Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

The Priority of Democracy: Political Consequences of Pragmatism
The Priority of Democracy: Political Consequences of Pragmatism
The Priority of Democracy: Political Consequences of Pragmatism
Ebook558 pages8 hours

The Priority of Democracy: Political Consequences of Pragmatism

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Why democracy is the best way of deciding how decisions should be made

Pragmatism and its consequences are central issues in American politics today, yet scholars rarely examine in detail the relationship between pragmatism and politics. In The Priority of Democracy, Jack Knight and James Johnson systematically explore the subject and make a strong case for adopting a pragmatist approach to democratic politics—and for giving priority to democracy in the process of selecting and reforming political institutions.

What is the primary value of democracy? When should we make decisions democratically and when should we rely on markets? And when should we accept the decisions of unelected officials, such as judges or bureaucrats? Knight and Johnson explore how a commitment to pragmatism should affect our answers to such important questions. They conclude that democracy is a good way of determining how these kinds of decisions should be made—even if what the democratic process determines is that not all decisions should be made democratically. So, for example, the democratically elected U.S. Congress may legitimately remove monetary policy from democratic decision-making by putting it under the control of the Federal Reserve.

Knight and Johnson argue that pragmatism offers an original and compelling justification of democracy in terms of the unique contributions democratic institutions can make to processes of institutional choice. This focus highlights the important role that democracy plays, not in achieving consensus or commonality, but rather in addressing conflicts. Indeed, Knight and Johnson suggest that democratic politics is perhaps best seen less as a way of reaching consensus or agreement than as a way of structuring the terms of persistent disagreement.

LanguageEnglish
Release dateAug 22, 2011
ISBN9781400840335
The Priority of Democracy: Political Consequences of Pragmatism
Author

Jack Knight

About the AuthorJack Knight was born in Lancashire, in the United Kingdom, and moved to South Yorkshire at the ripe old age of ten. He now lives in a small township with his wife and the small woodland creatures that come to visit them from time to time, an idyllic setting where he writes from an inkwell full of his victims' blood, lavishly spilling it onto the pages for his readers' enjoyment.Outside of work Jack likes eating out, watching the occasional movie and reading. His favourite authors are Richard Laymon and Dean Koontz.

Related to The Priority of Democracy

Related ebooks

Political Ideologies For You

View More

Related articles

Related categories

Reviews for The Priority of Democracy

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    The Priority of Democracy - Jack Knight

    Index

    Preface

    In 1927 John Dewey published The Public and Its Problems in which he complained: Optimism about democracy is to-day under a cloud. This dispirited view, in large part, reflected widespread doubt—doubt Dewey himself did not share—about the capacity of regular men and women to act as democratic citizens. In part, skepticism about democracy reflected general concern for large-scale demographic, technological, and economic change in the late nineteenth and early twentieth century. The despair also had several more proximate causes: a credulous American public (Dewey included) had been persuaded to support a brutal war aimed putatively at securing democracy abroad; the same public endeavored to constitutionalize moral strictures, giving rise to the protracted, ultimately insuperable, tasks of legal monitoring and enforcement that accompanied prohibition; and the same public displayed widespread skepticism—animated to a large extent by religious fundamentalism—not just about this or that scientific finding but about the enterprise of science itself and how it was taught in the public schools. In the face of wartime propaganda, prohibition, and fundamentalist creationism, critics of democracy no doubt felt well warranted in their skepticism.

    One might well say that in very broad strokes, the American political landscape has not changed terribly much in the intervening eight decades. Like Dewey, we confront ongoing, poorly justified military adventures overseas; economic dislocation and rapid technological change; extreme and growing disparities of wealth and income; judicially sanctioned infiltration of those financial resources into politics; and a poorly informed, credulous electorate confronting complex, large-scale, entrenched social, economic, and environmental problems. Like Dewey, we have witnessed the effectiveness of wartime propaganda, the persistence of moralism in politics with its devastating consequences, and a widespread skepticism about science and its findings. There is little in all that to inspire political optimism. Yet, like The Public and Its Problems, this book is a defense of democratic politics. Indeed it is, we think, a robust defense of democracy. While Dewey regularly proclaimed his faith in democracy, we do not embrace that term. It is not that we lack faith in the capacity of regular people to engage in self-government. But we recognize that in order to effectively exercise their capacity, ordinary men and women must be able to rely on the existence of certain material and institutional conditions. In that, too, we take up and extend Dewey’s pragmatist commitment to democratic politics. Although in our day, like his, optimism about democracy remains under a cloud, the proper response, we believe, is not to shrink from but rather to renew our commitment to and engagement in democratic politics.

    Reasonable people may differ about what they think a commitment to democratic politics entails. We emphasize here what we believe to be a fundamental aspect of the democratic project—political and legal institutions that instantiate the practice of democratic decision-making. This follows, in part, from our more general concern with the central importance of institutions, formal and informal, in social life. As pragmatists, we are concerned about the consequences of our choices and actions. Social institutions are one of the most important determinants of those consequences. They coordinate all aspects of our social lives. Without them we would fail in the pursuit of our goals—not only our collective goals but also, to the extent that they rely on the actions of others, our individual life plans. With them we may achieve success, but only when we remain attentive to the various ways in which they affect us and, perhaps more important, to the conditions necessary for us to enjoy the positive benefits of those institutions.

    Other advocates of democracy may place their primary emphasis elsewhere, but we would argue that any compelling attempt to justify democracy must give pride of place to the formal institutions that facilitate democratic governance. As we argue, the formal institutional rules set the terms and conditions of democratic participation and practice and, in doing so, vitally influence the quality and effectiveness of our collective decision making. When, in our efforts to defend democratic politics, we neglect to account for how we will actually implement our most basic values and commitments, for how we will institutionalize the abstract democratic ideal, then we fail to make the most persuasive case for the priority of democracy. Too often we focus on the question of why we should act democratically at the expense of the equally important explanation of how we should do so.

    One final matter bears comment. While our argument is pragmatist, we rely at key junctures on the apparatus of rational choice theory. This confluence will no doubt puzzle more traditional pragmatists and aficionados of rational choice alike. We have two reasons—one critical, one constructive—for proceeding as we do. On the critical side, political theorists typically have marshaled the results of rational choice theories to cast what they take to be grave doubt upon the viability of democracy. Their arguments trade upon particular, contestable interpretations not only of democracy but of what various families of rational choice models are useful for and what they tell us. One principle subtext of this book is a more or less systematic challenge to those interpretations. We believe that we can develop that challenge best by operating on intellectual terrain that such skeptics themselves will find conducive. In other words, we wish to assume the burden of argument and show why skeptics about democratic politics and institutions place inordinate faith in the results of rational choice theory. This is not because we find rational choice analysis problematic, but because we interpret it in ways that, while nonstandard, are, we think, persuasive.

    On a more constructive note, our own interpretation of rational choice models itself is inspired by Dewey’s concerns in the opening chapter of The Public and Its Problems. There, Dewey discusses the difficulties involved in discerning the consequences, especially the indirect consequences, of interdependent action, and he does so in the context of reflections on observation, causality, and interpretation. The difficulties that preoccupy Dewey confront both political agents and social scientists. He concludes by holding out the need for a method which proceeds on the basis of the interrelations of observable acts and their results. From our perspective, the related families of rational choice models afford just such a method. They provide an instrument that is useful for analyzing the interdependencies that call publics into existence—interdependencies that, especially when they go unrecognized or unexamined, generate the problems that publics rely on democratic politics to surmount.

    It has taken us a long time to write this book. Over the course of many years we have, jointly and individually, incurred many debts. We would like to acknowledge those debts and thank those who have supported us in our work. We first acknowledge some joint debts and then take turns extending some individual appreciation.

    Joint Acknowledgments. We have, singly or together, presented material from this book to a large number of audiences in various departmental seminars and conference panels. These opportunities almost invariably generated healthy skepticism among members of the audience and, thereby, useful comments, questions, and suggestions. We will not try to single out particular individuals but instead simply acknowledge the extent to which we have benefited from engagement with colleagues over the years.

    We spent the 2002–2003 academic year as Visiting Scholars at the Russell Sage Foundation. Eric Lomazoff provided extremely helpful research assistance during our year at Russell Sage. By the end of that time, we had a nearly complete draft of the manuscript. We both also realized that the draft was inadequate and required substantial reorganization. We were right. But the resulting delays as we reworked the manuscript have tried patience all around. We are grateful to the foundation for funding our work. And we thank Suzanne Nichols and Eric Wanner for their forbearance as we worked things out.

    At Princeton University Press, Chuck Myers has been an efficient, encouraging, and patient editor. He has overseen the entire process, from coaxing us to complete the manuscript through the production of the book in what we can only describe as a masterful way.

    We published a condensed version of some arguments from the book in On the Priority of Democracy: A Pragmatist Approach to Political-Economic Institutions and the Burden of Justification (American Political Science Review, 2007). We thank the American Political Science Association and Cambridge University Press for permission to use reworked versions of that material here.

    Jack Knight. When working on a project that takes as long as this one has, one inevitably taxes the patience and goodwill of many friends. Or, at least, that is my excuse for many contrarian moments over the last several years. Some deserve special mention for their good nature and support: James Bohman, John Bowen, Randy Calvert, Ingrid Creppell, Alfred Darnell, Lee Epstein, Henry Farrell, Wayne Fields, Marilyn Friedman, Mitu Gulati, Clarissa Hayward, Mark Hornung, Ellen Kennedy, Margaret Levi, Susan Liebell, Frank Lovett, Ian MacMullen, Larry May, Gary Miller, Douglass North, Sunita Parikh, Andrew Rehfeld, Norman Schofield, Melissa Schwartzberg, Itai Sened, Kit Wellman, and James Wertsch. I also want to thank many people in the administration and staff at both Washington University in St. Louis and Duke University for helping me with support and assistance during the time that I was working on this project.

    I met Jim Johnson in the fall of 1979 in Hyde Park. We began a conversation about pragmatism and democracy that was challenging and stimulating in an uncommon way. Anyone would be lucky to have had that intellectual experience for a short period of time. I have been fortunate enough to have had it for over thirty years. This book is, in an important way, merely a statement of where we stand in that discussion as of 2011.

    My greatest personal debt is to Margaret Louise Brown. As a pragmatist I can only imagine what the consequences would have been for me if I had not settled down and finally finished this book. Even the most tolerant person has her limits. She has always believed in the value of this project, even on those days on which I questioned it myself. Without her support and encouragement I am sure that I would have set this project aside long before it was finished. Margaret Louise and I have been true partners in every endeavor we have undertaken over the last twenty years. I look forward to many more.

    I started this book in the years before my son, Benjamin Brown Knight, was born. He is now seven. During those seven years, the social, political, and economic events that have occurred in the world would challenge even the strongest commitments to democratic self-government. But my commitment has not diminished even if the contours of that commitment may have changed. I am still not sure about that. What I am clear about is that my perspective on the underlying questions in this book has changed significantly since his birth. I guess that it is trivial to say that as a parent I now assess the implications of social events in terms of the future implications for his life as opposed to mine. There are days in which I have serious concerns about that future, but they only arise in the context of more general concerns about the prospects for real and vibrant democratic politics in the United States and around the world. I began this book for me, but I finished it for Benjamin.

    Jim Johnson. My longest-standing debt is to my parents, Roy and Janet Johnson, who long ago put aside their qualms and supported my, to them nearly incomprehensible, decision to pursue an academic career. I thank them for that. My sister Cindy, her husband Fred, and their now-grown children Matthew and Amelia have tolerated my inscrutability and preoccupation. Seeing this book might make them wonder about me even more. But hopefully it will help them see what I think is important.

    By the time this book appears, I will have taught at the University of Rochester for two decades. I thank two deans—Thomas LeBlanc and Peter Lennie—for funds that have supported my research on the book. During my time at Rochester, the staff of the Political Science Department—Pamm Ferguson, Lisa Zimmerman, Donna Smith, and Kelly Corbett Wicks—have been unfailingly helpful. I thank them for the many ways they have made it easier to do my job. For four years, I also had the good fortune to work with Linda Lindenfelser. Her hard work, good humor, and kind words did not just make the task of being a journal editor easier; they made it possible. Finally, at different times Caroline Kobick and Heather Winegrad provided welcome help with research and with preparing the manuscript.

    During those two decades, I also have experienced considerable mayhem in my personal life. This is not the place to either recount the details or identify the cast of characters. I mention those troubles only because, for a significant portion of that time Susan Horwitz proved to be a terrific shrink. Susan listened carefully, told me when I needed to cut the bullshit and take responsibility, pushed hard to help me see the very many points where responsibility rested with others—usually places where I had neither any control nor hope of it—and helped me figure out how to navigate all that. She also laughed easily, talked about the travails of juggling research with seeing clients, bragged about her students and her own grown children, and gushed about her baby grandsons. I am sure she would be pleased to see this book finally appear in print. Susan died suddenly in the Fall of 2009. So, while my thanks come too late, they are no less heartfelt. I could not have kept working on this project without Susan’s insight and support.

    Three other people in particular deserve my special thanks. The first is Robert Westbrook, my colleague in the Department of History at Rochester. He has encouraged my interest in pragmatism and, twice, has kindly allowed me to sit in on his graduate seminar on the topic. It is impossible to overstate my respect for Robb or the influence he has had on my thinking.

    The second person is my friend and coconspirator, Jack Knight. From our first days in Pick Hall to the present, Jack has been not just an unfailing friend but a model intellectual colleague. Over the years I often worried aloud to him that perhaps he and I are the only living creatures who might agree about some point, political or theoretical. At this juncture I worry more when we disagree! This book is, from my perspective, a joint project in the true sense. There are very few sentences in what follows that might be attributed to either of us alone.

    The third person I want to single out is Susan Orr. I will say only that we share our lives. She has been steadfast through the cold weather, the hard work, and the mayhem. For that I am grateful. By the time this book appears, we hopefully will have set off on a whole new, exciting adventure together. I look forward to that with pleasure.

    When you look at the big picture, I am a lucky man. I have three sons. Nearly anything I say about my boys and their profound effect on me will be inadequate. Simply put, they are the love of my life. And they have shown me how important it is to keep one’s eye on the consequences and how to tell the difference between those that are important and those that are not. The worst of my personal mayhem, by far, came in April 2007 when my middle son Jeffrey died at age 14. Jeff was as smart and talented and good-natured a son as a father could ask for. Sometimes his goofiness drove me crazy. I miss him every single day and wish he were here to hold this book in his hands. My youngest son, August, was born in February 2006. He is a sweet, bright, mischievous little boy who, to my amazement, wakes each morning with a grin. At this point, at least, he rightly is oblivious to my obsessions with the politics and theory of democracy. I am sure that will change soon enough. Watching August grow is a continuing delight. Finally, my oldest son Douglas has grown to be a decent, accomplished young man. He has navigated the foibles of adults in his life (me included) and endured his brother’s death with remarkable strength and maturity. I admire him more than he can imagine. I also am pretty sure he figured he’d never see the day that this book would appear.

    I dedicate this book to my three wonderful sons.

    PART ONE

    Chapter 1

    Preliminaries

    I. Preliminaries

    Politics, in large part, is a response to diversity. It reflects a seemingly incontrovertible condition—any imaginable human population is heterogeneous across multiple, overlapping dimensions, including material interests, moral and ethical commitments, and cultural attachments. The most important implication of this diversity is that disagreement and conflict are unavoidable. This is, in part, not only because the individuals and groups who constitute any population are diverse in the ways just suggested but because that diversity is irreducible. There simply is no neutral institutional arrangement that will accommodate their competing demands and projects without leaving some remainder over which they still disagree. But the inevitability of disagreement and conflict also partly reflects the fact that precisely as members of a relevant population, those individuals and groups are commonly, as it were, stuck with one another. Their fates are highly, irrevocably interdependent. Thus, despite their diversity and the discord to which it gives rise, they require some means of coordinating their ongoing social and economic interactions. For this, they need, most importantly, social institutions. More specifically, in their efforts to coordinate in mutually beneficial ways, they require a set of institutional arrangements consisting of everything from the most decentralized institutional mechanisms, like informal norms, practices, and conventions, to a wide range of decentralized (e.g., markets) and centralized (e.g., government) formal institutions. Under these circumstances of discord and interdependence, politics largely consists in deep, persistent contests over the contours and distributive implications of these shared institutional arrangements.¹

    Institutions are sets of rules that emerge from and subsequently structure social and political interaction. They are persistent means of coordinating ongoing social, economic, and political activity. And typically they have a systemic quality such that in any particular circumstances, what we call an institutional arrangement will hang together in a more or less coherent, if more or less arbitrary, and more or less contested fashion. Institutional rules often demand that individuals act in ways that run, wholly or partly, counter to their immediate or even longer-term interests, commitments, and attachments. They therefore must specify not simply what can be done, by and to whom, for what purposes, and when but also what happens when the rules are breached and who decides whether a breach has occurred.

    On this account, institutions ultimately must be self-enforcing—that is, they must rest on the mutual expectations of the relevant participants.² For most forms of social interaction, there will typically be several, perhaps many, alternative and feasible ways to institutionalize that interaction. For example, if we want to establish an institutional framework to coordinate the multiplicity of social interactions involved in the production and distribution of health care, there are several types of arrangements that could accomplish it. Each will differ in the degree to which they rely on decentralized, as opposed to centralized, mechanisms. In such situations, we encounter further unavoidable sources of disagreement. Institutional arrangements are indeterminate in at least two ways. They are indeterminate in the sense that they represent arbitrary outcomes of strategic interactions. Given that there are alternative ways of institutionalizing social and economic affairs, relevant individuals and groups will endorse arrangements that they expect to operate over time in ways that favor their own interests, commitments, and attachments. They also are indeterminate in their operation insofar as the individuals and groups for whom they are relevant will differ over time about what the rules mean, whether and when they are being followed or breached, who is to decide such matters, and so on. Here again, involved parties will seek to resolve such interpretive disputes to their own advantage.³

    The view we sketch here clearly converges with the way others portray the circumstances of politics.⁴ It just as clearly departs from the views of others who hope to distance themselves from the sort of political theory that presumes conflict and competition as characteristic modes of interaction.⁵ That said, people confronting the circumstances of politics on our view share a judgment or recognition or assessment that even as violence, coercion, and force constitute the ubiquitous backdrop to politics, they do not afford effective means of coordinating ongoing interactions. In this sense, these circumstances are themselves something of a tenuous achievement in the absence of which social actors might adopt one of (at least) two broad alternative strategies. The first would be exit, whether individual (via emigration) or collective (via secession). The second is violence (e.g., ethnic cleansing, genocide) aimed at eliminating or expelling others whose interests, commitments, and attachments animate projects that appear threatening or even just inconvenient.

    At this juncture, a skeptic might respond by noting that the historical record is replete with instances in which people adopted either of these two alternatives. We concede the point but suggest the views we advance hardly are unique in being susceptible to the challenge posed by the well-documented willingness of individuals and groups to fundamentally abandon politics in favor of exit or violence. The skeptical view is a challenge to any general argument about the normative significance of political-economic institutional arrangements. It raises a general question: What might persuade people to eschew direct recourse to violence and coercion and to accept institutionalized ways of resolving conflict and achieving cooperation? Our answer to this question is that democratic politics, and especially reliance on democratic institutional arrangements, afford the best prospect for doing so.

    John Dewey’s perspective on the relationship between the use of force and the use of democratic arrangements is especially informative in this regard. Dewey acknowledged that force was a fundamental characteristic of social activity, asserting that [n]o ends are accomplished without the use of force.⁶ From this premise, he argued that the important social questions involved how force is marshaled and employed in the pursuit of social cooperation. The relevant criterion was the relative efficiency and economy of the expenditure of force as a means to an end. Thus, what is justly objected to as violence or undue coercion is a reliance upon wasteful and destructive means of accomplishing results.

    For Dewey, institutional arrangements like democracy and the rule of law offered a practical and collectively beneficial alternative to the use of violence.If law or rule is simply a device for securing such a distribution of forces as keeps them from conflicting with one another, the discovery of a new social arrangement is the first step in substituting law for war.⁹ In fact, the benefits of institutional solutions to conflict that avoid the use of violence play a fundamental role in Dewey’s argument in support of democracy:

    Democracy is the belief that even when needs and ends or consequences are different for each individual, the habit of amicable cooperation—which may include, as in sport, rivalry and competition—is itself a priceless addition to life. To take as far as possible every conflict which arises—and they are bound to arise—out of the atmosphere and medium of force, of violence as a means of settlement into that of discussion and of intelligence is to treat those who disagree—even profoundly—with us as those from whom we may learn, and in so far, as friends. A genuinely democratic faith is faith in the possibility of conducting disputes, controversies and conflicts as cooperative undertakings in which both parties learn by giving the other a chance to express itself, instead of having one party conquer by forceful suppression of the other—a suppression which is none the less one of violence when it takes place by psychological means of ridicule, abuse, intimidation, instead of by overt imprisonment or in concentration camps.¹⁰

    Yet, few if any have followed Dewey’s lead in adopting this relatively unromantic view of democratic politics. Normative political theorists tend to ignore or assume away the challenge posed by those who would repudiate politics.¹¹ There tends to be a common assumption that our debates about the normative legitimacy of democratic decision making, as well as other types of institutions, take place exclusively among participants already committed to the nonviolent resolution of disagreements and differences. And even here we admit that this challenge will not be the primary focus of our argument. Nonetheless, we feel that our emphasis on the persistence and ubiquity of disagreement and conflict gives politics more room in our discussion than is to be found in most normative theories. And it will allow us to return later, in the spirit of Dewey’s analysis, to the question of whether the institutional argument we advance—if successfully implemented—would diminish the likelihood that significant actors would opt for nonpolitical means and, crucially, what would happen if it did not.

    II. Institutional Pluralism

    As we have said, any population inhabiting the circumstances of politics as we have sketched them can avail itself of a plurality or range of feasible institutional forms. In addition to markets and democratic decision-making procedures, this includes, but is not limited to, bureaucracy, adjudication through courts, private associations, economic hierarchies, and social norms. And, of course, these institutional mechanisms, which themselves come in different varieties or forms, also need to be combined in various ways into what we will call institutional arrangements. Once we recognize this plurality, the task of choosing which institutions would best coordinate our social interactions in any particular setting appears quite daunting. This in turn raises the difficult task of discerning how, in such circumstances, any heterogeneous constituency, with its diverse and often conflicting interests, values, and commitments, might determine which array of institutional forms to use to coordinate ongoing interactions across various social domains. We offer some examples in the next section. It is, in any case, likely that members of the population in question will disagree pointedly and legitimately on this matter. In other words, the choice of which institutional form or combination of forms to rely on in which domains is a political problem whose resolution in any given circumstances will be contested.

    Determining which institutional arrangement is appropriate for which purposes turns out to be a very complex task. As standard textbook accounts make clear, in the case of markets, for example, any form of institution will operate effectively and thus generate normatively attractive outcomes only under particular (and, in principle, specifiable) conditions. Not only will the effectiveness with which any institution operates be a function of the extent to which these conditions in fact obtain (e.g., the structural and participatory conditions necessary for effective market competition), it may well be a function of social and cultural norms that characterize any particular society.¹² Thus, in any particular context, the task of institutional creation involves not only the selection of one among several available institutional forms but also the identification of mechanisms needed to monitor whether the conditions necessary for effective institutional performance are being adequately fostered and sustained.

    This point is general. It does not apply only to the selection or design of economic institutions. The effectiveness of any type of institution will be largely a function of the conditions in which it operates. This remains obscured because social scientists have undertaken considerably less systematic analysis of the preconditions for the effective performance of institutions of democratic, bureaucratic, or judicial decision making than has been undertaken on economic transactions in markets. Nonetheless, the task of institutionalizing more centralized arrangements requires that we make a commitment to establishing and maintaining our best understanding of the conditions that make bureaucracy or democratic governance or courts effective in achieving the goals we impute to them.

    This obviously places a considerable burden on the members of any society in terms of information and knowledge about institutional performance and effects. On our account, this is where experimentalism emerges as central to politics. Institutional experimentation is a useful instrument for generating knowledge about the effectiveness of institutions in various social contexts.¹³ Theoretical analysis can make important contributions to our understanding of issues of institutional performance, but it alone cannot provide definitive answers to questions regarding the actual effects of adopting one or another institution. Such knowledge will reliably emerge only from the cumulative experience of using for various purposes the various institutions at our disposal. We thus need to be able to rely on the lessons such experience affords us. In the end, we will trust or value experimental outcomes insofar as they emerge under proper conditions, and we must therefore expend considerable effort in establishing and monitoring those conditions.

    The importance of proper conditions highlights the fact that experimentalism is itself an institutional choice. Institutional experimentalism will generate useful knowledge only insofar as the conditions are in place to let the experimental process itself operate in effective ways. To foster and maintain these conditions, we require some kind of institutional framework of monitoring and assessment. Here the logic of institutional experimentation starts to resemble an infinite regress of institutions and conditions and meta-institutions and meta-conditions, and so forth. Yet, in this way, it nonetheless clarifies the task before us: to avoid the regress, we must identify some institutional arrangement (or set of arrangements) that can serve as a mechanism for (1) coordinating effective institutional experimentation, (2) monitoring and assessing effective institutional performance for the range of institutions available in any society, and, most importantly, (3) monitoring and assessing its own ongoing performance. Our argument, unsurprisingly, is that we should accord priority to democracy precisely to the extent to which it is adept at performing these tasks.

    III. Examples and Comparisons

    We speak throughout this book of institutional pluralism or diversity. On the view that we advance, institutions consist of sets of rules that emerge from and subsequently structure social and political interaction. They are persistent, systematic means of coordinating ongoing social, economic, and political activity. Institutions specify what can be done, by and to whom, for what purposes, and when, as well as what happens when the rules are breached and who decides whether they are. Recognizing institutional pluralism simply means grasping that in any given instance, there may well be various ways to structure ongoing social, economic, or political interaction. Moreover, there typically is no general criterion for deciding among the sets of institutional rules on offer.

    Given the problem of establishing, monitoring, and assessing ways of coordinating ongoing interactions in various domains, consider just a small handful of the institutional arrangements we might adopt for just a limited number of purposes.

    Economic Exchange. In many instances, a population will confront the choice between trying to regularize commercial transactions by creating and sustaining a market for particular goods and services or trying to block such transactions. For instance, the population might confront the problem of dealing with the selling and buying of votes. It might create a market in votes, or it might adopt the secret ballot as an institutional mechanism that can effectively block such exchanges by preventing voters from revealing to potential buyers how they cast their vote.¹⁴

    The primary point of the secret ballot is to prohibit trafficking in the good altogether.¹⁵ In other instances, a population may want to facilitate the availability of some crucially important, scarce good or service and thus face the problem of whether or not to have recourse to markets for that purpose. In other words, it wants to allow exchanges but not allow them to be commercial in the sense that they involve buying and selling. Consider, for instance, human blood.¹⁶ A population might opt to allow for voluntary contributions (gifts) of blood for medical purposes and establish an official agency to collect, process, and distribute it. Or it might encourage markets in which blood is procured and circulated via commercial transactions and distributed by private entities, whether they be for-profit business corporations or not-for-profit agencies like the Red Cross.

    Distribution of the Franchise. Any democratic institutional arrangement confronts the problem of how to distribute voting rights. If we focus solely on nation-states, it turns out that participation is partitioned across multiple dimensions. Virtually all countries exclude individuals under some minimum age (usually, but not always, eighteen) and those with a documented mental disability. But while there is imperfect convergence on those exclusionary rules, there is more or less wide cross-national divergence on whether voters must be citizens, whether they must reside in the country, whether they must reside in the electoral district in which they vote, and whether prison inmates can vote.¹⁷ In short, even if we set aside variation over time, the rules governing inclusion and exclusion from this minimal political right differ considerably.

    Constitutional Politics. A central feature of many contemporary constitutions is some form of separation of powers among legislative, executive, and judicial branches. Such arrangements inevitably generate problems of what to do in cases of disagreement or conflict among branches. Such conflict might be resolved by force (e.g., a coup) or by any of a range of political gambits (e.g., impeachment or defunding). Either manner of dispute resolution could evolve into an informal norm to govern ongoing interbranch interactions. But such conflict might also be resolved by accommodation. Among the most common forms of the latter is the institution of judicial review, which affords constitutional courts the prerogative of ruling on the legality of acts of the executive and/or legislature.¹⁸ But even if judicial review either emerges informally or is intentionally adopted, a range of possibilities remains; judicial review can itself take different forms.¹⁹

    Democratic Decision Making. Judicial review is rightly viewed as antimajoritarian and therefore as nondemocratic. We sidestep the ongoing debates on that point. Instead we simply point out that democratic polities often incorporate a range of submajority voting rules into their decision-making institutions. Such a rule authorizes (i) a predefined numerical minority within a designated voting group (ii) to change the status quo (not merely to prevent change) (iii) regardless of the distribution of other votes in the body.²⁰ Just in the context of the U.S. federal government, the following examples meet these criteria:

    The Journal Clause which allows one-fifth of the legislators present in either House of Congress to call for a roll call vote;

    The discharge rule in the House of Representatives, which (at various points, although not today) has permitted a specified minority of legislators to force bills out of committee for consideration on the floor;

    Senate Rule XXII, under which a cloture petition is valid when signed by sixteen Senators;

    The Seven Member Rule under which a minority of designated committees in the House and Senate can require the executive branch to divulge information;

    House Rule XI, which entitles committee minorities to call witnesses at hearings;

    The famous Rule of Four that allows four Justices to grant a writ of certiorari and thereby put a case on the Supreme Court’s agenda.²¹

    So, not only is there, as is commonly recognized, a variety of voting rules that incorporate the principle of majority rule, there are a number of operative voting mechanisms that make no pretense of so doing.

    Property Rights and Common Pool Resources. Markets are not adept at providing or distributing public goods, that is, goods characterized by joint supply and nonexcludability.²² Neither are they useful for coordinating interactions on what are called common-pool resources, which consist in a natural or man-made resource system that is sufficiently large as to make it costly (but not impossible) to exclude potential beneficiaries from obtaining benefits from its use.²³ Pertinent examples here are fisheries, irrigation systems, grazing lands, and forests. Given such a resource, a population might want to establish an official, more or less centralized institution to monitor its use and enforce restrictions on those who use it. In some contexts, such a centralized solution may be appropriate, but there are many reasons why a population might deem a more local, less centralized arrangement preferable.²⁴ Having reached that conclusion, however, the population still confronts a choice between relying on some variety of privatization and one or another regime of common property. In other words, a population deciding on how to govern a common pool resource faces a complex problem. Instead of there being a single solution to a single problem . . . many solutions exist to cope with many different problems.²⁵ Neither the state nor a regime of private property rights is always and everywhere appropriate to the governance of common-pool resources. There are other options.²⁶

    These are just a few examples of situations where institutional diversity makes itself felt. We might well extend the catalog but believe we have made the basic point. Rather than offer more examples, we now briefly want to situate our approach to the matter of institutional pluralism in the context of some provocative recent research that also addresses the problems it raises.

    The studies we have in mind are Democracy and Knowledge, by classicist Josiah Ober, and One Economics, Many Recipes, by political economist Dani Rodrik. These works offer robust defenses of democratic practices and institutions in terms of their consequences for macro-level performance. Ober aims to explain the success of Athens relative to other Greek poleis in terms of political-economic and military competitiveness. Rodrik analyzes the factors that account for economic growth, and thereby political-economic development, cross-nationally. Despite their seemingly divergent preoccupations the books share several features. Both Ober and Rodrik recognize the exigencies of inferring from particular evidence—whether case-based or statistical studies—to broader conclusions regarding political and economic institutions.²⁷ Both promote the importance of experiment in face of the tendency to premise institutional analysis on formal blueprint designs.²⁸ And both gesture toward a pragmatist justification for their arguments.²⁹

    For both Ober and Rodrik, democratic institutions are crucially important. Both focus on the capacity of democratic institutions to coordinate and communicate socially dispersed or distributed knowledge in the face of difficult, persistent, large-scale problems or social, economic, and political interaction. Ober attributes the relative success of Athens to the ways its democratic arrangements facilitated the aggregation, alignment and codification of useful knowledge, while Rodrik argues that economic growth, and hence economic development, requires reliable intuitions for processing and aggregating local knowledge and insists that democratic institutions are the most effective mechanism for accomplishing that task.³⁰

    As will become clear, we find this general line of argument congenial. Yet we think it is, by turns, troubling and incomplete. We find the arguments Ober and Rodrik advance troubling to the extent that they tend toward a functionalist account in which political institutions emerge because they are efficient or are market supporting.³¹ Indeed, if institutions—including markets—are themselves public goods, and if we assume in our explanatory account that agents are, if not opportunistically self-regarding, then not naively other regarding either, surely there is no reason to assume that those agents will be motivated to contribute to the provision or maintenance of that public good.³² If, as Ober reasonably suggests at various points, political agents will avail themselves of the opportunity to use the system in ways that will promote their own personal and partial interests to the detriment of the interests of the less powerful or the general interest or, conversely, if institutions are susceptible to being exploited by strategic actors for socially unproductive purposes, what leads us to believe that in setting up those institutions in the first place, those same agents will set aside narrow preoccupations and the advantages of power to promote the general welfare or collective good?³³ We offer a realist account of institutional emergence and change that makes no such presumption and that depicts institutions as by-products of bargains between self-interested but differentially situated actors. And we argue that that account raises a serious burden of justification for anyone who embraces it.

    We find the arguments Ober and Rodrik advance incomplete in the following sense. The claim, which Rodrik makes a running theme, that democratic institutions . . . can be viewed as metainstitutions that help society make appropriate selections from the available menu of economic institutions partially anticipates the argument we advance in this book.³⁴ While Ober does not state his case quite so directly, his analysis of Athenian democratic institutions rides heavily on examples of how they enabled Athenians to adopt especially effective political-economic institutions and practices (say, the owl currency or the physical design of public spaces). Yet—quite properly, given their own substantive preoccupations—they offer no systematic account of how democracy operates, in Rodrik’s sense, as a metainstitution. That said, if they are to be fully persuasive, the arguments that Ober and Rodrik advance presuppose the case for the priority of

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1