, and stop it
away from the five men, saving into the road in the path of the and the other five will not be hurt. from continuing on toward the
them, but into the path of the one truck, be killed, and stop it from If the man who is sitting by the five, saving them. If the man sitting
man in front of his house, killing continuing on toward the five, road calls out to the man about to by the road does nothing, the truck
him. If the man sitting by the road saving them. If the man sitting by cross the road and says ‘look out!,’ will travel on and kill the five. The
says nothing the truck will travel the road says nothing, the truck the man will not walk into the road man decides to push the other
on and kill the five, and the one will travel on and kill the five. The in the path of the truck, and will be man, so the one other man is killed
man in front of his house will be man decides to call out so the one safe. But the truck will continue on and the five men are saved
safe. The man decides to call out, so man is killed and the five men are toward the five, killing them. If the
the one man is killed and the five saved man sitting by the road says
men are saved nothing, the truck will travel on
and kill the man crossing the road.
The man decides not to call out, so
the one man is killed and the five
men are saved

Mayan population tested. First, based on the fact that par- tion of 30 adult participants from the same community
ticipants showed a significant difference in their judg- with two new pairs of dilemmas, specifically targeting
ments between harms caused as a side-effect and the the action–omission distinction, using the same general
three other distinctions, it appears that our methods are methods as in Condition 1.
sufficiently sensitive to detect at least this difference. That
is, the translations appeared to preserve some of the essen-
tial differences between cases, and participants were able 5. Condition 2
to understand and use the scale. Second, participants did
not, on average, display a significant distinction in their 5.1. Methods
moral judgments between killing and letting die (i.e., ac-
tion and omission), or between contact and non-contact We tested a population of 30 adult participants (M = 12,
harm. The absence of a significant difference in judgments F = 18, mean age = 42.3 years (SD = 9.54, range 23–62),
of moral severity between killing and letting die is partic- mean years of schooling = 1.83 (SD = 2.21, range 0–6)) with
ularly striking given that a significant number of published no prior experience using scales and reading moral dilem-
papers testing this distinction report an omission bias (Bar- mas. All methods of testing were the same as in Condition
on, 2009; Baron & Ritov, 2004; Cushman et al., 2006, 2008; 1, except where otherwise noted.
Haidt & Baron, 1996; Hauser et al., in press; Ritov & Baron, We presented each subject with four moral dilemmas,
1990; Spranca et al., 1991), including studies using the specifically, two pairs of action–omission cases with the
same general methods (e.g., sequential presentation of sce- order of presentation randomized across participants (see
narios, judgments on a Likert-scale). Moreover, Cushman Appendix A). One pair of cases involved a man in his boat
et al. (2006) found that most participants judging such who could save five drowning swimmers, but either ac-
cases, when asked to justify their responses, had based tively kills one in the process or fails to save one; here,
their decision on consciously available information; in con- there is no intent on the part of the man in the boat to kill
trast, only half of the participants recovered an explicit jus- (by means or side-effect) the one, a difference that may be
tification for the contact vs. non-contact distinction, and important when contrasted with the dilemmas in Condi-
once recovered, typically rejected the distinction as mor- tion 1, and with the second pair of dilemmas used in this
ally relevant. condition. The second pair involved a boulder rolling
There are two possible interpretations for the absence downhill toward five people. If the boulder continues
of a significant difference in the judgments of this particu- down its path, unobstructed, it will kill all five people un-
lar Mayan population for a pair of dilemmas focusing on less a nearby farmer either actively calls out to another
the distinction between killing and letting die: either they person to move in front of the boulder (unaware of its
do not perceive a morally significant difference between presence) or fails to warn the other person who is about
actions and omissions, or there was something unusual to walk in the way of the boulder’s path. In both cases,
about the particular set of dilemmas presented, including the scenarios make clear that the main protagonist (the
potential differences in the translation, as well as the rela- farmer) either intends to call out and cause a person to
tive salience of certain factors, such as the intentions of the walk into the path of danger or intends to remain quiet
protagonist and his knowledge of impending harm. To ad- (when it would be of no cost to call out), thereby allowing
dress these potential factors, we presented a new popula- a person to walk into the path of danger.
L. Abarbanell, M.D. Hauser / Cognition 115 (2010) 207–224 213

5.2. Results dren (Cushman et al., in preparation), and as such,


consisted of shorter sentences and child-appropriate
For the boat cases, paired t-tests showed that there was vocabulary. In a preliminary test of English-speaking, Is-
no statistically significant difference between action raeli born children, a significant number (29 out of 46)
(MACT = 4.03, SE = 0.18) and omission (MOMIT = 4.10, judged the actor in the Vase dilemma as ‘‘more bad” than
SE = 0.16; t(29) = 0.35, p = 0.73, d = 0.08). Similarly, for the the omitter (binomial: p = 0.025; Knafo & Hauser, in prep-
boulder cases, there was no statistically significant differ- aration). While the children viewed power-point slides
ence between action (MACT = 3.30, SE = 0.23) and omission accompanying the dilemmas and were asked to directly
(MOMIT = 3.60, SE = 0.26; t(29) = 0.96, p = 0.34, d = 0.22). compare the actor vs. the omitter rather than using a judg-
ment scale, these results at least demonstrate that the con-
5.3. Discussion tent of the stories was not only understandable to these
young children, but also, sufficient to trigger an omission
Replicating the pattern obtained in Condition 1, we bias. Thus, if the absence of a perceived moral difference
again find that this Mayan population does not show a sig- between actions and omissions was due to the complexity
nificant difference in their moral judgments between ac- of the dilemmas, then this simpler case should make the
tion and omission in the context of harm. Combining the distinction more transparent, and hopefully, more mean-
results from Conditions 1 and 2, we find that for three dif- ingful with respect to the moral difference between actions
ferent dilemmas targeting the distinction between actions and omissions.
and omissions, this Mayan population shows no evidence The second pair of cases (‘‘Pond”, see Appendix A) had
of an omission bias. This consistency reduces the possibil- yielded a very robust omission bias among an adult, inter-
ity that participants simply did not understand these par- net sample (Cohen’s d = 0.84). As the cases were all either
ticular dilemmas but understood the means-side-effect action or omission, we used a pseudo-randomized design
case. Further, given that participants generated different to allow for the greatest mix, with consecutive dilemmas
overall permissibility scores for the different dilemmas alternating between the two cases (i.e., Vase–Pond–Vase–
(ranging from a mean of 1.90–4.10), they are at least able Pond or Pond–Vase–Pond–Vase) and staggered for action
to use different parts of the scale. The absence of a statisti- and omission (i.e., omit–act–act–omit or act–omit–omit–
cally significant difference across three dilemma pairs is act). If the absence of a moral distinction between actions
therefore consistent with the conclusion that this particu- and omissions is due to culture-specific factors, then nei-
lar Mayan population does not perceive a moral difference ther the simplicity nor the robustness of the cases when
between actions and omissions. presented to a more industrialized population will have
an effect on our Mayan participants.
Second, to test whether the means-side-effect distinc-
6. Condition 3 tion was robust, we presented another pair of moral dilem-
mas to 30 adults (M = 8, F = 22; mean age = 46.00 years
The goal of Condition 3 was to further test the robust- (SD = 15.67, range 22–83); mean years of schooling = 2.23
ness of the means-side-effect distinction, and to test an (SD = 2.75, range 0–9)), 13 of whom had participated in
additional set of action–omission cases, with one simpli- one prior condition (between approximately 5 and
fied pair previously presented to young (4–6 year old) 15 months prior). This pair of dilemmas (‘‘Peccaries”, see
children who judged the action as worse than the omission Appendix A) captured the distinction between harm
(Cushman, Young, & Hauser, in preparation; Knafo & caused as a means to a greater good and harm caused as
Hauser, in preparation), and a second pair, designed for a side-effect, but differed in content from the dilemmas
adults, that had previously yielded a highly robust differ- presented in Condition 1. Specifically, a woman is carrying
ence between action and omission judgments on the Moral a baby while picking fruit atop a tree when she sees a herd
Sense Test. More generally, the goal of this condition was of peccaries stampeding towards her five other babies be-
to assess, by presenting new scenarios, whether this low. To save the five babies, she can either throw the baby
Mayan population is sensitive to some distinctions irre- she is carrying down to scare the peccaries away, thus kill-
spective of context (e.g., means vs. side-effects), but not ing the one baby but saving the five (means), or she can
others (e.g., actions vs. omissions). rush down herself, dropping the baby she is carrying as a
result (side-effect). The order of the dilemmas was coun-
6.1. Methods terbalanced across participants.

We ran Condition 3 using the same methods as for Con- 6.2. Results
ditions 1 and 2 with the following exceptions. First, we
presented 31 adults (M = 12, F = 19, mean age = 49.10 - For the two pairs of action–omission dilemmas, paired
years (SD = 14.85, range 31–80), mean years of school- t-tests showed that there was no difference in judgments
ing = 2.87 (SD = 3.65, range 0–9)) with the two new pairs for either the vase case (MACT = 1.87, SE = 0.20 vs. MO-
of dilemmas targeting the action–omission distinction MIT = 1.94, SE = 0.20; t(30) = 0.28, p = 0.78, d = 0.06) or for
(see Appendix A); three of our subjects had participated the pond case (MACT = 2.87, SE = 0.28 vs. MOMIT = 3.06,
in one prior condition approximately 9 months prior. One SE = 0.26; t(30) = 0.66, p = 0.52, d = 0.13).
dilemma pair (‘‘Vase”, see Appendix A) was, as noted, spe- For the pair of means-side-effect dilemmas, we ran a re-
cifically designed for 4–6 year old English speaking chil- peated measures ANOVA with prior participation and di-
214 L. Abarbanell, M.D. Hauser / Cognition 115 (2010) 207–224

lemma order as between-subjects factors and the means- Condition 2. We ran the non-moral pair because of work
side-effect contrast as a within-subjects factor. As in Con- showing that moral attributions can affect, downstream,
dition 1, participants, on average, judged the means-based causal attributions, including especially, cases involving
harm as more forbidden (MMEANS = 2.67, SE = 0.27) than the the doing/allowing distinction (Cushman et al., 2008).
side-effect (MSIDE-EFFECT = 3.44, SE = 0.30; F(1, 26) = 10.79,
p = 0.003, g2p ¼ 0:29). There were no main effects or inter- 7.1. Methods
actions for the order of the dilemmas or for prior participa-
tion (p’s > 0.16). All testing procedures were the same as Conditions 1–3,
except that in the first dilemma pair we asked participants
6.3. Discussion for their causal attributions regarding a non-moral case,
and in the second dilemma pair we presented a moral case
Condition 3 provides further evidence that this Mayan and asked for both their permissibility judgment (using the
population does not perceive a moral difference between same scale as in Conditions 1–3) as well as their causal
actions and omissions, while perceiving a difference be- judgment. For our causal analysis, participants judged on
tween means and side-effects. The absence of an omission a 5-point scale how much of a role the protagonist played
bias here is even less likely than in the previous cases to be in bringing about the consequences of the event, with
due to the complexity of the dilemmas: even when pre- 1 = none at all (e.g., ma ba swenta te Juan3), and 5 = very
sented with a dilemma that among children triggered an much (bayel swenta te Juan).
omission bias, no difference emerged among our adult Ma- In the non-moral dilemma (see Appendix A), a man
yan sample; we draw this conclusion somewhat conserva- finds a banana tree that has fallen into a pond. The man
tively, however, given that the children were aided by can either remove (act) a very buoyant branch to allow
illustrations, a methodological difference that could facili- the tree to sink and thereby eliminate bugs from the area,
tate the perception of a moral difference. or can refrain (omit) from cutting a rotten branch that is
Adding the results of Condition 3 to those obtained in filling with water, thereby resulting in the tree sinking.
Conditions 1 and 2, we find that this Mayan population We tested 29 adult participants (M = 7, F = 22, mean
generates similar moral judgments for actions and omis- age = 44.10 years (SD = 10.86, range 24–64), mean years
sions, across five different moral dilemmas, while generat- of schooling = 1.86 (SD = 2.56, range 0–9)) from the same
ing different judgments for means-based harms as parajes as the previous conditions. Twelve of the partici-
opposed to side-effects for two different dilemmas. The pants had participated in one prior condition and one
remaining two conditions explore an initial explanation had participated in two prior conditions (between approx-
for why this Mayan population might not exhibit an omis- imately 1 and 17 months prior). The order of the dilemmas
sion bias, and the factors that might contribute to express- was counterbalanced across participants.
ing such a bias. The moral dilemma was the same ‘‘boulder” scenario
used in Condition 2. To avoid retesting participants from
previous conditions, we tested 31 adults in the next near-
7. Condition 4 est paraje, Pajaltón, none of whom had participated in a
prior condition (M = 12, F = 19, mean age = 38.97 years
Both philosophical work (Bennett, 1995; Hart & Honore, (SD = 13.52, range 22–72), mean years of schooling = 3.90
1959) as well as recent empirical investigations (Alicke, (SD = 2.99, range 0–12)). As described in the introduction,
2000; Cushman et al., in preparation; Haidt & Baron, Pajaltón is similar in demographic characteristics and so-
1996; Spranca et al., 1991) suggest that the perceived dif- cial structure to the Cañada Chica and Cañada Grande
ference between actions and omissions may derive from where the previous samples were primarily drawn. Both
differences in our attribution of causal responsibility to dilemma order (act–omit vs. omit–act) and question order
agents. In particular, agents appear more causally respon- (causal–moral vs. moral–causal) were counterbalanced
sible for their actions than for their omissions. If, for some across participants.
reason, there are cross-cultural differences in the percep-
tion or attribution of causal responsibility, and this Mayan 7.2. Results
population is either less sensitive to the underlying causal
factors in an event, or conversely attributes more causal For dilemma 1, the non-moral case, a repeated measures
responsibility to agents for their omissions than partici- ANOVA with the contrast between action and omission
pants from more industrialized societies, then the differ- judgments as a within-subjects factor and dilemma order
ence between actions and omissions might be rendered and prior participation as between-subjects factors showed
opaque. To test this possibility, we presented two action– that participants overall judged the protagonist in the action
omission dilemma pairs. One pair, which involved a non- case as more causally responsible for the banana tree sinking
moral situation, had previously yielded a high effect size (MACT = 4.18, SE = 0.18) than in the omission case (MO-
among an internet sample, readily triggering a perceived 2
MIT = 2.92, SE = 0.31; F(1, 25) = 13.61, p = 0.001, gp ¼ 0:35).
difference in causal responsibility (Cushman, 2008b). In
particular, among this sample, participants judged the act- 3
Swenta most closely glosses as ‘with respect to’ or ‘concerning’ but,
ing agent as more causally responsible for the consequence according to our consultants, implies causality in this context. We chose
than the omitting agent. The second pair, which involved a this as opposed to the more direct smul (‘fault’ or ‘sin’), since the latter
moral situation, was the same ‘‘Boulder” case presented in implies a negative judgment.
L. Abarbanell, M.D. Hauser / Cognition 115 (2010) 207–224 215

This difference, however, depended upon dilemma order responsibility between action and omission for both moral
(F(1, 25) = 4.25, p = 0.05, g2p ¼ 0:15): participants who re- and non-moral dilemmas. For the moral dilemma, how-
ceived the action dilemma first, judged the protagonist in ever, they did not perceive a corresponding difference in
the omission case as significantly less responsible moral permissibility; of potential relevance here is the fact
(mean = 2.33, SE = 0.41) than in the action case that participants’ causal judgments for both actions and
(mean = 4.27, SE = 0.25; F(1, 14) = 14.83, p = .002, omissions were quite high for the moral case, which may
g2p ¼ 0:51), while those who received the omission dilemma have resulted in a similar level of moral reprehension for
first did not (omit (mean = 3.36, SE = 0.43) vs. act both action and omission. While omission judgments in
(mean = 4.07, SE = 0.27); F(1, 13) = 2.66, p = 0.13, particular appeared to be sensitive to dilemma and ques-
g2p ¼ 0:17). In other words, receiving the action dilemma tion order, this did not, on the whole, affect the relative dif-
first appeared to temper participants’ judgments regarding ference or lack thereof between action and omission for
causal responsibility in the omission case. There was no main either the causal or moral judgments for this moral case.
effect of order and no effects of prior participation (p’s > 0.15). When a person acts and a consequence ensues, we are
For the moral dilemma, the difference in the scales be- much more likely to perceive the causal connection be-
tween the moral and causal questions prevented us from tween the act and the consequence than when a person
directly comparing the two. We therefore ran separate AN- omits an action and a consequence ensues. Our common
OVAS for each question type, with the contrast between sense experience should make this clear. After all, we are
action–omission judgments as a within-subjects factor constantly omitting actions, and there are consequences
and dilemma order and question order as between-sub- that arise, but we are clearly not responsible for all, or even
jects factors. For the causal judgment, participants on aver- a fraction of these consequences. Consistent with previous
age judged the protagonist in the action case as more philosophical and empirical work, this Mayan population,
causally responsible for the consequence (MACT = 4.65, on the whole, judged acting agents as more causally
SE = 0.11) than in the omission case (MOMIT = 4.11, responsible for the consequences of an event than omitting
SE = 0.21; F(1, 27) = 5.97, p = 0.02, g2p ¼ 0:18). Participants agents (Baron, 1994; Cushman et al., 2006; Haidt & Baron,
who received the omission dilemma first tended to use a 1996; Hart & Honore, 1959; Ritov & Baron, 1990; Spranca
higher end of the scale overall (mean = 4.69, SE = 0.17) et al., 1991), and this attribution held for both a moral
than participants who received the action dilemma first and non-moral dilemma. The difference in causal responsi-
(mean = 4.08, SE = 0.18; F(1, 27) = 5.99, p = 0.02, bility for actions and omissions appeared greater in the
g2p ¼ 0:18); however, the relative difference between ac- non-moral than moral case although it showed some sen-
tion and omission judgments did not vary by dilemma or- sitivity to order effects; further, for the moral case, partic-
der (F(1, 27) = 0.15, p = 0.70). ipants tended to see the protagonist as causally
In contrast, participants on average perceived no differ- responsible for the outcome in both action and omission
ence in moral permissibility between the action (i.e., means above 4), though more so in the action case.
(MACT = 2.45, SE = 0.26) and omission cases (MOMIT = 2.55, However, because we only presented one dilemma each,
SE = 0.23; F(1, 27) = 0.09, p = 0.77, g2p ¼ 0:003). There was we cannot attribute this difference to moral context as op-
a two-way interaction between the action–omission con- posed to details of the dilemma. We conclude that this Ma-
trast and dilemma order (F(1, 27) = 5.11, p = 0.03, yan population perceives a distinction in causal
g2p ¼ 0:16) and a three-way interaction between the con- responsibility for actions and omissions in the absence of
trast, dilemma order, and question order (F(1, 27) = 9.28, seeing a moral difference.
p = 0.005 g2p ¼ 0:26). In general, participants who received
the omission dilemma first judged the omission to be more
permissible (mean = 3.19, SE = 0.35) than those who re- 8. Condition 5. Contrasting two different Mayan groups
ceived the action dilemma first (mean = 1.87, SE = 0.37,
F(1, 29) = 6.73, p = 0.02, g2p ¼ 0:19. However, post hoc anal- In the introduction, we set up the design of these exper-
yses of the three-way interaction revealed that this differ- iments by pointing to the frequent, though certainly not
ence held only among those participants who received the ubiquitous finding that people judge means-based harms
moral question before the causal question (F(1, 14) = 13.76, as worse than side-effects, and actions as worse than omis-
p = 0.002, g2p ¼ 0:50). Those participants who received both sions. We further stated that our studies with this Mayan
the moral question and the omission dilemma first judged population implemented design features used in our inter-
the omission to be more permissible (mean = 4.13, net studies, including similar dilemmas, scales, and pre-
SE = 0.35) than the action (mean = 2.00, SE = 0.38; sentation mode (i.e., one vignette at a time as opposed to
F(1, 7) = 17.00, p = 0.004, g2p ¼ 0:71). The rest of the ques- paired dilemmas presented simultaneously). Though these
tion and dilemma order pairings showed no difference be- are important similarities, there are also potentially signif-
tween action and omission judgments, and no differences icant differences. For example, the internet sample judged
from one another for either the action or omission judg- dilemmas that differed in terms of specific content and
ments (all p’s > 0.14). precise wording (but not in terms of more general features
of the dilemma such as harms caused and lives saved, and
7.3. Discussion ongoing vs. introduced threats), using a different scale
(e.g., permissibility scale from 1 to 7), tested alone (as op-
Results from Condition 4 show that participants per- posed to being in the presence of an experimenter). To be-
ceived a statistically significant difference in causal gin addressing some of these differences, we carried out a
216 L. Abarbanell, M.D. Hauser / Cognition 115 (2010) 207–224

within-population comparison of a group of adult Mayans Any of these factors could be associated with the difference
that was, on average, more educated and less rural. We in action–omission judgments between the two groups,
presented this population with a sample of the same either instead of or in addition to a more general (and less
dilemmas, in Tseltal, as our more rural and less educated measurable) difference in cultural norms.
Mayan population, and used the same scale.
We presented two pairs of dilemmas to this less rural, 9. Overall analysis
more educated sample of 30 adult Mayans, two of whom
had participated in a prior condition (M = 7, F = 23, mean Though work on the internet (Banerjee, Huebner, & Haus-
age = 23.23 years (SD = 6.31, range 17–39), mean years of er, in press; Cushman et al., 2006; Hauser et al., 2007, in
schooling = 8.83 (SD = 1.21, range 6–12 years)). This sam- press) has failed to reveal a consistently significant effect
ple had, on average, more contact with the municipal cen- of demographic factors on moral judgment, given the differ-
ter than our previous samples, which as noted in the ence in both context and variation we decided to explore
introduction is more urbanized and has more contact with these factors here, carrying out an overall analysis. Specifi-
the non-indigenous, ladino population than the outlying cally, we regressed all major background characteristics
parajes. Ten of the participants resided in the municipal across the difference between action and omission judg-
center, and almost all would have traveled daily to the cen- ments for all action–omission cases presented to our Mayan
ter to attend secondary or preparatory school (equivalent population. The limitation of this analysis is that it pools
to middle and high school). It is also, on average, younger across dilemmas varying in content, as well as in the severity
than the previous sample – something that is difficult to with which participants’ judged the protagonist’s decision
avoid given the changing rates of educational attainment to act or omit an action. The advantage of this analysis is that
in the municipality. takes account of all of our cases, and allows us to look at the
While this sample is at once younger, more educated and contribution of different demographic factors such as age
more urban than the other samples tested, the demograph- and education.
ics of the region and the dynamics of community develop- Our regression analysis combined all of the action–
ment make this type of correlation difficult to avoid. Until omission dilemma pairs across all conditions, with the
fairly recently, most individuals did not have access to exception of Condition 4 since it included a causal as well
school beyond the 6th grade. Even today, the majority of as a moral question. For conditions in which participants
parajes do not have a secondary school (7–9th grade) and received two action–omission pairs (‘‘Boat” and ‘‘Boulder”
there are currently only two high schools for the entire in Condition 2, and ‘‘Vase” and ‘‘Pond” in Condition 3),
municipality (10–12th grade). Our purpose, however, was we included both and treated them as between-subjects
not to tease apart the individual contributions of these fac- data for a total of 182 cases. For each case, we created a dif-
tors, but rather to provide an initial contrast with our target ference score by subtracting the action from the omission
Mayan population, matched for dilemmas, testing condi- judgment; higher (positive) scores indicate cases where ac-
tions, language, and general geographic region and ethnic tions are judged more severely than omissions. This differ-
identification. Specifically, we presented the contrast be- ence served as the dependent variable in the regression
tween means and side-effect for the ‘‘Truck” case from Con- analysis. Independent variables consisted of two sets of
dition 1, and the contrast between action and omission for dummies controlling for condition and scenario, and covar-
the ”Boulder” case presented in Conditions 2 and 4. The or- iates of sex, age, years of schooling, and whether the partic-
der of the dilemmas was randomized across participants; ipant currently resided in the municipal center or in one of
these cases were selected because the first showed a strong the outlying parajes. Repetition of participants was not in-
side-effect bias, and the second consistently, across two con- cluded as only 8 of the 182 cases had prior participation.
ditions, showed no omission bias, while revealing a differ- A stepwise linear regression retained the dummy vari-
ence in causality. able controlling for the more educated, more urban condi-
This population of less rural, and more educated Ma- tion (from Condition 5) as the only significant predictor of
yans judged the means-based harm as worse the difference score ((b = 0.78, t = 2.88, p = 0.005). That is,
(MMEANS = 2.30, SE = 0.20) than the side-effect harm the average difference between action and omission judg-
(MSIDE-EFFECT = 2.83, SE = 0.26; paired t(29) = 2.01, ments was 0.78 points higher for the more educated, more
p = 0.054, d = 0.42) for the truck dilemmas. They also urban group (mean difference = 0.90, SE = 0.26) than for all
judged the action (MACT = 1.97, SE = 0.22) as worse than of the other conditions combined (mean difference = 0.125,
the omission (MOMIT = 2.87, SE = 0.27; paired t(29) = 3.53, SE = 0.11; see Fig. 1). All other predictors were not
p = 0.001, d = 0.67) for the boulder dilemmas. statistically significant (p’s > 0.43) and were removed
from the final regression model (Diff(Omit-Act) = 0.13 +
8.1. Discussion 0.78  (Condition 5 dummy) + e). Although most of the var-
iation in the difference score was not explained by this
While both Mayan groups perceived a significant, moral model (R2 = 0.04), the overall ANOVA confirmed that the
difference between means and side-effects, only the more model was significant (F(1, 181) = 8.28, p = 0.005).
educated sample perceived a significant moral difference
between action and omission for a case that yielded no dif- 9.1. Discussion
ference among the less educated group. These two Mayan
groups differed, however, in several respects, including This multivariate analysis yielded two relevant findings.
age, education, and exposure to an urban environment. First, it showed that the responses from the less rural and
L. Abarbanell, M.D. Hauser / Cognition 115 (2010) 207–224 217

Fig. 1. Means and standard errors of the difference score (omission–action) for the less educated/more rural and more educated/less rural comparison
groups from the regression analysis comparing all of the action–omission cases (N = 182).

more educated Mayans (see Condition 5) differed from the scales that accompanied them, and perceived a distinction
rest of the conditions on the critical action–omission con- between means-based harms and side-effects. This signifi-
trast, showing a statistically significant interaction be- cant difference not only aligned well with our internet
tween the action–omission contrast and group. sample in which subjects consistently judged means-based
Specifically, the difference between action and omission harms as worse than side-effects (Cushman et al., 2006;
judgments differed by almost a full point between our Hauser et al., 2007), but also showed that the translations
two comparison groups, a fairly impressive difference gi- were sufficiently accurate to capture this difference. In a
ven a 5-point scale. Second, we found no effects of any of follow up condition, using a different dilemma, partici-
the other background factors across all conditions. These pants again showed that they perceived a moral difference
results held even when rerunning the analysis without between harms caused as a means to a greater good and
controlling for condition or scenario, thus avoiding any po- harms caused as a side-effect, suggesting that the means-
tential collinearity with condition (p’s > 0.13). side-effect distinction is independent of the particular con-
tent of the scenario explored, although the particular struc-
10. General discussion ture of each dilemma may influence the strength of the
effect.
The goal of these studies was, at a general level, to build In contrast to the evidence for a side-effect bias in this
on recent developments in experimental cultural psychol- Mayan population, we did not find evidence for an omission
ogy (Atran et al., 2001; Haidt, Koller, & Dias, 1993; Hauser bias across five different pairs of dilemmas [including one
et al., 2007; Henrich et al., 2005, 2006; O’Neill and Petrino- developed for young children], and nor did we find evi-
vich, 1998; Sugiyama, Tooby, & Cosmides, 2002), designed dence for a distinction between harm caused by contact
to complement existing ethnographies of small-scale soci- and harm caused by non-contact (one dilemma). The fact
eties by examining more systematically their underlying that these distinctions did not trigger a morally salient con-
psychology. More specifically, our goal was to extend exist- trast is unexpected when placed in the context of other
ing empirical work on the nature of moral intuitions that, published studies with comparable methods (including
up to the present, has largely focused on Western, industri- scenario content, sequential presentation of dilemmas,
alized populations (for exceptions, see Haidt et al., 1993; and judgment scale). That is, a significant number of studies
O’Neill and Petrinovich, 1998). have provided evidence of an omission bias, as well as evi-
The design of our study mirrored, as much as possible, dence for the importance of physical contact (Cushman
studies carried out on the internet using the Moral Sense et al., 2006; Greene et al., 2001, 2009; Huebner et al., in
Test as this provided the largest baseline sample, robust re- press; Baron & Ritov, 2004); for exceptions to the omission
sults, and well tested dilemmas presented sequentially. As bias, see (Connolly & Reb, 2003; Mandel & Vartanian, 2007;
a first attempt in this line of research, we sought to assess Tanner & Medin, 2004). If we consider the conditions pre-
whether people living in a small-scale, largely unschooled, sented here, along with those presented in both Cushman
agrarian society would understand our adaptations of et al. (2006) and Hauser et al. (in press) – the most appro-
these artificial moral dilemmas and perceive some of the priate studies for comparison as they used comparable
critical, targeted distinctions. dilemmas and presentation methods (i.e., sequential pre-
sentations, Likert-scale responses, carefully controlled and
10.1. Summary of results matched hypothetical cases), we find that 11 out of 11 pairs
of act-omission dilemmas revealed an omission bias,
Results from our first condition suggested that the Ma- whereas 0 out of the 5 cases (and one replication) presented
yan participants comprehended the dilemmas and the to the target Mayan population showed an omission bias
218 L. Abarbanell, M.D. Hauser / Cognition 115 (2010) 207–224

Table 2
A comparison of omission biases across studies.

N Scale (points) Omission bias? Mean diff. (omit–act) SD t Effect size (d) p-Level (2-tailed)
Cushman et al. (2006)
Boxcar 332 7 Yes 0.70 2.03 6.32 0.34 <0.001
Pond 332 7 Yes 1.69 2.00 15.34 0.84 <0.001
Ship 332 7 Yes 0.83 2.01 7.56 0.41 <0.001
Car 332 7 Yes 0.90 1.77 9.26 0.50 <0.001
Boat 332 7 Yes 0.98 1.98 8.97 0.49 <0.001
Switch 332 7 Yes 0.26 1.87 2.56 0.13 0.011

Hauser et al. (in press)


Boxcar 404 7 Yes 0.55 1.53 7.12 0.71 <0.001
Pond 404 7 Yes 1.29 1.80 14.43 1.45 <0.001
Car 404 7 Yes 0.75 1.71 10.43 1.05 <0.001
Boat 404 7 Yes 0.29 1.52 8.74 0.88 <0.001
Switch 404 7 Yes 0.55 1.53 2.62 0.26 <0.001

Target Mayan population


Condition 1
Truck 30 5 No 0.00 0.91 0.00 0.00 1.00
Condition 2
Boat 30 5 No 0.07 1.05 0.35 0.08 0.73
Boulder 30 5 No 0.30 1.71 0.96 0.22 0.34
Condition 3
Vase 31 5 No 0.07 1.26 0.28 0.06 0.78
Pond 31 5 No 0.19 1.64 0.66 0.13 0.52
Condition 4
Boulder 31 5 No 0.10 2.12 0.25 0.07 0.80

Educated Mayan population


Condition 5
Boulder 30 5 Yes 0.90 1.40 3.53 0.67 0.001

(see Table 2); for one of the cases given to this Mayan pop- the patterns presented, and specifically, an attempt to ex-
ulation (i.e., ‘‘Vase”), young Israeli children perceived an plain why this Mayan population, and perhaps other
omission bias (Knapfo & Hauser, unpublished data). Fur- small-scale societies, may not perceive a moral difference
ther, the less rural and more educated Mayan sample between actions and omissions, at least under the condi-
showed an omission bias using the same methods. tions tested.
Though the consistency of the patterns among the At least four factors are unlikely to have contributed to
internet and Mayan sample are suggestive, they are hin- the absence of an omission bias among the target Mayan
dered by several critical differences that place limitations population. First, it seems unlikely that there are linguistic
on our conclusions regarding cross-cultural differences. complexities associated with translations of actions and
In particular, all of the internet studies had large sample omissions, but not means and side-effects. Expressing
sizes, with hundreds of subjects responding to the moral negation in Tseltal (i.e., that the protagonist did not act)
dilemmas. In contrast, all of the Mayan studies had sample is straightforward and unambiguous. Moreover, neither
sizes between 29 and 31. Further, the internet populations the Mayan participants nor the translator expressed any
were far more heterogeneous than the Mayan populations, particular difficulty with the action–omission cases as op-
with a much greater range of ages, educational and reli- posed to the means-side-effect cases. Further, for the
gious backgrounds, and experience with moral philosophy. ‘‘Boulder” dilemmas, though subjects did not report a mor-
Given that some of the internet studies yielded statistically al difference between the action and omission cases, they
significant effects for the target distinctions, but some- did report a causal difference, again arguing that the key
times with small effect sizes (see Table 2), it is possible distinction between action and omission was understood
that studies of small-scale societies are, by definition, hin- by the participants and therefore translated appropriately.
dered by the limited sample sizes. That said, the samples Second, the absence of a perceived moral distinction be-
sizes used here were sufficient to detect statistically signif- tween actions and omissions is unlikely to be mediated by
icant effects with the target Mayan population for two an inability to understand the dilemmas or to understand
means-side-effect dilemmas and two scenarios exploring and use the full dimensionality of the scale. Both within
differences in causal responsibility, as well as a difference and across conditions, participants responded appropri-
among the educated Mayan population for one means- ately, with mean responses varying with the particular di-
side-effect case and one act-omission case. lemma presented. In particular, some action–omission
The results presented in this paper represent only a first pairs were judged more harshly overall than others, even
step in the study of moral decision-making in small-scale though participants appeared to perceive no moral differ-
societies. We turn next to a more detailed discussion of ence between actions and omissions.
L. Abarbanell, M.D. Hauser / Cognition 115 (2010) 207–224 219

Third, the absence of an omission bias was not due to oed by Medina Hernandez (1991), who notes in his ethnog-
cross-cutting effects related to causal attributions. In partic- raphy of Tenejapa that the family socializes the individual to
ular, though the target Mayan population did not express an participate in the wider institutions of Tenejapan society
omission bias, they judged agents engaging in an action as whose structure and division of labor it mirrors.
more causally responsible for the harm than agents engaged Gossip within these tight-knit communities is a favorite
in an omission; and they showed this difference in causal activity as well as a means of enforcing social norms,
attributions for one of the same cases in which they did including the need to fulfill family and community obliga-
not show a difference in moral judgments (although they tions, such as being a good worker, providing for one’s fam-
did assign a high level of causal responsibility to both the ac- ily, and maintaining an orderly household (cf. Haviland,
tor and the omitter in this moral case). This pattern of assign- 1977, for an analysis of gossip in Zinacantan). Personal
ing greater causal responsibility to actions over omissions is and family histories are public knowledge and are often in-
consistent with several other studies (Cushman et al., 2006; voked retrospectively to account for conflict, illness or
Ritov & Baron, 1990; Spranca et al., 1991). harm. For example, Collier (1973), in her ethnographic
Fourth, the failure to treat actions as worse than omis- study of conflict in Zinacantan, found that conflicts were
sions is not due to an explicit law or religious doctrine, generally complex affairs, rooted in the interpersonal
such as the Good Samaritan Law, that is explicit in coun- dynamics of a small, closed community. The goal of the
tries like France and Quebec. In such countries, the failure judge or mediator in such cases was not simply to deter-
to help someone in harm’s way is a moral transgression, on mine the appropriate punishment, but to uncover and ad-
a par with actively harming someone. In our review of the dress the underlying causes of a conflict, to ‘‘end the anger
relevant ethnographic literature, in addition to interviews in (people’s) heart” so that both parties might resume their
with local judges and community members of this Mayan responsibilities and obligations toward their community
population, we found no evidence that would imply the and one another (Collier, 1973, p. 101). It is possible, there-
operation of an explicit law or social norm equivalent to fore, that our Mayan subjects were evaluating the actions
the Good Samaritan Law. This does not, of course, rule of the protagonists in the dilemmas within the context of
out the possibility that an implicit norm has been internal- a wider social network or explanatory framework, and gi-
ized among this population. ven the emphasis on obligations, might very well code
While we can only speculate, there are several charac- inaction as a kind of action, thereby reducing the moral dif-
teristics of the rural Mayan population we tested that, ta- ference between actions and omissions.
ken singularly or together, may provide enough of an This framework may be underwritten by a belief in a
impetus to eliminate the moral distinction between ac- moral universe where harm eventually begets retaliatory
tions and omissions resulting in harm, or possibly, to make harm. Victims may inflict harm on their perpetrators either
other distinctions more salient. We turn next to a discus- by directly bargaining with the gods in an act of witchcraft,
sion of some of these characteristics and consider how or indirectly as the wounded soul cries out to the gods for
the quality of interpersonal relationships, causal belief sys- justice (Collier, 1973). Such beliefs have certainly dimin-
tems, and community obligations in this small-scale soci- ished in recent years; however, the accusation that some-
ety may function to minimize the perceived moral one is an ak-chamel, literally giver of sickness, are not
difference between actions and omissions. uncommon, and the services of traditional healers who
specialize in diagnosing and curing such illnesses are still
sometimes sought, often alongside allopathic or Western
10.2. Linking experimental results to Mayan life
remedies (see e.g., Berlin & Berlin, 1996; Granich, Cantwell,
Long, Maldonado, & Parsonnet, 1999). These healers,
As previously noted, daily life among the Maya of Ten-
known as pik’-k’ab in Tseltal (pulseadores or pulse readers),
ejapa is centered within extended family units residing in
question the patient about his or her interpersonal history,
small hamlets, or parajes, many of which have less than
especially any conflicts or misgivings, and then listen to
500 residents (INEGI, 2005). From birth, children are inte-
the patient’s pulse for any signs while reciting specific
grated to be fully participating members of these units. It
names (Villa Rojas, 1990, for detailed descriptions of these
has therefore been argued that Mayan children grow up
interactions [carried out in the 1940s] in Tenejapa). These
in a state of permanent inter-subjectivity where they are
interrogations may reveal a causal chain where even sim-
socialized to be in constant communication and synchroni-
ple offenses, including the omission to act in the expected
zation with those around them (see Leon Pasquel, 2005, for
or appropriate way, may be believed to have resulted in a
an analysis of early childhood socialization in Zinacantan, a
retributional illness. These highly personal beliefs may
nearby Tsotsil Mayan community4). This sentiment is ech-
help bind individuals into a kind of social contract where
4
all parties must try to preserve good will among all, while
Tsotsil is a closely related language to Tseltal. Each language defines a
reinforcing the notion that even intentions, be they real, in-
broad ethnolinguistic group which can be divided into different dialects
with even further cultural and linguistic distinctions between different ferred or imagined, may result in harm.
municipalities where each dialect is spoken. So the Tsotsil Maya of These principles have been framed more positively in
Zinacantan are a different ethnolinguistic group from the Tseltal Maya of more contemporary ethnographies, no doubt influenced
Tenejapa. However, as the two are closely related and reside in the same by indigenous movements for self-determination. For
geographical region, they share many general social, cultural, and linguistic
characteristics. Since there are few ethnographies specific to Tenejapa (in
example, based on his many years of living and working
contrast to Zinacantan which has been extensively studied), we borrow among the Tojolobal, a related Mayan population, Lenkers-
from the different ethnographies of the region where appropriate. dorf (2002) concurred that Mayan justice is recuperative
220 L. Abarbanell, M.D. Hauser / Cognition 115 (2010) 207–224

rather than punitive, with the goal of reintegrating the only support this perspective, but raise the question of
strayed individual into the community and restoring a whether all small-scale societies, regardless of their life-
sense of harmony and balance among all. This principle, styles as hunter-gatherers, subsistence farmers, or people
expressed as jultesbeyel ch’ulel in Tseltal – literally to make from an industrialized nation living in a small rural hamlet,
the soul of the other return – suggests a moral obligation in will judge actions as comparable to omissions with respect
which community members are actively responsible for to moral permissibility, or whether this is something un-
guiding one another towards the common end of achieving ique to the characteristics of this particular Mayan popula-
a good life for all (see Paoli (2003) for a sociolinguistic tion. For example, though the primary measured difference
analysis of this and other Tseltal concepts related to educa- between our two Mayan populations was level of educa-
tional and social values in the community). In light of these tion, it is possible that the less rural population had a wider
principles, the failure of the rural Mayans to express a mor- circle of less close relationships, and perhaps less of a sense
al distinction between actions and omissions becomes a of obligation to others which might show up in court re-
plausible consequence of the social and moral premiums cords. Further exploration of how, cross-culturally, intui-
exacted from community ties. tive judgments of right and wrong track explicit
While these observations do not license definitive con- decisions from courts or other systems of authority are
clusions, together they paint a portrait of a small-scale needed to fully test these ideas.
society characterized by ‘‘personal intimacy, emotional These results also raise questions about the starting-
depth, moral compromise, and social cohesion” (Paoli, state of our moral sense, and the extent to which specific
2003, p. 25), where the well-being of all is dependent on cultural factors can change the nature of our intuitive judg-
maintaining good relations among all, and where there is ments. Given the considerable evidence from philosophical
a special emphasis placed on the mutual obligations and discussion (Kamm, 2007), results from a large population
responsibilities entailed by living in a community. Said of Western industrialized subjects (Cushman et al., 2006;
simply, because of the relatively small-scale of the Tene- Hauser et al., 2007; Mikhail, 2000, 2007), preliminary evi-
japa community, not only do people hold each other dence from young children (Cushman et al., in preparation;
responsible for their obligations, but are vigilant and Knafo & Hauser, in preparation), and the present Mayan re-
responsive to situations in which individuals fail to uphold sults, it appears that the side-effect bias is relatively robust
their obligations by omitting particular actions. across cultural variation in age, sex, religious background,
Haidt and Baron (1996), using scenarios similar to the education, and size of community. In contrast, the omis-
ones we used here, found that manipulating social dimen- sion bias appears to be more open to contextual and cul-
sions such as the proximity between characters, affected tural variation. The fact that Mayan adults from our
participants’ moral judgments regarding actions and omis- target rural population did not express a moral distinction
sions. For example, while US college students judged between actions and omissions suggests that something
harmful actions to be worse than harmful omissions, this about this particular Mayan culture, or perhaps small-scale
difference diminished when the omission resulted in harm societies more generally, is causally relevant. At this point,
to a close friend or kin as opposed to a stranger. That is, the we are not able to pinpoint the precise cause of this differ-
failure to prevent harm (an omission) from occurring to a ence, but at least two testable alternatives are possible.
close relation was judged similarly to committing a harm- First, given that young children perceive a distinction be-
ful act. Further, in a study by Miller et al. (1990), results tween actions and omissions, it is possible that this repre-
showed that subjects from the city of Mysore, India were sents the starting-state for all children; that is, once the
more likely than Americans subjects from New Haven, relevant capacity to link cause and effect kicks in, all chil-
Connecticut to judge hypothetical scenarios involving the dren perceive actions as worse than omissions. Soon there-
omission of help as a moral wrong, regardless of the sever- after, certain kinds of culturally-relevant experiences may
ity of the consequences and the nature of the relationship eliminate or lessen this distinction. Second, there may be
between participants; Americans tended to view most of no universally instantiated starting-state. Instead, cultural
these cases in terms of personal choice. experiences may, early in development, either support or
Together, these studies reveal a role for cultural experi- eliminate a moral difference between actions and
ence, and support the possibility that in a small-scale soci- omissions.
ety such as the Mayans of Tenejapa, the highly intertwined We consider the results presented here as a starting
nature of social relationships and their associated obliga- point for further experimental research and discussion of
tions may have reduced the perceived moral distinction which morally relevant psychological distinctions are uni-
between actions and omissions. As noted in Collier’s versal, which open to cross-cultural variation, and how
(1973) anthropological study of conflict and law in Zina- experience and development can create distinct moral sig-
cantan, observations suggested that intentions and mo- natures (Haidt, 2007; Hauser, 2006a; Kohlberg, 1981; Turi-
tives, often inferred from complex histories of past el, 1983). Ultimately, this research may suggest that some
relationships, were more important than actions in assign- psychological distinctions are moral absolutes, true
ing blame and determining harm. (descriptively) in all cultures, whereas others may be more
The pattern presented in this paper is also consistent plastic, relative to a culture’s social dynamics, mating
with the empirical work and theoretical considerations behavior, and belief systems. We leave for future discus-
presented by Haidt and Baron (1996), who have argued sion how a project on descriptive moral relativism con-
that the distinction between actions and omissions is sen- nects with prescriptive moral relativism, and in
sitive to social distance. The results presented here not particular, how it might connect to metaethical concerns
L. Abarbanell, M.D. Hauser / Cognition 115 (2010) 207–224 221

that target the question of whether there are moral truths man will not die, but the truck will continue towards the
that hold universally. five men. Thus the five men will die. Thus for this reason,
the man shouts, ‘‘Come here!” – he calls the other man over.
Thus, the other man walks into the middle of the road.
Acknowledgments
Thus, the five men are saved and the one man dies.”
Omission, letting die [truck] = ‘‘A man is sitting at the side
For help with selecting some of the dilemmas, and for
of the road. He sees a truck coming very fast. It is headed
providing unpublished data, we thank Fiery Cushman. For
straight towards five men. The five men do not hear or
help with some of the statistical analyses, we thank Ansgar
see that the truck is coming. If no one realizes that it is
Endress. For comments on earlier drafts of the manuscript,
coming, the five men will die by being run over by the
we thank Jonathan Baron, Penny Brown, Jane Collier, Ben
truck. On the other side of the road there is another man
Fraser, Jonathan Haidt, Bryce Huebner, Richard Nisbett,
starting to walk onto the road. If he walks into the middle
and three anonymous reviewers for Cognition. Funding
of the road, he will die by being run over by the truck. But
for this project was provided to MDH by an NSF-HSD grant,
thus, he will block/stop the truck so that it will not con-
and from grants by J. Epstein and S. Shuman. Funding to LA
tinue toward the five men. Thus, the five men will be
was provided by a Foreign Language and Area Studies Fel-
saved. If the man sitting at the side of the road shouts,
lowship from the US Dept. of Education and a Harvard Uni-
‘‘Watch out!” to the man starting to walk onto the road –
versity Traveling Fellowship. Special thanks to the
if he warns the other man – the other man will remain
community of Tenejapa, and especially to Antonieta Lopez
standing. He will not walk onto the road. Thus, he will
Santiz and family for her assistance in translating and run-
not die. But thus, the truck will continue towards the five
ning the studies.
men. Thus the five men will die. If the man sitting at the
side of the road does not shout – if he does not warn the
Appendix A. Dilemmas used with the Mayan other man – the other man will walk into the middle of
population, back-translated into English from Tseltal the road. Thus, he will die by being run over by the truck.
But thus, the five men will not die. Thus for this reason, the
A.1. Condition 1 man does not shout – he does not warn the other man.
Thus the other man walks into the middle of the road.
Side-effect killing [truck] = ‘‘A man is sitting at the side of Thus, the five men are saved and the one man dies.”
the road. He sees a truck coming very fast. It is headed Means-contact killing [truck] = ‘‘A man is sitting at the
straight towards five men. The five men do not hear or side of the road. He sees a truck coming very fast. It is
see that the truck is coming. If no one realizes that it is headed straight towards five men. The five men do not
coming, the five men will die by being run over by the hear or see that the truck is coming. If no one realizes that
truck. On the other side of the road there is another man it is coming, the five men will die by being run over by the
sitting beside his house. If the first man who is standing truck. There is another man standing beside the man sit-
at the side of the road shouts, ‘‘Watch out!” to the driver ting at the side of the road. If the man who is sitting at
of the truck, the driver will swerve the truck away from the side of the road pushes the other man into the middle
the five men so they will not die, but towards the one of the road, the other man will die by being run over by the
man sitting beside his house. Thus, the man sitting beside truck. But thus, he will block/stop the truck so that it will
his house will die by being run over by the truck. If the man not continue toward the five men. Thus, the five men will
sitting at the side of the road does not speak – if he does be saved. If the man sitting at the side of the road does not
not warn the driver – the truck will continue straight to- push the other man into the middle of the road, the other
wards the five men. Thus the five men will die, but the man will not die, but the truck will continue towards the
one man sitting beside his house will not die. Thus for this five men. Thus, the five men will die. Thus for this reason,
reason, the man shouts, ‘‘Watch out!” to the driver of the he pushes the other man into the middle of the road. Thus,
truck. Thus, the driver swerves the truck. Thus, the five the five men are saved and the one man dies.”
men are saved and the one man dies.”
Means-non-contact killing [truck] = ‘‘A man is sitting at A.2. Condition 2
the side of the road. He sees a truck coming very fast. It
is headed straight towards five men. The five men do not Killing [boat] = ‘‘There is a man in his boat. He is carrying
hear or see that the truck is coming. If no one realizes that a net to catch fish, when he sees that there are five men
it is coming, the five men will die by being run over by the drowning in the river in front of his boat. There is another
truck. On the other side of the road there is another man man in between the front of his boat and where the five
sitting beside his house. If the first man who is standing men are. The other man knows how to swim. The man in
at the side of the road shouts, ‘‘Come here!” to the other his boat knows that the other man will not die. The man
man sitting beside his house – if he calls the other man in the boat wants to save the five men that are drowning.
over – the other man will walk into the middle of the road. If he steers his boat towards the men, his net for catching
Thus, the other man will die from being run over by the fish will drag over the swimming man and kill him, but
truck. But thus, he will block/stop the truck so that it will he will save the five men. If the man in the boat pulls the
not continue toward the five men. Thus, the five men will net into the inside of his boat, he will be late as a result.
be saved. If the man sitting at the side of the road does not Thus, the five men will die. If the man in the boat does
speak – if he does not call the other man over – the other nothing, the five men will die, but the one man who knows
222 L. Abarbanell, M.D. Hauser / Cognition 115 (2010) 207–224

how to swim will live. Thus, the man in the boat thinks if the fruit is in the tree. She is carrying one baby. She leaves
he can/should help the five men or only help the one. Thus the five other babies there at the bottom of the tree. When
he helps the five men, thus only the one man dies from she reaches the top of the tree, she sees a pack of peccaries.
being dragged by his fishing net.” They are running towards the five babies. The woman
Letting die [boat] = ‘‘There is a man in his boat, when he knows that the peccaries will trample and kill the babies.
sees that there are five men drowning in the river in front The only thing that the woman can do is to throw down
of his boat. He begins to steer his boat towards the five the baby that she is carrying towards the peccaries. Thus,
men because he wants to save them. Then he sees that the peccaries will be frightened away. If she throws the
there is another man who is drowning in between the front baby down, it will die. Thus, she throws down the baby,
of his boat and where the five men are. There is not enough thus the one baby dies and the five babies are saved.”
time to save all the six men that are in the water. The man Side-effect killing [peccaries] = ‘‘A woman has gone out to
who is in his boat thinks to himself who he can/should help pick fruit with six babies. She sees ripe fruit at the top of
for this reason. He knows that if he helps the five men, the the tree. The tree is very tall. Slowly, she climbs to where
one man will die. If he helps the one man, the five men will the fruit is in the tree. She is carrying one baby. She leaves
die. Thus, he helps the five men, thus only the one man the five other babies there at the bottom of the tree. When
dies.” she reaches the top of the tree, she sees a pack of peccaries.
Killing [boulder] = ‘‘A man is farming on the side of a hill. They are running towards the five babies. The woman
He sees a boulder coming down towards five men that are knows that the peccaries will trample and kill the babies.
at the bottom of the hill. The five men do not hear or see The only thing that the woman can do is to go down
that the boulder is coming. If no one realizes that the boul- quickly and frighten away the peccaries. In order to climb
der is coming, the five men will die by being smashed by down quickly, she must drop down the baby that she is
the boulder. On the other side/across the way is another carrying. If the baby drops down, it will die. Thus, she
man. If the farmer shouts, ‘‘Come here!” to the other man drops down the baby, thus the one baby dies and the five
– if he calls the other man over – the other man will walk babies are saved.”
into the path of the boulder. Thus, the other man will die
from being smashed by the boulder. But thus, he will A.4. Action–omission
block/stop the boulder so that it will not continue toward
the five men. Thus, the five men will be saved. If the farmer A.4.1. Children version
does not speak – if he does not call the other man over – Action [Vase] = ‘‘Lucia is standing there close to her sis-
the other man will not die, but the five men will die from ter’s vase by the window. If the wind enters, the vase will
being smashed by the boulder. Thus for this reason, the fall down and it will break. The window is closed. Never-
farmer calls the other man over. Thus, the five men are theless, Lucia knows that if she opens the window, the
saved and the one man who he calls over dies.” wind will enter, the vase will fall down, and it will break.
Letting die [boulder] = ‘‘A man is farming on the side of a Lucia wants to play with her dog; however, her dog is
hill. He sees a boulder coming down towards five men that asleep. She knows that if the vase breaks, the dog will wake
are at the bottom of the hill. The five men do not hear or up. Thus for this Lucia opens the window. Thus, the wind
see that the boulder is coming. If no one realizes that the enters. The vase falls down. It breaks. Thus because of this,
boulder is coming, the five men will die by being smashed the dog wakes up so that it can play with Lucia.”
by the boulder. On the other side is another man starting to Omission [Vase] = ‘‘Juana is standing there close to her
walk into the path of the boulder. If he walks into the path sister’s vase by the window. If the wind enters, the vase
of the boulder, he will die by being smashed by the boul- will fall down and it will break. The window is open. Juana
der. But thus, he will block/stop the boulder so that it will knows that if she does not close the window, the wind will
not continue toward the five men. Thus, the five men will enter, the vase will fall down, and it will break. Juana
be saved. If the farmer shouts, ‘‘Watch out!” to the other wants to play with her dog; however, her dog is asleep.
man – if he warns the other man – the other man will re- She knows that if the vase breaks, the dog will wake up.
main standing. Thus he will not die by being smashed by Thus, for this, Juana does not close the window. Thus, the
the boulder, but the boulder will continue towards the five wind enters. The vase falls down. It breaks. Thus because
men. Thus the five men will die. If the farmer does not of this, the dog wakes up so that it can play with Juana.”
shout – if he does not warn the other man – the other
man will walk into the path of the boulder. He will die A.4.2. Adult version
by being smashed by the boulder. But thus, the five men Killing [Pond] = ‘‘Jose is going for a walk in the moun-
will not die. Thus for this reason, the farmer does not shout tains. He comes across a paraje that he does not know.
– he does not warn the other man. Thus, the five men are He hears talk that there is a man who has fallen into an en-
saved and the one man dies.” chanted lagoon there. However, the man did not die from
the spell of the spirit of the lagoon. If the man does not
A.3. Condition 3 die by sunrise, another five men will have to be sacrificed
to the lagoon. Jose is a medicine man. He knows that if
A.3.1. Means-side-effect he gives poison to the man who fell into the lagoon, he will
Means killing [peccaries] = ‘‘A woman has gone out to die from it. Thus, they will not sacrifice the five men. If he
pick fruit with six babies. She sees ripe fruit at the top of does not give the poison, the man will not die. Thus, they
the tree. The tree is very tall. Slowly, she climbs to where will sacrifice the five men. Thus, for this reason, Jose gives
L. Abarbanell, M.D. Hauser / Cognition 115 (2010) 207–224 223

the poison to the one man. Thus, the one man dies, thus the Baron, J., & Miller, J. G. (2000). Limiting the scope of moral obligation to
help: A cross-cultural investigation. Journal of Cross-Cultural
five men remain living.”
Psychology, 31, 705–727.
Letting die [Pond] = ‘‘Roberto is going for a walk in the Baron, J., & Ritov, I. (2004). Omission bias, individual differences, and
mountains. He comes across a paraje that he does not normality. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 94,
know. He hears talk that there is a man who has fallen into 74–85.
Bennett, J. (1995). The act itself. New York: Oxford University Press.
an enchanted lagoon there. However, the man did not die Berlin, E. A., & Berlin, B. (1996). Medical ethnobiology of the highland Maya
from the spell of the spirit of the lagoon. If the man does of Chiapas, Mexico: The gastrointestinal diseases. Princeton, NJ:
not die by sunrise, another five men will have to be sacri- Princeton University Press.
Brandt, R. B. (1954). Hopi ethics: A theoretical analysis. Chicago: University
ficed to the lagoon. Roberto is a medicine man. He sees that of Chicago Press.
the man who fell into the lagoon drank poison. Roberto Collier, J. F. (1973). Law and social change in Zinacantan. Stanford: Stanford
knows that there is medicine so that one will not die if University Press.
Connolly, T., & Reb, J. (2003). Omission bias in vaccination decisions:
one drinks poison. If he does not give the medicine to the Where’s the ‘‘omission”? Where’s the ‘‘bias”? Organizational Behavior
man, the man will die by sunrise from the poison. Thus, and Human Decision Processes, 91, 186–202.
they will not sacrifice the five men. If he gives the medicine Cushman, F. (2008a). Crime and punishment: Distinguishing the roles of
causal and intentional analyses in moral judgment. Cognition, 108,
to the man, the man will not die, and they will sacrifice the 353–380.
five men. Thus for this reason, Roberto does not give the Cushman, F. (2008b). The origins of moral principles. Unpublished doctoral
man the poison. Thus, the one man dies, thus the five dissertation, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA.
Cushman, F., Young, L., Hauser, M. D. (in preparation). Patterns of moral
men remain living.”
judgment derive from non-moral psychological representations.
Cushman, F., Knobe, J., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2008). Moral appraisals
affect doing/allowing judgments. Cognition, 308, 281–289.
A.5. Condition 4 Cushman, F., Young, L., & Hauser, M. D. (2006). The role of conscious
reasoning and intuition in moral judgments: Testing three principles
of harm. Psychological Science, 17, 1082–1089.
Action [fruit tree] = ‘‘Juan is going for a walk in the
Doris, J., & Plakias, A. (2008). How to argue about disagreement:
mountains when he comes across a pond. There is a bana- Evaluative diversity and moral relativism. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong
na tree that has fallen into the pond. However, it has not (Ed.), Moral psychology, Vol. 2: The cognitive science of morality:
fallen to the bottom of the pond – it is floating on top of Intuition and diversity (pp. 303–331). Cambridge: MIT Press.
Evans-Pritchard, E. E. (1969). The Nuer: A description of the modes of
the pond. If it does not fall to the bottom by sunrise, many livelihood and political institutions of a Nilotic people. Oxford: Oxford
flies will come to eat the fruit. Juan knows that there is one University Press.
tree branch because of which the banana tree will not sink Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1992). Ethics: Problems and principles. New
York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston.
– it is floating on top of the tree branch. If he cuts off the Fraser, B., Hauser, M. D. (in press). The argument from disagreement and
tree branch, the banana tree will fall to the bottom of the the role of cross-cultural empirical data. Mind and Language.
water – thus, the flies will not come. If he does not cut Gert, B. (2004). Common morality. New York: Oxford University Press.
Gowans, C. (2008). Moral relativism. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
off the branch, the banana tree will not fall to the bottom <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2008/entries/moral-
of the water – thus, the flies will come. Thus, for this rea- relativism/>.
son, Juan cuts off the branch.” Granich, R., Cantwell, M. F., Long, K., Maldonado, Y., & Parsonnet, J. (1999).
Patterns of health seeking behavior during episodes of childhood
Omission [fruit tree] = ‘‘Alfonso is going for a walk in the diarrhea: A study of Tzotzil-speaking Mayans in the highlands of
mountains when he comes across a pond. There is a bana- Chiapas, Mexico. Social Science and Medicine, 48, 489–495.
na tree that has fallen into the pond. However, it has not Greene, J. D., Cushman, F. A., Stewart, L. E., Lowenberg, K., Nystrom, L. E., &
Cohen, J. D. (2009). Pushing moral buttons: the interaction between
fallen to the bottom of the pond – it is floating on top of
personal moral force and intention in moral judgment. Cognition,
the pond. If it does not fall to the bottom by sunrise, many 111(3), 364–371.
flies will come to eat the fruit. Alfonso knows that there is Greene, J. D., Nystrom, L. E., Engell, A. D., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D.
one tree branch that is filling with water – thus it is weigh- (2004). The neural bases of cognitive conflict and control in moral
judgment. Neuron, 44, 389–400.
ing down the tree. If he does not cut off the tree branch, the Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L. E., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D.
banana tree will fall to the bottom of the pond – thus, the (2001). An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral
flies will not come. If he cuts off the tree branch, the bana- judgment. Science, 293, 2105–2108.
Haidt, J. (2007). The new synthesis in moral psychology. Science, 316,
na tree will not fall to the bottom of the pond – thus the 998–1002.
flies will come. Thus, Alfonso does not cut off the tree Haidt, J., & Baron, J. (1996). Social roles and the moral judgment of actions
branch.” and omissions. European Journal of Social Psychology, 26, 201–218.
Haidt, J., Koller, S., & Dias, M. (1993). Affect, culture, and morality, or is it
wrong to eat your dog? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 65,
613–628.
References Harman, G., & Thomson, J. J. (1996). Moral relativism and moral objectivity.
Cambridge: Blackwell.
Alicke, M. (2000). Culpable control and the psychology of blame. Hart, H. L. A., & Honore, T. (1959). Causation and the law. Oxford:
Psychological Bulletin, 126, 556–574. Clarendon Press.
Atran, S., Medin, D., Lynch, E., Vapnarsky, V., Ek’, E. U., & Sousa, P. (2001). Hauser, M. D. (2006a). Moral minds: How nature designed our sense of right
Folkbiology doesn’t come from folkpsychology: Evidence from and wrong. New York: Ecco/Harper Collins.
Yukatek Maya in cross-cultural perspective. Journal of Cognition and Hauser, M. D. (2006b). Moral minds. New York: Ecco/Harper Collins.
Culture, 1, 3–42. Hauser, M. D., Cushman, F., Young, L., Jin, R. K.-X., & Mikhail, J. (2007). A
Banerjee, K., Huebner, B., Hauser, M. D. (in press). Moral judgments are dissociation between moral judgments and justifications. Mind and
immune to the effects of age, sex, education, and religion. Journal of Language, 22, 1–21.
Cognition and Culture. Hauser, M. D., Tonnaer, F., & Cima, M. (2009). When moral intuitions are
Baron, J. (1994). Nonconsequentialist decisions. Behavioral and Brain immune to the law: A case study of euthanasia and the act-omission
Sciences, 17(1), 1–10. distinction in the Netherlands. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 9,
Baron, J. (2009). Looking at individual subjects in research on judgment and 149–169.
decision making (or anything). Unpublished manuscript.
224 L. Abarbanell, M.D. Hauser / Cognition 115 (2010) 207–224

Haviland, J. B. (1977). Gossip, reputation, and knowledge in Zinacantan. Miller, J. G. (1994). Cultural diversity in the morality of caring:
Chicago: University of Chicago press. Individually oriented versus duty-based interpersonal moral codes.
Henrich, J., Boyd, R., Bowles, S., Camerer, C., Fehr, E., & Gintis, H. (2005). Cross-cultural Research, 28, 3–39.
Economic Man’ in cross-cultural perspective: Behavioral experiments Miller, J., Bersoff, D. M., & Harwood, R. L. (1990). Perceptions of social
in 15 small scale societies. Behavioral and Brain Research, 28, 795–855. responsibilities in India and in the United States: Moral imperatives
Henrich, J., McElreath, R., Barr, A., Ensminger, J., Barrett, C., & Bolyantz, A. or personal decisions? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 58,
(2006). Costly punishment across human societies. Science, 312, 33–47.
1767–1770. Nisbett, R. E., & Cohen, D. (1996). Culture of honor: The psychology of
Huebner, B., Pettit, P., Hauser, M. D. (in press). How the source, violence in the south. Boulder: Westview Press.
inevitability, and means of bringing about harm interact in folk- O’Neill, P., & Petrinovich, L. (1998). A preliminary cross cultural study of
moral judgments. Mind and Language. moral intuitions. Evolution and Human Behavior, 19, 349–367.
INEGI (2005). II conteo de población y vivienda 2005. Aguascalientes, Ags., Paoli, A. (2003). Educación, autonomía y lekil kuxlejal: Aproximaciones
México: Instituto Nacional de Estadística y Geografía. sociolingüísticas a la sabiduría de los tseltales (1st ed.). Mexico: Distrito
Kamm, F. M. (2007). Intricate ethics. New York: Oxford University Press. Federal: Universidad Autónoma Metropolitana, Unidad Xochimilco.
Knafo, A., Hauser, M.D., (in preparation). Moral judgments in monozygotic Patt, A., & Zeckhauser, R. (2000). Action bias and environmental decisions.
and dizygotic twin children. Unpublished Data. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 21, 45–72.
Kohlberg, L. (1981). Essays on moral development, Vol. 1: The philosophy of Ritov, I., & Baron, J. (1990). Reluctance to vaccinate: Omission bias and
moral development. New York: Harper Row. ambiguity? Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 3, 263–277.
Ladd, J. (1957). The structure of a moral code: A philosophical analysis of Shweder, R. A., Mahapatra, M., & Miller, J. G. (1987). Culture and moral
ethical discourse applied to the ethics of the Navaho Indians. Cambridge: development. In J. Kagan & S. Lamb (Eds.), The emergence of morality in
Harvard University Press. young children (pp. 1–82). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lenkersdorf, C. (2002). Filosofar en clave tojolabal. Mexico: Miguel Angel Spranca, M., Minsk, E., & Baron, J. (1991). Omission and commission in
Porrua. judgment of choice. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 27,
Leon Pasquel, L. d. (2005). La llegada del alma. lenguaje, infancia y 76–105.
socialización entre los mayas de Zinacantán. Mexico: Centro de Sugiyama, L. S., Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2002). Cross-cultural evidence of
Investigaciones y Estudios Superiores en Antropología Social; cognitive adaptations for social exchange among the Shiwiar of
Instituto Nacional de Antropología e Historia. Ecuadorian Amazonia. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,
Malinowski, B. (1922/1984). Argonauts of the Western Pacific. New York: USA, 99, 11537–11542.
Waveland Press. Sunstein, C. R. (2005). Moral heuristics. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28,
Mandel, D. R., Vartanian, O. (2007). Taboo or tragic: Effect of tradeoff type 531–573.
on moral choice, conflict, and confidence. Mind and Society. Tanner, C., & Medin, D. (2004). Protected values: No omission bias and no
doi:10.1007/s11299-007-0037-3. framing effects. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 11, 185–191.
Mead, M. (1928/2001). Coming of age in Samoa. New York: Harper Collins. Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social knowledge: Morality and
Medina Hernandez, A. (1991). Tenejapa, familia y tradicion de un pueblo convention. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
tzeltal (1st ed.). Chiapas, Mexico: Gobierno del Estado de Chiapas, Turnbull, C. (1987). The forest people. New York: Touchstone Press.
Consejo Estatal de Fomento a la Investigacion y Difusion de la Cultura, Villa Rojas, A. (1990). Etnorgrafia tzeltal de chiapas: Modalidades de una
Instituto Chiapaneco de Cultura. cosmovision prehispanica (1st ed.). Tuxtla Gutierrez, Mexico: Gobiemo
Mikhail, J. M. (2000). Rawls’ linguistic analogy: A study of the ‘generative del Estado de Chiapas, Consejo Estatal para el Fomento a la
grammar’ model of moral theory described by John Rawls in ‘A theory of Investigacio y Difusion de la Cultura.
justice’. Unpublished PhD, Cornell University, Ithaca. Westermarck, E. (1906–1908). The origin and development of the moral
Mikhail, J. (2007). Universal moral grammar: Theory, evidence, and the ideas (Vols. 1 and 2). New York: Macmillan Co.
future. Trends in Cognitive Science, 11, 143–152.

You might also like