You are on page 1of 18

Affective Spaces Frederik Tygstrup University of Copenhagen In a series of draft chapters from Robert Musils unfinished novel The

Man Without Qualities, the protagonist embarks, in his diaries, on a dissertation on emotions, pondering questions pertaining to the genesis of emotions, the nature of emotions, and the (puzzling) location of emotions. At some point, he makes the following note: The German language says: I feel anger inside, and it says: I am in anger. () This difference between the linguistic images of our feelings () is mirrored by our present scientific ideas (). There are psychological doctrines to whom the I is an indisputable core piece, detectable in every movement of the spirit and particularly in the emotion, and there are doctrines that completely disregard the I and only consider the relations between expressions and describe them as appearances in a field of forces, their origin notwithstanding. (Musil, 1978: 1160) This distinction, pretty evident and then quite subtle at the same time, suggested by Musil in the 1930s, provides a good starting point for a preliminary mapping of the extensive interest in the understanding of emotions that can be witnessed in a wide array of academic disciplines today. Current research in the history of emotions, phenomenology of emotions and psychology of emotions seems to comply most with the first alternative set forth by Musil, i.e. regarding emotions as something that exist within an I and thus appears as a predicate to a subject. This approach also has the merit of conforming to the grammar of our present everyday understanding of things, positing an I who is able to account for its worldly position in space and time as well as for the reactions this position provokes as emotions in an inner dimension of the self. On such a basis, we can study the self in different historical situations and chart different historically contextualized emotions, we can see how subjectively felt emotions taint the perception of outer stimuli, we can even start graphing the physiological markers of specific emotions, whose nature we establish simply by applying the habitual designations of how an individual reports feeling.

What one risks forgetting, however, when applying this model for the different ventures of mapping emotions according to historical, pragmatic or physiological distributions, is the historical nature of the model itself. The grammar of emotions as a designation of predicates to a subject, of the model NN feels XX, is probably a predominantly modern one. If I were a nobleman, Goethes Wilhelm Meister at some point longingly exclaims, and explains: a nobleman appears, according to a specific code, whereas the bourgeois simply is, by virtue of his individual qualities (Goethe, 1979: 174f). Emotion, thus, for the aristocrat, is a matter of appearance (Schein), of codified expression, whereas for the bourgeois it is a matter of being (Sein), of inner authenticity. Goethes selfconscious bourgeois could have been the case in point for Arnold Hausers harsh historical diagnosis: Emotionalism, like individualism, is a means for the bourgeoisie to express its spiritual autonomy in relation to the aristocracy. The bourgeois, so long held in contempt, now fashions himself in the mirror of his own spiritual life and feels the more important when he contemplates with utmost seriousness his own emotions, moods and inner movements. (Hauser, 1953: 576) Historicizing the grammar of emotion along these lines would thus entail an awareness of how not only emotions, but also the ways in which we attribute them and talk about them as facts of inner human life, are embedded in characteristic social and epistemic conditions and in fact constructed through a quite specific historical set of agencies and interests. Eventually, when glossing and interpreting different emotional states as something ongoing inside psychological persons, we would have to see ourselves as the heirs of the 18th century, of all the Rousseaus and the Richardsons and their insistent elaboration of a panoply of inner sentimental movements paving the way for a grammar of feelings that we have by now interiorized to a degree where they appear to be perfectly natural objects of scientific mapping and measurement. It is when embarking on this skeptical line of thought, to which the founding and synthesizing powers of the I might not amount to more than a frail historical compromise, that Musils other option comes to the fore: that emotional life might in some cases be more accurately described as relations between expressions and appearances in a field of forces. And where, consequently, the grammar is turned

upside-down, no longer addressing emotional states as something that we carry within us, but rather as something in which we find ourselves passing or dwelling. This reversal seems to inform the increasing interest of late in the notion of affects and in affect studies1. Although there might not be any clear-cut and consensual distinction between the notions of emotion and of affect (of which a proper conceptual history still remains to be written) other than somehow vague and intuitive semantic groupings, a preliminary differentiation might be established on the basis of the two different grammars evoked by Musil: emotions are something you have, whereas affects is something you are in. Put differently: subjects have emotions, but affects produce subjectivity. This will not of course provide us with a workable distinction pertaining to the object-side, i.e. enabling us to point and say this is an emotion and that is an affect; we are still dealing with a somehow nebulous set of states of mind and feelings, as was also the case initially for Musil. But what we do have with these two grammars are two distinct ways of approaching and talking about feelings: one, say, Romantic, describing feelings in terms of psychology and interiority, and another, post-Romantic, describing them in terms of contexts (relations between expressions) and events (appearances in a force-field). It will of course ultimately depend on the object you want to study, i.e. the event of some feeling appearing in a precise set of conditions, which of the two approaches proves the better. Take an example: the opening sequence of the 2008 HBO-series Generation Kill, directed by David Simon, portrays a handful of young soldiers in an SUV traversing the Iraqi desert; the inside of the vehicle is noisy, the speed of their convoy high and the outlook fragmented, the men are fully harnessed for battle but do not seem to know exactly what to expect and are thus all the more ready in some general sense, yelling among themselves and on the radio, fiddling with their equipment, eating chocolate bars, trying to be on watch while also tending to internal hierarchies and jargons.

Some prominent contemporary examples include Thrift (2008), Butler (2009), Frdric Lordon (2010), Brian Massumi (2002), and Yann Moulier Boutang (2007).

The intensity of feeling permeating the sequence is beyond question panic, fear, aggression, boredom would all be eligible candidates for naming it but then again, and that would be the central point here, not really as someones feeling. It seems more accurate to say that an affect prevails in the SUV traversing the blank and inscrutable desert space loaded with frail young men in full military gear. The first-person perspective and the related languages of contemplation and introspection would appear somehow inadequate because the affect is so obviously derived from the situation. Thus, analyzing affects entails a shift of focus from the psyche to the situation. And, in turn, the situation appears as a complex composition of material elements, social scripts and protocols for agency, human bodies and their different tools and prostheses, and an ensemble of individuals expressing their different volitions, imaginaries and propensities. It is by way of such a relational arrangement that the locus of a given feeling moves from the inner state of the individual to a less clearly delineated field of shared atmosphere. This does not prevent, of course, that a feeling is actually felt by someone and can be articulated as a specific state of mind. Only the way in which that particular feeling emerges, amplifies and propagates transcends the strictly individual and autonomous sphere. We are propelled, in other words, to consider the situation in what would be

Sartrean terms, that is, as a negation of any individual aspiration and self-projection onto the world, and at the same time as the very possibility of such a thing as an individual aspiration. The individual is always already heteronomous and given over to the situation in which one finds oneself, but indeed also invited precisely to find oneself by way of affirming the constraints of the situation. The situation, in this rather strong sense of the notion, thus already entails an attenuation of the strict demarcation usually drawn between what would pertain to an individual and what would pertain to its surroundings, taking us from considering these somehow overly abstract entities to analyzing more concretely what Sartre calls the internal metabolism of the situation (Sartre, 1943: 611). Given the situation as a relational ensemble, we can study the logic of affects in one of its basic forms, as the dynamic interplay of affecting and being affected. If you put a young man into a SUV in a convoy on a military mission in some sunny desert, you affect him by framing him in a specific situation characterized by the ways in which spatiality, temporality and alterity are formatted (to stick here to Sartres elements for analysing situations): the convoy, the mission, the crew. This framing, however, is not only an interchangeable frame for an otherwise self-identical individual; the composition of the situation also defines the individual as it prescribes the range of reactions he can mobilize. His training and socialization as a soldier, the equipment around him and attached to his body, the entire set of relations in the box in which he is enclosed invites him to act in particular ways, clumsily or cleverly, depending on his ability to be affected. Relational analysis of a situation invites consideration of the kind of micro-mechanics involved in the production of affect. How is a peculiar component of a situation (the soldier, or the unit, or the convoy) affected by what happens, which affects does this component in turn produce? This almost engineer-like approach to the affective component of a situation is spelled out by Gilles Deleuze in his influential commentary on Spinoza. Affectivity here stands out as something fundamentally processual, as the signature of an event that unfolds, combining on the one hand the modification of a body (affectus) and on the other hand the way in which this modification is taken up or responded to by the receiving body (affectio). Deleuze: Affectio refers to the state of an affected body and implies the presence of the affecting body, whereas affectus refers to a

passage from one state to another, in relation to the correlative variation of the affecting bodies (Deleuze, 1981: 69). Affect, then, and ultimately the production of feeling, is inscribed in a relational network where processes of affecting on the one hand and articulation of specific affects on the other develop through an ongoing relational interaction. Such an empiricist mapping of the relational structures that underpin affectivity in turn gives us an opportunity to characterize more precisely the nature of the situation. In fact, the situation can be described according to two different perspectives: we can consider it as a diagram, i.e. as a kind of blueprint of relations charting the reciprocal relations between elements that are put together in a particular way, and we can consider it as an event, where the relations are so to speak set in motion, where the intensities produced through the relational juxtaposition of elements spark something happening. The situation is a set-up, and designed to unfold the potential invested in the set-up. Describing affects as something that pertains more to situations than to psychological persons as events in a force-field, to once again retain Musils instructive definition underscores the role of contingency in human matters (also a core facet to Sartres theorizing of the situation), contingency understood both in a pragmatic sense referring to what is nearby, and in a more logical sense referring to the relative chance of what happens to be nearby. Affects mark out the contingency of any being and invite us to understand how the production of subjectivity essentially relies on this contingency. Judith Butler succinctly spelled it out as follows: That the body invariably comes up against the outside world is a sign of the general predicament of unwilled proximity to others and to circumstances beyond ones control. This coming up against is one of the modalities that define the body. And yet, this obtrusive alterity against which the body finds itself can be, and often is, what animates responsiveness to that world. That responsiveness may include a wide range of affects: pleasure, rage, suffering, hope, to name a few. () Hence, precariousness as a generalized condition relies on a conception of the body as fundamentally dependent on, and conditioned by, a sustained and sustainable world; responsivenessand thus, ultimately, responsibilityis located in the affective responses to a sustaining and impinging world. (Butler, 2009: 34)

Whereas Butlers stress on contingency and involvement is clearly in line with the situational approach outlined above, it also adds an important dimension to the understanding of affectivity, namely the ways in which affect has to be understood as a fundamentally bodily phenomenon. Bodies are affecting and affected through the situational relations in which they are engaged. It is equally important, however, not to think about bodylines as a just a slightly more materialistic version of personhood, substituting the egological I with an enhanced, corporeal version of the autonomous subject. Butler, to be sure, stresses this reservation by remarking that the body is fundamentally dependent on, and conditioned by, a sustained and sustainable world, thus taking as the point of departure the presence of a body, while not positing the body as an epistemologically fundamental category. Bodylines, then, is not a metaphor of the subject, but rather a stage for the processes of subjectivization taking place. This understanding of the body is thus neither Cartesian, as opposed to the mind, nor the traditional phenomenological one, as a situated center of perception, but more akin to the idea of bodylines formulated by the late Merleau-Ponty as a dynamic point of intersection between outer and inner impulses. According to Merleau-Ponty, bodylines remains a reflective moment, the body being at the same time just another thing in the world, and the agent of a self experiencing the world: object and subject in one, and thus consequently neither properly one nor the other. Alternatively, in the clever formula coined by Terry Eagleton: It is not quite true that I have a body, and not quite true that I am one either (Eagleton, 1993). Being in the world, for Merleau-Ponty, is essentially a negotiation of this chiasmic structure, an undulating movement to-and-fro between subjectivizing the predicaments of what is given as objective, and giving over the subjective to the objective conditions that determine and carry it. The idea of the body never comes to rest on either side, as something predominantly subjective or something predominantly objective, but remains suspended in the reciprocal reflection between these aspects, like two mirrors facing each other, giving birth to two indefinite series of infolded images that no longer belong to either of two surfaces, as each image is just a reflection of the other, thus making the couple of mirrors more real than any of the two (Merleau-Ponty, 1965: 183). The sustained paradoxical nature of these different formulae, however tiresome, has the merit of emphasizing the processual nature of any

(embodied) situation, the ongoing metabolism, as Sartre had it, between inner and outer reality. Thus, while we cannot pin down a straightforward definition of the body, we can see bodylines as an interface involved in any human situation and an interface that constantly coordinates and processes the interaction between psychic and material components as they swiftly oscillate and transcend into the realms of the other. That affects are bodily, therefore, implies that we localize affect precisely at this elusive interface where internal and external reality are projected onto each other, or where affectus and affectio come together in a specific affective quality, excessively involved in the situational context to be deemed strictly subjective and overly tainted by individual receptivity to be strictly objective. The triple approach to affects as relational, as situational and as corporeal thus all point in the same direction: that affects cannot be pinned down to one specific realm or layer of reality, but seems to persist as a material/immaterial halo or sphere hovering indistinctly but none less insistently above and within any field of human agency and interaction. Affects alight and persist in the unfinished and processual, as scintillating qualities of the present with their own characteristic signature. They appear as a kind of quasi-objects, atmospheric facts, as it were, to which we must accord a being of their own as they emerge from the stratum of human reality. It is this almost objective nature of affects that makes Brian Massumi argue for what he calls the autonomy of affect, and it seems to be very much the same endeavor that made Raymond Williams coin the succinct (and slightly oxymoronic) notion of structure of feeling, combining the connotative vagueness of feeling with the regularity of the structural: We are talking about characteristic elements of impulse, restraint, and tone; specifically affective elements of consciousness and relationships; not feeling against thought, but thought as felt and feeling as thought; practical consciousness of a present kind, in a living and inter-relating continuity. We are then defining these elements as a structure: as a set, with specific internal relations, at once interlocking and in tension. Yet we are also defining a social experience which is still in process, often indeed not yet recognized as social but taken to be private, idiosyncratic, and even isolating, but which in analysis (though rarely otherwise) has its emergent, connecting and dominating characteristics []. (Williams, 1977: 132)

Both Massumi and Williams thus highlight the need to take the reality of the affective as an object of cultural studies, precisely because affects not only derive from, but also inform and guide cultural agency and the formation of ideas and beliefs that will eventually be socially institutionalized. The crucial question then remains, of course, how cultural analysis of the social reality of affects would proceed. Given the theoretical emphasis on the exteriority of affects developed from Musils second option for studying appearances in a field of forces, a lot of traditional approaches to individual feelings and their expression become somehow unattractive due to the limitations on the scope of analysis they imply. The somatic approach, localizing the affect in the bodily presence and the swift interactions and reversions it mediates between inside and outside, between the psychological and participatory on the one hand and the social and the positional on the other, furthermore directing interest towards the dimension of the ambient, the expanse of relations that mark out specific situations and the capacities and capabilities inherent herein. In other words, towards the dimension of space. Theorizing affects in terms of exteriority, atmosphere, or ambience: as something you are in rather than something you have, already invests the affective with spatial qualities. It is probably also no coincidence, by the way, that contemporary academic focalization on affects as an important research topic has very much been advocated by sociologists and geographers (not least following Nigel Thrifts groundbreaking writings on the subject) working on techniques of mappings social spaces, rather than by scholars in the historical and aesthetic disciplines. The methodological challenge, thus, clearly seems to be to develop analytical tools and concepts with which we can describe affects as spatial phenomena, or perhaps better: with which we can pinpoint the spatial existence of affects. The idea of adding affects to the list of what can be mapped converges well with the prolific use of mapping techniques in the wake of what has been called the spatial turn in cultural studies. The power of maps to chart not only metric relations but, as Rem Koolhaas once put it, the diagram of everything (Koolhaas, 2004: 20) has been intensively developed to enhance our understanding of the spatial distribution of all sorts of flows, of social relations, of power and authority, of social agency, of modes of imagination and contemplation, and much more. The expanded field of mapping practices is very much dependent on the thriving theories of space throughout recent generations,

updating as it were our ideas of space to match the spatial complexity and malleability of contemporary social life. A good starting point for developing this flexible notion of space could be the distinction proposed by David Harvey (2009: 133ff) between absolute space, relative space and relational space. The two first, absolute and relative space, are quite well known, and also really the only two notions of space that are generally acknowledged and widely understood. Absolute space was invented by the Renaissance. This was the realm of Galileos and Keplers space in which planets could be conceived as bodies in motion and in positional relations to each other space, in other words, where all things have their proper coordinates. The practical usefulness of this notion of space has remained uncontested; it became the space that rendered Newtons mechanics and modern physics feasible as well as the foundations on which Kants critique of pure reason rests and is indeed the space within which we map the distances we experience, a homogenous, theoretically unlimited space on which we may plot every bit of matter with utmost exactitude through three coordinates (x, y, z). From Galileo to GPS, absolute space (or objective space) has set the standard of spatial positionality of everything that is and everything that takes place. The second notion, relative space, may be considered as a reversal of this idea. Here, we are no longer dealing with the space in which events take place, but rather the space the organization of space, and the intuition of space which is produced through the individual event. Relative space is, precisely, relative to a perspective, to the event of seeing and using space in a particular way. This idea of space goes back to more ancient understandings of space, most notably to the notion of place. Place, here, is not just something positional but is also endowed with a more qualitative side, the resonance of all the traditions, narratives and practices it has become imbued with. Furthermore, relative space also became a prominent notion in modern phenomenology, which contributed to shift the focus from our understanding of space to our perception of space and thereby highlighting the experiential relativity of space, extending always from a specific point of view and conditioned by the receptive capacities and inherent prejudices of the beholder. These two notions of space pretty much cover the ways in which we think about space and somehow intuitively conceive of space on an everyday basis and despite the fact that

they are obviously very different, we have learnt to combine them freely and flexibly by locating relative space in absolute space and developing absolute space from relative space, maneuvering freely, as it were, between the map and the territory. But these notions also take us back to the predicament of the ancient cognitive architecture of object and subject, leaving us without any choice but to consider space as either objective or as subjective, and consequently with no real options for transgressing this polarity, which represented the precise challenge should we be able to understand the atmospheric nature of affectivity. This is where Harveys third notion comes in very usefully: that of relational space. To Harvey, relational space is really a category for all the rest, i.e. for that which does not fit into the two first and somehow more straightforward categories, such as the spaces of memories, spaces of dreams, spaces of imagination, and so on, but which nonetheless have a very real and effective importance for our understanding of space. Memory is an interesting case in point. To be sure, one could claim the way in which memory invests space with particular qualities would indeed be an example of a relative space, tainted by a subjective perspective; but if we then add that memory is not just an individual phenomenon, but really more often exists as a collective memory that is culturally produced, inscribed and circulated, then the space of memory transcends the neat polarity of the subjective and the objective: more than just subjective, but also without becoming objective, and not quite objective, but without being squarely subjective. This is thus precisely the merit to the notion of relational space: it outlines a social and cultural construct, a relational distribution of things and ideas, of sensation and imagination, which mark out a very real historical space that cannot be mapped according to the traditional notions of absolute and relative space. The usefulness of the relational space concept very much resides in its simplicity. As an analytical concept, it is directed towards an actual set of effective relations in an environment, and additionally, it specifically focuses on how this distribution of relations constitutes a spatial structure. In so doing, it draws on a very fundamental feature of spatiality, namely that everything spatial is essentially defined by relationality. This very generic definition of spatiality, going back to Leibniz and Kant, would eventually also allow us to consider both absolute space and relative space as relational spaces, i.e. pertaining to the special cases of metric relations and sensual or subjective relations, but

it moreover also invites us to chart all kinds of other relational distributions as well. In particular, it would enable us to gauge relations that are not composed by the same kind of elements, such as, for instance, the metrical relations of absolute space, but also relations between, say, material elements, linguistic forms, haphazard sensations, fragments of historical views, and so forth. In fact, this is the approach to space also suggested by Henri Lefebvre, who insisted that the historical space in which peoples lives unfold should always be considered as a compound space, merging, as he systematically put it, material, symbolic and experiential components. These components do not refer to different spaces but represent different aspects involved in the formation or, as Lefebvre (1991) has it, the production of human space. Space, in this understanding, is essentially a relational space, and lived space always a human participation in the web of relational structures between all sorts of facets that together make up its reality. Clearly, such complex spatial assemblages can be considered in numerous different ways, corresponding to different aspects of lived, human space, and the relational structures they embrace, consequently, apprehended in different ways, momentarily highlighting some lines of the web while ignoring others, depending on attention, receptivity and the directions of agency followed at a given moment. When proposing the term affective spaces, the intention is thus not to single out another particular spatial order, but to focus in on the relational spatiality of lived human experience according to one specific aspect, that is, the question of just which affects are produced in this relational economy. Coming back to the methodological challenge of analyzing affects as autonomous, as something that pertains more to social situations than to individual states of mind, a tentative answer would therefore be to examine how affects exist in the composition of relational spaces. To acknowledge, in other words, that the real relational spaces in which we live, and in the formation of which we take part as agents and participants in social and material situations, have an affective dimension. If affects somehow are there, out there, before they mature as inner sentiments and feelings, it is because they are spatial, virtually present in the blueprint of relational structures in which we express and unfold ourselves as spatial beings. Our interest in affects beyond psychology, in the social life of affectivity or in the historical formation of structures of feeling, following Raymond

Williams once again direct us towards analyzing bodily situations and the different social and material relations underpinning them. What we address here, and this is the important lesson of modern relational geographies, is the spatial being of social existence, inviting us to construe affectivity as a spatial phenomenon. To briefly sketch how such an analysis might work, I would like to evoke two recent novels by John DeLillo and J.G. Ballard, not particular to propose an interpretation of them as literary artworks but rather to show how they in fact interpret two specific historical spaces and their affective infrastructures. DeLillos Falling Man from 2007 is an examination of the reverberations of terror in the urban atmosphere of New York City in the aftermath of 9/11. Some of the challenges of writing this novel had already been formulated in DeLillos 2001 essay In the Ruins of the Future: The writer wants to understand what this day has done to us. () In its desertion of every basis for comparison, the event asserts its singularity. There is something empty in the sky. The writer tries to give memory, tenderness and meaning to all that howling space. We like to think that America invented the future. We are comfortable with the future, intimate with it. But there are disturbances now, in large and small ways, a chain of reconsiderations. Where we live, how we travel, what we think about when we look at our children. For many people, the event has changed the grain of the most routine moment. () What has already happened is sufficient to affect the air around us, psychologically. We are all breathing the fumes of lower Manhattan, where traces of the dead are everywhere, in the soft breeze off the river, on rooftops and windows, in our hair and on our clothes. (DeLillo, 2001) There are a number of important insights in this text, which have in turn been reworked in Falling Man. First of all, it pinpoints the atmospheric nature of the collective shock and outrage: that it affects the air around us. And furthermore, that this affect remains present, not just as a feeling, but through the ways in which it change[s] the grain of the most routine moment. The story of the novel is about a survivor from the Twin Towers who literally climbs out of the ashes and somehow by instinct heads back to his beloved ones, his wife and son. However, by the time of the catastrophe they had already long since been divorced and home but a faint memory; going back to this idea of normalcy, in other words, is not just going back to before the crash, but further back, before the average life-form of a NY corporate worker, into which the catastrophe intervened, was

put in place. Consequently, the novel is not about overcoming and the restoration of what was before, as in much bad 9/11-fiction, but about the reverberation of the event in three peoples lives (the fathers, the mothers and the sons), as they follow their own erratic and indeed diverging pathways. The three protagonists remain affected throughout but DeLillo seems to very consciously avoid any overly easy designation of this affect, such as fear, sense of danger, the feeling your life-form is being contested, vulnerability, and so on. Instead, he examines how the affect actually works as a transfiguration of the grain of the most routine moment, as a monumental and at times almost anaesthetizing defamiliarization of everything known and intuitively taken for granted. Through the protagonists, he diagnoses the affect in the ways in which the life of the city seems to stutter, how sensation becomes myopic and disoriented, how the familiar spaces of everyday life become partly unrecognizable, partly spaces of punctual wonder and strange beauty. Don DeLillo, to be sure, is an uncontested master of detailing those small fissures in the surface of the normal, where the well known breaks up in moments of inconsequential and bereaved contemplation of the ordinary and reveals something monstrous. This is the protagonist walking the city: Keith walked through the park and came out on West 90th Street and it was strange, what he was seeing down the community garden and coming toward him, a woman in the middle of the street, on horseback, wearing a yellow hard hat and carrying a riding crop, bobbing above the traffic, and it took him a long moment to understand that horse and rider had come out of a stable somewhere nearby and were headed toward the bridle path in the park. / It was something that belonged to another landscape, something inserted, a conjuring that resembled for the briefest second some half-seen image only half believed in the seeing, when the witness wonders what has happened to the meaning of things, to tree, street, stone, wind, simple words lost in the falling ash. (DeLillo, 2007: 103) Such a passage reveals the working of affect in its most primitive way. All the relations that make up the innocuous space of this everyday scene are shattered, disfigured, as if struck suddenly with a spell of meaninglessness, and in the same instant, then evoked and reiterating the power that was able to disrupt the solidity of the everyday. It is this very basic logic of the affect that DeLillo keeps developing throughout the novel, the collective state of being affected, of losing balance, of being unable all of a sudden to

read and understand what is around. De Lillos art is that of the still life, of spatial arrangements that stand out clear-cut but nonetheless vacillating in terms of what they might mean. Perception constantly stops dead, pieces of ingoing information that do not carry any meaningful knowledge along, lots of signs, but no signification. She was arguing with herself but it wasnt an argument, just the noise the brain makes (p. 236). The affect hovering over the city effectively subverts the routines and habits of those living there, and much of the novels plot is really about whether it will be possible to recultivate habits sufficiently robust to uphold a human life. The child concentrates on learning to talk only in monosyllables, the mother takes up volunteer aid for Alzheimer patients, in whose company she finds some relief, the father embarks on professional poker rather than going back to his job: they all struggle to obtain a life in the guise of a habit, but eventually never seem really to make it. They remain suspended in the affect in an unnaturally protracted moment of hesitation and disorientation, inhabitants of a city between two breaths, unsure whether it is processing the affect or simply waiting, waiting for the blessing of forgetting. DeLillos novel reads like a map, as a cartographical recording of an affect that resounds and reverberates in the very fabric of the urban space. A similar affective cartography, albeit starting out from a quite different set of parameters, can be found in J.G. Ballards late novels. With the three novels published after 2000, Ballard became increasingly known as an unsurpassed chronicler of his present. Shortly after his death in 2009, his younger colleague Jonathan Lethem wrote an essay on him in the New York Times, praising the stark visionary consistency of the motifs that earned him that rarest of literary awards, an adjective: Ballardian. This term, Ballardian, is now furthermore defined by the Collins English Dictionary as "resembling or suggestive of the conditions described in J. G. Ballards novels and stories, especially dystopian modernity, bleak man-made landscapes and the psychological effects of technological, social or environmental developments." Lethem also calls him a poet of desolate landscapes (Lethem, 2009). The landscapes of Ballards three last novels are the new European urban (or post-urban) designed landscapes of the thriving middle classes. In Super-Cannes from 2000, it is a new-built settlement around a hi-tech industrial production plant, with its innate life

around empty swimming pools, verandas with a view from where nobody views and twin carports made for expensive cars. In Millennium People from 2003, it is a refurbished dockland area in London replete with Range Rovers, kids in expensive public schools and a population of affluent lawyers, doctors and symbol managers. And in Kingdom Come, finally, from 2006, it is the new suburban sprawl in southwest London around Heathrow and M25 with pompous new or refurbished houses with lawns, fountains and flags, interspersed by corporate headquarters behind empty and evergreen lawns and gigantic shopping malls. In Kingdom Come, this new territory of the affluent and hardworking upper middle class is charted by an intruder, a successful advertising agent from London who comes to bury his father who has died under suspicious circumstances. As a professional in advertising, he knows quite a lot about this kind of place (and its potentials for consumption) but not from actually having spent time in the area. Thus, the reader explores this landscape together with the protagonist, as the latter meanders about, following the itineraries of his late father and his acquaintances. The topography of the site is quite simple; framed by the huge and constantly humming transportation infrastructure, there are four different landscape types: the extended sprawl of habitations, the malls, the sports arenas, and the derelict villages overgrown by the ramifying sprawl. And the life form of the area is partitioned along the same lines. In the sprawl, general boredom reigns, only partially kept in check by endless and industrious refurbishment works. The malls and the sports arenas then offer temporary relief from boredom by offering endless opportunities for consumption and for watching violent spectacles, respectively. And when this cocktail of boredom, buying and watching does not bring sufficient relief, the disciplined inhabitants transform into a violent mob and attack the Pakistani restaurants and Polish-owned garages of the villages. Ballard describes an ever more fragile sense of order and an atmosphere where aggression surfaces as a way out for an otherwise blocked propensity for acting. In this environment, as Ballard boldly describes it, consumerism and a new totalitarianism had met by chance in a suburban shopping mall and celebrated a nightmare marriage (Ballard, 2006: 188). Ballards critique of consumerism (where everything good comes with a barcode) as existentially hollow is of course not particularly new. However, he very aptly portrays the logic of frustration as he subtly plays out the perennial substitution of the new with more

of the same in an algorithm neatly spelled out by Rosi Braidotti: In a totally schizophrenic double pull, the consumerist and socially enhanced faith in the new is supposed not only to fit in with, but also actively to induce, the rejection of in-depth changes (Braidotti, 2006: 2). In Kingdom Come, Ballard offers a full-scale mapping of the atmosphere induced by this logic and how it permeates virtually everything that goes on in this slightly futuristic, but still chillingly recognizable settlement. The novel, however, also takes another few steps beyond this casuistic mode. It is narrated in the first person, and throughout large parts of the book, the protagonist and the reader so to speak share the outsiders observation mode, but eventually, and quite strangely, this accord between reader and narrator is somehow uprooted. What happens is that an uncanny amount of unpredictability enters into the universe. First, we experience this through the narrator, as the other characters he encounters inexplicably seem to develop striking inconsistencies in their actions and utterances, switching alliances and agendas in unpredictable ways and thus inconveniently blurring the distinction between friends and foes. This lability adds another layer to the already high-strung affective climate, as if everybody is constantly negotiating some tipping-point and maneuvering somehow blindly among all sorts of stratagems. And further down the road this infection also seems to take grip of the narrator himself, whereby the reader is somehow gradually brought to ask whether the alliance with the narrator is dissolving. This results in quite a powerful reading experience, as a first hand report of a progressive transformation of a consciousness when exposed to the affective climate of this particular place. Both DeLillo and Ballard are experimenting with developing techniques of mapping affective spaces and of recording how spatial being also implies a participation in affective transactions and becomings. As cartographers of affect, they delineate the relational diagrams of spaces with prominent contemporary interest: the city under the spell of terror, and the suburb under the spell of consumerism, and test the affective impact of living in these spaces. By charting affects as appearances in a field of forces, they contribute to the understanding of the contemporary micro-politics of affects and the changing relational geographies underpinning them and thus eventually also to understanding how affective spaces mould our lives and the selves we come to embody.

References Ballard, J.G., Kingdom Come, London: HarperCollins, 2006. Boutang, Yann Moulier, Le Capitalisme Cognitif: La Nouvelle Grande Transformation, Paris: d. Amsterdam, 2007. Braidotti, Rosi, Transpositions, Cambridge: Polity Press, 2006. Butler, Judith, Frames of War, London: Verso, 2009. Deleuze, Gilles, Spinoza. Philosophie Pratique, Paris: Minuit, 1981. DeLillo, Don, In the Ruins of the Future, Harpers Magazine, December 2001. DeLillo, Don, Falling Man, New York: Scribner 2007. Eagleton, Terry, It is not quite true that I have a body, and not quite true that I am one either (review of Peter Brooks Body Work), LRB vol. 15, no 10, 1993. Goethe, J.W., Wilhelm Meisters Apprenticeship, trans. Eric A. Blackall, Princeton: PUP, 1979. Harvey, David, Cosmopolitanism and the Geographies of Freedom, NY: Columbia University Press, 2009. Hauser, Arnold, Sozialgeschichte der Kunst und Literatur, Munich: Beck, 1953. Koolhaas, Rem, Content, Kln: Taschen, 2004. Lefebvre, Henri, The Production of Space, Oxford, UK and Cambridge, MA: Blackwell, 1991 [1974]. Lethem, Jonathan, Poet of Desolate Landscapes, New York Times, September 8, 2009. Lordon, Frdric, Capitalisme, Dsir et Servitude, Paris: La Fabrique, 2010. Massumi, Brian, Parables for the Virtual. Movement, Affect, Sensation, Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2002. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, Le Visible et lInvisible, ed. Claude Lefort, Paris: Gallimard 1965. Musil, Robert, Der Mann ohne Eigenschaften, Hamburg: Rohwolt, 1978. Sartre, Jean-Paul, Ltre et le Nant, Paris: Gallimard, 1943. Thrift, Nigel, Non-Representational Theory, London: Routledge, 2008. Williams, Raymond, Marxism and Literature, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977.

You might also like