You are on page 1of 8

A Quarterly

Message
on Liberty
Spring 2011
Volume 9
Number 2

Robust Political Economy


MARK PENNINGTON

I
f you look at some of the economic argu-
ments advanced in favor of markets, econo-
mists have come up with good defenses
against various market-failure theories. If
you look at political theorists, they have come up
with good responses to the kind of anti-market
arguments made by egalitarians and by communi-
tarians. What has been lacking is a unified theoreti- Mark Pennington is professor of
politics at the University of London.
cal framework that can bring together all these crit- He spoke about his new book,
icisms and the classical liberal responses. We don’t Robust Political Economy:
Classical Liberalism and the
have a unified framework that can respond not Future of Public Policy, at the
only to the economic objections that have been Cato Institute in March.

raised against classical liberalism, but to the politi-


cal and ethical challenges that have been raised
against the tradition as well.
here are three challenges kind of institutions minimize the

T that I think classical liberal-


ism needs to respond to:
the challenges from “market-failure
consequences of what will be in-
evitable human mistakes or human
errors?
economics,” the challenge of com- The second human imperfection
munitarianism, and, finally, the that we have to take account of is the
challenge of egalitarianism. We can problem of “limited benevolence.”
respond simultaneously to all of People may, under certain circum-
these challenges with the framework stances, act out of self-interested
of robust political economy. motivations. They may be oppor-
What is “robust political econo- tunistic in certain circumstances. We
my?” Something is “robust” if it’s need to evaluate institutions in
able to withstand various stresses terms of the incentives they provide
and strains. In the context of politi- to channel potentially opportunistic
cal and economic institutions, we actors to behave in a way that in-
can define something as being ro- creases the overall level of well-being
bust if it’s able to withstand the in society.
stresses and strains wrought by So those are the two human im-
human imperfections. There are two perfections that robust institutions
human imperfections that I want to have to deal with. In the first part of
focus on. the book, I claim that challenges to
The first is the idea of “limited classical liberalism fail to meet the
human rationality.” Human beings criteria of robustness. Their particu-
lar alternatives to the classical lib-


eral ideal of a minimal state and
If we’re in a world of open markets do not address
limited rationality, there’s how their own favorite institu-
tions will deal with the problems
no reason to suppose that of limited rationality and limited
government regulators
know what the ideal
market structure is.
“ benevolence. The classical liberal
case for a minimal state frame-
work with an open-market econ-
omy based on the dispersed own-
ership of property is based on the
are not fully rational agents; they are claim that these institutions are
not omniscient beings. Whenever more robust in the face of limited
they make decisions, they do so in a rationality and limited benevolence.
context of considerable uncertainty A competitive context is the best
and there is always imperfect infor- context to deal with the fact that
mation when they’re making deci- people are imperfectly informed.
sions. If decisionmaking takes place When we have lots of different
in a context of imperfect informa- decisionmakers making different
tion, what kind of institutions facili- sorts of decisions, we can facilitate a
tate learning over time, and what process of trial-and-error learning

2 • Cato’s Letter SPRING 2011


that minimizes the conse-
quence of any particular
error. If you centralize deci-
sionmaking and people make
“ The most important form
of learning takes place
from seeing what other
mistakes, then the conse-
quences are much more far
reaching than if the decision-
and learning from their
experiences.

people do in their lives,

making power is more dis-


persed. Likewise, a classical
liberal framework that pro-
vides for exit enables people to ered to be ripe for corrective govern-
escape from the depredations of ment action. If we’re in a world of
potentially predatory actors. If peo- limited rationality, of imperfect
ple are acting opportunistically, the knowledge, then knowledge of what
capacity to exit from relationships should be produced and how it
with these actors provides a disci- should be produced isn’t going to
plinary check on potentially self- be evenly distributed. Some firms
interested behavior. are going to judge the market better
Market-failure economics, or than others. Some firms are going to
“mainstream neoclassical econom- make more profits than others.
ics,” evaluates market institutions Other firms are going to make loss-
against the benchmark of full-infor- es. It is precisely through these im-
mation equilibrium. Any departures perfections, or inequalities, that a
from this full-information equilibri- learning process is set in motion, so
um are described as “market fail- that people can learn over time to
ures,” which are considered a right copy the more successful firms and
for some kind of corrective govern- to avoid the business models that
ment action. If we take the perspec- are adopted by the less successful
tive of robust political economy, and firms. Any market that is based on
focus first on the idea of limited ra- imperfect information and unevenly
tionality, then this notion of perfec- distributed knowledge is going to
tion, or full information, simply isn’t look imperfect when judged against
a valid standard against which to a standard of perfection. The ques-
evaluate either market institutions— tion is, what is the alternative to this
or any other institutions for that imperfection? Is it a world where reg-
matter. The case for markets isn’t ulators somehow magically know
that they are “perfect” institutions; what the ideal market structure is? If
the case for markets is based on the we’re in a world of limited rationali-
view that they are best placed to cope ty, there’s no reason to suppose that
with the inevitability of imperfect in- government regulators know what
formation and limited rationality. the ideal market structure is.
Take the notion that neoclassical You may say that this kind of
economists focus on—imperfect analysis is somewhat old hat, that
competition—which is often consid- there are new market failure theo-

SPRING 2011 Cato’s Letter • 3


rists, such as Nobel laureate Joseph whether they have the capacity to
Stiglitz, who are well aware that gov- challenge the preferences of individ-
ernment is likely to fail in the way uals. What they’re getting at is the
that markets fail. When push comes notion that liberalism lacks any
to shove, however, they always hold account of how we can elevate peo-
markets to a different standard than ple’s preferences, how we can en-
public policy interventions or gov- courage people or educate them
ernment regulators. Stiglitz is fond to have a more informed or en-
of saying that the price system, be- lightened set of preferences. In a
cause of its various imperfections, is communitarian view, democracy
too coarse a deci- is better placed than
sionmaking instru- the market to chal-
ment to enable peo- lenge irrational or
ple to make effective prejudiced prefer-
decisions. What he ences that people
lacks is an account may have, precisely
of why government because it’s based
regulators should be on majority rule. In
assumed to be in a a communitarian
position to correct view, people’s pref-
for these market erences should have
imperfections. We’re to be justified to the
supposed to trust majority before they
that government can be put into
regulators are going practice, and this
to be improving on majoritarian check
the market out- will provide the con-
come. Stiglitz does- text within which
n’t give any justification for this as- bad preferences can be weeded out,
sumption whatsoever. He fails, in creating an overall elevation in the
my view, to meet the standards of a quality of the preferences.
robust political economy. This kind of view, if we think
Let’s now turn to communitari- about it in terms of robust political
anism. There are many different economy, is based on a hopelessly
claims that communitarians make, romanticized view of how any dem-
but there is only one that I want to ocratic or majoritarian process can
focus on for the purpose of this brief actually operate. It’s based on a
talk. Communitarians challenge complete failure to understand how
classical liberalism on the grounds most people learn in most situa-
that we shouldn’t evaluate institu- tions in life. The most important
tions on their capacity to respond to, form of learning in society—espe-
or to satisfy, given individual prefer- cially if you take Hayek’s ideas seri-
ences. In the communitarian view, ously—isn’t the kind that takes
we should evaluate institutions on place when we argue with one an-

4 • Cato’s Letter SPRING 2011


other in a public forum and
come to a majority decision
about which particular view
is best. The most important
form of learning takes place
“ A system of private-
property rights that
allows people to carry
out experiments in living
from seeing what other peo-
ple do in their lives, and learn-
is much more likely to
ing from their experiences. In challenge existing preju-
order for that sort of learning
to take place, it’s absolutely
imperative that the widest
dices and preferences
than is any socialist or
collectivist alternative.

possible number of experi-
ences—or experiments in liv-
ing, if you like—actually
occur. Majoritarianism, by its very Caplan makes the point very per-
nature, squelches the process of suasively, following people like Ge-
experimentation. The way we get offrey Brennan and Loren Lomasky
value change in most fields of life is in the past, that the institutions of
by entrepreneurs, whether in the democracy do not actually provide
economic domain or in the moral people adequate incentives to chal-
domain, breaking from the majori- lenge their own preferences. Why?
ty position and doing something Because if you try to revise your
different. Then, gradually, through preference in a majoritarian context,
an incremental process, the majori- it actually makes no difference to
ty view changes. the final outcome that you person-
Hayek puts this very well when ally will experience. That is going to
he states, “It is always from a minor- be determined by whether every-
ity acting in ways different from body else challenges their prefer-
what the majority would prescribe ences. In a market context, you can
that the majority in the end learns profit personally by challenging the
to do better.” A system of private- prejudices you may have. If you’re
property rights that allows people an employer who has racist or sexist
to carry out experiments in living prejudices, you can profit by break-
is much more likely to challenge ing from those prejudices, thus ex-
existing prejudices and preferences panding your market. But nobody
than is any socialist or collectivist in a democratic arena can actually
alternative. profit personally from challenging
Now it’s not only in terms of this their own views when they can’t
knowledge problem or the problem change the outcome until they’ve
of limited rationality that the com- persuaded everybody else to expect
munitarian view fails. It also fails some kind of a change in the law. So
to adequately take into account again the communitarian view fails
notions of incentives. I draw in to meet the requirements of a ro-
the book on Bryan Caplan’s work. bust political economy.

SPRING 2011 Cato’s Letter • 5


Cato Scholar Profile:
ILYA SHAPIRO
ILYA SHAPIRO is a senior fellow in constitutional studies at the Cato
Institute and editor-in-chief of the Cato Supreme Court Review. He has
contributed to a variety of academic, popular, and professional publica-
tions and regularly provides commentary on a host of legal and political is-
sues for various TV and radio outlets. Shapiro lectures regularly on behalf
of the Federalist Society. He holds an AB from Princeton University, an
MSc from the London School of Economics, a JD from the University of
Chicago Law School, and is a member of the bars of New York, the District
of Columbia, and the U.S. Supreme Court.
You’ve spent much of the last year touring the collected from all taxpayers but returned only
country, debating the constitutionality of the to Medicaid states.
Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act. Another issue is that the state-specific carve-
What’s your impression of how students outs—the Louisiana Purchase, Cornhusker
assess that issue? Kickback, Gator-aid, etc.—violate the principle
It’s been gratifying to see a real thirst for knowl- that all federal legislation needs to be for the
edge about the constitutional issues being raised, general welfare. This is different than earmarks
among all audiences, not just law students. As because here New York, say, isn’t eligible for a
on many other issues, the American people are similar benefit to what Florida gets.
not just engaging in a policy debate—does a par-
ticular proposal make economic sense?—but are What’s your prediction of the outcome of the
questioning the source of the power the govern- eventual Supreme Court decision?
ment asserts. That’s a healthy discussion to be Upholding the legislation would allow the fed-
having. In the health care context, we’ve come a eral government to mandate that Americans
long way since Nancy Pelosi reacted to this type engage in assorted activities, turning citizens
of question by implying that the Constitution into subjects. Without exaggeration, nobody
was the last refuge of the scoundrel who lacked would be able to claim that the Constitution
“serious” (policy) arguments. limits federal power.
But will the Court go there? On the one
Are there other constitutionally troubling hand, it refrained from striking down such fa-
portions of the Act besides the individual cially unconstitutional pieces of fundamental
mandate? legislation as Social Security. On the other, that
The individual mandate is crucial: if you knock legislation was popular and came during a time
it out, the whole Rube Goldberg machine—set- of great social upheaval. If, as the old saw goes,
ting aside tangential provisions like those relat- “the Court follows the election returns,” the rise
ing to Indian reservations and indoor tanning of the Tea Parties and the “shellacking” the De-
services—simply ceases to function. But there mocrats received in 2010 may have steeled judi-
are plenty of other problems, some of which cial spines.
make for viable claims under existing doctrine It will, unsurprisingly, come down to Justice
and others that would require a constitutional Anthony Kennedy. We advocates need to con-
revolution of sorts to remedy. vince him that this is about basic liberty—he is
For example, the Act’s transformation of fairly libertarian in cases thus framed—rather
Medicaid impermissibly coerces states by forc- than “mere” governmental structures. But if
ing them to accept a greatly expanded program. Kennedy rules against the individual mandate,
States face a Hobson’s Choice: accept the new it will likely be Chief Justice John Roberts who
regime and suffer devastating consequences to dictates how much of the remaining legislation,
strained budgets, or forgo billions of dollars if any, survives.

6 • Cato’s Letter SPRING 2011


The Estate
Tax . . .
Congress
Kicks the
Can Down
the Road
I
n December 2010, Congress slapped an kicker. Tax rates and exemptions levels were to
11th hour band-aid on the estate-tax be reinstated at punitive 2001 levels—that is,
mess. Essentially this quick fix pumps rates as high as 55 percent and a mere $1 mil-
up the exemption level (the amount of assets lion exemption.
exempted from estate tax) and lowers the tax Given the widespread recognition of the
rate for a couple of years. It does not tackle the innate unfairness of the estate tax, Congress
larger questions of whether estates should be and the president knew that something had
taxed at all and, if so, at what level. to be done before the reinstatement witching
Indeed, Cato’s scholars have long argued hour. Hence, a last-minute compromise,
for a complete repeal of the estate tax, com- signed into law on December 17, 2010, rein-
monly called the “death tax.” They point out stated the estate tax but provided for an in-
that the tax is typically imposed on the accu- creased exemption amount of $5 million per
mulated earnings and savings from a lifetime person and a decreased maximum rate of 35
and, therefore, tends to tax—for a second percent.
time—assets that were already subjected to in- The catch is that the increased exemption
come and/or capital gains taxes during a per- and decreased rate are available for 2011 and
son’s life. Beyond the inherent unfairness of 2012 only. Unless Congress intervenes again,
this double taxation, Cato’s scholars main- these relief provisions sunset on December
tain that the estate tax is hugely inefficient—it 31, 2012, and the law reverts back to a $1 mil-
is difficult to enforce and administer and it is lion exemption and a 55 percent top rate.
the progenitor of a wasteful cottage industry So, once again, Congress has kicked the can
devoted to estate-tax avoidance. It is also down the road and taxpayers are left with
worth noting that several industrial nations some temporary relief but lack the long-term
have no estate tax. stability necessary for generational planning.
If you are wondering why we reached a cri- Hopefully, when the debate heats up some-
sis point at the end of 2010, the answer is that time in 2012, Congress will get it right and will
the Bush administration could not garner finally repeal the estate/death tax. Perhaps the
enough votes for the full repeal of the estate only certainty in this sorry mess is that Cato’s
tax. As an alternative, it opted for an awkward scholars will continue to argue that the estate
legislative compromise: a series of increases in tax is both unfair and unworkable.
the amount of assets exempted from the tax If you would like to discuss estate plan-
and a one-year repeal in 2010, followed by a re- ning or gifting ideas, please feel free to contact
instatement of the tax in 2011. That 2011 re- Gayllis Ward, our director of planned giving,
instatement was scheduled to come with a at gward@cato.org or at (202) 218-4631.

SPRING 2011 Cato’s Letter • 7


Books from the
Climate Coup: Global Warming’s Invasion of
Our Government and Our Lives
Edited by Patrick J. Michaels
A first-rate team of experts offers compelling documentation on the
pervasive influence global warming alarmism now has on almost
every aspect of our society—from national defense, law, trade, and pol-
itics to health, education, and international development.
HARDCOVER: $24.95 • E-BOOK: $14.95

Schools For Misrule: Legal Academia and an


Overlawyered America
By Walter Olson
This new book reveals how our nation’s law schools have become a
hatchery of bad ideas, many of which confer power and status on the
schools’ graduates and faculty, as law comes to pervade more areas
of life.
HARDCOVER: $24.95 • E-BOOK: $14.00

Available at bookstores nationwide, online at www.cato.org, or by calling toll-free (800) 767-1241.


Cato Institute, 1000 Massachusetts Avenue, N.W., Washington, DC 20001 l www.cato.org
Cato Institute
Organization
U.S. Postage
Nonprofit

PAID
1000 Massachusetts Ave., N.W.
Washington, D.C. 20001
www.cato.org

You might also like