You are on page 1of 381

The Work of Sartre

BY THE SAME AUTHOR

Satire and Reality, Szpirodalmi Knyvkiad, Budapest 1955


La rivolta degli intellettuali in Ungheria, Einaudi 1958 Attila Jzsef e larte moderna, Lerici 1964 Marxs Theory of Alienation, Merlin Press 1970 The Necessity of Social Control, Merlin Press 1971 Aspects of History and Class Consciousness (ed.), Routledge 1971 Lukcss Concept of Dialectic, Merlin Press 1972 Neocolonial Identity and Counter-Consciousness: The Work of Renato Constantino (ed.), Merlin Press 1978 The Work of Sartre: Search for Freedom, Harvester Wheatsheaf 1979 Philosophy, Ideology and Social Science, Harvester Wheatsheaf 1986 The Power of Ideology, Harvester Wheatsheaf 1989 Beyond Capital: Toward a Theory of Transition, Merlin Press 1995 Lalternativa alla societ del capitale: Socialismo o barbarie, Punto Rosso, 2000 Socialism or Barbarism: From the American Century to the Crossroads, Monthly Review Press, 2001 A educao para alm do capital, Boitempo Editorial 2005 O desafio e o fardo do tempo histrico, Boitempo Editorial 2007 The Challenge and Burden of Historical Time, Monthly Review Press 2008 A crise estrutural do capital, Boitempo Editorial, 2009 The Structural Crisis of Capital, Monthly Review Press, 2009 Social Structure and Forms of Consciousness: Vol. 1, The Social Determination of Method, Monthly Review Press 2010 Vol. 2, The Dialectic of Structure and History, Monthly Review Press 2011

The Work of Sartre


Search for Freedom and the Challenge of History
by ISTVN MSZROS

MONTHLY REVIEW PRESS

New York

Copyright 2012 by Istvn Mszros All Rights Reserved Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Mszros, Istvn, 1930The work of Sartre : search for freedom and the challenge of history / by Istvn Mszros. [Expanded ed.]. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references (pp. 331, 357) and index. ISBN 978-1-58367-292-1 (pbk. : alk. paper) ISBN 978-1-58367-293-8 (cloth : alk. paper) 1. Sartre, Jean-Paul, 1905-1980. I. Title. B2430.S34M42 2012 194dc23 2012026841

Monthly Review Press 146 West 29th Street, Suite 6W New York, New York 10001 www.monthlyreview.org 5 4 3 2 1

Contents
Preface to the Expanded Edition . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9 Introduction to the First Edition . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15

PA R T O N E

The Unity of Life and Work: Outline of Sartres Development 1The Writer and His Situation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 33 2Philosophy, Literature and Myth . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 47 3From The Legend of Truth to a True Legend: Phases of Sartres Development . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 67

PA R T T W O

Search for Freedom 4Search For the Individual: The Early Works . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 91 5Freedom and Passion: The World of Being and Nothingness . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 143 A Note on Being and Nothingness . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 217

PA R T T H R E E

The Challenge of History Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 225 6Material and Formal Structures of History: Critique of Sartres Conception of Dialectical Reason and Historical Totalization . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 239 7Lvy-Strauss Against Sartre . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 279 8The Role of Scarcity in Historical Conceptions . . . . . . . . . . . 295 9The Missing Dimension . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 307 Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 325

Notes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 331 Index . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 375

For Donate lla

A M A N C A R R IE S A WHOL E E POCH WITHIN HIM, JU ST AS A WAVE CAR R IE S THE WHOL E OF T HE SEA.

The Purposes of Writing

I D E P E ND ON LY ON THOSE WHO D E PE ND ONLY O N G O D, A ND I D O N OT B E L IEVE IN GOD . TRY AND SORT T HIS O UT !

Words

I T I S NOT M Y FAULT IF R E AL ITY IS M ARXIST.

Sartre Quoting Che Guevara

TH E FUNDAM E NTAL QUE STION IS : W H AT HAVE YOU M ADE OF YOUR L IFE?

La Question

Preface to the Expanded Edition


Radical Philosophyin an interview published in its Number 62asked me the question: You met Sartre in 1957. Why did you decide to write a book about him? This was my answer:
I N A P R IL 1992 T HE QUARTERLY JO URNA L

I always felt that Marxists owed a great deal to Sartre because we live in an age in which the power of capital is overbearing, where, significantly, the resounding platitude of politicians is that there is no alternative, whether you think of Mrs Thatcher, or also of Gorbachev, who endlessly repeated the same until he had to find out, like Mrs Thatcher, that after all there had to be an alternative to both of them. But it goes on and on, and if you look around and think of how both Conservative and Labour politicians talk, they always talk about there is no alternative, and the underlying pressures are felt everywhere. Sartre was a man who always preached the diametrical opposite: there is an alternative, there must be an alternative; you as an individual have to rebel against this power, this monstrous power of capital. Marxists on the whole failed to voice that side. I dont say that you have to become therefore an existentialist in order to face it, but there is no one in the last fifty years of philosophy and literature who tried to hammer it home with such singlemindedness and determination as Sartre did: the necessity that there has to be a rebellion against the wisdom of there is no alternative and there must

10

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

be an individual participation in it. I dont embrace Sartres philosophical ideas but I fully share the aim. How you realize that aim is up to you in the context of your own approach; but the aim is something without which we wont get anywhere. Sartre today in France is a very embarrassing person even to mention. Why? Because what happened is that in the name of privatism and individualism they have totally sold out to the powers of repression, a capitulation to the forces of there is no alternative, and that is why Sartre is a terrible reminder. When you also look into the background of the people we are talking about, post-modernists of a great variety, they very often were politically engaged people. But their engagement was skin-deep. Some of these people, around 1968, were more Maoist than the extreme Maoists in China, and now they have embraced the right in a most enthusiastic way; or they were in the French Socialism or Barbarism group and have become the peddlers of the most stupid platitudes of post-modernity. What these people have lost is their frame of reference. In France intellectual life used to be dominated in one way or another by the Communist Party. That goes also for Sartre who tried criticizing it from outside and pushing it in a direction which he advocated until he had to come to the conclusion that work in collaboration with the Communist Party is both necessary and impossible; which is a terrible, bitter dilemma. He said that at the time of the Algerian war when the role of the Communist Party was absolutely disgraceful. Necessary because you need a movement to oppose the repressive force of the state; and impossible, because look what that movement is like. What happened, of course, was the disintegration of the French Communist Party like several other parties of the Third International in the last two decades. And with the sinking of that big ship in relation to which the French intellectuals for a long time defined themselves in one way or another, here are these intellectuals left behind: the ship has disappeared and they find themselves in their self-inflated rubber dinghies throwing little darts at each other. Not a very reassuring sight: and they are not going to get out of it by simply fantasizing about some individuality which doesnt exist; because true individuality is inconceivable without a community with which you relate yourself and define yourself.

In this sense the relevance of Sartres uncompromising message about the necessary alternative to there is no alternative is greater today than ever before. That is so even if Sartres passionate advocacy could be spelled out,

P R E FACE TO T HE E XPAN D ED ED ITIO N

11

right from his early writings onwards, only in the form of a radical negation of the existent. Already way back in 1939, in his beautiful essay on the novel by Faulkner, The Sound and the Fury, Sartre insisted that Faulkners despair precedes his metaphysics: for him, as for us all, the future is barred. Everything we see, everything we live through, incites us to say: It cannot last, and meanwhile change isnt even conceivable except in the form of a cataclysm. We live in an epoch of impossible revolutions, and Faulkner employs his extraordinary artistry to describe this world which is dying of old age, and our suffocation. I love his art and I dont believe in his metaphysics: a barred future is still a future. The stubborn determination with which Sartre could carry on defying all odds against those who were (and continue to be) pressing for a radical change remains exemplary also in our age. For the stakes are getting higher all the time. At this critical juncture of history they amount to nothing less than threatening the very survival of humanity. Threatening it in a make or break historical epoch when the future seems to be fatefully barred by capitals deepening structural crisis and by the all too obvious power of wanton destruction emanating from it against the necessary revolutionary transformation and emancipation. However, it is highly significant that Sartre did not stop at focussing simply on the grave facticity of the barred future. His work is most relevant precisely because he could stress even in his darkest and most pessimistic moments that a barred future is still a future, underlining at the same time every individuals direct responsibility to face up to the corresponding historical challenge. That is the reason why he had to becomein a world of shabby compromises and evasions pursued as a blindly self-imposed response to the worsening crisisan embarrassing reminder and a disturbing presence. More than fifty years ago, in 1958, in an article entitled Of rats and men, Sartre expressed in a most inventive way his concern about the apparently prohibitive magnitude of the task to be faced. This is how he had put it at the time:
I remember seeing a puppy after the partial removal of the cerebellum. . . . He pondered before going around an object, requiring a great deal of time and thought to accomplish movements to which he had previously paid no attention. In the language of the time, we said that the cortex had assumed for him certain functions of the lower regions. He was an intellectual dog. . . . he either had to die or reinvent the dog.

12

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

So we othersrats without cerebellawe are also so made that we must either die or reinvent man. . . . without us, the fabrication would take place in the dark, by tinkering and patching, if we, the debrained, were not there to repeat constantly that we must work according to principles, that it is not a matter of mending, but of measuring and constructing, and finally, that mankind will be the concrete universal, or that it will not be.

Could it be true that the partially debrained dog reinvented the dog as an intellectual dog, in order not to die? The simple fact is that it is quite immaterial whether the puppy really succeeded in reinventing the dog. The issue at stake is not the literal truth (or not) of the described situation but something incomparably more fundamental than that. It is the same vital truth which indelibly affects the life of all human beings in their unavoidable historical setting; the life of every one of them no less than the vision of their deeply committed poets and philosophers who try to render explicit the shared concerns of their time in tune with the changing historical predicament of humankind. This non-literal truth is the same which was highlighted in the first half of the nineteenth century by the great poetic genius of Hungary, Sndor Petfi, when at the time of celebrating the appearance of the first railways all over Europe he asked and answered his fundamental question in this way:
Why did you not built railways before? Did you not have enough iron? Break and melt down all your shackles, You shall have plenty of iron!

Petfis truth is the same as Sartres vital existential belief concerning the survival of humanity. Only the circumstances have changed. They share their meaning also in the sense that the necessary reinvention of man which cannot be accomplished, as Sartre rightly says, by tinkering/patching and mending in the dark but only by constructing guided by principlesis quite impossible without breaking and melting down all our shackles. Literally as well as in the broadest figurative sense. And that makes imperative the revolutionary opening up of the barred future before it becomes too late. This is why the Sartrean message, going to the roots of our problems, is even more relevant today than in the past.

P R E FACE TO T HE E XPAN D ED ED ITIO N

13

I N 1 9 7 9, WHE N T H E WO R K O F SA RTR E : S E A R CH F O R FR E E D O M was first published in the Harvester Philosophy Now series, edited by my very dear friend Roy Edgley, the book was meant to be followed by an analysis of Sartres conception of history in a second volume, under the subtitle of The Challenge of History. Other work intervened to delay the completion of this project and modify some of its originally intended details. The complicated problems involved in it had to be explored in their most comprehensive settingattempted especially in my books on The Power of Ideology and Beyond Capital, as well as in the recently published two volumes of Social Structure and Forms of Consciousnessincluding the positive dimension of the necessary alternative that had to remain to the end missing from Sartres radical negation of the existent. Without undertaking such complementary work in its required overall framework, Sartres passionate outcry about the paralyzing burden of impossible revolutionswhich marked his final years with unredeemable pessimismcould not be put in its historically challengeable proper perspective. At the time of publishing the first edition of this book to which an extensive Part Three is now added, a reviewer wrote that Mszross work is a philosophical study . . . It not only provides a telling critique of Sartre, but situates him in relation to twentieth century thought. Its approach to Sartre comprehends all his manifestations novelist, playwright, philosopher, and politicianand does justice to this most extraordinary man. While never sharing Sartres openly confessed or implied pessimism about the feasible solutions, the general orientation and spirit of the now completed project is the same as originally intended. It is to put into relief, against diametrically opposed but equally tendentious misrepresentations, not only the insoluble dilemmas and antinomies of Sartres radical negation, as formulated from the perspective of his class against which he rebelled with the greatest integrity, but also their representative value and relative historical validity for the whole of our critical epoch. So as to do justice to this most extraordinary man: our real comrade in arms.

This page intentionally left blank

Introduction
Without falling into manicheism, one ought to intensify intransigence. At the extreme limit any Left positionin the measure that it is contrary to what they try to inculcate to the whole of societyis found to be scandalous. This does not mean that one should look for scandal that would be absurd and inefficaciousbut that one should not dread it: it has to come, if the position taken is right, as a side-effect, as a sign, as a natural sanction against Left attitude.1

JE A N -PAU L SART R E IS A MA N W H O LIVED half his life in the limelight of extreme notoriety. An intellectual who already in 1945 had to protest against attempts aimed at institutionalizing the writer, turning his works into national goods, for which he had to exclaim: it is not pleasant to be treated in ones lifetime as a public monument.2 What must be equally unpleasant is to be constantly subjected to abuse. And the fact is that no writer in his lifetime has been the target of so many attacks, from the most varied and rather powerful quarters, as Jean-Paul Sartre. What are the reasons? How should we approach the work of this man, our contemporary?

16

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

1.
I N O CTOB E R 1960 A M AS S D EMO NSTRATIO N of war veterans on the ChampsElyses marches to the slogan: Shoot Sartre. In the same period, ParisMatch carries an editorial with the title: Sartre, civil war machine. Some of the demonstrators or readers of Paris-Match mean business: his flat is bombed on 19 July 1961, and again, a few months later, on 7 January 1962. For how could one leave in peace a civil war machine? Nor is October 1960 the first time he is called a war machine. In June 1945that time from the opposite side of the barricadehe is attacked as manufacturer of war machine against marxism.3 The irony of it all. Is it Sartre who has changed so much? Or is it, perhaps, that this passionate advocate of every individuals full responsibility in the midst of the forces of impersonal institutionalization is deemed irrecoverable and thus, by a curious logic, must be declared to be an alien body, a machineindeed a mythical war machine at that? How revealing is the shared, bombastic imagery? Why is it that powerful institutions in their confrontations with solitary individuals represent the relation of forces upside down and denounce the voice of dissent as sinister sounds of a powerful enemys war machine? In 1948 no less a power than the Soviet Government takes an official stand against Sartre: its diplomatic representatives in Helsinki try to pressurize the Finnish Government to forbid the performance of Sartres play: Les Mains sales (Dirty Hands). It is supposed to be hostile propaganda against the USSRnothing less, nothing more! Who is this man, this machine de guerre, armed with such mythical powers? During the war, when Churchill tried to back his own arguments by making references to the Pope, Stalin remarked with a sense of realism and candid cynicism: How many Divisions, did you say, the Pope had? Did the aging Stalin think, in 1948, that Sartre was about to launch an invasion, with many more Divisions at his disposal than the Pope could ever dream about? And while we are talking about the Pope, we should recall that in the same year, on 30 October 1948, a special decree of the Holy Office puts the whole of Sartres work on the Index. It is in the spirit of this Index that sixteen years later, in October 1964, on the occasion of Sartres rejection of the Nobel Prize, the gentle Gabriel Marcel, spokesman of Christian existentialism, thunders against him in a very non-Christian voice, calling him inveterate denigrator, systematic blasphemist, man of pernicious and poisonous views, patented corrupter of youth, grave-digger of the West.4 Thus the decree of the Holy Office under the reign of Pope Pius

I N T R O D U CT ION

17

XIIthe same man who blessed Hitlers arms in their Holy Crusade becomes the license to open the floodgates of unholy venom, in the name of Christianity and as upholding the values of the West. It seems, then, that Sartre is responsible for inflicting a mortal offense not only on the great powers of this world of ours, but also on the earthly representatives of the world of beyond. No mortal is likely to accomplish much more.

2.
Y ET, EVE RY C OIN HAS T WO SID ES , and Sartres case is no exception to the rule.

And the rule is that institutions also try to neutralizeabsorb, recuperate, assimilate (Sartres words)their rebels. To describe in any detail the temptations extended toward Sartre would fill too many pages. We must be satisfied with the mention of just a few. Characteristically, offers of integration arrive from both directions. Not long after being elected Vice-President of the Association of France-USSR (a post he keeps up to his resignation following the events of Hungary in 1956), he is received with the greatest honors on his journey to Russia. Once denounced by Stalins literary spokesman, Fadeev, as the Hyena of the pen, now his booksproducts of the same penare published, and some of his plays performed, in the USSR. Even Les Maines salesonce the subject of a diplomatic exchange between the Soviet and the Finnish Governmentsis performed in the East, though not in Russia but in Prague. Ironically, not before but after the Soviet intervention in 1968. Equally, his relations with the French Communist Partynotwithstanding some major setbacks, as in Hungary in 1956are on the whole quite good between 1949 and 1968. Until, that is, Sartres evaluation of May 1968 leads to a complete, and it seems irreparable, rupture. As to the other side, the number of offers is literally legion; from that of the Lgion dHonneur to the award of the Nobel Prize. In 1945, in recognition of his merits during the Resistance, he is offered the Order of the Lgion dHonneur, but declines it. In 1959, though almost as a clumsy attempt to take back an offer that has not been accepted Malraux accuses Sartre of collaboration, on the absurd ground that he allowed the performance of his anti-fascist play, Flies, during the German occupation, while in fact it all happened in complete agreement with the Resistance group of writers.5

18

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

In May 1949, following Mauriacs attack on his political position,6 Sartre turns down Mauriacs offer to get a seat for him among the selected few living immortalsthe forty members of the Academie franaiseinsisting, in a tone of irony, that he is not going to learn equality in the company of those who display their own sense of superiority.7 In the same spirit, he rejects the idea of joining another pinnacle of French culture, the Collge de France, though his former friend, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, gladly did so. Sartres stature has to be recognized even as high as the very apex of the institutional pyramid: several Presidents of the French Republic address him with respect. Vincent Auriol, in 1952, confides in Sartre that he finds Henri Martins sentence excessive, but he cannot reduce it until he is allowed to get off the hook of political protest in which Sartre plays a prominent part. (Sartre, characteristically, does not oblige.) Giscard dEstaing, twenty three years later, hastens to assure him that he had found much spiritual nourishment and inspiration in Sartres writings on freedom. And even the proud General de Gaulle, who considered himself Frances destiny, calls Sartre Mon Chr Matre, to which the latter retorts: It is to mark well, I believe, that he intends to address himself to the man of letters, and not to the president of a tribunal [the Bertrand Russell tribunal on VietnamI. M.] which he is determined not to recognize. I am no Matre, except for the waiter in the caf who knows that I write.8 There cannot be much left to be said after that. But perhaps the most scandalous of Sartres refusals is his public rejection of the Nobel Prize,9 in 1964. Though he makes it amply clear in his letter to the Nobel Prize Committee that he would turn down with equal firmness the Lenin Prize, in the unlikely event that it was awarded to him, Andr Breton accuses him of performing a propaganda operation in favor of the East bloc.10 Sartre is condemned for an allegedly premeditated, calculated publicity stunt (as if he were in desperate need of publicity, like surrealism gone stale), although he writes privately to the Swedish Academy the moment the rumors start to circulate that he might be awarded the Prize, trying to prevent a decision in his favor, thus rendering unnecessary all publicity. This confirms again Fichtes wisdom, namely that when the facts do not fit the preconceived ideas, umso schlimmer es fr die Tatsachen, all the worse for the facts. The only institution that remains curiously aloof from this race for Sartres soul is the church. But then the church has a well established tradition of first burning the alleged hereticsas Jeanne dArcs fate reminds uselevating them to the ranks of sainthood long after they are dead and gone.

I N T R O D U CT ION

19

3.
T H US NO ONE C AN DE N Y that Sartre generates intense passions. And when he rejects the generous offers of integration, he is attacked with all the greater indignation: for what could be more wicked than biting the hand that wants to spoon feed you? There is another stratagem: pretended indifference, but this is not of much use with Sartre, as his old adversary Mauriac illustrates very well. When Sartre assumes responsibility for the persecuted Maoist groups journal, La Cause du Peuple, Mauriac writes in a tone of superiority: The thirst for martyrdom which Sartre possesses is no reason for putting in prison this incurably inoffensive character.11 Sartre answers a few weeks later to all those who adopt Mauriacs line of approach: They often say, for the ruse of the bourgeoisie is like this, that I want to be a martyr and get myself arrested. But I dont care at all for being arrestedquite the contrary! What I am interested in is that one should not arrest me, for in that way I can demonstrate, and my comrades with me, Louis Malle or someone else, that there are two weights, two measures.12 Here we can clearly see how Sartre, surrounded by the establishment chorus of self-complacent laughter, succeeds not only in extricating himself from a difficult situationdespite the uneven odds that characterize nearly all the confrontations in which he is involvedbut also, a somewhat unlikely outcome, in ending up on top. For if they arrest him, there will be an outcry the world over for imprisoning Sartre for a crime of opinion (i.e. a political, and not a criminal offense); and if they do not arrest him, fearing the consequences in world opinion, it is a humbling admission that the crime of those who are prosecuted by the Government is in fact a political crime. A crime of opinion which can lead to imprisonment only in the form of trumpedup charges, under the conspiracy of silence (often condemned by Sartre) of liberal public opinion. This is how Sartre squeezes victory out of what is supposed to be a hopeless position of defeat. The positive outcome does not just happen: Sartre is highly conscious of the paradoxical constituents of his precarious position. It is by no means accidental that he returns time and again to the problem of winner loses. He explores the complex dialectic of defeat and victory in order to grasp and lay bare the ways through which one can reverse the prefabricated odds: so as to show how it does come about that Loser wins; indeed that at times loser takes all.

20

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

4.
H OW I S IT P OS S IB L E for a solitary individual, whose pen is his only weapon, to be as effective as Sartre isand he is uniquely soin an age which tends to render the individual completely powerless? What is the secret of this intellectual who defies, with immense pride and dignity, any institution that interposes itself between him and the realization of the values he cares for? The secret is no real secret: Sartre loudly speaks it out when he defines the essence of living literature as commitment. All the controversy, indeed scandal, follows from such definition. It is this passionate commitment to the concerns of the given world; the Finite (as against the fictitious pursuit of literary immortality), that acts as a powerful catalyst in the present, and a measure of achievement linking the present to the future. Not the remote future over which the living individual has no control whatsoever, but the future at hand, the one within our reach which therefore shapes and structures our present life. Other than such commitment to ones own, however painful, temporality, there is only the world of evasion and illusion. This is the measure we propose to the writer: as long as his books arouse anger, discomfort, shame, hatred, love, even if he is no more than a shade, he will live. Afterwards, the deluge. We stand for an ethics and art of the finite says Sartre.13 And in every sense he lives up to his own measure. He is a strange grave-digger of the West. For one could hardly even imagine a writer more intensely concerned with moral values than this systematic blasphemist and corruptor of youth. This is how he sees the writers task:

The most beautiful book in the world will not save a child from pain: one does not redeem evil, one fights it. The most beautiful book in the world redeems itself; it also redeems the artist. But not the man. Any more than the man redeems the artist. We want the man and the artist to work their salvation together, we want the work to be at the same time an act; we want it to be explicitly conceived as a weapon in the struggle that men wage against evil.14

If talking in such terms means grave-digging for the West, who can say that the West does not deserve the fate of being buried forever? The work, as we can see, is defined in its total setting, and emphatically not on its own. It is its dimension of being an act in the struggle against evil

I N T R O D U CT ION

21

that compels the reader to define his or her own position on the issues at stake; and since the act is always clearly in evidence in Sartres works, no one can bypass him with indifference. They can reject the moral intensity of his measure but they cannot ignore it. Throughout his development he applies with great consistency his criteria of commitment in literature, even though he changes inside permanence.15 Almost twenty years after writing the passage quoted above, he asks the question: Do you think that I could read Robbe-Grillet in an underdeveloped country? And he answers it with a self-critical affirmation: Facing a dying child Nausea has no weight.16 It goes without saying, the literary world recognizes, with hostility, its own indictment and defends Sartre against himself (not to mention Robbe-Grillet). For did they not try, as long ago as 1945, to praise Sartres first work, Nausea, as his literary testament,17 so as to lock him into the walls of this national good, produced by its author at the age of thirty?

5.
I T I S NOT E ASY TO LOC K SA RTRE into anything, let alone into the prison cell of timeless literary excellence. His view of the writers commitment is a total one:

If literature is not everything, it is worth nothing. This is what I mean by commitment. It wilts if it is reduced to innocence, or to songs. If a written sentence does not reverberate at every level of man and society, then it makes no sense. What is the literature of an epoch but the epoch appropriated by its literature? . . . You have to aspire to everything to have hopes of doing something.18

This conception of literature as a critical mirror19 of man and the epoch shared by the writer with his fellow men sounds outrageousa scandal to all those whose sensitivity has been modeled on lart pour lart and on the self-contemplating irrelevance of various isms. Goethe could still take for granted that every poem was a Zeitgedicht, a poem of its time. But that was before the ravages of alienation succeeded in inducing the writer to fall back upon his own inner resources. And while this isolation of the writer from its epoch and from the fellow human beings is the real scandal, as a general acceptance of alienation by prevailing literary

22

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

opinion, Sartres passionate rejection of it appears as unforgivable scandal, as betrayal, indeed as blasphemy. To challenge established opinion, with all its institutions and institutionalized values, requires not only a set of firmly held beliefs but a very strong ego as well. And Sartre undoubtedly possesses them all. The articulation of his lifework is characterized by immense pride and dignity. For what could he accomplish with humility in a hostile environment? An insane pride is necessary to write you can only afford to be modest after you have sunk your pride in your work, writes Sartre.20 And he is by no means alone in this. His vision of total commitment reminds us of a great Hungarian poets words:
Pushing aside intruding Graces, I didnt come to be an artist, But to be everything, I was the Master; The poem: fancy slave.21

In Sartres view, Art in its totality is engaged in the activity of a single man, as he tests and pushes back its limits. But writing cannot be critical without calling everything into question: this is its content. The adventure of writing undertaken by each writer challenges the whole of mankind.22 To take upon oneself the burden of this challenge, and consciously so, as happens to be the case with Sartre, is far from being an easy decision. But once the writers fundamental project is defined in such terms, he cannot shrink from the magnitude of his task without losing his own integrity (or authenticity). He has to articulate the concerns of the whole of his epoch, and follow them through, no matter what. His vision of the whole carries with it a constant reminder of his own responsibility for it all. Even if they want to absolve him of this responsibility, he must by calling everything into question assert and reassert his own inalienable right to assume the burden of total responsibility. For the whole of his epoch and the whole of mankind. This is why he cannot help being intransigent in an age dominated by evasion and subterfuge, compromise and escape; in short by reified institutional self-assurance, in place of facing and tackling the contradictions which in their chronic nonresolution ultimately foreshadow the prospect of collective suicide. And since this unflattering truth cannot be brought home to ears deafened by the self-complacent noise of comforting compromise except by the loudest cry of the voice of intransigence, uncompromising moral and intellectual

I N T R O D U CT ION

23

intransigence (not to be confused with the quarrelsome pursuit of narrow self-interest) becomes the fundamental virtue of the epoch, a sine qua non of significant achievement.23
6.
Y ES, EVE RY M AN C AR R I ES A W H O LE EPO CH within him, just as a wave carries the whole of the sea. But there are waves and waves, as there are seas and seas. The sea which is our own epoch is far from being a quiet one, even in its most peaceful moments; it is the turbulent sea of a make or break age of transition from one social order to another, and Sartre is a giant wave of this mighty sea. He can express many aspects of the dynamic turmoil, following its changes in many different ways, but he categorically refuses to assume the shape of entertaining ripples on the surface of the sea, so as to hide under some cheerful diversion the gathering storm. It is not comforting to be reminded of the coming of the storm, but Sartre cannot help being a constant reminder: one would look in vain for playful serenity in his massive oeuvre. No one in this century has summoned up with greater intensity the combined resources of philosophy and creative literature in order to demonstrate the possibilities and the limitations of the individual as situated at this crucial juncture of human history. If the tormented articulation of his vision is disturbing, it is not his fault. Nor is it surprising that precisely the most valid and farsighted elements of this vision as we shall see latershould meet with the greatest incomprehension and hostility, leading to isolation: the ironical predicament of lonely notoriety. In this again he shares the fate of the great poet Jzsef, who says:

No easy comfort for men: My words are rising mould. Clear and heavy to bear I am, like the cold.24

Comfortless, cold clarity pervades many of Sartres works, and no reader can assume in relation to them the attitude of cool detachment. There are two principal factors which make such detachment impossible: the organic connection of the methods of literature and philosophy, and the careful situation of every detail in relation to the complex totality to which they belong.

24

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

From the beginning, Sartres work has been characterized by a conscious effort to combine philosophy and literature in order to intensify the powers of demonstration and persuasion. We shall see later the specific forms of this effort across his development. The point here is simply to stress the purpose behind this method. It arises out of the authors conviction that against the power of prevailing myths and vested interests the force of analytical reason is impotent: one does not displace an existing, firmly rooted positive (in the Hegelian sense positive) reality by the sheer negativity of conceptual dissection. If the weapon of criticism is to succeed, it must match the evocative power of the objects which it opposes. This is why the real work of the committed writer is . . . to reveal, demystify, and dissolve myths and fetishes in a critical acid bath.25 The imagery clearly displays the nature of the enterprise. It is to prevent opting out with cool detachment. What is at stake is nothing less than a general assault on the well established positions of cosy comfort, whether they appear as the complicity of silence or in any other form. Sartre wants to shake us, and he finds the ways of achieving his aim, even if in the end he is condemned as someone constantly in search of scandals. The other point, the concern with totality, is equally important. Sartre insists that the beauty of literature lies in its desire to be everythingand not in a sterile quest for beauty. Only a whole can be beautiful: those who cant understand thiswhatever they may have said have not attacked me in the name of art, but in the name of their particular commitment.26 Indeed, the real character of a particular commitment is not recognizable without laying bare its links with the given totality. Particularism can and must claim the status of universality in the absence of a comprehensive frame of reference, since the failure to be in a proper perspective necessarily transforms particularism itself into its own perspective, and thus into the measure of everything else. Any attempt to reveal the proper connections with totality must therefore clash with the interests of the prevailing particularisms. At the same time, the unveiling of particularisms does not leave only their champions naked but suddenly exposes also the vulnerability of all those who were previously able to find self-assurance and (however illusory) comfort in the sheltered corners of various particularisms. But there is no other way. The critical mirror cannot fulfill its functions if it is fragmented into a thousand pieces. Such a broken mirror can only show distorting details even when they appear to be faithful in their immediacy: distorting because severed from the whole which alone can confer upon them their full (i.e. true) significance. The choice is therefore

I N T R O D U CT ION

25

unavoidable. Either one abandons the aim of bearing witness to the age in which one lives, and thus ceases to be a critical mirror; or one appropriates the epoch in the only way in which this can be done through writing by the uncomforting, cold clarity of a work which reveals, shows, demonstrates the connections of the parts with the whole, demystifying and dissolving the fetishes of the seemingly rock-solid, established immediacy in the dynamic framework of constantly changing totality. There can be no doubt of which is Sartres choice.

7.
T H E F OC U S OF SART R E S GRA P P LING with totality is his search for freedom. Everything appears in relation to this concern. He calls his novel cycle Roads to Freedom: a title that might well sum up the character of his work as a whole. (This applies as much to his literary as to his philosophical/theoretical work.) And precisely because his work has the focus it does have, Sartre never gets lost in the sociohistorical totality of which he is a tireless explorer. Of course, his preoccupation with freedom goes through many metamorphoses. There is a world of difference, even if accomplished linterieur dune permanence (inside permanence), between saying that man is free so as to commit himself, but he is not free unless he commits himself so as to be free27 and recognizing that no one is free unless everybody is free . . . Freedom is conditionednot metaphysically but practically by protein.28 The first quotation offers a solution only in the form of a verbal paradox; the second, by contrast, assumes a more modest posture, but indicates some tangible targets for human action. All the sameand this is why he is right to talk about change inside permanencethe organizing centre and structuring core of Sartres work remains his all-embracing concern for freedom. The removal of hunger and exploitation do not appear as ends in themselves but as necessary stepping stones towards the liberation of man, towards the realization of his freedom. Sartres work covers an enormous area and shows an immense variety: from occasional articles to a novel cycle, from short stories to massive philosophical syntheses, from film scripts to political pamphlets, from plays to reflections on art and music, and from literary criticism to psychoanalysis, as well as monumental biographies, attempting to grasp the inner motivations of unique individuals in relation to the specific social-historical conditions of the age which shaped them and which in their turn they helped to transform.

26

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Yet one cannot say that the trees hide the wood. Quite the contrary. It is Sartres lifework as a whole that predominates, and not particular elements of it. While one can undoubtedly think of unique masterpieces among his numerous writings, they do not account by themselves for his true significance. One might go as far as to say that it is his total fundamental project, with all its manifold transformations and permutations, which defines the uniqueness of this restless author, and not the accomplishment of even his most disciplined work. For it is an integral part of his project that he constantly changes and revises his previous positions: the many-faceted work articulates itself through its transformations, and totalization is achieved through ceaseless de-totalization and re-totalization. Success and failure thus become very relative terms for Sartre: they turn into one another. Success is the manifestation of failure and failure is the reality of success. As Sartre puts it, in the domain of expression, success is necessarily failure,29 and he quotes his friend, Giacometti, according to whom when failure reaches its climax and all is lost, at this point . . . you can throw your sculpture in the rubbish bin or exhibit it in a gallery.30 The reason is (though this is not quite how Sartre puts it, tending at this point towards a timeless explanation) that the writer and the artist in our age have to assemble their work from fragmented pieces. For fragmentation and compartmentalization (or, at another level, isolation and privatization) are not mere figments of the intellectuals imagination but objective characteristics of contemporary socio-historical reality. And this makes the work, even when it consciously aims at totalizationinherently problematical. There are many different ways of facing up to this problem; the names of Proust and Thomas Mann indicate two clearly contrasting attempts. But neither Prousts ordered subjectivity, nor Thomas Manns disciplined and restrained objectivity can be compared to Sartres project. The relevant comparison is Picasso, whatever their differences: both devour, with insatiable appetite, everything that comes their way, and produce not so much representative works as a representative lifework. Thus it does not matter that particular works are not paradigm summations of the artist, in the sense in which la recherche du temps perdu and The Magic Mountain certainly are. It does not matter that the particular works (even Guernica) are more problematical than the ones which, by contrast, are constituted on the basis of a most careful sifting and elaboration of the given moments of reality. If Picasso and Sartre have to move on from a particular kind of synthesis to something on the face of it quite different, it is because what is involved in their quest is a type of totalization which

I N T R O D U CT ION

27

always refers to the artists lifework as its immediate ground. Theirs is a singular form of subjectivity in comparison to Proust and Thomas Mann. The former produces his synthesis by dissolving the world of objects in his interiority and subjectivity; the latter makes the writers subjectivity recede quietly behind a carefully reconstructed objectivity. In both Sartre and Picasso, subjectivity is always in evidence but uses as its vehicle the world of objects, not to subjectivize it but to nihilate it (to use Sartres expression) in the course of depiction. As a result of this dialectical process of objectivation-nihilationa first cousin of Brechts Verfremdungseffektthe lifework is enriched, paradoxically, at the expense of the particular work which it uses to stand on its own shoulders, so to speak. We are captivated by the process of nihilating objectification that produces the lifework, and not necessarily by particular results. Just how many individual works survive in the long run is irrelevant. What matters is the constitution of a representative lifework: a singular fusion of subjectivity and objectivity. The great variety and mass of Sartres particular projects readily combines into a coherent whole. The extraordinary coherence of his lifework is not preconceived. It is not the result of an original blueprint which is imposed on every detail as time goes by: that would be an artificial, external unity. Here we have to do, on the contrary, with an inner unity that prevails through the most varied manifestations of formal divergence. This is an evolving unity that emerges through more or less spontaneous explorations of the roads to freedomor, for that matter, of the manifold obstacles to freedomwhatever they happen to be. The unity is therefore structural and not thematic: the latter would be far too restrictive for a lifework. (Some of Sartres works are, though, characterized by an attempt to achieve a thematic unity, and by no means always with a happy result, most notably his novel cycle; but this is another matter.) Thus Sartre is right in rejecting suggestions that his conception of commitment in literature leads to thematic restriction and political illustration as well as to a paralysis of artistic spontaneity. But to stress how the exploration of the roads to freedom produces the structural unity of Sartres work is not enough to take hold of its specificity. It is equally important to put into relief the structuring role of Sartres conception of the individual in his work as a whole. For freedom does not appear in its generalitythat would be thematically restrictive political illustration or abstract symbolism, both rejected by Sartrebut always as manifest through particular existential predicaments, whether the subject is from Greek antiquity or from Modern France. It is in this sense that he is and remains an existentialist.

28

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Kant asserted the primacy of practical reason (i.e. the supremacy of moral judgement) in the architectonic of his system, and he carried through this principle with exemplary consistency. Sartrenot only as a young man, but also as the author of an ethical work written at the age of sixty31 quotes Kants you ought to, therefor you can, and insists on the primacy and centrality of individual praxes vis--vis collective and institutional structures. Such a statement clearly assigns a prominent place to the world of morality. This could not be otherwise without undermining the inner unity and consistency of Sartres work. For, as he remarks in 1944, Morality is . . . my dominant preoccupation; it always has been.32 And so it has remained ever since, directly or indirectly, in theoretical and in literary forms. It is this primacy and centrality assigned to individual praxes, in close relation with the problematics of freedom, which defines the specificity of Sartres fundamental project through all the variety of its manifestations.

8.

is to recognize and examine ourselves in his critical mirror. This is not a one-way business. For reading is interpreting and thus necessarily implies not only an examination of ourselves, but at the same time also a critical examination of the mirror and of its relationship to the epoch which it reveals. As Sartre puts it, recognizably in terms of his own central concerns, the reader freely allows himself to be influenced. This fact alone is enough to quash the fable of his passivity. The reader invents us: he uses our words to set his own traps for himself. He is active, he transcends us.33 This is particularly true of reading a contemporary author. For there are many crucial junctures of experience which we share with him. This confers a privileged position on the reader in his critical dialogue with his living contemporary. But saying that only accounts for the credit side of the equation. The debit side consists in the particular difficulties of evaluating the lifework of a living contemporary. All my works, says Sartre, are facets of a whole whose meaning one cannot really appreciate until Ill have brought it all to an end.34 This is true enough. But not quite. Were it categorically true, evaluation of a contemporary author would be a priori impossible. The job of the critic would oscillate between arbitrary subjectivity (inventing the author entirely out of ones own concerns, using his words only as a pretext for pseudo-objective self-exhibition) and the dead objectivity of mere
T H E P OIN T OF R E AD IN G A CO NTEMP O RA RY

I N T R O D U CT ION

29

description of the works reviewed: a superfluous and hopeless venture. To be sure, evaluation can proceed only from the whole, which is, by definition, incomplete so long as the lifework has not been brought to its end. All the same, when one deals with a significant author, whose individual works are facets of a whole, new and possible additions are not capricious attempts at a radical break, but additions which are feasible in relation to the given and self-evolving whole. In other words, all modifications represent change lintrieur dune permanence, in accordance with the dialectic of continuity and discontinuity. The structuring elements of an original lifework are clearly visible at a relatively early age; and the tendencies of a writers quest are displayed through the type of variations the particular works represent in relation to one another. And there is a crucialone might say strategicpoint of reference: the stubborn recurrence of some basic concerns which assume the form of incomplete or unfinished (for within the given writers project unfinishable) works. When a writers lifework is suddenly brought to its end, what happens is that the former incompleteness is elevated to the level of completion. Paradoxically, in the shape of works unfinishable for inner reasons we find anticipations of the completed lifework; and we find these in particular abundance in Sartres oeuvre. A closer look at themnot in isolation but in relation to the restmay help to provide the vantage point from which a critical assessment of a living contemporary becomes possible.

This page intentionally left blank

P A R T

O N E

The Unity of Life and Work: Outline of Sartres Development

The important thing is not what one is but what one does.35

This page intentionally left blank

1. The Writer and His Situation


1.
A W R I TE R C R E AT E S HIS WO RK from the raw material of experience given to him by the contingency of his situation, even if, as in Kafka, the end result seems to have very little in common with the immediate ground from which the work emanates. Some writers, like Villon, throw themselves right in the middle of the turmoil of their epoch, and live through the events with great intensity at the level of particularized human conflicts and adventures. Others, like Schiller or Hegel, leave the ground of their direct experience much more radically behind them when they articulate in works their view of the meaning of their age. And, of course, there can be a virtually endless number of variations between the two extremes. The interchange of life and work of which Sartre is intensely awareit is enough to mention in this respect Saint Genet and The Idiot of the Family on Flaubertconstitutes the writers life in the interest of his work and vice versa; he makes his work and his work makes its author. But, of course, it all happens within a given social framework which constitutes both the horizon and the ground of human achievement. The writer does not lead a life of double book-keeping. He reaches out for experience in the spirit of his work in the course of its articulation, and he transforms the acquired experience into work. Thus he turns contingency into necessitywithin the broad framework of his social reality: the ground and the horizon of a

34

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

free and conditioned workand at the same time he turns the necessity of this ground and horizon into the new contingency of a somewhat modified starting point for his contemporaries, who are now challenged to define themselves also in relation to his work. Three important questions arise in this context: 1. How and why does a writer choose writing as the specific form in which the interaction of life and work is carried out? 2. Given his original choice, how does he erect from the scraps of contingency at his disposal the structured necessity of his work? For no man comes in direct contact with the World Spirit, not even Hegel who thinks to glance at it in the shape of Napoleon on horseback on the battlefield of Jena. 3. What is the spectrum of his feasible work, that is, what can be successfully accomplished in the framework of his fundamental project, given the dialectical interchange between the sum of the writers lived experience and the particular projects on which he embarks? In other words, what kind of work can he make while being made by them? The first question concerns the nature and constitution of the writers fundamental project. In a generalized form (i.e. asking the same sort of question about individuals in general, to whatever walk of life they may belong) it can be phrased like this: By what activity can an accidental individual realize the human person within himself and for all?36 This makes it clear that the form in which we encounter the problem in so many of Sartres works (Words, Saint Genet, Of rats and men, The Idiot of the Family, for example) is a searching confrontation of a typical modern problem rendered increasingly acute by a certain type of social development: a process of individualization and privatization inseparable from the advancement of alienation. As Marx puts it: The present condition of society displays its difference from the earlier state of civil society in that in contrast to the pastit does not integrate the individual within its community. It depends partly on chance, partly on the individuals effort, etc., whether or not he holds on to his station.37 The accidental individual, divorced from his universal being, must therefore embark on a project of great complexity: a journey of discovery how to realize the human person within himself and for all. A journey that ends only by death: either the suicide of a

T H E WRIT E R AND HIS S I TUATIO N

35

self-complacent coming-to-a-halt (for example, the institutionalized and recuperated writer) or the natural death which is the completion of life. Thus, the fundamental project and its articulation through particular projects become the same, and the originally envisaged discovery assumes the form of a constant rediscovery of authentic self-renewal in accordance with the individuals changing situation, in the interest of realizing the human person within himself and for everyone else. Accordingly, Sartres often recurring examination of the constitution of a writers project whether his own or someone elseswhich might appear to the superficial observer as a narcissistic obsession, is in fact concerned with the meaning of every individuals enterprise. A quest for a meaning in society in which he cannot help being an accidental individual but which he must in some way transcend if he is to snatch back his own humanityfor himself and for allfrom the powers of alienation.

2.

in detail is a truly forbidding undertaking. For it involves the collection and evaluation of a virtually infinite number of data. And once infinity enters an equation whether in quantum theory or in the Sartrean project on Genet and on Flaubert (not to mention those abandoned, after some hundreds of pages, on Mallarm and on Tintoretto) the whole equation becomes methodologically problematical to an extreme degree. It is by no means accidental that Saint Genet, originally intended as a short preface to a volume of Genets writings, grows into a massive work of 573 pages, only to be dwarfed later by the several thousandand always incompletepages of the study on Flaubert, also originally envisaged as a much more limited project. If one adds to these the considerable mass of Sartres abandoned works of this kind there is clearly something to be explained. This will be attempted in its proper context, in Part Three, for it is inextricably linked to Sartres conception of history as singular and nonuniversalizable; a conception that seeks to demonstrate the dialectical intelligibility of that which is not universalizable.38 Here the point is simply to emphasize the relevance of the question to an understanding of Sartre himself in two respects. First, Sartre always combines the investigation of a writers fundamental project with an enquiry, in extenso, into the concrete ways in which he squeezes necessity out of the contingencies of his situation, thus producing the exemplary validity of a work whose constituents are, in
TO A N SW E R T HE S E C ON D Q UESTIO N

36

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

principle, readily available in each and every one of us. Secondly, turning into necessity the scraps of contingency as encountered in everyday circumstances is much in evidence in Sartres own development. This is the sense in which the unity of his work emerges, not out of some mythical original blueprint, but on the basis of a totalizing determination which aims at integrating the elements of transformed facticity into a coherent whole. We can only indicate a few particular events and circumstances as types of such transformations, thus violating Sartres own rule about the non-universalizability of the singular. In 1940 41, while prisoner of war, Sartre obtains the works of Heidegger a persona gratissima with the Nazis and gives a course on his philosophy to some fellow-prisoner military chaplains. Naturally, Kierkegaard is also an integral part of their discussions, which in their intensity lay the foundations of Being and Nothingness, drafted a year later. Around Christmas, in the same company, Sartre writes his first play, Barionaor the Son of Thunder. Both events acquire a major significance for his future. The experience of writing Bariona and its reception by his comrades determine Sartres view that the theatre ought to be a great collective religious experience39a view reaffirmed by him on many occasions, stressing the organic connection between theatre and myth. (The idea goes well beyond theatre only, as we shall see in the next chapter.) Similarly, the integration of Kierkegaard and Heidegger into Sartres world of ideas and images carries far-reaching consequences. His book Saint Genet adopts as its structuring principle (for interpreting Genets metamorphoses) the Kierkegaardian stages: the ethical, the aesthetic, and the religious, though the third metamorphosis is now identified as the predicament of the Writer. But as we learn in many places, in my imagination, literary life was modeled on religious life. . . . I had transposed religious needs into literary longings.40 Also, the depth of his contact with Kierkegaard can be measured with Sartres innumerable references to the singular, or indeed to the singular universal. The same goes for Heidegger. His role cannot be overestimated in the formation of Sartres structure of thought. It would be useless to speculate what would have happened had Sartre been given the experience of a Russian instead of a Nazi prisoner of war camp, with the works of Marx and Lenin on the shelves. Useless not only because of the inherent sterility of counterfactual conditionals but also because his first acquaintance with Heideggers writings, though not very deep, predates the war experience by some ten years. In any case, Sartre puts Heidegger to his own use. It would be as mistaken to read Sartre through Heideggers eyes as the other way

T H E WRIT E R AND HIS S I TUATIO N

37

round. All the same, one cannot build a crystal palace from stone. Thus, while Sartre is right in defending himself against sectarian attacks on account of Heideggers Nazi past, his arguments on the real issue are far from convincing. He says: And then Heidegger, so what? If we discover our own thought propos of another philosopher, if we ask him for techniques and methods susceptible to make us accede to new problems, does that mean that we marry all his theories? Marx had borrowed from Hegel his dialectic. Would you say therefore that Capital is a Prussian work?41 The point is not only that Sartre borrows from Heidegger much more than techniques and methods but alsoand this is far more importantthat he never submits Heideggers work to that radical settling of accounts which characterizes Marxs relationship to Hegel. What we can see in all these instances is that contingency is in a sense superseded. Not that the writer can do whatever he pleases. (As a matter of fact, Sartre has to pay a high price for adopting a great deal from Heideggers truncated ontology which can found only itself and therefore must coil back into itself. More about this later.) Contingency does not give way to some mystical freedom emanating from the intellectuals subjectivity but to a structured necessity. What happens before our very eyes is that the accidental character of contingency is transcended and metamorphosed into the necessity of inner determinations.

3.

spectrum of a writers feasible work is directly linked to the range of his personal experiences. In 1959, after praising Franoise Sagan for producing something new on the basis of personal experience,42 Sartre indicates that one of the main factors in his decision to abandon writing novels was his awareness of the deficiencies (manque) in his own personal experiences. In a more generalized sense, his decision is linked to a definition of the novel as prose which aims at the totalization of a singular and fictive temporalization,43 and since his own personal experiences cannot provide the ground of the kind of representative totalization required by the novel form, Sartre has to adopt in the end someone elses singular temporalization by producing, in The Idiot of the Family, what he calls a true novel.44 This is not as simple as it looks. To be sure, Sartres life is not very adventurous. In fact most of it is spent on a demonic dedication to work. The

T H E T HIR D QU E ST ION RA ISED A B OVE the

38

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

sheer mass of his production is staggering. Some five or six million words already published, and perhaps another two to three million sunk in manuscripts lost or abandoned, or yet to be published: more than enough to keep half a dozen scribes busy all their life during the Middle Ages just to copy out such an amount. When asked about his extraordinary wealth of production, he explains half-apologetically: One can be productive without too much work. Three hours in the morning, three hours in the evening: this is my only rule. Even on journeys. I carry out little by little a consciously elaborated plan of work.45 It is daunting to learn that six hours of intensive work, every day, even on journeys, is considered little by little. The whole truth, however, is even more daunting. For we know from other sources (primarily from Simone de Beauvoirs memoirs) that often he writes day and night, and is prepared to spend twenty-eight hours in one stretch on revising a single article.46 Nor is such intensity reserved for rare occasions. On the contrary, it seems to be the rule rather than the exception. Many of Sartres literary works are written in a few days or weeks. More amazing still, his two monumental theoretical works, Being and Nothingness and Critique of Dialectical Reason were each written in a few months.47 Moreover, Franois Erval tells me, often whole chapters are rewritten from beginning to end just because Sartre is dissatisfied with some details. If one adds to all this the endless number of hours spent on discussions, correspondence, interviews, rehearsals of plays, lectures, political and editorial meetings, and so on, clearly there cannot be much time left over for personal experiences. One book authors, like Sagan, may abundantly afford them; not Sartre, who just cannot stop, to take life as it comes: he must be active all the time.48 In any case, the meaning of a writers personal experience is dialectical: it should not be turned into a frozen fetish. Does not Sartre always insist, rightly, that the work makes its author while he creates his work? This dialectical interchange between work and experience could not find a clearer manifestation than in Sartre. We can sense it already in his first original piece of theoretical writing, a letter contributed to an enquiry among students published in Les Nouvelles littraires at the beginning of 1929. There is only one earlier theoretical work by Sartre, an essay entitled Theory of the state in modern French thought,49 but that is a very different proposition. It shows nothing of Sartres future path. It merely puts a few sultanas of originality in the insipid dough of academic conventionality. By contrast, in the letter to the Nouvelles Littraires we get the first glimpse of the real Sartre: a formidable figure. It is not what he says but the way he approaches

T H E WRIT E R AND HIS S I TUATIO N

39

the problem that makes this letter a truly original beginning, well worth a longer quotation:
It is a paradox of the human mind that Man, whose business it is to create the necessary conditions, cannot raise himself above a certain level of existence, like those fortune-tellers who can tell other peoples future, but not their own. This is why, at the root of humanity, as at the root of nature, I can see only sadness and boredom. It is not that Man does not think of himself as a being. On the contrary, he devotes all his energies to becoming one. Whence derive our ideas of Good and Evil, ideas of men working to improve Man. But these concepts are useless. Useless, too, is the determinism which oddly enough attempts to create a synthesis of existence and being. We are as free as you like, but helpless. . . . For the rest, the will to power, action and life are not only useless ideologies. There is not such thing as the will to power. Everything is too weak: all things carry the seeds of their own death. Above all, adventureby which I mean that blind belief in adventitious and yet inevitable concatenation of circumstances and eventsis a delusion. In this sense, the adventurer is an inconsequential determinist who imagines he is enjoying complete freedom of action.50

No doubt this is already a synthesishowever preliminary: the result of much questioning and dissecting. It is the summation of all the personal experiences which made possible such reflection and generalization in the relatively trivial context of a student enquiry. The mark of a commanding and imposing personality is well evidenced by the fact that he elects to voice precisely such heavy-going metaphysical fundamentals on such an occasion, when others might be content to complain about digs and catering. This is not simply an occasional piece, though it is that too. What matters more is that it is the project of life, whatever the implications it may carry for the personal as well as literary-intellectual development of its author. He grasps a major paradox, which in turn takes hold of him, and thus he gets involved in the lifelong project of reaching the roots of being (italicized by Sartre) through questioning Man and nature, mind and existence, humanity and ideology, good and evil, freedom and adventure, death and determinism. What a maiden speech for a student learning to fly in the world of ideas! This quest for the roots of being is of necessity a project of totalization par excellence. It is the whole that predominates in so far as the elements and details of reality must be always brought into relation with the foundation of being. Thus the overriding characteristic of the work must be synthesis

40

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

and not analysis: the latter can only assume a subordinate position, as a well marked preliminary stage to the emerging synthesis. This is why Sartre considers himself diametrically opposed to Proust, despite his great admiration for this French classic writer, insisting that Proust takes delight in analysis while the inherent tendency of his own work is synthesis.51 Sartres description of his religious model of literatureconceived as an all-encompassing and all-fulfilling enterpriseis only another name for this synthesizing, which profoundly affects every facet of life and work, from character to work method, from personal relations to the writers perception of and attitude to the world of objects, and from the style of life to the structure and style of the work itself. And since the ultimate point of reference is being, with its existential bearing on everything, the surveyed facets of the whole cannot be approached with detached objectivity (we are always inside the perimeters of the quest: integral parts and not sovereign observers of it) but with a powerful fusion of subjectivity and objectivity, more often than not under the predominance of the former. Kierkegaard spoke of infinite compelling subjectivity.52 In Sartre we are faced also with compelling subjectivity (sometimes identified as voluntarism), even if with a more restrained form than in his great predecessor. No matter how abstract a problem may be in itself, it is always converted into a lived idea in the course of it being situated in relation to being.

4.

to illustrate this interpenetration of subjectivity and objectivity. Take the concept of space and distance. We are told by Sartre that distance was invented by man and has no meaning outside the context of human space; it separated Hero from Leander and Marathon from Athens, but does not separate one pebble from another. The point is hammered home by describing a personal experience of absolute proximity in a prison camp where my skin was the boundary of my living space. Day and night I felt the warmth of a shoulder or a thigh against my body. But it was never disturbing, as the others were a part of me. This is contrasted with his return home: I had rejoined bourgeois society. Where I would have to learn to live once again at a respectful distance.53 And all this is to prepare the ground for an exploration of Giacomettis handling of space and distance, in relation to the plenitude of being and the void of nothingness.
A F EW E X AM P L E S M U ST SUFF ICE

T H E WRIT E R AND HIS S I TUATIO N

41

Simone de Beauvoir writes of Sartre that if it had been necessary, he would have been willing to remain anonymous: the important thing was that his ideas should prevail.54 This is all very well, except that anonymity and the prevalence of Sartres ideaslived ideasis a contradiction in terms. Ideas like those of Sartre must be dramatically asserted, if necessary through the most extreme manifestations of compelling subjectivity. Thus notoriety and scandal are necessary concomitants of his all-embracing project towards being, and anonymity must remain at most some momentary longing for peace under the strain of scandal and notoriety. Sartres relations to people, works of art, everyday objects and so on, are sketched, in his works as much as in real life, with dramatic colors He does not simply like or dislike what he sees in the Prado Museum but loaths and detests Titian and admires Hieronymous Bosch. One look at a gathering in an Oxford College is enough to make him detest the snobbery of Oxford society and never to set foot in that city again. It is part of the economy of life that he has to make up his mind about everything with great speed and intensity, always looking for an overall evaluation which can be integrated into his totalizing search. Similarly with personal relations, even some of the closest friendships have to be dramatically terminated (for example those with Camus and Merleau-Ponty) as soon as he perceives that continued friendship would interfere with the realization of his aims. He orders all his personal relations, including the most intimate ones, in such a way that he shall never be diverted from his singleminded dedication to the central concerns of his life. He refuses to accept the responsibility and burden of family life precisely for that reason. He refuses to be trapped by the conditions of bourgeois comfort and tries to banish money and possessions from his personal life. Equally, he explores, with great passion and imagination, modes of experience which to a less compelling subjectivity would appear to be, in principle, a book closed forever. Thus he gets involved in a passionate discussion of Negritude, totally indifferent to the possibility that his eidetic analysis of it (since it cannot be other than that) might be, as it has been, dismissed as disastrous55 by those who experience it from the inside. Problematical as such a venture might be, how could he do without it in his totalizing quest for being when racism looms so large, with the most devastating implications, in the totality of our predicament? Thus, paradoxically, compelling subjectivity is the necessary condition of some degree of objectivity (the objectivity of facing up to the problem with real concern), whereas the objectivity of modest withdrawalthe acknowledgement of a white mans

42

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

inadequacies to such a taskwould mean the worst kind of subjectivity, that of evasive complicity. A similar manifestation of Sartres compelling subjectivity is when he tells Daniel Gurin that he doesnt understand anything of his own book.56 Preposterous as such a statement must appear from the point of view of the criticized author, the relative justification for it is that the context into which Sartre inserts Gurins account of the French Revolution (the Sartrean dialectical assessment of the ontological structure of history) imposes a significantly different angle on the particular events discussed and thus it puts into focus dimensions which remained hidden or secondary to the historian in the original context. One may thoroughly disagree with Sartres conception of the ontological structure of history, born out of his own specific concerns and clearly exhibiting the marks of his compelling personality, but it is impossible to deny that it throws radically new light on our understanding of the structures and institutions we can identify in the course of historical development. The I is in the foreground of virtually everything Sartre writes, and his subjectivity is carried, if necessary, to the point of belligerence. He emphatically refuses to withdraw into the background and assume the role of an objective guide whose function is merely to point at objects, works, and events, or at some well established connections between them. In his view, just like distance, objects must be brought to life by presenting them through the writers subjectivity before they can be inserted into meaningful human discourse, otherwise they remain dead things and fetishes. Critics have often wondered why Sartre does not write lyric poetry, not noticing that he does it all the time, though not as a separate genre, but as diffuse throughout his work. What could be more lyrical than his description of Giacomettis handling of distance as linked to his own homecoming from prison camp to live life at a respectful distance? Sartres style is determined by the great complexities of his overall project of totalization. Talking about the first volume of his Critique of Dialectical Reason, he admits that its length (nearly 400.000 words) could be somewhat reduced if he could spend on it much time and effort, but he adds: All the same, it would very much resemble the work as it is now. For, basically, its sentences are so long, so full of parentheses, quotation marks, of in so far as etc., only because every sentence represents the unity of a dialectical movement.57 It is impossible to convey the unity of a dynamic movement, with all its complexities, by using static devices such as short root sentences, simplified meaning, or by concentrating on one aspect, for the sake of clarity, while

T H E WRIT E R AND HIS S I TUATIO N

43

neglecting many others. The deceptive translucency of analytic dissection, disregarding the need for meaningful syntheses, produces only irrelevance or misrepresentation. Style and method must match the full complexity of the task itself, otherwise they are prefabricated devices artificially superimposed on any subject matter, irrespective of its specific nature and inner demands. Sartre consciously opposes to this practice of Procrustean superimposition (frequently witnessed in modern art and thought, from philosophy to sociology and from economics to anthropology) his own method of capturing movement and intricacy. If sharply focusing on one aspect at the expense of others represents distortion, since only the proper conjunction of the one with the many constitutes the relevant whole, he aims at clarifying and revealing indeterminacy, paradoxical as this may sound. This is what he praises in Giacometti, stressing that it should not be confused with vagueness the result of failure. For the indeterminate quality that comes from lack of skill has nothing in common with the calculated indetermination of Giacometti, which could more accurately be termed overdetermination (surdetermination).58 It is the adoption of this principle of overdetermination, corresponding to the structure of totality, in conjunction with what Sartre terms the principle of individuation,59 which defines the specificity of his style and the vitality of his method as arising from the soil of his totalizing quest for being. The whole is grasped through the simultaneity of calculated indetermination (overdetermination) and the shifting presence of graphic individuation whereby even absence becomes tangible as a vital dimension of totality (see for example the discussion of Pierre missing from the caf in Being and Nothingness). Thus movement and rest, the whole and its parts, the centre and the periphery, the premier plan and the background, the determinations from the past and the anticipations of the future converging on the present, all come to life in the synthetic unity of a dialectical totalization in which subjectivity and objectivity are inextricably fused.

5.
AS W E CAN S E E T HE N , the work carries the marks of the writers personality in every respect, from the choice of astonishing subject matter (like Negritude) through modes of analysis and depiction to the style and method of writing. Viewed from the other side, the inner determinations of a certain overall project determine in their turn a belligerent character, a compelling subjectivity, a writers own way of defining himself in relation to institutions,

44

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

people and property; in short, his style of life and the experiences he will embark on in accordance with his vision of the world and of his own place in it. Thus we can see the singularization of the work by the man and the universalization of the man by the work.60 In Sartres case the spectrum of his feasible work is circumscribed by that all-encompassing quest for being we have already seen in the groping words of the student confronting man and nature, mind and existence, humanity and ideology, good and evil, death and determinism. Since the target is being itself, conventional forms will not provide the ways of its unfolding; and since Sartres works always aim at revealing being, or at indicating the roads towards it, they must a priori exclude anything whatsoever to do with naturalism. Symbolism is also excluded as it would merely inflate isolated chunks of the given immediacy into some abstract and static generality, instead of reproducing the dynamic multiplicity of relations which characterize the whole. What is called for, then, is some form of mediation capable of conveying the plenitude of being and the void of nothingness without falling into abstract symbolism. He finds the mediation he needs in what he calls myth: a condensation61 of traits of character (in line with the density or plenitude of being) that elevates the perceived and depicted reality to the level of being without abandoning the ground of sensibility. Thus condensation provides the ground on which calculated indetermination and graphic individuation can flourish as truly creative principles. We shall see in the next chapter the place of myth in Sartres work in general. Here we are interested in its implications for our present context: the range of works the author can successfully accomplish on such grounds in the framework of his totalizing quest. The first is his novel cycle, Roads to Freedom. Considered not in isolation but in the totality of his development, Roads to Freedom is a failure in the sense of being a blind alley from which there can be no exit, no further explorations, no branching out, no roads not even a footpathto freedom. Despite its partial accomplishments, numerous and impressive though they may be, this work remains completely peripheral in Sartres lifework. He has to tear himself away from it, as late as 1949, extricating himself form the consequences of a false choice, in order to continue his quest in other directions. Ten years after abandoning work on the fourth volume, he gives his reasons as follows:
The fourth volume was to speak of the Resistance. The choice was simple in those dayseven if one needed much strength and courage to stand by it. One was for or against the Germans. The choice was black or white.

T H E WRIT E R AND HIS S I TUATIO N

45

Todaysince 1945the situation is complicated. One needs less courage, perhaps, to choose, but the choices are much more difficult. I could not express the ambiguities of our epoch in a novel situated in 1943.62
T H ESE AR E WHAT SART RE CA LLS

elsewhere his internal difficulties63 for

abandoning Roads to Freedom. In reality the issue is much more complicated, for it is not only the fourth volume which is problematical but the project as a whole. Reaching 1943 means that things become more visible, at a point of climax, but they are there from the beginning. The problematic character of the work manifests itself structurally in a disturbing tension between straightforward everydayness, depicted in its immediacy, and an abstract rhetoric which tries to project everydayness onto the plane of universality.64 In other words, it is the missing intermediary of myth or condensation that renders the work structurally abstract and problematical in the framework of Sartres totalizing quest. The perception of a whole epoch within the parameters of an extremely simplified conflict of black or white is in fact the consequence of this abstract structure, rather than its massively objective cause as Sartre curiously suggestsvery much out of character with his dialectical conception of subject and object, author and work, cause and effect in literature. Examining the conditions under which Roads to Freedom was written we find that Sartre allowed himself to be manoeuvred into the adoption of its abstract structure, first, by the scandal65 that followed the pervasive negativity of his early short stories and Nausea, making him unwisely promise a positive continuation, secondly (more understandable but artistically just as problematic), by the abstract heroism66 of his perception of the Resistance movement in which he cannot assume more than a very peripheral role, no matter how hard he tries. While it is true to say that his dramatic work as a whole is free from this structural abstractness, it would be quite wrong to see as the reason for it simply that here we are concerned with a novelwith prose which aims at the totalization of a singular and fictive temporalization, as he had put it. It is the type of prose which is in question: one that resists the necessary condensation of characters and situations and thus tempts the author to intervene repeatedly, in the form of abstract rhetoric, in order to compensate by producing some philosophical condensation. Prose showing affinity with Kafka, or with the works of E. Th. A. Hoffmann, as a much earlier example, would be a very different proposition. However, as things stand, the structure of Roads to Freedom opposes that calculated indetermination which is so vital to the realization of the Sartrean project.

46

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

We find the exact opposite in Huis Clos (No Exit). Written in a fortnight in the Autumn of 1943 and first staged in Paris in May 1944 (and banned by the censor in England in September 1946), Huis Clos is a most suggestive pice de circonstance. The occasion that calls it into being is a friends request for a play easy to stage, with few actors, by a traveling theatre company. And since Sartre wants to create roles of equal weight for his friends who are the principal actresses, he devises a situation in which they must remain together on the stage all the time. First he thinks of a bomb shelter, with its exit caved in, offering no escape. The time of writing is not far from the completion of Being and Nothingness,67 and Sartre wants to explore in the medium of drama the conflict inherent in interpersonal relations, the threat to freedom represented by the other. Thus the setting of a bomb shelter would, clearly, produce a failure. Such a situation would offer at least as much room for the display of human solidarity and fusion towards a shared end as for the intended manifestation of reciprocally paralyzing enmity. Sartres brilliant inspiration to locate the stage in hell from which there can be no exit, turns the work into a masterpiece. Elevating a human situation of consuming conflict to the level of a mytha myth in which the devastating negativity and all-consuming character of the conflict is intensified, to a degree inconceivable in whatever other form, by giving a dimension of eternity to destruction and consumption, which are normally paradigms of temporal limitation and determination, bringing things to a predictable endSartre creates a tangible intermediary in which the concerns of everyday life and some of the most fundamental dimensions of the structure of being converge. In such a medium of extreme condensation sentences like hell is the other arise spontaneously from the situation, whereas they could be superimposed only in the form of abstract rhetoric in the medium of, say, Roads to Freedom. Calculated indetermination, graphic individuation, multiple layers of ambiguous meaning, condensation and overdetermination, claustrophobic enclosure and its negation through the totality of being, constitute the hypnotic unity of movement and paralysis which characterizes Huis Clos. It is certainly No Exit for Ins, as well as for Estelle and Garcin; but many roads lead from it towards the realization of Sartres project. It illustrates very well how much the very nature of his overall quest for what might appear at first sight as mere abstractionthe plenitude of being and the void of nothingnessbrings with it forms of mediation through which even the most abstract ontological determinations can be conveyed as tangible manifestations of human destinies.

2. Philosophy, Literature and Myth


1.

is by no means confined to Sartres conception of Huis Clos. He sees in the same terms Bariona, Flies, The Trojan Women and Kean, as well as Lucifer and the Lord, Altona, and others. Concerning Altona, which he describes as a kind of Gtterdmmerung (crpuscule des dieux)68 he stresses his aim as demystification through inflating its subject matter to the proportion of a myth.69 And in a conversation with Kenneth Tynan he reveals that he would like to write a play on the Greek myth of Alcestis in such a way as to be able to condense into it the drama of womens liberation.70 Equally, he praises the works of his contemporaries in the same key. In an article entitled Forgers of myths the young playwrights of France71 he singles out Anouilhs Antigone, Camuss Caligula and Cross Purposes, and Simone de Beauvoirs Useless Mouths as examples of the same approach to characters and situations that animates his own plays. And twenty years later, in December 1966, he gives a lecture in Bonn with the title Myth and reality of the theatre in which he counterposes the form of drama he stands for to the bourgeois realist theatre whose aim was the direct representation of reality.72 In the same spirit, shortly after his lecture he characterizes Georges Michel as a truly original playwright who succeeded in transcending realism through a deformation towards myth,73 sharply contrasting this with the abstract symbolism of Ionescos Rhinoceros.
T H E I MP ORTAN C E OF MY TH

48

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

As we can see, ever since the time of writing Barionawhen Sartre reaches the conclusion that theatre must be a great collective religious experiencehe remains consistent to a conception of drama and myth. The function of the theatre is to present the individual under the form of myth74 says Sartre in an interview. And he reiterates the same point again and again, with variations in stress and with clarifications. He insists in the conversation with Tynan that the theatre must transpose all its problems into mythic form, and he spends much time clarifying his position in the interview given to New Left Review:
For me the theatre is essentially a myth. Take the example of a petty-bourgeois and his wife who quarrel with each other the whole time. If you tape their disputes, you will record not only the two of them, but the petty-bourgeoisie and its world, what society has made of it, and so on. Two or three such studies and any possible novel on the life of a petty-bourgeois couple would be outclassed. By contrast, the relationship between man and woman as we see it in Strindbergs Dance of Death will never be outclassed. The subject is the same, but taken to the level of myth. The playwright presents to men the eidos of their daily existence: their own life in such a way that they see it as if externally. This was the genius of Brecht, indeed. Brecht would have protested violently if anyone said to him that his plays were myths. Yet what else is Mother Couragean anti-myth that despite itself becomes a myth?75

It does not matter here that Sartres assessment of the possibilities of the novel is highly debatable. What is important is the definition of myth in drama as the eidos of daily existence. This makes it clear that the issue at stake transcends the limits of the theatre, and leads us right into the heart of Sartres overall quest. Indeed, this is the key that opens not only the door of his literary vision but also of his conception of art in general, and beyond. In an earlier essay on Giacometti, Sartre emphasizes the totality of this artists vision, saying that his characters are complete wholes, arising fully made in an instant and gushing forth in my field of vision as an idea in my spirit. He adds: only the idea possesses such immediate translucidity, only the idea is in one blow all that it is. Giacometti accomplishes the unity of multiplicity as the indivisibility of an idea.76 His myth as eidos is not some mysterious hidden absolute but the visible absolute, grasped as the unity of the act, in evidence as appearance in situation.77 Similar considerations are applied to the work of Masson, which is described as mythological in its essence so that the project of painting

P H I LO S OP HY, L IT E R AT U RE, A ND MY TH

49

does not distinguish itself from the project of being man.78 And there is no contradiction whatsoever between the concern with myth and the absolute on one hand and our historical predicament on the other. On the contrary, just like Giacometti, who grasps the absolute as appearance in situation, Massons monstrous universe is nothing else than the comprehensive representation of our own universe.79 For the absolute cannot be taken hold of except precisely through the well defined temporality of human existence. How to make a man out of stone without petrifying himthis is the great question for the sculptor. It is a question of everything or nothing80just like the question of literature, as we have seen above. This applies everywhere, even when the medium is not representational, like Calders mobile constructions which traversed by an Idea81 capture live movements and are, thats all; they are absolutes . . . strange beings, midway between matter and life.

2.

of Sartres conception of his own work as well as of the work of those he values highly it becomes clear that the crucial terms of reference are: myth, drama, absolute, idea, act, totality, conflict and situation. Philosophy fits organically into this picture.
F R O M THIS B R IE F S U RV EY

Today I think that philosophy is dramatic in nature. The time for contemplating the immobility of substances which are what they are, or for laying bare the laws underlying a succession of phenomena, is past. Philosophy is concerned with man who is at once an agent and an actor, who produces and plays his drama while he lives the contradictions of his situation, until either his individuality is shattered or his conflicts are resolved. A play (be it epic, such as Brecht, or dramatic) is the most appropriate vehicle today for showing man in action,i.e. man full stop. It is with this man that philosophy, from its own point of view, should be concerned. That is why the theatre is philosophical and philosophy dramatic.82

Thus philosophy is not abstract self-reflection and detached contemplation but total involvement in the drama of being. The project is concerned with choice and original choice is absolutely the same as destiny.83 Exploring human destiny84 at its greatest intensity is not confined to Sartres plays but characterizes all his synthesizing attempts, from a general

50

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

definition of contemporary European culture as only one aspect of a much greater problem, the whole destiny of Europe,85 to his fundamental works on philosophy. Both Being and Nothingness and Critique of Dialectical Reason are centrally concerned with conflict as inherent in the ontological structure of being as manifest in human destiny. The same drama is indicated in Sartres definition of the core of his moral philosophy, structured around a fundamental antinomy:
In the choice I make of my freedom, the freedom of others is reclaimed. But when I find myself on the plane of action, I am compelled to treat the other as means and not as end. Here we are evidently in the presence of an antinomy, but it is precisely this antinomy which constitutes the moral problem. I shall examine this antinomy in my Morale.86

The fact that after 2,000 pages of examination Sartre remains dissatisfied with the solutions he arrives at and abandons the project does not mean that he changes his mind about the fundamental underlying drama, but, on the contrary, that he finds it even more overpowering than originally thought, as the evidence of his later work clearly shows. The conflict and drama in question is not the quarrel between the pettybourgeois and his wife: philosophy and theatre in his view do not operate at that level. The drama of philosophy is the same as that which makes him conclude that plays are the most appropriate vehicle today for showing man in action: man full stop. The difference is that while philosophy, being a discursive form, can address itself directly to the fundamental question of being, theatre, a representational form, must proceed indirectly, through the presentation of individuals under the form of a myth, and thus producing an adequate artistic mediation between sensible reality and the most general determinations of being. They are similar in that they represent the highest level of synthesis or condensation, and thus they get the closest to the heart of being. This is why drama, in its Sartrean conception, is the most appropriatein Hegels term the most representativeliterary form today; and this is why philosophy, if it wants to be relevant, must be dramatic.

3.
NAT UR AL LY, P HILOS OP H Y A ND D RA MA do not comprehend everything. More precisely, they cannot take hold of all levels of the human totality. In

P H I LO S OP HY, L IT E R AT U RE, A ND MY TH

51

fact, according to Sartre, the sphere of singular universality87 is beyond their reach. Philosophy is dramatic but it does not study the individual as such.88 Nor does drama, for that matter. Consequently, if Sartre wants to study Flaubert as an individual, he cannot do it in drama, nor in philosophy. We have seen his definition of the novel as the totalization of a singular and fictive temporalization. Accordingly, he could tackle this task in the form of a novel, incorporating as best he can all the available factual evidence needed for a satisfactory totalization of the singularity of a historical individual. The consequence of this approach would be an inevitable overflow of the factual documentary material and a tendency to subdue the novelistic elements. Alternatively he could proceed from the available material and fill in the gaps as they appear with the novelists imagination. Paradoxically, the more he seeks to present a total portrait, the more inadequate the documentary evidence must appear, and consequently the more the fictional elements will tend to predominate. Thus, he either abandons full portrayal, or accepts its consequences for the nature of his work. This dilemma is expressed in the curious answer Sartre gives to the question: Why have you personally stopped writing novels?
Because I have felt no urge to do so. Writers have always more or less chosen the imaginary. They have a need for a certain ration of fiction. Writing on Flaubert is enough for me by way of fictionit might indeed be called a novel. Only I would like people to say that it was a true novel. I try to achieve a certain level of comprehension of Flaubert by means of hypotheses. Thus I use fictionguided and controlled, but nonetheless fictionto explore why, let us say, Flaubert wrote one thing on the 15th March and the exact opposite on the 21st March, to the same correspondent, without worrying about the contradiction. My hypotheses are in this sense a sort of invention of the personage.89

The beginning of the answerwhich is simply I dont feel like it gives way to a redefinition of fiction in general, leading to the conclusion that his Flaubert, in the course of his kind of totalization, turned out to be an invented personage and thus a form of novel or fiction. All this is inherent not in some a priori determination of the relationship between philosophy and drama, and philosophy and fiction in general, but in their characteristic Sartrean conception. The crucial determining factor is the conception of his overall quest into which everything is integrated with great vigor. In this vision the overriding determinations are levels of

52

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

generalitydramatic philosophy and philosophical theatre at one pole and the totalization of individuality at the otherand this tends to blur the lines of demarcation between the discursive and the representational forms in Sartres work. There are three clearly distinguishable forms of manifestation of this tendency: 1. In his shorter essaysfor example on Giacometti, Nizan, Merleau-Ponty, Gorzs Traitordiscursive and representational forms are often fused in lyric passages and in a conscious effort to give an evocative unity, a forceful Gestalt, to the essay as a whole, no matter how abstract the problems tackled in particular contexts. 2. Representational elements abound in his major philosophical works (e.g. the treatment of bad faith in Being and Nothingness), and philosophical elements in his plays and novels. 3. Perhaps the most significant in this respect: fictional totalization tends to turn into philosophical discourse, to the point of forcing him to abandon it (see Roads to Freedom, especially the fourth volume), and his most important critical monograph, on Flaubert (and this is by no means the only one) tends to turn into fiction. These characteristics cannot be isolated from the innermost nature of Sartres totalizing quest. For the concern with singular universality cannot stop at that level but must strive through totalization towards universality or the absolute, whatever formal transformations may necessarily follow from such movement. On the other hand, the Sartrean absolute is not some rarefied abstraction occupying a mysterious sphere of its own, but is existentially situated and therefore must always be rendered tangible through the evocative power of condensation and individuation at the writers disposal. This is why, despite his boundless admiration for Kafka, the latters fictional style and method of representation, with its hidden yet threateningly mysterious omnipresent absolute, constitute an altogether different universe of discourse which cannot conceivably be adopted by Sartre as the model of his novels. Problematical as some of the formal characteristics of Sartres work may at times appear, they are necessary manifestations of his overall vision in particular contexts, and thus cannot be properly weighed up without comprehending the nature of the whole. Significantly enough, his closely integrated

P H I LO S OP HY, L IT E R AT U RE, A ND MY TH

53

conception of philosophy and literature appears at a very early age. The same year that he writes the letter contributing to the student enquiry (1929) he also conceives The Legend of Truth:90 a strange mixture of philosophy, myth and literature of which only a fragment has been published. It is a kind of Urnebel (the Kantian primeval fog) from which the later creations emerge, through manifold differentiations and metamorphoses. What is clearly in evidence from the very beginning is that for Sartre form and meaning are always linked,91 indeed in an organic fashion. The overall configuration of meaning determines the form, and the articulation of form carries with it the concrete definition of meaning. The not very happy symbiosis of The Legend of Truth soon gives way to the primarily philosophical or predominantly literary works of the 1930s, without completely abolishing the reciprocal interpenetration. Nevertheless, Sartre feels that there are certain things in his overall quest which are too technical and therefore prescribe a purely philosophical vocabulary, and he promises to double up, so to speak, every novel with an essay.92 This is still a rather nave diagnosis of the problem, characteristic of the avid learner of the new philosophical vocabulary of German phenomenology and existentialism. Once he has behind him this period of learning and succeeds in elaborating his own vocabulary, he soon discovers not only that there can be no doubling up between philosophy and novels, except for a short transitory period, but also that the real affinity for him is between philosophy and theatre, not between philosophy and fiction. Furthermore, in the course of articulating his original philosophical concepts in Being and Nothingness he realizes that they need not indeed cannot be kept in separate compartments, but call for the unity of philosophy and literature in the service of his monumental quest for man. Already Being and Nothingness is unthinkable without his conscious appeal to the idea of such a unity.

4.

cannot be understood without focusing attention on the network of terms and usages he introduces in the course of his development. They constitute a coherent set of closely interconnected concepts, each with its own field of radiation and points of link-up with all the others. This is obvious if we think of such examples as authenticity, anguish, bad faith, the spirit of seriousness, contingency, nausea, viscosity, facticity, negation, nihilation, freedom, project,
T H E SP EC IF IC IT Y OF SARTRES WO RK

54

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

commitment (engagement), possibility, responsibility, adventure, flight, chance, determination, seriality, fused group, temporalization, totalization, de-totalization, condensation, overdetermination, mediation, progression-regression, singular universal, irreducibility, and so on. However, we are talking about an omnipresent characteristic which comes to the fore even in the most unsuspected places and forms. Whether it is a direct confrontation of a major philosophical issue or of an apparently everyday matter, Sartres terms of analysis and evaluation are always typically his own, and from any particular point of detail they link up with the main supporting pillars of his thought structure. Take the term invention. Talking about the intellectual, of his vain yearning for universality, he makes his point like this:
I remember seeing a puppy after the partial removal of the cerebellum. He moved across the room, rarely colliding with the furniture, but he had become thoughtful. He established his itinerary carefully. He pondered before going around an object, requiring a great deal of time and thought to accomplish movements to which he had previously paid no attention. In the language of the time, we said that the cortex had assumed for him certain functions of the lower regions. He was an intellectual dog. I dont know whether this made him very useful or harmful to his kind, but we can quite well imagine that he had lost what Genet, another exile, has so well named, sweet natal confusion. To sum up, he either had to die or reinvent the dog. So we othersrats without cerebellawe are also so made that we must either die or reinvent man. Moreover, we know perfectly well that man will make himself without us, through working and fighting, that our models become obsolete from one day to the next, that nothing will remain of them in the finished product, not even a bone, but that also, without us, the fabrication would take place in the dark, by tinkering and patching, if we, the debrained, were not there to repeat constantly that we must work according to principles, that it is not a matter of mending, but of measuring and constructing, and finally, that mankind will be the concrete universal, or that it will not be.93

To suggest that the dog reinvents the dog is, of course, most unusual, to say the least. And yet it does not matter in the slightest whether or not Sartres description would match an objective scientific account. For the point is not about the dog but about man who has to be reinvented. And, again, invention-reinvention is by no means the term that would most

P H I LO S OP HY, L IT E R AT U RE, A ND MY TH

55

naturally present itself in the context. But, is the idea less unusual than the term of which Sartre avails himself to convey it? How can one reinvent man without falling into extreme voluntarism? Obviously one cannot if the term is taken in its literal sense, but that is not how it is intended. Nor is it intended as a poetic image. The meaning is conceptual, not figurative. But it is conceptual in the sense of the earlier discussed totalizing condensationoverdetermination; that is it derives its full meaning from the multiplicity of structural-contextual interconnections. It would be relatively easy to find some terms that could express in a more literal and univocal form the central idea of the passage on reinvention. But at what price? It would mean not only the loss of the writers characteristic style, but of a great deal of the meaning as well. Sartre deliberately chooses a term which keeps the central idea somewhat out of focus, in order to bring a multiplicity of allusions and connections into a joint focus. For the depth as well as the field of radiation of any particular concept is determined by the totality of interconnections it can summon up whenever it appears on its own. The difference between a profound thinker and a shallow one is that the former always operates with a whole network of organically interpenetrating concepts, whereas the latter contents himself with isolated terms and one-sided definitions. Thus the first establishes connections even when he has to single out specific contexts and draw lines of demarcation, while the second loses even the most obvious connections when he sacrifices complexity to shallow analytical precision and to the univocal clarity of oversimplification in place of overdetermination. Let us consider briefly the field of Sartres concept of invention. We have already quoted one of the contexts in which he suggests that The reader invents us: he uses our words to set his own traps for himself.94 This is not paradox for the sake of paradox. It underlines a firm belief that inventing is not a sovereign activity, carried out from a safe distance, but a complex relationship of being inside and outside simultaneously, like man who makes and reinvents himself by being both at one with his own projects and at some distance from them. (As we can see, the idea of distance is an integral part of these considerations, both as it appears in Sartres discussion of Giacometti and in his references to Brechts vision of the simultaneity of inside and outside achieved through his Verfremdungseffekt.) Talking about Genet, Sartre brings another aspect into the foreground. Genius is not a gift but an outcome one invents in desperate situations.95 Here invention is response to a situation in which everything seems to be lostit is like the sudden leap and escape of the cornered animal above the head of its pursuers.

56

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Similarly, authentic feelings, essential to the production of good literature, are not just given, in advance; every one must invent them in his turn.96 Thus, again paradoxically, the spontaneity of authentic feeling is an invented spontaneity. Nor is this an isolated instance. The Liberation of Paris in 1944 is described as the explosion of freedom, the rupture of the established order and the invention of an efficacious and spontaneous order.97 We are thus presented with invention as a fusion of negativity and positivity: invented discipline triumphs over learned discipline, and Apocalypse is defined as a spontaneous organization of the revolutionary forces, foreshadowing a central problem of Sartres Critique of Dialectical Reason. Invention is the key term also when, in 1947, he speaks about the need to invent the road to a socialist Europe98 in order to secure humanitys survival. And in 1968, appealing for Power to the imagination, he recalls that in 1936 [the working class] invented the occupation of factories because that was its only weapon to consolidate and to exploit its electoral victory.99 In a similar vein, he talks about the task of inventing a university whose aim is no longer the selection of an elite but the transfer of culture to all.100 One could go on giving further examples from different fields of Sartres thought, from his ontology to his theory of language, but there is no need. The instances we have seen so far are amply sufficient to indicate the nature of the conceptual interconnections earlier referred to. Linking invention to a paradox is not a formal stylistic device but a recognition of objective constraint, to be transcended by the act of invention which itself is the paradoxical result of such constraint. (A cunning of history against its own determinations, if you like.) Thus freedom and order, discipline and spontaneity, negation and self-affirmation, etc., are brought into play as necessary dimensions of invention as a human enterprise. All these dimensions must be simultaneously recalled, by means of the condensation of a multiplicity of interrelations into a joint focus, in order to be able to link the part to the whole and thus to confer upon it its full significance. This is how, starting out from Sartres invention of the dog which reinvents the dog, we arrive at the roots of the human enterprise: man reinventing man and thus producing the concrete universal. But we must note not only the structure of conceptual interconnections but also its sign in Sartre: not unproblematically positive attainment but prevalent negativity. For the way in which invention articulates itself through its linkages is dominated by distance and constraint, determination and anguish from which invention extricates itself only for an ecstatic moment. In such moments, when freedom explodes and imagination

P H I LO S OP HY, L IT E R AT U RE, A ND MY TH

57

assumes power (or genius commutes a mans death sentence into his lifeimprisonment as a writer), the ecstatic fusion of human interchange manifests itself as the doomed temporality of Apocalypse which is always defeated by order101by the established order, that is, to which invented discipline and spontaneous order do not seem to be able to provide a lasting answer. This is why in the end the positive moment of invention cannot be envisaged by Sartre except as a radical negation of the powers of alienation and negativity. Thus a passionate ought. The inventive task of making humanity is spelled out not as the construction of a system (be it the socialist system) but as the destruction of all systems.102

5.
I T I S NE C E S SARY TO I NTRO D UCE here another complex of problems: Sartres conception of temporality as one of the most fundamental constituents of his system of ideas, determining the articulation of many of his specific concepts. In a very early piece on LArt cinmatographique (1931),103 Sartre contrasts the temporality of scienceits conception of irreversible order and absolutely determining march forward, which would be unbearable as a feeling if it went with all our actionswith the sudden movements and spontaneous manifestations of life perceived by the individual. He suggests that the arts of movement (music, theatre, cinema) have the task of representing this irreversible order outside us, painted in things. He talks about the fatality of musical progression in the melody; of tragedys forced march towards the catastrophe, and of a kind of fatality also in the cinema. He characterizes music as abstraction and tragedy as strongly intellectual . . . a product of reason . . . a logical deduction starting from certain principles proposed right at the beginning. While the unfolding of action in the cinema too is described as fatal, it is contrasted with the theatre in that it has not got the abstract and cut time of tragedy. According to Sartre, it is the cinema which represents by nature the civilization of our epoch. Cinema is the art form which is the closest to the real world, which captures best the inhuman necessity of the dure of our life, and teaches us the poetry of speed and of the machines, the inhumanity and splendid fatality of industry. What saves the cinema from the abstract and cut time of the theatre as well as from its intellectualism is its simultaneity and overimpression (or overprinting, superimpressionthe predecessor of Sartres

58

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

concept of overdetermination). He refers to Abel Gances Napoleon in which the imagery of a tempest at the Convention is intensified by the scenes of a tempest on the Mediterranean. The two themes are cut into each other in such a way that they accuse and enlarge themselves and in the end they fuse with one another. Just as in Giacometti, the particular themes do not convey their meaning individually but only if they are taken together in a combined unity. Thanks to the formal characteristics of overimpression the artist can develop several themes simultaneously and thus achieve a cinematographic poliphony. Many points of this analysis are changed in the course of Sartres subsequent development. Yet, the enrichment and concretization of his views proceeds from the concepts first spelled out in this article. As he discovers the theatre for himself through his own practice, he changes his views on abstract time and intellectualism as necessarily inherent in all theatre. That is to say, in the light of his own dramatic work he identifies the intellectual type of drama with a certain form of classical tradition which he continues to oppose. Talking about Flies he insists that he aims at creating the tragedy of freedom in opposition to the tragedy of fatality.104 Also, he retains his aversion to intellectualism when he criticizes Orson Welless film, Citizen Kane, as an intellectual work, the work of an intellectual,105 which shows that the affirmation of spontaneity is a Leitmotif of his own work, from its earliest inception. And in terms of formal criteria, he retains and expands the idea of simultaneity linked to overimpression (overdetermination) and the polyphony of integrated multiplicity (condensation and joint focus), as we have seen. But this is as far as we can go in identifying similarities. Sartres tragedy of freedom is inconceivable on the basis of his youthful conception of temporality and causation, since it accepts necessity and fatality as the guiding principles of all three art forms he refers to. Consequently the characteristics of simultaneity and polyphony can only soften the blow; they cannot transcend the fundamental determination and limits of fatality. Characteristically, he has to ask us to admire cinemas inflexible but supple concatenation (enchainement inflexible, mais souple)106 which is not much more than a consolation prize in the form of a verbal-paradoxical solution. Ex pumice acquamone cannot squeeze spontaneity and freedom out of fatality by calling it supple. We can witness in Sartres youthful article on the cinema a tension between his passionate adherence to spontaneity, the surprise of life, and the acceptance of a conception of temporality as absolute concatenation in the

P H I LO S OP HY, L IT E R AT U RE, A ND MY TH

59

world around us (which inevitably means that the cinema, closest to the real world, representing real man in a real countryside, real mountains and real sea,107 etc., is essentially trapped and only marginally free). This is a fertile tension because it is not simply a conflict of ideas but a contradiction between a restrictive theory and an existential striving towards freedom. In order to extricate himself from this contradiction Sartre has to get rid of Bergsonwhose libert intrieure, with its evasion of the question of destiny, is, as Sartre later recognizes, an illusory freedom, remaining always merely theoretical and intellectual,108 but not real (existential)and elaborate a conception of temporality in affinity with his own quest. This new conception of temporality is clearly formulated in an essay on Faulkner, written in 1939, in which Sartre analyses The Sound and the Fury,109 concentrating on the question of time. The contrast between affective (emotional) and intellectual order of time found in the youthful essay is recognized in Faulkners novel as treated in favor of the affective order, to Sartres great satisfaction. What bothers him is the absence of the future. Nothing happens, everything has already happened . . . the present is only . . . past future (p. 68). Proust and Faulkner have simply decapitated time, they removed its future, that is the dimension of acts and freedom.110 The way Quentins suicide is treated shows that he has no human possibilities; what we are confronted with is not a human enterprise, it is fatality.111 The whole problem hinges on the future: If the future is real, time moves away from the past and brings nearer the future; but if you suppress the future, time is nothing but what separates, that which cuts off the present from itself.112 But is it true, asks Sartre, that human time is devoid of future? The temporality of the nail, of a lump of earth, of the atom, is perpetual present. But man, is he a thinking nail? Faulkner, in accordance with his vision of time, represents man as a creature deprived of possibilities. He defines man as the sum of all that he has.113 To this Sartre opposes his own definition of man as the totality of that he does not yet have, of all that he could have.114 In History and Class Consciousness (1923), Lukcs analyses possible consciousness as the consciousness of a historically progressive class which has a future ahead of it and therefore has the possibility of objective totalization. In our epoch, according to Lukcs, only the proletariat has proper temporality, inseparable from the possibility of socio-historical totalization, because the bourgeoisie has lost its futurebecause its temporality, as Sartre puts it about Proust and Faulkner, has been decapitatedin that its fundamental aims as a class are radically incompatible

60

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

with the objective tendencies of historical development. Given this fundamental contradiction between aim and reality, the class without future cannot realize the unity of subject and object but must, instead, produce a dualistic-antinomous structure of thought, centred around individualism and subjectivity, and dominated by the conditions of reification which it can oppose only in and through subjectivity, thus exacerbating the contradiction between subject and object. Heidegger, facing the Lukcsian problematic, proposes a solution by transcending Lukcs towards his youthful essay, The metaphysics of tragedy (1910) published in the volume Soul and Form, in which nearly two decades before Heidegger Lukcs had spelled out some of the central themes of modern existentialism.115 Heidegger offers a conception of temporality which ascribes possibility (projection towards the future ultimately identified with death, in the spirit of The metaphysics of tragedy) to consciousness in general. Thus, by turning possibility into an ontological dimension of consciousness as such, Lukcss Marxian critique of bourgeois class consciousness is theoretically liquidated, and a project of unified ontology is announced, on the basis of the Heideggerian reconstruction of subjectivity. Significantly, however, the project is never brought to its conclusion. And twentyfive years after publishing Being and Time originally intended as the founding preliminary to the overall project Heidegger is forced to make an admission: While the previous editions have borne the designation First Half, this has now been deleted. After a quarter of a century, the second half could no longer be added unless the first were to be presented anew.116 This sounds very reasonable, except that no reasons are given for the failure to complete, not just in twenty-five years but ever since, the whole project. Clearly we are not concerned with Heideggers Nazism which is more like a consequence than the causebut with the nature of the project itself: the extreme subjectivism of its temporality and being. Ex pumice acquamone cannot squeeze the foundation of being out of a mythically inflated subjectivity by calling it Fundamental Ontology. Sartre adopts some elements of Heideggers conception when he writes: The nature of consciousness implies that it throws itself forward by itself into the future . . . it determines itself in its present being by its own possibilities: this is what Heidegger calls the silent force of the possible 117 At the same time, right from the beginning, he goes well beyond Heidegger, putting the German philosopher to his own use. Proceeding from his own existential quest for freedom and spontaneity, he finds support in Heideggers conception of temporality against fatality and inertia. But this is only the

P H I LO S OP HY, L IT E R AT U RE, A ND MY TH

61

negative side of his overall view. The positive aspect is clearly exemplified in a beautiful concluding passage of the essay on Faulkner:
How comes it that Faulkner and so many other authors have chosen an absurdity which is so little in character with the novel, and so little true? I believe we have to look for reasons in the social conditions of our present day life. It seems to me that Faulkners despair precedes his metaphysics: for him, as for us all, the future is barred. Everything we see, everything we live through, incites us to say: It cannot last, and meanwhile change isnt even conceivable except in the form of a cataclysm. We live in the epoch of impossible revolutions, and Faulkner employs his extraordinary artistry to describe this world which is dying of old age, and our suffocation. I love his art, and I dont believe in his metaphysics: a barred future is still a future.118

The phrase a barred future is still a future (which becomes the model of many a Sartrean paradox, like refusal to commit oneself is a form of commitment, or failure to choose is itself a choice) does not mean much, if anything, in and by itself. What breathes life into this abstract formal tautology is the context (or situation) into which it is inserted. The subjectivism of the Heideggerian conception of temporality helps Sartre negate the barred future of an epoch torn by the inherent contradiction of the necessity of change and the impossibility of revolutions. Yetand this is what decides the issuethe whether or not of impossible revolutions is a question of real temporality which is being decided in the actual sociohistorical arena. Thus while the abstract temporality of a barred future is still a future negates the real temporality of social inertia (determined by the temporal-historical conditions of alienation and reification), this subjectivist temporality of abstract possibility is also being negated by the real possibility of actual revolutions. Heideggerian purists would no doubt describe the way Sartre inserts the adopted concepts into the context seen above as eclecticism. In fact, such eclecticism constitutes Sartres exemplary originality and philosophical significance. He succeeds in freeing himself of the tension manifest in his youthful conception of temporality by acquiring a much greater tension. The latter is not only much greater it is incomparably more fertile as well. From now on, even if he does not yet know it (perceiving change in his own development as commitment initiated by the war) he is situated right in the turmoil of real temporality which he cannot just contemplate from the sideline, from the temporalit intrieure of literary withdrawal. Indeed,

62

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

his act of commitment during the war becomes possible within the framework of this new conception and intensified existential tension which are suitable to provide the basis of articulating a rich lifework. For without the changed framework he might well respond to the inhumanity of the war and the fatality of falling bombs in terms of the same decadent aestheticism of interiority with which he once raved about the poetry of speed, of the machines and about the inhumanity and splendid fatality of industry. But cataclysm arrives and is followed by upheavals and revolutions some unfinished, others defeated, others still partially successful, or delayed, frustrated, brutally interfered with, but all painfully real. Could it be that they all should have no major consequences for the other side of the contradiction locked up in Sartres new existential tension? Hardly, as his subsequent development clamorously proves.

6.
T H I S I S NOT T HE P OIN T TO A NTICIPATE Sartres later development, but to lay bare the structure of his thought as the inner necessity that constitutes a vital condition of such development. In this sense, we have to indicate another fundamental dimension: the way in which Sartre becomes a moral philosopher malgr lui. The problem arises out of the characterization of the present as an inert totality: a world dying of old age, an epoch of impossible revolutions, spreading and intensifying the feeling of paralysis even through the consciousness of cataclysm as the only feasible form of change. How can the abstract proposition of barred future is still a future effectively negate such gloom and doom? Only if it is turned into a categorical absolute which necessarily transcends all given temporality, no matter how suffocatingly real. And who is the subject of this barred future? If it is the individual, the proposition is clearly false, because barred future for the individual is inexorably barred. On the other hand, if the subject is mankind, the proposition is absurd, because mankind cannot possibly have a barred future except by barring it for itself in the form of a collective suicide, in which case there can be no future, barred or unbarred nor indeed mankind, for that matter. Paradoxically, the existential (non-tautological) meaning of the proposition is produced by conflating the individual and the collective subject. Its meaning is thus not what it literally suggests (a tautology or a banality at best), but the functional meaning of a radical negation which cannot point

P H I LO S OP HY, L IT E R AT U RE, A ND MY TH

63

at tangible historical forces as carriers of its truth and therefore must assume the form of a categorical imperative: the moral ought. This dimension of Sartres structure of thought, as inextricably linked to the question of individual and collective subject, remains a fundamental characteristic of his work throughout his development. Not that there can be no changes in this respect for the rest of his life, for there are many. The point is that such changes as they arise must always affect this whole set of relations, notably the problems of temporality and morality as articulated in terms of subject and object, the individual and the collective subject. These problems are discussed in Part Three; here the point is simply to stress the necessary interconnection between Sartres conception of temporality and the paradoxical specificity of his moral philosophy. The truth is that the latter is not an explicit but a latent moral philosophy and it remains so no matter how hard he tries in some unfinished (unfinishable) manuscripts to turn it into an explicit one. To some extent it resembles his writing lyric poetry: he cannot write it because he does write itin a diffuse formall the time. It is inherent in all his analyses, as the positive standpoint of the future which assumes the form of a radical negation while it is unable to identify itself with a historical subject. In the specific works which he is forced to abandon his attempts at rendering explicit his moral principles are necessarily frustrated because he tries to accomplish the task while remaining within the confines of his phenomenological-existential ontology, which renders redundant such explicitness. Paradoxically, in order to remain a moral philosopher Sartres moral philosophy must remain latent. In order to spell out his latent moral philosophy in a fully developed form, as he tries to again and again, Sartre would have to substantially modify the structure of his philosophy as a whole, including the function of the categorical moral ought in it. But such modification would radically displaceindeed, possibly render superfluousprecisely the categorical moral ought in the structure of his thought. Thus he could produce his projected Morale only by ceasing to be a moral philosopher at all. This explains why, curiously, his conscious efforts aimed at transcending his earlier positions result in their strongest possible reaffirmation as the necessary precondition of the impossible enterprise he is involved in: the deduction of a socially oriented moral philosophy from the ontological structure of individual praxes. No text is nearer to his original system as spelled out in Being and Nothingness than Determination and freedom, a lecture delivered twentythree years later, in May 1966, at the Gramsci Institute in Rome, and part of

64

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

a substantial manuscript on his Morale. It could be inserted into the pages of the early work, Being and Nothingness, without too much difficulty. By the same token, if he wants to transcend some of his earlier positions, he has to do it without really trying. That is, he has to transcend through expansion, by bringing into the picture new ontological structuresas indeed he does, in his Critique of Dialectical Reasonwhich objectively imply a certain supersession, even if he does not spell it out in what is intended again as a first volume. This means that the old and the new structures must be left side by side, without integration. For as soon as the task of integration is attempted, in the second volume or in some related work, the inherent difficulty of moving from latency to explicitness presents itself with renewed intensity, and we are back to the world of Being and Nothingness through the route of Determination and freedom. We can see, then, how right Sartre is when he characterizes his concern with morality as his dominant preoccupation. With one necessary qualification. This concern enters his horizon malgr lui, in a paradoxical form, via his definition of temporality and transcendence as opposed to his earlier conception. Up to the time of writing LArt cinmatographique, and for a few years thereafter, there can be no room for morality in his world of sheltered interiority which laughs off mans concern with Good and Evil as useless ideology and aesthetically reconciles itself with the splendid fatality of capitalist inhumanity, without realizing the enormity of such pronouncements. Thus when Paul Nizan, his closest friend, notes while reviewing Nausea119 that Sartres thought is entirely alien to moral problems, he is correct in characterizing an early phase in Sartres development, although it is highly debatable whether one should include Nausea in it. (Nizan is no doubt influenced by the memory of their college discussions.) In any case, it is a very limited phase. By the time Nausea is published, it is certainly over, thanks to Sartres investigation of the nature of emotion and imagination, and thanks to his radical redefinition of temporality.

7.
SA RT R E S NET WOR K OF CO NCEP TS constitutes an amazingly coherent whole in which the particular elements are organically linked. The way he uses invention, for instance, might appear at times rather subjective, perhaps even capricious, so long as it is not related to the conceptual framework as a whole. But as soon as we become aware of the related concepts, as we

P H I LO S OP HY, L IT E R AT U RE, A ND MY TH

65

have seen above, the one-sided impression of subjectivity disappears. The Sartrean concept of invention would indeed seem extremely voluntaristic and even utterly futile within his own youthful vision of temporality. Not so in his later conception. Once the fatality of absolute determination and irreversible concatenation is banished from his picture, invention and imagination can come into their own and acquire a major importance in his system of ideas. Conversely, too, his preoccupation with the Imagination and LImaginaire (the latter translated into English as the Psychology of Imagination) greatly contribute to the elaboration of his conception of temporality. Past becomes associated with the intellectual ordera sombre condition, without surprise, ruled by the one-sided causality of concatenationand with inertia, lifelessness, despair. In Citizen Kane the game is over. We are not involved in a novel but in a story in the past tense. . . . Everything is analyzed, dissected, presented in the intellectual order, in a false disorder which is the subordination of events to the rule of cause; everything is dead.120 The same goes for Zola with whom everything obeys the narrowest kind of determinism. Zolas books are written from the past, while my characters have a future.121 And when he realizes that the future is locked out from some of his own works, he does not hesitate to condemn them. Talking about Men without shadows (Morts sans spulture: unburied dead) he insists that It is a failed play . . . the destiny of the victims is absolutely determined in advance . . . The cards are already on the table. It is a very sombre play, without surprise.122 Similarly with volume IV of Roads to Freedom, which he abandons. Simone de Beauvoir echoes Sartres own strictures and imagery of gambling when she comments: For his heroes, at the end of Drle damiti [the chapter published from volume IV] the game is over.123 It is the future that gets his approval, expressed with great consistency in the positive connotation of its field of associated concepts, from hope and authenticity to surprise and life, and from the affective order (the opposite of intellectual order) to dialectical totalization which brings to life the object of its synthesis, instead of dissecting it on the mortuary table of analysis for the sake of analysis. Of course, as has been stressed repeatedly, we are talking about a unique fusion of subjectivity and objectivity. Sartre makes no claims to scientific objectivity. His network of concepts aims as much at evoking as at situating and explaining. Yet, his fused subjective objectivity is infinitely more objective than the pretended objectivity of academic jargon. Knowing only too well that we are always within the parameters of mans fundamental quest, he does not simply observe and describe; he participates and moves at

66

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

the same time as he demonstrates. His way has nothing in common with the pseudo-scientific objectivity of socially insensitive academic jargon that resembles the enzymes of the digestive system which turn everything that comes their way invariably into the same sort of end-product. Sartres conceptual framework is radically different. It is more like a sensitive dual prism which collects from all directions the lightwaves of the epoch of which he is an exemplary witness. He breaks up the received impressions into their constituents through the dual prism of his compelling personality only to resynthesize them in his totalizing vision that powerfully re-enters the world from which it is taken. To show and move at the same time, from the standpoint of the feasible futurethat is his aim. This implies being simultaneously outside and inside and it explains why he needs the combined powers of philosophy, literature and myth. Id like that the public should see our century, this strange thing, from outside, as a witness. And that, at the same time everyone should participate, for this century is made by the public.124 Sartre takes his full share in making this century, by attacking its fetishes and increasing its self-awareness. It is this character of participating testimony, creative and revealing commitment to a total involvement, which gives his lifework its philosophical depth and its dramatic intensity.

3. From The Legend of Truth to a True Legend: Phases of Sartres Development


1.
BE I N G S IM U LTANE OU S LY O UTSID E and inside is also the task of a biographer, as Sartre himself clearly demonstrates on more than one occasion (Baudelaire, Mallarm, Genet, Flaubert). Writing on someone is a specific relationship between two distinct singular temporalizations in which sometimes affinities, sometimes elements of contrast predominate. In the case of Flaubert, it is primarily the contrast that attracts Sartres attention: Flaubert represents for me the exact opposite of my own conception of literature: a total disengagement and a certain idea of form, which is not that which I admire . . . He began to fascinate me precisely because I saw him in every way as the contrary of myself.125 On other occasions (for example when writing on Mallarm and on Genet), major affinities are in the foreground. But whether confrontations or affinities set the tone, the job of revealing exploration cannot be properly done without combining the viewpoints of inside and outside: the sympathetic understanding of inner motivations, however sharp the contrast, and the forward drive of critical transcendence, however close the affinities.

68

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Writing on someone is connecting two socio-historically different temporalizations, even when Lenin writes about Marx. Such an enterprise sets out from the premise that the first is meaningful for the second, provided that the process of explorationwhich is at the same time also a form of clarifying self-reflectioncan mediate to the present those features of the original temporalization which objectively contribute to the solution of given tasks and problems. Reflection on the past can only proceed from the meaning the present gives itselfvery much in the spirit of the Sartrean projection towards the future: that is, towards the solution of the existing tasksbut the very act of reflection, in virtue of establishing determinate relationships with the past, inevitably also determines its own orientation. Thus reflection and critical exploration become self-reflection and critical self-definition. The meaning of the present is used as a key to unlock the meaning of the past leading to the present, which in its turn unlocks formerly unidentified dimensions of the present leading to the future not in the form of rigid mechanical determinations but as anticipations of aims linked to a set of inner motivations. Thus we are involved in a dialectic movement which leads from the present to the past and from the past to the future. In this movement the past is not somewhere there, in its remote finality and closure, but right here, open and situated between the present and the future, paradoxical as it may sound to those who think in terms of the intellectual order of mechanical chronology. For the fact is that the present can only have one mediation between itself and the future: not the infinitesimal empty moment that separates it from what lies ahead, but the great wealth and intensity of a past, brought to life in the expounded time of searching reflection and critical self-examination. History is thus not simply unalterable but inexhaustible. This is what gives sense to being concerned with the past and determines the need for constant reinterpretations. Nothing is more absurd than the notion of definitive history, and definitive treatment of this or that period, or a definitive biography, etc., which, by implication, anticipate a stage when, given the abundant accumulation of definitive chunks, there will be no more need for a constant re-examination of history. In the event of such definitiveness, it would not be only the historian who puts himself out of business but man himself who can ignore or routinize his past only at the price of decapitating his own future. However, there is no danger that such notions might prevail except perhaps in some areas of institutionalized irrelevance. To be sure, the industry of routinized popular history and biography must promise its

F R O M THE " L E G E ND OF TRUTH " TO A "TRUE LEGEND "

69

readers (who are denied the chance of making history beyond the point of abdication through the ballot box) the thrill of authentic voyeurism, providing them with the consolation of definitive treatments and allegedly great secret revelations. If ones participation is confined to looking in on history through the keyhole, the spectacle had better be seen as definitive, so as to give one the illusion of observing history in its finality and massive permanence. For mans relation to the past is no privileged domain of positivistically disoriented specialists but an existential dimension inseparable from the dilemmas and challenges of the present. Evaluation of past events and figures, in so far as it arises from the needs of a determinate relationship, has to be as definitive as possible in terms of the given relationship which necessarily means that the more definitive it is as a specific articulation of linked socio-historical temporalizations, the less definitive it can be in its universality. Or, to put it more precisely, its universality must manifest itself through a determinate socio-historical temporality. Only the skeleton of pure chronology can have some sort of mute universality and neutral validityin that it extends over all periods which is indistinguishable from sheer immediacy and flat particularity. For the data of pure chronology must first be selected and arranged in a structured order, from a determinate historical standpoint, before they can acquire any meaning whatsoever. Thus meaning, at any level and in all contexts, is not simply found in the subject of ones enquiry (as some sociological and other scientific myth-makers presume, condemning themselves to tottering at the level of generality of a local telephone directory without its self-evident function), but unfolded from it through the meaning of the searching temporality. Saying with Sartre that the important thing is not what one is but what one does is one side of a vital interrelationship. The other was spelled out by Goethe when he insisted that to be able to do something one must already be something.126 It is this being in a situation at a determinate juncture in history, rooted in specific social forces with their interests, needs and orientation, which constitutes the necessary principle of selection. Without that how could one simply reproduce the meaning of Sartres work, short of reprinting his eight or nine million words, together with an account of a few million related facts and events? Such an enterprise would amount to doing absolutely nothing, even if it were possible. What makes Isaac Deutschers biographies lasting works is not that they contain everything in a definitive form (how could they?), but that they offer a meaningful selection of data, relevant to his own quest and to the orientation of his contemporaries.

70

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Thus, the most important single factor in the constitution of meaning is the underlying passion that animates the search itself. All this does not mean, of course, that objectivity in history is negated. On the contrary, a precise definition of its nature and limits rescues historical objectivity from the fate of extreme relativism which it suffers through the self-contradictory aspirations of positivism and scientism. They start from the presumed objectivity of completeness, ignoring the arbitrariness of the choice of the enquiry itself, whereby the proper relationship between research and researcher is completely overturned. It is not the researcher who looks for data; on the contrary, the availability of abundant data produces the reified researcher of institutionalized routine. And, of course, the self-justifying ideology of such procedure takes the form of ruling out the need for justification of any research whatsoever, absolving its triviality and irrelevance. Anything goes that can be researched, nailed to a display board in a form through which the dead objectivity of dusty data is linked to an impersonally objective pseudo-subject. Are we not reassured by the originator of this practice (Ranke) that all human facts and events are equidistant from God? He spends his life fighting historical relativism, only to end up producing the most exasperated form of it. This is supremely ironical. For the methodology of unstructured completeness liquidates not only historical objectivity but itself as well. It turns the equidistant data into tokens of equally meaningful or meaningless equivalences, thus nihilating any need for completeness: its original aim and raison dtre. And having succeeded in nihilating its own ground, it turns the activity of producing equidistant equivalences into a form of self-consuming superfluity. In truth, the only God relevant to human history is made in the image of living three-dimensional man, and therefore the data of this history are decidedly not equidistant from him. Some are more meaningful than others, and some are more meaningful to one epoch than to another. Objectivity in history is not that of a nail, let alone of a stone, for man is not a thinking nail, as Sartre often reminds us. Historical objectivity is dynamic and changing, as is life not in and by itselffor that would be still reducible to a set of more or less simplified natural lawsbut as it evolves, on a natural basis radically modified by work and self-reflection, in the social sphere. The objectivity of the search itself is determined by the conditions of a given temporality which, of course, include anticipations and assessments of future trends of development. Nonetheless, in its dynamic objectivity, every search is subject to criteria of evaluation both as regards its social determinants (including their limitations) and the nature (realistic or otherwise) of its anticipations.

F R O M THE " L E G E ND OF TRUTH " TO A "TRUE LEGEND "

71

Similarly, in the past itself we are concerned with linking temporalizations, and not with some arbitrary projection backwards onto an empty screen. For while the past is inexhaustible, it is certainly not characterless. It cannot be just moulded, whichever way one pleases, in accordance with arbitrary whim and caprice: the weight and inner logic of its evidence sets objective limits to possible reinterpretations. The past is inexhaustible not in an by itself but in virtue of the fact that it is objectively linked to the future which is never completely made. As man makes his own history, on the basis of temporal and structural determinationspreserving and transcending them certain characteristics of the past come to the fore which were not visible before. They were not visible not because people were blind or shortsighted (though, of course, there is an abundance of such instances too) but because they did not exist in the same form before the objective articulation of determinate relationships. The ground has certain features before the house is built on it, which in certain conditions (of which the house itself is an integral part), are painfully evidenced as subsidence by the cracks in the wall. The future does not invent or create the characteristics of the past but articulates them in the course of its own self-realization. This produces the need for constant reinterpretations, setting at the same time well defined objective limits as to which way and how far they can go. In the course of such reinterpretationsin so far as they correspond to a genuine movement in the social sphere that generates them, rather than being mechanically turned out by the routine of a reified industry of culturethe previous ones are inevitably aufgehoben (not refuted) in the sense that a more advanced stage can unfold a greater complexity of meaning out of the subject of its linking search. Lukcss assessment of Goethe gives a deeper insight into the great German writer than Hegels reflections on him, irrespective of the comparative stature of the two philosophers. Nor does his evaluation lay claims to definitiveness. The characteristic feature of a Marxist line of approach is not some attempt to go beyond the sphere of its own transcendabilitya petrified absurditybut precisely its awareness of the temporal determinations of its own quest, not only that of its subject. By leaving the lines of research open, instead of vainly trying to close them, and by reflecting on its own inner motivations and temporal determinations, such an approach, no doubt, radically rejects the illusions of definitiveness and complete finality. At the same time, by acknowledging and exemplifying the dynamism of historical objectivity, it can not only bring to life with greater effectiveness the subject of its search, but also prepare the ground for further interpretations and revaluations, rooted in new

72

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

existential predicaments which it thus also helps to bring to the fore. No one can realistically aim at more than this linking search which is simultaneously outside and insidea preserving transcendence of the past which is also a form of determinate temporality and self-transcendence. This is, precisely, what gives such search its raison dtre.

2.
A N OT HE R M YT H T HAT N EED S D ISP ELLING concerns the alleged phenomenon of ruptures and radical breaks in historical and intellectual development. The dialectical interchange of life and work, epoch and writer, make such idea as an explanatory hypothesis a definite non-starter. The writer, according to Sartre, goes on writing even when he has lost his illusions about the nature and impact of literature, and thus of his own work, for he has invested everything in his occupation.127 Even if there was nothing beside this ideological interest,128 it should be enough to caution one against disregarding the dialectic of continuity and discontinuity. For the writers ideological interest points to something deeper, namely to the fact that you have a past that you cant repudiate. Even if you try, you can never repudiate it completely because it is as much part of you as your skeleton . . . In the long run you have not changed much, since you can never discard the whole of your childhood.129 And the man who speaks in such terms, in 1970, is none other than Sartre, who is supposed to have radically repudiated his own past. Considering the relationship of the writer and his epoch, the problem to be explained is twofold: individuality and autonomy on the one hand, and social determination on the other. This is how Sartre formulates the issue:

I would like the reader to feel the presence of Flaubert the whole time; my ideal would be that the reader simultaneously feels, comprehends and knows the personality of Flaubert, totally as an individual and yet totally as an expression of his time.130

And in more general terms:


I believe that a man can always make something out of what is made of him. This is the limit I would today accord to freedom: the small movement which makes of a totally conditioned social being someone who does

F R O M THE " L E G E ND OF TRUTH " TO A "TRUE LEGEND "

73

not render back completely what his conditioning has given him. . . . The individual interiorizes his social determinations: he interiorizes the relations of production, the family of his childhood, the historical past, the contemporary institutions, and then he re-exteriorizes these in acts and options which necessarily refer us back to them.131

Thus the constituents of an individuals development may be summed up as follows: 1. The formation of his personality and thought in his youth and the interiorization of the institutions he experiences (family, class, etc.); 2. The continued determinations of his social environment, with all its changes, and their interiorizations by the individual; 3. The self-definition of the individual in his social setting through work (e.g. writing) and the response of his social environment to it; 4. The interiorization of his own work and of its social consequences by the individual concerned (of his ideological interest as an intellectual, for instance); 5. A possible re-exteriorization of a critique of the last interiorization as a negation of the social basis of the type of work in question (e.g. the negation of the role of the traditional intellectual, in Sartres case). It is clear that while the first four constituents are characteristic of the development of individuals in general, the fifth represents a form of critical self-awareness which is inseparable from a radical critique of society. Furthermore, since that critique appeals to the perspective of a distant future as the necessary condition of its realization, the negation may remain theoretical only (like Bergsons libert intrieure), coupled with an actual reaffirmation, even if not necessarily re-interiorization, of the mode of existence of the criticized traditional intellectual, not as an ideal but as an insuperable reality for the individual concerned, thus reasserting the power of continuity over the expectation of a break. We can see this clearly in Sartres answer to the question: How do you see the new mission of the intellectual?, which begins with the suggestion that He must first of all suppress himself as an intellectual, and ends with his confession: I decided to finish

74

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

the book [on Flaubert], but as long as I go on working on it, I remain at the level of the traditional intellectual.132 Evidently, in a writers development the crucial factor is how he responds to the conflicts and changes of the social world in which he is situated. This can be differentiated into two basic elements: his own constitution (structure of thought, character, tastes, personality), and the relative degree of dynamism with which the social forces of his epoch confront one another, drawing him in one way or another into their confrontations. To describe the interchanges between a writer and his epoch in terms of ruptures is at best extremely nave on both counts. For neither socio-historical, nor individual development is characterized by breaks alone, but by a complex configuration of changes and continuities. In some epochs (such as the French Revolution) discontinuities are in the foreground, and in others (such as the period between 1871 and 1905) continuities predominate. But there are always changes beneath the surface of continuities, and some basic continuities persist, no matter how radical the breaks in certain regions (the Russian Revolution and the stagnating conditions of agricultural production for decades thereafter, for instance). A society is made of multiple layers of coexisting social instruments and practices, each with its own specific rhythm of temporality: a fact that carries far-reaching implications for social development as a whole. This is a major problem which must be treated in its proper setting, namely in the framework of a theory of social transformation and transition. What matters in the present context is that even in the same sphere (material production, for instance) practices going back almost as far as the Stone Age may more or less happily coexist with activities requiring the most advanced forms of technology. This is by no means confined to societies like India where primitive subsistence agriculture is, ironically, complemented by the technology of nuclear arms production. We can find similar instances in our own societies (although the relative weight of the more ancient social practices is, of course, very different in the economic life of our society as a whole). For a Stradivarius on the Assembly Line is a contradiction in terms. The best chisels for sculptors are made today by an old blacksmith in London who works with tools and techniques of thousands of years ago, but nonetheless he is able to put to shame the most advanced Japanese, German and American computerized chisel production techniques, by tempering steel in such a way that it optimally combines the qualities of hardness and resilience which together constitute the most desirable chisel, as Henry Moore himself insisted about it. Now if we try to think of all the social spheres combined, with their manifold

F R O M THE " L E G E ND OF TRUTH " TO A "TRUE LEGEND "

75

varieties, different degrees of complexity, phases of uneven development (Marx), and differences in what might be called structural inertia, as well as their reciprocal interactions, conflicts, clashes, and even antagonistic contradictions under determinate historical conditions, it is obvious that the reduction of this breath-taking complexity to the voluntaristic (e.g. Stalinist) simplification of instant ruptures resulting in radical break with the past, whereafter all problems are caused by the enemy, can only produce painful social hernias which might take ages to cure. Mutatis mutandis, the same considerations apply to the development of the individual. For one thing, his need for and ability to change does not necessarily coincide with the dynamism (or, for that matter, social stagnation) of his epoch, and conflicts may be generated from both directions. (This is what produces the individual who is out of phase with his time.) Furthermore, certain dimensions of his complex being are structurally less readily amenable to change than others. Thus taste, for instance. In some cultures eating chillies constitutes supreme delight, in others a form of torture. The problem to be explained is not only the stubborn persistence of the acquired taste in the individual even when he is transferred into a sharply different culture, but also the fact that the two extremes are constituted on the shared basis of the original experience of sucking the mothers milk. Both problems are explicable only by some specific configuration of continuity and discontinuity, with the relative predominance of one or the other. Incomparably more so when we take into account the whole complexity of a singular individuality. The way in which the various dimensions combine into a coherent whole (and when they do not, we have the problems of a dislocated personality), despite the structural differences and tensions between the respective temporal rhythms (for, thankfully, a man does not age in one piece, with uniformity, otherwise he would age with the self-accelerating speed of a steel ball rushing down a steep incline) can only be comprehended through the dialectic of continuity and discontinuity. The structure of an individuals thought is constituted at a relatively early age, and all its subsequent modifications, however great or small, can only be explained as alterations of the original structure, even if the distance covered is as great as from the mothers milk to chillies. But it cannot be explained simply as the structures rupturewhich, in and by itself, is nothing and thus explains absolutely nothing: rupture is meaningful only as a well defined interaction of determinate forcesor as the invention of a brand new structure, either out of nothing, or through a mechanical transference of the determinations of an age on to the mysterious tabula rasa

76

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

(another name for nothing) of a rupturally emptied individuality (which is a contradiction in terms). The lifework of an intellectual exhibits many layers of structural transformations, which are intelligible only as increasingly more complex superseding preservations (or preserving supersessions) of the original structure. But to refer to the dialectic of continuity and discontinuity is not enough. To say that history, both individual and collective, manifests itself through continuities and changes would acquire the status of a truism, were it not that determinate ideological interests turn it into a hotly debated theoretical proposition. In considering a writer like Sartre the interesting problem is not the unity of continuity and change in his development but its specific form of configuration. Generally speaking, we can think of this problem in terms of a spectrum within which continuities predominate more or less extensively and to varying degrees of intensity (compare in this respect Modigliani and Picasso, or Kodly and Bartk, for instance). Nor should one be deceived by changes which are precisely manifestations of a deeper underlying continuity. For an individuals intellectual development is made up of many aspects, some of which are far more weighty than others in determining the articulation of the overall structure. When Sartre exclaims that on nest pas plus sauv par la politique que par la littrature (one isnt any more saved through politics than through literature),133 he gives away the key to understanding that the sharply contrasting forms of his praxis are different ways of expressing the fundamental underlying continuity: his passionate quest for the absolute of a non-religious salvation. The salient feature of Sartres development is the ultimate predominance of continuity through a multiplicity of transformations. His life activity assumes an extremely paradoxical form. For it is not simply dominated by continuities but, on the contrary, appears to be punctuated by apparently incomprehensible discontinuities, described variously as radical conversion, lapse into ultra-bolshevism, radical break with the past, and so on. It is both the paradoxical form of the continuity and the heterogeneous tensions which determine its relative transformations, which together define the specificity of Sartres intellectual development.

3.
I F WE WAN T TO F OL LOW particular phases of this development, we have to proceed with great caution. For movements in real life are much more subtle

F R O M THE " L E G E ND OF TRUTH " TO A "TRUE LEGEND "

77

than what might be captured through periodizations which, of necessity, freeze any live movement. Changes occur not only between workslet alone between periods or phasesbut inside particular works. Moreover, continuities are not broken off at points of transition but persist sometimes throughout the whole of a lifework. Nevertheless, the relationship between a writer and his epoch cannot be properly understood without fully taking into account the impact of historical events and social transformations even if one must make all the necessary allowances for existing overlaps on the one hand, and the constant capillary changes which are primarily determined by the inner logic of the chosen subject on the other. Keeping in mind these qualifications, we may define the principal phases of Sartres development as follows: 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. The Years of Innocence: 1923 1940 The Years of Abstract Heroism: 19411945 Search for Politics in the Key of Morality: 19461950 Search for Morality in the Key of Politics: 19511956 Search for the Dialectic of History: 19571962 The Discovery of the Singular Universal: 1963 onwards

Let us have a brief look at each of these phases.

1. The Years of Innocence: 19231940 The year 1923 stands for the publication of a short story134 and of three fragments of a lost novel,135 followed after a four-year break by the essay on The theory of state in modern French thought referred to above. None of these works has other than purely documentary interest, for they are truly pen exercises, rather than original works. The first of Sartres writings to give a hint of what is to come are his letter contributing to the student enquiry (see above, page 39) and The Legend of Truth, both written in1929 but the latter published only in 1931. LArt cinmatographic (see above, pages 56-57) is in the same category in that all three exhibit traits of originality against a background of borrowed wisdom, but are still far from indicating a viable road ahead. The situation changes with The Transcendence of the Ego, written in 1934 (published in 1936) and three other major essays on problems of

78

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

philosophical psychology: Esquisse dune thorie des motions, LImagination (both 1935-36) and LImaginaire: Psychologie phnomnologique de limagination, written between 1935 and 1940, when it was published.136 According to Simone de Beauvoir, the grand project on philosophical psychology (of which The Transcendence of the Ego and Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions constitute a small part) is abandoned by Sartre because he considers it little more than an exercise.137 In truth they are a great deal more than that. While Sartre later sharply revises some of the most extreme statements made about freedom on the basis of the philosophical psychology expressed in these works, he retains their conceptual framework not only in Being and Nothingness but throughout his subsequent development. (See, for instance, Itinerary of a thought, 1969, which explains his project on Flaubert with the categories of LImaginaire.138) To these works we have to add not only the important essay on temporality in Faulkner (see above pages 58-61) but also his fine short stories139 and a most remarkable novel, La Nause (Nausea). The general trend is clear. After the first years (1923-28) which produce nothing more than exercises, out of the gropings of The Legend of Truth some philosophical and literary works emerge which define Sartres quest as the exploration of individual experience at the level of a great existential intensity. The social and political dimensions are almost completely absent, or appear only on the horizon, painted with the colors of resignation and Melancholia (the original title of Nausea), signaling the triumph of reification and alienation. This absence of the social and political dimensions, before the fall of commitment, give a marked unity to Sartres first phase of development as the years of sinfully self-oriented innocence.

2. The Years of Abstract Heroism: 19411945 The war brings commitment of a certain kind.
What the drama of the war gave me [explains Sartre], as it did everyone who participated in it, was the experience of heroism. Not my own, of course all I did was a few errands. But the militant in the Resistance who was caught and tortured became a myth for us. Such militants existed, of course, but they represented a sort of personal myth as well. Would we be able to hold out against torture too? The problem then was solely that of physical endurance it was not the ruses of history or the paths of alienation. A man

F R O M THE " L E G E ND OF TRUTH " TO A "TRUE LEGEND "

79

is tortured: what will he do? He either speaks or refuses to speak. This is what I mean by the experience of heroism, which is a false experience. After the war came the true experience, that of society. But I think it was necessary for me to pass via the myth of heroism.140

This experience of heroism is abstract not only because Sartre has to contemplate it from the sideline but also because the whole complexity of the epochfor even a period of historical emergency has its own ruses and paths of alienation, however different they may be from those of the postwar worldis reduced to a moral dilemma, in accordance with the horizon of a problematical subjectivity and very tentatively self-transcending individuality. The main philosophical work of this phase is Being and Nothingness (1943), which announces the possibilities of such transcendence in the extremely abstract categories of phenomenological ontology, structured around subjectivity. Sartres three early playsBariona (1941), Flies (1943), and Huis Clos (1943)fit well into this intellectual framework, and so does Roads to Freedom (its first two volumes written in 194144 and published in 1945), apart from the aesthetic considerations discussed above. 1945 is also the year of writing two important programmatic essays: propos de lexistentialisme: Mise au point141 and LExistentialisme est un humanisme142in which the tone is more positive but the conceptual framework remains the same, despite the new experience of society. The work in which the problematic features of Sartres abstract heroism break to the fore, without however resulting in an aesthetically or conceptually viable alternative, is Morts sans spulture,143 his failed play (see page 65). And yet, when we notice the distinguishing characteristics of this phase, we should also be aware of some important continuities. We should notice not only the fact that the ontological structure of individual praxes remains the framework of orientation of Sartres later writings on morality, including Determination and freedom (1966), but also the structural affinities with the Critique of Dialectical Reason, where the contrast is supposed to be the sharpest. For implicitly in Being and Nothingness, and explicitly in Huis Clos, hell is the other. Now one of the central themes of the Critique is what Sartre calls the practico-inert: the reign of the other and of his instruments and institutions. And we are confronted with the same gripping definition: hell is the practico-inert.

80

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

3. Search for Politics in the Key or Morality: 19461950 If the first phase is characterized by the predominance of self-oriented subjectivity, and the second by the assertion of an abstract moral heroism (freedom as inherent in the ontological structure of being), the third phase is under the sign of the pursuit of a morally committed politics while retaining the sovereignty of the individual. It follows naturally from the earlier phases of which the third represents an extension towards real socio-historical problems, without paying much, if any, attention to institutional realities which are necessary conditions of any possible solution of these problems. Even Les Mains sales and LEngranage (both from 1948) which directly confront some major political issues, do this in the form of moral dilemmas that apparently are not amenable to a solution. Sartres reflections on commitment are articulated with great intensity and coherence in Baudelaire (1946), Forgers of myth: the young playwrights of France (1946), The writers responsibility (1947) and, above all, What Is Literature? (1947). His articles on politics are full of imperatives, even in their titles: Jeunes dEurope, unissez-vous! Faites vous-mme vtre destin!; Il nous faut la paix pour refaire le monde; Il faut que nous menions cette lutte en commun, etc. He defines the fundamental task of the RDR (Rassemblement Dmocratique Rvolutionnaire)a shortlived political movement with which he is associated for a whileas the unification of revolutionary demands with the idea of freedom,144 but he has nothing to say on how to achieve it, except by unrealistically appealing directly to the consciousness of individuals, irrespective of their political affiliations. The RDR soon collapses, but Sartres conception of politics as a moral imperative persists for some time. He sees the essence of the Yugoslav experience as subjectivity . . . not as a formal ideal but as an effective reality.145 And in an introduction to Roger Stphanes Portrait of the Adventurer (1950) he sings the eulogy of Lawrence of Arabia for living to the limit an impossible condition, an unbearable tension of antinomies and contradictions.146 And this is how he defines morality too: it is for us simultaneously inevitable and impossible.147 Should one be surprised therefore to learn that in the same period he abandons not only volume IV of Roads to Freedom, but his Morale as well, after 2,000 pages of struggle with its insurmountable impossibility.148

F R O M THE " L E G E ND OF TRUTH " TO A "TRUE LEGEND "

81

4. Search for Morality in the Key of Politics: 19511956 The frustration of the previous phasethe exasperations of the Cold War period and Sartres feeling of impotence to make an impact in a positive direction by means of his moral-political appeals to the concerned individualbrings a major soul-searching. Its outstanding results are Saint Genet (195052) and, above all, Le Diable et le Bon Dieu (1951, translated as Lucifer and the Lord in English), a magnificent playperhaps his greatest single work: a drama we might call Sartres Guernica. The objectivity of history is discovered obliquely, under the threat of nuclear self-annihilation: In order to prevent the world from following its own course, they threaten with the suppression of history through the liquidation of the historical agent.149 Sartre throws himself into feverish political activity, in order to help prevent such ultimate disaster. He becomes a prominent figure in the World Peace Movement, writing articles, and making numerous public speeches on the subject of world peace; and on the plane of internal politics he is a passionate advocate of a new Popular Front.150 There are still moments when he maintains the illusions on the political power of independent individuals,151 but he is trying to establish a close relationship with the French Communist Party. Two major publications mark this trend: The Communists and Peace (195254), and LAffair Henri Martin (1953), apart from the play Nekrassov (1955) and the film scenario The Witches of Salem (1956). And in the field of literary studies his passionate interest is with those who consciously commit themselves; he makes this clear in an interview: Mallarm and Genetthey are both conscious of their commitment. . . . [Mallarm] is our greatest poet. A wild, impassioned man. . . . His was an all-embracing commitmentsocial as much as poetic.152 Sartres political radicalization brings also his clamorous break with Camus, and then, not so clamorous but with equal finality, with his much closer friend and collaborator, Maurice Merleau-Ponty. He is accused of abdication, which is very far from the truth. In reality, he is trying to influence the Communist Party from the outside (as witnessed by an important critical article, Le reformisme et les ftiches153) while insisting that in France the only viable force of mediation of working-class politics is the Communist Party. As he later realizes, after the shock of the Hungarian upheavals in October 1956, he is trying to do the impossible. His characterizations of the Party are often straightforward projections of his conception of morality

82

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

which needs tangible historical agencies for its realization. In the end his effort to unify his moral ideals with political reality, despite his willingness to make some concessions, flounders and a new crisis sets in. And just as he characterized our moral predicament earlier as ruled by insurmountable impossibility and simultaneous inevitability and impossibility, he later sums up the dilemmas and antinomies of our political predicament in the same terms: Collaboration with the CP is both necessary and impossible.154 Thus Politics in the Key of Morality, and Morality in the Key of Politicshowever different their emphases in determinate historical situationscome structurally to the same thing: the assertion and reassertion of fundamental antinomies.

5. Search for the Dialectic of History: 19571963 The disappointment of his political expectations passionately denounced in the book-length essay, Le fantome de Staline,155 raises the questions why did it all happen? and what are the hopes for the future?, calling for a searching investigation of the structures and determinations of history vis--vis the possibilities of individual praxis. This means going back to the foundations, in order
to provide a philosophical foundation for realism. This in my opinion is possible today, and I have tried to do it all my life. In other words, how can one give man both his autonomy and his reality among real objects, avoiding idealism without lapsing into a mechanistic materialism. I posed the problem in this way because I was ignorant of dialectical materialism although I should add that this later allowed me to assign certain limits to itto validate the historical dialectic while rejecting a dialectic of nature, in the sense of a natural process which produces and resolves man into an ensemble of physical laws.156

This foundation and validation is a monumental enterprise of which Critique of Dialectical Reason, massive as it is, constitutes only a small part. Indeed, in an interview by Madeleine Chapsal in 1959, Sartre optimistically announces that The first volume will be published within a month, and the second within a year.157 However, the second volume is abandoned after early chapters, and the project is altogether displaced a few years later by a close investigation of singular individuality through the life and work of Flaubert.

F R O M THE " L E G E ND OF TRUTH " TO A "TRUE LEGEND "

83

Naturally, Sartres contacts with politics are not broken off, but they assume a very different form. This is the time of the Algerian war, and he is fully involved, as an individual, in the fight against the danger of fascism, against torture, the OAS, and so on. Similarly, the victory of the Cuban revolution is greeted by Sartre with great enthusiasm, and he continues to defend it against all kinds of attack. But he is a loner supporting worthy causes rather than a member or associate of a political movement.158 Critical self-examination in the essays on Brecht, Gorzs Traitor, Nizan, and Merleau-Ponty vivant (1961) takes the form of a severe indictment of his whole generation, together with its sclerotic institutions. The overall picture is rather sombre (likewise in his Critique), and Altona (1959) one of his most powerful plays fits organically into it, with its examination of historical determinations in relation to human responsibility. History is questioned with a hopeful eye towards the future, but no reassurance seems to be forthcoming at least not for the time being.

6. Discovery of the Singular Universal: 1963 onwards The publication of Words (1963) signals a form of peace, expressed with serenity also in the lines we have seen on salvation in literature and in politics. It goes without saying, Sartre takes a keen interest in the world of politics, especially in the Third World, from writing an introduction to a collection of Lumumbas essays to presiding over the deliberations of the Russell Tribunal. And he defends Rgis Debrayin danger of being executed in Boliviawith the same passion with which he condemns the Russian intervention in Prague. There is even a moment of great positive enthusiasmMay 1968 in Pariswhen his best dreams about imagination in power seem to come true in his own homeland. All the same, politically he remains an isolated figure even when for reasons of solidarity he accepts the nominal directorship of the persecuted paper, La Cause du Peuple. Realizing that the concrete universal is possible only in a society which is made of the same stuff, he accepts the limitations of the intellectualin Words, in the essays on Luniversel singulier, in A plea for intellectuals, for examplewhile questioning the conditions of his existence. By far the most important project in this respect is The Idiot of the Family (vols. I and II, 1971, vol. III, 1972)an immense work of which nearly 3,000 dense pages are already printed, though it still seems to be very far from the end.

84

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Sartres Critique of Dialectical Reason was supposed to be continued in the following way:
The difference between the first and second volume is this: the first is an abstract work where I show the possibilities of exchange, degradation, the practico-inert, series, collectives, recurrence and so on. It is concerned only with the theoretical possibilities of their combinations. The project of the second volume is history itself . . . my aim will be to prove that there is a dialectical intelligibility of the singular. For ours is a singular history. . . . What I will seek to show is the dialectical intelligibility of that which is not universalizable.159

It is extremely difficult to imagine how one can comprehend history itself through these categories, since the problem of history is precisely how to universalize the singular without suppressing its specificities. By contrast, however, it is very easy to see the natural transition from history to biography, namely from this Sartrean conception of history to the project on Flaubert. For the intelligibility of the non-universalizable singular calls for lived experience as the basis of its comprehension. And the reconstruction of the personage through limaginaire necessarily involved in it, gives us a True legend, at the highest level of complexity. Some of the fundamental structures of history itself thus remain hidden away in the second volume of the Critique that never comes, for they do not seem to fit into the framework of Sartres quest. But, by compensation, the existential dimensions of singular universality are brought to life, with great richness and penetration.

4.
AS W E C AN S E E F R OM T H IS necessarily sketchy account, the particular phases of Sartres development are not simply the result of external determinations, but of a complex interaction between the internal determinations of his structure of thought, and the social and political events of his epoch. The fatal immobilism of pre-war years; the immense human drama and suffering of the Second World War; the cold war inaugurated by Churchills Fulton speech after the short interval of serene rejoicing over the shared victory over Fascism; the menace of a nuclear devastation in the aftermath of the establishment of NATO, soon followed by the outbreak of the Korean War; the explosion of the inner contradictions of the Stalinist system, and the

F R O M THE " L E G E ND OF TRUTH " TO A "TRUE LEGEND "

85

new dynamism of the Third World gathering its own momentum (with Algeria, Cuba, Vietnam, etc.)each coincides, roughly, with a phase in Sartres development for which it provides a broad historical and political framework. But the way in which Sartre proceeds, and the distance he is able to travel, is determined by the innermost nature of his vision itself, as we could clearly perceive in his transitions from self-oriented subjectivity ultimately leading, through the intermediary forms of active (one might even say activist) moral and political commitment, to the problematic individuality of the singular universal. On the surface, changes not only are in evidence, but they assume the striking form of apparently radical breaks: every phase is abandoned in its turn, with conscious public declarations by Sartre as to the why? of the clamorous discontinuities. But if we look closer, we realize that the succession of striking changes unfolds a fundamental continuity. Trying to understand Sartre through his breakswhich on the whole are confined to the political levelis like explaining the nature of the tides by the prevalent wind currents. Just as the tide is understood through the force of the moon, and not by the power of the wind even if hurricane strong, Sartres development is explained by the stubborn continuity of his fundamental quest. If the breaks were the determining feature, how could one account for the lasting validity of the works produced in the preceding phases? The fact is, however, that Sartres advances do not invalidate his earlier results but essentially preserve them, both in his world of literature and in his philosophical thought. He is a man who perceives the contradictions around him in the form of dilemmas, antinomies and paradoxes. His praise of the adventurer is not a temporary lapse but an expression of his inner tensions which remain a permanent dimension of his lifework. He is the man who keeps together the unbearable tension of the perceived contradictions as insuperable antinomies. For the unresolved tensionthrough all its transformationsdrives him forward and produces the lasting validity of his major works: Nausea, LImaginaire, Being and Nothingness, Flies, Huis Clos, Les mains Sales, Lucifer and the Lord, Saint Genet, Altona, Critique of Dialectical Reason, and The Idiot of the Family.160 In 1945 he declares: Mathieus childhood . . . doesnt matter,161that is, it doesnt matter in his vision of the world, which means that however much it matters in real life ruled by Bad Faith, it ought not to matter. In 1959, through the play Altona, he shows how the past conditions the present, commenting on the sad reality whereby the characters are all the time commanded and held back by the past, as they are by the others. It is because of

86

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

the pastof their own and of all the othersthat they act in a certain way. As in real life.162 The contrast is as striking as it is misleading. For again he appeals to the viewpoint of the future, and urges men to look at themselves from the outside, in order to be able to notice that it ought not to be like that at all. As he tries to demonstrate also in Determination and freedom six years later, there is absolutely nothing in the ontological structure of being to make them behave like that. If they do, it is because of social and political determinations and their interiorizations by the individualsbut they ought not to. Witness and participant, he warns us that we shall be judged163 by the future, our future. Thus we ought to act in accordance with the ontological structure of our being (in relation to which Mathieus or anyone elses past really does not matter), and not the way we actually do. The most striking continuity lies beneath the surface of an apparent break. The moon that determines the movement of Sartres tidal waves is his radical quest for unfolding the fundamental dimensions of being, in a world of distracting compromises and temptations, offering lines of easy resistance which lead towards disaster through unfounded self-reassurance and the promise of comfort. This is not his way, and ought not to be ours, he tells us, pursuing the task of persuasion with tireless passion. The marvelous unity of this life is its intransigence in the quest for the absolute, writes Sartre about his great friend, Giacometti.164 There can be no better way of summing up the movement and the direction of his own lifework. Such a quest for the absolute is not something mysterious and transcendental. On the contrary, it is very precise and tangible. It means a radical definition of a mans fundamental project in a sense which necessarily implies going to the limit, whatever the limit may appear to be to the individual in question at any particular time in the course of his development. Sartres heroesMallarm, Genet, Nizan, Fucik, Giacometti, Hikmet, and in fiction Julien Sorelare men who explore their predicament to the limit. Similarly, his anti-heroesamong them Baudelaire and Flaubertare those who refuse to do so, thus condemning themselves to the consequences of their fundamental choice: an escape into the imaginary and the acceptance of alienation. What interests me about Flaubert is that he refused to go to the limit,165 writes Sartre, clearly indicating the moral sense of his painfully long involvement in the subject. It is going to the limit he himself opts for, and champions with single-minded determination and intransigence, insisting that the question is What have you made of your life?166 Success is measured by ones ability to establish the real connection with others, with oneself and with death167 as opposed to the reassuring, dreary world

F R O M THE " L E G E ND OF TRUTH " TO A "TRUE LEGEND "

87

of the inauthentic168 in which men are trapped by a moiling of flabby, many-tentacled evasions.169 Whatever one may think of Sartres achievements, no one can accuse him of evasions. Probing the limits, irrespective of the consequences, this is the fundamental defining characteristic of his lifework. His road, from self-oriented subjectivity to the problematic individuality of the singular universal, leads over territories full of explosive dilemmas which he depicts in the most paradoxical form. There is a morality of politicsa difficult subject, and never clearly treatedand when politics must betray its morality, to choose morality is to betray politics. Now find your way out of that one! Particularly when the politics has taken as its goal bringing about the reign of the human.170 Much of Sartres lifework is spent on identifying such dilemmas and paradoxes, even if he cannot offer solutions to them. For, again, the innermost nature of these dilemmas and paradoxes is that willingness to face the limits is the vital condition of their identification and possible solution. It is Sartres passionate search for the limits which determines the fundamental continuity of his lifework through all its transformations.

This page intentionally left blank

P A R T

T W O

Search for Freedom

To come into the world as a freedom, confronting Others is to come into the world as alienable. If to will oneself free is to choose to be in this world confronting Others, then the one who wills himself such must also will the passion of his freedom. Whether in fury, hate, pride, shame, disheartened refusal or joyous demand, it is necessary for me to choose to be what I am.
From Being and Nothingness

This page intentionally left blank

4. Search for the Individual: The early Works


1.
DI S C USS ING T HE INT E L LECTUA L D EVELO PMENT

of his generation, Sartre

writes in The Problem of Method:


We plunged blindly down the dangerous path of a pluralist realism concerned with man and things in their concrete existence. Yet we remained within the compass of dominating ideas. For a long time we confused the total and the individual. Pluralism, which had served us so well against M. Brunschwicgs idealism, prevented us from understanding the dialectical totalization. It pleased us to decry essences and artificially isolated types rather than to reconstitute the synthetic movement of a truth that had become. 1 71

Such self-description, with which Sartres work abounds, must be taken with a pinch of salt. We must constantly keep in mind that in Sartres declarations we are confronted with such a fusion of subjectivity and objectivity whereby the meaning of the statement is always self-assertion, even when its apparent form is self-criticism. Sartres compelling subjectivity cannot admit being in the wrong in the present tenseonly retrospectively in a somewhat remote

92

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

past. Furthermore, the function of his retrospective self-criticisms (which are as a rule spelled out with the pronoun we, rather than I) is precisely to assert the transcendence of the criticized position, in place of demonstrating it. This is exactly what happens in the passage on the alleged early confusion of the total and the individual and on the claimed supersession of this position in The Problem of Method and in the Critique of Dialectical Reason. We shall return to this particular problem in a moment. Now the point to stress is that the identification by a thinker of a problematic aspect of his own work does not automatically mean that he has found a solution to it. Nor does it mean that the retrospective self-criticism is necessarily valid and is to be accepted at face value. In both instances we are presented with assertions in need of substantiation and evidence before we can come to a conclusion one way or another. Ones awareness of a problem may provide the possibility of a solution, but should not be confused with the solution itself which has to be established on objective grounds rather than on the sole basis of critical self-assertions, however genuinely felt they might be. This is particularly important in assessing Sartres development. For one of the salient features of his lifework is that he cannot allow his case to rest simply on the evidence of the works he produces but must provide also what he considers to be their only legitimate interpretations. This is not simply because he is a controversial writer. Rather, being controversial is itself a necessary consequence of the structuring and organizing principle of his work of its compelling subjectivity. So much so that beyond a certain point it is impossible to separate work from self-interpretation. To be sure, Sartres personal interventions in discussions about his own works ever since the publication of Nausea are quite unparalleled. He gives an endless number of interviews which he completely dominates. He answers his critics in the most outspoken fashion not only in interviews but in other forms as well, from short articles to book-length essays and from lectures to open letters. Furthermore, his views on his various concerns and on the meaning of his numerous works are faithfully reproduced in Simone de Beauvoirs five long autobiographical volumes. Such an amount of overpowering self-reflection is quite extraordinary by any standard. But all this is very far from being the whole extent of Sartres self-interpretations. We have to complement the picture not only with his autobiographical Words and Self-Portrait (1975) but also with many of his essays, such as those on Giacometti, Natalie Sarraute, Camus, Nizan, and MerleauPonty, in which his personal reflections predominate whatever the immediate subject matter. And we have to add to them some of his plays (e.g.

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

93

Lucifer and the Lord) and two major biographical works (on Genet and on Flaubert) in which self-interpretations are very much in the foreground. Indeed the vast majority of his lifework is more or less directly concerned with self-examination. The nature of Sartres quest is such that probing the limits means two things: first, an uncompromising assessment and reassessment of his own internal limitsof the authenticity or non-authenticity of his own choices and decisions; and second, the assertion of his subjectivity, his constantly scrutinized self in the world around him, with the aim of highlighting the fundamental difference between the ontological structure of being and the historically given situation. (The problem of interiorization is concerned with the intersection of the two.) Self-examination is thus the vehicle of assessing the problems of an epoch, and the concern with the problems of the age, as articulated through the categories of responsibility and authenticity, constitutes the nodal points of renewed self-examination. This is why whatever may happen to be the subject of Sartres enquiry, he is always completely absorbed in it. The frequent self-references of his analyses are not simply formal characteristics of presentation and style: they are inseparable from the conception of the subject matter itself. Consequently it is very difficult (and rather problematical) to divorce a Sartrean proposition from its existential contextthe when? and why? of its conception and assess its validity entirely on its own. Sartre not only agrees with his own generalizations: he is one with them. (His self-references are often meant as authentications172 of this existential dimension of his assertions.) In other words, he is fully and passionately committed to the position he happens to hold at any given time. No wonder, therefore, that Sartre cannot concede a point except retrospectively, when the point at issue has ceased to be an integral part of his overall theoretical framework. It is because of such intense existential involvement in the problems at stake that Sartre must assume a belligerent posture vis--vis his critics, and not because of some mysterious temperament that might be considered the underlying psychological cause of his aggressive self-assertions. (In any event, a mans temperament is controllable, if there is a good enough reason, and Sartre would be the first to argue this, in the spirit of his early works on philosophical psychology.) The passionate defense of his position is as vital to the realization of his fundamental project as its original formulation. And since the subjective element is such an integral part of the whole enterprise, up to a point he can rightfully claim for himself a privileged status in explaining the meaning of his own works, in that a completely objective

94

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

reading of works of this kind is by definition inadequate. No doubt there is something suspicious about the recurrent formula with which he rejects criticism from both left (be it the French CP173 or Lukcs174) and right (e.g. Camus175) by declaring that the critics have not read his works, not to mention his dismissal of Gurins self-explanation with the summary statement that he doesnt understand anything of his own book,176 as we have seen above. All the same, the partial truth in such accusations is that Sartres own reading of the works in question is very different from the interpretations he contests. In other words, he insists on the importance of the angle (the subjective element) in the articulation of theories which has a bearing on the question of validity in a much more positive sense than is generally acknowledged. However, having said that, we cannot ignore the problematical aspect. A lifework that requires the authors frequent intervention on his own behalf reveals its vulnerability in that he will not be eternally there to supply every age with self-interpretations which are constantly reformulated so as to be in tune with the changing socio-historical circumstances. Ultimately his work, just as anyone elses, must rest on the evidence the work itself displays, in relation to which self-interpretations are necessarily marginal. A compelling personality may succeed in imposing his self-image on his contemporaries at least on some of thembut future generations will make up their own mind about him without such interventions. Paradoxically, in the long-drawn-out process of historical validation the authors assertive self-interpretations may prove to be counter-productive in that they may give support to artificial polarizations and sidetrack the orientation of critical assessment from the whole of the lifework to some of its partial aspects. For while it is vitally important to keep in mind the authors passionate involvement in specific problems and concernsfrom the angle of which he interprets himself as much as anything elsein order to be able to understand the particular points and phases of his development, self-interpretations are of a very limited value in assessing the totality of his development precisely because they are always deeply rooted in specific situations and concerns. Thus we are again confronted with the dilemma of individualization and universalization: the same thing that is a great asset at one level turns out to be a potentially major drawback at another. To account for the whole of a lifework, one has to integrate the totality of particular points and phases in a dynamic movement without suppressing the existential vitality of the individual elements. Any attempt at directly universalizing a particular phasewhich is always constituted out of more

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

95

or less conflicting elementswill only result in an ahistorical projection of a specific part over the whole, and at the same time in the liquidation of the dynamic tension inherent in it. For any particular phase represents ipso facto also a specific level of attainment and point of rest which, if generalized, inevitably freezes the movement (which led to it and will go beyond it) and sharply distorts the overall picture. By contrast, the only properly historical mode of proceeding is to use the movement itself as the principle of selection applied to all specific points and phases. Accordingly, those elements will be highlighted at any particular point in an authors development which represent the links of the overall movement and thus display the fundamental trend of his development. Thus universalization will emerge as the overall structurea dynamic and not a static structureof which the individual elements have changing relative weights. For what dominates a specific point or phase may occupy a very subordinate position at another, and vice versa; and it is the overall patternthe dynamic wholewhich ultimately and objectively determines the respective structural correlations, maybe assigning a much greater relative weight to an element of embryonic strength than to the temporarily dominant but transitory elements whose importance diminishes as the pattern of overall development unfolds. It is thus easy to see that the authors self-interpretations, in so far as they are expressions of whatever may happen to be his dominant preoccupations at a particular point in time, need not (one might indeed argue, cannot) faithfully reflect the overall movement with all its intricacies and delicate balances. Such intricacies and balances have to be assessed from a certain distance, but not from the distance of the newly acquired and championed position that itself must be integrated and made subject to a critical examination in the overall framework. And since the intensity of an authors passionate involvement in a new phase is what is in question here, we must be particularly careful about the self-interpretations of an authorJean-Paul Sartrewho consciously carries the principle of existential involvement and commitment to its utmost limits. A hasty acceptance of his self-explanations at their face value (it does not matter whether approvingly or with a negative attitude towards the claimed changes), which seems to characterize too many writings on Sartre, tends to bog down discussion on rather peripheral aspects of his work (e.g. the notoriety of his allegedly radical conversion), diverting attention from its structuring principles and basic dimensions. This is why we have to treat them with particular care.

96

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

2.
T H I S TAK E S U S BAC K TO O UR O RIG INA L Q UESTIO N: should we subscribe to Sartres strictures about the alleged confusion of the total and the individual, the failure to understand the problem of dialectical totalization in his early work, coupled with the claim of a radical advance in this respect in his Critique and in the works related to the Critique? We have to postpone for a while any attempt at a more detailed answer to the second half of the question, apart from reiterating that Sartres conception of dialectical totalization leads to an impasse in the second part of the Critique and to the transmutation of its quest for making historical totalization intelligible into a form of deliberately fictional biography. Let us see now how things are in the early works. There can be no doubt about it, the search for the individual is the central preoccupation of these works. This is inherent in the attempt at laying the foundations of a phenomenological psychology, setting out from the irreducible fact177 of consciousness. However, it would be quite wrong to suggest that the problem of totality is ignored. On the contrary, it occupies a very important place in every one of the early works. And there are no signs of the total being confused with the individual. If anything, the lines of demarcation are too sharply drawn, rather than being blurred. What is highly problematical about Sartres early analyses of totality is of an altogether different character, as we shall see in a moment. We find already in Sartres first important philosophical study, The Transcendence of the Ego, a theory of consciousness articulated in relation to the problem of totality. In a critical reference to Husserls view of the transcendental I as the condition of unity and identity of consciousness Sartre writes:

The individuality of consciousness evidently stems from the nature of consciousness. Consciousness (like Spinozas substance) can be limited only by itself. Thus it constitutes a synthetic and individual totality entirely isolated from totalities of the same type, and the I can evidently be only an expression (rather than a condition) of this incommunicability and inwardness of consciousness. Consequently we may reply without hesitation: the phenomenological conception of consciousness renders the unifying and individualizing role of the I totally useless. It is consciousness, on the contrary, which makes possible the unity and the personality of my I. The transcendental I, therefore, has no raison dtre.178

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

97

This point is further developed in the section on The constitution of the ego as the pole of actions, states, and qualities:
. . . the individuality of the ego is a constantly gulling mirage, for it simultaneously yields everything and yields nothing. How could it be otherwise, moreover, since the ego is not the real totality of consciousness (such a totality would be a contradiction, like any infinite unity enacted), but the ideal unity of all states and actions? Being ideal, naturally, this unity can embrace an infinity of states. But one can well understand that what is given to the concrete, full intuition is only this unity in so far as it incorporates the present state. By virtue of this concrete nucleus a more or less sizeable quantity of empty intentions (by right, an infinity of them) are directed towards the past and towards the future, and aim at the states and actions not presently given. Those who have some acquaintance with phenomenology will understand without difficulty that the ego may be at the same time an ideal unity of states, the majority of which are absent, and a concrete totality wholly giving itself to intuition: this signifies merely that the ego is a noematic rather than a noetic unity. A tree or a chair exist no differently. Naturally the empty intentions can always be fulfilled, and any state or action whatsoever can always reappear to consciousness as produced or having been produced by the ego.179

Thus we are presented with a whole cluster of conceptsindividual totality and totalities of the same type, real totality, ideal unity (or ideal totality), and concrete totalityin terms of which the relationship between consciousness and the world is spelled out. And Sartre is by no means content to remain within the sphere of subjective experience. On the contrary, his central aim is ontological. Not only in the sense that he claims to have produced in his conception of the ego the only possible refutation of solipsism,180 rectifying Husserls failures in this respect,181 but also in so far as he aims at undermining what he calls metaphysical materialism182 by opening the phenomenological bracket in the spirit of a philosophical realism.183 Sartres interest in phenomenology is, from the beginning, existentialontological. He wants to grasp the existents in their facticity, as opposed to the various kinds of metaphysical presuppositions or prejudgements which seem to dominate not only philosophical theories but also their applications in psychology and elsewhere, and his enthusiasm184 for the potentialities of phenomenology is the direct expression of such concerns. However,

98

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

he must soon realize also the limitations of Husserlian phenomenology as regards his own programme:
Phenomenological descriptions can discover, for instance, that the very structure of the transcendental consciousness implies that this consciousness is constitutive of a world. But it is evident that they will not teach us that consciousness must be constitutive of such a world, that is exactly the one where we are, with its earth, its animals, its men and the story of these men. We are here in the presence of a primary and irreducible fact which presents itself as a contingent and irrational specification of the noematic essence of the world. And many phenomenologists will call metaphysics the investigation whose aim it is to uncover this contingent existent in its entirety.185

Thus the concern with totality is further concretized as facing the world as it is, as it exactly happens to be in its contingency and facticity, with a view to uncover this contingent existent in its entirety. This contingent world of the existents is the world of things and the world of men which we can uncover in its complex totality. Even the famous subjective responses: hatred, love, dread, sympathy . . . are nothing but modes of uncovering the world.186 In the spirit of his own interpretation of phenomenology which already treats Husserls bracket as opened, Sartre hails the German philosopher as someone who restored to us the world of the artists and prophets . . . he cleared the ground for a new treatise of the passions. . . . ; from now on the cult of interiority (Bergson, Proust) is completely untenable: everything is outside, everything, including ourselves: outside, in the world, together with others. It is not in I dont know what kind of retreat that we discover ourselves but on the highway, in the city, in the middle of the crowd: thing among things, man among men.187 The new treatise of the passions for which Husserl is supposed to have cleared the ground is, of course, Sartres Being and Nothingness in which we learn that Existential psychoanalysis is going to reveal to man the real goal of his pursuit, which is being as a synthetic fusion of the initself and the for-itself; existential psychoanalysis is going to acquaint man with his passion.188 In truth, it is not Husserl who clears the ground for this conceptionexcept in an indirect sense, by providing the field for Sartres corrective reflectionsbut Sartre himself in his early works, and to a large extent also in Being and Nothingness. As we know, volume two of the latter, which should have carried out in detail the programme announced in the

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

99

last quotation, has never been written at least not in the originally intended form. But of course many of Sartres subsequent writings not only the abandoned Morale but also Saint Genet, as well as numerous short essays, and above all The Idiot of the Family take up the problematic of making man acquainted with his passion, and try to carry it nearer to a conclusion. Thus the Sartrean quest for the absolute the elucidation of the real goal of mans pursuit, which implies the refutation of various misconceptions has to set out from the analysis of passion and emotion as we encounter it in the world of contingent existents: in the goal-directed life-activity of living individuals. The question: what makes man drive on through success and failure, achievement and disaster, cannot be answered in abstraction, at the generic plane of some mystifying universality (like World Spirit), but must find its supporting evidence in the various manifestations of human passion as ways in which living individuals take cognizance of the world in which they are situated and try to cope with the problems and challenges of their situation. The early works, while clearing the ground, articulate the main tenets of Sartres philosophy. The critique of Husserl proceeds on two lines: 1. the establishment of a genuine need for phenomenological reduction (Husserls epoch) in terms of Sartrean existential categories, as spelled out in The Transcendence of the Ego; 2. an examination of what Sartre considers to be inadequate in Husserls account of the forms and modalities of consciousness, which lead Sartre to specify an ontological framework in which solution might be envisaged to all that remained elusive to Husserl. On the first point, Sartres judgement is very severe. He quotes with approval Finks study on Husserl189 which insists that the natural attitude of mindwhich gives rise to scientific theoriesis perfectly coherent in itself, and therefore there is no reason whatsoever for exercising a phenomenological reduction. Sartre goes on:
There [in the natural attitude] one will find none of those contradictions which, according to Plato, lead the philosopher to effect a philosophical conversion. Thus, the epoch appears in the phenomenology of Husserl as a miracle. Husserl himself, in Cartesianische Meditationen [Section 1.], made an extremely vague allusion to certain psychological motives which would

100

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

lead to undertaking reduction. But these motives hardly seem sufficient. Moreover, reduction seems capable of being performed only at the end of lengthy study. It appears, then, as a knowledgeable operation, which confers on it a sort of gratuitousness. On the other hand, if the natural attitude appears wholly as an effort made by consciousness to escape from itself by projecting itself into the me and becoming absorbed there, and if this effort is never completely rewarded, and if a simple act of reflection suffices in order for conscious spontaneity to tear itself abruptly away from the I and be given as independent, then the epoch is no longer a miracle, an intellectual method, an erudite procedure: it is an anxiety which is imposed on us and which we cannot avoid: it is both a pure event of transcendental origin and an ever possible accident of our daily life.190

Even if Sartres conclusion is rather unexpected, the trust of his argument is abundantly clear. Having successfully liberated himself from the shackles of academic philosophy (Brunschwicg, etc.), Sartre is determined not to get involved in some other kind of academic operation which might turn out to be merely an intellectual method, a complicated erudite methodological procedure preserved for the few. He is looking for a method which has an existential basis in life and is thus open to all. This conception, which directly links the epoch to anxiety and dread, establishes through the same link also the vital relationship with the existential categories of freedom, thus indicating the possibility of self-liberation through purifying reflectionof which Sartre speaks in Emotions, a closely related work191 as the tangibly relevant function of the whole philosophical enterprise he is engaged in. Thus, in the course of the Sartrean analysis, a rather abstract problem of phenomenological methodology is transmuted into a major pillar of existential ontology. The second point of criticism mentioned above concerns the forms and modalities of consciousness as characterized by Husserl. Sartre takes as his point of reference a Drer engraving which we can perceive at will as a thing-object or as an image-object, and he makes the following observation: Such hyletic ambivalence is possible only in a small number of privileged cases (paintings, photographs, copies, etc). Even if the alternatives were available, one would still have to explain why my consciousness intends some matter as image rather than as perception. . . . the distinction between mental images and perceptions cannot derive from intentionality alone. A difference in intention is necessary but not sufficient. The matter must also

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

101

be different. . . . [Husserls solution, though insightful, is quite incomplete.] . . . We know now that we must start afresh, setting aside all the phenomenological literature, and attempting above all to attain an intuitive vision of the intentional structure of the image. . . . We should also compare imageconsciousness and sign-consciousness, in order to free psychology once and for all from the egregious error of making images into signs and signs into images. Finally and above all the hyle peculiar to images should be examined. It might be that on the way we would have to leave the realm of eidetic psychology and resorting to experimentation and inductive procedures. But eidetic description is the starting point. The way is open for phenomenological psychology.192 Thus the question why? concerning the formation of an image rather than of a perception, again leads towards the articulation of an existential ontology. For the possibility of a phenomenological psychology as envisaged by Sartre (as being synonymous with existential psychology, in contrast to the strictly phenomenological eidetic psychology) has for its precondition a radical departure from all the phenomenological literature in that its programme necessarily implies the opening of the phenomenological bracket. This we find clearly indicated, in a more generalized form, in a key passage of LImaginaire:
We shall give the name of situations to the different immediate ways of apprehending the real as a world. We can therefore say that the essential prerequisite that enables consciousness to imagine is that it be situated in the world or more briefly, that it be-in-the world. It is the situation-in-theworld, grasped as a concrete and individual reality of consciousness, which is the motivation for the construction of any unreal object whatever and the nature of that unreal object is circumscribed by this motivation. Thus the situation of consciousness does not need to appear as a pure and abstract condition of possibility for all imagination but as the concrete and exact motivation for the appearance of a certain particular imagination. . . . Thus, although as a result of producing the unreal, consciousness can appear momentarily delivered from being-in-the-world, it just is this being-in-theworld which is the necessary condition for the imagination. . . . 193 We may therefore conclude that imagination is not an empirical and superadded power of consciousness, it is the whole of consciousness as it realizes its freedom: . . . as consciousness is always in situation because it is always free, it always and at each moment has the concrete possibility of

102

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

producing the unreal. These are the various motivations which decide at each moment whether consciousness will only be realized or whether it will imagine. The unreal is produced outside world by a consciousness which stays in the world and it is because he is transcendentally free that man can imagine.194

As we can see, the reality of the world is asserted through the category of situation which assumes a central role in Sartres lifework. (Significantly, his essays on a variety of subjects are collected in ten volumes of Situations, and one of the most important areas of his activity, drama, is defined by Sartre as the theatre of situations.) Indeed, the category of situation, linked to the surpassing function of human reality, constitutes the philosophical foundation of Sartres idea of commitment which is thus not something arbitrary, subjective and voluntaristic, but inherent in the ontological structure of being as conceived by the existential philosopher. Of course, at this stage situation is not spelled out yet as commitment, but remains an abstract philosophical principle. Nevertheless, the formulation of this principle is the necessary precondition for the articulation of Sartres vision as commitment during the war, as well as of the organic insertion of commitment into his philosophical system as a whole. We should also notice that the phenomenological bracket is opened by Sartre in the only possible way accessible to him, given his vital existential concerns. As a solution to Husserls problem of motivations, the specific character of a determinate mode of consciousnessin this case: imagination is explained by the specificity of the situation itself. But the whole of consciousness which finds itself in situation is, of course, the consciousness of a living human individual. This is why the relationship is described in terms of the concrete and exact motivations of a certain particular imagination as opposed to the pure and abstract condition of possibility for all imagination. Thus consciousness in situation is related to the whole of the world in which it is situated at a given temporal juncture. Its total character which makes Sartre speak of the whole of consciousnessis therefore necessarily that of an individual totality (isolated from totalities of the same kind, as we have seen before) confronting the whole world. All this does not mean that the total and the individual are confused, since the dialectical totalization of individual totalities as situated in the real world is a perfectly legitimate concernand indeed it remains Sartres characteristic way of proceeding up to the present time. What it certainly does mean is that Sartre sets out from individual existential determinationsconcrete life-situations and the projects corresponding to themin his search

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

103

for an ultimate overall synthesis. He builds his ontological structure on the foundation of that synthetic and individual totality which is for him the existential reality, and he asserts the primacy of individual praxes in all his works. This is why he has to reject with undisguised hostility what he calls in his earliest as much as in his latest worksmetaphysical materialism which would introduce the individual totality on the historical stage at a much later point of development than Sartres conception for which it constitutes the primary premise and the absolute point of departure. But it is meant only as the point of departure, not as the overall synthesis itself. In Sartres conception we are presented with a movement: one that has the internal logic of totalization in which the parts constitute an organic whole, or at least point to the whole:
We said, in our Introduction, that the significance of a fact of consciousness came to this: that it always pointed to the whole human-reality which was making itself emotional, attentive, perceptive, willing, etc. The study of the emotions has indeed verified this principle: an emotion refers to what it signifies. And what it signifies is indeed, in effect, the totality of the relations of the human reality to the world. The onset of emotion is a complete modification of the being-in-the-world according to the very peculiar laws of magic.195

Thus the lines of demarcation are firmly drawn, and the overall framework of reference is the totality of the relations of the human reality to the world. Sartre is, therefore, less than just towards his early works when he summarily characterizes them as works in which the total is confused with the individual. And he is more than generous towards the later works in claiming the solution of the problem of totalization, while in fact on this point his position is characterized by minor changes and fundamental continuity throughout his lifework.

3.
L ET US N OW E XAM IN E TH E PRO B LEMATIC ASPECTS of the young Sartres conception of totality and see what happens to them in the course of his later development. The first point to note is that the methodological dualism of phenomenology is transmuted by Sartre into an ontological law:

104

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

That exists spontaneously which determines its own existence. In other words, to exist spontaneously is to exist for oneself [exister pour soi et par soi]. One reality alone deserves to be called spontaneous: consciousness. To exist and to be conscious of existing are one and the same for consciousness. Otherwise stated, the supreme ontological law of consciousness is as follows: for a consciousness the only way of existing is to be conscious that it exists. It is therefore evident that consciousness can determine itself to exist, but that it cannot act on anything but itself. A sensory content may be the occasion for our forming a consciousness, but we cannot act by means of consciousness on the sensory content, dragging it from nowhere (or from the unconscious), or sending it back. If images are consciousness, they are pure spontaneities. Consciousness of itself, self-transparency, and existing only to the extent that it knows itself, an image therefore cannot be a sensory content. It is perfectly futile to represent it as rationalized, as permeated by thought. There is no middle ground: either it is wholly thought, and one thinks by means of the image, or it is sensory content and one would think on the occasion of an image. In the latter case, the image will be independent of consciousness, appearing to consciousness according to laws peculiar to an image which is not consciousness. Such an image, which must be awaited, deciphered, and observed, is simply a thing. Any inert and opaque content takes its place, by the necessity inherent in its type of existence, among objects, that is to say, in the external world. That there are only two types of existence, as thing in the world and as consciousness, is an ontological law.196

We have the greatest sympathy for Sartres implicit aim: the critique of reified consciousness as manifest in mechanistically determinist theories, including the unconscious of psychoanalysis197 inasmuch as it falls into this category. It is in the same context that Sartre elaborates his concept of bad faith (mauvaise foi)198 as the dialectical alternative to the theories he criticizes. There can be no doubt about it, both his critique of crude psychological determinism,199 and his concept of bad faith represent major and lasting achievements in Sartres philosophy. At the same time, the social dimension is missing in both respects, thus greatly reducing the effectiveness of his explanations. The critique of reified consciousness remains necessarily partial so long as its terms of reference are confined to the theories themselves, without asking the question about the social foundations of those theories which reproduce, in however sophisticated a manner, the objective structure of practical reification in a reified theoretical form.200 For reification does not arise out of the structure of consciousness itself (if it did,

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

105

we could do nothing about it) but appears as a result of a complex totality of social processes of which the consciousness of the individuals constitutes an integral part. Similarly, the concept of bad faith must be integrated into a general theory of ideology of which even in Sartres later works there are only some fragments. In the absence of such integration, bad faith is called upon to explain too much, with the result of getting the focus of its explanatory specificity blurred. The efficacy of Sartres critique of reified consciousness is, moreover, vitiated by the extreme dualism of his approach. The active character of consciousness is established on the basis of the tautology that the existence of consciousness is one and the same thing as the consciousness of its existencein other words, that consciousness is conscious and selfconsciousness is conscious of itselfwhich is then declared to be the supreme ontological law of consciousness. This ontological law is in turn used to rule out a priori the middle ground, and thus all possibility of mediation is foreclosed. As a result we are presented with the ultimate ontological law according to which there are two types of existence: the thing in the world, and consciousness. The whole argument is built on this dualistic assumption without which it cannot be sustained. As it stands, its critique can only apply to some inconsistent dualism which might wish both to retain its dualistic principles and to make use of the notion of a middle ground as a bastard third type of existence; this is why Sartre insists there can be only two types. But what if we entertain as an alternative the monistic framework of explanation? What if we seek in the dialectic of the one and the manythe one and only type of existence and its manifold mediations and transitions the answer to the problems at stake? Clearly, in that case the argument that rests on the categorical assertion of extreme dualistic assumptions evaporates in thin air. Sartre, however, never makes a serious attempt at facing the monistic alternative, for such a confrontation would compel him to justify his own assumptions. He prefers to thunder, instead, against metaphysical materialism and the dialectic of nature, while simply reaffirming the categorical validity of his own premises as the necessary basis of all discussion on the subject. And thus, starting out from the positions of methodological dualismthe programme of a phenomenological reduction of experience to its irreducible elements within consciousnesswe end up with the ontology of a radically fractured totality from which mediation is exiled, with the antinomies necessarily inherent in this fracture. As we have seen above, Sartre censured Husserl on account of the miracle of the epoch.

106

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Now, as a result of his own dualistic ontological law which produces his radically fractured totality, we are presented with a mystery in place of the miracle: the bewildering ability of consciousness to use the sensory world as the vague occasionfor heaven forbid to think in terms of dialectical determinationsof its own spontaneous self-generation. The second point to mention is the negative determination of totality. This solution appears in the course of Sartres application of some Heideggerian principles (with significant modifications) to the analysis of the imaginary:
All creation of the imaginary would be completely impossible to a consciousness whose nature it would be precisely to be in-the-midst-ofthe-world. . . . For a consciousness to be able to imagine it must be able to escape from the world by its very nature, it must be able by its own efforts to withdraw from the world. In a word it must be free. Thus the thesis of unreality has yielded us the possibility of negation as its condition. Now, the latter is possible only by the negation of the world as a whole, and this negation has revealed itself to us as being the reverse of the very freedom of consciousness. . . . But, reciprocally, the possibility of constructing a whole is given as the primary structure of the act of taking perspective. It is therefore enough to be able to posit reality as a synthetic whole in order to posit oneself as free from it and this going-beyond is freedom itself since it could not happen if consciousness were not free. Thus to posit the world as a world or to negate it is one and the same thing. In this sense Heidegger can say that nothingness is the constitutive structure of the existent.201 The imaginary thus represents at each moment the implicit meaning of the real. . . . this specific position of the imaginary will be accompanied by a collapsing of the world which is no more than the negated foundation of the unreal.202

This position should not be mistaken for some advocacy of arbitrariness. Sartre makes explicit his firm opposition to such views. This is how he clarifies his relation to Heideggers idea of surpassing which establishes nothingness as the constitutive structure of the existent:
But this surpassing cannot be brought about by any means whatever, and the freedom of consciousness must not be confused with the arbitrary. For an image is not purely and simply the world-negated, it is always the world negated from a certain point of view, namely, the one that permits the

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

107

positing of the absence or the non-existence of the object presented as an image. The arbitrary position of the real as a world will not of itself cause the appearance of the centaur as an unreal object. For the centaur to emerge as unreal the world must be grasped as a world-where-the-centaur-is-not, and this can only happen if consciousness is led by different motivations to grasp the world as being exactly the sort in which the centaur has no place.203

Similarly, he makes some important qualifications on the relationship between imagination and freedom as well as between nothingness and the world of existence:
. . . the imagination, which has become a psychological and empirical function, is the necessary condition for the freedom of empirical man in the midst of the world. For, if the negating function belonging to consciousness which Heidegger calls surpassingis what makes the act of imagination possible, it must be added on the other hand that this function can manifest itself only in an imaginative act. There can be no intuition of nothingness just because nothingness is nothing and because all consciousness intuitive or not is consciousness of something. Nothingness can present itself only as an infra-structure of something. The experience of nothingness is not, strictly speaking, a direct one, it is an experience which is in principle given with and in. The analyses of Bergson are pertinent in this connection: any attempt to directly conceive death or the nothingness of existence is by nature bound to fail. The gliding of the world into the bosom of nothingness and the emergence of human reality in this very nothingness can happen only through the position of something which is nothingness in relation to the world and in relation to which the world is nothing. By this we evidently define the structure of the imagination. It is the appearance of the imaginary before consciousness which permits the grasping of the process of turning the world into nothingness as its essential condition and as its primary structure. . . . The imaginary is in every case the something concrete towards which the existent is surpassed.204

Thus, Sartres intention is perfectly clear. On the one hand he wants to assert the complete freedom of consciousness and its vital negating function. On the other hand, he is very much concerned with showing that consciousness, despite its freedomor rather because of it, since consciousness is always in situation because it is always free, and the other way round, as we have seen abovecannot possibly construct another world than exactly the

108

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

one in which we happen to live. Of course, this is a most uneasy solution that constantly oscillates between the extreme poles of total indeterminacy and its diametrical opposite: the massive contingency, facticity, absurdity205 and absolute givenness of the things in the world, with all their iron determinations. The very moment the freedom of consciousness is affirmed in its categorical form, it is already negated, in an equally categorical form, by the absolute contingency of the real as it exactly happens to bethus the feeling of absurdity. Equally, the moment the real is asserted as exactly given, it is already negated and surpassed, for the function of consciousness is the surpassing of the real in order to make a world of it.206 Nevertheless, no matter how paradoxical this conception is, the existential motivation behind it is the affirmation of great concern: the full acknowledgement of the objectivity of the real in its exact givenness (in opposition to any attempt at directly inflating nothingness into a pseudo-objective myth), and the equally full and passionate rejection of its iron determinations in the name of surpassing through the existential projects of the human world. But to return to the negative determination of totality, constructing a whole (or positing the world as a world) and negating it comes to one and the same thing. This view assigns to nothingness and negation the key role, as the constitutive structure of the existent. The consequence of such a definition is that totality (the real as a world) is identifiable only through its collapse, that is when the world appears as nothing more than the negated foundation of the unreal. Thus the world is not the foundation of the unreal (the imaginary)for that would still preserve the reality of the real when it is elevated to the status of totalitybut only its negated foundation. This means that when the imaginary constructs the real as a whole through its negating function, what it brings about is not totality as real but merely a complete nihilation which assumes the form of an unarticulated imaginary totality that necessarily loses its totality in direct proportion to its reconstitution as the real. We are thus presented with another, even if this time inexplicit, ontological law; one which postulates an inverse ratio in the relationship between the total and the real. The problem is, therefore, not the confusion of the total and the individual but the existential nihilation of the former through the identification of totalisation and nantisation. In such a conceptual framework there can be no room for negation within the sphere of objective reality itself: negation must always come from the outside. For that which is denied must be imagined. In fact, the object of a negation cannot be real because it would be affirming what is being denied but neither can it be a complete nothing, since it is something

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

109

that is being denied. So the object of a negation must be posited as imaginary.207 Thus the dialectic of nature indeed any non-Sartrean kind of realist ontologymust be a priori ruled out by this conception. In truth, not because of the alleged logical contradiction, for Sartre is the last person to worry about formal logical contradictions. (There is nothing wrong with that. One of the most crucial dialectical categories: Aufhebungsuperseding preservation and preserving supersession is precisely a fusion of positivity and negativity. It is exactly the kind of surpassing affirmation which Sartre strangely wants to exclude here as a violation of logic.) The real reason is the overall ontological construct which precedes the logical argument rather than being derived from it, notwithstanding Sartres presentation of the issues. As a matter of fact, Sartre must disregard any possible counter-argument to his ownfor example, the simultaneously positive-affirmative and negative-surpassing character of Aufhebungbecause such counter-arguments would undermine his ontological assumptions. As we have seen above, in the passage on the supreme ontological law of consciousness, Sartre declares that consciousness can determine itself to exist because its nature is to be free (by definition). However, the price he has to pay for such a definitionand he does so with great consistency is to admit that this free consciousness cannot act on anything but itself. Consequently, in order to be able to fulfill its negating function, consciousness must first homogenize the object of its negation with itself. This can take place only in the form of a peculiarly Sartrean double negation which, unlike Hegel or Marx, does not reproduce reality at a higher level but constantly reestablishes the fragmentation of reality. The first negation is universal or generic in that it must comprehensively (or categorically) nihilate the reality character of the real in order to be able to act upon it once the real (transmuted into the negated foundation of the unreal) is subsumed under the sphere of nihilatingly totalizing consciousness. (As we can see, totalization is the necessary function of this nihilating homogenization.) And the second negation is partial or specific in that something is being denied by imagination on the ground of the previous universal negation. And since the specificity of the second negation cannot arise without affecting universality (the imaginary totality) itself, as produced through the first negation, we are thrown back into a real completely severed from totality: the world of fragmentation and isolation, compartmentalization and serialization, privatization and deadly confrontationin one word, the desolate world of reification. No wonder, therefore, that the existential picture of this world is painted with the most sombre colors: When the imaginary is not posited as

110

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

a fact, the surpassing and the nullifying of the existent are swallowed up in the existent; . . . the person is crushed in the world, run trough by the real, he is closest to the thing.208 This takes us to the third major point which concerns the world of objects and their utilizability. In Nausea the problem appears in a most graphic form as the main theme of the novel:
I am no longer free, I can no longer do what I want. Objects ought not to touch, since they are not alive. You use them, you put them back in place, you live among them: they are useful, nothing more. But they touch me, it is unbearable. I am afraid of entering in contact with them, just as if they were living animals. Now I see; I remember better what I felt the other day on the seashore when I was holding that pebble. It was a sort of sweet disgust. How unpleasant it was! And it came from the pebble, Im sure of that, it passed from the pebble into my hands. Yes, thats it, thats exactly it: a sort of nausea in the hands.209

From here Sartres hero goes on to say, as the theme unfolds, first, that Nausea is not inside him but, on the contrary, he is the one who is inside it,210 and then, that Nausea is himself.211 Such a transition, on the surface of it, seems to correspond to the stages whereby (1) man comes into contact with the world of objects and simply utilizes them (absence of nausea); (2) he perceives the threatening character of objects (the pebble, the nausea in the hand); (3) he is surrounded and engulfed by the world of objects (he is inside nausea); and (4) he is himself reified (he is one with nausea, he is it). However, things are rather more complicated than that in Sartres vision. For the point of total takeoveran unexpected, strange experience of wholenesssuddenly transmutes everything by some magic into fullness and life and into overflowing plenitude. Significantly, at this point Sartres hero has his revelation about the nature of existence. This is how he describes it:
It took my breath away. Never, until these last few days, had I suspected what it meant to exist. . . . usually existence hides itself. It is there, around us, in us, it is us, you cant say a couple of words without speaking of it, but finally you cant touch it. . . . And then, all of a sudden, there it was, as clear as day; existence had suddenly unveiled itself. It had lost its harmless appearance as an abstract category: it was the very stuff of things, that root was steeped in existence. Or rather the root, the park gates, the bench, the

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

111

sparse grass on the lawn, all that had vanished; the diversity of things, the individuality, was only an appearance, a veneer. This veneer had melted, leaving soft, monstrous masses, in disordernaked, with a frightening, obscene nakedness.212

Such a wholeness from which the veneer of diversity and individuality has been removed, cannot be grasped, according to Roquentin-Sartre, in terms of human measures which we apply to the world of utilizable objects. Thus the reflection about the superfluity of all existents leads to the identification of the absolute and the absurd, nausea and existence, existence (nausea) and contingency (nausea) all explained as dimensions of the World . . . that huge absurd being:
I realized that there was no half-way house between non-existence and this rapturous abundance. . . . Superfluous: that was the only connexion I could establish between those trees, those gates, those pebbles. It was in vain that I tried to count the chestnut trees, to situate them in relation to the Velleda, to compare their height with the height of the plane trees: each of them escaped from the relationship in which I tried to enclose it, isolated itself, overflowed. I was aware of the arbitrary nature of the relationship, which I insisted on maintaining in order to delay the collapse of the human world of measures, of quantities, of bearings; they no longer had any grip on things. . . . The Word Absurdity is now born beneath my pen; . . . I had found the key to Existence, the key to my nausea, to my own life. . . . over there, I touched the thing. But here I should like to establish the absolute character of this absurdity. . . . I, a little while ago, experienced the absolute; the absolute or the absurd. Absurd; irreducible; nothing:not even profound, secret aberration of Naturecould explain that. . . . the world of explanations and reasons is not that of existence. . . . Yes, I had already scrutinized, with that same anxiety, unnameable objects, . . . I had already felt their cold, inert qualities escape, slip between my fingers. . . . And the pebble, that wretched pebble, the origin of this whole business: it was not . . . I couldnt remember exactly what it refused to be. But I had not forgotten its passive resistance. . . . The essential thing is contingency. I mean that, by definition, existence is not necessity. To exist is simply to be there; what exists appears, lets itself be encountered, but you can never deduce it. There are people, I believe, who have understood that. Only they have tried to overcome this contingency by inventing a necessary, causal being. But no necessary being

112

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

can explain existence: contingency is not an illusion, an appearance which can be dissipated; it is absolute and consequently perfect gratuitousness. Everything is gratuitous, that park, this town, and myself. When you realize that, it turns your stomach over and everything starts floating about, . . . that is the nausea; . . . I was the root of the chestnut tree. Or rather I was all consciousness of its existence. Still detached fromsince I was conscious of it and yet lost in it, nothing but it. An uneasy consciousness and yet one which let itself hang with all its weight over that piece of inert wood. . . . Existence is not something which allows itself to be thought of from a distance; it has to invade you suddenly, pounce upon you, weigh heavily on your heart like a huge motionless animalor else there is nothing left at all. . . . That idea of transition was another invention of man. An idea which was too clear. . . . Admittedly a movement was something different from a tree. But it was still an absolute. A thing. . . . everything was full, everything was active, there was no unaccented beat, everything, even the most imperceptible movement, was made of existence. . . . Existence everywhere, to infinity, superfluous, always and everywhere; . . . my very flesh was throbbing and opening, abandoning itself to the universal burgeoning, it was repulsive. . . . There were fools who talked to you about willpower and the struggle for life. . . . Impossible to see things that way. Weaknesses, frailties, yes. . . . 213 [The trees] did not want to exist, only they could not help it; . . . Tired and old, they went on existing, unwillingly and ungraciously, simply because they were too weak to die, because death could come to them only from the outside: melodies alone can proudly carry their own death within them like an internal necessity; only they dont exist. Every existent is born without reason, prolongs itself out of weakness and dies by chance. . . . Did I dream up that huge presence? . . . It went up as high as the sky, it flowed away everywhere, it filled everything with gelatinous subsidence and I could see it going deeper and deeper, far beyond the limits of the park and the houses at Bouville. I was no longer at Bouville or anywhere, I was floating. I was not surprised, I knew perfectly well that it was the World, the World in all its nakedness which was suddenly revealing itself, and I choked with fury at that huge absurd being. You couldnt even wonder where it all came from, or how it was that a world should exist rather than nothing.214

As we can see, the depiction of Roquentins experience in the park graphically unfolds the main tenets of Sartres existential philosophy. The world of objectsas differentiated, determinate, utilizable, countable, comparable,

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

113

etc.turns out to be the world of appearance and veneer, and, through anxiety, the absolute unveils itself as undifferentiated wholeness, huge and overpowering presence, absurd and gratuitous contingency, all-pervasive existence, the World as irreducible, naked, huge absurd being. Here we are given the Husserlian direct intuition of essence in its existentialist version, with the phenomenological bracket wide open. Its driving force (or motivation) is passion and emotion which force the absolute to reveal itself. This enterprise is characterized at the plane of experience as anguish, nausea, powerless fury, etc. Man is driven on by passion which shows itself as the primary structure of his existential reality. Naturally, Nausea is trying to convey the existential message in a fictional form, utilizing the means of graphic depiction, metaphorical suggestion, and dramatic presentation. The evocative aim requires that the philosophical ideas be wedded to vivid imagery and cannot simply follow a course of their own. Thus the various conceptual elements become fused into one another sometimes as a direct result of the imagery itself, while a strictly conceptual development of the same ideas would require a sharper definition and a more clearly differentiated expression. Nevertheless, all the constituents of the young Sartres general conception are present in Nausea, in a specific form, and the world of objectsin relation to the problem of utilizabilityis depicted in fundamentally the same way as in his rather more abstract works on philosophical psychology written in the same period. We can see this very clearly in his Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions, though of course there the lines of demarcation are more firmly drawn. This is how Sartre characterizes in this work the fundamental contrast between the world as the totality of utensils and the world as a non-utilizable whole:
Consciousness can be-in-the-world in two different ways. The world may appear before it as an organized complex of utilizable things, such that, if one wants to produce a predetermined effect, one must act upon the determinate elements of that complex. As one does so, each utensil refers one to other utensils and to the totality of utensils; there is no absolute action, no radical change that one can introduce immediately into this world. We have to modify one particular utensil, and this by means of another which refers it in its turn to yet another, and so on to infinity. But the world may also confront us as one non-utilizable whole; that is, as only modifiable without intermediation and by great masses. In that case, the categories of the world act immediately upon the consciousness, they are present to it at no distance (for example the face that frightens us through the window acts

114

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

upon us without any means; there is no need for the window to open, for a man to leap into the room or to walk across the floor). And conversely, the consciousness tries to combat these dangers or to modify these objects at no distance and without means, by some absolute, massive modification of the world. This aspect of the world is an entirely coherent one; this is the magical world.215

Here we are confronted with another hopeless dichotomy. The world in which we have to act by means of utensilsthe world of countable things and comparable objects, predetermined instruments and goal-oriented institutions, teleological targets and individual actions, determinate powers and specific transformationsis an infinitely fragmented world which cannot be pictured as a whole from the point of view of the individual who is trying to act upon it because doing so would involve us in yet another logical contradiction: that of putting an end to infinity, or controlling and transforming infinity through a particular, infinitesimal part of it. The Sartrean construction is so fatefully dichotomous that we are either confined to the infinitesimal fraction so as to resign ourselves to the idea of action as an infinite series of small mediations of utensils by utensils by . . . to infinity, or we directly confront totality as undifferentiated wholeness and non-utilizable whole (the huge absurd being we have encountered in Nausea) and act upon it at no distance and without means, producing some absolute, massive modification through the magic of emotion. Even to envisage taking hold of totality in order to affect it radically in a non-magical way would mean contemplating a dreadful self-contradiction. Obviously, one would be an extremely simple-minded neo-positivist cheerfully to accept the predicament of fractional instrumental mediations in the name of a social engineering: the labour of a demented Sisyphus who disregards the odds of infinity against him and predicates a successful outcome to his own efforts. Sartre has nothing in common with such an attitude. His picture of the predicament of man in the world of utensils is very far from being a cheerful one. On the contrary, for him the Universe remains dark (1964), as we have seen above.216 And it would be vain to expect the removal of the gloom through the other side of the dichotomy. For the massive modification of the world occurs only in what Sartre explicitly calls the magical world. But, of course, this could not be otherwise, thanks to the Sartrean characterization of the world of utilizable things. His representation of the totality of utensils as an infinite series of strictly partial mediations is a

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

115

self-defeating (but in relation to the acting isolated individual coherent) misrepresentation in that it is depicted as an unstructured totality. The vague talk about the organized complex of utilizable things (as earlier about the occasion of the self-generation of consciousness, in place of its dialectical determination through mediated reciprocities and interactions), does not help in the least to solve this problem. For an organized complex which is assigned the form of an infinite series is not organized at all in any proper sense of the term. It is more like a contradiction in termsan organized whole which is not a totalitythan a genuine structure. Indeed, seriality as such is not an ontological structure of being but the mere postulate of an inherently problematical structure: the countable arrangement of unstructured things in an infinite (open) series, at the formal-conceptual level; and a mystifying phenomenal manifestation of an underlying structure (the structure of reification and commodity fetish) in the sphere of social reality. On closer inspection Sartres picture of the world as unstructured totality turns out to be the product of a double dichotomy: (1) the diametrical opposition between the thing in the world (the world of things and objects) and consciousness, and (2) the antagonistic existential opposition between man (consciousness) and the other. It goes without saying, radical change through action is conceivable if the world is a structured totality in which some constituents have a greater strategic function than others; and the strategic importance of any particular factor (utensil, institution, means) is in direct proportion to its ability to control the structure as a whole. (As we can see, this is not a question of mere countability, but of a qualitative locationkey, strategically vital, etc.of the factor in question within the overall structure.) If we try to bring about a radical change in our society by first addressing, say, a local tea-party of fox-hunters wives, urging them to use their good offices with their husbands, and then we move on to the next particular utensil and to the next thereafter, and so on in the chain of the established organized complex, we are indeed going to get lost forever in the maze of our self-imposed infinite series. Fortunately, however, there are other ways of producing radical changes in the social world. The necessary preconditions of major social change are (1) the identification and utilization of the historically given contradictions, forces and institutions, and (2) the adequacy of the subject of the action to the task. If, however, the subject is conceived as an isolated individual, he is bound to remain a prisoner of the infinite series. For social reality is a structured totality only in relation to a subject who is himself a complex whole: the social individual integrated (through his class or, in a classless society,

116

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

in some other form) into the community to which he happens to belong. In the eyes of the isolated individual the social totality must, of course, appear as the mysterious aggregate of particular steps which he cannot conceivably control beyond an extremely limited point, if that. Thus this isolated individual who is opposedin the spirit of the Sartrean double dichotomynot only to the world of objects but also to the human beings of the social world characterized as the other, cannot do other than admit the powerlessness of his own actions in the world of utilizable things and embark on the curious strategies of the magical world. This is where the Heideggerian heritage weighs heaviest on Sartres shoulders. The undialectical conception of the world as an unstructured totality, and the closely interrelated characterization of the subject of human action as an isolated individual, are transmuted into ahistorical existential structures, and the social world is subsumed under the world of magic: the world of the emotion.
. . . during an emotion, the consciousness abases itself and abruptly transmutes the determinist world in which we live, into a magical world. But, conversely, sometimes it is this world that reveals itself to consciousness as magical just where we expect it to be deterministic. It must not, indeed, be supposed that magic is an ephemeral quality that we impose upon the world according to our humor There is an existential structure of the world which is magical. . . . the category of magic governs the interpsychic relations between men in society and, more precisely, our perception of others. The magical, as Alain says, is the mind crawling among things; that is, an irrational synthesis of spontaneity and passivity. It is an inert activity, a consciousness rendered passive. But it is precisely in that form that we appear to others, and this, not because of our position in relation to them, nor in consequence of our passions, but by essential necessity. Indeed, consciousness can only be a transcendent object by undergoing the modification of passivity. . . . It follows that man is always a sorcerer to man and the social world is primarily magical.217 Emotion may be called a sudden fall of consciousness into magic; or, if you will, emotion arises when the world of the utilizable vanishes abruptly and the world of magic appears in its place. We must not, therefore, see in emotion a passing disorder of the organism and the mind which enters and upsets them from outside. On the contrary, it is the return of consciousness in the magical attitude, one of the great attitudes which are essential to it, with the appearance of the correlative worldthe magical world. Emotion is not an accident, it is a mode of our conscious existence, one of the ways

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

117

in which consciousness understands (in Heideggers sense of Verstehen) its Being-in-the-World.218

While some parts of these quotations are most illuminating about the nature of the emotion itself, the utilization of emotion as the key to understanding the social world (as magic) is problematical in the extreme. For man may be a sorcerer to manbut do we not all know that sorcerers are an invention of man, in the Sartrean sense of the term? And if men behave as if they were sorcerers, it is not because of some essential ontological necessity issuing from a permanent existential structure that forever manifests itself as an unavoidable irrational synthesis of spontaneity and passivity, but because of determinateand at least in principle removablesocio-historical conditions. To embark on the task of removing these conditions by restructuring the social world in which we happen to live, in accordance with genuine human ends and in opposition to the self-propelling power of magically reified institutions, is precisely what confers meaning on the human enterprise at the present stage of history. And no magic is going to help in that. It is not necessary to go on any longer; for some additional aspects of this complex of problems which we might wish to examine are only corollaries of the basic tenets seen so far. As the examples quoted above have shown, in Sartres early philosophy totality is: (1) dualistically fractured; (2) negatively determined; and (3) unstructured both as totality of utensils projected in an infinite series, and as social totality called the magical world. Naturally, in Sartres later works there are some changes also in these respects and their extent and precise nature will be discussed in some detail in the chapters that follow. Now we must confine ourselves to indicating briefly the general trend of Sartres later development as directly related to the present context. On the first point we find that in some of his later works Sartre becomes aware of the need for mediation, and at least the postulate of such mediation repeatedly appears in the Critique and elsewhere. However, the dualistic structure of his thought tends to reassert itself, no matter how hard he tries to overcome the fracture in particular contexts. He puts forward one side of the dualistic opposition, to function as mediation, which it cannot conceivably do. Thus, in place of genuine structural mediations we get declarations such as irreducible particularity is one way of living universality219 and the child becomes this or that because he lives the universal as particular220 whereby lived and living (which belong to the particular) become the pseudo-mediations between universality and particularity. This solution provides a blanket justification for the systematic avoidance

118

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

of the true problem of mediation, namely: how is it possible to live the universal as particular? A question to which the answer can only be: through specific mediations (which, of course, calls for the precise identification of the specificities) and not through living itSartres answerwhich is begging the question. And, of course, begging the question not as a result of some confusion (a favorite pseudo-explanation in neo-positivist philosophy, which itself begs the question by explaining alleged confusion by alleging confusion) but out of the internal necessity of a philosophy which simultaneously wants to retain unchanged its dualistic presuppositions (the structural framework of its reasoning)e.g. What we call freedom is the irreducibility of the cultural order to the natural order221and mediate them by declaring that irreducibility is mediation itself. Second, negative determination remains all-pervasive in Sartres philosophy, wherever we look. Three illustrations should suffice here, concerning (1) reality in general; (2) particular individuals; and (3) a complex social whole like the city. According to Sartre, the fundamental dimension of human reality, possibility, articulates itself as the presence of the future as that which is lacking, and that which, by its very absence, reveals reality.222 In the second respect we learn that Every man is defined negatively by the sum total of possibles which are impossible for him; that is, by a future more or less blocked off.223 And in the third context we read that a city is a material and social organization which derives its reality from the ubiquity of its absence.224 Again, Sartre tries to introduce historical qualifications, and again the original structure tends to reassert itself. We can see this dilemma in the way he approaches history. He is critical of marxism for its alleged failure to study the structures of historythe object of Sartres enquiry in the Critiquefor themselves.225 Paradoxically, however, his ontological analysis of these structures under the aspect of the theoretical possibilities of their combinations,226 tends to negate the historicity of history by defining it as a fundamental existential structure: If History escapes me, this is not because I do not make it; it is because the other is making it as well.227 Thus, if history escapes me, this is not because the other is whatever he is like (i.e., antagonistically opposed to me, for determinate socio-historical reasons), but because he is the other (i.e., because of the existential ontological structure of otherness). Consequently, either the other ceases to make history and leaves that job to me, or history will continue to escape me. And again, either the other ceases to be the other, or history will remain the way we know it from the past, namely beyond conscious human control. And since such possibilities are at best confined

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

119

to transitory momentslike the obliteration of the antagonism between the I and the other in the structurally unstable fused groupthe other continues to cast its immense dark shadow on history, thanks to Sartres negative determination of the existential ontological structures. And finally, the problem of unstructured totality. It is in this respect that the changes are most obvious in Sartres later philosophy. He gets involved in an intensive study of historical temporalization as manifest through exchange, the practico-inert, series, collectives, recurrence, etc., although primarily from the point of view of the theoretical possibilities of their combinations, as we have seen a moment ago. At times he even remarks on the historical specificity of the conditions under which the infinite series dominates, but with a tendency to take backor at least greatly to weaken through the next step in his line of reasoning the historical specification. We can see this very clearly in the following quotation:
It is necessary to take up the study of collectives again from the beginning and to demonstrate that these objects, far from being characterized by the direct unity of a consensus, represent perspectives of flight. This is because upon the basis of given conditions, the direct relations between persons depends upon particular relations, and these on still others, and so on in succession, because there is an objective constraint in concrete relations. It is not the presence of the others but their absence which establishes this constraint; it is not their union but their separation. For us the reality of the collective objects rests on recurrence. It demonstrates that the totalization is never achieved and that the totality exists at best only in the form of a detotalized totality.228

Furthermore the early double dichotomy reappears, in that history as such is depicted as the sphere of irreconcilable antagonism in which man is opposed to the other and existencein its particularity and irreducibilityto knowledge. (Also: we are confronted with a struggle of thought against its social instruments229as if thought itself were not a social instrument.) And even references to magic are retained as late as 1973 (relations between people . . . are complicated by some magic), together with the famous sentence from the early work on Emotions: man is a sorcerer for man230 repeated word for word. No wonder that for Sartre the resolution of the antagonism depicted in his existential-ontological account of history cannot be the realization of history (in Marxs words, true history that follows mankinds antagonistic pre-history) but only the problematical

120

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

postulate of its dissolution: History will have only one meaning, when it will tend to be dissolved in the concrete men who will make it in common.231 Thus, since the various institutional etc. forms of our detotalized social totality are characterized as realities, whose being is directly proportional to the non-being of humanity,232 the ideal of human self-realization must appear as the direct experience of universality by concrete man whose precondition is the progressive dissolution of all those differentiations and mediations through which real history articulates itself.

4.
T H E M ET HOD OLOG IC AL PRINCIPLES of a philosophy are inseparable from the basic propositions through which any comprehensive orientation of thought towards reality can be defined. Naturally, for analytical purposes, methodological rules may have to be treated separately. But they are not intelligible in themselves, nor are they capable of providing justifications for themselves. To try to explain methodological principles and rules by themselves can only result in the infinite regress of meta-meta- . . . metamethodology, or in circularity, or in a combination of the two (as in some neopositivistic analytic philosophy which exhausts itself in the production of a self-consuming methodology for the sake of methodology by obsessively sharpening its carving knife until the blade completely disappears in the steeldust of self-perfection and the philosopher is left holding the bare handle). The problems of method arise out of the task at hand, and the philosophical comprehension of experience prescribes its own explicit or latent method. Any particular set of methodological rules presents itself as a specific way of sifting and selecting from among all the available data, with a view of constructing a coherent whole. Specifying how to proceed, what to include or exclude, how to define the relationship between philosophical knowledge and the totality of available (including scientific and everyday) knowledge, how to relate philosophical activity to the totality of human praxis, and so on,all this would be meaningless if it could not be justified by the nature of the philosophical enterprise itself as developed throughout history. (Why on earth should one pay the slightest attention to the rules of a particular philosophical method unless one wanted to participate in the further development of this collective human enterprise?) Furthermore, the rules of a particular method would be arbitrary if they could not be justified by the results as compared to those obtainable through the adoption of alternative methods.

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

121

Phenomenological reduction, for instance, is totally pointless without the explicit or implicit critical references to the alleged deficiencies of the natural attitude, and thus to the whole complex of controversial issuesin epistemology and ontologywhich gave rise to the elaboration of the phenomenological method in the first two decades of the twentieth century. The methodological rules and principles are constituted in the course of the articulation of a given philosophy as a whole. This is why they cannot be simply transferred from one setting to another without all the necessary modifications which homogenize the rules of method and the thematic principles of the philosophy in question. Ontological shifts call for significant methodological changes even in philosophies which explicitly profess to abide by the same rules. Husserl, Heidegger, Sartre, Merleau-Ponty are all phenomenologists in a sense. However, the way they all apply and modify the rules of phenomenology varies considerably not only from one philosopher to the other but even in the development of each.233 This is not the place to pursue these problems systematically. Limitations of space demand that we confine ourselves to a brief discussion of the dialectical interrelationship between method and Weltanschauung (world view) as manifest in Sartres own writings. Already at the time of his earliest encounter with Husserl, Sartres enthusiasm for phenomenology is tempered by concerns which are eminently his own. When Raymond Aron, in the spring of 1933, draws his attention to Husserls philosophy, he is already looking for some method through which he might be able to express his own views on existence and contingency in a more coherent form. He welcomes the discovery to the extent to which it can be subordinated to his own conception and integrated into his own quest. This is the most telling part of Simone de Beauvoirs account of the incident. For while leafing through Levinass book on Husserl which he picks up on the Boulevard Saint-Michel soon after the talk with Aron, Sartres heart missed a beat when he found references to contingency: Had someone cut the ground from under his feet, then? As he read on he reassured himself that this was not so. Contingency seemed not to play any very important part in Husserls system.234 Thus, Sartre has very firm ideas right from the beginning on what he wants the phenomenological method for: the coherent formulation of his own existential-ontological concerns. His commitment to the latter precedes by several years his encounter with phenomenology, but they fill his mind in a rather chaotic form. Now that he has made his discovery, he is determined to use phenomenology so as to give shape, order and discipline to his strongly felt views. From such intention it also follows

122

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

that in so far as the new method is not suited to the task he has in mind, it will have to be modified as required. For he sees clearly, right from the outset, thatthrough his own problematic of contingencyhe introduces something significantly new into Husserlian phenomenology. No wonder, then, that Sartres very first serious reflection on this method, in 1934, takes the form of a radical reassessment of its principal tenets, from the transcendental ego to the epoch, and from the question of motivation to the characteristically Sartrean way of opening the phenomenological bracket. Of course, the relationship between method and ontology should not be conceived on the model of one-sided determinations but as a form of dialectical reciprocity. This means that once the Sartrean version of phenomenology is constituted, on the basis of his major ontological principles, the methodological framework tends to circumscribe the limits within which reality is experienced and evaluated. Thus, for instance, when in The Problem of Method Sartre expresses his total agreement with the marxist Lefbvres method, he reads the latters words characteristically in his own key. For these are the exact terms of Lefbvres analysis: (a) Descriptive. Observation but with a scrutiny guided by experience and by a general theory. (b) Analytico-regressive. Analysis of reality. Attempt to rediscover the present, but elucidated, understood, explained.235 And this is how Sartre interprets it:
We have nothing to add to this passage, so clear and so rich, except that we believe that this method, with its phase of phenomenological description and its double movement of regression followed by progress, is validwith the modifications which its objects may impose upon itin all the domains of anthropology. Further, it is this method which we shall apply, as we shall see later, to significations, to individuals themselves, and to the concrete relations among individuals. This method alone can be heuristic: it alone at once defines the originality of the fact and makes comparisons possible.236

As we can see, Sartres primary interest is in significations (elsewhere he calls it hierarchized specifications237), individuals, concreteness, and originality (uniqueness) to be connected with universality through comparisons, in the service of a heuristic. In one word, his concern is to find a method best suited to explain a particular individual (Flaubert, for example) in a most comprehensive way. Anthropological knowledge, as Sartre sees it, is mobilized towards this end. By contrast, Lefbvres enquiry is concerned with a rural community and, through studying it, with the definition of the

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

123

methods appropriate to the field of rural sociology. Accordingly, for him the descriptive phase is just what it says, namely, taking inventory of the data as encountered in the given rural community, within the framework of a general theory of society. Which means that there can be no pure description, since evaluation is an integral part of the enterprise at all phases, in virtue of the general theory brought to bear upon the data of description. Significantly, however, Sartre translates descriptive into phenomenological descriptionwhich is a radically different enterprise both in that it claims to be pure description and that its aim is the identification of essences. The second phase for Lefbvre is analytico-regressive. For he wants to date (his italics) with precision the various historical layers that coexist in the given structure; that is, he wants to identify the heterogeneity of the elementswith all their contraststhat make up the structure. In other words, this phase is concerned with the elucidation of a cross-section of the structure, whereas the third phase concentrates on the historical-genetic comprehension and elucidation of the dynamic whole of the present. Characteristically, again, this complementarity of the analytico-regressive (or structural-analytic) and the historical-genetic dimensions is translated by Sartre as the double movement of regression followed by progress, while in fact the term progress does not appear in Lefbvres classification. In any case, it is not clear why the historical-genetic phase should be called progressive, since Lefbvres point was not meant to establish a temporal sequence but to stress the two forms in which history and structure are treated in the study: history as subordinate to structure (the analyticoregressive dating of the various elements of the structure), and structure as subordinate to history (the historico-genetic comprehension of the present). If we want to understand the reasons why Sartre decodes for himself and translates for us Lefbvres terms the way he does, we have to go back a long way into the past, right to the early constitution of his methodological principles as spelled out in the Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions. In this work we find the following key passage:
The various disciplines of phenomenological psychology are regressive although the ultimate term of their regression is, for them, purely ideal: those of pure phenomenology, on the contrary, are progressive. It may, no doubt, be asked why, under these conditions, one should choose to employ the two disciplines simultaneously; pure phenomenology might seem to suffice. But, if phenomenology can prove that emotion is realization of the essence of the human reality in so far as the latter is affectivity, it will be impossible for it to

124

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

show that the human-reality must necessarily manifest itself in such emotions as it does. That there are such and such emotions and not othersthis is, beyond all doubt, evidence of the factitious character of human existence. It is this factitiousness that necessitates a regular recourse to the empirical; and which, in all probability, will forever prevent the psychological regression and the phenomenological progression from complete convergence.238

Here we have Sartres original methodological principles which continue to structure, notwithstanding some important changes, also his much later reflections on the progressive-regressive method: psychological regression (or recourse to the empirical), and phenomenological progression orientated towards the essence of the human reality. The reason why Sartre must envisage a double movement is itself twofold: on the one hand, the purity of pure phenomenology which means that the facticity (or factitiousness) of the human existence must escape it by definition; and on the other hand, the facticity of human existence (that is to say, its such-andsuch character; its nature exactly as we experience it) calls for disciplines to which facticity is accessible if one wants to understand and elucidate the object of the enquiry. How to integrate the two, remains somewhat of a mystery, given the radical dualism of Sartrean ontology and its correspondingly dualistic methodological rules. The double movement is bound to remain a constant to-and-fro, an oscillatory movement of reciprocal reflection from one pole towards the other, and so on. Sartre himself admits this by saying that psychological regression and phenomenological progression are destined forever not to converge, although strangely enough he adds, in all probabilitya qualification contradicted by the necessity inherent in his own depiction of the irreconcilable opposition between existential facticity and pure phenomenological essence. This dilemma is clearly visible also in another youthful work, LImagination, in which the earlier seen opposition between facticity and essence is complemented by that between particularity (individual fact, examples) and universality.
Phenomenology is a description of the structure of transcendental consciousness based on intuition of the essences of these structures. This description takes place, of course, on the level of reflection . . . which aims at the discovery of essences. That is to say, it begins by taking its stand from the outset on the terrain of the universal. Though proceeding in terms of examples, little importance is attached to whether the individual fact which

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

125

serves as underpinning for the essence is real or imaginary. Should the exemplifying datum be pure fiction, the very fact that it was imaginable means that it embodied the sought-for essence, for the essence is the very condition of its possibility.239

Thus, we are confronted with the dichotomies of facticity versus essence (the essences of the structures of transcendental consciousness), actuality versus possibility, and existential particularity versus phenomenological universality. We get essences, possibilities and universality at one pole, and facticity, actuality and particularity at the other. And since mediation (the middle ground, the third type of existence, etc.) has been a priori ruled out, as we have seen above, integration is hardly conceivable. In its place we find the suggestion of a somewhat mysterious dissolution of the two poles (and of the problem at stake) through the oscillatory double movement of reciprocal reflection (in later terminology: cross-referencing, va-etvient), just as the antagonism of history is supposed to disappear through the dissolution of history. This is why even in its much later formulation
the existential method . . . wants to remain heuristic. It will have no other method than a continuous cross-reference; it will progressively determine a biography (for example) by examining the period, and the period by studying the biography. Far from seeking immediately to integrate one into the other, it will hold them separate until the reciprocal involvement comes to pass of itself and puts a temporary end to the research.240

5.
A N OT HE R M AJ OR P R E O CCUPATIO N in Sartres philosophy is his attempt to provide a foundation to marxism through his own existential phenomenology. It would again be quite wrong to see this only in the Sartre of The Problem of Method and its aftermath. For in point of fact the origins of this orientation go back in his work at least as far as The Transcendence of the Ego, although his early attitude to marxism shows greater reservations than in the late 1950s. We have to bear in mind two important considerations in this respect. First, that Sartre as a student learns about a mechanical kind of marxism both from those hostile to it (his professors) and those (like Politzer) who champion its cause. And second, that there is a long-standing philosophical

126

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

traditionSimmel and Max Weber are among its founderswhich concedes to marxism, after many years of Totschweigen (execution by silence) the value of being of partial interest (as a supplier of interesting historical hypotheses) while insisting that it is devoid of a proper philosophical and methodological foundation. Accordingly, even the young Lukcs entertains for a number of years the idea of producing the missing philosophicalmethodological foundation, and Heidegger moves in the same intellectual orbit as far as the problematic of founding is concerned, although, understandably (in the years of German disintegration following the 191418 war rendered only more painful by the success of the Russian revolution) his fundamental ontology is meant as a foundation not for marxism but against it, transferring the problems of alienation and reification from the socio-historical sphere (the world dominated by capital) to the plane of existential-ontological temporality as manifest through the human condition in history as such.241 As we have seen in connection with Temporality in Faulkner, the young Sartre is very far from simply adopting the Heideggerian approach. His political sympathies are on the side of the working class, even if he is unable to identify himself with it as a militant, unlike his friend Nizan. If Sartre is apathetic, it is because he is highly sceptical about the possibility of a successful socialist revolution, and not because he is hostile towards the aims of such a revolution, which he himself predicates as an abstract imperative. His quest, at this stage of his development, is orientated towards defining the field of action of the individual, and therefore any conception of determinationsbe it psychoanalysis or marxismwhich does not set out from the individuals conscious (though in different ways conscious) selfdetermination, must be considered extremely problematical. Obviously, if the value of marxism is assessed in a framework whose centre of reference is the existentialist individual and his consciousness (with the aim of ascribing responsibility even to unreflective consciousness242), even a dialectical conception of marxism must appear mechanical. In this sense, it is quite secondary how subtle Politzer and other marxists of Sartres youth might or might not be. (In other words, this point is relevant at best only as one limited factor in explaining the formation of Sartres ideas, but not the persistence of his views on marxism.) For any form of marxism evaluated from the standpoint of an existential-individual ontology must appear in need of founding. In such a framework, marxism cannot be more than a fertile (maybe even: the best) historical hypothesis whose possibility, however, must be established on the foundation of

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

127

a phenomenological-existential methodology. That history is made under determinate socioeconomic conditions, indicating certain laws at work, all this may be very plausiblebut how is it possible in relation to consciousness and its fundamental project? So long as this foundation is not defined in terms of the individual and his existential project, the historical conditions and laws must appear as external mechanisms that precede the individual, and the philosophy which concentrates on them as a mechanical philosophy, whatever its merits at the level of historical hypotheses that, by definition, must be established on the ground of a fundamental ontology (existential anthropology) and therefore cannot found themselves. Thus, in so far as the historical hypotheses of marxism cannot be subsumed under the existential conception of ontology (anthropology), marxism must be validated, complemented, corrected, etc.in short it must be superseded by the existentialist quest. This is why Sartre maintains an ambivalent attitude towards it even in works in which his explicit aim is to announce the dissolution of existentialism within marxism, as we shall see in a moment. But to return to the early works, this is how this problem appears in The Transcendence of the Ego:
It has always seemed to me that a working hypothesis as fruitful as historical materialism never needed for a foundation the absurdity which is metaphysical materialism. In fact, it is not necessary that the object precede the subject for spiritual pseudo-values to vanish and for ethics to find its bases in reality. It is enough that the me be contemporaneous with the World, and that the subject-object duality, which is purely logical, definitely disappear from philosophical preoccupations. The World has not created the me; the me has not created the World. These are two objects for absolute, impersonal consciousness, and it is by virtue of this consciousness that they are connected. This absolute consciousness, when it is purified of the I, no longer has anything of the subject. It is no longer a collection of representations. It is quite simply a first condition and an absolute source of existence. And the relation of interdependence established by this absolute consciousness between the me and the World is sufficient for the me to appear as endangered before the World, for the me (indirectly and through the intermediary of states) to draw the whole of its content from the World. No more is needed in the way of philosophical foundation for an ethics and a politics which are absolutely positive.243

128

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

As Sartres subsequent development shows, things are a great deal more complicated than our quotation suggests. For notwithstanding the adoption of the proposed philosophical foundation for an absolutely positive ethics and politics, both remain an elusive goal in his lifework. And this is by no means a surprising development. To declare that the subject-object duality is purely logical, in conjunction with the ultimate postulate of a subjectless absolute, impersonal consciousness: the absolute source of existence, is not sufficient to make the underlying problem disappear. In any case, such consciousness is very far from humbly conforming to Sartres characterization of not having anything of the subject. Although it is contrasted with the strictly individual consciousness, it represents in Sartres philosophy that conflation of the individual and the collective subject which we have seen above, in connection with his essay on Faulkner. The phenomenological concept of intentionality enables Sartre to tie the two poles together, so that he can describe consciousness in general, despite calling it impersonal, in terms indistinguishable from the characteristics of an individual consciousness. Consciousness is frightened by its own spontaneity because it senses this spontaneity as beyond freedom;244 indeed, in this framework even the ego can be described as intended by consciousness to mask from consciousness its very spontaneity.245 In other words, consciousness is said to produce its egological structure in order to deceive itself. At this point we can see that the philosophical function of the Sartrean solution is not so much theoretical as practical246in the sense that it points to a latent moral philosophy, though of course not to an absolutely positive one:
Everything happens, therefore, as if consciousness constituted the ego as a false representation of itself, as if consciousness hypnotized itself before this ego which it has constituted, absorbing itself in the ego as if to make the ego its guardian and its law. It is thanks to the ego, indeed, that a distinction can be made between the possibility and the real, between appearance and being, between the willed and the undergone. But it can happen that consciousness suddenly produces itself on the pure reflective level. Perhaps not without the ego, yet as escaping from the ego on all sides, as dominating the ego and maintaining the ego outside the consciousness by a continued creation. On this level, there is no distinction between the possible and the real, since appearance is the absolute. There are no more barriers, no more limits, nothing to hide consciousness from itself. The consciousness, noting what would be called the fatality of its spontaneity,

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

129

is suddenly anguished: it is this dread, absolute and without remedy, this fear of itself, which seems to us constitutive of pure consciousness.247

The concept of barriers is the key to understanding this whole set of relations, as indeed also the analysis of temporality in Faulkner culminated in the passionate exclamation: a barred future is still a future. Collision with barriers is an indubitable fact of the human-reality. In this respect the existential question, according to Sartre, is twofold: (1) how to account for the barriers we meet; and (2) how to deal with them? Since any deterministic conception of the world has been a priori rejected, and consciousness described both as the human-reality itself248 and as the absolute source of existence, consciousness as such must be responsible for producing its own barriers. It sets up the ego as its guardian and its law, and thus it produces the distinction between the possible and the real, between appearance and being, between the willed and the undergone, etc.distinctions which all rebound against it. Thus the reality principle appears (through differentiating between the possible and the real) and takes charge of our daily life. The result is a mode of existence that can be described only with the negative categories of Sartres latent moral philosophy. The picture of such existence is truly desolate and well deserves Sartres passionate condemnation. All seems to be lost until, suddenly and paradoxically, the barriers themselves come to the rescue: All ways are barred and nevertheless we must act. So then we try to change the world; that is, to live it as though the relations between things and their potentialities were not governed by deterministic processes but by magic. But be it well understood, this is no playful matter: we are cornered, and we fling ourselves into this new attitude with all the force at our command.249 The new attitude appears as the effective negation of the previous mode of existence: consciousness lives the new world it has thereby constituted lives it directly, commits itself to it, and suffers from the qualities that the concomitant behavior has assigned to it. This means that, all ways out being barred, the consciousness leaps into the magical world of emotions.250 However, this negation is bound to remain a problematic solution. Not only becausein accordance with the underlying spontaneitythe new attitude cannot be induced but simply arises on its own whenever it does happen to arise (it can happen . . . , suddenly . . . etc.), but also because the new state is ruled by fatality. The fatality of its [consciousnesss] spontaneity is described as consciousness dropping asleep251 because

130

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

consciousness is caught in its own snare. Precisely because it is living in the new aspect of the world by believing in it, the consciousness is captured by its own belief, exactly as it is in dreams and hysteria. The consciousness of the emotion is captive, but by this it must not be understood to be fettered by anything whatever outside itself. It is captive to itself . . . Thus, when consciousness is living the magical world into which it has precipitated itself, it tends to perpetuate that world.252

Hence Sartres fascination with the imagery of man who is simultaneously the victim and the executioner responsible for his own undoing.253 Thus the vertiginous freedom and infinite overflow of consciousness does not bring liberation and fulfillment to man. Consciousness succeeds in extricating itself from the contradictions of one of its fundamental attitudes only to get trapped by the fatality of the other. Man seems to be locked into a world of antinomies: a predicament which imposes on him, as the only authentic mode of existence, the imperative of ceaseless negation. This is why the adventurer is Sartres hero who recognizes the vanity of action and its necessity, based on the absolute existence of man and the absolute impossibility of such existencea hero who finds fulfillment only in the infinitesimal moment that separates life from death.254 Sartres latent moral philosophy thus unfolds as the categorical negation of this antinomous world; or, to put it another way, the categorical negativity of his thought makes itself intelligible as a latent moral philosophy that never comes to a point of rest. In his vision man ought to negate the conditions of existence, and the more so the harder he is tossed between the horns of the existential antinomies. It is the moral intensity of this negating passion which refuses to admit any set of determinations prior to the self-determination of consciousness, so that the latter shall assume total responsibility for the human-reality it constitutes. Significantly enough, in this conception of philosophy the epistemological-ontological and the moral categories are inextricably intertwined. So much so, that epistemological-ontological objections to phenomenology are answered by moral assertions:
The theorists of the extreme Left have sometimes reproached phenomenology for being an idealism and for drowning reality in the stream of ideas. But if idealism is the philosophy without evil of Brunschwicg, if it is a philosophy in which the effort of spiritual assimilation never meets external resistance, in which suffering, hunger, and war are diluted in a

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

131

slow process of the unification of ideas, nothing is more unjust than to call phenomenologists idealists. On the contrary, for centuries we have not felt in philosophy so realistic a current. The phenomenologists have plunged man back into the world; they have given full measure to mans agonies and sufferings, and also to his rebellion.255

We can witness here the shift from epistemology to moral philosophy as idealism is defined in terms of a failure to face up to evil dominating our world in the shape of suffering, hunger and war; and similarly, realism is defined as a passionate moral concern about mans agonies and sufferings. It is secondary, whether or not the phenomenologically bracketed and reduced hunger retains much resemblance to real hunger: in any case, in Sartres philosophy the doors of the phenomenological bracket are wide open. What is of paramount importance for understanding the structure of Sartres philosophy is the fact that right from their early constitution his epistemological-ontological categories are permeated by the intense moral passion which has its primacy in his thought as deeply as the principle of the primacy of practical reason predominates in the Kantian system. This means that we are confronted with a structural integration of moral and ontological and other categories, and not just with lateral connections and associations. Sartre articulates his epistemological-ontological categories in order to sustain his own conception of morality. He takes notice of what he calls metaphysical materialism only to the extent to which the presumed ethical corollaries of such a conception of philosophy clash with his own moral concerns. He does not examine and refute the basic propositions of this philosophy at the level at which they are formulated but simply insists that one does not need the absurdity which is metaphysical materialism for spiritual pseudo-values to vanish and for ethics to find its bases in reality. And the reason why he cannot contemplate a philosophical foundation different from his own (in which consciousness is the first condition and the absolute source of existence) is, again, not epistemological-ontological but moral. For if the object preceded and determined the subject, it would be impossible to ascribe to the subject that categorical, absolute, total responsibility which Sartre wants to ascribe to it.256 Naturally, in this conception, because of the inextricable structural integration and fusion of the epistemological-ontological and the moral categories, ontology must be identified with anthropology. For nothing is admissible prior to the human reality which becomes the absolute foundation

132

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

of everything. Fundamental ontology and existential anthropology thus become synonymous:


. . . it is precisely for the human reality that to exist is always to assume its being; that is, to be responsible for it instead of receiving it from outside, as a pebble does. And since the human reality is essentially its own possibility, this existent can itself choose what it will be, achieve itselfor lose itself. Thus the human reality which is myself assumes its own being by understanding it. This understanding is mine. I am, then, first of all, a being who more or less obscurely understands his reality as a man, which means that I make myself a man by understanding myself as such. I can therefore question myself and, on the basis of that interrogation, carry out an analysis of the human reality which will serve as the basis for an anthropology.257

The structural integration and fusion of the categories works, of course, both ways. Not only are the anthropological-ontological categories permeated by existential morality but also, the other way round, the categories of Sartrean ethic are fully intelligible only in their anthropological-ontological context. Responsibility, freedom, possibility, choice, and so on, are not quite what they would mean in a specific ethical proposition. At times even Sartre feels that he must put them in inverted commas, as the term choose in the last quotation since the subject is denied by Sartre the status of a subject (which in fact amounts to a characteristic Sartrean conflation of the individual and the collective subject, as we have seen above). This is why Sartres moral philosophy must remain a latent one, resisting all his efforts which aim at articulating it as a relatively autonomous system of morality. And this is why any concept of ontology that fails to identify itself with existential anthropology must be rejected by Sartre even when his openly professed and genuinely believed aim is the integration (or dissolution) of existentialist ideology within marxism. Sartres ambivalent attitude to marxism mentioned above has its roots in the incompatibility between existentialist anthropology and marxian ontology. Not that he himself conceptualizes the problem in that form. On the contrary, given his political-moral solidarity with the perspective of a socialist transformation of society, he is anxious to stress his complete agreement with Marx. All the same, the ambivalence transpires through the shift in his arguments, as well as through his final summing up of the prospects of integrating existentialism and marxism. He gives three different explanations for his critical attitude: (1) His criticisms are meant for Engels;258 (2) He

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

133

is critical of contemporary mechanical marxism;259 (3) His critical qualifications are intended to assign certain limits to dialectical materialismto validate the historical dialectic while rejecting the dialectic of nature.260 In the third explanation we are remarkably close to the original formula which praised historical materialism as a fruitful working hypothesis (now he wants to validate the hypothesis) and rejected the absurdity which is metaphysical materialism (now he limits dialectical materialism by rejecting the idea of a dialectic of nature, worried that it would reduce man261 to a simple product of physical laws, which exactly corresponds to the early complaint against metaphysical materialism). As to Sartres final summing up of the prospects of integrating existentialism and marxism, we can see very clearly that those who lamented the alleged liquidation of existentialism and talked about Sartre being swallowed up by marxism262 had no real ground for such views. For Sartres own words speak loud for themselves, and they speak very differently:
Thus the autonomy of existential studies results necessarily from the negative qualities of Marxists (and not from Marxism itself ). So long as the doctrine does not recognize its enemies, so long as it founds its Knowledge upon a dogmatic metaphysics (a dialectic of Nature) instead of seeking its support in the comprehension of the living man, so long as it rejects as irrational those ideologies which wish, as Marx did, to separate being from Knowledge, and, in anthropology, to found the knowing of man on human existence, existentialism will follow its own path of study. This means that it will attempt to clarify the givens of Marxist Knowledge by indirect knowing (that is, as we have seen, by words which regressively denote existential structures), and to engender within the framework of Marxism a veritable comprehensive knowing which will rediscover man in the social world and which will follow him in his praxisor, if you prefer, in the project which throws him toward the social possibles in terms of a defined situation. Existentialism will appear therefore as a fragment of the system, which has fallen outside of Knowledge. From the day that Marxist thought will have taken on the human dimension (that is, the existential project) as the foundation of anthropological Knowledge, existentialism will no longer have any reason for being. Absorbed, surpassed and conserved by the totalizing movement of philosophy, it will cease to be a particular inquiry and will become the foundation of all inquiry. The comments which we have made in the course of the present essay are directedto the modest limit of our capabilitiestoward hastening the moment of that dissolution.263

134

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Thus, in place of a radical conversion leading to a liquidation of existentialism we find a statement which firmly reasserts not only Sartres opposition to dogmatic metaphysics but also his lifelong programme of founding marxism on an existential anthropology. And the last word, dissolution, could not be more distant from what it suggests to careless reading. For the message is spelled out with precision in the preceding sentence. Existentialism will be dissolved only when it becomes the foundation of all inquiry; that is: the universally accepted premise of all future philosophy. In any case, even if Sartre is willing to read Marx in his own key, their views on the relationship between ontology and anthropology are far from being identical. For as far back as 1844 Marx emphasized that
mans feelings, passions, etc., are not merely anthropological phenomena . . . but truly ontological affirmations of essential being (of nature) . . . Only through developed industry, i.e., through the medium of private propertydoes the ontological essence of human passion come to be both in its totality and in its humanity; the science of man is therefore itself a product of mans establishment of himself by practical activity.264

Thus, for Marx, ontology and anthropology are not synonymous; the former is the unquestionable foundation of the latter and in that sense precedes it. Consequently, the problem is not simply materiality, namely the fact that the point of departure is man as animal organism which sets out from needs and creates material ensembles,265 but precisely the objective ontological conditions under which such development can take place. This is what makes Marx insist on the ontological principle inherent in the development of modern technology which consists in resolving each process into its constituent movements, without any regard to their possible execution by the hand of man.266 Whether or not one should apply the term dialectic of nature (and if so, with what qualifications) to the study of such conditions, need not worry us here. What matters is that they are clearly not anthropological they concern natures fundamental laws of motion and the prerequisites of human development in accordance with and in response to such objective laws but constitute the ultimate points of reference of ontology into which a dialectical conception of anthropology must be integrated as a part in the whole. Since, however, the integration of existentialism and marxism envisaged by Sartre is diametrically opposed to this, his programme of founding marxism remains for Sartre as far from its realization today as in 1934.

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

135

6.
SA RT R E S E AR LY WOR K S A RE W RITTEN in a period of great contradictions which threateningly foreshadow the possibility of a cataclysm never seen before. For perceptive men who are willing to bear witness, the gravity of the predicament is evident not only in the great world economic crisis of 1929-33, but also in the solutions that follow that crisis, from the rise of fascism to the chronic depression and unemployment that characterizes the life of all the liberal capitalist countries throughout the 1930s, alleviated only at the tragic price of re-vitalizing the economy, at the outbreak of the Second World War, in the service of war material production which sets its devastating pattern for the production of prosperity also after the war. Looking back on this period in Situation of the writer in 1947, Sartre describes its formative power in graphic terms:

From 1930 on, the world depression, the coming of Nazism, and the events in China opened our eyes. It seemed as if the ground were going to fall from under us, and suddenly, for us too, the great historical juggling began. The first years of the great world Peace suddenly had to be regarded as the years between wars. Each sign of compromise which we had greeted had to be seen as a threat. Each day we had lived revealed its true face; we had abandoned ourselves to it trustingly and it was leading us to a new war with secret rapidity, with a rigour hidden beneath its nonchalant airs. And our life as an individual which had seemed to depend upon our efforts, our virtues, and our faults, on our good and bad luck, on the good and bad will of a very small number of people, seemed governed down to its minutest details by obscure and collective forces, and its most private circumstances seemed to reflect the state of the whole world. All at once we felt ourselves abruptly situated. The detachment which our predecessors were so fond of practicing had become impossible. There was a collective adventure which was taking form in the future and which would be our adventure. . . . The secret of our gestures and our most intimate designs lay ahead of us in the catastrophe to which our name would be attached. History flowed in upon us; in everything we touched, in the air we breathed, in the page we read, in the one we wrote; in love itself we discovered, like a taste of history, so to speak, a bitter and ambiguous mixture of the absolute and the transitory.267

The experience of history can be bewildering if it is reflected in consciousness as a form of historical relativism. Similarly, the perception of the

136

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

collective forces which dominate a historical situation can be paralyzing if the individual is unable to define his own margin of action in relation to them. Sartre is extremely anxious to steer clear of both dangers. With respect to the first, the overriding interest of his quest is to find the absolute at the heart of relativity itself so as to be able to oppose it to moral relativism.268 And with regard to the power of the collective forces, his aim is to demonstrate the possibilitiesand the responsibilityof the individual to face up to mans agonies and sufferings in this world of collective adventure which he cannot really escape, no matter how hard he might try to through the strategies of bad faith. In his search for the integral, though not sovereign, individual Sartre wants to demonstrate that the man of his quest is totally free (responsible) and yet totally situated in a contingent world. How is this possible? Is such a view compatible with the prevailing conceptions of man? Sartres answer is an emphatic no, and he sets out to prove the validity of his own idea: this is in fact the most central theme of all his early works. We have already seen his objections to marxism. In addition, let us briefly refer to two other principal lines of approach from among those he criticizes: positivism and psychoanalysis. In the positivistic cult of the facts, Sartre identifies a basic structural defect: the absence of a proper concept of man which means that we get an aimless, almost totally blind accumulation of facts and no real theory. Thus: If, later on, there ought to be a definitive concept of manwhich itself is doubtfulthis concept is to be envisaged only as the crowning concept of a complete science, which means that it is postponed to infinity.269 The whole is disregarded and fragments usurp its place. And since the specificity of the human (man as a synthetic totality) does not guide the enquiry itself, hopes that it might emerge from the maze of fragmentary, mechanistic determinations, must be considered completely gratuitous. Sartres attitude to psychoanalysis is equally negative, althoughin contrast to his views on the varieties of positivismhe acknowledges that its problems are novel and important and therefore must be accounted for in his own alternative terms. The reason why he must reject the psychoanalytic theories is the same that lies behind the criticisms he voices in other directions: the radical inadmissibility of determinations prior or external to the self-determinations of consciousness. This is why the critique of psychoanalysis remains central with him, no matter how hard he triesin an intellectual climate highly favorable to psychoanalytic explanationsto give the maximum credit to Freud himself for focusing attention on an area of great importance. He sees clearly that what he is calling into question is the

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

137

principle itself of psychoanalytic explanation, for in psychoanalysis what is signified is entirely cut off from the signifying.270 To this approach he opposes his own dialectic conception of the relationship between signifying, signified, and signification:
If, then, it [consciousness] has a signification, it must contain this within itself as a structure of consciousness. This does not mean that the signification must be perfectly explicit. There are many possible degrees of condensation and of clarity. It only means that we should not interrogate the consciousness from outside, as one would study the remains of the fire or the encampment, but from within; that we should look onto it for the signification. The consciousness, if the cogito is to be possible, is itself the fact, and signification and what is signified . . . if symbolization is constitutive it is legitimate to see an immanent bond of comprehension between the symbolization and the symbol. Only, we must agree upon this, that consciousness constitutes itself by symbolization. In that case there is nothing behind it, and the relation between symbol, symbolized and symbolization is an infrastructural bond of consciousness. But if we go on to say that the consciousness is symbolizing under the causal compulsion of a transcendent factwhich is the repressed desirewe are falling back upon the theory previously indicated, which treats the relation of the signified to the signifying as a causal relation. The profound contradiction in all psychoanalysis is that it presents at the same time a bond of causality and a bond of understanding between the phenomena that it studies. These two types of relationship are incompatible.271

Significantly enough, the same line of reasoning is followed by Sartre in an interview more than three decades later, culminating in the rejection of the mythology of the unconscious constituting a set of rigorous mechanistic determinations . . . a causality . . . a mechanism.272 And no wonder. For too much would have to go if Sartre decided to significantly modify his views on these points. The fact is that he does not just reject the psychoanalytic principle of explanation for certain facts and problems but provides his own rival explanation. As we learn from Simone de Beauvoirs memoirs, the main concepts of his alternative to psychoanalysis were spelled out already in the early 1930s when:
Sartre worked out the notion of mauvaise foi [bad faith] which, according to him, embraced all those phenomena which other people attributed

138

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

to the unconscious mind. We set ourselves to expose this dishonesty in all its manifestations: semantic quibbling, false recollections, fugues, compensation fantasies, sublimations, and the rest. We rejoiced every time we unearthed a new loophole, another type of deception.273

A great deal more is built on such foundations later on, and mauvaise foi remains one of the central concepts in the whole of Sartres lifework, articulated in all its details in Being and Nothingness and used in many subsequent works. And the function envisaged by Sartre for his own existential psychoanalysis is radically different from that of traditional psychoanalysis. Again, it is important to bear in mind the role of morality in Sartrean philosophy as a whole in order to be able to understand and appreciate the function he assigns to existential psychoanalysis: the various tasks of the for-itself can be made the object of an existential psychoanalysis, for they all aim at producing the missing synthesis of consciousness and being in the form of value or self-cause. Thus existential psychoanalysis is moral ascription, for it releases to us the ethical meaning of various human projects.274 Clearly, no variety of Freudian theory could fulfill such functions. This is why traditional psychoanalysis and existential psychoanalysis remain worlds apart, and Sartre has to embark on the arduous task of writing a new treatise of the passions relying entirely on his own resources, taking for his centre of reference the factitious predicament of the existential individual. Socially, Sartres early works are conceived between two poles of negativity: on the one hand, the passionate condemnation of his own class and of the bourgeois order of society that goes with it, and the rejection of the idea of identifying himself with the struggle of the working class on the other. Simone de Beauvoirs recollections of an incident illustrates very well that the negation of the prevailing order by Sartre is not coupled with a positive involvement. Instead, he opts for the position of the self-oriented outsider, however much sympathy he might feel at times for the underdogs from a fairly remote distance. This is how Simone de Beauvoirs account goes:
The columns of the daily press were full of bankruptcies, scandals, and the suicides of businessmen and international financiers. The world was moving into a state of flux. Sartre often wondered whether we should not join those who were working for this revolution. I recall one conversation in particular, which took place on the terrasse of the big caf in Rouen, the Caf Victor, that looked out on the quais. Even in spheres where we were ideologically well-informed, to come up against some concrete fact still always had an

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

139

effect on us, and would give rise to copious subsequent discussions. This was what happened on this particular afternoon. A docker, decently dressed in his blue smock, sat down at a table next to ours: the manager ejected him. The incident did not teach us anything, but it illustrated the idea of class segregation with all the naivet of an Epinal print, and served as the point of departure of a far-reaching discussion. We got to asking ourselves whether it was enough for us to sympathize with the struggle being fought by the working classes: ought we not to join in it? . . . On this particular occasion we decided . . . that though the proletarian struggle was of concern to us, it was even so not our struggle; all that could be asked of us was that we should always speak out on its behalf in any argument.275

Thus, instead of a passionate identification with the struggle for a new society, we find a paternalistic intellectualism, confined to taking part in merely theoretical discussions and arguments. Naturally, this is not just a biographical detail that serves simply to add color to the background of Sartres development, but a major factor in the constitution of his philosophical system as a whole. The decision to be critical rather than constructive276 is a rather vague way of describing what is at stake here. For in reality it means that the criticism itselfwhich is devoid of a positive (constructive) frame of referenceis condemned to be extremely abstract and remote from the tangible social realities. The young Sartre takes up his stand in the no-mans-land of the self-oriented outsider, which carries far-reaching consequences for the articulation of his philosophy. Since his moral rebellion is voiced in a social vacuum, his criticism can only be manifested in the form of an abstract moral imperative that must remain latent and wedded to the categories of an existential ontology, as we have seen above. Similarly, since the idea of social-political commitment is rejected by Sartrealthough the concept of moral commitment is an integral part of his philosophy right from the early 1930sthe existential categories in which his views are spelled out in his original system tend to be ahistorical (for-itself, in-itself, vertigo of possibility, absolute flight, monstrous spontaneity, etc.), notwithstanding the experience of history which he describes retrospectively in 1947. And as far as the relations of domination and oppression are concerned (which, again, he condemns in the form of a moral ought), in his early works they are converted into the abstract existential-ontological antagonism between the for-itself and the other at one level, and into the conflicts of interpsychic (and indeed intra-psychic) relations at another, thus depriving them of their

140

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

socio-historical specificity. (Also, alienation and objectification tend to be fused with the help of variants of the category of reification, and such fusion produces the same sort of effect.) Finally, since the standpoint of Sartres early works is that of the negatively defined, self-oriented outsider who emphatically rejects the orientation of his own class without being able to adopt the perspective of its polar opposite, the subject of his philosophy cannot be a socio-historically specific and tangible collective subject but an existentialist fusion of particular individuality (the contingency and facticity of the existential individual) and abstract universality (consciousness as such in its impersonal spontaneity). Thus, Sartres search for the individual in his early works reveals in the spirit of the Kierkegaardian opposition to Hegel the absolute as the unsurpassable opaqueness of the lived experience,277 or in other words, as the irreducibility and the specificity of what is lived.278 What this quest produces is not the individualfor the real individual cannot be truly grasped except in his socio-historical specificity and universality, as the social individualbut individuality and particularity as such: the absolute at the heart of relativity itself, defined as the opaque irreducibility of the lived experience. (This is particularity directly raised to the level of the absolute, which procedure becomes the Sartrean version of universalizing the individual while insisting on irreducibility and nonuniversalizability.) Here, again, we can see the social determinants of this conception. For later Sartre has to admit that the unsurpassable opaqueness of lived experiencefor instance, sufferingvis--vis knowledge holds only to the degree that knowledge remains powerless to transform it;279 which means that the whole question of absolute irreducibility and unsurpassable opaqueness hinges on social praxis itself, of which knowledge and lived experience are integral dimensions and therefore cannot be abstractly-antinomously opposed to one another on the alleged ground of some fundamental ontology. Many things change significantly in the course of Sartres later development. The war years shatter the self-erected walls of his social vacuum, and the problem of commitmentnot only moral and literary-aesthetic but also social and politicalcomes to occupy a central place in his writings in the most varied contexts (from literary analyses to political polemics) and at all levels (from occasional remarks to systematic philosophical treatments). Naturally, the increasing social awareness carries with it a conscious effort to put into relief the political and the historical dimensions of his concerns, which calls for the modification of some fundamental early propositions and

S EA R CH F OR T HE INDIV ID UA L

141

categories. Inevitably, though, such an enterprisehowever passionately felt in the circumstances of tangible social crisesmust be carried out by Sartre in the framework of a philosophy whose structure has been constituted under very different conditions and with rather different preoccupations in mind. Thus he is forced to respond to the challenge of the dramatic sociohistorical developments (during the war and after) in terms of his philosophy as originally articulated during the 1930s, while restructuring it to the extent to which this is feasible internally. This of course is not possible without the constant manifestations of major tensions280 between the original structure and the new demands of which he becomes a passionate champion. That he is unable to resolve these tensions, is inherent in the antinomous structure of his original system. That he is unwilling to resolve them simply by discarding his antinomies is a measure of his stubborn integrity and of the depth of his commitment. The fact that a philosophical solution to the problems he had embraced in his original system is not forthcoming must be considered in conjunction with the other side of the coin. For keeping alive the unbearable tension of his antinomies is the fertile ground on which Sartre dramatically depictsand by no means only in the medium of the theatrethe world in which we all live, thus creating a lifework which is manifestly representative of our time.

This page intentionally left blank

5. Freedom and Passion: The World of B EING AND N OTHINGNESS


1.
F UN DAM E N TAL LY M AN IS TH E D ESIRE TO B E (565)281states a cryptic phrase

in Being and Nothingness. To understand it, we must realize that in the world of Being and Nothingness all the principal categories hinge on being, including the desire to do, which is reduced either to having (576) or to being (581). Furthermore, having itself is turned into being through possession which is said to be a magical relation: I am these objects which I have (591), for In possession I am my own foundation in so far as I exist in an In-itself (592). Thus when two years after writing Being and Nothingness Sartre asserts that existentialism defines man through action,282 and that existentialism is a morality of action and of commitment,283 we witness a significant shift of emphasis which opens up new possibilities of tangible social and political involvement in his postwar development. However, during the war years things remain more abstract in Sartres conceptual universe. Being and Nothingness is a monumental synthesis An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology, according to its subtitle which sets out from asserting the primacy of subjectivity and remains anchored to the psychological categories of Sartres early work. The abstractness of Being and Nothingness is the consequence of the compression of a great variety of

144

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

heterogeneous philosophical problems into the categories worked out on the basis of Sartres early inspiration in philosophical psychology. And when he later calls it the eidetics of bad faith, sharply contrasting its approach with the empirical study of our fidelities, and of the inhuman forces which pervert them,284 he provides a very apt characterization of the limits of this great work. For the notorious difficulties of comprehension are not so much a matter of inherent complexity as rather of the forbidding strangeness of the subjective key in which the work is composed, presenting a comprehensive synthesis of man and the world under its subjective aspects, and objectivity in the spirit of phenomenological realism appears massively transmuted into the categories of Sartrean existentialist subjectivity. Being and Nothingness is an ontology conceived from the standpoint of this subjectivity, and the experience of society is brought into play only to the extent to which it can provideoften splendidly graphicillustrations for the highly abstract world (not the empirical world but an ontological construct) in which human reality (subjectivity or individuality) is situated.
All this happens as if the For-itself had a Passion to lose itself in order that the affirmation world might come to be In-itself. . . . the world and the instrumental-thing, space and quantity, and universal time are all pure hypostatized nothingnesses . . . There is being because I am the negation of being, and worldliness, spatiality, quantity, instrumentality, temporalityall come into being only because I am the negation of being.(217)

All this may sound disturbingly subjective and remotely abstract. Nevertheless, the underlying intent is amply clear: to provide a forcefully coherent elucidation of everything in terms of the being of the human reality and the passion which animates it and makes its project intelligible. As we have seen in the preceding chapter, in 1934 Sartre credited Husserl with the great achievement of clearing the ground for a new treatise of the passions. Now he makes it clear why in his view Husserl himself could not embark on the realization of the project of writing the much needed new treatise of the passions. Because Husserl has reduced being to a series of meanings, the only connection which he has been able to establish between my being and that of the Other is a connection of knowledge. Therefore Husserl cannot escape solipsism any more than Kant could. (235) It goes without saying, to envisage a new treatise of the passions in terms of even the most sophisticated form of solipsism would be absurd.

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

145

Asserting the primacy of being must be the point of departure and the necessary ground of analysis on which such a study is feasible. Sartre therefore proposes an approach not just different from but diametrically opposed to Husserls. Instead of reducing being to meanings (knowledge), he explains knowledge and meanings in terms of being and its existential project, insisting that being is the self-evident irreducible and therefore any attempt at reducing it to something else, and thus trying to go beyond it is self-contradictory: for obviously it is impossible to advance further than being and we have reached the absolute limit when we have reached the project of being. (565) All that remains then is an elucidation of the project of beingthe same thing as to acquaint man with his passion (626)which in no way implies going beyond being or reducing it to something else. On the contrary, the task of elucidation amounts to the project of advancing towards being as it constitutes itself, and the understanding of the ontological structure of being is not a theoretical enterprise but an inherently practical one (the task of Practical Reason in Kantian terminology), involving the elaboration of thenever completedEthics and Existential Psychoanalysis. Sartrean ontology thus culminates in the latter, providing a foundation for them, but it is simultaneously also founded by its own Ethics and Existential Psychoanalysis, in that it cannot conceivably envisage any other foundation.

ONTOLOGY (Existential Anthorpology)

ETHICS

EXISTENTIAL PSYCHOANALYSIS

146

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

This conceptual structure can be summarily illustrated by stressing the close structural interrelationship and reciprocity between Sartrean ONTOLOGY (equated by Sartre also with EXISTENTIAL ANTHROPOLOGY) and ETHICS in its inseparability from EXISTENTIAL PSYCHOANALYSYS. Such a conceptual structure may appear to be circular, and in a particular sense certainly it is circular. However, the circularity involved is not some conceptual confusion or defect whose removal might improve Sartres philosophy. Removing it could be conceived only at the price of liquidating the essential characteristics of Sartrean existentialism which cannot be reduced to a neat, formally consistent but platitudinous epistemology, nor indeed to a Husserlian phenomenology envisaged as a rigorous science (eine strenge Wissenschaft) as the idea of a madman genius, but a mad idea none the less.285 For in Sartres philosophy we are directly concerned with man interrogating himself about his own project which he tries to hide from himself, with all the ambiguities, subterfuges, strategies of bad faith and circularities involved. This is why Sartrean phenomenological ontology must be conceived as an existential anthropology which is fused with practical moral and psychoanalytical concerns in this new treatise of the passions, and thus circularly it coils back into itself by founding itself precisely through the selfsame existential dimensions which it claims to found. Consequently, to try to eliminate existential anthropology from Sartres phenomenological ontology, in order to render it formally consistent, would be tantamount to the futility and absurdity of trying to square the circle. In any event, Sartre is not in the least embarrassed by this circularity but openly assumes it, as we shall see in numerous contexts, from Being and Nothingness to the dialectical circularity discussed in the Critique of Dialectical Reason. Assertions like: no dialectic for my relations with the other but rather a circle (363) abound in Being and Nothingness, and they constitute an essential part of its existential message. The circularity of the overall conceptual framework and the paralyzing stalemate suggestively conveyed through remarks like the one just quoted are inseparable from one another. The fundamental propositions of Sartrean existentialism are determined by this overall conceptual structure, and, conversely, the latter must assume the form it actually does as a result of the innermost nature of the fundamental existentialist propositions. Indeed Sartre would argue that given the absolute character of the existential circle the necessary assumption of contingency and facticity, which means that we can never get outside the circle (363) the existentialist circle is its only adequate philosophical equivalent or approximation.

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

147

We shall have to return to these problems on more than one occasion. Now the point to stress is that Being and Nothingness is truly intelligible only as a monumental sketch of the strikingly original outlines of the new treatise of the passions, structured around the apparently circular proposition that freedom is passion and passion is freedom. Thus in this work we get not simply a reconciliation of freedom and passion, after centuries of philosophical debate which insisted on the primacy of one or the other, at the expense of one or the other, but the passionate assertion of the essential identity of the two. Thus freedom is no longer conceived as purely transcendental, leaving the world of appearance and necessity locked into itself while claiming to supersede it transcendentally by postulating a separate world of essences and freedom (the world of the Ding an sichthing initself of Kant and his followers)it is the most fundamental dimension of human existence passionately striving to realize itself. And Sartre violates traditional philosophy not only as regards the formal characteristics of his work but even in the mode of development and style of presentation. Instead of providing a detached, objective description, followed by rigorously sustained proof (the ideal even of that madman genius, poor Husserl), he passionately asserts and reasserts his basic proposition concerning freedom and passion in so many different forms, and the existential proof emerges through the plausibility of its authenticity: another concept which refers back to freedom in an apparent circularity, by reasserting in its own way the basic identity of freedom and passion. If the fundamental project, the person, the free realization of human truth is everywhere in all desires (567), and if it is our freedom itself which constitutes the limits which it will subsequently encounter (482), as Sartre asserts, then all varieties of psychological determinism are a priori ruled out as being structurally incapable of even perceiving the problem, not to mention providing a viable solution for its difficulties. Exact and objective psychology must be dismissed as a solipsism (229) which treats the other as an object, denying its subject character in much the same way as we find in Sartres famous description of one of the fundamental strategies of bad faith. The same considerations apply to knowledge in general. The point of view of pure knowledge is contradictory; there is only the point of view of engaged knowledge. . . . an engaged upsurge in a determined point of view which one is. (308) Thus, knowledge is a dimension of being, and mistakes or misconceptions of knowledge must be made intelligible on the ground of the fundamental ontological structures, instead of being dissolved through conceptual manipulation: a solipsistic circularity

148

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

which assumes the separate existence and absolute legislative power of its owndetached, objective, exact, rigorous, unambiguous, etc. thought. As against all such approaches, Sartre insists on the necessary practical embeddedness of theoretical viewpoints. In his advocacy of an existential psychoanalysis he does not proceed from a theoretical refutation of psychological determinism (traditional psychoanalysis being only one of the manifold varieties of the latter) but from identifying the practical determinants which are uncritically projected in the theoretical image:
In each moment of reflection anguish is born as a structure of the reflective consciousness in so far as the latter considers consciousness as an object of reflection; but it still remains possible for me to maintain various types of conduct with respect to my own anguishin particular patterns of flight. Everything takes place as if our essential and immediate behavior with respect to anguish is flight. Psychological determinism, before being a theoretical conception, is first an attitude of excuse, or if you prefer, the basis of all attitudes of excuse. It is a reflective conduct with respect to anguish; it asserts that there are within us antagonistic forces whose type of existence is comparable to that of things, . . . endowing them with an inertia and externality is eminently reassuring because they constitute a permanent game of excuses. . . . But this determinism, a reflective defense against anguish, is not given as a reflective intuition. It avails nothing against the evidence of freedom; hence it is given as a faith to take refuge in, as the ideal end towards which we can flee to escape anguish. . . . Thus we flee from anguish by attempting to apprehend ourselves from without as an Other or as a thing. (4043)

As we can see, the reified images of psychological determinism are explained in terms of determinate practical attitudes emanating from the ontological structure of being which constitutes Sartres basic concern in this eidetics of bad faith. Such theoretical reifications of the human reality are both necessary, in so far as they arise out of the anguishing ontological structure, and not out of theory as such, and freely assumed, in that they can be practically opposed by alternative types of attitude and conduct and by their appropriate conceptualizations. And the necessary failure of these deterministic theories of psychological reifiction, which represent a capitulation to flight and excuses, calls for a radically new treatise of the passions which insists simultaneously on the inescapability of freedom (man is condemned to be free) and on the necessary situation

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

149

of this freedom in the contingency of human existence motivated by its ontological passion. (Empirical passion is said to be the symbolic expression of the fundamental ontological passion.) For all human existence is a passion, the famous self-interest being only one way freely chosen among others to realize this passion. (626)
2.

is consciously assumed and cultivated, rather than being considered a residue of conceptual imperfection which must be removed by means of appropriate analytical procedures, the use of metaphors is not meant simply to enliven the style of presentation. In Being and Nothingness metaphors appear with great frequency, and they are inextricably entangled with the philosophical message which cannot be conveyed in any other form. Many years later in an interview Sartre criticizes his own use of metaphors in Being and Nothingness, giving as an example the much quoted phrase: Man is a useless passion, which received hostile comments not really on account of its literary qualities, but because of its atheistic message according to which the passion of man is the reverse of that of Christ, for man loses himself as man in order that God may be born. But the idea of God is contradictory and we lose ourselves in vain. Man is a useless passion. (615) This is how Sartre argues his case in 1965:
If I forget myself for a moment and use a literary turn of phrase in a philosophical work I always feel slightly that I am pulling a fast one on my reader; it is a breach of trust. I once wrote the sentenceremembered because of its literary aspectlhomme est une passion inutile (Man is a useless passion). A case of breach of trust. I ought to have put that in strictly philosophical terms. In my Critique of Dialectical Reason I do not think I was guilty of breach of trust at all.287

I N A D IS C ORU S E IN W H ICH A MB IG UITY 286

To be sure, it is far from being the case that Sartre avoids in his later works the literary practices which he now condemns as a breach of trust, even if their extent is more limited in the Critique of Dialectical Reason than in Being and Nothingness. However, this is not at issue at this point where our concern is to show the role they play in articulating and authenticating the suggestive philosophical message of Sartres eidetics of bad faith. In any case, it is hard to accept not only that the example given by Sartre is a breach of trust, but also that the phrase in question could be translated

150

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

into strictly philosophical terms. For if the literary mode of expression is an essential condition of conveying the philosophical message (not to mention also subjectively authenticating it, which is very much the case with Being and Nothingness), then obviously it cannot be considered a breach of trust. One may then still legitimately challenge the problematical character of a particular philosophical discourse which needs the extensive use of metaphors for its articulation. In that case the whole discourse would be called into question, and not just some isolated phrases which could be translated into a less evocative form. But how could one put in strictly philosophical terms the undoubtedly striking phrase: Man is a useless passion? As we have seen already, so much hinges on references to passion as a fundamental ontological characteristic in this new treatise of the passions that any attempt at removing passion from the definition of the human reality would empty it of its central core around which everything else is structured.
Each human reality is at the same time a direct project to metamorphose its own For-itself into an In-itself-For-itself and a project of the appropriation of the world as a totality of being-in-itself, in the form of a fundamental quality. Every human reality is a passion in that it projects losing itself so as to found being and by the same stroke to constitute the In-itself which escapes contingency by being its own foundation, the Ens causa sui, which religion calls God. (615)

Take away passion from this discourse and it loses both its suggestive power and its existential meaning. On the other hand, if Sartres strictures apply to the adjective useless only, and not to passionwhich is hard to know, since he gives no indication of how to render the criticized phrase in strictly philosophical termsthen the self-criticism amounts to very little indeed, if anything at all, in that the message of a necessary failure (the literal meaning of ontologically frustrated useless passion) is in fact very effectively conveyed by the adjective he uses, without involving any breach of trust at all. Paradoxically, therefore, Sartres sweeping condemnation of the particular example in rather harsh terms is the expression of his reluctance to be critical of the philosophical discourse of Being and Nothingness as a whole, since the continuities of this discourse with his later thought, despite some significant differences, are far too weighty to enable him to embark on a far-reaching critical examination of this work. Self-criticism again appears as a retrospective should have been coupled with a positive self-assertion

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

151

claiming an exemplary solution of the problem in the Critique of Dialectical Reason, while in fact not only is the greater part of the categorial framework of Being and Nothingness retained (though, of course, complemented by a range of new categories) but even some particular arguments and examples from the early work reappear in new contexts in the later Critique, requiring a reference to the original context (not provided by Sartre himself) in order to acquire their full significance.288 The overpowering use of metaphors in Being and Nothingness is not simply a literary way of rendering with greater evocative power an abstract philosophical proposition. If it had been meant as such, it would have been a failure; for the characteristic of abstractness remains despite the graphic imagery, as we have mentioned before. Nor is it the consequence of an unavoidable dialectical complexity in terms of which Sartre emphatically defends the long involved sentences of his Critique of Dialectical Reason. The numerous metaphors of Being and Nothingness are not isolated examples of literary presentation: they constitute a coherent whole, and as such they are inextricably linked to the ambiguities of the conceptual framework itself. To understand and appreciate the nature and importance of these metaphors we must first focus attention on the underlying ambiguities in light of which the particular images of Sartres eidetics of bad faith reveal their necessity in the constitution of a coherent, powerful and highly specific philosophical discourse. A few examples should suffice to illustrate the connections we are concerned with. After asserting that my freedom eats away my freedom (480), Sartre goes on to discuss the relationship between the particular and the global:
. . . it is necessary to consult each mans history in order to get from it a particular idea with regard to each individual for-itself. Our particular projects, aimed at the realization in the world of a particular end, are united in the global project which we are. But precisely because we are wholly choice and act, these partial projects are not determined by the global project. They must themselves be choices; and a certain margin of contingency, of unpredictability, and of the absurd is allowed to each of them, although each project as it is projected is the specification of the global project on the occasion of particular elements in the situation and so is always understood in relation to the totality of my being-in-the-world. . . . freedom is the freedom of choosing but not the freedom of not choosing. Not to choose is, in fact, to choose not to choose. (48081)

152

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

The elements of this reasoning are most intricate, and they are made even more complicated by the fact that they are not always rendered conceptually explicit. Instead, metaphors are brought forward at some key points, and they are fully integrated into the development of the argument so that they can carry part of and thus support the whole of the existential message. It is the need to keep together a number of antinomous factorsresisting the temptation of an easy solution by paying just lip service to one side of the antinomy while dogmatically asserting the validity of the other; say freedom, at the expense of contingencywhich makes the task of putting everything in strictly philosophical terms not merely difficult but well-nigh impossible. If I am wholly choice (wholly freedom), then the particular elements of a situation cannot possibly amount to a determinationwhich would sharply contradict my absolute freedom and the corresponding absolute responsibilitybut only to an occasion on which my freedom must freely determine itself. (Must, in that even if it does not, it actually does, in the mode of choosing not to choose.) Consequently, that strange hybrid of a conceptual metaphor (or metaphorical concept): the Sartrean occasion289 is born which keeps perilously balanced on a razors edge the antinomous requirements of freedom and contingency-facticity, without suppressing either side in favor of the other. Furthermore, since the free project is fundamental, for it is my being (479), it must have some significant characteristics which, however, cannot possibly amount to a definite character, nature, or determining determination, since that would, again, undermine my freedom. Similarly, every one of my choices must be freely chosen from an infinite range of possible choices, and at the same time they must be totally unjustifiable in that justifiability would impose itself as a kind of moral determination which preempts and destroys my freedom and thus reveals itself as existentially repugnant, no matter how moral. If, therefore, the concept of my original, initial, fundamental and global290 project is to be meaningful at all, the global project must have some significant effect on my particular choices without, however, determining them in the slightest. Thus another strange concept is brought into play: the specification of the global project in the form of the particular projects on the occasion of the particular elements of my situation, which in no circumstances should be interpreted as a determination of my choices either by my global project (my being) or by the (social, political, psychological, and other) forces at work in my situation. Situation, too, should not be thought of as a set of objective conditions which determine my project, but rather as the concrete embodiment of my project, and thus as something created

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

153

by me on the occasion and through the unification of certain elements which I happen to encounter in my contingency and facticity. As in Kants philosophy, the determinations of the empirical world cannot condition or contradict my freedom which retains, despite all evidence to the contrary, its absolute power. (Man cannot be sometimes slave and sometimes free; he is wholly and forever free or he is not free at all (441)as Sartre puts it.) But in contrast to Kants philosophy, freedom can be contradicted by itself, and not even just a little, but wholly and absolutely, and still without invalidating in the least the categorical absoluteness of freedom. If this sounds absurd, it does not really matter in a strictly philosophical sense. Sartre takes up the gauntlet and defiantly calls it absurd, with the proviso that this is not because a philosophical thought fails to master its formal rules, but as a matter of the ontological conditions of the human reality:
Since freedom is a being-without-support and without-a-springboard, the project to be must be constantly renewed. I choose myself perpetually and can never be merely by virtue of having-been-chosen; otherwise I should fall into the pure and simple existence of the in-itself. The necessity of perpetually choosing myself is one with the pursued-pursuits which I am. But precisely because here we are dealing with a choice, this choice as it is made indicates in general other choices as possibles. The possibility of these other choices is neither made explicit nor posited, but it is lived in the feeling of unjustifiability; and it is this which is expressed by the fact of the absurdity of my choice and consequently of my being. Thus my freedom eats away my freedom. (480)

As we can see, freedom is not limited by something external to it, and yet it is totally nihilated. The absolute validity of freedom is categorically asserted, and yet, the conditions of its realization (negation) in conformity with my contingency and facticity are fully respected, without prejudging in the least whether the particular manifestations of my freedom as unified under my unique global project will be marked by authenticity or by bad faith. The Kantian problematic which insists on the absoluteness of freedom is fully retained, and yet it is totally transformed in that it is no longer confined to a transcendental world. The antinomous elements of the Sartrean conception are held together, even if in a most uneasy way, and the existential concept of freedom ceases to be a sublime transcendental principle. It assumes a tangible shape, indeed a body, and appears voraciously engaged in a very un-Socratic function which should scandalize any self-respecting

154

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

utilitarian liberal. We catch a glimpse of it: eating. And, horror of horrors, my freedom eats away my freedom, for which I can only blame myself. The metaphor just like the others mentioned before is neither a literary device for rendering things more vivid, nor is it translatable. It is an essential part of the specific philosophical structure which displays a number of very different levels, including the unsaid and the figuratively implied as well as the metaphorically condensed, in addition to the strict philosophical terms of an explicit conceptual progression. To be sure, one may very well question the fundamental ambiguity of Sartres conception of freedom in Being and Nothingness, with its antinomous structure of categorical assertion and simultaneous negation. What must, however, be beyond dispute is that given theno matter how problematicalelements of this conception, my freedom eats away my freedom represents an essential constituent as well as a most fitting summing up of it. The same ambiguity is in evidence in Sartres depiction of the relationship between the For-itself and the In-itself as a double play of unilateral oppositions devoid of reciprocity, insisting on the affinity of the For-itself with the ambiguous realities of Kierkegaard (94), so as to be able to assert that Value is everywhere and nowhere; at the heart of the nihilating reflection-reflecting, it is present and out of reach, and it is simply lived as the concrete meaning of that lack which makes my present being. (95) Given the antinomous conception of the relationship between the For-itself and the In-itself as unilateral (rigid, non-dialectical) oppositions, one needs the metaphor of double play to bring them together at all. And since we are confronted with a relationship totally devoid of reciprocity, the envisaged synthesis of In-itself-For-itself or value can only be conceived as an unrealizable totality (94). Thus the fundamental ambiguity is unavoidable in view of the antinomous structure. The impossible synthesis of unilateral oppositions can only exist as an unrealizable totality, and as such it must reside everywhere and nowhere: it must be simultaneously at hand, immediately present, and totally out of reach. The sense we encounter here is a strictly subjective sense. It amounts to saying that even though Value (the In-itself-For-itself ) is an unrealizable totality, the fundamental project of the human reality (my own being, with all its absurdity) is intelligible as a passionate striving for the realization of the unrealizable, impossible synthesis. The sets of metaphorical concepts employed by Sartre do not change the antinomous relations; nor are they meant to. They cannot create the movement of reciprocity leading to synthesis on a ground for which a priori antagonism is predicated forever. All they can do and are meant to do is

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

155

to provide a subjective authentication for the striving of my human reality toward the impossible synthesis of an unrealizable totality. In the absence of such an authentication the discourse about authenticity would become totally vacuous and Sartres eidetics of bad faith would undermine and destroy itself. Thus the metaphors are both necessary and untranslatable. For given the elements of this conception, only a subjective authentication is feasible,291 which, however, cannot be produced in strictly philosophical terms. At the same time the double play of unilateral oppositionsarguably a contradiction in terms in strict philosophical termseffectively and legitimately provides just the kind of movement which keeps the antinomies together and holds them apart while subjectively authenticating the possibilities of individual choice against all odds: very much in the spirit of Sartres existential discourse as articulated in Being and Nothingness. Similarly, the relationship between the For-itself and being is described as an extreme paradox: the For-itself is immediate presence to being, and yet at the same time it slips in as an infinite distance between itself and being (218). The coincidence of immediate presence and infinite distance cannot be conceptualized in strictly philosophical terms. It must be established through the vivid imagery of the For-itself turned into infinite distance slipping in between itself and being. This particular conceptual edifice is extremely fragile: it would collapse even under the most delicate touch of a strict philosophical examination. The perilously unstable conceptual elements (the For-itself which is one with immediate presence but at the same time it slips in between itself and being as an infinite distance) are supported by the imagery which does not reconcile the antinomous constituents conceptually (that would be impossible) but glues them together figuratively. In other words, the discourse functions by inventing a graphic imagery whose purpose is the subjectively authenticated unification of the elements of another impossible unification: that is, the figurative-evocative synthesis of the antinomous terms which at the discursive level are deliberately kept apart. The paradoxical unification-separation and the fundamental ambiguity corresponding to it again assert themselves as inherently necessary to the existentialist message. Having designated value as an unrealizable totality in virtue of its being the impossible unification of the In-itself-For-itselfan unrealizable totality which we nevertheless must strive for, as we have seenthe being of value which we must encounter (and indeed we must encounter it, otherwise it would be totally devoid of existential plausibility and subjective authentication) can only be a phantom-being which surrounds and penetrates the

156

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

For-itself through and through (203). (Note even the way in which the expression through and through is superadded in order to intensify the evocative power of the surrounding and penetrating phantom-being.) In an axiological framework like this the realization of the aims we set ourselves is, yet again, depicted as an impossible unification by definition, and it is compared to the predicament of an ass trying to reach a carrot tied, hopelessly beyond its reach, to the shaft of the cart he is pulling:
Thus we run after a possible which our very running causes to appear, which is nothing but our running itself, and which thereby is by definition out of reach. We run toward ourselves and we aredue to this very fact the being which cannot be reunited with itself. In one sense the running is void of meaning since the goal is never given but invented and projected proportionately as we run toward it. In another sense we cannot refuse to it that meaning which it rejects since in spite of everything possibility is the meaning of the For-itself. Thus there is and there is not a meaning in the flight. (2023)

The imagery is very suggestive and its function is the same as before: the simultaneous assertion of immediate vicinity and unreachable distance sustains the impossible unification of the human reality with its being. In the spirit of existentialism, just as my being must be constantly recreated through the perpetual renewal of the project which it is, the goal of my pursuitsince I am pursued-pursuitscan never be given in that its givenness would act as a determinism and undermine my freedom. From this negative determination of the existentialist position vis--vis determinism arises the strange imagery of running toward ourselves, pursuing the goal of the impossible unification of ourselves with our being, which is by definition out of reach. What else could such a pursuit be if not meaningless meaning and meaningful meaninglessness? And since the goal must forever remain out of reach, authenticity must reside in the running itself which proportionately invents and projects its goal without ever making it. (This is why all human activities are equivalent . . . and all are doomed to failure. Thus it amounts to the same thing whether one gets drunk alone or is a leader of nations. (627) What counts is the running itselftowards ourselveswhich we invent proportionately as we run toward it, namely toward ourselves.) Again, the discourse would be thoroughly incoherent in strictly philosophical terms. For how does one run toward oneself, strictly speaking? (The image of the ass and the carrot is a very bad example. It does not

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

157

convey at all Sartres meaning as it emerges from the lines that immediately follow it. For in the asss case the goal is in fact given in the carrot, and the ass would not be an ass enough to go on forever as a pursued-pursuitpursuing an unreachable carrot.) In the spirit of Sartres existentialism, the antinomous elements must be firmly kept apart at the discursive level. And yet, this must be accomplished without allowing them to be represented as antagonistic forces within us whose type of existence is comparable to that of things. (40) The possibility of an existential mastery over them must be demonstrated, if the existentialist conception of freedom is to mean anything at all. But given the role of contingency and facticity in the same conception, the power of freedom in reaching its unreachable goal of the impossible unification can only be demonstrated in the form of a subjective authentication, which is suggestively accomplished by complementing the discursive level with a metaphorical level in such a way that the two levels are not developed side by sidethat would amount to no more than the introduction of conceptually superfluous literary embellishmentsbut become fully integrated. The remarkable mass-appeal of Sartres existentialism (to the point of becoming a cult which dominated the cafs of the Quartier Latin in Paris in the immediate postwar years), despite the forbidding abstractness and intense ambiguity of its conceptual framework as a whole, is inseparable from this characteristic of total integration (fusion) of the metaphorical and discursive levels in Being and Nothingness. The last example which we can afford to quote in this limited space concerns the concepts of causality, motion and time. In a conceptual framework in which freedom and choice, project and goal, situation and being are defined in the form we have seen, the concepts of causality, motion and time must equally be defined in such a way that the existentialist discourse is not disrupted but, on the contrary, intensified. The language of determinism is emphatically rejected, and we get a definition of causality as
the apprehension of the appeared, as being already there in its own nothingness so as to prepare its apparition. (208)

Similarly,
Motion has no more of being; it is the least-being of a being which can neither arrive nor be abolished nor wholly be. Motion is the upsurge of the exteriority of indifference at the very heart of the In-itself. This pure vacillation of being is a contingent venture of being. (213)

158

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

And from this point it is only one step to say that


universal time is revealed as present vacillation; already in the past it is no longer anything but an evanescent line, like the wake of a ship which fades away; in the future it is not at all, for it is unable to be its own project. It is like the steady progression of a lizard on the wall. Moreover its being has the inapprehensible ambiguity of the instant, for one could not say either that it is or that it is not. (213)

The fundamental ambiguity of is and is not, of everywhere and nowhere, of immediate presence and infinite distance, of meaning and meaninglessness, and so on, is central to the existential message. This ambiguity, in all its particular manifestations, is the existential ambiguity of freedom and contingency: of the absoluteness of freedom and the iron necessity of its embodiment in the concrete situation of the human reality. Keeping the anguishing authenticity of the existentialist discourse diametrically opposed to determinism and its bad faith while acknowledging the full weight of contingency and facticity, means an immensely difficult balancing act on a high wire, with the constant danger of precipitating, split into two, on the side of mechanical determinism with one half, and of pure indeterminacy with the other. To rescue causality, temporality, and motion from the reified objectivity of mechanical determinism without allowing them to disintegrate in the vacuous discourse of indeterminacy Sartre needs not only the strange imagery of a something-nothing which preparesnot determinesits apparition, but also a whole range of metaphors and imagesfrom pure vacillation and present vacillation to the evanescent line of a ship which fades away and to the steady progression of a lizard on the wallso that the arduous balancing act can be maintained. The pressures of sustaining the existentialist discourse through this balancing act, which uses the metaphorical level to join together in a most unstable union elements of strict determination and absolute indeterminacy, produce a manipulation of concepts which may appear sheer sophistry if read in a purely discursive sense, separated from the total context. We have seen the telling description of the various manifestations of the global project as its specification, so as to guard against the possibility of a deterministic reading. Similarly, in our quotation of a moment ago, nothingness is already there before it appears in order to prepare292 its apparition, leaving the meaning of the term prepare vaguely undefined in function of the balancing requirements. But perhaps the most striking example is to be

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

159

found in the context of a definition of the relationship between past and facticity. These two terms, insists Sartre, indicate one and the same thing:
The Past, in fact, like Facticity, is the invulnerable contingency of the Initself which I have to be without any possibility of not being it. It is the inevitability of the necessity of fact, not by virtue of necessity but by virtue of fact. It is the being of fact, which cannot determine the content of my motivations but which paralyses them with its contingency because they can neither suppress it nor change it. (118)

It is a sour consolation that the inevitability which permeates our being in the mode of necessity of fact does so not by virtue of necessity but by virtue of fact, and this kind of differentiation, considered in strictly philosophical terms, appears to be nothing but hair-splitting sophistry. The same goes for the assertion that this curious necessity of fact which imposes itself as inevitability does not ipso facto also determine our motivations but only paralyses them. And yet things appear in different light if we insert these propositions into Sartres discourse as a whole, instead of examining them in isolation. For Sartre draws a firm line of demarcation between motivation and determination, which in turn carries with it the necessity of a radical redefinition of all the interrelated concepts in the same spirit, including causality, temporality, motion, and indeed necessity and inevitability inasmuch as they are admissible into the framework of the existentialist discourse. But since the innermost structure of this discourse is starkly antinomous, there remains in it an immense tension through and through which tends to split it apart, despite all efforts of conceptual manipulation and metaphorical unification. It is this tension which bursts out into the open as an apparent sophistry in those contexts in which the naked discursiveness still predominates: before, that is, Sartre succeeds in complementing the discursive level of his discourse with the metaphorical level, thus producing the only feasible existentialist unification of the antinomous elements in the form of a subjective authentication. This is what we can witness in the example just quoted. The existentialist antinomy sternly asserts itself immediately after the somewhat baffling talk about the necessity of fact and the non-determining paralysis of motivations, making them intelligible in strictly discursive terms when Sartre admits that Between past and present there is an absolute heterogeneity. (119) But things cannot be left at that, nor are they intended to be, as evidenced by the strange conceptual manipulation of inevitability and

160

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

free motivation which anticipatesor, rather, postulatessome sort of a synthesis, even if it cannot accomplish its aim. And, of course, a conceptual unification of absolute heterogeneity in strictly philosophical terms would be a monstrous contradiction in terms. Yet it must be accomplished somehow for the sake of the existentialist message. Thus we find on the other side of the brutally open conceptual dividethe explicit admission of an absolute heterogeneitya most remarkable homogenization of this heterogeneity, accomplished through the use of a graphic imagery. We witness a presentification of the past (that is, its transformation into some sort of a lived present)which could not conceivably work on a strictly discursive leveland the assertion of its evanescent value, with an appeal to memory as a framework of subjective authentication. We are presented with a beautiful description which successfully buries the existentialist antinomy deep below the surface (where it remains until it is bound to erupt again in some other context) and we are left with the impression of a unification:
. . . memory presents to us the being which we were, accompanied by a plenitude of being which confers on it a sort of poetry. That grief which we hadalthough fixed in the pastdoes not cease to present the meaning of a For-itself, and yet it exists in itself with the silent fixity of the grief of another, the grief of a statue. (119)

There is no attempt to pretend that the antinomy of absolute heterogeneity no longer exists. All that happens is that it is made existentially bearable through the poetic power of memory which turns the past into some sort of a present and confers upon it a plenitude of being while also retaining its past character in the silent fixity of a statue. The act of balancing is successfully accomplished without distorting or falsifying its own terms of reference, thanks to the fact that the impossible unification of absolute heterogeneity is confined to the subjective plane. There it produces an existentialist authentication of its categorical rejection of the past as a determinism with an appeal to the experience of lived memory: a procedure which, again, leaves the question entirely open whether we constitute the plenitude of being of our past authentically or in bad faith. Sartres existentialism needs no more than an indication (proof would be far too strong a term) of the possibility of authenticity vis--vis the absolute contingency of the past, and this is preciselyno less, no morewhat it succeeds in producing through the full integration of the discursive and metaphorical levels. For given the inherently antinomous structure of Sartres discourse, (a) the only

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

161

way it can produce the indication of a possible authenticity is the massive use of metaphorical imagery; and (b) even through the most extensive use of such imagery it can only produce the indication of a mere possibility, followed by frequent assertions of doom and necessary failure, as we have seen above. Thus the occasional footnotes about the possibility of an ethics of deliverance which should follow a somewhat mysterious radical conversion (412) must be taken with a mountain-size pinch of salt. To squeeze a coherent ethics of deliverance and salvation out of the category of mere possibility forebodingly resembles the Sartrean imperative of an impossible unification. If later the author of the Critique of Dialectical Reason is less dependent on metaphorical imagery than in Being and Nothingness, this is partly because he is less orientated toward abstract possibility than before (in that he gives a more positive hearing to the categories of need, necessity and determination) and partly because he tries to introduce the category of mediation into the discourse of antinomous oppositions. However, the examination of the precise character of such changes and of the extent to which they may be considered successful must be left to Part Three.293 In Being and Nothingness the antinomous conceptual structure remains in evidence from beginning to end, determining the constant recurrence of ambiguities and metaphors. These three characteristicsantinomies, ambiguities and metaphorsare thus inextricably linked together as structural characteristics of Sartres existentialist discourse on freedom and contingency. Since the unstable balance that characterizes the existentialist message must be invented and constantly recreated in the form of a coherent set of concepts, and since the metaphorical level plays an essential part in the production of the unique coherence which emerges through the radical transformation of the deterministic language of everydayness in each and every particular context, we encounter the ubiquitousness of the metaphorical imagery as an ongoing process. The suggestiveness of this imagery cannot be properly appreciated simply in terms of the graphic qualities of the particular imageslike the play-acting waiter in the caf, quoted everywhere taken in isolation,294 but goes much deeper. Its intensity is cumulative and arises partly from the ongoing articulation of a coherent system of interlinked images, constituted not entirely unlike a set of musical variations on some fundamental existentialist themes whereby the particular item is always incomparably richer in conjunction with the set as a whole than by itself. But the intensity goes even beyond the remarkable structural coherence of the metaphorical level as a whole. It is also due to the vitally important function which the metaphorical imagery fulfills, through the intermediary of its

162

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

particular images and concept-metaphors, in the constitution of Sartres existentialist discourse. In other words, the almost hypnotic intensity of this imagery is just as much conceptual as it is representational. Thus, when Sartre asserts that he should have written Being and Nothingness in a way which would have avoided what he now calls a breach of trust, he does not realize295 that he could not have done so. And all the better for that. For had he succeeded in conforming to his retrospective ideal, we would have been deprived of one of the most original and representative philosophical works of the twentieth century.

3.
T H E WAY IN W HIC H T H E VA RIO US existentialist themes are developed in Being and Nothingness might be termed kaleidoscopic, in the sense that a conceptual framework made of remarkably few elements is articulated in detail through a virtually endless number of particular examples and descriptive specifications. The conceptual framework itself might seem very simple at first sight, in view of the extremely limited number of basic categories. However, a closer look reveals some forbidding complications at all levels. For a start, the constantly recurring categories are arranged as antinomous pairs (Being/Nothingness, In-itself/For-itself, Self/Other, Freedom/Contingency, Possibility/Necessity, Authenticity/Bad Faith, and the like), and their interrelationship is conceived in the form of the unilateral oppositions of absolute heterogeneity, as we have seen. A further complication is that the contrast of such unilateral oppositions does not constitute a movement: rather, it represents the picture of a paralyzing stalemate and therefore any movement we encounter must be introduced from outside, as it were. But, of course, there can be nothing outside the fundamental structural outlines of a synthesizing philosophical conception. If a particular philosophical totalization conceives the world as a paralyzing stalemate, the movement that can be accommodated within the framework of such a totalization must be a rather problematical one. And, indeed, the kaleidoscopic development of themes, as we shall see in a moment, has the function of creating this peculiar movement in Being and Nothingness. We are presented with an endless succession of ingenious transformations and permutations, both conceptual and metaphorical, whereby illustrative instances taken from everyday life unfold Sartres conception of the basic ontological structures.

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

163

The pattern of this development is most revealing. For the various instances of everyday life, and the corresponding common-sense use of language, are described, moulded, and manipulated by Sartresometimes to the point that he himself has to admit that they are forced296until the full correspondence of the empirical instances to the fundamental ontological structures can be asserted. Thus the movement of kaleidoscopic particularization and exemplification cannot introduce any dynamism into the underlying static structures but invariably culminates in the stark reassertion of an all-pervasive paralysis. The conceptual framework of unilateral oppositions sharply delineates the character of the superadded movement which must disappear abruptly the very moment it helps to bring into relief the essential identity of the particular existents with the underlying ontological structures. The movement of particularization is strictly in the service of, and indeed subordinated to, asserting and reiterating the primary message of the overall conception. It is therefore a total misconception of the nature of Being and Nothingness to speak in terms of high praise about Sartres descriptive talent while making dismissive remarks about his theoretical conception and philosophical rigour. These two dimensions not only stand or fall together but the overall philosophical conception unquestionably constitutes the bergreifendes Moment297 in relation to descriptive detail and graphic particularization. Undoubtedly, Sartres description of Pierres absence from the caf is a most impressive piece of writing; but only in terms of the total set of relations as specified by Sartre. Indeed, it is completely pointless, and perhaps even meaningless, without the overall ontological conception in which nothingness and lack assume a determinate, multi-faceted, and most unusual meaning in terms of which Pierres tangible absence can and must be read. Sartres great preference for writing philosophy, which is by no means surprising in view of the incomparable ease with which he produces monumental works of philosophy, is understandable precisely in relation to a talent which embarks on the laborious process of drafting the work from the premises of a most firmly laid down (some might say: rigidly preconceived) overall conception as the dominant feature of the whole enterprise. The synthesis is there right from the beginning in the original intuition of the overall conceptual framework, and the process of writing consists in the detailed articulation of the basic intuition under extremely close control at every stage. The great ease of writing arises from the fact that the overall direction of development is unhesitatingly anticipated from the first moment, and thus the new treatise of the passions writes itself, so to speak, much as it is described by Sartre in his Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions:

164

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

The words that I am writing . . . are exigent. It is the precise manner in which I grasp them in the course of my creative activity that makes them what they are: they are potentialities that have to be realized. . . . I simply feel the traction they exert; I feel their exigence objectively. I see them realizing themselves and, at the same time, demanding further realization. . . . the exigence of the words that I am tracing is directly present, weighty and felt. They impel and direct my hand. But not as though little demons, alive and active, were driving and guiding it in fact: this is a passive exigence.298

The curious concept of a passive exigence becomes meaningful in fact with reference to the overall design. Sartre knows the words in advance as they are about to realize themselves because the overall design firmly guides his hand with its passive exigence. For even if the minute details and particular images obviously cannot be known in advance, the precise direction of the development and the specific character or type of the admissible imagery is peremptorily anticipated in the original intuition of the basic outlines and of the categorial framework of an enterprise which consciously undertakes the elaboration of a new treatise of the passions on a premise asserting the fundamental identity of freedom and passion. This is very different indeed from the situation when Sartre rightly castigates his own failed play, Morts sans spulture (Unburied Dead), as a play without surprise,299 in that the destiny of the characters is absolutely defined in advance. Such a procedure may be totally inadmissible in the medium of the drama, but the absence of surprises does not constitute a drawback in the development of a philosophical conception in which the relationship between the parts and the whole is justifiably ruled by necessity, even in Sartres existentialism.300 And inasmuch as the whole enterprise is conducted in the spirit that even the apparently most insignificant gestures are meaningful manifestations of the human reality in its entiretyhence the definition of the task of philosophy as the hermeneutic of existence301 already in the Sketch for a Theory of the Emotionsthe interpretative approach in relation to the analysis or description of any particular situation is automatically given and unceremoniously imposed on whatever detail or illustrative example Sartre happens to mention, from food to mountain-climbing or ice-skating, leaving no room whatsoever for surprises as to the ontological meaning which the particular instances will be allowed to disclose.302 There is something quasi-mechanical in this pattern of closely controlled interpretative development which never tires of reiterating the underlying elementary ontological structures on the occasion of each and every

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

165

particular instance. The extreme unevenness of Being and Nothingness a characterization applicable, mutatis mutandis, also to Sartres other philosophical ventures of equally or even more massive proportions, from Saint Genet to the Critique of Dialectical Reason and to the unfinished trilogy on Flaubert is a necessary consequence of this kaleidoscopic pattern of development. For the immensely ingenious overall structurethe invention of the kaleidoscope itself which in turn produces an inexhaustible variety of complex images through the interplay of a few simple elementsmay just as easily yield some splendidly impressive and suggestive pictures as some tediously repetitive permutations. The following example gives a good idea of what is involved in the latter:
The Present could not pass except by becoming the before for a For-itself which constitutes itself as the after of that Present. There is the only one phenomenon: the upsurge of a new Present which is making-past the Present which it was, and the Making-Past of a Present involving the appearance of a For-itself for which this Present is going to become Past. The phenomenon of temporal becoming is a global modification since a Past which would be the Past of nothing would no longer be a Past and since a present must be necessarily the Present of this Past. This metamorphosis, moreover, affects not only the pure Present; the former Past and Future are equally affected. The Past of the Present which has undergone the modification of Pastness, becomes the Past of a Pastor a Pluperfect. So far as the Pluperfect is concerned, the heterogeneity of the Present and the Past is now suddenly suppressed since what made the Present distinct as such from the Past has now become Past. In the course of the metamorphosis the Present remains the Present of this Past, but it becomes the past Present of this Past. That means first that this present is homogeneous with the series of the Past which extends from it all the way back to its birth, second that this present is no longer its Past in the form of having to be it but in the mode of having had to be it. The connection between Past and Pluperfect is a connection which is in the mode of the In-itself, and it appears on the foundation of the present For-itself. It is this which holds the series of the past and pluperfect welded into a single block. . . . Future and past Present are solidified in the In-itself on the foundation of my Present. Thus the Future in the course of the temporal process, passes to the In-itself without ever losing its character as Future. In so far as it is not achieved by the Present, it becomes simply a given Future. When it is achieved, it is affected with the quality of ideality; but this ideality is ideality in-itself, for it presents itself as a given lack of

166

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

a given past and not as the lacking which a present For-itself has to be in the mode of not being. When the future is surpassed, it remains forever on the margin of the series of Pasts as a former futurea former Future of a particular Past becomes Pluperfect, an ideal given Future as co-present to a Present become past. (1445)

And so it goes on, and on, with bewildering tortuosity and repetitiveness. If there can be in philosophy a real breach of trust in Sartres sense of pulling a fast one on the reader, certainly this is it. We might even think that he is here only pulling the readers leg, if we did not actually know that Sartre is always very serious about everything he writes. The trouble with passages like this is that they bring into play the mechanism of verbal transformations and content themselves with going round and round in circles. If we ask ourselves at the end of the verbal transformations how far we advanced with the problem, the sobering answer is: not at all. This is so strongly the case here that a mere four lines after our heavy quotation Sartre is led to declare that it would almost be correct to reverse our terms in order to find the truth. And why not? We would still be going round in circles, even if in the other direction. This is in fact what we are compelled to do by Sartre for two more pages, at which point he admits that We find ourselves once more, it seems, at our point of departure. (147) And since in this particular context Sartre has now exhausted the possibilities of abstract conceptual permutations, backwards and forwards, we are presented with another twist as the solution in the sentence that immediately follows: But the truth is that there is no problem. Perhaps so. But if so, what was all the fuss about? And here is the answer: If we believe that we have met one [problem], this is because in spite of our efforts to think of the For-itself as really For-itself, we have not been able to prevent ourselves from fixing it in the In-itself. (147) It is good to know that while we were being taken for a ride Sartre was our sincere companion and shared our predicament. This knowledge, however, does not change the disconcerting fact itself, namely that after our long and tortuous journey of verbal selfindulgence we managed to get exactly nowhere. And yet in a sense it is fortunate that Sartre did not edit out these passages of inconclusive verbosity. For they help to identify the tension involved and the reasons why even Sartres incomparable dexterity of conceptual manipulation and linguistic transformation cannot succeed in advancing the problem. If we re-read carefully our quotationand we must do so several times in order to be able to acquire some perspective over

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

167

its captivating mazewe find that it takes us nowhere because it merely reasserts in their naked abstractness the basic conceptual imperatives of Sartres categorial framework as a whole in the context of temporality, without any attempt at a necessary mediation. We know right from the beginning that the fundamental relationship between the For-itself and the In-itself is conceived in such terms that it has inescapable implications for the various dimensions of temporality, just as much as for everything else. (For instance, the absolute heterogeneity between past and present is the necessary concomitant of this fundamental relationship.) However, such implications must be substantiated through particularization and specification, in accordance with the precise character of the existential context in question, otherwise the philosophical enterprise which aims at demonstrating the essential identity of the empirical manifestations of existence with the underlying ontological structures fails to reach its object, and thus fails to indicate the possibility of an authentic existentialist choice in the spirit of the programmatic hermeneutic of existence. In our quotation, regrettably, we witness the unfolding of such a failure. The original implications are spelled out as abstract imperatives and are reiterated again and again as such. We catch a glimpse of the necessary heterogeneity of past and present, followed by a sudden hint of homogeneity. The latter though, in sharp contrast to our earlier quote which tackled the same problem, is not demonstrated through particularization and subjective authentication. It is merely asserted as an abstract structural requirement (the heterogeneity of the Present and the Past is now suddenly suppressed) and since there is nothing to sustain it, it must be immediately taken back (the connection between Past and Pluperfect is a connection which is in the mode of the In-itself ). Furthermore, since we witness the manifestation of contradictory imperativesthe preservation of heterogeneity just as much as its suppressionthe two are abstractly brought together in yet another unsustained declaration according to which the connection between Past and Pluperfect which is in the mode of the In-itself appears on the foundation of the present For-itself. And the failure is significantly in evidence also at the metaphorical level. For the metaphor of welded into a single block is not integrated into the discourse butagain, in sharp contrast to our earlier quotesit is merely appended to the tail-end of it as a decorative image which wildly overstates what it asserts, thus revealing just as much the authors strongly felt need for the reconciliation of the antinomous tensions as his inability to bring them together in other than abstractly imperatival form. The same considerations apply to the rest of our long quotation, and

168

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

therefore they need not detain us any longer. What it all adds up to in the end is that in the example we have just seen we are presented not with an existential demonstration of a significant correspondence between the temporal dimension of existence and some fundamental ontological structures but with the singularly uninstructive restatement of what we knew from the very beginning, namely that the For-itself is radically different from the In-itself, and therefore one should not try to fix the For-itself in the In-itself. The contrast could not be greater with our next example, which displays at its best Sartres legendary power to bring to life as a tangible existential reality even the most abstract philosophical connections. Here Sartres analysis sets out from defining play as an activity of which man is the first origin, for which man sets the rules, and which has no consequences except according to the rules posited. (580) Play is considered a manifestation of freedom through which man escapes his natural nature (581) in virtue of the fact that he is in complete control over the act, its value and the rules. The empirical instances of play are described by Sartre in terms of their deepest existential meaning:
. . . the desire to do is here reduced to a certain desire to be. The act is not its own goal for itself; neither does its explicit end represent its goal and its profound meaning; but the function of the act is to make manifest and to present to itself the absolute freedom which is the very being of the person. This particular type of project, which has freedom for its foundation and its goal, deserves a special study. It is radically different from all others in that it aims at a radically different type of being. It would be necessary to explain in full detail its relations with the project of being God, which has appeared to us as the deep-seated structure of human reality. But such a study cannot be made here; it belongs rather to an Ethics. . . . Nevertheless the fact remains that the desire to play is fundamentally the desire to be. (581)

Thus the ontological concern with the experience of play is pushed in one direction to the point where the ultimate structure of the human realitythe project of being Godbrings into the picture Ethics as the necessary complementary to the ontological analysis. And as Sartres graphic particularization and specification of the ontological structures progresses in the other direction, again it reaches a point where it necessarily calls for being complemented by the third constituent of his discourse, Existential Psychoanalysis (586), as we shall see in a moment. The intensity and richness of these pages would not arise simply from the particular imagery.

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

169

Rather, they are inseparable from the fact that the empirical instances are referred to the totality of their dimensions in that all three regions of the existentialist discourseOntology, Ethics and Existential Psychoanalysis as reciprocally founding one anotherare brought into play around the focus of tangible experiences, which in turn clearly display the structural coherence of a complex philosophical conception as a whole. Sartre takes as his principal example the experience of skiing:
That pure In-itself [the field of snow], comparable to the absolute, intelligible plenum of Cartesian extension, fascinates me as the pure appearance of the not-me; what I wish precisely is that this In-itself might be a sort of emanation of myself while still remaining in itself. This is the meaning even of the snowmen and snowballs which children make; . . . To ski means not only to enable me to make rapid movements and to acquire a technical skill, nor is it merely to play by increasing according to my whim the speed or the difficulties of the course; it is also to enable me to possess this field of snow. . . . The upsurge of the snow is the matter of my act in the same way that the upswing of the hammer is the pure fulfillment of the hammering. At the same time I have chosen a certain point of view in order to apprehend this snowy slope: this point of view is a determined speed, which emanates from me, which I can increase or diminish as I like; through it the field traversed is constituted as a definite object, entirely distinct from what it would be at another speed. . . . It is myself then who give form to the field of snow by the free speed which I give myself. But at the same time I am acting upon my matter. The speed is not limited to imposing a form on the matter given from the outside; it creates its matter. The snow, which sank under my weight when I walked, which melted into water when I tried to pick it up, solidifies suddenly under the action of my speed; it supports me. . . . This is because I hold a special relation of appropriation with the snow: sliding. . . . I realize a synthesis which has depth. I realize that the bed of snow organizes itself in its lowest depths in order to hold me up; the sliding is action at a distance; it assures my mastery over the material without my needing to plunge into that material and engulf myself in it in order to overcome it. To slide is the opposite of taking root. The root is already half assimilated into the earth; it can utilize the earth only by making itself earth;303. . . Sliding, on the contrary, realizes a material unity in depth without penetrating farther than the surface; it is like the dreaded master who does not need to insist nor to raise his voice in order to be obeyed. An admirable picture of power. From this comes the famous advice: Slide,

170

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

mortals, dont bear down!304 This does not mean Stay on the surface, dont go deeply into things, but on the contrary Realize syntheses in depth without compromising yourself. . . . Thus the sliding appears as identical with a continuous creation. The speed is comparable to consciousness and here symbolizes consciousness. (5824)

Thus the eidetic description of the particular example of skiing culminates in the revelation of a symbolic relationship which universalizes its significance. Now we can really understand and appreciate why the particular example has been brought into the existentialist discourse. Equally, in relation to this example, we can understand the fundamental difference between pure phenomenology and Sartrean phenomenological description which is undertaken in the service of the hermeneutic of existence. For the essence which a Husserlian description of skiing would disclose could not have anything to do with the existential-ontological region of being: that would be ruled out by the necessary bracketing out which is an a priori methodological prerequisite of its approach. Husserlian disclosure of the essence of skiing could only refer to itself for its meaning, and in no circumstance to some fundamental ontological passion which it might existentially symbolize. By contrast. Sartre makes intelligible the project of skiing as a project of realizing syntheses in depth, embracing the totality of relations of the human reality in their full intensity. Thanks to this approach, the everyday experience of skiing recedes from our horizon by billions of light years: the conception of a symbolic meaning makes the commonplace experience simply incommensurable with its existentialist counterpart. Now the hermeneutic of existence puts in front of us something totally different: the snow as impenetrable and out of reach, representing the synthesis of self and not-self (585) in a specific mode of possessive appropriation. Even the resistance the snow seems to exert over us is made intelligible in the same terms of ontological appropriation:
I have realized this resistance through my fatigue, and I have been able to measure at each instant the progress of my victory. Here the snow is identical with the Other, and the common expression to overcome, to conquer, to master, etc. indicate sufficiently that it is a matter of establishing between me and the snow the relation of master to slave. This aspect of appropriation which we find in the ascent, exists also in swimming, in an obstacle course, etc. The peak on which a flag is planted is a peak which has been appropriated. (585)

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

171

Thus everything is set in the same light, and the ontological significance of the particular examples can be brought out in a generalized form:
. . . a principal aspect of sportand in particular of open air sportis the conquest of these enormous masses of water, of earth, and of air, which seem a priori indomitable and unutilizable; and in each case it is a question of possessing not the element for itself, but the type of existence in-itself which is expressed by means of this element; it is the homogeneity of substance which we wish to possess in the form of snow; it is the impenetrability of the in-itself and its non-temporal permanence which we wish to appropriate in the form of the earth or of the rock, etc. Art, science, play are activities of appropriation, either wholly or in part, and what they want to appropriate beyond the concrete object of their quest is being itself, the absolute being of the In-itself. (585)

And this is the point where the overall design becomes wholly visible, asserting the unity of the particular and the general in the synthesis of existentialist ontology with existential psychoanalysis:
Thus ontology teaches us that desire is originally a desire of being and that it is characterized as the free lack of being. But it teaches us also that desire is a relation with a concrete existent in the midst of the world and that this existent is conceived as a type of In-itself; it teaches us that the relation of the For-itself to this desired In-itself is appropriation. We are, then, in the presence of a double determination of desire: on the one hand, desire is determined as a desire to be a certain being, which is the In-itself-For-itself and whose existence is ideal; on the other hand, desire is determined in the vast majority of cases as a relation with a contingent and concrete In-itself which has the project of appropriating. Does one of these determinations dominate the other? Are the two characteristics compatible? Existential psychoanalysis can be assured of its principles only if ontology has given a preliminary definition of the relation of these two beings the concrete and contingent In-itself or object of the desire, and the In-itself-For-itself or ideal of the desire and if it has made explicit the relation which unites appropriation as a type of relation to the In-itself, to being, as a type of relation to the In-itself-For-itself. (5856)

These few pages present to us in a microcosm, as it were, the totality of Sartres existentialist conception. We can witness the development of the particular themes on the ground of the fundamental existentialist categories.

172

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Inevitably, the closer we get in the process of eidetic description to the ontological core, the more the antinomies of its structure are pushed into the foreground, profoundly affecting the character of the particular instances. It is because of the underlying structural antinomies that appropriation must be conceivedin sharpest possible contrast to our empirical notion of it as nothing but a symbolic relation to an ideality, and in its ideality, corresponding to the ultimate ontological structure, it must be envisaged simultaneously as something given at one stroke . . . and as requiring an infinite time to be realized. (592) In other words, we are again confronted with an impossible realization, in the truest spirit of the existentialist message:
. . . it is impossible to realize the relation symbolized by appropriation. In itself appropriation contains nothing concrete. It is not a real activity (such as eating, drinking, sleeping) which could serve in addition as a symbol for a particular desire. It exists on the contrary, only as a symbol; it is its symbolism which gives it its meaning, its coherence, its existence. There can be found in it no positive enjoyment outside its symbolic value; it is only the indication of a supreme enjoyment of possession (that of the being which could be its own foundation), which is always beyond all the appropriative conduct meant to realize it. (593)

It is not an idiosyncratic inclination for paradoxical transformations which produces such antinomous contrasts but, on the contrary, the conceptual framework of structural antinomies tends to articulate itself often through extreme, and sometimes even shockingly extreme, paradoxical formulations, like: Destruction realizes appropriation perhaps more keenly than creation does, for the object destroyed is no longer there to show itself impenetrable, . . . to destroy is to recreate by assuming oneself as solely responsible for the being of what existed for all. (593) True enough, no matter how shockingly paradoxical. But of course true only in terms of the fundamental definitions of the overall conceptual framework which must precede it. The particular paradoxes are only instantiations of the conceptual framework of unilateral oppositions: they can be derived from the latter with the ease of the kaleidoscopic transformations which throw at one moment the light on one side of the antinomy, and the next moment the contrasting light of its opposite, on the particular point at issue, and in the most extreme cases they can even combine the two lights into a single beam, so as to display with authenticity the uneasy balance of the existentialist conception.

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

173

Contrary to interpretations which arbitrarily isolate the particular descriptions from the philosophical conception and oppose them to the latter, we can clearly identify the determination of even the most minute details by the overall conception. Taken in isolation, assertions like the In-itself is transformed into nothingness (582)that is, when I pick up some snow and my fingers melt itor the snow solidifies suddenly under the action of my speed; it supports me (583) are unsustainable absurdities. Melted snow is by no means nothingness, and in any case things might turn out the other way roundnamely my frozen fingers departing into nothingness from my hand rather than the snow melting awaydepending on the outside temperature. Nor is it true that the snow solidifies and supports me under the action of my speed. For speed or no speed, what I need, above all, is the supporting platform of my skis, or some similar devices, and they do the supporting, not my speed which itself must be supported: that is, made possible by the underlying support. But obviously such factual trivia cannot be allowed to stand in the way of Sartres eidetic sweep. All the less so, since admitting that it is the clumsy materiality of my skis which supports me and not the free determination of my elegantly speeding nothingness would undermine the existentialist opposition of sliding to taking root, in that one may be compelled to say that skiing is a moving concretion of snow by analogy with root described as a living concretion of the earth. (584) For obviously we are talking about the same process of material inertia mastering material inertia: in one case it can utilize the earth only by making itself earth, (584) and in the other it can utilize for sliding compressed snow only by making itself a kind of compressed snow. (The liberty involved in calling the ski compressed snow is not one whit greater than in calling the root earth.) The selectivity of the particular imagery, with its telling omissions, is dictated by the necessary requirements of the existentialist conception as a whole. The outlines of the particular imagery are speedily sketched in the self-generative process of kaleidoscopic transformations as mediated projections of the basic categorial framework (ultimately identified as symbolic equivalents of the latter) and nothing can be allowed to disturb the picture. If a contrary example crops up in the course of the self-generative transformationsfor instance in that as soon as the particular case of skiing is generalized as sliding (and it must be generalized in the process of becoming a symbolic equivalent), it inevitably brings forth to our attention also other forms of slidingit is categorically dismissed the moment it appears. Sliding on ice, which scratches the ice and finds a matter already organized,

174

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

is very inferior [to skiing], and if people continue to do it despite all this, it is for other reasons. (584) Whatever those other reasons might be, we are never told. The kaleidoscopic mode of progression enables Sartre to get out of the difficulty by simply declaring the characteristic that has emerged (scratching the surface of the ice) to be inferior. This, however, brings another problem with it, namely the realization (as an afterthought) that in a sense skiing also scratches the snow. But not to worry; another eidetic assertion will help to extricate Sartre also from this difficulty by nullifying the counter-effect of the disconcerting characteristic and thus by taking back in some form what he was forced to admit by the logic of his own example. He does this by referring to a slight disappointment which always seizes us when we see behind us the imprints which our skis have left on the snow. How much better it would be if the snow re-formed itself as we passed over it! Besides, when we let ourselves slide down the slope, we are accustomed to the illusion of not making any mark; we ask the snow to behave like that water which secretly it is. (584) And this is where Sartres dominating subjectivity turns out to be the necessary sustaining power of the whole enterprise. For if some people might question the liberties he takes with his own terms of analysis and description, he will not hesitate for a moment to dismiss his critics just as categorically as he sweeps aside examples and instances perceptibly contrary to his own interpretative direction, saying that his critics have not read his work, or if they did they have not understood it, or that they are a priori incapable of understanding it, or even that they are incapable of understanding their own works. This could not be otherwise in a conception in which we set out from a description of skiing and end up with a legislative assertion of how the ideal snow ought to behave in the symbolic act of appropriation. No philosophical conception can be divorced from its authors specific subjectivity which sustains it in its articulation. This is just as true of Sartre as of Spinoza and Descartes, Hegel and Marx, Wittgenstein and Heidegger. Sartres overpowering subjectivity is a necessary complement to a conception which must impose on the reader, through whatever liberties its eidetic descriptions might require, the conviction that things are in the ontological depth (of which the empirical manifestations and modes of behavior are only the symbol) as they ought to be according to the existentialist hermeneutic of existence. It is the total context which confers the proper meaning on the particular examples and instantiations. It is the articulation of the overall conception which sustains the particular points, no matter how much they

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

175

may be forced. All selectivity is necessarily tendentious and therefore it needs a broader frame of reference for its justification than the accuracy of details. Indeed, the selection of accurate particulars is no less in need of justification than taking liberties. In both cases the criterion of justification can only be the coherence of a significant discourse, and the accuracy of details is no guarantee whatsoever that we are on the right road to the latter, as all depressingly pedestrian varieties of positivism and neo-positivism testify. Equally, the fact that a writers terms of description or analysis strongly depart from our everyday experience is no evidence by itself against the meaningful coherence of his discourse. Sartres inaccuracies and forced descriptions are not just inaccuracies and forced descriptions. As we have seen also in the case of taking root as diametrically opposed to sliding, they are highly tendentious constituents of the intended meaning. Reading the great majority of his analyses and descriptions we realize their significant departure from our own perception of the same relation, and yet we do not mind this precisely because of the powerful suggestive coherence of his discourse. We do not mind the liberties he takes precisely because we realize, in relation to the overall conception, what he is driving at as his vision unfolds in front of us in its existentialist coherence and originality. No one can deny the profound originality of Sartres discourse in Being and Nothingness. But simply to refer to this originality is not enough for identifying its specificity. For there is a fundamental difference between the originality of, say, Marxs Capital and Sartres work. Our concern here is not the question of relative greatness but the determination of a writers attitude toward his own work as an essential condition of the particular character of that work. In Sartres case, as a direct manifestation of his dominating subjectivity, originality is not only the type of solution given to some significant problems: it is also a constantly pursued conscious aim of the intellectual undertaking. The quest for originality appears to him at a crucial time in his development as an imperative to emancipate himself entirely from the influence of others so as to be able to follow his own unique road. It is in this spirit that he writes in a letter to Simone de Beauvoir in 1940:
Since I have broken my inferiority complex vis--vis the extreme left, I feel a freedom of thought which I never had before. Also vis--vis the phenomenologists. It seems to me that I am well on the way of finding myself.305

176

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

This attitude is strongly reinforced through its elevation to a theoretical status in Sartres conception of existentialist authenticity as the pursuit of ones unique project; and from that moment on this cardinal tenet of the hermeneutic of existence is inseparable from the radical self-assertion of his dominating subjectivity. Indeed, to be more precise, the Sartrean pursuit of originality as a conscious aim is very much part of his original project from a very early age, as we can see through Words and other autobiographic material at our disposal. The change that we can witness around 1940 which happens to coincide with his traumatic experience with the left and consequently with the definition of his own pursuit as a strictly individual ventureis that his attitude as a writer toward his own work is now crystallized around a specific version of the authenticity of individual existence, defined in a diametrical opposition to bad faith seen above all as the spirit of seriousness which dares to presume that the pursuit of social objectives is more commendable than getting drunk alone. Thus we see a unique fusion of personal determinations with a particular theoretical posture, and this fusion becomes the organizing core of the synthesis of Being and Nothingness. As such it determines in the last analysis not only Sartres attitude to other thinkers, relegating the matter of scholarly considerations to a status of no real importance,306 but also his relation to the treatment of experience as interpretative evidence. It is Sartres overpowering subjectivity as embodied in the structural framework of his conception which sharply determines what sort of evidence is admissible at all for consideration and what kind of use is to be made of the admitted data. (Indeed, the term data is rather inadequate. For by the time the empirical particulars are brought into the focus of theoretical generalization by Sartre they are fundamentally transformed through eidetic description and kaleidoscopic specification.) Marx may spend the greater part of his life, buried in the British Museum Library, engaged in unearthing evidence which not merely sustains his theoretical conception but expands, modifies and intensifies it as well, displaying thus an inherently dialectical relationship between theory and research. Nothing could be more alien to Sartres way of proceeding. (Not surprisingly, therefore, he must break off the project of investigating history precisely at the point where the more or less self-generative permutations of the formal structures of history are sketched out and the need for evidence in the form of a sustained historical research inescapably asserts itself.) Sartre maintains the same sort of attitude toward his particulars as the Absolute Monarch toward his subjects: he treats them as he pleases; and

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

177

quite legitimately so in that, being the categorically self-asserting foundation of legality itself, he constitutes them in such a way that they owe their very existence as subjects to the constitutive framework of the overall conception in which they are allowed to arise. And just as the conscious pursuit of originality has been existentialistically theorized and authenticated as the unique project of strictly individual venture, now the sovereign attitude toward empirical experience is elevated to a theoretical status in the spirit of the hermeneutic of existence that declares its interest only in their symbolic meaning which it itself generates, creates, and invents. What we see then is a unique integration of subjective and objective determinations in a specific type of synthesis which constantly maintains the sovereignty of the overall conception over the particulars of its articulation. The kaleidoscopic mode of development is a most adequate form of manifestation of such a synthesis. For it is simultaneously open and closed. It is breathtakingly open with respect to the possibilities of self-generative partial transformations, and it is rigidly closed as regards the fundamental structure and categorial framework of the whole. It is for this reason that every new phase in Sartres development must bring with it a new presentation of detail, coupled with the claim that it amounts to a radically new synthesis. The novelty is both true and wildly overstated. True in the sense that the new phase, inasmuch as it represents a richer experience (e.g. the challenge of politics and the experience of society in the postwar years), requires the reformulation of Sartres fundamental concerns in relation to the elements of the new experience. And since the specific synthesis of Being and Nothingness is complete precisely in its incompleteness and unfinishability, the new experience of politics and society cannot be simply inserted into its categorial framework, which articulated itself as a new treatise of the passions conceived under its individualistic-subjective aspects as the eidetics of bad faith. At the same time, the claim of radical novelty characteristically brushes aside two basic continuities. First, the most important earlier categories are always transferred into the later syntheses (as indeed is the case also in the relationship between Being and Nothingness and the earlier studies in philosophical psychology as well as Nausea), even if complemented by new ones, establishing thus a most remarkable continuity in the categorial framework of Sartres philosophy as a whole, notwithstanding its numerous partial transformations. And second, the structural relationship between any given set of categoriesin LImaginaire, in Being and Nothingness, in the Critique of Dialectical Reason, or, for that matter, in The idiot of the Familyand the empirical particularizations in terms of which they are spelled out, remains

178

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

essentially the same, whatever field of experience happens to supply the instances of interpretative specification. In other words, we always set out from the sharply defined outlines of the overall conception as the overpowering bergreifendes Moment of the given enterprise, which leaves no room for a genuine dialectic between theory and research. Thus Sartres approach remains the same whether he writes about the experience of anger and skiing, or about negritude, or indeed when he invents with sovereign mastery the deeply significant experiences that Flaubert ought to have had. It is the representative value of this unique mode of synthesis, of which Being and Nothingness is a supreme example, which working through, and not in spite of, his overpowering subjectivity makes Sartre an outstanding figure.

4.
SA RT R E C R IT IC IZ E S HE ID EGGER for his failure to concern himself with sexuality, the result of which is that his Dasein appears to us as asexual. (383) In contrast to this Sartre insists that the For-itself is sexual in its very upsurge in the face of the Other and that through it sexuality comes into the world. (406) The problem at stake is therefore not a matter of secondary importance (though this is the impression one would get by reading some books on Sartres ontology307) but, on the contrary, quite fundamental to the hermeneutic of existence which is concerned with the meaning of the human reality in all its manifestations. For if the For-itself is sexual in its very upsurge in the face of the Other, then sexuality can only be elucidated in terms of the deepest ontological structures. Here, as everywhere else, when we reach the ultimate connections, we are invited to grasp the problem not as doing but as the project of being. To-be-in-the-world is to form the project of possessing the world (597), and sexuality is an integral part of the realization of this project, and as such it occupies a vital place in the existentialist treatise of the passions. One cannot stress enough that the meaning of these relations is far from being immediate: it is symbolic. Sartre adopts as the point of departure of his own hermeneutic Pascals insight that in an activity [hunting, or playing tennis, for instance] which would be absurd if reduced to itself, there was a meaning which transcended it; that is, an indication which referred to the reality of man in general and to his condition. (562) Sartre generalizes this approach and reads the various manifestations of psychic life as symbols

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

179

maintaining symbolic relations to the fundamental, total structures which constitute the individual person. (569) Thus whatever experience may be under scrutinybe it fatigue on a mountain climbing expedition, or sexual desire, or play, or nausea, or preference for certain types of food, and so on our search for meaning must be guided by the same principle: it is a matter of rediscovering under the partial and incomplete aspects of the subject the veritable completeness which can be only the totality of his impulse toward being, his original relation to himself, to the world, and to the Other, in the unity of internal relations and of a fundamental project. (563) In this sense, sexuality is understood as a fundamental existential project which aims simultaneously (a) at the Other and (b) at being in general. In the first respect: in desire I make myself flesh in the presence of the Other in order to appropriate the Others flesh. (563)
Desire is an attitude aiming at enchantment. Since I can grasp the Other only in his objective facticity, the problem is to ensnare his freedom within this facticity. . . . and by touching this body I should finally touch the Others free subjectivity. This is the true meaning of the word possession. (394)

And in the second respect:


To plug up a hole means originally to make sacrifice of my body in order that the plenitude of being may exist; that is, to subject the passion of the For-itself so as to shape, to perfect, and to preserve the totality of the In-itself. . . . A good part of our life is passed in plugging up holes, in filling empty places, in realizing and symbolically establishing a plenitude. (613)

But, of course, here as everywhere else the ideal involved turns out to be an impossible ideal: desire itself is doomed to failure (396) in that pleasure is the death and the failure of desire, (397) and the fullness of being is equally unrealizable, which ultimately makes man a useless passion. As we can see, human reality under its aspect of sexuality corresponds to the same ontological determinations of freedom and passion which we have encountered in other contexts, in the spirit of a truly totalizing vision. Thus Sartres involvement in psychological research already in his student days, which is further intensified in his literary projects (Nausea and the short stories of the 1930s) as well as in his theoretical writings on Emotion and Imagination, reveals itself as incomparably more than a contingent beginning. Indeed, there is a sense of necessity about it: an organic development

180

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

with a growing achievement in the 1940s. In Being and Nothingness the early psychological insights are integrated with the ontological categories of a unique brand of existentialist hermeneutic, and the new treatise of the passions is articulated as an eidetic of bad faith aimed at unveiling the paradoxical realities of the ontological structure, thus not only making intelligible the bewildering ploys and manifestations of bad faith which escape even the most ingenious psychoanalytic approaches, but also offering the possibility of an existential solution to the problems involved. In the structure of Being and Nothingness we can identify two essentially different, though of course interlinked, lines of reasoning. First, the often explicit polemic thrust in Sartres definition of the basic categories and relations. In this respect the most obvious target is constituted by the various psychological theories (especially psychoanalysis and positivist-behaviorist psychology), but all related conceptions, from Descartes theory of the passions of the soul308 to Marx as the paradigm of the standpoint of seriousness309 and to Prousts idea of a passional mechanism310 are critically dissected by Sartre in accordance with his concept of bad faith. The second discernible dimension of analysis is in fact the more fundamental. It consists in Sartres attempt at defining the basic ontological structures themselves in terms of which the meaning of human reality can be identified. What is the meaning of the being which includes within itself two radically separated regions of being? (XLIII), asks Sartre, and he undertakes an elucidation of this meaning strictly in terms of the ontological relationship between the two indicated regions of being: For-itself and In-itself, categorically excluding the possibility of a religious explanation. And he combines the polemical and substantive dimensions of his analysis under the hypothesis that the various theoretical misconceptions arise as strategies of flight in the face of the anguishing existentialist choices which man is compelled to confront. The remarkable structural cohesion of Being and Nothingness311our impression that the whole massive work is made of the same piece or written in the same breath, in that whatever particular problem is at stake, we are always confronting the one central idea: mans quest for the unrealizable totalityis closely connected with this treatment of the theoretical alternatives as subordinate moments of the overall conception of the meaning of human reality. The conscious rejection of the religious framework of explanation carries with it the claim that the existentialist meaning of the human reality must be constituted by the being who is at the centre of the hermeneutic of existence. The nature of the human enterprise is identified as the self-constitution of

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

181

meaning and value at all levels, from the everyday projects of alarm clocks, sign boards, tax forms, policemen, so many guard rails against anguish (39) to the ultimate desire to be God. (566) If there is a meaning to the human enterpriseand according to Sartre most emphatically there is, although some sectarian religious critics312 accuse him of nihilismit must be inherent in all facets of experience. Accordingly, Sartre pursues his quest by systematically scrutinizing the most varied forms of life-activity: work, sexuality, play, art, science, and the production and consumption of food. He finds that although the forms and modalities of these activities significantly differ among themselves, so that we can grasp certain specificities of, say, play in comparison to eating, the ultimate existential meaning of all of them is fundamentally the same. It is given in the project of possessing the world, which is conceivable only as a possessive appropriation of the world, whether we think of sexualityas the project to possess the Others transcendence as pure transcendence and at the same time as body (394) or of the existential significance of food described as the appropriative choice of being. (615) We can understand now in this light why for Sartre desire cannot be a desire of doing. All activities, in Pascals sense, refer to the reality of man in general and to his condition, and thus they represent merely the form in which a fundamental ontological characteristic of the human realitylack asserting itself through desire (87)manifests itself as the desire of a transcendent object, (385) that is as a desire of being. In the constitution of meaning through activity, a privileged position is assigned to the constitution of value, in that all everyday values derive their meaning from an original projection of myself which stands as my choice of myself in the world (39) and as such it becomes the source of further action. Naturally, the constitution of value is not a separate activity. Rather, it is inherent in all activities as a supportive structure which links the symbolic manifestations of being to their ontological ground. Strategies of bad faith originate in the course of the constitution of these values and, by contrast, in good faith we try to extricate ourselves from the self-imposed trap of bad faith. Characteristically, Sartre not only declares that it is indifferent313 whether one is in good faith or in bad faith, (70) but he goes as far as asserting the primacy of bad faith over against good faith. Good faith seeks to flee the inner disintegration of my being in the direction of the In-itself which it should be and is not. Bad faith seeks to flee the In-itself by means of the disintegration of my being. (70) Thus the talk about authenticity is bound to remain somewhat vacuous, since the apparent positivity of good faith is nothing but the double negativity of a flight

182

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

of a flight of disintegration to which it is impossible to assign other than a purely imperatival regulative meaning. As such it has an ontological status radically different from that of bad faith. The latter constitutes an immediate, permanent threat to every project of the human being, and this permanent threat or risk originates in the fact that the nature of consciousness simultaneously is to be what it is not and not to be what it is. (70) Bad faith, therefore, arises from the innermost structure of consciousness itself, whereas good faith is parasitic on the persistent negativity of the disintegrating flight which it tries to flee. Good faith is, in fact, doubly problematical. First because in contrast to bad faithwhich emanates from the ontological structure of consciousness itself and thus needs no additional supportgood faith has no such obvious ontological underpinning and must be sustained through some well-founded existential motivation which Sartre fails to specify. (Significantly, he evades the problem, which is for him structurally insoluble, by rather gratuitously suggesting in a footnote a radical escape from bad faith through self-recovery or authenticity the description of which has no place here, (70) nor for that matter anywhere else in Being and Nothingness.) And the second problematical feature of good faith is that even if a motivation has been found, given good faiths parasitic character or structural dependency on bad faith, it is bound to remain an unrealizable ideal and a permanently frustrated one. But whatever ones reservations about Sartres approach to these problems, no one should fail to see that in the framework of his existential hermeneutic the most varied aspects of experience are synthesized in a powerfully coherent form. All kinds of activity as well as all forms of psychic life are made intelligible in terms of particular existential projects structured around ones fundamental project, which is said to be identical with the original choice of ones being. The concept of passion occupies a strategic position in this hermeneutic of existence; and indeed no other concept could take its place. For Sartre must explain first of all what makes human reality persist in its quest for being, and he must be able to do that without introducing a determinism into the picture. Consciousness, on its own, could not accomplish anything. Nor could the abstract principle of the freedom of the will help, since it could not supply the motivation for its own deliberations. And this is where passion proves its vital importance for Sartres vision. We shall see in a moment the fundamental ontological meaning of his concept of passion. But first we have to glance at the other sense in which passion is referred to in Being and Nothingness. This second sense is much the same as that used in everyday language, or by philosophers and

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

183

psychologists, and Sartre sets out to extricate it from what he considers to be a network of deterministic misrepresentations:
There is a fairly common tendency to seek to identify free acts with voluntary acts and to restrict the deterministic explanation to the world of the passions. . . . In this case it would be necessary to conceive of man as simultaneously free and determined, and the essential problem would be that of the relation between this unconditioned freedom and the determined processes of the psychic life: how will it master the passions, how will it utilize them for its own benefit? A wisdom which comes from ancient timesthe wisdom of the Stoicswill teach us to come to terms with these passions so as to master them; in short it will counsel us how to conduct ourselves with regard to affectivity as man does with respect to nature in general when he obeys it in order better to control it. Human reality therefore appears as a free power besieged by an ensemble of determined processes. One will distinguish wholly free acts, determined processes over which the free will has power, and processes which on principle escape the human will. (441)

Sartre emphatically rejects this view and opposes to it his own conception:
Here as everywhere we assert that the state of consciousness is a pure idol of a positive psychology. If the will is to be freedom, then it is of necessity negativity and the power of nihilation. But then we no longer can see why autonomy should be preserved for the will. (442) But this is not all: the will, far from being the unique or at least the privileged manifestation of freedom, actuallylike every event of the Foritselfmust presuppose the foundation of an original freedom in order to be able to constitute itself as will. The will in fact is posited as a reflective decision in relation to certain ends. . . . Passion can posit the same ends. For example, if I am threatened, I can run away at top speed because of my fear of dying. This passional fact nevertheless posits implicitly as a supreme end the value of life. (443) Thus since freedom is identical with my existence, it is the foundation of ends which I shall attempt to attain either by the will or by passionate efforts. Therefore it cannot be limited to voluntary acts. Volitions, on the contrary, like passions are certain subjective attitudes by which we attempt to attain the ends posited by original freedom. (444)

184

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Thus passions (in the plural), as subjective attitudes, are on a par with volitions in that they are both manifestations of original freedom. The passional act is that which has a specific passion for its motive, (445) but it is free none the less. It is the ensemble of the desires, emotions, and passions which urge me to accomplish a certain act, (446) but they all arise on the ground of an original freedom. However, Sartre does not stop at this point but turns the table completely on the will which appeared to have a privileged position in relation to freedom at our point of departure. Now we learn that assigning a privileged position to the will could not be more illusory. For a voluntary deliberation is always a deception (450)
When I deliberate, the chips are down. And if I am brought to the point of deliberating, this is simply because it is a part of my original project to realize motives by means of deliberation rather than by some other form of discovery (by passion, for example, or simply by action, which reveals to me the organized ensemble of causes and of ends as my language informs me of my thought). . . . When the will intervenes, the decision is taken, and it has no other value than that of making the announcement. (451)

And this takes us to the fundamental meaning of passion, which is not a subjective attitude but the basis on which all attitudes arise. This is in the last analysis identical to original freedom itself which posits the ends we attempt to attain. It constitutes our very existence as the original choice [an impulse toward being] which originally creates all causes and all motives which can guide us to partial actions. (465) If I want to understand the existential-ontological meaning of the fact that I freely abandon myself to fatigue (as opposed to some deterministic physiological or psychological hypothesis), I must refer this action to my original choice of being, since this passion of the body coincides for the For-itself with the project of making the In-itself exist. (456) To put it in a generalized form:
The For-itself by its self-negation becomes the affirmation of the In-itself. . . . in the quasi-totality of Being, affirmation happens to the In-itself; it is the adventure of the In-itself to be affirmed. This affirmation which could not be effected as the affirmation of self by the In-itself without destroying its being-in-itself, happens to the In-itself as the affirmation is realized by the For-itself. The affirmation is like a passive ecstasis of the In-itself which leaves the In-itself unchanged yet which is achieved in the In-itself and from the standpoint of the In-itself. All this happens

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

185

as if the For-itself had a Passion to lose itself in order that the affirmation world might come to the In-itself. (217)

As we can see, the introduction of passion into the primary set of relations radically modifies everything. It is in virtue of this passion that the human enterprise can take place at all, and assume a character, a direction, and a meaning without it we would be stuck to consciousness and freedom conceived as an icy abstraction totally devoid of any possibility of development. Through passion, freedom and consciousness acquire a bodyand indeed not just in a figurative senseso much so that it becomes possible to talk about the passion of the body for carrying out the original project of freedom to make the In-itself exist: a description which stands in diametrical opposition to the customary view of the body as the depository of physical and psychological determinations. It is thanks to the primary identity of freedom with passion that freedom can be situated: that is conceived in such a way that it can be nothing but situated (though, of course, with all the ambiguities314 necessarily involved). It is through this fusion of freedom with passion that freedom becomes a meaningful existential category. And passion, likewise, through its fusion with freedom acquires a unique character. It is not just any old passion, but the fundamental ontological passion of the human reality which aims at making the existential venture happen through the facticity of freedom315 tied to an absolute contingency and yet remaining absolutely free. Fundamental ontological passion is thus defined as self-negation and self-sacrifice: a passion to lose oneself so that the world might come to the In-itself, as we have just seen, or that the plenitude of being may exist, (613) or again so as to found being and by the same stroke to constitute the In-itself which escapes contingency, (615) and so on, and so forth. Fundamental choice is the original choice of our being and as such it must of necessity be a conscious choice, (461) although, Sartre hastens to add a few lines later, not a deliberate choice. Rather: it is the foundation of all deliberation in that a deliberation requires an interpretation in terms of an original choice. (4712) Consciousness in this Sartrean sensewhich makes the firm distinction between conscious choice and (deliberate) conscious choice, so as to be able to dismiss the idea of the unconsciousis non-positional consciousness.316 Corresponding to non-deliberate conscious choice, nonpositional consciousness is

186

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

. . . we-as-consciousness since it is not distinct from our being. And as our being is precisely our original choice, the consciousness (of) the choice is identical with the self-consciousness which we have. One must be conscious in order to choose, and one must choose in order to be conscious. Choice and consciousness are one and the same thing. . . . to be conscious of ourselves and to choose ourselves are one and the same. (462)

Sartre insists that there can be no such thing as an unconscious psychic phenomenon, (44) and later he adds that the proponents of the psychoanalytic theory have hypostatized and reified bad faith, they have not escaped it. (54) It goes without saying, the problematic of the unconscious is far too complex to be dissolved by any particular formula, since an adequate treatment requires the development of a coherent theory of ideology, spelled out not simply in general terms but in great concreteness and specificity directly applicable to particular individuals. And whatever one may discover in Sartres philosophy, given its individualistic framework of categories, it certainly cannot be an adequate theory of ideology. But this need not concern us here. For the point at issue in this particular context is that his existentialist equation of choice and being, choice and consciousness, choice of ourselves and consciousness of ourselves in the non-positional mode, enables Sartre to suggest a non-deterministic solution to the psychoanalytic problem of the unconscious. For a start, the unconscious is ruled out by definition as a priori impossible, since we set out from the original identity of fundamental passionchoice of being (freedom) non-positional consciousness, and all the specific structures of consciousness, whether affective (like desires, emotions and passions), or volitional, reflective, and therefore fully share the burden of absolute responsibility as specific modes of manifestation of the original synthesis. The phenomenon of the unconscious is accounted for as bad faith which pretends to itself (in the non-positional mode of fundamental unreflective consciousness (473) as contrasted to the consciousness reflected on) to be unconscious in order to be able to flee anguish (namely the burden of inescapable freedom). The possibility of such a strategy is not proved but obliquely assumed by analogy with Gestalt psychology which couples the primacy of the total form with the variability of the secondary317 structures. Accordingly, Sartre asserts that it is possible for me to impose upon myself reflectivelythat is, on the voluntary planeprojects which contradict my original project without, however, fundamentally modifying the initial project. (471) Thus it is possible to talk even about the bad

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

187

faith of the will, (473) in the sharpest possible contrast to any theory of the unconscious. To be sure, Sartre must consider the psychoanalytic hypothesis an absolute outrage, in that it diametrically contradicts his own conception of our absolute freedom and absolute responsibility which insists that we are totally responsible not only for the wars from which we suffer but even for our birth, race, nationality, place of living and past.318 All this would sound a thousand times more absurd than the fateful laments of a demented prophet of doom if Sartre could not sustain at least in the form of a subjective authentication his shocking assertions. We have seen briefly in an earlier section the reasons why, given his individualistic conception of human reality as a strictly individual venture, he must content himself with a subjective authentication and construct a phenomenological ontology in the mould of an existential anthropology, and the concluding section of this chapter will be dedicated to a close investigation of this crucial problem. At this point the issue is not the determination of the existentialist limits of Sartres conceptual framework as a wholethat is, the question why it must articulate itself the way it actually doesbut the identification of the structural links and conceptual interconnections. In other words, the question of how it all works and what makes possible the manifold kaleidoscopic transformations which we have already witnessed. As we have seen, the most fundamental ontological relations are defined by Sartre in terms of the identity of freedom and passion in the self-constitution of human reality which also corresponds to the primary identity of being, choice, and self-consciousness. This ultimate ontological equation proves to be extremely fruitful because its terms are defined in such a way that they become interchangeable right from the beginning, thus establishing the possibility of virtually endless variations and self-generative transformations. The primary concepts can be combined in the first place among themselves, and all additional conceptual derivations can be fused with the preceding ones, resulting in an ever-enlarging circle319 of relations and sets of definitions. We may be taken aback when we read the apparently arbitrary suggestion that being is the same as being free. If, however, we grasp the meaning of Sartres assertionthere is no difference between the being of man and his being free (21)in the context of the original equation of freedom and passion as its fundamental ontological ground, it ceases to be shocking and appears as a quasi-analytic specification of the original terms of reference, in that the being of man as being free is merely another way of asserting the

188

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

inextricable unity of freedom and situation according to the rules of an existentialist hermeneutic. The same procedure is followed in asserting the identity of freedom and obligation, (35) being and choice, (440) choice and consciousness, (462) choice and action, (484) consciousness and desire, (391) situation and motivation, (487) contingency and facticity, (486) and a great many other combinations (such as intention and action, consciousness and consciousness of freedom, facticity of freedom and contingency of freedom, etc.), including at times even the most unexpected ones, like play and anguish. (581) On the ground of Sartres fundamental ontological equation some rather unorthodox logical procedures become thoroughly legitimate: such as, for instance, the establishment of lack as the fundamental ontological characteristic of the human reality with reference to the existence of desire. (87) While strictly speaking it is taking liberties with logic to say that since desire is a lack therefore man is a lack, nevertheless it is perfectly tenable on the ground on which this equation arises, namely the fundamental definition of human reality as an ontologically meaningful passion to lose itself so that the original lack should be remedied through the establishment of the plenitude of being. In a discourse which is structured in this way, there can be nothing wrong with saying that consciousness chooses itself as desire, (391) or indeed much more shockingly that my body is a conscious structure of my consciousness. (329) The Sartrean discourse is structured the way it is in order to be able to impose on us its own framework and terms of reference, and consequently to make acceptable the shocking assertions of the existentialist hermeneutic. And the close integration of metaphors into the discourse as a whole, as well as the use of the method of kaleidoscopic transformations which we have seen in the preceding sections, serve precisely the same purpose. Seen in this light, the insistence on absolute freedom and absolute responsibility is far from being as absurd as even Sartre suggests sometimes in his relatively recent interviews.320 His extreme statements on the absoluteness of freedom are integral parts of a highly complex discourse which must be read within its own terms of reference, whether one agrees with the principal tenets of this philosophy or not. Partly this is a question of remembering the direct or indirect qualifications which one can find elsewhere in the work and which constitute the necessary complement to the extreme formulations. And partly it is a matter of appreciating the moralist-exhortative function which claims on the strength of an ontological description mans absolute freedom so as to be able to address to him the obligation of an absolute responsibility.

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

189

But more than anything else, the legitimacy of reading Sartre within his own terms of reference concerns the fundamental coherence of a representative philosophical discourse which obeys its inner determinations. Once the core of a significant conception is constitutedas a result of an original choice or fundamental project, or whatever other name we care to give to those existential-social determinations which ultimately structure a coherent world vieweverything else follows with an iron necessity even if one is the champion of absolute freedom. (Departure from this inner necessity is either some kind of inconsistency, whatever its reasons, or a step toward a meaningful transformation and restructuring of the original conception. In this sense the idea of a radical conversion is certainly feasible, but an adequate treatment of its conditions would require some very precise definitions in the framework of a totalizing theory.) In this sense, given certain propositions and fundamental definitions, one must insist not only that motivation is not causation, (27) but also that the structure of motives as ineffective is the condition of my freedom. . . . there is never a motive in consciousness; motives are only for consciousness since consciousness has the task of conferring on the motive its meaning and its importance. (34) We should also notice here the imperatival structure of this element of Sartres discourse: the definition of consciousness in terms of its task. Just as in an earlier mentioned passage freedom-anguish is said to be characterized by a constantly renewed obligation to remake the self which designates the free being, (35) the fundamental ontological passion of human reality, losing itself, is sustained through an as if clause. Sartre explicitly turns away from Kantian morality, which is orientated toward doing (action), in the name of an existentialist ontology whose ultimate point of reference is being, (431) and near the end of Being and Nothingness he declares that we cannot possibly derive imperatives from ontologys indicatives. (625) The problem is, though, that the alleged indicatives of phenomenological ontology (existential anthropology) are deeply impregnated with imperatives at all levels, from the most fundamental sets of relations to the secondary structures and partial descriptions, and the being in question is a choice of being which ought to be constantly renewed: that is, a doing, in the Kantian sense of the term. Also, when Sartre claims that the existentialist hermeneutic succeeds in eliminating the distinction between the intention and the act, the actual state of affairs is far more problematical than the claim suggests. For the act in question is choosing, which is said to be by definition identical to doing, (484) and

190

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

the freedom of our action is made subjectively plausible merely in terms of the possibility of an authentic choice the choice of our being. Kantian philosophy haunts Being and Nothingness from beginning to end (and not just Being and Nothingness, of course), even if the Kantian constituents are fully integrated into Sartres unique mould of discourse. The ontological indicatives of absolute freedom and responsibility arise in Sartres philosophy under the sign of the strictest ought, and they operate in the context of the most severe contingency. And of course all this is articulated in characteristically Sartrean terms. The absoluteness of freedom is established through its definitional identity with the unavoidability of choice even in the circumstances of a deliberate refusal to choose, and the categories of contingency and facticity are brought into the foreground in order to remind us that we should not have any voluntaristic illusions as to the possible impact of our actions. Sartre goes as far as he possibly can in acknowledging the force of circumstance, in talking about the necessity of fact and the inherent ambiguity of freedom in situation, as we have seen. To concede more than that would not just qualify his conception of freedom but undermine and ultimately destroy his philosophical framework as a whole. He must go on insisting that we are absolutely free and absolutely responsible, adding at the same time that it is the contingency of freedom and the contingency of the In-itself which are expressed in situation by the unpredictability and the adversity of the environment, (509) meaning that the adversity of my environment imposes on me the absolute obligation of carrying the full burden of responsibility also for my situation which I therefore must be, rather than just being in it. And so it goes to and fro, emphasizing now one side and then the other. Sartre is fully aware of the extremely uneasy balance which threatens to precipitate the whole structure in one moment on one side and the next moment on the other: that is why he must be constantly engaged in re-balancing and re-qualifying, so as to maintain the integrity of the fundamental conception. I am responsible for everything, in fact, except for my very responsibility, for I am not the foundation of my being. (555) Quite so. But then ultimately I am not responsible for anything at all! It shows Sartres great honesty as a thinker that he makes no attempt at hiding this unpalatable dilemma. Obviously, however, he cannot allow it to remain the final word on the subject. And since there is no other way out, the Kantian as if comes again to the rescue. Just as the fundamental passion of the human reality for losing itself for the plenitude of being could only be established in terms of as if, here, in the sentence that immediately follows the one just quoted, we

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

191

are confronted with the ultimate qualification: Therefore everything takes place as if I were compelled to be responsible. The imperatival underpinnings of the whole structure reveal themselves in an unmistakeable fashion. I am absolutely free in virtue of being compelled to choose (condemned to be free), and because everything happens as if the human reality through the free exercise of its fundamental passion decided to lose itself so that the plenitude of being might exist. And likewise, I am absolutely responsible because in my absolutely free being I am identical with my situation, no matter how devastating the coefficient of adversity321 might be, and therefore everything happens as if I were compelled to be absolutely responsible, whether I assume the awesome burden of this responsibility or try to run away from it through the ruses of bad faith. On which side is Sartres heart in this balancing of freedom and responsibility against contingency and adversity? The answer is revealed by an astonishing inconsistency: surely an existentialist version of the Freudian slip for a man of Sartres stature. It occurs in the context of Sartres discussion of death and suicide. He rightly takes Heidegger to task for the latters treatment of death, insisting that in view of the fact that death is a radical contingency, it cannot belong to the ontological structure of the For-itself, and consequently it must be ruled out of all ontological conjectures. (545) Death cannot be my possible, since it is the nihilation of all my possibles, which is outside my possibilities. (537) Similarly, suicide is an absurdity which causes my life to be submerged in the absurd, and of course it carries with it the nihilation of all my possibilities. And yet, when it comes to dealing with a situation of extreme gravity in which the possibilities of an authentic choice are suffocated by adversity, Sartre does not hesitate for a moment to elevate ones death by suicide to the dignity of an authentic ontological possibility. Thus we are told that there are no accidents in a life; . . . If I am mobilized in a war, this is my war; it is in my image and I deserve it. I deserve it first because I could always get out of it by suicide or by desertion; these ultimate possibles are those which must always be present for us when there is a question of envisaging a situation. For lack of getting out of it, I have chosen it. (554) Desertion, yes, but suicide? Such a view is no less grotesque than Lockes theory of a tacit consent, and the ideological interest is equally visible in it. The only difference is that we are much more favorably disposed toward the ideology of assuming ones responsibility in a fight for freedom than toward the Lockean liberal legitimation of institutionalized wage-slavery.

192

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

However, we can entertain Sartres view only as a moral ought which requires, of course, an appropriate justificationone which suicide cannot be given even in his own terms of referenceand definitely not as an indicative of ontology. The assertion: suicide is one mode among others of being-in-the-world, (556) far from being one of ontologys indicatives, is a mere rationalization of extreme voluntarism, no matter how much we might sympathize with the underlying intent. Yet, the need to assert the existentialist message in Being and Nothingness at the price of such inconsistency is extremely rare. As a matter of course the delicate balancing enterprise is successfully accomplished through those legitimate and powerful original methods of articulation which we have seen above. Inevitably, the discourse on absolute freedom and absolute responsibility deeply marks Being and Nothingness, in its allpervasive negativity, with a character of abstract heroism. According to this passionate eidetic of bad faith, it is in the innermost nature of our ontological conditions, which transcend temporality and hold for feudalism just as much as for our present-day predicament, that we have infinite possibilities of choice, (522) and therefore we should not resign ourselves to the choice of disintegrating flight in an attempt at escaping from the responsibility of freedom. And no degree of adversity or failure is allowed to invalidate the abstract heroism of this imperative of authenticity which remains undefined as a generic choice of being, necessarily devoid of any indication of what might constitute a tangibly authentic form of action. For the imperative is coupled with a revealing qualification that blends perfectly with both the abstract heroism and the subjective authenticity of Sartres existentialist hermeneutic: There can be a free For-itself only as engaged in a resisting world. . . . Success is not important to freedom. (483) We are presented with the abstract imperative of engagement generically confronting a resisting world, and the enterprise remains a strictly individual venture, struggling against the Other or capitulating to the illusion of collective solidarity in the spirit of seriousness on the barren road of disintegrating flight. If this is the relation of forces, if this is how the lines of demarcation are drawn in the eidetic of bad faith, obviously success must not be important to freedom. What counts is the authenticity of the undertaking itself: a principle which is compatible not only with the assertion of the ontological equivalence of all kinds of endeavor,322 but even with the gloomy forecast of the ultimately necessary failure of all projects of the human reality: a forecast which is not really a forecast but the acknowledgement of an absolute

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

193

certainty, inherent in the fundamental ontological structure of being which defines man as a useless passion. We are bound to fail in our attempt at dominating others just as much as in the project of love which holds in its being-for-others the seed of its own destruction. (377) And yet, if to will oneself free is to choose to be in the world confronting Others, then the one who wills himself such must will also the passion of his freedom. (526) This is why whether in fury, hate, pride, shame, disheartened refusal or joyous demand, it is necessary for me to choose to be what I am. (529) Which sums it all up again, in a characteristically Sartrean fashion. And in the ultimate re-balancing effort we are also given a glimmer of hope, though only as the promise of the possibility of a radical conversion.323 Again we are really presented with the imperatival conditions of possibility of this radical conversion, although it appears as an indicative of ontology. And again it is authenticated in strictly individual terms, on the strength of the subjective integrity of a particular example, taking its inspiration from the world of the imaginary (limaginaire), especially the world of Dostoevskys and Gides heroes. The concept which is meant to convey the glimmer of hope in a Delphic form, anticipating Sartres postwar cult of the adventurer, is the instant as a beginning which is given as the end of a prior project, and we are told that it is precisely this which is produced in the case of a radical modification of a fundamental project. (466) In truth, the condition of possibility of a radical conversion is the suspension of the temporal determinations specified by my earlier choice, and this may be envisaged in the framework of the Sartrean hermeneutic of existence only as the infinitesimal instant which interposes itself between two radically different fundamental projects. But it must be presented as an indicative of ontology: we are told that it is produced in the case of a radical modification of a fundamental project. In other words, the condition of possibility of a radical conversion is the radical modification of the fundamental project through the instant. The change is envisaged as a liberating instant in which I am suddenly exorcized and become radically other, accomplishing a total metamorphosis of my original project. (475) And if Sartre paradoxically also maintains that we must conceive of the original choice as unfolding time, (465) that only brings to the fore the often forbidding complexities of an antinomous structure of thought, without invalidating the primary importance of the liberating instant which puts the chips down in an exhilarating moment and allows unfolding time merely to make the more or less prosaic announcements:

194

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

These extraordinary and marvelous instants when the prior project collapses into the past in the light of a new project which rises on its ruins and which as yet exists only in outline, in which humiliation, anguish, joy, hope are delicately blended, in which we let go in order to grasp and grasp in order to let gothese have often appeared to furnish the clearest and most moving image of our freedom. (476)

A moving poetical description indeed of the existentialist unity of freedom and passion. As to what it is which we grasp when we let go in order to grasp and grasp in order to let go, or where it will all take us on the necessary premise of our useless passion, or again what the value is of this radical conversion while the Other remains the ontologically established permanent threat and perverter of even the most authentic project, all such questions are permanently banished from the horizon of a hermeneutic of existence conceived as an inescapably individual venture.

5.

articulates his hermeneutic of existence is that of an anarchistic individualism,324 and its ultimate point of reference is the ontological solitude of the For-itself. (456) In this spirit he insists that what he calls the impulse toward being can be only purely individual and unique. (563) Understandably, therefore, Sartres ontology of solitude assumes the dimension of an eidetic of bad faith which can be coherently formulated from the standpoint of isolated individuality. And in keeping with this character of the work, the proofs we are presented with in Being and Nothingness are either analytic-deductive325 or appear as subjectively authentic and plausible representations of an existential predicament. Sartres individualistic ontological posture asserts itself by ascribing to the Other a radically different ontological status from the For-itself s, with far-reaching consequences for all aspects of this conception. According to Sartre, the Other is an a priori hypothesis with no justification save the unity which it permits to operate in our experience. (227)
T H E STANDP OIN T F R O M W H ICH SA RTRE

Human reality remains alone because the Others existence has the nature of a contingent and irreducible fact. We encounter the Other; we do not constitute him. And if this fact still appears to us in the form of a necessity,

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

195

yet it does not belong with those conditions of the possibility of our experience orif you preferwith ontological necessity. (250)

Like Marx, Sartre owes a great deal to Hegels characterization of the Master-Slave relationship in The Phenomenology of Mind. However, they develop Hegels original insights in diametrically opposite directions. Marxs criticism of Hegels approach aims at intensifying the historical dynamism inherent in this relationship, rectifying the ideologically determined violations of the inner logic of his own conception by Hegel himself.326 Sartre, by contrast, radically eliminates the historical dimension from the relationship and transforms it into a timeless existential structure. And by denying to the Other a proper ontological status, he renders the whole relationship extremely problematical, determining in a peculiar way not only the character of the Other but also the nature of self-consciousness, especially in its collective form (the We-subject), as we shall see in a moment. To be sure, the assertion of the fundamental ontological solitude of the For-itself cannot be sustained in isolation. Consequently, the whole range of categories to which the For-itself is closely connected must be defined in structurally identical terms. In other words, the categories are arranged as ontologically primary or fundamental on one side, and as derivative or parasitic on the other. This is how the most important relations are depicted in Being and Nothingness:
O N TO LOG IC AL LY P R IM A RY D ERIVATIVE O R PAR AS I TI C

Consciousness Individual point of view Negation For-itself Ontological solitude Self Individual totality Conflict Incomparable uniqueness Bad faith Lack Possibility Freedom and passion Contingency and facticity

The World Global point of view Affirmation In-itself Togetherness The Other Humanity Solidarity We-subject and Us-object Good faith Realization Probability Causality and necessity Ens causa sui

196

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Detotalized totality Missing God The Imperative (to realize the unrealizable) Imperfection and fragmentation

Totalized totality Ideal or value Societys demands The Imaginary Synthesis (Beauty)

Inevitably, if this is the ontological structure of being, then the deepest ontological meaning of human reality cannot be other than suffering, and the consciousness of this human reality must be defined as an ontologically unhappy consciousness: an approach which, again, radically liquidates all historical connotations of Hegels concept of unhappy consciousness:
. . . human reality arises as such in the presence of its own totality or self as a lack of that totality. . . . it combines in itself the incompatible characteristics of the In-itself and the For-itself. . . . The being of human reality is suffering because it rises in being as perpetually haunted by a totality which it is without being able to be it, precisely because it could not attain the In-itself without losing itself as For-itself. Human reality therefore is by nature an unhappy consciousness with no possibility of surpassing its unhappy state. (90)

Sartre constructs an ontological framework from a set of antinomously structured relations, and consequently, situating himself on one side, he can argue that the unification of one side with the other is impossible because they are structurally incompatible. Thus, what may very well be an antinomous relationship in virtue of some identifiable relative historical determinations is transformed into an absolute. In the spirit of his ontological commitment to an individualistic standpoint, coupled with an a priori exclusion of the possibility to take a global point of view, (359) Sartre insists, as if it were a matter of absolute self-evidence, that the self is individual; it is the individual completion of the self which haunts he For-itself. (91) It is not difficult to agree that so long as the ontological project is conceived as the individual completion of the self, such a completion can only haunt the For-itself. Equally, if I adopt as my absolute point of departure the ontological solitude of the For-itself, I can only ascribe a derivative or hypothetical ontological status to the Other. But, of course, this whole procedure is extremely problematical. For it is only analytically (tautologically) true that the self is individual, in so far as the individual self is certainly individual. But such individual self is nothing more than a one-sided philosophical construct.

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

197

The real human self, by contrast, is the dialectical unity of individual and social determinations, hence both individual and non-individual, and therefore it cannot conceivably have a merely individual completion. Since, however, I started out from a purely individualistic ontological conception of the self, the idea of a completion must and can only arise as the abstract imperative of an unrealizable totality. Furthermore, since the Other could only be given a totally inadequate ontological status as a mere hypothesis, all possible combinations of the self with the Other must suffer the consequences of the Others problematical ontological determination. As a result, the self s social dimension appears as an ontological afterthought which arises on the derivative ground of the hypothesis of the Other, transforming the For-itself into a degraded, petrified and reified being: The For-itself when alone transcends the world; it is the nothing by which there are things. The Other by rising up confers on the For-itself a being-in-itself-in-themidst-of-the-world as a thing among things. This petrification in In-itself by the Others look is the profound meaning of the myth of Medusa. (430) We should notice a significant change of emphasis in comparison to Sartres early essay on Husserls idea of intentionality which ends with some enthusiastic words, in the spirit of an epistemological and ontological optimism: we discover ourselves on the highway, in the city, in the middle of the crowd, thing among things, man among men.327 Now the last three words are revealingly eliminated, and the suffocating atmosphere of reification is all-pervasive. Besides, the epistemological and ontological optimism which characterized not only the essay on Husserl but also The Transcendence of the Ego328 now becomes an existentialist target to fire at, condemning Hegel in the name of a fundamental conception of the human predicament ruled by irreconcilable conflict:
In the first place Hegel appears to us to be guilty of an epistemological optimism. It seems to him that the truth of self-consciousness can appear; that is, that an objective agreement can be realized between consciousnessesby authority of the Others recognition of me and my recognition of the Other. (240) . . . But there is in Hegel another and more fundamental form of optimism. This may be called an ontological optimism. For Hegel indeed truth is truth of the Whole. And he places himself at the vantage point of truthi.e., of the Wholeto consider the problem of the Other. . . . individual consciousnesses are moments in the whole, moments which by themselves are unselbstndig (dependent), and the whole is a mediator between consciousnesses. Hence is derived an ontological

198

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

optimism parallel to the epistemological optimism: plurality can and must be surpassed toward the totality. (243) . . . [By contrast] . . . the sole point of departure is the interiority of the cogito. . . . No logical or epistemological optimism can cover the scandal of the plurality of consciousnesses. If Hegel believed that it could, this is because he never grasped the nature of that particular dimension of being which is self-consciousness. . . . [For] even if we could succeed in making the Others existence share in the apodictic certainty of the cogitoi.e., of my own existencewe should not thereby surpass the Other toward any inter-monad totality. So long as consciousnesses exist, the separation and conflict of consciousnesses will remain. (244)

Thus, the plurality of consciousnesses is a scandal and conflict is a primary and insurmountable ontological condition. Conflict is the original meaning of being-for-others, (364) and unity with the Other is radically impossible. (365) The relationship is conceived in the formal structure of reciprocity, understood as symmetry, obliterating the dimension of an actual social-historical genesis. I seek to enslave the Other, the Other seeks to enslave me. (364) The plain and bitterly unpalatable truth of the matter is, though, that in actual history only one side of the allegedly symmetrical conflict is successful in enslaving the other, and even then not in virtue of some abstract formally structured ontological reciprocity, but becauseas a matter of brute existencehe historically gains control of the conditions of work and thus destroys even the semblance of formal reciprocity, instituting the structure of domination not as an ontological imperative but as a historically persistent, and therefore at least in principle also historically surmountable, set of actual social relations. Sartres formal reciprocity, however, which is constituted on the ontological premise of antagonistically opposed individual thisesmuch like Hobbess bellum omnium contra omnescan only be depicted as a fateful existential-ontological circle: the circle of relations with the Other. (408) My project of recovering myself is fundamentally a project of absorbing the Other, (364) but the formal structure of reciprocity makes sure that the project fails and perpetually reproduces itself as unrealizable, thus a priori denying all possibility of escape from the ontologically dignified circle. The idea of a dialectical relationship with the Other is categorically rejected in favor of the existential circularity, stipulating that we can never get outside the circle, (363) as we have already seen. And even the most fundamental strategies of escape, sadism and masochism, are condemned to futility. Nor does hate fare any better:

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

199

Hate does not enable us to get out of the circle. It simply represents the final attempt of despair. After the failure of this attempt nothing remains for the For-itself except to re-enter the circle and allow itself to be indefinitely tossed from one to the other of the two fundamental attitudes. (412)

If the fundamental ontological conditions and determinations are depicted in this way, how could the idea of an ethic of deliverance and salvation, achieved after a radical conversion which we cannot discuss here, (412) be more than a gratuitous postulate encapsulated in a three line footnote? For how could my radical conversion329 fundamentally change the ontological structure of being which is defined as a priori incompatible with the idea of a change, in the sharpest possible contrast to the psychological experience of an historic man? (429) And what about the Other? In this respect either I must envisage the simultaneous radical conversion of allwhich is a priori rejected eleven pages after the three line footnote as an abstract, unrealizable project of the For-itself toward an absolute totalization of itself and of all others (423)or I must take refuge in the mythical idea of the instant, coupled with the enthusiasm for the equally mythical Apocalypse, an idea that appears in Sartres work immediately after the war. As things stand in Being and Nothingness, the existential-ontological circle defines the character and limits of the human enterprise:
We work to live and we live to work. The question of the meaning of the totality life-workWhy do I work, I who am living? Why live if it is in order to work?this can be posited only on the reflective level since it implies a self-discovery on the part of the For-itself. (201)

This passage follows Sartres description of the roof repairers workclothes as an example of how the being-for-others refers us to the infinite regress of instrumental complexes, pictured as a chain of which the for whom is merely a link incapable of breaking the chain itself. Understandably, therefore, the ontological determination of the structures of reification confines the search for meaning to the reflective level of a discovery of ones own incomparable uniqueness. And this is where the limitations of the individualistic stance become painfully visible. For obviously the chain of capitalistic reification must be broken if I want to constitute a meaning which is refused to me within the circle, while, to be sure, it is impossible to envisage the realization of this task through a purely individual action.

200

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Sartre is, of course, far too great a thinker to settle for such an absurdly individualistic solution, which would elevate Don Quixote to the stature of all positive heroes of world literature rolled into one, from Hercules and El Cid to Figaro and to Stendhals Julien Sorel. Sartres sense of realism not only specifies the necessary inseparability of Don Quixote (absolute freedom) from Sancho Panza (absolute contingency and facticity), but also produces a complete fusion of the two in the stipulated identity of authentic choice with radical action: a full-blooded Don Quixote who carries in him, and not just with him, his Sancho Panza. (No danger, therefore, of a head-on collision with the windmill of society. Our fused hero is not interested in the success of freedominsisting that success is not important to freedom but in the abstract possibility of action. And he can always succeed in acting. For whatever he does or does not do is always necessarily an action, even when it all amounts to no more than the choice of refusing to choose.) But even so, the enterprise remains problematical. For ones individual self-discovery, no matter how authentic the choice, cannot significantly affect the massive structures of domination, with all their antagonisms and instrumental complexes. This is why the search for meaning cannot be made intelligible purely on the reflective level: the terrain of isolated individuality. We work to live and we live to work is not just a circle, but the most vicious of all conceivable vicious circles in the circumstances of alienated labour, precisely because as the circularity of a brute existent it constitutes the material foundation of all domination, and hence is radically incompatible with a meaningful life. Thus the search for meaning is identical with breaking the vicious circle of alienated self-objectification, which implies not a self-discovery on the part of the For-itself but the practical breaking up and radical restructuring of the whole immense chain of instrumental complexes in relation to which the isolated individual in all his incomparable uniqueness is nothing but a helpless victim. And given the sheer size of the undertaking, not to mention its inherent character, this means that the realization of the task involved can only be envisaged as a radical intervention at the level of social praxis, with the aim of bringing under conscious social control the crucial material, human, institutional and instrumental determinations: a task which implies a viable social consciousness in charge of the situation, in contrast to the purely individual self-consciousness concerned with its own authentic self-discovery on the reflective-contemplative level. However, the world of Being and Nothingness is radically incompatible with this social consciousness. Setting out from the ontological solitude of

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

201

the For-itself, the existence of the Other is established at the price of identifying objectivity with alienation and stipulating the absolute insurmountability of this alienation:
My original fall is the existence of the Other. . . . I grasp the Others look at the very center of my act as the solidification and alienation of my own possibilities. (263) . . . my possibility becomes probability which is outside me. (265) Thus being-seen constitutes me as a defenseless being for a freedom which is not my freedom. . . . this slavery is not a historical result capable of being surmounted. (267) My being for-others is a fall through absolute emptiness toward objectivity. (2745) Shame is the feeling of an original fall, . . . I have fallen into the world in the midst of things and I need the mediation of the Other in order to be what I am. (289) . . . by the fact of the Others existence, I exist in a situation which has an outside and which due to this very fact has a dimension of alienation which I can in no way remove from the situation any more than I can act directly upon it. This limit to my freedom is, as we see, posited by the Others pure and simple existence. (510) Thus the very meaning of our free choice is to cause a situation to arise which expresses this choice, a situation the essential characteristic of which is to be alienated; that is, to exist as a form in itself for the Other. We cannot escape this alienation since it would be absurd to think of existing otherwise than in situation. (526)

How could one get out of the circle through solidarity arising on the foundation of a shared predicament if the pure and simple existence of the Other turns objectivity into permanent slavery by defining the essence of all situation as alienation? How could one even conceptualize the possibility of a social struggle against reified objectivity if reification is given the ontological dignity of solidification and petrification as contained in the profound meaning of the myth of Medusa?330 And how could one envisage an end to the helplessness of isolated individuality through a dialectical reciprocity and mediation with others if the dialectic of reciprocity is turned into a self-defeating circularity, and mediation is a priori condemned as the Other in my very being, after I have mythically fallen through absolute emptiness into the objectivity-alienation-petrification of my situation? By adopting the standpoint of anarchistic individualism, Sartre imposes on himself the characteristic limitations of this framework as a range of possible conceptualizations to the exclusion of others: an approach the salient feature of which is the a priori rejection of the possibility of a historical

202

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

suppression of alienation through a conscious social disentanglement of objectivity from reification, in a radical reversal of the original historical process of entanglement corresponding to the unconscious condition of human development hitherto. Sartres individualistic stance, however, deprives him of the conceptual tools required for envisaging a solution to such problems. In the conceptual framework of Being and Nothingness the possibility of a genuine collective consciousness is an a priori non-starter, since self-consciousness is by definition purely individual, and the idea of an unconscious is categorically rejected already at the level of individual consciousness. Thus we can see again that Sartre goes in a direction diametrically opposed to Marxs way of developing the problems. While he adopts the Hegelian identification of alienation and objectivity, which is inherently ahistorical, he goes a great deal further, liquidating even the remnants of historicity from these relations by declaring the emptiness of the concept of a historically developing humanity. Anticipating Althussers laments by more than two decades Sartre writes:
But if God is characterized as radical absence, the effort to realize humanity as ours is forever renewed and forever results in failure. Thus the humanistic Usthe Us-objectis proposed to each individual consciousness as an ideal impossible to attain although everyone keeps the illusion of being able to succeed in it by progressively enlarging the circle of communities to which he does belong. This humanistic Us remains an empty concept, a pure indication of a possible extension of the ordinary usage of the Us. Each time that we use the Us in this sense (to designate suffering humanity, sinful humanity, to determine an objective historical meaning by considering man as an object which is developing its potentialities) we limit ourselves to indicating a certain concrete experience to be undergone in the presence of the absolute Third; that is, of God. Thus the limiting concept of humanity (as the totality of the Us-object) and the limiting concept of God imply one another and are correlative. (423)

The fact is, though, that humanity as ours does very much exist in alienated form and practically asserts itself as world history through the world market and the division of labour on a world scale.331 Furthermore, the concept of man developing his potentialities does not imply in the least the formulation of an impossible ideal, viewed from the illusory standpoint of the absolute Third, God, but requires grasping the disconcerting reality of the structures of domination in the dynamic process of their objective unfolding and potential

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

203

dissolution, from the standpoint of a self-developing collective subject.332 In the absence of such social consciousness the structures of alienation remain in dominance over against the isolated individual who is lost in the jungle of an unstructured totality and the infinite regress of instrumental complexes. And history, deprived of its fundamental dimension of continuity in change and change in continuity through the categorical negation of the possibility of an actual collective subject, ceases to exist in a meaningful sense of the term and becomes an ontologically insignificant dimension of individual existence, affecting only the thinnest layer of the psychological surface. The multiplicity of individual ventures cannot be united even at a given point in time: how could it be united then through history? Human agency is conceived as purely individual, and the direction of a series of actions is defined through the structural coherence of the primary and secondary structures of the fundamental project. As to change, or indeed radical change, we are presented with the mysterious moment or instant which is put forward to provide its own explanation in virtue of its simple occurrence, without any possibility of prior determinations. The definition of the human enterprise as a strictly individual venture and the radical negation of the possibility of a meaningful social consciousness arising on the real ground of history leaves us with the ultimate Fourth: the contemplative philosopher whonegating the position of the absolute Third and its necessary correlative, the humanistic Usannounces the deepest ontological meaning of the human reality: man is a useless passion. And he does that by directly identifying isolated individuality with the universality of ontological manin sharp contrast to the alienated objectivity of historical man representing the degraded mediation of the For-itself with the Otherby stipulating a fundamental symbolic relationship of equivalence between the two. In the context of Sartres individualistic presuppositions, the ontological solitude of the For-itself and the essentially degraded character of the Others mediatory function, there can be no other way than that. There can be no genuine social consciousness, not only at the level of humanity as ours but equally in the domain of class relations. We are either confronted with the direct symbolic manifestations of allegedly profound ontological relationships, or with the psychological experience of historic man. Accordingly, the idea of class consciousness is relegated to the position of a derivative and strictly psychological experience which cannot significantly affect the fundamental ontological relations:

204

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Class consciousness is evidently the assuming of a particular Us on the occasion of a collective situation more plainly structured than usual. . . . the situation of the oppressing classes presents the oppressed classes with the image of a perpetual Third who considers them and transcends them by his freedom. (420) The primary fact is that the member of the oppressed collectivity, who as a simple person is engaged in fundamental conflicts with other members of this collectivity (love, hate, rivalry of interests, etc.) apprehends his condition and that of other members of this collectivity as looked-at, and thought-about by a consciousness which escapes him. . . . I discover the Us in which I am integrated or the class outside, in the look of the Third, and it is this collective alienation which I assume when saying Us. (421) The oppressed class can, in fact, affirm itself as a We-subject only in relation to the oppressing class. (422) But the experience of the We remains on the ground of individual psychology and remains a simple symbol of the longed-for unity of transcendences. . . . the subjectivities remain out of reach and radically separated. (425) . . . the experience of the We-subject has no value as a metaphysical revelation; it depends strictly on the various forms of the for-others and is only an empirical enrichment of certain of these forms. It is to this fact evidently that we should attribute the extreme instability of this experience. It comes and disappears capriciously, leaving us in the face of others-as-objects or else of a They who look at us. . . . We should hope in vain for a human we in which the intersubjective totality would obtain consciousness of itself as a unified subjectivity. Such an ideal could be only a dream produced by a passage to the limit and the absolute on the basis of fragmentary, strictly psychological experiences. Furthermore this ideal itself implies the recognition of the conflict of transcendences as the original state of being-for-others. (428) . . . the We-subject is a psychological experience realized by an historic man immersed in a working universe and in a society of a definite economic type. It reveals nothing particular; it is a purely subjective Erlebnis (experience). . . . the We-subject is a psychological experience which supposes one way or another that the Others existence as such has been already revealed to us. It is therefore useless for humanity to seek to get out of this dilemma: one must either transcend the Other or allow oneself to be transcended by him. The essence of the relations between consciousnesses is not the Mitsein (being-with); it is conflict. (429)

Here we have a succession of extremely problematical principles which spell out the hermeneutic of existence on the social plane as a system of total immobility. In this system the collective situation is not a primary ontological condition but merely an occasion in relation to which the

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

205

consciousness of a particular Us may be assumed if the situation is more plainly structured than usual. (What makes it become more plainly structured we are never told.) This derivative situation is contrasted with the primary fact of fundamental conflicts (love, hate, rivalry of interests, etc.) in which all individuals are involved (bellum omnium contra omnes) as a matter of ontological determination, and therefore any conceivable solidarity of the members of the oppressed class, who are among themselves necessarily torn by ontologically fundamental conflicts, must remain secondary, hopelessly unstable, and ultimately illusory. Furthermore, collective situation is not an objective determination but merely an assumed one which I bring upon myself when I say Us under the gaze of the perpetual Third.333 Consequently, the We-subject, in its capricious instability must necessarily posit the permanence of the oppressing class on which it structurally depends in this upside-down-ontology of Being and Nothingness, in sharp contrast even to Hegels insights on this point in his account of the Master-Slave relationship, not to mention Marx. This means that we are forever locked into the structures of the class-initself 334 which derives its identity and consciousness from its mere negation of the opposing class, and the constitution of the class-for-itself 335 through which an end to class antagonism and class existence may be envisaged is declared to be a priori impossible. The experience of collective solidarity is confined to individual psychology, and the inherent contradiction is explained away by gratuitously suggesting a symbolic relationship of identity between this paradoxical manifestation of individual psychology and longing for the impossible unity of radically separate transcendences. The strictly psychological character of these relations is reiterated again and again, and it is sharply contrasted with the original state of being-for-others defined as insoluble conflict to be perpetually acted out within the confines of the existential-ontological circle. Thus the psychological experiences of historic man, trapped in a working universe of (by definition) alienated objectivity, yield the inescapability of impotence as a degraded mirror-image of the ultimate ontological uselessness of human passion. But again we should ask the question: how could all this be different on the assumed premise of the ontological solitude of the For-itself which stipulates the a priori impossibility of a unity of the self with others through meaningful social mediation? So long as totality is defined as an internal ontological relation of thises which can be revealed only in and through the individual thises, (180) and so long as the human reality is conceived as

206

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

a detotalized totality which temporalizes itself in a perpetual incompleteness, (180) just as long all possible combinations for the For-itself with others must remain secondary and problematical. The a priori rejection of interpersonal-social mediation as objectivity-alienation condemns the possibility of combinations to the futility of mere exteriority (while in fact one would need a precise definition of the criteria which can separate the meaningful combinations from their reified counterparts) and dismisses the idea of constituting ontologically significant relationships on their basis:
Being a group of three is not a concrete property of the group. Neither is it a property of its members. . . . The relation of quantity is therefore a relation of In-itself but a purely negative and external relation. . . . it is isolated and detached from the surface of the world as a reflection (reflet) of nothingness cast on being. (191)

But since the relation of quantity is a necessary prerequisite of the constitution of a viable social mediation and collective consciousness, the step from the self-oriented one to the self-conscious many surely amounts not to a purely negative and external relation but to the challenging positivity of a different kind of internal relation: one made possible by the dialectic of quantity and quality inherent in an effective social mediation. Consequently, it cannot be subsumed under the model of a detotalized totalization of the individual thises aimed at preserving in the unrealizable totality of an impossible unification the incomparable uniqueness of the ontologically solitary For-itself. By contrast, in the framework of Sartres individualistic ontological presuppositions the step from the I to the We that appears in our freedom itself creates the obstacles from which we suffer (495) represents an arbitrary conflation of the individual and collective subjects into an entity of extreme ambiguity: a quasi-collective subject336 which becomes intelligible only as an inherently historical being, and yet he transcends all history in the abstract-ontological discourse on absolute freedom and absolute responsibility. And the procedure which produces this ahistorical and curiously plural subject is all the more suspect since Sartre dismisses the We-subject of actual social-historical action as a strictly psychological experience totally devoid of a proper ontological status. If, as Sartre admits, his proposed method for an existential psychoanalysis leaves much to be desired, this is not simply, as he suggests, because everything remains to be done in this field, (457) but because the problematical character of the methodological principles themselves inherent in

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

207

its ontological standpoint. The assertions that in each inclination, in each tendency the person expresses himself completely (363) in that each drive or tendency is the entire person (364) may well agree with the principle according to which the being of the For-itself is an individual venture and the choice of the For-itself is always the choice of a concrete situation in an incomparable uniqueness, (598) but they produce a method of analysis which tends to disintegrate in the interminable particularization337 of a bad infinity (Hegel). The definition of the original project as the center of reference for an infinity of polyvalent meanings (570) is coupled with the idea that the For-itself in its freedom invents not only primary and secondary ends; by the same stroke it invents the whole system of interpretations which allows their interconnections. . . . the subject must furnish his touchstone and his personal criteria. (471) Accordingly, the analyst will have to rediscover at each step a symbol functioning in the particular case which he is considering. (573) For the choice is living and consequently can be revoked by the subject who is being studied. [Revoked through] abrupt changes in orientation. . . . Our concern here is to understand what is individual and often even instantaneous. The method which has served for one subject will not necessarily be suitable for another subject or for the same subject at a later period. (573) Needless to say, it is the rejection of a dialectical social mediation which brings with it the dispersive particularization of this method. And the latter, far from following the way in which the subject itself is supposed to invent the appropriate system of interpretations and provide his personal touchstone and his personal criteria, ends up, on the contrary, inventing for the subject a quasi-fictional framework of interpretation, as Sartre himself is later forced to admit338 with respect to the actual realization of his long-standing project on Flaubert.339 The methodologically explicit rejection of generalization produces both the dispersive particularization of the underlying ontological generalities of the claimed fundamental choice of being,340 as well as the quasi-fictional framework of interpretation, which in Sartres own words invents even the subject, in a desperate attempt at encapsulating the bad infinity of dispersive particularization in a world of its own invention. Thus even in this respect the adoption of an extreme individualistic standpoint makes Sartre pay very dearly for maintaining the absolute ontological primacy of solitude over against the merely psychological experience of historic man and his social mediations.

208

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

PA R A D OXIC AL LY, HOWEVER, SO ME O F TH E GREATEST IN S I G H TS of Sartres philosophy arise on the same ground in Being and Nothingness as its problematical features. And while it is certainly true that the historical and social dimension would greatly enhance their significance, it is equally arguable that Sartres conscious distancing of himself from the prevailing social and historical theories was an essential condition of the production of these insights. In this respect the profoundly imaginative depiction of the complex manifestations of individual existence in Sartres eidetic of bad faith which we have looked at need not detain us here any further, save just to mention that his almost fanatical insistence on the freedom of the For-itself was an essential condition of undertaking at all such an enquiry in the circumstances of apparently uncontrollable collective forces. We must now look, even if only briefly, at some less obvious instances, in which Sartres insights are produced in virtue of the vantage point of his ontological presuppositions, and not in spite of them. Furthermore it must be stressed that these acquisitions of Sartrean philosophy do not simply provide a welcome corrective to the prevailing varieties of mechanical vulgar Marxism but represent a potential enrichment even to the most subtle dialectical approach. The fact that there is no evidence of a serious acquaintance with Marxs thought in Being and Nothingness, indeed that the available evidence shows rather the opposite,341 need not concern us here. For it makes even more remarkable Sartres achievements, arising almost in isolation in the process of single-mindedly carrying to the utmost conclusions the far-reaching implications of his own ontological principles. The first point concerns the definition of the human reality in relation to the whole network of instrumental complexesfrom the most primitive tools to the monstrous materiality of the crowd-instrument without which human existence is simply inconceivable. While the necessary social-historical embeddedness of all instrumentality cannot be stressed enough, there is also a dimension of instrumentality as such which transcends all particular phases of history, in a transhistorical (but by no means suprahistorical) sense. Understandably, the historical conditions under which Marxist theory was originally constituted pushed this transhistorical dimension into the background. However, the original historical contingency cannot change the fact that an adequate treatment of this dimension is a vital part of elaborating a coherent theory of instrumentality without which even the most dedicated social enterprise is bound to remain under the threat of utter failure. To be

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

209

sure, Sartre tends to emphasize only this dimension, or rather, he tends to transform all aspects of instrumentality into an ahistorically defined ontological dimension. None the less, through his overpowering stand against the almost universally prevailing tide, he achieves in this respect single-handed more than anyone else in the twentieth century. The same goes for the problematic of the instant. We have seen the dubious uses to which Sartre puts this concept in Being and Nothingness in order to fill the immense lacunae produced by the missing social dimension of his ontology. Nevertheless, his recurrent amplification of the ontological importance of the instant pushes to the forefront of our attention a major factor without which the structure of historical change itself remains unintelligible. Naturally, the category has important individual and social applications whose manifold specificities cannot be subsumed under a single model. And, of course, an adequate solution presupposes its treatment in the dialectic of continuity and change for which one would look in vain in Being and Nothingness. But again, what we actually do find there is both illuminating and challenging enough to provide a major inspiration to some long overdue research. For it is not enough to insist on the necessary social conditions of a radical historical change. Stalinism simply assumed the radical novelty of its own reality, while its opponents, like Lukcs, tended to overemphasize the element of continuity in historical change. Sartres great insight, which insists both on the being of the instant as a structure sui generis and on its structuring function as the center of reference of the new fundamental project, offers a great deal for a better understanding of social causation and social consciousness. The assessment of the nature of structural dependency is closely connected with the previous point. We have seen Sartres problematical approach to interpersonal and social relations and its consequences for the articulation of his philosophy as a whole. And yet, in his analysis of the way in which the Other determines me, he suddenly confronts us with a tremendous insight: Our relation is not a frontal opposition but rather an oblique interdependence. (246) We must appreciate the importance of this insight in contrast to many theories which picture social conflict on the model of a frontal opposition and heavily contribute to the generation of necessarily disappointed expectations. But surely, the concept of a historically irreconcilable structural antagonism should not be confused with that of a frontal opposition. Oblique interdependence is not only thoroughly compatible with the persistence of an objective structural antagonism but may very well

210

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

constitute its fundamental modality, as Sartre tells us. Indeed, the real explanatory value of the instant is precisely this, that it suggest a radical restructuring of the normally prevailing modality of oblique interdependence into the transient modality of frontal opposition: a restructuring both on the plane of the key material and instrumental complexes and at the level of social consciousness. An adequate social strategy, arising on the basis of a correct historical understanding, requires the precise definition of the moment of a major historic change together with its before and after, in terms of the complex modalities of the prevailing structural relations and their dialectical transformations. History has its structures just as much as anything else: if this were not the case, it would hopelessly escape us. Thus whatever we may think of the defects of Sartres conception of history, insights like the one just quoted on no frontal opposition but oblique interdependencewhich paradoxically arise out of an individualistic project of defining his own position in the form of an equidistance from the major social forces, ontologically fixing their relations in the ahistorical immobility of the existential circlerepresent a major contribution to a deepening historical understanding. The final point in this survey concerns the problem of appropriation. And this is where we can see perhaps most clearly the way in which the individualistic stance produces the paradoxical unity of the depth of Sartres insights and the limitations which determine the various conceptual combinations, including the symbolic claims of his existential heuristic. Reflecting on the problem of appropriation from the standpoint of a radical individualism, Sartre perceives an elemental contradiction between ownership and utilization: an insight which would be obviously denied to all those who situate themselves at the standpoint of a utilitarian liberalism. Since, however, Sartre cannot transcend his ontological presuppositions, he produces a characteristic solution of this contradiction:
ownership appears to the owner simultaneously as something given at one stroke in the eternal and as requiring an infinite time to be realized. No particular act of utilization really realizes the enjoyment of full possession. . . . handing over a banknote is enough to make the bicycle belong to me, but my entire life is needed to realize this possession. In acquiring the object, I perceive that possession is an enterprise which death always renders still unachieved. Now we can understand why; it is because it is impossible to realize the relations symbolized by appropriation.

F R E E DOM AND PAS S ION

211

In itself appropriation contains nothing concrete. It is not a real activity (such as eating, drinking, sleeping) which could serve in addition as a symbol for a particular desire. It exists, on the contrary, only as a symbol; it is its symbolism which gives it its meaning, its coherence, its existence. There can be found in it no positive enjoyment outside its symbolic value; it is only the indication of a supreme enjoyment of possession (that of the being which would be its own foundation), which is always beyond all the appropriative conducts meant to realize it. (5923)

Thus the symbolic solution of the insoluble contradiction between the eternality of the act of ownership and the disintegrating limitedness of appropriation in the particular acts of utilization becomes the paradigm of Sartres explanatory framework. The ultimate meaning of the human reality is, as we have seen above, the appropriation of being in the form of the world. Since, however, appropriation cannot be other than symbolic, my appropriative relation to being must be also symbolic in every significant respect. Thus we are given a heuristic framework in the form of symbolic relations which both pinpoint (even denounce) and at the same time preserve the inherent contradictions. The ultimate meaning of the human reality is tantamount to revealing the insoluble character of contradictions (hence all the categories of unrealizable totality, impossible unification, impossible ideal, insoluble dilemma of radically separated transcendences, the circle of relations with the Other, and the like): which is both profoundly true and thoroughly problematical. For it is true only with a vital social-historical qualification which, however, appears to Sartre as ontologically insignificant in the form of historic man immersed in a working universe of a definite economic type. And the missing element of the theory speak equally loud. For, in truth, the world which we must appropriate must also be produced, in the dialectic mode of a productive appropriation and appropriative production. And while it is still plausible to envisage the act of appropriation as a symbolic act of isolated individuality, the production of the world as a totality of appropriative relations and corresponding objects cannot conceivably be envisaged from the standpoint of an isolated individuality. Thus work appears in Sartres writings only marginally, if at all (tellingly, its instances are confined to some highly selective individualistic manifestations, from the waiter to the roof-repairer, both productive only in the sense of being producers of surplus value in the economically tertiary sphere of services) and the working universe occupies an ontologically insignificant status, in the

212

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

sharpest possible contrast to the fundamental ontological significance of symbolic appropriation. There is an alternative solution, namely an approach according to which the act of appropriation need not be conceived as a symbolic act if we remove the contradiction between ownership and utilization through the abolition of exclusive ownership and the simultaneous accessibility of utilization to all, together with the harmonization of the totality of actual appropriative relations with the totality of productive relations in the self-realization of the transindividual and transhistorical subject. But such a solution is radically incompatible with the ontological horizons of Being and Nothingness, no matter how intensely it is animated in its search for freedom by an authentic passion.
AS WE C AN S E E , T HE N, SA RTRES UND ERTA KING produces as many illuminating insights as major question marks, in a synthesis full of tensions. No one is supposed to feel comfortable in the presence of his conclusions, least of all the author himself. The restlessness of the determination to move forward appears to be an integral part of his fundamental project. How far can Sartre go in his postwar development in resolving the tensions we have encountered in his ontological framework, and to what extent is it possible for him to modify his original ontological conception through the experience of society and the challenge of history? The investigation of these questions will be the task of Part Three.

A Note on B EING

AND

N OTHINGNESS

Here is a representative selection of metaphorical imagery in the order in which the particular metaphorical concepts appear in Being and Nothingness. They were originally printed as endnote 294 in the first edition of this book.
Consciousness is a plenum of existence. (XXXI) the preceding reflections have permitted us to distinguish two absolutely separate regions of being; . . . two regions without communication. (XXXIX) being is opaque to itself precisely because it is filled with itself. (XLI) The necessary condition for our saying not is that non-being be a perpetual presence in us and outside of us, that nothingness haunt being. (11) Negation cannot touch the nucleus of Being, which is absolute plenitude and entire positivity. By contrast Non-being is a negation which aims at this nucleus of absolute density. Non-being is denied at the heart of being. (15) Non-being exists only on the surface of being. (16) Nothingness carries being in its heart. (18)

214

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

If I emerge in nothingness beyond the world, how can this extra-mundane nothingness furnish a foundation for those little pools of non-being which we encounter each instant in the depth of being? (19) There is an infinite number of realities which are not only objects of judgement, but which in their inner structure are inhabited by negation, as by a necessary condition of their existence. (21) Nothingness lies coiled in the heart of beinglike a worm. (21) The questioner nihilates himself in relation to the thing questioned by wrenching himself from being in order to be able to bring out of himself the possibility of non-being. (23) Human freedom precedes essence in man and makes it possible; the essence of the human being is suspended in his freedom. (25) Every psychic process of nihilation implies then a cleavage between the immediate psychic past and the present. This cleavage is precisely nothingness. (27) Freedom is the human being putting his past out of play by secreting his own nothingness. (28) Anguish is precisely my consciousness of being my own future, in the mode of not-being. (32) The immediate is the world with its urgency and in this world where I engage myself, my acts cause values to spring up like partridges. (38) Bad Faith provides us with a permanent game of excuses. (40) If I am anguish in order to flee it, that presupposes that I can decenter myself in relation to what I am, that I can be anguish in the form of not-being it, that I can dispose of a nihilating power at the heart of anguish itself. (44) a perpetually disintegrating synthesis and a perpetual game of escape from the For-itself to the For-others and from the For-others to the Foritself. (58) One puts oneself in bad faith as one goes to sleep and one is in bad faith as one dreams. Once this mode of being has been realized, it is as difficult to get out of it as to wake oneself up. (68)

A N OT E ON B E IN G AN D N OTH INGNESS

215

This perpetual act by which the In-itself degenerates into presence to itself we shall call an ontological act. (79) as a perpetually evanescent totality, being-in-itself must be given as the evanescent contingency of my situation. (83) the contingency which paralyzes these motivations to the same degree as they totally found themselves is the facticity of the For-itself. (83-4) Facticity resides in the For-itself as a memory of being, as its unjustifiable presence in the world. (84) Value is everywhere and nowhere; at the heart of the nihilating relation reflection-reflecting, it is present and out of reach, and it is simply lived as the concrete meaning of that lack which makes my present being. (95) We shall use the expression Circuit of Selfness for the relation of the Foritself with the possible which it is, and world for the totality of being in so far as it is traversed by the Circuit of Selfness. (102) The world is mine because it is haunted by possibles. (104) memory presents to us the being which we were, accompanied by a plenitude of being which confers on it a sort of poetry. That grief which we hadalthough fixed in the pastdoes not cease to present the meaning of a For-itself, and yet it exists in itself with the silent fixity of the grief of another, the grief of a statue. (119) The For-itself is present to being in the form of flight; the Present is a perpetual flight in the face of being. (123) The Future is the ideal point where the sudden infinite compression of facticity (Past), of the For-itself (Present), and of the possible (a particular future) will at last cause the Self to arise as the existence in-itself of the Foritself. (128) To be free is to be condemned to be free. (129) The mode of being of the For-itself is diasporatic. (136) the For-itself, dispersed in the perpetual game of reflected-reflecting, escapes itself in the unity of one and the same flight. Here being is everywhere and nowhere: wherever one tries to seize it, it is there before one, it has escaped.

216

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

It is this game of musical chairs at the heart of the For-itself which is presence to being. (142) Thus the time of consciousness is human reality which temporalizes itself as the totality which is to itself its own incompletion; it is nothingness slipping into a totality as a detotalizing ferment. This totality which runs after itself and refuses itself at the same time, . . . can under no circumstances exist within the limits of an instant. (149) Impure reflection is an abortive effort on the part of the For-itself to be another while remaining itself. (161) We use the term psyche for the organized totality of these virtual and transcendental existents which form a permanent cortege for impure reflection (163) The psyche object appears as an unachieved and probable totality there where the For-itself makes itself exist in the diasporatic unity of a detotalized totality. (165) It is precisely because it [quantity] does not belong to either things or to totalities that it is isolated and detached from the surface of the world as a reflection of nothingness cast on being. (191) The ideal fusion of the lacking with the one which lacks what is lacking is an unrealizable totality which haunts the For-itself and constitutes its very being as a nothingness of being. (194) Thus the world is revealed as haunted by absences to be realized, and each this appears with a cortege of absences which point to it and determine it. . . . Since each absence is being-beyond-beingi.e. an absent-initselfeach this points toward another state of its being or toward other beings. But of course this organization of indicative complexes is fixed and petrified in In-itself; hence all these mute and petrified indications, which fall back into the indifference of isolation at the same time that they arise, resemble the fixed, stony smile in the empty eyes of a statue. (199) This connection in isolation, this inert relation within the dynamic is what we call the relation of means to end. It is a being-for which is degraded, laminated by exteriority. (200) the For-itself apprehends temporality on being, as a pure reflection which plays on the surface of being without any possibility of modifying being. (206)

A N OT E ON B E IN G AN D N OTH INGNESS

217

This exteriority-to-self . . . appears as a pure disorder of being. (212) Motion is the upsurge of the exteriority of indifference at the very heart of the In-itself. This pure vacillation of being is a contingent venture of being. (213) universal time is revealed as present vacillation; already in the past it is no longer anything but an evanescent line, like the wake of a ship which fades away; in the future it is not at all, for it is unable to be its own project. It is like the steady progression of a lizard on the wall. (213) time appears as a finite, organized form in the heart of an indefinite dispersion. The lapse of time is the result of a compression of time at the heart of an absolute decompression and it is the project of ourselves toward our possibilities which realizes the compression. (215) Thus time appears through trajectories. But just as spacial trajectories decompose and collapse into pure static spaciality, so the temporal trajectory collapses as soon as it is not simply lived as that which objectively implies our expectation of ourselves . . . time is revealed as the shimmer of nothingness on the surface of a strictly a-temporal being. (216) To the extent that the Other is an absence he escapes nature. (228) Consciousnesses are directly supported by one another in a reciprocal imbrication of their being. (236) The Other is the test of my being inasmuch as he throws me outside of myself toward structures which at once both escape me and define me. (245) The appearance of the Other in the world corresponds therefore to a fixed sliding of the whole universe, to a decentralization of the world which undermines the centralization which I am simultaneously effecting. (255) it appears that the world has a kind of drain hole in the middle of its being and that it is perpetually flowing off through this hole. (256) My original fall is the existence of the Other. (263) My being for others is a fall through absolute emptiness toward objectivity. . . . Thus myself-as-object is neither knowledge nor a unity of knowledge but an uneasiness, a lived wrenching away from the ecstatic unity of the Foritself, a limit which I cannot reach and which yet I am. (275)

218

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

When objectivized the prenumerical reality of the Other is decomposed and pluralized. (282) Shame is the feeling of an original fall, not because of the fact that I may have committed this or that particular fault but simply that I have fallen into the world in the midst of things and that I need the mediation of the Other in order to be what I am. (289) Modesty and in particular the fear of being surprised in a state of nakedness are only a symbolic specification of original shame. (289) It is precisely through its results that we apprehend fear, for it is given to us as a new type of internal haemorrhage in the worldthe passage from the world to a type of magical existence. (295 Thus the Other-as-object is an explosive instrument which I handle with care because I foresee around him the permanent possibility that they are going to make it explode and that with this explosion I shall suddenly experience the flight of the world away from me and the alienation of my being. (297) The relation which I establish between the Others body and the external object are really existing relations, but they have for their being the being of the for-others; they suppose a center of intra-mundane flow in which knowledge is a magic property of space, action at a distance. (305) knowledge can be only an engaged upsurge in a determined point of view which one is. (308) the world as the correlate of the possibilities which I am appears from the moment of my upsurge as the enormous skeletal outline of all my possible actions. . . . The world is revealed as an always future hollow, for we are always future to ourselves. (322) A dull and inescapable nausea perpetually reveals my body to my consciousness. . . . We must not take the term nausea as a metaphor derived from our physiological disgust. On the contrary, we must realize that it is on the foundation of this nausea that all concrete and empirical nauseas (nausea caused by spoiled meat, fresh blood, excrement, etc.) are produced and make us vomit. (338-9) The flesh is the pure contingency of presence. (343)

A N OT E ON B E IN G AN D N OTH INGNESS

219

motion is a disorder of being. (348) this instrument which I am is made-present to me as an instrument submerged in an infinite instrumental series, although I can in no way view this series by surveying it. (352) But precisely because I exist by means of the Others freedom, I have no security; I am in danger in this freedom. It moulds my being and makes me be, it confers values upon me and removes them from me; and my being receives from it a perpetual passive escape from self. (366) In love it is not a determinism of the passions which we desire in the Other nor a freedom beyond reach; it is a freedom which plays the role of a determinism of the passions and which is caught in its own role. (367) in desire there is an attempt at the incarnation of consciousness (this is what we called earlier the clogging of consciousness, a troubled consciousness, etc.) in order to realize the incarnation of the Other. (391) The world is made ensnaring; consciousness is engulfed in a body which is engulfed in the world. (392) Desire is an attitude aiming at enchantment. Since I can grasp the Other only in his objective facticity, the problem is to ensnare his freedom with this facticity. It is necessary that he be caught in it as the cream is caught up by a person skimming milk. So the Others For-itself must come to play on the surface of his body, and be extended all through his body; and by touching this body I should finally touch the Others free subjectivity. (394) Thus the other meaning of my incarnationthat is, of my troubled disturbanceis that it is a magical language. (396) sadism and masochism are the two reefs on which desire may founder. . . . It is because of this inconsistency on the part of desire and its perpetual oscillation between these two perils that normal sexuality is commonly designated as sadistic-masochistic. (404) this explosion of the Others look in the world of the sadist causes the meaning and goal of sadism collapse. (406) The person who say Us then reassumes in the heart of the crowd the original project of love, but it is no longer on his own account; he asks a Third to save the whole collectivity in its very object-state so that he may sacrifice his

220

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

freedom to it. Here as above disappointed love leads to masochism. . . . The monstrous materiality of the crowd and its profound reality (although only experienced) are fascinating for each of its members; each one demands to be submerged in the crowd-instrument by the look of the leader. (422) When I deliberate the chips are down. . . . When the will intervenes, the decision is taken, and it has no other value than that of making the announcement. (451) By the sole fact that our choice is absolute, it is fragile. (465) If the given cannot explain the intention, it is necessary that the intention by its very upsurge realize a rupture with the given, whatever this may be. (478) my freedom eats away my freedom. (480) The For-itself discovers itself as engaged in being hemmed in by being, threatened by being. (487) the upsurge of freedom is the crystallization of an end across a given and the revelation of a given in the light of an end. (508) death is a boundary and every boundary (whether it be final or initial) is a Janus bifrons. (531) freedom enchains itself in the world as a free project toward ends. (551) man condemned to be free carries the weight of the whole world on his shoulders. (553) In knowing, consciousness attracts the object to itself and incorporates it in itself. Knowledge is assimilation . . . to know is to devour it yet without consuming it. We see here how the sexual and alimentary currents mingle and interpenetrate in order to constitute the Actaeon complex and the Jonah complex; we can see the digestive and sensual roots which are reunited to give birth to the desire of knowing. (579) all serious thought is thickened by the world; it coagulates; it is a dismissal of human reality in favor of the world. (580) sliding appears as identical with a continuous creation. The speed is comparable to consciousness and here symbolizes consciousness. (584)

A N OT E ON B E IN G AN D N OTH INGNESS

221

But creation is an evanescent concept which can exist only through its movement. If we stop it, it disappears. (591) No particular act of utilization really realizes the enjoyment of full possession, but it refers to other appropriative acts, each one of which has the value of an incantation. (592) my freedom is a choice of being God and all my acts, all my projects translate this choice and reflect it in a thousand and one ways. (599) A psychoanalysis of things and of their matter ought above all to be concerned with establishing the way in which each thing is the objective symbol of being and of the relation of human reality to this being. (603) What is the metaphysical purport of yellow, of red, of polished, of wrinkled? And after these elementary questions, what is the metaphysical coefficiency of lemon, of water, of oil, etc.? (604) slimy . . . represents in itself a dawning triumph of the solid over the liquidthat is, a tendency of the indifferent In-itself, which is represented by the pure solid, to fix the liquidity, to absorb the For-itself which ought to dissolve it. Slime is the agony of water. (607) Here we can see the symbol which abruptly discloses itself: there exists a poisonous possession; there is a possibility that the In-itself might absorb the For-itself, that is, that a being might be constituted in a manner just the reverse of the In-itself . . . Slime is the revenge of the In-itself. A sickly-sweet, feminine revenge which will be symbolized on another level by the quality sugary. (609) Thus in the project of appropriating the slimy, the sliminess is revealed suddenly as a symbol of antivalue: it is a type of being not realized but threatening which will perpetually haunt consciousness as the constant danger which it is fleeing, and hence will suddenly transform the project of appropriation into a project of flight. (611) Man is a useless passion. (615) The For-itself, in fact, is nothing but the pure nihilation of the In-itself; it is like a hole of being at the heart of being. . . . The For-itself is like a tiny nihilation which has its origin at the heart of Being; and this nihilation is sufficient to cause a total upheaval to happen to the In-itself. This upheaval is the world. (6178)

222

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

The real is an abortive effort to attain to the dignity of the self-cause. Everything happens as if the world, man, and man-in-the-world succeeded in realizing only a missing God. Everything happens as if the In-itself and the For-itself were presented in a state of disintegration in relation to an ideal synthesis. (623) Man pursues being blindly by hiding from himself the free project which is this pursuit. He makes himself such that he is waited for by all the tasks placed along his way. (626)

P A R T

T H R E E

The Challenge of History

This page intentionally left blank

Introduction
Jean-Paul Sartres direct participation in politics changed beyond recognition. As he modestly wrote about his role in the resistance movement during the war: all I did was a few errands.1 After the war the role assumed by him in politics could only be described as ever more prominently active. Indeed, for some time Sartre even maintained the idea of exercising a seminal influence in the establishment of a fully independent political movement which was supposed to assemble under a large electoral umbrella the individuals who would openly distance themselves from the political partiesin a movement naively misnamed as the R.D.R.2which could only fail, as we have seen above. Nevertheless, Sartres personal impact on political events and developments, not only in France but also internationally, could only increase in a most remarkable way almost until the last two or three years of his life. Indeed his influence continued to grow much more than that of any other intellectual in Europe, and in other parts of the world. This became possible partly through the great periodical which he founded and for many years actively edited, Les Temps Modernes, and even more so through his powerful writings conceived in the spirit of a passionate advocacy of the most radical emancipatory causes sustained by Sartre, not only in philosophical and political theory but also in the world of the theatre and the medium of the film.
A F T ER T HE S E C OND WO RLD WA R

226

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Inevitably, controversyeven of the sharpest and bitterly condemnatory kindbecame an integral part of Sartres direct involvement in political matters very soon in the aftermath of the war, carrying with it equally ferocious attacks voiced against him from opposite directions. As we have seen earlier, Sartre was denounced not only as the manufacturer of war machine against marxism3 and the Hyena of the pen,4 by one side, but also as a systematic blasphemist and a patented corruptor of youthand even as the grave-digger of the West5by the other. Naturally, in order to successfully assert the causes he went on advocating, it was very far from sufficient to defiantly rejectwhich Sartre in a most outspoken manner always didthe often prejudiced and blind condemnations leveled against him. In political terms, if he wanted to prevail, many things had to be radically reconsidered and clearly redefined by Sartre himself. A critical reexamination of his earlier political stance became unavoidable for Sartre once the illusions attached by him to the wishfully projected role of stillborn political formations like the R.D.R. had to be abandoned as a result of the increasing polarization experienced all over the world in the postwar years. For those years had precipitously brought with them the military establishment of the Atlantic Alliance of NATO and the corresponding domination of world politics by the United States of America. Thus the question arose of constituting a political force organizationally suited to counter the dangerously advancing trend toward yet another world-wide conflagrationswitching from the cold war openly pursued ever since Churchills belligerent Fulton Speech in August 1946to what ultimately could not turn out to be other than a truly catastrophic war in the age of the fully operative atomic Weapons of Mass Destruction, possessed at that time only by the United States, as proved by Hiroshima and Nagasaki.6 In Sartres view, subsequent to his rejection of the R.D.R. perspective, the only organized political movement in France capable of effectively facing up to this issue, provided that it succeeded in overcoming its past failures and contradictions deplored by Sartre already before the Second World War, was the Communist Party. And Sartre certainly hoped to greatly contribute to the positive solution of the identified contradictions through his own political and ideological influence as a militant theoretician and creative writer. Although Sartre never joined the French Communist Party as a cardcarrying member, his relationship with it greatly improved after the immediate postwar years, which were characterized by bitter controversy not only in France but also in the international communist movement. Parallel to the improvement of his relationship with the party in France in the early

I N T R O D U CT ION

227

1950s, in the same period his stature as an outstanding intellectual of the left became clearly acknowledged in the whole of Eastern Europe as well as in the Soviet Union itself. But even under the best of circumstances the rapport between Sartre and the French CP remained a rather uneasy one. Indeed, in October 1956, as a result of the French CPs totally subservient approval of the Soviet military repression of the Hungarian uprising, it resulted in a sharp condemnation of the party by Sartre, even if he tried to leave the door open to a more positive future. However, the conflicts during the Algerian war, with no significant improvement in subsequent years, were leading toward a complete break, brought about at the time of the French explosion of May 1968. Thus Sartres earlier quoted paradoxical formulation of the reasons for critically distancing himself from the party in Franceaccording to which co-operation with the Communist Party is both necessary and impossible7had to be irretrievably abandoned in the end. He considered such break absolutely necessary notwithstanding the fact that he could not indicate any real alternative to what in his own view would be required by an organizationally sustainable force fit to counter the new historical danger, as he openly admitted a year later.8
TO BE SU R E , SART R E S S EVERE critique of the strategic orientation pursued by the French Communist Party, which pointed in the direction of their ultimate break, was not initiated at the time of the military repression of the Hungarian uprising in 1956. As a matter of fact Sartre prophetically warned the CPnot after the role it played in the Hungarian October and thereafter, but way back in February 1956 9 against the far-reaching consequences of its failure to adopt the right strategic perspective and the corresponding course of action, without which it would be impossible for the party to avoid the fateful impact of the false choices following from projecting a revolution emptied of its content10 and a reformism which will end up destroying the substance of the Party.11 Ironically, the French CPwhich among the major Communist Parties of the Third International was by far the most heavily tainted with dogmatic Stalinism in its practice of emptying the revolution of its contentin due course (as if it wanted to prove Sartre unreservedly right) also ended up destroying the substance of the Party by capitulating to self-delusory reformism which had put an end even to its once noteworthy electoral effectiveness.

228

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

The year 1956 constituted a major line of demarcation in postwar history, due to the fundamental contradiction between officially announcing through Nikita Khrushchev, the General Secretary of the Soviet Party, at the Twentieth Party Congressthe much needed program of destalinization, followed by its dramatic failure to turn it into reality as painfully demonstrated by the Soviet military response to the popular uprising in Hungary. Nevertheless we were still very far from the time when the major Communist Parties in the West, including not only the French but also the Italian CP, would transform themselves into neoliberal political entities, just as traditional social democracy had done. Understandably, therefore, even after the traumatic year of 1956, Sartre was still hoping for a change for the better, trying to exercise his influence on the French Party in favor of the destalinization promised first in the USSR and then in the world communist movement in general. This is how he expressed his still remaining hope in the book-length critical essay entitled Le Fantme de Stalin, in the triple issue of Les Temps Modernes dedicated to the Hungarian uprising:
Notre programme est clair: travers cent contradictions, des luttes intestines, des massacres, la dstalinisation est en cours; cest la seule politique effective qui serve, dans le moment prsent, le socialisme, la paix, le rapprochement des partis ouvriers: avec nos resources dintellectuels, lus par des intellectuels, nous essaierons daider la dstalinisation du Parti franais.12

More or less at the same time, in theoretically more important terms, Sartres Critique of Dialectical Reason was conceived in the same spirit of attempting to bring more closely together those intellectuals who would be positively disposed toward socialism. In other words, Sartre was trying to formulate his new approach to philosophical method and history in his Critique of Dialectical Reason in order to offer a theoretical framework also politically more acceptable to the left in general. In this sense he advocated a new philosophical and historical orientation in which the once firmly asserted rejection of marxism by Sartrean existentialism could be remedied by the notion of existentialism itself becoming an ideological enclave within marxism. Accordingly, in his Problem of Method, published in September and October 1957 in Les Temps Modernes,13 he praised most generously the writing of Henri Lefbvreone of the most prominent intellectuals of the French Communist Partyfor his approach to philosophical methodology and anthropology, as we have seen above.14 The same Henri

I N T R O D U CT ION

229

Lefbvre who once crudely dismissed Sartre himself as the manufacturer of war machine against marxism.15 This could only underline the double generosity of the Sartrean praise conferred on Lefbvre in The Problem of Method. Sartres by no means simply tactical/political but in a genuine theoretical way intended redefinition of existentialism as an ideological enclave within marxism, must be the subject of a much closer scrutiny in the remaining chapters of this book.
T H E CON TAT / RYBAL K A CH RO NO LO G IE B IB LIO G RA PH IE C OM M E N T E of Les crits de Sartre indicates that the text of Questions de mthode was incorporated in the Gallimard edition of the Critique of Dialectical Reason without major changes.16 This is true, with one significant qualification. The necessary qualification concerns the removal by Sartre himself of a few lines in which the politically infuriated author of Questions de mthode sharply insulted Lukcs on the basis of an accusation leveled against the Hungarian philosopher without the slightest justification. The reason for Sartres fury was a characteristic but total misinformation communicated to him by some Hungarian emigrs who lived in Paris. According to that misinformation Lukcs, after being released from Rumanian deportation, returned to Budapest and actively supported Jnos Kdrs government set up by the Soviets in Hungary after the military repression of the uprising. As I wrote in a letter to Lukcs, posted to him from Paris in November 1957, I made Sartres acquaintance at a conference and he invited me to his home, where yesterday we had a two hours long conversation. His apartment, in rue Bonaparte near Boulevard Saint Germain, was the same one which he had to abandon later, because it was bombed by the French extreme right on the 19th of July 1961. There I told Sartre that the accusation of Lukcss capitulation after his return to Budapest was totally absurd. For, in truth, at the time Lukcs lived under house arrest, receiving the sharpest orchestrated attacks in the Hungarian press, and refused to make even a minimal concession. On the contrary, when he was threatened, he defiantly reminded Jnos Kdr in a letter addressed to him, that in Imre Nagys shortlived government (of which they both were members) Kdr himself curiously voted in favor of abandoning the East European military alliance called the Warsaw Pactwhich gave the Soviets the legalistic pretext for their military intervention on the 4th of Novemberwhereas Lukcs firmly argued and voted at the crucial ministerial meeting against taking such a fateful step. And indeed it was Lukcs who had been proved to be right.

230

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Moreover, the Hungarian philosopher behaved with the greatest moral integrity and personal courage even under the most dangerous circumstances, including the inquisition which he had to suffer, together with other members of Imre Nagys Government deported to Rumania. When he was placed there under duress and pressed to make a confession against Imre Nagy, with whom Lukcs had honorable comradely differences in approach to some political matters for many years, he forcefully retorted to his inquisitors in these words: when Imre Nagy and I are free to walk the streets of Budapest, I am willing to express with full openness my political disagreements with him; but I make no confession against my fellow-prisoner.17 In this spirit, when his close friend Zoltn Sznt yielded to inquisitorial pressure in the same setting in Rumania, and spoke out against Imre Nagy, Lukcs in the presence of other people demonstratively broke off at once his lifelong friendship with the man who inexcusably made his confession an accusation against their fellow-prisoner.18 Naturally, Sartres furious insulting words against Lukcs, already published in the first French version of Questions de mthode in Les Temps Modernes, could not be undone. But in our conversation, as I reported it to Lukcs, Sartre expressed his great regret, saying that he has been badly misled, and he promised me that he would cut out the offensive words when the book itself is published, which he actually did. The final version of the text was scheduled to appear in the Gallimard edition of Sartres Critique of Dialectical Reason, using Questions de mthode as its long introduction. And that was the versionwithout the groundlessly insulting words against Lukcswhich came to be used in the English as well as in the other foreign language translations of Sartres widely read Questions de mthode. There was also another major reason why I went to see Sartre on the 28th of November 1957. In fact I tried to do so more than two years earlier, in September 1955. Unfortunately, however, right at that time in 1955 Sartre was traveling with Simone de Beauvoir in China, and I could only discuss the matter with Francis Jeanson, then Managing Editor of Les Temps Modernes, since soon after seeing Jeanson I had to return to Hungary. The important reason at issue already in 1955 was my attempt to establish a working contact and ongoing cooperation between Sartre and Lukcs. I knew from Lukcs himself that he was most positively disposed toward an exchange, possibly even a very intensive exchange, of views and cooperation with Sartre. The need and the occasion for establishing it was even greater in 1957 than in 1955. For both Sartre and Lukcs were working in that period on very similar problems. Sartre was deeply immersed then in

I N T R O D U CT ION

231

the monumental work of the Critique of Dialectical Reason,19 of which the first volume was to appear in January 1960, with its continuation in a second volume planned for a year or two later, while Lukcs was working on his equally monumental systematic Aesthetic andwhat could only have been of especial interest to Sartreon his Ontology of Social Being. We had a positive conversation about this matter with Sartre, who was welcoming the idea of an ongoing working relationship with the Hungarian philosopher, highly respected by him,20 and he promised me that he would presently write a letter to Lukcs to establish their cooperation. A day after visiting Sartre I described this encounter in my letter sent to Lukcs, which he did receive.21 I mentioned in it also the fact that Sartre expressed his most sincere disposition to resume a positive intellectual exchange of views, expressing also his desire to publish in Les Temps Modernes a part of [Lukcss] Die Gegenwartsbedeutung des kritischen Realismus22 and through Gallimard the whole book. I was stressing at the same time in this letter to Lukcs my own conviction that we need today such an exchange of intellectual dialogue more than ever,23 adding that I imagine that by now you have received Sartres letter. Sadly, however, the potentially most fruitful cooperation between these two outstanding intellectuals of the twentieth century did not materialize. Three months later Lukcs himself wrote to me from Budapest24 that he never received the promised letter from Sartre. Naturally, this does not mean that Sartre never sent the letter in question. For precisely the years 1957-1960 constituted the period when Lukcs was under very heavy state control, and Sartres letter, which undoubtedly would have strengthened Lukcss embattled position, could have very easily disappeared in some secret archive, as numerous other documents directly related to Lukcss political and intellectual activity, going back all the way to the 1920s, did indeed actually disappear for some considerable period. If actually sent by Sartre, as promised, also this letter might one day re-emerge, like some other documents did from time to time, including the lengthy study written by Lukcs in 1925 or 1926 in defense of History and Class Consciousness25 and also the text of his famous Blum Theses. Today, after having read and re-read Sartres Critique of Dialectical Reason and Lukcss Ontology of Social Being, I am more than ever convinced that such an ongoing cooperation between their authors would have been positive to both of the major synthesizing projects which they had been working on during those critical years.

232 T H E D IF F IC U LT YE AR F O R SA RTRE

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

after his conflicts with the French Communist Party over the Soviet military response to the Hungarian popular uprising was followed by an even more traumatic period in the midst of the Algerian war. He always took a most courageous stand against the atrocities committed by the French military, exposing himself not only to repressive state measures but also to direct threats to his life. Francis Jeansonwho was truly devoted to Sartre ever since the publication of his own book on Le Problme moral et la pense de Sartre, in 194726abandoned his position in 1957 as Managing Editor of Les Temps Modernes because of his strong disagreement with Sartre over the most outspoken critique of the French CP expressed by the author of Le Fantme de Stalin concerning Hungary. During the Algerian war, however, Jeanson published with his group of militant intellectuals a clandestine monthly journal to which Sartre gave a defiant interview in June 1959 openly under his name. In this powerful interview Sartre called for the most active solidarity of the French working class with the persecuted Algerian combatants, exposing himself thereby to the danger of a trial by a military tribunal. This is how Sartre and Jeanson reconstituted their close friendship, through a deeply shared cause and the corresponding imperative of their common struggle. In the same period, Sartre forcefully sided with Henri Alleg, a most courageous militant who was fighting in clandestinity against the Algerian war and published in 1958under the title: La Question27his moving account and compelling denunciation of being tortured by the French parachutists in Algeria. Allegs work had been immediately impounded and destroyed on the order of the French Government. Indeed, the seriousness of the situation was clearly underlined by the fact that the order imposed by the Government against Henri Allegs La Question was the first such repressive measure against an intellectual work in France since the Eighteenth Century. Sartres rejoinder on the subject, entitled Une Victoire, was equally powerful. It was published in the weekly journal LExpress, on the 6th of March 1958, generating great indignation on the right and in government circles. As a result not only the March 6, 1958 issue of LExpress was immediately confiscated and destroyed but also the other publications which reprinted Sartres expression of solidarity with Alleg, in a continued defiance of the French government order, suffered the same fate. In this critical period the danger of a military coup, actively promoted by the colonizers in Algeria and in other parts of the still existing French empire, was not very far from the darkening political horizon of France, and

I N T R O D U CT ION

233

Sartre was in the forefront of all those who warned and did everything they could against it. This danger did not disappear even after General de Gaulle assumed again the Presidency of the French Republic. On the contrary, the atrocities and outrages committed by the military supporters of the colonizers in Algeria and in Indo-China continued for years, as demonstrated also by the bombing of Sartres apartment on more than one occasion, as earlier mentioned. This picture became even more complicated, and darker with regard to its personal dangers for Sartre and for his deeply committed intellectual comrades, by the worsening international situation, and especially by the far-reaching impact of the war of the United States against Vietnam. As is well known, also under such circumstances Sartre did everything possible to expose in public the fateful implications and the potentially most devastating consequences of that war, maintaining with great determination his longstanding anti-war stand. We should recall in this connection that already way back in 1951-1952 Sartre intervened on behalf of Henri Martin, who as a young soldier had to take part in the French colonial war against the people fighting for their independence in Vietnam, despite his clearly expressedbut by the military authorities rejectedconscientious objection to it. After returning to France, still a soldier in Toulon, Henri Martin wrote and distributed leaflets of protest against the French imperialist war. As a result he was sentenced to five years imprisonment by a military tribunal in Toulon. Sartres intervention in his interest was in connection with that sentence, intended by the military authorities to serve as a general deterrent. In January 1952 Sartre was stressing in his conversation with Vincent Auriol, President of the French Republic at that time, the absurd severity of the military tribunals judgement against Henri Martin. Moreover, following his encounter with Vincent Auriol, in an interview given to the journal Action Sartre underlined the moral justice of the young generations rebellion under the circumstances,28 and he played a prominent role also in publishing the collective volume on the whole issue.29 As history repeated itself a decade later, replacing the military oppression of French colonialism in Indo-China with the new form of global hegemonic imperialism embodied in the United States of America and its escalating war against Vietnam, Sartre condemned in the strongest possible terms the continuing colonial military aggression against the Vietnamese people. He raised his voice in every way he could, forcefully presiding over the Bertrand Russell Tribunal which pilloried the principal political figures who supported the imperialist military adventures as war criminals.

234

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Sartres tireless advocacy of the fundamental progressive social and political causes were pursued with absolute consistency and growing intensity throughout the postwar period. Understandably, his passionate militancy generated the vituperative fury of the conservative and reactionary forces in France. But nothing could deter him from taking the side, in the clearest possible terms, of the persecuted and the oppressed whenever people asked for his support, as they continued to do. Not even when his personal safety was quite obviously at stake. At the height of the conflict arising from the Algerian war and of its sharply divisive aftermath, the most reactionary representatives of the French state authorities wanted to induce General de Gaulle to order Sartres imprisonment. It is a measure of de Gaulles stature that he brushed them aside in no uncertain way by saying: one doesnt arrest Voltaire!
SA RT R E S N E E D TO R E C O NSID ER H IS CO NCEPTIO N O F H I STORY in terms of its painfully tangible reality, with its explosive conflicts and social determinations, was closely connected with his witnessing how the cold war was being transformed into hot war in different parts of the world, foreshadowing the obvious danger of humanitys total destruction as the ultimate implication of the unfolding developments. In France the political polarization in the early 1950s assumed the form of imprisoning major political figures of the left, like Alain Le Lap, the General Secretary of the oldest and most influential trade union movement, the C.G.T., and even the arrest of some high-ranking communist politicians with parliamentary immunity, like Jacques Duclos, who took an active part in organizing the demonstration against General Ridgway in Paris on May 28, 1952. As for the unforgivable crime of the imprisoned C.G.T. General Secretary, it was decreed to be his demoralization of the nation, on the ground that he was opposed to the French colonial war in Vietnam.30 This was the period when the relationship between Sartre and the Communist Party greatly improved. The reason why Sartre sought the improvement was inseparable from his concern for finding an organizationally effective ground for countering the dangerous trend toward another global conflagration and thereby the annihilation of humanity. This stand by Sartre represented, since 1949, a critical and also deeply self-critical position, acknowledging the irreversible failure of the R.D.R. as a feasible independent political force, and explicitly distancing himself at the same time also from the illusory promotion of the American Gary Daviss movement calling itself the Citizens of the World. That movement was naively

I N T R O D U CT ION

235

favored and even actively promoted in France by Albert Camus, a great writer and the editor of the journal Combat, but judged with utmost scepticism by Sartre himself.31 In protest against the growing military rearmament, the Atlantic Pact, the ongoing wars in the Far East, and the threat of another global war, Sartre joined the World Peace Movement and wrote a series of very long critical articles entitled Les Communistes et la Paix, published originally in several issues of Les Temps Modernes and made available much later in English by Hamish Hamilton in the volume: The Communists and Peace: With an Answer to Claude Lefort.32 In this series of combative articles Sartre was castigating with extreme sarcasm not only the accommodatory position of the traditional social democratic forces but also the contradictory and utterly unreal attentism of the sectarian left which failed to take seriously the great danger of humanitys potential destruction. This is how Sartre summed up his position at the end of the second article of Les Communistes et la Paix,33 published in Les Temps Modernes in October-November 1952:
Already it is whispered, Are you mad! To want an independent left linked with the Party! Do you want the Party to recover its influence over the masses? If not, let well alone, quietly; leave the disintegration to go on; one day the Party will fall to pieces. Fortunately things have not yet reached that point: but when they are at their worst and if you are the irreconcilable enemy of the Party, I cannot prevent myself from finding despicable those who wait for Communist collapse through the workers despair. I am told that the worker will pull himself together. . . . If you are to be believed, there is no occasion for anxiety. In twenty, fifty years, we shall see arise a new reborn proletariat. In short, patience is the thing: after all, life is not so bad, and anti-Communism pays. Good. Let us wait then. Twenty years, if you like. Unless, in six months, the Third World War breaks out. In which event it may well be that there will be no one at the meeting place: neither you nor I, nor a liberated proletariat, nor France.34

Inevitably, this series of sharply ironical articles resulted in Sartres irrevocable break not only with Albert Camus (who initiated the break) but also with his once much closer friend, Merleau-Ponty, who subsequently attacked Sartre for his alleged ultra-Bolshevism35 in the Adventures of the Dialectic: a book celebrated by the political and academic establishment in France not

236

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

for theoretical but for well identifiable ideological reasons, in grateful recognition for Merleau-Pontys adhesion to the League of Abandoned Hope,36 which he himself once labelled and sharply condemned in such terms. Sartre adopted his positive stance toward the CP in The Communists and Peace was his conviction that the agglomeration of isolated individuals, making up also the popular masses of the workers,37 was incapable of meeting the historical challenge of humanitys potential destruction on the horizon. Only the workers as a classin the Marxian sense of the class for itself could do that in Sartres view, repeatedly expressing in these articles his full agreement on the subject with Marx. At the same time Sartre stressed that the Communist Party constituted the necessary mediation without which combining and unifying the masses of workers into the class required for the purpose of the radical transformation of the dangerously developing social order was unthinkable. Moreover, even after his sharp conflicts with the French CP Sartre maintained the validity of the main tenets expressed in The Communists and Peace, although a decade later he added the qualification that in the course of its development the party itself has become serialized and therefore lost its ability to fulfill the necessary role of mediator which he was defending in the much debated articles. The concepts of seriality and serialization were developed by Sartre in his Critique of Dialectical Reason in which he tried to elaborate the general theoretical framework of his conception of the intelligibility of our history, including not only the categories of what he called the formal structures of history but also a sustainable account of real history. In the period of the early 1950s Sartres principal concern was the fateful eventuality of an all-destructive war. That was also a seminally important consideration for redefining his original conception of the relationship between man and history. In his Notebooks for an Ethicsabandoned in 1948 949this problem was approached in a most abstract way, in terms of the structural relationship between the For-itself and the In-itself, with the assertion of ontologically necessary failure very much in line with his Being and Nothingness: an essay on phenomenological ontology. In this sense he wrote in his Notebooks for an Ethics:
T H E F U N DAM E NTAL R EASO N W H Y

Every attempt of the For-itself to be In-itself is by definition doomed to fail. From this we can account for the existence of Hell . . . Even though this

I N T R O D U CT ION

237

failure may be indefinitely covered over, made up for, by itself it tends to reveal the world as a world of failure and it can push the For-itself to ask itself the pre-judicial question of the meaning of its acts and the reason of its failure. Then the problem gets posed as follows: Why is the human world inevitably a world of failure, what is there in the essence of human effort such that it seems doomed in principle to failure?38

However, when the question of failure is not postulated in terms of the ontologically necessary failureby definitionof the abstract Foritself trying to be In-itself, but confronted as the real failure of human beings to save themselves from nuclear annihilation, then also the figurative Hell becomes the real hell of absurdly self-imposed but preventable human action, with identifiable human historical agencies that can and must be stopped. For that kind of catastrophic failure cannot be indefinitely covered over, due to the unalterable absence of anybody who might be able to do any covering over. This is how the challenge of history assumes a concrete form, confronting the individuals in every walk of life with real questions and real alternatives which no one can simply ignore. Indeed, this is why history itself and the historical agent must be reconsidered in its painful objective reality also by the existentialist, in terms of the actual and threatening unfolding of history under the existing conditions, which in their worsening destructiveness are still very much part of our own predicament today. And Sartre unhesitatingly engages in facing up to such vital issue by pointing his accusing finger at those whoblinded by determinate class interests which cannot be effectively countered by any agglomeration of isolated individualsare complicitously choosing the destructive alternative course of action, with devastating overall implications, and thereby, knowingly or not, siding with the potential termination of history. Accordingly, nothing could be clearer in terms of Sartres explicit answer to the tangible challenge of real history than these warning words: In order to prevent the world from following its own course, they threaten with the suppression of history through the liquidation of the historical agent.39 In March 1980, two weeks before dyingafter many years of dedication to the cause of positively meeting the challenge of history, punctuated by major personal successes and grave disappointmentsSartre gave what turned out to be his last interview. The general tone of this interview was rather pessimistic, in tune with the pessimism which characterized the last decade of his life, after the failure of his expectations attached to May 1968

238

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

and its political and organizational aftermath. In the concluding minutes of this interview, anticipating that he might live ten or perhaps only five more years, Sartre was referring to the invasion of Afghanistan and he reiterated his deep concern about a third world war, saying that With this third world war, which could break out one day, and with this miserable ensemble which is our planet, despair comes to tempt me. . . . In any case, the world seems to be ugly, bad, without hope. This is the quiet despair of an old man who will die in it. However, I resist and I say that I shall die in hope, but this hope must be founded. One must try to explain why this world of today, which is horrible, is only a moment in the long historical development; that hope has always been one of the dominant forces of the revolutions and insurrections; that how much I continue to feel hope as my conception of the future.40 Sadly, two weeks later Sartre was already dead. Thus he could not elaborate as his final contribution the promised foundation of hope for his conception of the future of which only hope in despair remained to him in the final years of his life.

6. Material and Formal Structures of History: Critique of Sartres Conception of Dialectical Reason and Historical Totalization
of The Dialectic of Structure and History, it was one of Jean-Paul Sartres great merits as a thinker and exemplary militant to address the fundamental question of historical totalization in the post-Second World War period. His famous Critique of Dialectical Reason was dedicated to the subject, announcing in its already massive first volume the soon to be followed completion41 of this project. It is important to bear in mind that Sartres Critiqueas published by Gallimard in Paris in 1960, with the subtitle of Theory of Practical Ensembleswas never intended to offer the complete picture on its own. On the contrary, it explicitly promised the proper elaboration of the categorial framework of real history, as the necessary complementary and indeed the theoretical climax to Sartres project. This is how he had put it in his Introduction to the published work:
AS M E N T ION E D IN C HA PTER 2

240

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Volume I of the Critique of Dialectical Reason stops as soon as we reach the locus of history; it is solely concerned with finding the intelligible foundations for a structural anthropologyto the extent, of course, that these synthetic structures are the condition of a directed, developing totalization. Volume II, which will follow shortly, will retrace the stages of the critical progression; it will attempt to establish that there is one human history, with one truth and one intelligibility . . . by demonstrating that a practical multiplicity, whatever it may be, must unceasingly totalise itself through interiorising its multiplicity at all levels. . . . Then we shall be able to glimpse what these two volumes together will try to prove: that necessity, as the apodictic structure of dialectical investigation, resides neither in the free development of interiority nor in the inert dispersal of exteriority; it asserts itself, as an inevitable and irreducible moment, in the interiorisation of the exterior and in the exteriorisation of the interior.42

However, there were some very good reasons why this project could never be brought anywhere near its promised completion. The intended analysis of real historyin contrast to the philosophical problematic outlined in the first volume of the Sartrean Critique only in terms of the formal structures of historyrefused to materialize in the interminably growing pages of the posthumous second volume; a manuscript amounting to a volume of almost five hundred pages which in the end was not considered suitable for publication by its author. For whereas Sartre had no difficulties in illustrating the categories adopted in the published first volume with most imaginatively used historical material, categories also accurately defined by him as the strictly formal structures of history, the attempted evaluation of particular conflictual situations and major historical developments discussed in the second volume remained firmly anchored, despite his intentions, to the same formal categorial framework. Thus in the end not much choice remained to Sartre himself than to abandon his originally promised comprehensive account of real history as the integral part and terminus ad quem of his vision of historical totalization. Yet, it would be quite wrong to see in this outcome the corrigible personal failure of a particular thinker. In the case of one of the outstanding intellectual figures of the twentieth century, as Jean-Paul Sartre undeniably happened to be, the non-realizability of an important theoretical enterpriseattempted, to be sure, from a determinate social and historical standpointhas its deep-seated objective ground and corresponding representative significance. On this particular occasion this is the case all the more

M AT ER IAL AND F OR M AL STRUCTURES O F H ISTO RY

241

because Sartre intended to put forward his conception, in the midst of the turmoil of some far-reaching historical events,43 as an integral part of a quest pursued with great passion throughout his life in the service of the cause of human emancipation.44 In this sense Sartre rejected in the strongest possible terms any idea of a mysterious totalizer which we have seen advocated even by the greatest thinkers of the bourgeoisie in the ascending phase of the capital systems historical unfolding. He insisted that in any viable historical conception people must be wholly defined by their society and by the historical movement which carries them along; if we do not wish the dialectic to become a divine law again, a metaphysical fate, it must proceed from individuals and not from some kind of supra-individual ensemble. the dialectic is the law of totalization which creates several collectivities, several societies, and one historyrealities which impose themselves on individuals; but at the same time it must be woven out of millions of individual actions.45 Another major achievement of the Critique of Dialectical Reason is Sartres elaboration of the categorial framework of what he calls the formal structures of history, as we find them outlined in the work published by Gallimard in 1960, with powerfully depicted historical material, ranging from some key episodes of the French Revolution of 1789 to twentieth century developments. These formal categoriesfrom the constitution of seriality and the fused group to disintegrative institutionalizationas elaborated in the first volume of the Sartrean Critique, by no means could be said to constitute the formal structures of history in general. They are on the whole applicable to a determinate phase of human history only, in that they encapsulate some characteristic determinations of social interchange under the bourgeois order. In that way, though, their potential for illuminating some important aspects of modern historical transformations is truly remarkable. Indeed precisely thanks to their formal structuring orientation they are well in tune with some of the fundamental material imperatives of capitals productive order which must subsume under its fetishistically quantifying formal equalizations and abstract homogenizing determinations the most disparate qualities of societal metabolic interchange in which exchange value must absolutely dominate use value, as we have seen these problems discussed in Chapter 4 as well as in Section 6.2 of The Dialectic of Structure and History. Thus the fact that Sartre was unable to complete his original project of integrating the propounded formal structures of history with his intended account of real history cannot take away anything from their explanatory value in their own setting.

242

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

TO UN DE R STAN D T HE I NSUP ERA B LE IMPED IMENTS at the roots of Sartres project for elucidating the problem of totalization in real history it is worth quoting a passage from an important interview he gave in 1969 to New Left Review. As it clearly transpires from this interview, even as late as 1969 Sartre was still promising to complete the second volume of the Critique of Dialectical Reason, although he had already put aside its nearly five hundred pages way back in 1958. These were his words in the 1969 interview:

The difference between the first and the second volume is this: the first is an abstract work where I show the possibilities of exchange, degradation, the practico-inert, series, collectives, recurrence and so on. It is concerned only with the theoretical possibilities of their combinations. The project of the second volume is history itself . . . my aim will be to prove that there is a dialectical intelligibility of the singular. For ours is a singular history. . . . What I will seek to show is the dialectical intelligibility of that which is not universalizable.46

However, as the case turned out to be, the drafting of the second volume, which was actually interrupted for Sartres compelling internal reasons before the end of 1958, was never taken up again. Its abandoned manuscript was posthumously published in French five years after Sartres death, in 1985, and in English six years later, in 1991. Nevertheless, the destiny of this major Sartrean project was by no means surprising. My own comment, when Sartre was still alive and fully active, on the just quoted passage and on the anticipated unfinishability of his theory of historical totalizationas clearly demonstrated to me by volume one of the Critique of Dialectical Reason as well as by the 1969 interview itself was as follows: It is extremely difficult to imagine how one can comprehend history itself through these categories, since the problem of history is precisely how to universalize the singular without suppressing its specificity. By contrast, however, it is very easy to see the natural transition from history to biography, namely from this Sartrean conception of history to the project on Flaubert. For the intelligibility of the non-universalizable singular calls for lived experience as the basis of its comprehension. And the reconstruction of the personage through limaginaire necessarily involved in it,47 gives us a True Legend, at the highest level of complexity. Some of the fundamental structures of history remain hidden away in the second volume of the Critique that never comes, for they do not seem to fit into the framework of Sartres quest.48

M AT ER IAL AND F OR M AL STRUCTURES O F H ISTO RY

243

The insurmountable problem for Sartre was, and always remained, that the way to universalize the singular without suppressing its specificity is feasible only through the appropriate mediations which link thesocially definedmultiplicity of particular individuals to their groups and classes at any given time, and to the unfolding societal development across the whole of history. Sartres answers to the question of mediation were always extremely problematical in his conception of historical totalization. And, again, the missing social/historical mediations from his thought were not a corrigible absence. To be sure, Sartre rightly stressed that history is woven out of millions of individual actions, as we have seen his firm insistence on this issue elsewhere. However, despite a claim made explicit in the period of writing and publishing the first volume of the Critique of Dialectical Reasonaccording to which existentialism has been left behind by him in his later development as no more than an ideology49some of the crucial categories developed in his early work, prior to and during the Second World War, and indeed most strikingly in Being and Nothingness, remained always dominant in his philosophy. He even took back in 1975 the 1958 assertion about existentialism being merely an ideological enclave within Marxism,50 accepting instead, and in a curious way,51 the existentialist label again. The point of seminal importance in this respect was that by his de factoeven if under the given political circumstances not programmatically expressed yet persistentattempt to give an existential ontological foundation to his own categorial framework also in the Critique of Dialectical Reason,52 Sartre barred his own road to making dialectically intelligible the process of historical totalization in real history. Namely, he made it prohibitively difficult to envisage how it could be possible at all for the millions of individual actionsin truth always deeply embedded in historically most specific and dynamically interrelated social structuresto add up to a network of lawlike determinations in the proper sense of historical necessity, conceived as progressively changing and in its modality of asserting itself in due course vanishing necessity. The missing historical mediations played a crucial role in derailing Sartres intended overall account of real history. In his problematical attempt to give an ontological foundation to his own existentialist enclave within Marxism, Sartre had to turn the eminently historical and socially transcendable category of scarcity into a paralyzing ahistorical and anti-historical absolute, arbitrarily proclaimed to be the insuperable permanence and the overall determination and horizon of our real history. He did this by postulating that to say that our History is a history

244

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

of men is equivalent to saying that it is born and developed within the permanent framework of a field of tension produced by scarcity.53 At the same time, he repeatedly contradicted his earlier categorical assertion according to which there is no such thing as man; there are people.54 However, for the sake of the existentialistically absolutized declaration of a perverse reciprocity between each particular individual and the mythical Other who inhabits every individual, a direct line of identity was decreed by Sartre to be fatefully prevailing between the ethically both rebellious and at the same time also viciously inhuman individual and the mythical/ demonic man under the rule of permanent scarcity. It is important in this respect to quote in some detail Sartres words from the first volume of the Critique of Dialectical Reason:
In pure reciprocity, that which is Other than me is also the same. But in reciprocity as modified by scarcity, the same appears to us as anti-human in so far as this same man appears as radically Otherthat is to say, as threatening us with death. Or, to put it another way, we have a rough understanding of his ends (for they are the same as ours), and his means (we have the same ones) as well as of the dialectical structures of his acts; but we understand them as if they belonged to another species, our demonic double. Nothingnot even wild beasts or microbescould be more terrifying for man than a species which is intelligent, carnivorous and cruel, and which can understand and outwit human intelligence, and whose aim is precisely the destruction of man. This, however, is obviously our own species as perceived in others by each of its members in the context of scarcity. . . . it makes everyone objectively dangerous for the Other and makes the concrete existence of each individual endanger that of the Other. Thus man is objectively constituted as non-human, and this non-humanity is expressed in praxis by the perception of evil as the structure of the Other.55

This ahistorical Sartrean discourse on evil as the structure of the Otherand indeed the Other as each and every particular individualin the Critique was articulated in such a way that with relative ease it could be incorporated into the existentialist ontological design of his first great synthesizing philosophical work, Being and Nothingness. In this way we were told by the marxisant56 Jean-Paul Sartre of the Critique of Dialectical Reason that
I may try to kill, to torture, to enslave, or simply to mystify, but in any case my aim will be to eliminate alien freedom as a hostile force, a force which

M AT ER IAL AND F OR M AL STRUCTURES O F H ISTO RY

245

can expel me from the practical field and make me into a surplus man condemned to death. In other words, it is undeniable that what I attack is man as man, that is, as the free praxis of an organic being. It is man, and nothing else, that I hate in the enemy, that is, in myself as Other; and it is myself that I try to destroy in him, so as to prevent him destroying me in my own body.57

Naturally, the passionately committed militant intellectual Sartres motivation for constructing this vision of inescapable conflict, characterized as necessarily arising from and ruled by permanent scarcity, inseparable from its existentialist ontological underpinning, was not the submissive defense but the radical negation of the existent societal order. He needed the heightened ontological emphasis for his proclaimed existentialist enclave in order to put into dramatic relief the enormity of the struggle that must be pursued against the enemy Other, paradoxically defined as myself and every individual self. However, by doing so without bringing into the picture the appropriate social and historical mediationsindeed by obliterating the vital distinction between historically insuperable first order and capitals to be transcended antagonistic second order mediations58he ended up with absolutizing the historically relative against his own critical intentions.
UN DER T HE S P E C IF IC C O ND ITIO NS O F REA L H ISTO RY asserting themselves in our time, as we are forced to live them under the structurally determined rule of capital, the antagonistic second order mediations must always prevail. They represent a historically in the long run absolutely untenable imposition and domination of the established societal reproduction process, with their ultimately destructive and self-destructive implications. The historical supersession of such antagonistic second order mediations, no matter how prohibitive the obstacles to their overcoming might appear under the present conditions, is the key to the solution of the thorny issuethe veritable vicious circle in the capital systems real historyof scarcity inseparably combined with recklessly produced waste on the one hand and the often oversimplified wishful counter-image of abundance on the other. The idea of the pseudo-ontological permanence of capitals oppressive second order mediations, postulated on the premise of historically already long before capitals appearance imposed class domination, as the necessary structural framework of self-imposing scarcity, is a falsely stipulated distortion. For the relative continuity which we can find between the qualitatively different antecedents of capitals antagonistic second order mediations and its own

246

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

distinctive modality of class-exploitative societal reproductive domination by means of the economically enforced extraction of surplus labor as surplus value, is trans-historicaland in that sense superablebut emphatically not supra-historical. Once, however, the existentialist ontological underpinning of Sartres categorial framework asserts itself, offering a vision of some kind of human condition inseparable from destructive conflict under the rule of permanent scarcity, the original intellectual motivation of critical negation of this great militant thinker is inevitably pushed into the background. Thus the corollary of absolutizing the relativei.e., absolutizing the historical category of scarcity by turning it into ontologically interiorized permanencemarks its far-reaching negative impact. This corollary of absolutizing the relative in Sartres existentialist ontological enclave paradoxically assumes the form of relativizing the absolute conditions of human existence by suppressing its unique character as a historical absolute. The actually existing and, this cannot be stressed enough, by no means ahistorical absolute constituent of humanitys dialectical determinationnamely the forever inescapable, and in that sense, but not in its particular modality, absolutenatural substratum of human existence is the issue here. Its unique determination as a historical absolute remains in force none the less. For no matter to what degree this natural substratum might (indeed must) be modified by ongoing human productive development, in the course of the historical creation of new needs and the corresponding extension of the conditions of their satisfaction, ultimately it always remains firmly circumscribed by nature itself. And that circumstance also means that in as much as it is violatedwhich continues to happen in our time to an increasingly dangerous degree in humankinds relationship to natureit must be also unceremoniously, and even punitively, imposed upon society by the objective requirements of human existence itself. Naturally, this makes absolutely imperative for humanity the positive articulation of a viable and historically sustainable interchange of the social individuals with nature and among themselves, as the changing but necessary social ground of their relationship to nature, if they want to avoid self-destruction. But to do so is possible only by observing the unique and inherently historical character of the relationship in question. Only on that basis is it feasible to redefine in a proper way, especially under the conditions of the intensifying structural crisis of their mode of social metabolic reproduction, the vital relationship of humanity to nature in the necessarily open-ended historical framework of development.

M AT ER IAL AND F OR M AL STRUCTURES O F H ISTO RY

247

Accordingly, it would be self-defeating to characterize in any attempted account of real history the objective character of the natural substratum of human existencewhich must be in the course of human development subject to appropriate historical transformations,59 in view of the intervention of, by human beings instituted and changing, historical necessity in the order of naturewith the timeless existentialist ontological materiality of scarcity, postulated on the arbitrarily assumed ground that man is objectively constituted as non-human, and this non-humanity is expressed in praxis by the perception of evil as the structure of the Other.60 To presume and repeatedly proclaim that man is objectively constituted as non-human is an existentialistically misrepresented prejudgement of the issue, devised for the purpose of switching immediately, in the same sentence, from the apparently neutral/objective meaning of non-human to the fateful characterization of the non-humanity of human praxis as necessarily carrying with it the perception of evil as the structure of the Other. The so-called objective constitution of man, called in this way by Sartre, with regard to its primary/primitive objectivity, does not and cannot refer at all to man, nor to an existentialistically projected demonic/mythical non-human, but only to the animal world. In relation to the being that emerges later in historyby constituting itselfas human, it can be legitimately called, from a human perspective, pre-human, but decidedly not in a tendentious sense, proclaimed to fit the somber spectrum of existentialist ontology, as non-human. For prior to the open ended historical self-constitution of the human beingof which the creation of a new need is the first historical act, as we have seen it discussed in The Dialectic of Structure and Historythere is no such being properly so called as non-human in the Sartrean sense. It must be revealingly called by Sartre in that way so that later the being in question should be easily presentable in the spirit of existentialist ontological gloom as evil, with its structural determination assigned to the Other embedded in every individual self, including myself. In actuality the natural substratum of human existence itself is not a massive materiality but a changing social structural relationshipan always historically specific mediationof human beings in general with nature and among themselves. Thus this inescapable mediation is necessarily constituted and reconstituted through socially specific and historically changing human intervention in the absolutely inescapable order of nature. In other words, it is constituted and reconstituted in the form of the dual causality of natures own lawfulness, on the one hand (which can

248

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

be dynamically adapted but not violated), and the progressively modified/ displaced (and in its particular modality in due course vanishing/superseded) historical necessity, on the other. In the same sense, the category of scarcity is from its inception an inherently historical category, acquiring its meaning from the relationship of its temporary (no matter how long) domination over the human beings that under determinatethat is, historically specific and alterableconditions must suffer its power. This is far from being a self-sustaining power. It must be simultaneously also defined as subject to becoming historically superseded, at least in principle. Or not, as the case might be. But it is not superseded only if the projected necessary failure of the human species is absolutized as the all-embracing ultimate catastrophe, amounting to the termination of human history itself. Scarcity makes no sense at all in itself and for itself as an absolute. It is always scarcity in relation to something or someone. Moreover, even in its objective determination as a weighty contingency it makes senseone way or anotheronly in relation to human beings who may suffer or overcome it, thanks to their own inherently historical determination and self-determination. Unlike humans, animals do not live in a world of scarcity. They just liveand dieas the species-determinations of their genus-individuality permit and destine them to do. Scarcity must therefore be understood in its appropriate historical context, as parasitic on human history, and not as the postulated ground and pessimistically hypostatized causal foundation of history. To say with Sartre that history is born and developed within the permanent framework of a field of tension produced by scarcity61 can only absolutize the relative and relativize the absolute. For, in the latter sense, the just quoted Sartrean assertion subordinates to the hopeless vicissitudes of demonically magnified and likewise interiorized scarcity62 the absolute imperative of instituting a viable alternative to the established mode of social metabolic reproduction at the present critical juncture of history. By contrast, in the framework adopted by Sartre, the gloom of insuperably absolutized anti-historical scarcity as the ground of historical intelligibility, wedded to the earlier quoted perverse reciprocity between myself and the Other in me, is overwhelming. The fact that the imperative facing human society today for adopting a radically different mode of historically sustainable social metabolic reproduction is absolute, in direct opposition to capitals destructive pursuit of unlimitablehence by definition always scarcecapital-expansion, does not and cannot obliterate the inherently historical character and

M AT ER IAL AND F OR M AL STRUCTURES O F H ISTO RY

249

corresponding urgency of such absolute. For all conceivable absolutes in the human context are necessarily historical at the same time, including those concerning the ineliminable natural substratum of human existence itself. However, by submerging the historically determinate practical imperative for elaborating a viable societal reproductive alternative into the generic pseudo-absolute existentialist ontological projection of the permanent framework of scarcity can only generate desolate pessimism63 and the noble but impotent ought to be as its envisaged counter-image.64 There can be no room therefore in the structurally prejudged existentialist ontological enclave, dominated by permanent scarcity, for exploring the conditions of feasibility of the required and historically sustainable positive alternative. The strange result of all this is the diminishing of responsibility for the capital system itself, notwithstanding its historically overwhelming range of destructive second order mediations. Such responsibility is diminished in Sartres proclaimed existentialist ideological enclave within Marxism on account of the mythically magnified role ascribed by him to the antihistorically extended generic interiorized scarcity made by myself as the Other. And that Other in me is hypostatized by Sartre in a form overburdened with the most unreal projection of responsibility by being characterized in an earlier quoted passage from the Critique of Dialectical Reason as the demonic double of not only the human species in generalcalled in that quote, as we have seen it earlier, a species which is intelligent, carnivorous and cruel, and which can understand and outwit human intelligence, and whose aim is precisely the destruction of man65but at the same time of every single individual member of society in their personal capacity. This is a most peculiar way of exempting the capital system of its quite obvious responsibility for being actually bent in our time on the very real destruction of man rightly deplored by Sartre himself. Moreover, what makes the kind of existentialist ontological underpinning which we have seen in the categorial framework of the Critique of Dialectical Reason rather paradoxical is, of course, the circumstance that Sartre would be the last person to offer such exemption as a matter of conscious deliberation to the inhuman power of capital. No one raises more often in a dramatic way than Sartre himself the question of responsibility in general and the grave responsibility of the intellectuals in particular. His moral indignation and radical negation remain always very intense. But the only historical subject he can appeal to and try to enlist for the fights he is engaged in is the isolated particular individual.

250

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

T H E P OL IT IC AL D IM E NS IO N O F SA RTRES A P P ROACH to history is expressed in a brilliant occasional piece from 1973: Elections: A Trap for Fools,66 published in Les Temps Modernes in January 1973, and as we learn with precision from the article itself, written on the 5th of January 1973, shortly before the French General Election under Pompidous Presidency. Elections: A Trap for Fools is a very significant article as the political actualization of the Sartrean formal structures of history, developed in great detail in the first volume of the Critique of Dialectical Reason. For in the Sartrean vision the categories of the Critique are perfectly applicable to the electoral situation itself, considered by him a strictly and reprehensibly formal structure of history. In this respect it is directly relevant that Sartres Critique of Dialectical Reason, as regards its inspiration, can only be understood in the context of the dual crisis of (1) French colonialism in Vietnam and Algeria, and (2) the deepening crisis of the Soviet type system, including the East German (1953), the Polish (1955/56) and the Hungarian upheavals. Indeed, the Hungarian popular explosion of October 1956 has a greater impact on Sartres thought than any other contemporary historical event, as evidenced by his major essay: The Phantom of Stalin as well as by the Critique of Dialectical Reason itself.67 The formal categories elaborated by Sartre in the first volume of his Critique of Dialectical Reason, arising to a considerable degree from his passionate assessment of this dual crisis, remain to the end the orienting principles of his interpretation of the unfolding political events and of the role to be assigned to the individuals participating in them. This is so irrespective of the fact that he is unable to theorize the problem of totalization in real history either in the repeatedly promised but unfinishable second volume of the Critique or anywhere else.68 The process of fateful serialization, corresponding to one of his most important formal structures of history, in conjunction with the practicoinert field, is described by Sartre in Election: A Trap for Fools in most vivid terms. Talking about the serialized individual he insists that a soldier takes the bus, buys the newspaper, votes. All this presumes that he will make use of collectives along with the Others. But the collectives address him as a member of a series (the series of newspaper buyers, television watchers, etc.). He becomes in essence identical with all the other members, differing from them only by his serial number. We say that he has been serialized. One finds serialization in the practico-inert field, where matter mediates between men to the extent that men mediate between material objects. . . . serial thinking

M AT ER IAL AND F OR M AL STRUCTURES O F H ISTO RY

251

is born in me, thinking which is not my own thinking but that of the Other, which I am and also that of all the Others. It must be called the thinking of powerlessness, because I produce it to the degree that I am Other, an enemy of myself and of the Others, and to the degree that I carry the Other everywhere with me.69 At the same time, the grave consequences of such serialization are graphically put into relief by saying that Now, these citizens, identical as they are and fabricated by the law, disarmed and separated by distrust of one another, deceived but aware of their impotence, can never, as long as they remain serialized, form that sovereign group from which, we are told, all power emanatesthe People.70 Sartres accusing finger, as we can see, is not pointed at society in general but to every individual. For, according to him, I as the serializedand indeed actively self-serializingindividual am the guilty one who produces the thinking of powerlessness, and in that way I become an enemy of myself and of the Others. He thereby clearly ascribes responsibility not only to the ruling societal order but directly to each one of us, looking at the same time also for the required remedy in the form of a direct appeal to our individual consciousness. Not surprisingly, therefore, the article of Elections: A Trap for Fools ends with an ought to be presented as a must, by saying that We must try, each according to his own resources, to organize the vast antihierarchic movement which fights institutions everywhere.71 The question of how the now actually serialized individuals could prevail against the hierarchic institutions everywhere, as he invites them to do, cannot be addressed by Sartre. Some of his centrally important categoriesindicting the power of serialization as such and the necessity of the fused groups institutionally foreshadowed disintegration, as well as the fateful relapse of the particular members of the group into self-imposed serialityspeak eloquently against his own proclaimed imperative. This is the reason why the ought to be of the unspecified mode of organization of the individuals is strongly contradicted by Sartres explicit judgement against the feasible success of organization itself. This is expressed with great sincerity in an interview given by Sartre in 1969 to the important Italian political movement, the Manifesto group, in these words: While I recognize the need of an organization, I must confess that I dont see how the problems which confront any stabilized structure could be resolved.72
T H E M OST S IG N IF IC ANT PASSAGE in Elections: A Trap for Fools which illuminates the political and theoretical roots of Sartres militant strategic

252

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

orientation, is his emphatic condemnation of the act of voting itself, in the name of his passionate advocacy of sovereignty celebrated also in one of his most important categories, the sovereign group. This seminal passage of Sartres 1973 article on elections reads as follows: When I vote, I abdicate my powerthat is, the possibility everyone has of joining others to form a sovereign group which would have no need of representatives.73 The importance of Sartres concern with the imperative of sovereignty cannot be stressed strongly enough. The same idea is emphasizedindeed idealizedby him in the immediate aftermath of the defeat of the dramatic May 1968 upheavals in France. In fact Sartre singles out the embryonic appearance of sovereignty as the great novelty of the 1968 historical events in general. For he insists in his sharp condemnation of the critics of the student movement that What I reproach all those with, who insulted the students, is that they failed to see that the students expressed a new demand: the need for sovereignty.74 Of course, the sovereignty here referred to, wholeheartedly supported by Sartre, is nothing less than the unique social formation which in his view should beor, in more accurate terms, ought to bespontaneously constituted by all those who reject serialization, in opposition to the stabilized structures whose politically favored organizational establishment is turned down by him even in one of his most succinctly articulated political reflections on the subject, presented in the interview given to the Manifesto group of the Italian radical left. And the mode of constituting such sovereignty, according to Sartre, is either through some revolutionary explosion, like May 1968 in France, or by means of the admittedly problematical organizational form brought into being by the direct appeal of the militant intellectuals to the consciousness of the potentially anti-hierarchical individuals in general, who are said to be favorably disposed in that way by their need for liberty. The idea that such direct appeal might be able to produce the required outcome is often expressed by Sartre with a confession of self-critical scepticism, even pessimism, as we have seen it earlier.75 It persists, nevertheless. For the roots of advocating politically commended solutions in the form of such direct appeals to individual consciousness reach back a long way in Sartres political development. Indeed, as far as the individualistic addressee of political enlightenment is concerned, such views reach back even more soin fact much more sonot only into the rather remote past of French political and intellectual history but in the philosophical tradition of the

M AT ER IAL AND F OR M AL STRUCTURES O F H ISTO RY

253

European bourgeoisie in general, in terms of its earlier discussed orientation to aggregates of individuality76 in neglect of class reality. In terms of the political organizational form based on the idea of some direct appeal to individual consciousness shared by Sartre, we have to remember the Rassemblement Dmocratique Rvolutionnaire (R.D.R.)77 with which Sartre was formally associated in 1948 and 1949. He insisted in an interview given to the Paris edition of the New York Herald Tribune that such movement was addressing itself strictly to the individuals, and not to constituted groups.78 Accordingly, the programmatic pieces written by Sartre and his associates about thisfar from really influentialmovement explicitly stressed the desire to be very different from the established political organizations and parties of the left. It was explicitly stated by Sartre that they are meant to orient their individual supporters, instead, toward the defense of some important long-standing political ideals. In this sense he argued:
The question is not to abandon liberty; not even to abandon the abstract liberties of the bourgeoisie, but to fill them with content . . . The first objective of the Revolutionary Democratic Assembly is to combine the revolutionary demands with the idea of Liberty.79

In this way, under the political circumstances of 1948, the direct appeal to the progressive individuals remained rather vague and generic. But the same form of direct appeal was put later into relief by Sartre in his much more radical interpretation of May 1968, in sharp contrast to the traditional organizational forms and parties. His stress on sovereignty, in his praise of the students, is most relevant in that respect. However, the most important defining characteristic of the Sartrean position concerning the required historical alternative is precisely his categorical rejection of the act of voting itself in the passage quoted from the 1973 article. A rejection made on the ground which we have seen a little while ago, namely that When I vote, I abdicate my powerthat is, the possibility everyone has of joining others to form a sovereign group which would have no need of representatives. In the form of this direct appeal to individual consciousness of the would-be voters, dismissing the traditional state institutions and the constituted political parties, the Sartrean rejection is formulated in the spirit of the best bourgeois tradition of the Enlightenment. We can see its close affinity with Rousseaus radical dismissal of voting and his condemnation

254

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

of the parliamentary representative political system. This is how Rousseau argues his case:
The deputies of the people, therefore, are not and cannot be its representatives; they are merely its stewards, and can carry through no definitive acts. Every law the people has not ratified in person is null and voidis, in fact, not a law. The people of England regards itself as free; but it is grossly mistaken; it is free only during the election of members of parliament. As soon as they are elected, slavery overtakes it, and it is nothing. The use it makes of the short moments of liberty it enjoys shows indeed that it deserves to lose them.80

In the same way as Rousseaus self-deluding Englishmen who foolishly renounce their power in favor of parliamentary representatives and quickly lose their momentary liberty, which they are said to deserve, Sartres selfserializing fools, who likewise consent to abdicate their power by voting, instead of joining others to form a sovereign group which would have no need of representatives, they also fully deserve their fate according to the great French marxisant existentialist intellectual. But even so, Sartres militant adhesion in the twentieth century to the heroic Enlightenment perspective championed by Rousseau in support of direct democracy in the eighteenth century is paradoxical. For Sartre formulates the most radical critique of the bourgeoisie while remaining within the bourgeois class horizon. He often even consciously and explicitly states that his sharp critical position is that of an insider. Sartre does that so as to be able to denounce as strongly as feasible, from the critical insiders position, the mortal danger posed by the historically given socioeconomic and political reality in which all individuals are, according to him, deeply implicated. Thus Sartre defines his own position as a bourgeois with an acute critical conscience who assumes a position of open revolt against the increasing destructiveness of the established order, without the ability to detach himself from the bourgeois integument.81 The passionate direct appeal to individual consciousness is in this Sartrean vision the necessary corollary to his explicit or implicit advocacy of instituting some kind of direct democracy whose distant ancestry was supposed to be in tune with the Rights of Man. His earlier quoted desire to fill with content the abstract liberties of the bourgeoisie speaks volumes for itself in that respect. But it also shows the difficulties and limitations of attempting to produce totalization in real history within the categorial framework of the formal structures

M AT ER IAL AND F OR M AL STRUCTURES O F H ISTO RY

255

of history compatible with a radically intended but in its origin necessarily abstract and formalistic horizon. One conceived in its time within the boundaries of the never realizedand for that matter never realizable bourgeois Rights of Man. Accordingly, it would take the labor of Sisyphus to fill with content the abstract liberties of the bourgeoisie, and of course to no avail. For the distance from the formal liberties of the bourgeois order to their socialist counterparts which are inconceivable without all-embracing real contentas for instance the question of substantive equalityis literally astronomical. The actual constitution of a radically different social metabolic order, structurally defined in a qualitatively different way from capitals mode of societal reproductionfrom its elementary material productive practices to the highest levels of cultural interchanges, together with the corresponding decision making practices of its substantively equal social individuals emancipated from capitals antagonistic second order mediations82is required for the realization of such relationships to which the bourgeoisie could not significantly contribute even in the abstract heroic period of its historical past prior to the French revolution. And that would need infinitely more than to fill with content the abstract liberties of the bourgeoisie. For the sobering truth of the matter is that those abstract libertiesdevised in accordance with the requirements of a structurally iniquitous social order, and therefore within their own terms of reference appropriately confined to the formal/ legal spherecannot be filled with socialist content. They are incompatible with substantive socialist determinations, notwithstanding the slogan about filling them with content adopted from time to time in well meaning but greatly constrained political discourse. Paradoxically, therefore, Sartres reformulation of the idea of some kind of unspecified and organizationally undefinable direct democracy is put under heavily accented question marks in relation to any feasible future by his own rather pessimistic account of the constitution and fateful disintegration of the fused group. Yet, it is retained as an ought to be. But even as a noble ought to berevealingly enough coupled with his repeated exhortations addressed to individual consciousness to join a sovereign group which would need no representativesthe Sartrean idea tuns out to be an openly admitted formal structure only. A most problematical formal structure which would have to be (but, as it happens, cannot be) filled with content in his elusive second volume of the Critique, envisaged for making intelligible his apodictic project about the dialectic of real history.

256

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

SA RT R E C R IT IC IZ E S HU S SERL in the first volume of the Critique of Dialectical Reason for his conception of apodictic certainty. This is how he puts it:

Husserl could speak of apodictic certainty without much difficulty, but this was because he remained on the level of pure, formal consciousness apprehending itself in its formality; but, for us, it is necessary to find our apodictic experience in the concrete world of history.83

To be sure, the way Sartre intends to pursue his own project of demonstrating apodicticity in real history cannot be satisfied with the internal resources of pure, formal consciousness apprehending itself in its formality, within the confines of self-proclaimed Husserlian immanence. However, despite the intended major differences Sartre continues to share important aspects of his own orientation toward apodicticity with the bourgeois ancestry in view of the fact that he never submits the material foundations of capitals social order to a sustained critical analysis. For he addresses his critical observations to the political and ideological/psychological dimensions only. Thus it is by no means accidental that Sartres categorial framework in the Critiqueincluding its unfinishable second volumecan only be spelled out in terms of the formal structures of history, which undoubtedly happen to be highly relevant to the evaluation of some important aspects of the societal interchanges of capitalist aggregative individuality, but they are most problematical in relation to overall historical development as real history. For in the society of generalized commodity production, operated on the basis of formally reductive homogenization and abstract value-equation of all substantive/qualitative incommensurability, capitals perverse formal apodicticity can, to be sure, prevail. But in the open-ended development of real history it can do so only as long as the antagonistic second order mediations of the material reproductive system itself can impose the ultimately self-destructive imperative of endless capital-expansion on the producers through the substantively most iniquitousbut formally/legally equalized and in that way securedorder of hierarchical structural domination and subordination. In this sense the perverse but for a long historical stage preponderantly successful formal apodicticity of the capital systems law of value, with its rationally unlimitable self-expansionary imperative as the dynamic material determinant of its apodictic certainty sui generis, can appear to be insuperable. It can proclaim with categorical absoluteness its ownin reality

M AT ER IAL AND F OR M AL STRUCTURES O F H ISTO RY

257

in historical terms most specific84 and in substantive terms most limited insuperability in view of the total absence of identifiable self-limiting targets of productive pursuit admissible from the standpoint of capitals mode of social metabolic reproduction. This is an incorrigible and dangerously missing, but absolutely necessary, self-limitation. It is due to the fact thatto be a meaningful self-limitation at allit would have to be defined in substantive terms necessarily excluded by capital. Such structural impediment to the vitally important self-limitation is imposed on capital as a historically specific reproductive system in view of its innermost and unalterable material determination which must assert itself in generalized commodity production. For that kind of production cannot operate without formally reductive universal value-equation. And that is because such a system must formally equate under its most discriminatory exchange relations the qualitatively/substantively incommensurable use values corresponding to human need. Moreover, this incorrigible determination is further aggravated on account of the utterly fallaciousyet as a rule apologetically asserted and perpetuatedfalse identification of commendable productive development, idealized as unquestionably desirable growth in general, with the fetishistic absolute of increasingly more destructive capital-expansion. Nevertheless, even if there can be no rationally conceived and instituted limits admitted to capitals self-expansion in its own terms of reference, there are some absolutely vital systemic limits. They are twofold. On the one hand, the limits in question arise from the irrepressible antagonistic second order mediations of the capital system in general, and on the other from the increasing destructivenessforeshadowing at the same time also potential systemic self-destructionof capitals mode of social metabolic reproduction in relation to nature. Indeed, the grave transgression of capitals systemic limits is coupled with devastating military adventurism exercised in the interest of imposing the globalized system of destructive production (while preaching the self-mythology of productive destruction) by the imperialistically dominant powers in our ever more precarious planetary household. Sartres pessimism is boundless when he calls out in despair: It is impossible to find a rational basis for revolutionary optimism, since what is is the present reality.85 In this way the destructive dominance of the rationally unlimitable self-expansionary imperative of the capital system is unhappily interiorized also by Sartre as the apparently undefeatable rationality of actuality.

258

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

However, capitals formally equalizing rationality is in reality substantive irrationality that must be imposed with ruthless apodictic necessity in the production sphere as much as in all fields of the political domainfrom the most comprehensive state practices involved in safeguarding the internal and international class relations and interests of the established mode of material production to the ideological/political regulation and value-determination of the nuclear familyno matter how destructive the consequences in the descending phase of the systems development. No wonder, therefore, that we are presented with bleak pessimism concerning the future in Sartrean discourse after the bitter disappointment that follows the shortlived enthusiasm of 1968. This is understandably so because, similarly to Marcuse, also in Sartres approach too much of the apparent stability of capitals material reproductive order and of its allegedly integrated social subject of potential change rejected by Sartre as unable to overcome the inertia of constituted groups and stabilized structuresis granted at face value to organized capitalism. As a result, the wishfully postulated but in actuality extremely fragile social subject of the ought to be radical transformationthe allegedly sovereignty-embodying French student movement of 1968 for Sartre, and Marcuses minoritarian groups of the intelligentsia86 (sharply opposed by him to the working class)offer no more solid ground for envisaging the required changes in the unfolding future than the abstract declaration of needs which are said by Sartre to be the needs of every man, irrespective of their social class belonging and corresponding material and ideological determinations. We can clearly see that Sartre, like Marcuse (who in this respect to a large extent inspires Sartre), adopts the dubious notion of organized capitalism, contrasting it with competitive capitalism. Sartre puts into relief the politically challenging novelty of organized capitalism in order to call for an anti-authoritarian way of approaching the task ahead on the model of the aspirations of French Maoist students, in contrast to the traditional political parties of the left which are in his view anchored to the nineteenth century. These are Sartres words:
The classical leftist parties have remained in the nineteenth century, in the time of competitive capitalism. But though the Maoist movement is still in its first stages, these militants, with their anti-authoritarian praxis, appear to be the only revolutionary force capable of adapting to new forms of the class struggle in a period of organized capitalism.87

M AT ER IAL AND F OR M AL STRUCTURES O F H ISTO RY

259

Marcuses concern is very similar both in calling for a new social subject of transformation, indicating the militant youth as the embodiment of antiauthoritarian politics, and in claiming that the now established societal reproductive order must be characterized as indefinitely stable organized capitalism, in contrast to the past. In both cases the claimed novelty and corresponding power of organized capitalism is paradoxically overstated. It is overstated to such an extent that when the somewhat euphoric period of 1968 passes away, together with the idealized expectations attached to its claimed antiauthoritarian political praxis, the pessimistic readjustment of the former strategic perspective can only offer in favor of its own support the noble but abstract postulate of the internal need of the individuals in the case of both Sartre and Marcuse, coupled with constant references to Kantian imperatives in the writings of the German militant intellectual from the 1960s to his final years.88
T H E KANT IAN L E GACY W EIGH S D OW N as heavily on Sartre as on Marcuse. And that is a major part of the problem. For in order to give a substantive rational foundation to a positive and historically sustainable alternative to the capital system, it is necessary to extricate ourselves from the established orders merely formal rationality and corresponding formal apodicticity of gravely iniquitous but pretendedly unobjectionable universal value-equation. Yet in terms of the pretended equitable value-determinations even the absolute human outrage of decreeing capital and labor to be formally/rationally equal in the exchange relation as individually sovereign buyers and sellers can be totally misrepresented, turning into a travesty the real character of the relationship involved. For the pretended equality of contractually related individuals, who are supposed to regulate voluntarily and freely their interchanges in accordance with the Rights of Man, is in fact brutally forced upon the class of living labor by the actual power relations embodied in the alienation and expropriation of the means of production from the producers, originally instituted by great violence,89 and ever after protected by the state. Accordingly, with the passing of historical time the idealized and statelegitimated formal rationalitywhich in actuality (i.e. in the Hegelian rational actuality of real history) always amounts to substantive irrationalitybecomes in capitals descending phase of development ultimately self-destructive in view of the historically untenable but rationally unlimitable imperative of capital expansion.

260

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

The formally idealized Rights of Mancuriously invoked even by Sartre when he appeals to the idea of the individuals joining that sovereign group from which, we are told, all power emanates, the People.90cannot be exempted from the requirement of giving a substantive rational foundation to a historically sustainable positive alternative to capitals formally legitimated and in the name of its pretended formal and instrumental rationality91 peremptorily enforced mode of social metabolic reproduction. Otherwise we must remain trapped by Sartresand Marcuses utter pessimism. However, in Sartres lifework it is impossible to supersede the established orders formal rationality and corresponding formal apodicticity without abandoning the idea that the categorial framework of his marxisant existentialist conception, as spelled out in his Critique of Dialectical Reason, encapsulates the formal structures of history in general, and as such applicable also to a strategic view of the necessary historical alternative to capitals social metabolic order. The unfinishable second volume of the Critique does not stand alone in Sartres lifework. The same fate affected his project announced at the very end of Being and Nothingness, concerning the problems of situated freedom to be pursued on the ethical plane,92 and the work on structural anthropology whose early publication was also repeatedly promised by Sartre in interviews many years before his death, but never materialized. The reasons for the revealing unfinishability of these major Sartrean projects are very similar. But this is in no way meant to be a negative judgement on Sartres lifework. Paradoxically, the major projects in question are in fact complete in their incompleteness and truly representative as integral parts of his great militant intellectual achievement precisely in their unfinishability. For they embody a tirelesseven heroicstruggle on his part to radically negate the established order from within its own class parameters. Sartre himself voices the insuperable dilemmas involved by using the same expression about the nature of the enterprise which he tries to pursue as necessary but at the same time impossible. He says that in different but interrelated contexts. Thus, talking about the most powerful organized political force of the left in France he asserts that Collaboration with the Communist Party is both necessary and impossible.93 That sums up very well Sartres position on the issue, indicating the painful double-sided acknowledgement that, on the one hand, without a major organizational force the advocated objectives cannot be accomplished, yet on the other hand, the force in question is very far from actually promoting the necessary change.94

M AT ER IAL AND F OR M AL STRUCTURES O F H ISTO RY

261

The same dilemma is put by Sartre in more generalized terms when he insists that Ethics is for us inevitable and at the same time impossible. 95 All these paradoxical and self-torturing insights are by no means publicity-seeking occasional remarks of which he is accused by his capital-apologetic detractors.96 They are consistently coupled with the most dedicated theoretical work in composing thousands of pages97 of his major unfinishable projects, formulated from within the horizon of his own class whose conscience Sartre tries to challenge and indeed shake. The unfinishable manuscripts express with great personal authenticity the impossibility to realize the chosen historical task by the reactivation of even the best Enlightenment tradition, together with the once sincerely believed (but never instituted) Rights of Man characteristic of its horizon. Sartres inability to go beyond the formal apodicticity of the shared class horizon, confining his own categorial explanatory framework to the formal structures of history, despite his explicit promise and conscious efforts aimed at elucidating real history both in the political domain and in the world of morality, is inseparable from this connection. Sartres writings on ethics, which were not lost, show a repeated attempt to overcome the forbidding practical impediments of the given historical situation in terms of his appeal to the moral imperative, formulated frequently in the Kantian spirit. In a major lecture, written not in his youth but nearly at the age of sixty, he quotes Kants famous dictumyou ought to, therefore you canand insists on the primacy and centrality of individual praxes in contrast to collective and institutional structures.98 However, this attachment to the Kantian legacy and its corollaries is not without serious problems. For the German philosopher, to whom Sartre is deeply indebted throughout his intellectual life, does not hesitate to reconcile the fundamental contradiction between the formal requirements of Enlightenment rationality (and corresponding equality) and the most blatant perpetuation of substantive inequality even in the domain of the law. He argues in this way:
The general equality of men as subjects in a state coexists quite readily with the greatest inequality in degrees of the possessions men have, whether the possessions consist of corporeal or spiritual superiority or in material possession besides. Hence the general equality of men also coexists with great inequality of specific rights of which there may be many. . . . Nevertheless, all subjects are equal to each other before the law which, as a pronouncement of the general will, can only be one. This law concerns the form and not the matter of the object regarding which I may possess a right.99

262

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

As we can see the greatest moral philosopher of the bourgeoisie in the ascendant, Immanuel Kant, who models the universality and validity of the moral judgement as such on the form of the natural law, can find absolutely nothing wrong with the total denial of substantive equality to the overwhelming majority of the people. Even his reference to the idea of Rousseaus general will cannot make any difference in that respect. The insoluble contradiction between the actually existing system of formalized law and the legitimately enforced substantive inequality in society and in the state is supposed to be overcome by Kants peremptory decree according to which the law as such can be concerned only with the form and not with the matter of the object in question. Consequently the law can be most iniquitously discriminatory even in terms of the specific rights which it may or may not grant to whoever it pleases, and yet qualifying at the same time as fully adequate to the rational requirement of the general equality of men as subjects in a state, justified with reference to its claimed harmony with the general will. Although in this way we find in Kantwho was, like Sartre, greatly inspired by Rousseaua characteristic interpretation of the general will, corresponding to the Sovereignty of the People, the Kantian advocacy of the materially discriminatory idea of equality, in tune with the established order of private property, is not in conflict with some of Rousseaus most important tenets. For the great French philosopher of the Enlightenment insists with unmistakable firmness that the right of property is the most sacred of all the rights of citizenship, and even more important in some respect that liberty itself; property is the true foundation of civil society, and the real guarantee of the undertakings of citizens100 . . . the general administration [embodied in the state] is established only to secure individual property, which is antecedent to it.101 Naturally, Sartre advocates the real equality of all individuals in society, and he can only scorn the great inequality of specific rights (in favor of those who can pay for it) imposed by the hypocritical practices of actually existing law. However, he cannot extricate himself from the formal apodicticity of the system oriented toward asserting the primacy and historical viability of the individual praxes, in the spirit of the aggregates of individuality idealized by the best philosophical tradition of capitals ascending phase of development, including the conceptions of Rousseau, Kant, Adam Smith and Hegel. Sartres ever renewed direct appeals to individual consciousness are obvious manifestations of that. That kind of orientation carries with it idealizations of its own kind in relation to the present, as we find it clearly demonstrated in Sartres greatly overrated characterization of the French Maoist

M AT ER IAL AND F OR M AL STRUCTURES O F H ISTO RY

263

students directly supported by him,102 who later in fact ceased to have anything to do with an even vaguely progressive, let alone genuine revolutionary, perspective. And, of course, the problems go much deeper than that as far as the question of the necessary historical alternative to the established order is concerned. For the obverse side of the same coin of expecting the required solution from the direct appeal to individual consciousness had to be that far too much was granted by Sartre, exactly the same way as by Marcuse, to the continued historical viability of so-called advanced capitalism and organized capitalism.
SA RT R E S HISTOR IC AL CO NCEP TIO N IS H AUNTED to the very end by his dismissal of the idea of the We-subject in Being and Nothingness. As we have seen in Section 7.3 of The Social Determination of Method, according to the Sartrean existentialist ontology

The oppressed class can, in fact, affirm itself as a We-subject only in relation to the oppressing class. . . . But the experience of the We remains on the ground of individual psychology and remains a simple symbol of the longedfor unity of transcendences. . . . The subjectivities remain out of reach and radically separated. . . . We should hope in vain for a human we in which the intersubjective totality would obtain consciousness of itself as a unified subjectivity. Such an ideal could be only a dream produced by a passage to the limit and to the absolute on the basis of fragmentary, strictly psychological experiences. . . . It is therefore useless for humanity to seek to get out of this dilemma; one must either transcend the Other or allow oneself to be transcended by him. The essence of the relation between consciousnesses is not the Mitsein [being with]; it is conflict.103

This view of the nature of the We-subject as a mere projection of individual psychology is linked by Sartre in the same work to the assertion according to which the conception of humanity is totally illusory, derived from the notion of God as a radical absence, and thus it is forever renewed and forever results in failure. Accordingly Each time that we use the Us in this sense (to designate suffering humanity, sinful humanity, to determine an objective historical meaning by considering man as an object which is developing its potentialities) we limit ourselves to indicating a certain concrete experience to be undergone in the presence of the absolute Third; that is, of God. Thus the limiting concept of humanity (as the totality of the Us-object) and the limiting concept of God imply one another and are correlative.104

264

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

By the time we reach the Critique of Dialectical Reason Sartre is willing to give some tangible meaning to the concept of humanity by saying that Our critical investigation must also show how the practical multiplicity (which may be called man or Humanity according to taste) realizes, in its very dispersal, its interiorization.105 However, also in this work the existentialist ontological underpinning of the relationship between myself and the Otherdepicted as the interchange in reciprocity between the Other as myself and myself as the Other, in the domain of history developed within the permanent framework of a field of tension produced by scarcity106makes conflictuality and struggle insuperable. Also, defining Humanity by the term practical multiplicityor, rather, agreeing politely to call Sartres really operative term of practical multiplicity also by the name of Humanity according to tasteleaves the door wide open to an insuperably individualistic account of some vital historical processes. This outcome cannot be helped by Sartre in view of the absence of theorizing in his philosophy the required complex mediations (not confined to the circularly deterministic field of materiality107) through which the objective and subjective factors can be brought together, not least by indicating the sustainable constitution of the we-subject as the transformatory agent of historical development, in contrast to the fateful necessity of its relapse into self-induced seriality. We have to consider here a most difficult and somewhat convoluted passage from the Critique of Dialectical Reason. Its great complexity is due to Sartres internal difficulties of trying to find solutions in this important work to the addressed problems within the categorial framework adopted by him. For his categorial framework itself stubbornly resists his attempts at finding the desired solutions. Nevertheless, it is necessary to quote this passage in its integrality because it sums up better than anything else Sartres general approach to history. This is how it reads:
In its attempted transcendence of this concrete objectivity (which only succeeds in so far as it is not prevented by the Other), the praxis of struggle awakens, actualises, comprehends and transcends the constitutive praxis of the Other in so far as he is himself a practical subject; and in its action against the Other, on the completion of this very transcendence and through the mediation of the field of materiality, it reveals and produces the Other as an object. From this point of view, the anti-dialectical negation appears as a moment in a more complex dialectic. At first, in fact, this negation is precisely what is transcended: the praxis is constituted for both as the

M AT ER IAL AND F OR M AL STRUCTURES O F H ISTO RY

265

negation of negation: not only through everyones transcendence of his object-being, but practically through everyones attempts to liquidate the practical subject in the Other outside and from the outside and to recover his objectivity through this transcendent destruction. Thus the antagonistic negation is grasped by everyone as a scandal which has to be transcended. But at the level of scarcity its origin does not lie in this revelation of scandal: it is a struggle for life; thus the scandal is not only grasped in its appearance as scandal, but also profoundly comprehended as the impossibility that the two should co-exist. Consequently the scandal is not, as Hegel supposed, the mere existence of the Other, which would take us back to a statute of unintelligibility. It lies in suffered (or threatened) violence, that is in interiorised scarcity. In this respect, although the original fact is logically and formally contingent (scarcity is only a materially given), its contingency is far from impairing the intelligibility of violence. What is important for the dialectical comprehension of the Other, is the rationality of his praxis. Now this rationality appears in violence itself, in so far as this is not the contingent ferocity of man, but everyones intelligible reinteriorisation of the contingent fact of scarcity: human violence is meaningful. And as this violence is a negation of the Other in everyone, negation, in its reciprocity, becomes meaningful in and through everyone, as scarcity turned practical agent, or in other words as human-scarcity. Thus practical negation is constituted as a negation of scandal-negation both in so far as the latter is the Other in everyone and in so far as this Other is interiorised scarcity. From this point of view, what is indissolubly negated by praxis is negation as the condition of man (that is to say, as a conditioning readopted in violence by the conditioned) and as the freedom of an Other. And in fact the scandal of the presence in me (as a mark of my object-being) of the Others freedom as the freedom-negation of my freedom, is itself a determination in rationality in so far as this negative freedom actualizes in practice the impossibility of our co-existing in the field of scarcity.108

Thus the dialectical intelligibility of history in this Sartrean vision is primarily concerned with the comprehension of the scandalous dialectical rationality of the Others praxis, in its threatening freedom that must be negated and transcended (indeed possibly liquidated as practical subject) in the unavoidable struggle for life. The question of violence is explained as dialectical intelligibility and rationality in terms of the full reciprocity at work whereby the objective determinations of conditioning are readopted in violence by the conditioned. In this way we are always

266

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

offered by Sartre a definition of the Other as the Other in everyone: a definition inseparable at the same time from the comprehension of violence as meaningful human violence. And precisely because interiorised scarcity as meaningful violence involves (and implicates) everyone, the antagonistic relationship affecting all human beings must be considered ipso facto dialectically intelligible and comprehensible. This conception of meaningful historical interchange also carries with it a most problematical definition of the historical agent. In one sense, applying to all individuals, it is the freein as much as consciously and actively threateningOther in everyone, including of course myself as the Other to the Other. But since this Other in everyonein its necessary constitution in and through full reciprocityis interiorised scarcity, through this marxisant existentialist ontological underpinning of the Sartrean vision of scarcity as such assumes a quasi-mythical status as the effective agent of history. This strange determination of the historical agent is paradoxically by directly linking the abstract universal to the abstract individual, in an attempt to demonstrate the dialectical intelligibility of that which is not universalizable, as mentioned before109due to the irreducible (repeatedly commended in that way by Sartre himself) individualistic conception of his philosophy. For due to the fact that the claimed dialectically intelligible violence in history is said to be a negation of the Other in everyone, negation itself, in its reciprocity, becomes meaningful in and through everyone, as scarcity turned practical agent. In this spirit we are subsequently presented by Sartre with the firmest possible assertion concerning the nature of comprehension, positive and negative reciprocity and intelligibility itself, modeled also at this point in his analysis, in terms of its simultaneously individualistic orientation and abstract universality, on the existentialist life or death struggle of myself with the Other. These concluding remarks lead again to the frequently repeated promise about elucidating in the forthcoming second volume of the Critique, on the basis of the formal structures discussed in its first, the dialectical intelligibility of historical totalization in real history. The lines in question read like this:
To comprehend in struggle is to grasp the praxis of the Other in immanence, through its own objectivity and in a practical transcendence. I now comprehend the enemy through myself and myself through the enemy. . . . Comprehension is an immediate fact of reciprocity. But as long as this reciprocity remains positive, comprehension remains abstract

M AT ER IAL AND F OR M AL STRUCTURES O F H ISTO RY

267

and external. Struggle, in the field of scarcity, as negative reciprocity, engenders the Other as Other than man, or as anti-human; but at the same time I comprehend him, in the very springs of my praxis, as a negation of which I am a concrete practical negation, and as mortal danger. For each of the adversaries, this struggle is intelligible; or rather, at this level, it is intelligibility itself. Otherwise, reciprocal praxis would in itself have no meaning or goal. But what concerns us is the general problem of intelligibility, particularly at the concrete level. . . . These questions bring us at last to the real problem of History. If History is to be the totalization of all practical multiplicities and of all their struggles, the complex products of the conflicts and collaborations of these very diverse multiplicities must themselves be intelligible in their synthetic reality, that is to say, they must be comprehensible as the synthetic products of a totalitarian praxis. This means that History is intelligible if the different practices which can be found and located at a given moment of the historical temporalisation finally appear as partially totalising and as connected and merged in their very oppositions and diversities by an intelligible totalisation from which there is no appeal.110

However, the insuperable difficulty is that the Sartrean formal structures of historyvalidly applicable in terms of their illuminating political determinations, if coupled with their complementary socioeconomic qualifications, to capitals highly specific and historically transient stage of developmentcannot yield the dialectical intelligibility of real history in general. On the one hand they are made problematical by their existentialist ontological underpinning which structurally opposes itself to the We-subject even in Sartres marxisant phase of development, and on the other, by the Sartrean conception of advanced capitalism and organized capitalism, and its militantly with great integrity postulated but socially undefined counterforce. This is what we must consider on the remaining pages of this chapter.
T H E F I RST ID E A T HAT N EED S REASSESSMENT is the concept of reciprocity postulated by Sartre. He puts forward that idea as part of the existentialist ontological underpinning which he intends to give to his own categorial framework. The envisaged Sartrean conceptual framework is meant to account thanks to his marxisant existentialist idea of reciprocityas fully for the relationship between the particular individuals as for those social formations which should be described in his view as practical multiplicities,

268

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

including humanity according to taste. For Sartre claims that such a categorial framework is the only way to provide the dialectical foundations of a structural anthropology, formulated first in synchronic terms as the elementary formal structures.111 This is according to Sartre the necessary conceptual foundation on the basis of which it becomes possible for him to consider the diachronic depth of practical temporalization112 in the promised second volume of the Critique of Dialectical Reason, thereby accounting for the dialectical intelligibility of real history. Sartre needs the claimed marxisant existentialist concept of full reciprocity (and circularity) because in his view the symmetrical relationship between the Other and the individual subjectin that the subject must be reduced by the Other, in accordance with the requirement of Sartrean reciprocity, to the status of an object and threatened to be destroyed in that way in the course of the insuperable struggle for life in the historical domain asserted by Sartre to be born and developed within the permanent field of tension produced by scarcity113enables him to postulate at the same time the negative but again appropriate and full reciprocity as the necessary condition of dialectical intelligibility. For this way of conceiving the relationship in question makes it possible for him to posit also on the opposite side of the equation the same negative and circular reciprocity through which the Other in myself likewise transforms the free praxis of the Other outside into the enemy objectso as to liquidate it as the rival subject that must be prevented from realizing its own design as free praxis and mortal danger for mein the process of my self-assertion as the only acceptable free praxis prevailing against the Other in interiorized scarcity. This is how I comprehend the enemy through myself and myself through the enemy as a result of which dialectical comprehension itself becomes an immediate fact of reciprocity.114 This is perfectly coherent in its ownSartrean marxisant existentialistterms of reference. The problem is, however, that all individuals in our historically created, and up to the present thus maintained societies, are constitutive parts of determinate class formations. Inevitably, therefore, in the actual class reality of real history, as we have to confront it until it is historically superseded by actual societal developmentin obvious contrast to the abstractly postulated individualistic account of the permanent enmity between myself and the Other in the Sartrean categorial framework of circularly reciprocal determination and negationthere is definitely not, and there cannot possibly be, any symmetrically conceptualizable relationship of circular reciprocity. On the contrary, we find not

M AT ER IAL AND F OR M AL STRUCTURES O F H ISTO RY

269

only in the present order but also in the class societies constituted across history some system of very far from symmetrical structural domination and subordination which changes only in its historical specificityfrom slavery through serfdom to the wage slavery of the capitalist orderbut not in its fundamental modality of hierarchical structural domination that lacks any resemblance to Sartrean reciprocity. Accordingly, the challenge for the class of labor (and of its particular members), in their capacity oriented toward constituting the necessary and only feasible historical alternative to capitals societal reproductive order, concerns the establishment of a non-hierarchical structural framework of social metabolic reproduction, to be accomplished on a substantive equitable and thereby historically sustainable material and political basis. And that involves, to be sure, the task of overcoming within such qualitatively different new societal reproductive horizon the historically to our own days prevailing, and through its unique vicious circle wastefully perpetuated, but at least in principle superable, objective conditions of socially specific capital-accumulating scarcity. Indeed, the now fetishistically enduring vicious circle of scarcity is quite unique precisely in its immense but deliberately promoted wastefulness. Moreover, as such it is supposed to remain operative in its totally untenable cultivated wastefulness and globalizing destructiveness for the unsustainable prosaic cause of endless capital-accumulation, in contrast to the somber vision of our struggle for life over the existentialistically postulated mortal danger embodied in the Other in everyone, defined as ontologically insuperable interiorized scarcity. After 1968 Sartre confessed that I have always remained an anarchist. When Michel Contat reminded him of that admission, in the interview published under the title of Self-Portrait at Seventy, this was Sartres answer:
That is very true. . . . I have changed in the sense that I was an anarchist without knowing it when I wrote Nausea. I did not realize that what I was writing could have an anarchist interpretation; I saw only the relation with the metaphysical idea of nausea, the metaphysical idea of existence. Then, by way of philosophy, I discovered the anarchist in me. But when I discovered it I did not call it that, because today anarchy no longer has anything to do with the anarchy of 1890.
CONTAT : Actually, you never identified yourself with the so-called anarchist movement.

270

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E SARTRE : Never. On the contrary, I was very far away from it. But I never allowed anyone to hold power over me, and I have always thought that anarchywhich is to say, a society without powersmust be brought about.115

Revealingly enough, the question of advocating the establishment of a society without powersirrespective of the name conferred upon the political creed associated with it, from nineteenth century anarchism to the presentgoes to the heart of the matter. Naturally, it is not enough for a prominent and throughout his life socially most privileged individual to say: I never allowed anyone to hold power over me. The really difficult problems are: whether, to what extent, and in which sustainable form, the rejection of power exercised over oneself is generalizable in its applicability to the present and to the future. For, obviously and Sartre would have to be the first to admit itin the case of the overwhelming majority of the people in our actually existing societies today, even simply raising that question, not to mention the major impediments encountered for successfully translating it into their practically sustainable circumstances by the far from privileged individuals, in their capacity as more or less isolated individuals, cannot arise. Wage slavery is not very reassuring in that respect, even if the old historical forms of slavery and serfdom have been as a rule successfully consigned to the past, even if by no means everywhere. Naturally, the fact itself that the issue can be raised at all in our time, and indeed that it could be raised in some form already in the nineteenth century, shows some significant advancement in terms of the objective dialectic of historical development, and not only in terms of its comprehensibility and intelligibility. For in the remote past the slaves could be simply categorized as talking tools even by a giant of philosophy, like Aristotle, as mentioned before. In this sense Sartres ideal of anarchy that must be brought about, called by him a society without powers, can only mean a society in which there is no separate body exercising power over the individuals against their aspirations and will. The issue is then: what are the conditions for the realization of such a society? And that is the point where the question of how to deal with the established social orderdescribed by Sartre and others as advanced capitalism and organized capitalismmust be confronted. In other words, the fundamental question is: what are the actually required and feasible leverages through which capitals social order can be radically transformed in the desired direction?

M AT ER IAL AND F OR M AL STRUCTURES O F H ISTO RY

271

Nineteenth century anarchism was dismissed by Marx in no uncertain way. He wrote about Bakunins book: Statehood and Anarchy, that its author has only translated Proudhons and Stirners anarchy into the barbaric idiom of the Tartars.116 And Marx argued that A radical social revolution is bound up with definite historical conditions of economic development; these are its premises. . . . Bakunin understands absolutely nothing of social revolution, only its political rhetoric; its economic conditions simply do not exist for him. . . . Willpower, not economic conditions, is the basis of his social revolution.117 But even if we ignore the weighty historical baggage of the nineteenth century varieties of anarchism, for the sake of an idealized anarchist society without powers advocated by Sartre, some fundamental objective determinations and difficulties cannot be disregarded. Especially if at the same time the supposedly inexorable power of advanced capitalism and organized capitalism is reasserted, so as to be opposed by a direct political appeal to individual consciousness invited to join a new sovereign group118illustrated with the example of the French Maoist studentsand contrasted with organized Parties (and other stable organized structures) that are said to have remained in the nineteenth century. Yet capitalisminseparable from those historical conditions of economic development which were put so powerfully into relief by Marx in all of his seminal workscannot be overcome at the political level only,119 no matter how genuine might be the willpower of the individuals who wish to oppose it in that way.
T H E KEY P R OB L E M IN T H IS RESP ECT is the objectively grounded centrifugality of the capital system itself in its innermost constitution as a mode of social metabolic reproduction. As the interested reader can see it discussed in my book on The Dialectic of Structure and History,120 the modern state emerged and expanded in relation to that insuperable centrifugality, not least for the purpose of bringing under a feasible degree of control its potentially most disruptive aspects. This epochal historical process was accomplishedon the ground of the underlying material determinationsin the interest of the dynamic expansion of the capital system as a whole, in its inseparability from the increasingly more powerful modern state. That is indeed where we can see a real reciprocity. But, of course, this kind of reciprocity is, again, very far from being symmetrical. It is defined by a determinate type of social and historical interrelationship in which the dialectical primacy121not to be confused with a mechanical onesidednessbelongs to the fundamental material determinations.

272

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Naturally, this type of reciprocally secured development between politics and the economy, on the material reproductive ground of capitals necessary centrifugality, also means that negating the political dimension on its own, in the spirit of even the most idealized conception of anarchism, could only absolutize or exasperate the systemic centrifugality of the established mode of social metabolic reproduction, resulting in total uncontrollability. This is why anarchism had to prove to be a non-starter in all of its varieties in the past. The historically constituted and structurally entrenched reciprocity of capitals fundamental dimensions can only be overcome by radically altering the material reproductive as well as the political dimensions together, and doing that on the appropriate systemic scale. The partial material co-operative ventures known to uswhich attempted to change the system through the work of the productive and distributive co-operativesrepresented the obverse side of the anarchist political coin. Significantly, however, despite the good will invested in such co-operatives by their adherents, they could not make a practicable inroad into the structural determinations of capitals social order on other than a minute scale. Not even when the political anarchist and the material co-operative sides of the coin have been brought together, as in Spain, in the anarcho-co-operative enterprises. Here it is well worth reminding ourselves of the fact that Marx never hesitated theoretically stressing the idea, and also passionately advocating it in his pioneering organizational involvement in the international socialist movement of his time, that the economic emancipation of the working class is the great end to which every political movement ought to be subordinate as a means.122 The same idea, underlining the dialectical primacy of the material basis of capitals social order, was reiterated by one of the greatest intellectual and political figures of the socialist movement, Rosa Luxemburg, when she wrote:
What distinguishes bourgeois society from other class societiesfrom ancient society and from the social order of the Middle Ages . . . is precisely the fact that class domination does not rest on acquired rights but on real economic relations; the fact that wage labour is not a juridical relation but purely an economic relation.123

In the same sense, it would be a great mistake to imagine that imperialism can be overcome at the political/military level, as many people after the

M AT ER IAL AND F OR M AL STRUCTURES O F H ISTO RY

273

second world war naively started to celebrate the arrival of the age of postimperialism. Also in this regard Rosa Luxemburgs words, which highlighted the inescapable and historically evolved economic foundations of imperialist political/military strategies, remain valid to our own days, despite the fact that they were written almost a century ago. This is how they read:
Imperialism is not the creation of any one or of any group of states. It is the product of a particular state of ripeness in the world development of capital, an innately international condition, an indivisible whole, that is recognizable only in all its relations, and from which no nation can hold aloof at will. Capitalism is incompatible with economic and political divisions. . . . It needs for its development large, united territories . . . and [to] lift the demands and needs of society to a plane corresponding to the prevailing stage of capitalist production and to the mechanism of modern capitalist class rule.124

Accordingly, the devastating political/military dangers of imperialisma system of most iniquitous internal determinations and corresponding interstate relations which can change its historical specificity but not its structurally entrenched substancecannot be consigned to the past without radically overcoming the material reproductive dimension of the capital system as an integrated whole. The incurable centrifugality of the capital system can only intensify its contradictions and heighten the dangers necessarily associated with them in an age of globally conflicting vested interests asserted by the dominant monopolistic forces, corresponding to the now prevailing stage of articulation of capitals mode of social metabolic reproduction. Direct political appeals to individual consciousness, even in the most idealized spirit of anarchism, cannot counter the power of the vital material reproductive determinations whose analysis is missing from Sartres work not only before the Critique of Dialectical Reason but also later. The formal structures of history offered by Sartre in the two volumes of the Critique of Dialectical Reason, and reiterated in different ways in his subsequent writings, always remained well within the framework of the posited formal determinations, oriented toward an increasingly more elusive political advocacy after the great disappointments he suffered following the moments of hope in 1968 and in its immediate aftermath. Sinking into a deeply pessimistic mood in his final years was therefore sadly but perfectly understandable in the case of a combative intellectual, like Sartre, who after the defeat of 1968 could not envision any leverage

274

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

by which he could from within even slightly alter, let alone dislodge from its hinges, as he once hoped, the political consciousness of the class against which he passionately rebelled. The pessimistic idea that advanced capitalism and organized capitalism might be able to offer some long-term sustainable remedy to capitals antagonistic second order mediations could not be of any help in this respect. The necessary point of departure for an alternative approach cannot be other than an attempt to put firmly into relief the material structures of history. Not as given once and for all, in an abstractly posited generality, with unsustainable claims to formally universalizable validity extended to all possible phases of history, but in its actually unfolding and changing specificity. And that framework would have to be identified in our time in accordance with the never in the past experienced historical determinationswith their deeply antagonistic and therefore in the last analysis unrealizable tendency toward global integrationwhich correspond to the ever more destructive monopolistic material and political/military stage of capitals imperialist articulation as a societal reproductive system, directly threatening even humanitys relationship to nature. To be sure, this point of departure, in its unavoidable historical specificity and orientation, could offer no a priori apodicticity of any kind for understanding the dialectical intelligibility of historical development once and for all. Any attempt to do so would be in relation to actually unfolding history a crass contradiction in terms. The idea of postulating a set of eternally valid material structures of history in the spirit of some kind of aprioristic apodicticity could only assume the shape of a strait-jacket, or a bed of Procrustes, to which necessarily open-ended real history would have to be arbitrarily tied or imaginarily chained. In truth there can be no categorically generalizable material structures for all conceivable phases of real history, nor indeed any universally extended formal structures. For the real history of human societal existence could not qualify for being history at all by closing its gates to alternative forms of development with the help of some hypostatized permanent structures, even if they be at a determinate time in history clearly identifiable material structures. Nothing illustrates this proposition better than Marxs explicitly stated insistence that the category of historical necessity makes no sense at all unless it is understood as historically changing and vanishing necessity. Moreover, once the objective and subjective conditions for the establishment of a rational planning process are consolidated in the course of the historically pursued and sustained socialist transformation, the power

M AT ER IAL AND F OR M AL STRUCTURES O F H ISTO RY

275

of earlier overwhelming economic determinations is bound to be greatly diminished. It is put into its place as an integral but subordinate part of a conscious socialist accountancy. That form of accountancy becomes practicable only in the absence of the predetermined and self-perpetuating vested interests of capitals willing personifications who expropriate to themselves the power of managing the societal metabolism even if they cannot control it, irrationally steering society instead in the direction of systemic annihilation. For only the socialist accountancy can confer their properand not fetishistically absolutizedweight upon the objectively limiting factors, within the adopted framework of humanly rewarding and positively interiorized objectives. That is so because the real meaning of the words quoted about the economic emancipation of the working class is the emancipation of humanity from the blindly prevailing power of economic determinism under which no human being can ever be in genuine control of the social metabolism, not even the most willing personifications of capital. Only through the qualitative transformation of laborfrom being the alienated and structurally subordinate but necessarily recalcitrant social class of the reproduction process into the universal regulative principle of humanitys interchange with nature and among its individual members, freely embraced as their meaningful lifeactivity by all members of societyonly through such transformation can real human emancipation be accomplished in the course of open-ended historical development. That is the reason why Marx was contrasting to what he called prehistory not some kind of Messianic end of historyalthough he is often crudely accused of doing thatbut the dynamic process of actually unfolding and consciously controlled real history. That is: history no longer ruled by antagonistic economic determinations but lived in accordance with their chosen aims and objectives by the social individuals as freely associated producers. In fact the categories called by Sartre the formal structures of history are most illuminating for a limited phase of capitalistic developments, on account of their affinity with some important material and human characteristics of the formally equalized articulation of generalized commodity production. But they could not be extended to the whole of history, from the most remote past to the indefinite future. That kind of universal extensionand corresponding closureis inadmissible not only for the material structures of history, which must be grasped always in their historical specificity, irrespective of how long the underlying determinations can assert

276

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

themselves in the changing societal domain, but also for what may be legitimately called formal structures in an appropriately defined social setting. Sartre could be no exception to that. Indeed Sartre himself supplied his own proof for the impossibility of modifying and extending his own formal structures in the postulated way by his inability to complete the original project125 repeatedly announced for the elaboration of the conceptual framework of real history in the second volume of his Critique of Dialectical Reason.
T H E P E S S I M I ST I C I D E A S H A R E D A LS O BY SART R E that advanced capitalism and organized capitalism represent a significantly different and historically more sustainable phase of the capital systems development than its nineteenth century variety, to which the political Parties of the left have allegedly remain anchored, is quite unfounded. The opposite is much nearer to the by no means pessimistic truth. The deciding issue concerns the rational restrainability and controllability of any societal reproductive order in relation to the historical actuality and availability of its necessary conditions of reproduction. And the most uncomfortable truth of the matter in this respect is that a socioeconomic reproductive order, the now established societal order, whose viability depends on endless capital expansion, must constantly generate not only (to a large extent manipulable or even repressible) subjective but also irrepressible objective expectationsboth for others and for itselfwhich it cannot possibly fulfill. In this sense, in contrast to capitals existing order, only a qualitatively different way of managing the social metabolism, from the elementary material processes to the highest levels of artistic production and enjoyment could make a real difference in this respect. And that would imply a radically different orientation of the social individuals toward consciously pursued communal coherence of their activities, in place of the now prevailing and potentially disintegrative centrifugality of their conditions of existence. This is so because for as long as the antagonistic second order mediations of the capital system remain dominant, they are bound to call for some kind of political super-imposition, instead of militating against it in the spirit of the anarchistic desideratum of society without powers. There can be no such thing as a society without powers. Especially not in an age of globally unfolding production and societal reproduction. The now established reproductive order is inseparable from its antagonistic second order mediations for the simple reason that they are required for

M AT ER IAL AND F OR M AL STRUCTURES O F H ISTO RY

277

the irrational pursuit of endless capital-expansion irrespective of the consequences. However, this system is bound to produce recalcitrance (in the producing individuals), the superimposition of extraneous control (in order to defeat recalcitrance, if necessary by violence), and at the same time also institutionalized irresponsibility (because of the absence of rationally feasible and acceptable control). It is not too difficult to see how problematical it must be to regulate advanced capitalist society on the basis of such practices and corresponding results even on a limited national scale, not to mention the necessity to keep the intensifying contradictions under the lid in their unavoidably unfolding global setting. Understandably, therefore, the only way to sustain a globally coordinated reproductive order on our horizon is by envisaging co-operatively shared material and political power, determined and administered on the basis of not simply formal but substantive equality (an absolute must as the condition of feasibility of a viable future societal order) and the corresponding rational planning of their life activities by the freely associated producers. Naturally, this is inconceivable without the appropriate form of mediation of the social individuals among themselves and in their combined relationship, as real humanity (though not according to taste), to nature. However, there is nothing mysterious or prohibitively difficult about advocating a qualitatively different system of societal reproductive mediation. The conditions of its establishment can be spelled out in a tangible way, involving a determined and historically sustained effort to break the stranglehold of exchange value over humanly adopted and gratifying use value, corresponding not to formally equalizable and substantively incommensurable as well as callously ignored human needs, but to the individuals as freely associated individuals asserting directly meaningful human need. The basic organizing principle of the kind of societal reproductive activity which is oriented toward such a qualitatively different social metabolic order was described by Marx in very simple terms, with reference to the communal interchange of the life-activity of the individuals, when he wrote that
The communal character of production would make the product into a communal, general product from the outset. The exchange which originally takes place in productionwhich would not be an exchange of exchange values but of activities,determined by communal needs and communal purposeswould from the outset include the participation of the individuals in the communal world of products.126

278

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Obviously, regulating and freely coordinating their life-activities by the individuals implies ongoing positive adjustments. The required genuine positive adjustments in a socialist order become feasible thanks to the removal of the structurally entrenched vested interests of the alienating class existence of the past, with its institutionalized irresponsibility under the capital system. Accordingly, the productive and distributive activity of the individuals can be promoted and maintained not by postulating a society without powers but by the fully shared powers of the members of society, inseparable from the adoption of their fully shared responsibility. That is the only viable and historically sustainable alternative to the growing destructiveness of advanced capitalism and organized capitalism.

7. Lvi-Strauss against Sartre


by one of his devotees as structuralism personified admitted in an interview which he gave in 1971 to the prominent French weekly journal, LExpress, that since 1968 structuralism went out of fashion.128 In fact what was remarkable in this respect was not the fact that in the 1970s structuralism started to fade away, being pushed out of the limelight by post-structuralism and other similarly oriented post-denominations, like post-modernity.129 Rather, the somewhat astonishing circumstance was that after the second world war the ideology of structuralism had actually acquired an extremely dominant position, and maintained it for well over a decadefrom the middle of the 1950s to the end of the 1960sin European and American intellectual circles.130 Of course, this postwar period coincided with the pretenses of the end of ideology131 both in America and in Europe. Structuralism, with its claims to represent the ultimate of scientific rigour in the field of the human sciences,132 fitted very well into the prevailing intellectual and political climate. Even more strangely for Lvi-Strauss himself, the nonideological aspirations of his celebrated orientation were combined with explicitly claiming to be simultaneously a marxisant intellectual, like Jean-Paul Sartre. As late as the 1971 interview published in LExpress Lvi-Strauss was still asserting that he was a marxisant thinker. In this regard the postwar intellectual prominence of the Communist Party in France, professing its (Stalinistically updated) devotion to Marx, made
127

CLAUDE L V I- ST R AU S S eulogized

280

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

that ideological alignment perfectly understandable. At least to the extent of paying lip-service to Marx in the case of some important intellectuals like Lvi-Strauss. And even a figure openly hostile to any idea of socialism, Raymond Aron, who championed the American atlanticist perspective and Europes subservience to U.S. dominated NATO, could not avoid a negative dependency on the French C. P.s intellectual prominence. All this had changed considerably around the end of the 1960s. In fact the serious decline in the popularity of structuralism, dated by Lvi-Strauss himself to the years immediately following May 1968 in France, and the simultaneous appearance of various post-structuralist ideological approaches, coincided with the new phase in the development of the capital system marked by its deepening structural crisis. However, even Lvi-Strauss erstwhile claim that he was a follower of Marx, in any sense at all, should be taken with a mountain size pinch of salt. Not only with regard to hisextremely pessimisticposition recorded in his major interview in 1971,133 but also in relation to the rest of his work before that date or after. For as regards the theory of the superstructure in which he suggested that he had elaborated his own unique version of the Marxian conceptasserting at the same time without any justification that the superstructural domain was left virtually untouched by Marx, who was supposed to have assigned to it only an unfilled spacethe characteristic approach to the field offered by Lvi-Strauss was incorrigibly ahistorical. And nothing could be more alien to Marxs lifework as a whole as well as to any particular aspect of it.134 In this spirit Lvi-Strauss was not only completely ignoring Marxs fundamental answers to the problems of the superstructure and ideology, conceived by him as dialectically linked to, and in that way inseparable from, the changing material basis of societyas we could see them in considerable detail for ourselves in my book on The Dialectic of Structure and Historybut offered a diametrically contradictory line of approach to the problems elaborated by Marx always in a profoundly historical sense. It is also important to underline here that the various post-structuralist and post-modernist ideological trends could not be considered significantly different in this respect. The extremely skeptical and problematical attitude to history was by no means confined to Lvi-Strauss himself. Indeed, the incorrigibly ahistorical approach to their object of enquiry constituted the common denominator of all kinds of postwar structuralism and post-structuralism, including the general line of structural functionalism advocatedwith Weberian allegiancesby Talcott Parsons, and heavily

L V I -STR AU S S AGAINST SA RTRE

281

promoted for capital-apologetic ideological purposes in the United States of America. The major conservative Swiss historian of the nineteenth century, Leopold von Ranke, coined the famous orienting principle for fellow historians according to which every age was equidistant from God. That line of thought amounted to categorically asserting that whatever might indicate the signs of historical development, in terms of Rankes views belonged to the world of illusion and false appearance. The claimed marxisant contribution by Lvi-Strauss to elucidating the nature of the superstructure from the elementary structures of kinship135 to the logics of myth136 and to the characterization of the relationship between history and La pense sauvage137had much the same equidistancing orientation in LviStrauss structural anthropology, devoted to the defense of the conceptual universe of the North and South American indian peoples vis--vis the thought produced in modern times anywhere. In other words, according to Lvi-Strauss the idea of historical advancement as such had to be considered extremely dubious, to put it mildly. Accordingly, it was not in the least surprising that when Lvi-Strauss was asked the question in 1971 by the interviewer of LExpress: So you think that history is devoid of any sense?, his gloomy answer could only be: If it has a sense, it is not a good one.138 In this way Lvi-Strauss position was even more retrograde than the historical skepticism of the prominent British conservative Sir Lewis Namier, discussed in Chapter 5. of The Social Determination of Method, who asserted that if there is sense in human history it escapes our perception.139 The idea of historical advancement is rejected by Lvi-Strauss in the most romantic fashion by postulating that in the vision of the world produced by the savage mind the whole of nature could speak to man.140 His imaginary solution to the gloomily described troubles of our contemporary world was said by him to be: the management of technological progress in a rather stationary way and strict population control. However, Lvi-Strauss pessimistically rejected his own solution as unrealizable immediately after mentioning it, coupled with an endorsing reference to the utopian views once advocated by the nineteenth century reactionary and indeed racist French writer Gobineau,141 who also turned away from his own projected utopia by ruefully saying that it was unrealizable. But Lvi-Strauss never bothered to spell out the necessary social qualifications concerning even the elementary conditions of feasibility of his proposed solutions whichin terms of their concern with technology and population controlcould fit in perfectly well with the wishful common places of ubiquitously promoted

282

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

capital apologetics.142 The pessimistic formulation of his comments was voiced on account of the nostalgically deplored unrealizability of the should-be (but alas cannot-be) solutions. (Mytho)-logically, therefore, Lvi-Strauss could only end his 1971 interview with the earlier mentioned doom-laden tirades against humanity in general,143 exempting at the same time from all blame the regimes, parties, groups and classes144 whose role is clearly recognizable in our actually unfolding history. in many ways even anti-historical character of Lvi-Strauss work is by no means the only sense in which his approach is diametrically contradictory to Marx. An equally serious aspect is his rejection of the Marxian unity of theory and practice. In fact Lvi-Strauss presents his opposition to socially committed practice as a commendable virtue when he contrasts his own stance to Sartrean existentialism by saying that structuralism, unlike existentialism favored by the young in and after 1968, is devoid of practical implications.145 What is very difficult to understand in this respect is this: why should one try to elucidate the complexboth substantive and methodological problems of the superstructure and ideology if not for putting to appropriate practical use the knowledge acquired through such investigation? That was indeed the vital concern expressed by Marx in his insistence about the cardinal importance of practice in orienting the intellectual enterprise. After all, as we have seen in the Introduction to The Social Determination of Method, already Descartes forcefully stressed the inherently practical nature and justification of his own engagement with the theoretical challenge of untying the deceptive skeptical knots produced by scholasticism in the field.146 Short of such practical orientation, what is the point at all of Lvi-Strauss romantic tirades against humanity, condemning it as its own worst enemy, ifallegedlynothing can be done about it, because the technological and population control utopia advocated by him (against population explosion as the postulated source of all evil) is said to be unrealizable? If really nothing can be done in order to remedy the identified problems, then also the act of voicing the gloomy romantic laments must be utterly pointless, and in a curious way even self-contradictory. We can see the self-contradiction in Lvi-Strauss approach to these issues by recalling a typical passage from The Savage Mind on the nature of history. It reads like this:
T H E I NC OR R IG IB LY AHISTO RICA L and

L V I -STR AU S S AGAINST SA RTRE

283

History is a discontinuous set composed of domains of history, each of which is defined by a characteristic frequency and by a differential coding of before and after. . . .the discontinuous and classificatory nature of historical knowledge emerges clearly. . . . In a system of this type, alleged historical continuity is secured only by dint of fraudulent outlines. We need only recognize that history is a method with no distinct object corresponding to it to reject the equivalence between the notion of history and the notion of humanity which some have tried to foist on us with the unavowed aim of making historicity the last refuge of a transcendental humanism: as if men could regain the illusion of liberty on the plane of the we merely by giving up the Is that are too obviously wanting in consistency. In fact history is tied neither to man nor to any particular object. It consists wholly in its method, which experience proves to be indispensable for cataloguing the elements of any structure whatever, human or non-human, in their entirety.147

Thus, when it suits the requirements of Lvi-Strauss positivistic characterization of history, humanity is ruled out of court with the typical exorcizing label of transcendental humanism. This curtly dismissive treatment of humanity is even reminiscent of Sartres earlier seen prewar condemnation of the We-subject in Being and Nothingness, also re-echoed by some strange structuralist Marxist authors. At the same time, in complete contrast to his earlier position, when adopting the tone of the romantic Jeremiads seems to be a more convenient form of discourse, humanity is resuscitated again as thealas hopelessly deaf or unwilling to listen addressee of Lvi-Strauss utterly gloomy but in ruling ideological circles curiously welcome and prominently diffused sermon. Not even the faintest memory remains of the once categorically dismissed refuge of a transcendental humanism and historicity in this updated reference to humanity, well in tune with the newly emerging and appropriately promoted globalized utopian and respectably classless ideological and political climate. Lvi-Strauss also claims to be a dialectical thinker. In reality, with the repetitive dualisms and dichotomies of his timeless and rigid structuralist approach he is not only undialectical but also anti-dialectical. Opposing continuity and discontinuity in the way in which we have seen it done by him in the last quotation, defining history as a discontinuous set, is a graphic example of that. Again, nothing could be more alien to the Marxian approach to history in which the dialectical relationship between continuity and discontinuity is always stressed as strongly in relation to the material basis as to the superstructure of society.

284

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

We can clearly see this dialectic also in the following quotation from the Grundrisse, where Marx discusses the fundamental issue of the categories, underlining that Bourgeois society is the most developed and the most complex historic organization of production. The categories which express its relations, the comprehension of its structure, thereby also allow insights into the structure and the relations of production of all the vanished social formations out of whose ruins and elements it built itself up, whose partly still unconquered remnants are carried along within it, whose mere nuances have developed explicit significance within it, etc.148 In this way the meaning of structure is illuminated, thanks to the profoundly dialectical conception of continuity and discontinuity in actual historical development from the vanished social formations to the most complex organization and relations of production in bourgeois society. By contrast, Lvi-Straussian structuralism turns into a reified fetish the concept of structure precisely because of its arbitrary dichotomous treatment of history, counterposing even the mystificatorily frozen idea of space to that of historically unfolding time. We have seen that Marx had put into relief in the strongest possible terms that We know only one science, the science of history.149 Lvi-Strauss rejects that approach, to be sure, not by naming Marx (after all, he is supposed to be also a marxisant intellectual in the field of the superstructure) but by sharply criticizing sinfully radical Sartre.150 He writes that Sartre is certainly not the only contemporary philosopher to have valued history above the other human sciences and formed an almost mystical conception of it. The anthropologist respects history, but he does not accord it a special value. He conceives it as a study complementary to his own: one of them unfurls the range of human societies in time, the other in space.151 It is a very strange complementarity indeed which operates on the premise of the dichotomous separation and opposition of space and time. We have seen in the last chapter in considerable detail Sartres approach to history developed in his Critique of Dialectical Reason. It does not resemble in the slightest Lvi-Strauss strictures against this major attempt at elucidating the dialectical character of historical totalization, irrespective of how far Sartre succeeds in completing to his own satisfaction the chosen very real philosophical task. To say that Sartre has an almost mystical conception of history is nothing more than a gratuitous insult voiced by an anti-historical and antidialectical thinker. Sartre, who was in fact most generous in the Critique of Dialectical Reason to Lvi-Strauss, was well justified when in his answer to such insult retorted: anyone who can write down the dialectic of this dichotomy shows he knows absolutely nothing about dialectic. And we

L V I -STR AU S S AGAINST SA RTRE

285

find in the same quotation from pages 26162 of The Savage Mind the adoption of another anti-dialectical dichotomyfor dichotomies are ubiquitous in Lvi-Strauss workalso when he crudely counterposes the concept of method to that of the object (on top of space and time, as well as continuity and discontinuity) in his characterization of history, reducing it to the task of cataloguing the elements of any structure, and thereby confining to a strictly subsidiary position the historians enterprise; which means in fact demoting it even from its (politely/evasively granted) complementary role.
NAT UR AL LY, L V I- ST R AU SS REA L TA RGET O F CENSURE is not simply Sartre but the Left in general, although he is supposed to be, of course, also an intellectual figure of the Left. But in actuality the leading French structuralist celebrated by the conservative weekly LExpress is no more a man of the Left than he is a follower of Marx or a dialectical thinker. He claims that superstructures are faulty acts [his emphases] which have made it socially. Hence it is vain to go to historical consciousness for the truest meaning. . . . in Sartres system history plays exactly the part of a myth. Indeed, the problem raised by the Critique de la raison dialectique is reducible to the question: under what conditions is the myth of the French Revolution possible?152 Thus, after he himself conveniently reduces everything in his conception of myth to the proverbial darkness in which all cows are black, Lvi-Strausswell armed again with his own claim of being a man of science who stands outside the merely contextual field of history153can proceed to aim his fire at his principal political target by saying that The so-called men of the Left still cling to a period of contemporary history which bestowed the blessing of a congruence between practical imperatives and schemes of interpretation. Perhaps this golden age of historical consciousness has already passed.154 Thus, in view of the prominent figure of French structuralism the only proper thing to do is to abandon any concern with practical imperatives unlike socially committed Sartrean existentialism deplorably favored by the youth in 1968 and after 1968, and disparagingly described by Lvi-Strauss as an old thing (une vieille chose)so as to offer in its stead the detached rigor (devoid of practical implications) of the structural anthropologist man of science. Lvi-Strauss is not disturbed even by directly contradicting himself in the same paragraph by first claiming that he is engaged in doing scientific work and immediately adding another one of his bizarre romantic laments by saying that But I cannot help thinking that science would be more lovable if it did not have to serve to anything.155

286

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

And yet Lvi-Strauss does not hesitate to appoint himself to the lofty status of standing outside the mere contextuality of temporally limited contemporary history and above the faulty acts of the superstructure which have made it socially. But can it be done? And in any case, what does it really mean, if anything? In truth the textual record shows thatin contrast to the groundless accusation according to which the main tenets of Sartres Critique of Dialectical Reason amount to no more than a myth about the French Revolution still fashionable on the Leftnothing could be more mythically inflated than Lvi-Strauss universal panacea of exchange. It is propounded by him fully in harmony with the well established conservative treatment of that categorycorresponding to a totally ahistorical and wild extension of its meaningin twentieth century ideology, including the characteristic role to which it is put in the aggressively anti-socialist crusade by Friedrich von Hayek.156 The full structural anthropologist arsenal of kinship is used by LviStrauss for that purpose, even if much of it is considered rather questionable in terms of the evidence peremptorily claimed by him, according to the critical view of those fellow anthropologists who are not wedded to the structuralist ideology of standing above ideology in virtue of having scientifically deciphered its code through the universalist Mytho-logics of the Lvi-Straussian superstructure. As the English anthropologist Edmund Leach underlined it, many would argue that Lvi-Strauss, like Frazer, is insufficiently critical of his source material. He always seems to be able to find just what he is looking for. Any evidence, however dubious, is acceptable so long as it fits with logically calculable expectations; but wherever the data runs counter to the theory Lvi-Strauss will either by-pass the evidence or marshal the full resources of his powerful invective to have the heresy thrown out of court!157 In this respect, too, we find in the writings of Lvi-Strauss a most disturbing anti-historical conception, motivated by conservative, and indeed reactionary, ideological interests. So much so in fact that at a certain point in the extensive March 1971 interview even the conservative magazine LExpress finds the gloomy romanticism too much to take on board and respectfully asks the question: Isnt it what you say very reactionary, in inverted commas?158 It is to this question that we are offered by Lvi-Strauss the final answer of his interview, which is utterly reactionary without any inverted commas, condemning humanity altogether as its own worst enemy and, alas, at the

L V I -STR AU S S AGAINST SA RTRE

287

same time also the worst enemy of the rest of the creation.159 That is the blind alley into which the reader is led by Lvi-Strauss mythologics. The insuperable problem for Lvi-Straussian structuralism is that the concept of exchange is inherently historical. Indeed, precisely in view of the comprehensive nature of exchange relations which actually change in the dialectical sense of continuity in discontinuity, and discontinuity in continuity, the most diverse reality corresponding to the term exchange is a historical category (a Daseinsform, i.e. a form of being) par excellence. If it is treated in any other way, by obliterating the qualitatively different determinations of its modes of being, this important category becomes fetishistically blurred in a most revealing way. The socially telling fetishization in question by Lvi-Strauss and others takes the form of conflating some clearly identifiable aspects of the claimed exchange relations and corresponding values (to be discussed in a moment) into a fallaciously posited one. This is done in more or less conscious conformityand of course in the descending phase of the capital systems development in much more rather than in less conscious conformityto the interests of the established socioeconomic and political order. It is by no means surprising or coincidental, therefore, that in LviStrauss mythologizing procedure the anti-historical and generic extension of the concept of exchange is associated with crying over the loss of the sense and secret of equilibrium160the mythical postulate of capital-apologetic modern scientific (even mathematically rigorous) economists and market idolators161and over the disintegration of civilization.162 For heaven forbid to point the finger to the crisis of capitalism, let alone to its grave and deepening structural crisis of which the explosion of May 1968 was an obvious early manifestation. In Lvi-Strauss books, by contrast, the dramatic events of 1968 and their non-conformist aftermaths are interpreted as an additional sign of the disintegration of a civilization which fails to secure the integration of the new generations that could be so well accomplished by the societies without writing.163 He attributes to Marx the absurd idea that social consciousness always lies to itself.164 For if it was really true that social consciousness always lied to itself, in that case the destruction of humanityin the form of LviStrauss cataclysmwould be an absolute certainty, and not a socially produced and socially preventable danger. No scheme of interpretation, let alone the vacuously claimed structuralist deciphering of the code of what is supposed to be hiding behind the necessary lies of social consciousness, could show a way out of the very real associated dangers. Objective historical

288

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

antagonisms and their contradictory incorporation in social consciousness can be consigned to the past only by the radical intervention of the human historical subject in the domain of objective social metabolic reproduction and not at the level of mythologicsin response to the prevailing, but by the structuralist man of science dismissed, practical imperatives. Significantly and most disconcertingly, however, with regard to the human subject and historical agent165 whose development in actually unfolding history is envisaged by Marx in the form of actively overcoming the false consciousness that must arise from the objective determinations of historically specific class antagonism, Lvi-Strauss sets up not just one of his many dichotomies but a hopelessly self-paralyzing irreducible antinomy166 between the most comprehensive historical and dialectical categories of subject and object. Every criticized phenomenon is presented in Lvi-Strauss work in an utterly vague and generic form, so as to avoid the embarrassing requirement to name the grave social specificity of capitals antagonistic reproductive order. In the same way as he was vacuously lamenting over civilization in general, he complains that society is becoming enormous, that it minimizes difference and spreads similarity, and that it fails to escape abrupt and hard determinism, etc. At the same time Lvi-Strauss refuses even to mention, let alone to seriously analyze, the tangible character of ruthless capitalist determinism at the roots of the deplored phenomena. Instead, he denounces progress in the most grotesque way, by saying that it brings only 10% good while 90% of the efforts dedicated to it must be spent on remedying the inconveniences.167 Also, in his wide-ranging 1971 interview, given to LExpress in the period when in the aftermath of the events of 1968 the organized reactionary forces in Parisactively promoted by the Gaullist regimeopenly display their aggressive determination in favor of the most repressive measures, marching on the Champs dlise in the center of the French capital shouting kill Sartre, civil war-machine, and even bomb his nearby apartment,168 LviStrauss has the nerve to say in the concluding paragraph of his interview, in response to the delicately raised suggestion that his views might sound somewhat reactionary to the readers, that The terms reactionary and revolutionary have no meaning except in relation to the conflicts of groups which oppose one another. But today the greater peril for humanity does not come from the activities of a regime, a party, a group, or a class.169 This is what we are asked to believe by the structuralist man of science. After all, we have been also invited by him to accept, as we have seen above,

L V I -STR AU S S AGAINST SA RTRE

289

thatcontrary to the foolish beliefs of the so-called men of the Left, la Sartre and his socially non-integrated followers among the dissenting youththe golden age which bestowed the blessing of a congruence between practical imperatives and schemes of interpretation has already passed.
T H E C ON T R AD ICTORY T REATMENT O F TH E TH O RNY ISSU E S of the exchange relationship, closely connected with the questions concerning use value and exchange value, go back a long way in the various theoretical conceptions formulated from the standpoint of capital. Not surprisingly, therefore, neglecting and even obliterating the historical dimension of the major issues, so as to be able to eternalize capitals societal reproductive order, is a general tendency in this field. Moreover, this tendency is clearly visible not only in twentieth century capital apologetics but also in the writings of the classical political economists. In this way the capitalist exchange relations are ahistorically universalized (and of course at the same time also legitimated) through their confusion with a completely dehistoricized conception of utility. Thus in the case of Ricardo, for instance, we find the baffling conflation of exchange value with use value and utility in general. This tendentious confounding transformation is accomplished in Ricardos work by treating the capitalist labor process and the creation of wealth through thein reality historically specificcapitalist exchange relation as natural and by assigning, in Marxs word, merely a ceremonial form to exchange value. In other words, for Ricardo

wealth itself, in its exchange-value form, appears as a merely formal mediation of its material composition; thus the specific character of bourgeois wealth is not graspedprecisely because it appears there as the adequate form of wealth as such, and thus, although exchange-value is the point of departure, the specific economic forms of exchange themselves play no role at all in his economics. Instead, he always speaks about distribution of the general product of labour and of the soil among the three classes, as if the form of wealth based on exchange-value were concerned only with use-value, and as if exchange-value were merely a ceremonial form, which vanishes in Ricardo just as money as medium of circulation vanishes in exchange.170

In contrast to such approaches, the importance of grasping the necessary historical mediations of both exchange and utility could not be greater. For the failure to identify the historically specific mediations in theoretical analysis can only yield the profundity of conveniently embellished

290

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

tautologies which, on the basis of their ability to claim (common place) self-evidence for themselves, frequently constitute only the preliminary step and the jumping board to the most arbitrary assertion of ideological vested interests at the next step. In this sense it is a tautology to say that property (appropriation) is a precondition of production. But it is altogether ridiculous to leap [in bourgeois political economy] from that to a specific form of property, e.g. private property. (Which further and equally presupposes an antithetical form, non-property.)171 It is an obvious tautology to say that exchange is a necessary (and in that sense universal) condition of human society. For how could the multiplicity of human individuals exist and reproduce themselves in their societies without exchangingsomething, sometime and other, somewhere, and somehow172 among themselves? For the individuals in question are neither genus-individuals, nor isolated individuals, as depicted in the bourgeois Robinsonnades in modern timesliving each of them as single individuals on their particular well stocked desert islands, like Robinson Crusoe, and waiting only for the arrival of Friday to serve them as laboring hands, in accordance with the ideal determinations of nature173but inescapably social individuals even under the most extreme dehumanizing conditions of capitalist alienation. The notion of exchange is tellingly reduced to a platitudinous tautology when it is proclaimed as a universal and permanent panacea, devised for the purpose of fallaciously smuggling into the equation as the necessary premise of all reasoning in the field the desired apologetic conclusion, in the absence of the really vitalinseparably social as well as historicaldimension of the substantive relationships at issue. The important category of exchange can acquire its theoretically relevant meaning only when it is inserted into the dynamic historical framework of socially determined specific mediations174 and complex interrelations through which the objective changes and transformations of its modalities changes ranging from capillary alterations to qualitatively/radically different and all-embracing magnitudesare convincingly displayed. That is to say, changes which unfold in accordance with the dialectic of continuity in discontinuity and discontinuity in continuity characteristic of historical/ transhistorical development. But development is what we are concerned with, even if often it is misrepresented as a simplistic straw-man linear progress, invented for the purpose of being set to fire with a single matchstick in the service of romantic structuralist laments. Indeed the annals of history show substantive development from the exchange relations of our distant ancestorswho are compelled to live for

L V I -STR AU S S AGAINST SA RTRE

291

a long historical period from hand to mouthto the globally interdependent and irrepressibly interactive, as well as potentially emancipatory, present and future. The emergence of this emancipatory potential is an integral part of the historical process itself, irrespective of how great might be thesocially preventable or rectifiabledangers which are now inseparable from capitals globalizing modality of social metabolic reproduction and from their historically specific and correspondingly destructive second order mediations. Without the concrete grasp of the social and historical determinations at stake in these matters the platitudinous tautology about exchange commended as a universal panacea can only amount to the mystifying apologetics of the established order. In the same sense, it is quite obvious that in necessarily changingand not structuralistically frozen and reifiedhuman society there can be no structure without history, in the same way as there can be no history of any magnitude without its corresponding structures. Structural imperatives and historical temporality are closely intertwined. For human society is inconceivable without its dynamic structuring determinations (often misrepresented as rigid architectural constructs, so as to be able to dismiss the Marxian base and superstructure metaphor) which secure some kind of cohesion even under the conditions of the antagonistic capital systems structural centrifugality. The structural imperatives may indeed assume the most rigid and even destructive form under determinate historical conditions and assert themselves behind the backs of the individuals if need be, as precisely they happen to do that under our own conditions of existence. Accordingly, also the categories of structure and historyas all-embracing and temporally changing structural articulations of the corresponding forms of being (Daseinsformen) are inextricably conjoined in actually existing human society. However, without an inherently dialectical and historical treatment of both of them, the concepts of structure and history are also as much in danger of being turned into mere tautology as the timeless universal panacea of exchange. This means that an adequate conception of their relationship must account not only for the historical genesis of any structure whatsoever175 but also for the process of development in humanitys history itself, i.e. for its genesis and dynamic transformations, in accordance with its determination as an open-ended framework of societal change. And that includes the potential move from antagonistic prehistory to real history consciously lived and ordained by the non-antagonistically selfmediating social individuals.

292

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

If such historical genesis and ongoing transformation is avoided in theory, not to say even explicitly dismissed, as is done in Lvi-Strauss attacks on Sartre, we end up with the earlier seen hopeless dichotomies of space and time, continuity and discontinuity, subject and object, etc. Equally, we end up with the characteristic reduction of history itselfsaid to be devoid of any object and good for nothing but cataloguing the elements of any structureto a desolate collection of data complemented by the anti-progress mythologics of the retrograde structural anthropology propounded by Lvi-Strauss. It is necessary in connection with all of these fundamental social and corresponding categorial relations to keep the objective prioritieswhich happen to be both historical and logical primaciesin their proper perspective. For in the case of exchange, for instance, before one can envisage the exchange of anything, the objects to be exchanged must be somehow produced. And so must be also the social relations under which their historically specific production becomes feasible. In other words, the question of historical genesis must take precedence in these matters, as indeed it happens to be most important also for dialectically settling the question of what may or may not be legitimately considered the precondition, in contrast to the result, in any determinate relationship. Thus in distribution, for instance, analogously to exchange
The structure of distribution is completely determined by the structure of production. Distribution is itself a product of production, not only in its object, in that only the results of production can be distributed, but also in its form, in that the specific kind of participation in production determines the specific form of distribution, i.e. the pattern of participation in distribution. . . . In the shallowest conception, distribution appears as the distribution of products, and hence as further removed from and quasi-independent of production. But before distribution can be the distribution of products, it is (1) the distribution of the instruments of production, and (2) which is a further specification of the same relation, the distribution of the members of the society among the different kinds of production. (Subsumption of the individuals under specific relations of production.) The distribution of products is evidently only a result of this distribution, which is comprised within the process of production itself and determines the structure of production.176

As we can see, all of the named factors relevant to the evaluation of the historically always specific productive/distributive relationship are dialectically

L V I -STR AU S S AGAINST SA RTRE

293

treated here, fully respecting both the temporal and the structural priorities involved. The same must apply to the assessment of the exchange relationship as much with regard to the most remote historical past as its capitalist modality, as well as to its potential futureabsolutely vitaltransformation. For it is crucially important for the survival of humanity to institute a radically differentcommunalexchange relationship in the not too distant future, in place of the fetishistic and destructive domination of use value (corresponding to human need) by increasingly more wasteful capitalist exchange value. Revealingly, those who mythically inflate the concept of exchange and project its capitalist variety even into the most remote corners of the past, obliterate not only the real historical dimension of the exchange relationship itself but also the objective structural priorities, so as to block the road ahead, with its qualitatively different mode of regulating social metabolic reproduction also in terms of the unavoidable exchange/interchange of humanity with nature and among the particular individuals themselves in society. By defining exchange in terms of the product (the result) of the processirrespective of the question of what kind of product is at issue, from material goods to cultural entitiesthey obliterate all awareness of the specific productive activities and the corresponding relations of production at their roots, as their necessary precondition, under which the producing individuals are subsumed. They represent the exchange relationship in this way in order to be able to banish from view the feasibility of instituting a historically viable alternative. Thus the primacy of activity itself is characteristically wiped out in the interest of eternalizing and absolutizing the historically contingent capitalist alienation of both the productive activity and its commodified product. In reality there can be no aprioristic apodicticity for projecting the socially always necessaryexchange relations in the form of products, let alone of commodified products. The only reason for engaging in such projectionand grossly violating thereby both the historical and the conceptual primacies involvedis to harmonize, in the interest of social legitimation, the commodity form of exchange with the established, historically contingent form of property embodied in the relations of production, with its antagonistic second order mediations. For the given relations of production, ruled by the imperative of perennial capital-accumulation, are incapable of producing and distributing the products in any other way. However, the characteristically absolutized legitimatory claims of the established form of property and appropriation are historically false. For as Marx had clearly put it into relief in his discussion of property and appropriation,

294

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

against the eternalizing claims attached to the notion of private property: History rather shows common property (e.g. in India, among the Slavs, the early Celts, etc.) to be the more original form, a form which long continues to play a significant role in the shape of communal property.177 Thus, even if the historical primacy of common property is disputed and denied, in the service of the vested interests of capital-accumulation, no one can rationally deny the primacy of productive activity itself at the roots of all conceivable forms and varieties of production, from material goods to religious ideas and works of art. This is so even if this primacy can be practically violated, of course, as a matter of historical contingency, through capitals mode of class-exploitative appropriation, from the time of the primitive accumulation to the present. In this sense, advocating the exchange of activities as the only viable historical alternative and a qualitatively different mode of production and distribution for the future, means restituting to productive activity its ontological primacy, overturned and usurped by capitals forcibly discriminatory form of expropriating appropriation to which we have been accustomed for a very long time. But it goes without saying that the institution of a qualitatively different exchange relationship, compared to its now dominant form, based in the future on the self-managed exchange of activities in a consciously planned and coordinated productive and distributive order, requires the radical transformation of the alienated property relations into a communal type. That is precisely the reason why in the ideologically dominant theories (and mytho-logics) of the exchange relations even the mention of the feasibility of production and societal reproduction on the basis of the exchange of activities by the freely associated producers must be avoided like plague. Nevertheless, the necessity to regulate societal reproduction based on the voluntary exchange of activities, in contrast to the authoritarian division of labor inseparable from blindly pursued capital-accumulation, remains the vital practical imperative of our historical time, no matter how sharply it contradicts the apologetic structuralist schemes of interpretation. For that is the only feasible way of reconstituting the one and only historically sustainable relationship between production and human need through restoring use value to its rightful place in the exchange relationship, on the basis of substantive equality. That is, a genuine socialist modality of exchange, freed from the wasteful and destructive domination of formally reductive exchange value and, accordingly, viable both in humanitys reproductive microcosms and on the global scale.

8. The Role of Scarcity in Historical Conceptions


I R O N I CAL LY, T HE W ID E S P REA D ID EA LIZATIO N of the established reproductive order as a natural system takes care of everything, even of the problem of potentially most destructive scarcity, when scarcity is acknowledged as part of the overall scheme of difficult but workable solutions. For once the supreme authority of nature itself is postulated178 by the ideological representatives of the bourgeoisie as an integral part of the universal explanatory framework and justification of the given relations and processes, even what might appear at first sight as a major contradiction can be readily spirited away. In this sense, the liberal theory of the state was founded on the self-proclaimed contradiction between the assumed total harmony of endsthe ends posited to be necessarily desired by all individuals in virtue of their human natureand the total anarchy of means. And the anarchy of means conceptualized in this way was the allegedly insurmountable scarcity of goods and resources which must induce the human individuals to struggle, and ultimately to destroy each other, unless they succeeded in establishing over above themselves a superior authority, in the form of the bourgeois state, as the permanent restraining force of their individualistic belligerence. Thus the state was invented for the alleged purpose of turning anarchy into harmony. That is, to dedicate itself to the universally commendable task of harmonizing the nature-determined anarchy of means with the

296

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

wishfully postulatedand equally nature-determinedharmony of ends by reconciling the violent antagonism between these two natural factors: unalterable human nature and forever dominating material scarcity. And, of course, this reconciliation was asserted in the form of the absolute permanence of the states externally imposed political power over the individuals. To be sure, if the factors which were highlighted in this way were really the unalterable forces of nature, and consequently they could not be controlled in any other way than by an external supra-individual political authority superimposed on the individuals constituted by nature itself as antagonistically confronting and destroying one another as warring individuals, in that case the corrective state authority, in its capacity of making harmonizable societal interchanges feasible at all, would have its permanent legitimacy. In that case the Hegelian idealist version of this state ideology according to which the Absolute Spirits originally hidden design, establishing the state as the only feasible supersession of the contradictions of conflicting genus-individuals in civil society, and in this capacity the state being both Spirits perfect embodiment179 and the image and actuality of Reason180would be self-evidently true forever. There could therefore be absolutely no question of envisaging the states withering away. However, the fact that on the one hand the stipulated human nature181 was itself a self-serving assumption, invented for the purpose of a circular plausibility of its mere assumption by virtue of what it was supposed to explain and justify, and that on the other hand the actually existing scarcity was an inherently historical category, and consequently subject to feasible historical change and potential supersession, had to remain concealed in the liberal theory of the state and civil society under the multiple layers of circularity characteristic of such theory. For it was this kind of apologetic circularity, constituted on a merely assumed but totally unsustainable natural foundation, which enabled the intellectual representatives of liberalism to move at will backwards and forwards from arbitrary premises to the desired conclusions, establishing on the a priori foundations of their ideological circularity the eternal legitimacy of the liberal state. Thanks to such fundamental circularity between nature-determined individuals as well as their appropriately conflictual civil society and the idealized political state which was supposed to overcome the identified contradictions without changing the existing material reproductive order itselfboth capitals state formation and its societal reproductive framework could be assumed as forever given, in virtue of the justifying reciprocity and the thereby projected absolute permanence of their interrelationship.

T H E R OL E OF S C AR C IT Y IN H ISTO RICA L CO NCEPTIO NS

297

Scarcity (or anarchy of means) played a vital role in this scheme of things. It rationally justified both the irreconcilability of the warring individuals as genus individualswho, after all, had to assert their self-interest in accordance with their stipulated human natureand at the same time also provided the eternal reason for adopting the necessary corrective measures by the political state for making the system as a whole insurmountable by preventing its destructive fragmentation to pieces through individualistically pursued antagonisms. But take away from this picture insurmountable scarcity, and replace it by something akin to a sustainable availability of productive and humanly gratifying resources, often simplistically referred to as unqualified abundance, and you witness the immediate collapse of the entire pseudo-rational self-justificatory construct. For in the absence of fateful scarcity the allegedly nature-determined genus-individuals have no reason to engage in the postulated life or death struggle among themselves in order to survive. By the same token, however, if you accept the proposition concerned with nature-determinedand therefore by definition existentially primary, insurmountable, and all-justifyingscarcity, then you are entrapped by a structural framework in which the parts are reciprocally/circularly positing one another, barring thereby any possibility of exit from their vicious circle. For in that case you must accept even the fictitious postulate of nature-determined genus individuality, on the evidence that human beings undoubtedly survived with (and despite) their conflicts all the way to the present time in a world of scarcity within the confines of their civil society and the state. In this sense, if the socialist alternative intends to offer a way out of this tendentious entrapment, conceived from the standpoint of capital, it must challenge all of its circularly interlocking constituents. That goes not only for a viable conception of historically defined and socially changing human naturehighlighted by Marx in our earlier quote as the true community of men182 and elsewhere as the changing ensemble of social relations183but also for the rest. That is, for the eternalized bourgeois material reproductive order of civil society as much as for its state formation, so as to be able to envisage at the same time a radically different mode of social metabolic reproduction. A mode of reproduction capable of overcoming the established antagonistic class relations, misrepresented in the bourgeois conceptionseven in the greatest of themas genus-determined individual conflictuality. For capitals antagonistic second order mediations necessarily carry with them the perverse irrationality of eternalized scarcity even when

298

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

its original material conditions are productively overcome in the course of historical development.
PA R A D OX IC AL LY, D E S P IT E H IS PASSIO NATE D ETESTATIO N of the institutionally secured inhumanities of bourgeois civil society and its protective political state, Jean-Paul Sartre cannot break out from the entrapment mentioned above. For it is not enough to negate only two of the fundamental constituents of the perversely interlocking capital system. However, the difficulty is that in as much as Sartre wants to give an existentialist ontological underpinning to his conception of humanitys historical development even in the Critique of Dialectical Reason, he must present us with a most problematical account of scarcity in what he calls his existentialist enclave within Marxism. As we have seen in chapter 6 above, Sartre categorically asserted in the Critique of Dialectical Reason that to say that our History is a history of men is equivalent to saying that it is born and developed within the permanent framework of a field of tension produced by scarcity.184 We have also seen that for Sartre this is not a question of historically surmountable social contingency but a matter of the human beings existential ontological determination according to which man is objectively constituted as non-human, and this non-humanity is expressed in praxis by the perception of evil as the structure of the Other.185 And to make matters worse, this quasi-mythical Other is constituted not simply somewhere outside but also inextricably in myself as the Other. Accordingly, we are told by Sartre that It is man, and nothing else, that I hate in the enemy, that is in myself as Other; and it is myself that I try to destroy in him, so as to prevent him destroying me in my own body.186 Sadly, given the existentialist ontological presuppositions retained by Sartre to the end, even when he calls himself a marxisant thinker, it is impossible to find a viable solution to the problems of scarcity in his writings. And that goes not only for the first volume but also for the unfinishedand as we have seen above, within Sartres conceptual framework on principle unfinishablesecond volume of the Critique of Dialectical Reason, which was supposed to give a dialectical account of real history, in contrast to sketching the categorial outlines of the formal structures of history in the first. His discussion of scarcity and its human impact in the second volume of the Critique, presented with the much admired Sartrean graphic intensity through the example of boxing, tends to be in terms of its validity grounded on characteristics of the past andwith regard to the present and the future confined to individual psychological plausibility despite the authors claims to general validity.

T H E R OL E OF S C AR C IT Y IN H ISTO RICA L CO NCEPTIO NS

299

Sartre offers a curiously undialectical dialectic of the asserted interiorization of the contradictory predicament of the generic scarce man. For what we receive from him in the second volume of the Critique of Dialectical Reason is an unsustainable explanation of the depicted relationship, timelessly projected into the future. It is extended to the thornyand in the existing societal reproductive order absolutely fundamentalissue of the origin of profit, summed up in the Sartrean assertion in this way: profit springs from the non-sufficiency of satisfaction (worker and wage) and from non-abundance.187 The example of boxing claimed by Sartre to be representative of all struggle is not simply problematical in this respect but quite inappropriate to the characterization of historically determined and capitalistically enforced structural antagonism. The vital difference between the Sartrean representation of the boxers struggle and the real antagonism between capital and labor (for which boxing is also supposed to stand) transpires when we read that
This bout in which the two [boxing] beginners are embroiled, each a victim at once of his own blunders and the others, has a reality all the more striking in that such domination of the labourers by their labour, by producing their future before the eyes of all (they will vegetate at the foot of the ladder or abandon the profession), causes it to be seen and touched as a signification and as a destiny. . . . But it is a destiny, in so far as this domination of the boxers by boxing is directly grasped as presence of their future misfortune. . . . The social ensemble is incarnated with the multiplicity of its conflicts in such a singular temporalization of negative reciprocity. . . . In a direct sense, the fight is a public incarnation of every [Sartres emphasis] conflict. It relates, without any intermediary, to the interhuman tension produced by the interiorization of scarcity.188

However, in actuality the fundamental differencewhich arises from a grave social antagonism concerned with two diametrically opposed social metabolic alternatives and not from what could be characterized by the negative reciprocity of every conflictis that labor, as capitals hegemonic alternative, cannot abandon the profession. Its situation is not a profession at all but a structurally determined condition and a necessarily subordinate class position in the societal reproduction process. The particular workerbut not labor as suchcan abandon this or that profession (in the sense of changing a job), but due to his class situation he is at the same

300

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

time forced into another one. Labor as a social class cannot do anything like abandoning the profession. Equally, the domination of the boxers by boxing is inapplicable to the condition of labor. Labor is dominated by capital, and not by labor, in the Sartrean sense of the boxer being dominated by boxing. The domination of labor is historically most specific, and it is not due to scarcity and technology in Sartres sense, let alone to the interiorization of scarcity. In fact we are concerned here with a non-symmetrical relationship of structurally enforced domination and subordination, quite unlike the symmetrical struggle between two boxers who agree to co-operate within a voluntarily accepted set of rules. In the case of labor the rules are forced upon the members of the class as a whole (through their structurally enforced domination and subordination), and thefar from voluntarily embracedrules are not forced simply on individual workers but on the class as a whole. But even if the prevailing rules are not politically forced upon the members of the class, as they are under the conditions of slavery and feudal serfdom, they are forced upon them nevertheless, as economically imposed determinations. Thus the regulatory determinations in question are in the most fundamental sense objectivelymaterially/reproductivelyprevailing rules. Moreover, a significant further qualification is also needed in this respect. For the ultimate guarantoreven if only the ultimate guarantorof safeguarding the materially/structurally predetermined and enforced rules of commodity society is in fact the capitalist state, with its class-determined legal system and the corresponding law-enforcing apparatus. For
Every form of production creates its own legal relations, form of government, etc. In bringing things which are organically related into an accidental relation, into a merely reflective connection, they [the political economists of the descending phase of capitals historical development] display their crudity and lack of conceptual understanding. All the bourgeois economists are aware of is that production can be carried on better under the modern police than e.g. on the principle of might makes right. They forget only that this principle is also a legal relation, and that the right of the stronger prevails in their constitutional republics as well, only in another form.189

Sartre needs the ahistorical absolutization of scarcityin the name of historical intelligibility, of all thingsin order to make possible for himself the avoidance of elaborating the categories and structures of real history. He remains anchored to the formal structures of history in tune with the

T H E R OL E OF S C AR C IT Y IN H ISTO RICA L CO NCEPTIO NS

301

existential ontological determination given in his conception even at the time of writing the Critique to evil as the structure of the Otherand the Other also in myself engaged in permanent interiorized struggle over scarcity. Sartres way of linking together scarcity, struggle and contradiction in the modality of insurmountable necessity is also most problematical. For even if in the rather remote past we can identify the necessary linkage between scarcity and struggle, this is not so once rational control of the conditions at stake by the social individuals becomes feasible, in conjunction with sustainable productive advancement. Here, again, the example of the boxers is inapplicable. For we are concerned with different orders and types of rational control: one formally consistent with a voluntarily agreed set of rules devised for the purpose of anadmittedly most lucrativesport, and the other substantive, from the domain of real history. To be sure, in the case of the two boxers their rationalityi.e. their voluntary/conscious acceptance of the rules of their professionis inseparable from their claimed struggle. But their struggle is not a real struggle at all in the sense of the life or death struggle over insurmountable scarcity constantly called by that name by Sartre himself. Nor is it even slightly comparable, in its essential character, to the antagonistic confrontationa very real historic struggle over the contested outcome of the structurally determined antagonism between capital and labor over their incompatible hegemonic historical alternatives. Only a dubious formal analogy can be drawn between such fundamentally different forms of struggle, as the structural antagonism between capital and labor in real history and the consensual ritual of the two boxers even when they fight over a purse of a hundred million dollars. Sartre can offer us in the case of the two boxers a psychologically plausible picture. Thus he is at his most eloquent when he asserts that what is certain is that, in every brawl, the deep source is always scarcity . . . the translation of human violence as interiorized scarcity.190 And he proceeds with his graphic characterization of the meaning of the boxing match in the same vein by saying that
The two boxers gather within themselves, and re-exteriorize by the punches they swap, the ensemble of extensions and open or masked struggles that characterize the regime under which we liveand have made us violent even in the least of our desires, even in the gentlest of our caresses. But at the same time, this violence is approved in them.191

302

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

In this way the depicted particular boxing contest can be generalized by Sartre as representative of all human violence. This is how it appears in volume 2 of the Critique: Every boxing match incarnates the whole of boxing as an incarnation of all fundamental violence. . . . An act of violence is always all of violence, because it is a re-exteriorization of interiorized scarcity.192 Thus a direct line is drawn between the psychologically plausible depiction of two individuals in a boxing match and the general conditions of human violence said to correspond to the re-exteriorization of interiorized scarcity. Accordingly, in the Sartrean picture the psychological plausibility of the boxing individuals motivations, and its projection (without any intermediary, as he puts it elsewhere) as the claimed identity between the particular act of violence and the general condition of necessarily interiorizedas well as violently re-exteriorizedscarcity takes the place of what should be made socially/historically determinate and in that sense plausible. But that could only be done in the categorial framework of real history, where scarcity occupies its specific, but not absolutizable existential ontological place. often appears in some form counterposed to scarcity. Sometimes this is done for the purpose of a priori dismissing the possibility of overcoming scarcity any time in the, no matter how distant, future because it is said to be totally unrealistic to envisage the stable institution of abundance in human society in view of the insuperably conflictual determinations of human nature. No further comments are needed in relation to this position. On other occasions, however, the possibility of overcoming scarcity by abundance is not denied on principle, but none the less it is ruled out for the foreseeable time ahead of us on the ground that it would require some productively most advanced technological conditions which might perhaps materialize (or not) in the distant future. And there is also a third, positively assertive position about the emerging abundance which states that the conquest of scarcity is now not only foreseeable but actually foreseen.193 Marcuses position was much the same as the views just quoted from an essay by the prominent Canadian Marxist thinker, C. B. Macpherson. Marcuse insisted that the utopian possibilities which he advocated were inherent in the technical and technological forces of advanced capitalism on the basis of which one could terminate poverty and scarcity within a very foreseeable future.194 He kept on repeating that technical progress has reached a stage in which reality no longer need be defined by the debilitating
T H E P ROB L E M OF A BUN DAN CE

T H E R OL E OF S C AR C IT Y IN H ISTO RICA L CO NCEPTIO NS

303

competition for social survival and advancement. The more these technical capacities outgrow the framework of exploitation within which they continue to be confined and abused, the more they propel the drives and aspirations of men to a point at which the necessities of life cease to demand the aggressive performance of earning a living, and the non-necessary becomes a vital need.195 And in the same work, written by Marcuse well before sinking into deep pessimism in the last years of his life, he postulated a biological foundation to revolutionary change, saying that such a foundation
would have the chance of turning quantitative technical progress into qualitatively different ways of lifeprecisely because it would be a revolution occurring at a high level of material and intellectual development, one which would enable man to conquer scarcity and poverty. If this idea of a radical transformation is to be more than idle speculation, it must have an objective foundation in the production process of advanced industrial society, in its technical capabilities and their use. For freedom indeed depends largely on technical progress, on the advancement of science.196

This generously well-meaning unreality was written and published by Marcuse more than forty years ago, and we have seen absolutely nothing pointing in the direction of its realization. On the contrary, we have witnessed recently a devastating crisis of advanced industrial society, with food riots admitted by one of the ideological pillars of the established orderThe Economistto have taken place in no less than thirty five countries, despite all of the significant technical progress undoubtedly accomplished in the past four decades. Not even the slightest attempt has been made for the enduring conquest of scarcity. The great weakness of the Marcuse-type projections, shared by C. B. Macpherson and many others, is that the positive results regarding the actually foreseen conquest of scarcity are expected to arise from the propelling force of technical/technological progress and productive advancement. And that could not happen even in a thousand years, not to mention forty or even a hundred. For technology is not an independent variable. It is deeply embedded in the most fundamental social determinations, despite all mystification to the contrary,197 as we have seen above on several occasion. No one can doubt that the sympathy of the people who in this way anticipate the conquest of scarcity is on the side of the wretched of the earth who fight the affluent monster.198 But their moral discourse cannot even touch the fundamental objective determinations which so successfully perpetuate

304

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

the denounced plight of the exploited and oppressed, let alone effectively alter them. To expect from productive advancement, arising from technical progress in advanced industrial society, to move humanity in the direction of eliminating scarcity is to ask for the impossible. The same kind of impossibility as expecting that the capitalist should set a limit to his appetite for profit on the ground that he has enough profit already. For the society Marcuse and others talk about is not advanced industrial but only capitalistically advancedand for humanity itself suicidally dangeroussociety. It cannot take a single step in the direction of conquering scarcity for as long as it remains under the rule of capital, irrespective of its growing technical capabilities and the corresponding degree of improvement in productivity in the future. For two important reasons. First, because even the greatest technically secured productive advancement can beand under the conditions now prevailing in our society actually is and must bedissipated through profitable waste and the channels of destructive production, including the state-legitimated fraudulence of the military/industrial complex, as we have seen before. And secondwhat happens to be more fundamental herebecause of the objective character of the system of capital-accumulation. We should not forget that capital personified and endowed with consciousness and a will cannot be interested in the conquest of scarcity, and in the corresponding equitable distribution of wealth, for the simple reason that use-values must never be looked upon as the real aim of the capitalist; . . . The restless never ending process of profit-making alone is what he aims at.199 And in that respect, which is inseparable from the absolute imperative of endless capital-expansion and accumulation, the permanent structural impediment is that capital always isand, this cannot be stressed strongly enough, it always must remain, as a matter of inner systemic determinationinsuperably scarce, even when under certain conditions it is contradictorily overproduced.200
SA RT R E IS , OF C OU R S E , N OT IN TH E LEAST CO NCERNED with the conquest of scarcity and its sustainable replacement by productively generalized abundance. He is firmly negative in that respect, describing the man of scarcity as the man who imposes his will and expropriates abundance to himself.201 The existential ontological orientation and coloring of Sartres characterization of the insuperable conflictual relationship between myself and my adversaries is retained to the very end of the Critique of Dialectical Reason when he writes that in the field of scarcity an increase in the number or power of my neighbours has the result of increasing the precariousness of

T H E R OL E OF S C AR C IT Y IN H ISTO RICA L CO NCEPTIO NS

305

my existence. For that power seeks both to produce more (a ceiling though) and to eliminate me. My alteration is suffered, and is what incarnates the transformation in me.202 However, Sartres way of dealing with the problem of scarcity and abundanceby making scarcity the existential foundation of history, as its permanent framework produced by scarcity, as well as of historical intelligibility, rather than a (no matter how important) contingent factor in history, capable of being overcome under significantly altered conditions at some point in timedoes not solve the very real historical challenge facing us. In truth, some elementary qualifications are required for a proper characterization of abundance itself which can be legitimately posited in the context of overcoming the historical domination of scarcity. For at a relatively early stage of humanitys historical development the naturally necessary needswhich were for our distant ancestors fully in tune with the overwhelming material domination of scarcityare actually superseded by a much more complex, historically created, set of needs, as we have seen discussed in The Dialectic of Structure and History. To be sure, the productive advancement in question does not represent the end of this burdensome story but, none the less, it means a significant move in the direction of conquering the original domination of human life by scarcity. In this sense:
Luxury is the opposite of naturally necessary. Necessary needs are those of the individual himself reduced to a natural subject. The development of industry suspends this natural necessity as well as this former luxuryin bourgeois society, it is true, it does so only in antithetical form, in that it itself only posits another specific social standard as necessary, opposite luxury.203

Accordingly, consigning scarcity to the past is a long-drawn-out but, despite all obstacles and contradictions, an ongoing historical process. However, precisely because of the antithetical form in which this historical development must be carried on in bourgeois society, the real question for the future is not the utopian institution of unqualified abundance but the rational control of the process of productive advancement by the social individuals, feasible only in a socialist reproductive order. Otherwise the historically no longer justifiable domination of scarcityin the form of perversely wasteful but profitable destructive production in a variety of its capitalistically feasible formsremains with us indefinitely. In the absence of the required rational self-determination on a societal scalewhose absence under the present conditions happens to be not a fateful existential ontological

306

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

determination but a question of historically created and historically superable impedimenteven the greatest (abstractly postulated) abundance would be utterly powerless and futile as an attempt to overcome the domination of scarcity. Thus we are concerned in this respect with a historically determinate but not permanently history-determiningsocial force and impediment to social emancipation which dominated human life for far too long. It is that structural/systemic impediment that must be radically superseded through labors hegemonic alternative to capitals established mode of social metabolic control according to the Marxian conception of the new historic form.

9. The Missing Dimension


published in Le Nouvel Observateur, Sartre expressed both his extreme pessimism (called by him in the same interview also despair) and his hope to find a way out of it. He admitted at the same time that this hope must be founded.204 Accordingly, he promised at the end of that March 1980 interview to dedicate himself to the task of founding hope not simply in personal terms but with justifiable claim to general validity in the years remaining of his life, but as we know its achievement was denied to him. For unexpectedly he died two weeks later. In fact the deep pessimism haunted Sartre for nearly a decade, as a result of his great disappointment on account of the failure of the May 1968 radicalization and the conservative backlash. He readily confessed his pessimism in the 1975 interview given to Michel Contat and published also in Le Nouvel Observateur, addingeven with a touch of by his own standard most unusual litism about the past efforts of a few men in humanitys historythat If I am not completely pessimistic it is primarily because I see in myself certain needs which are not only mine but the needs of every man. To express it another way, it is the experienced certainty of my own freedom . . . But it is true that either man crumblesand then all one could say is that during the twenty thousand years in which there have been men, a few of them tried to create man and failedor else this revolution succeeds and creates man by bringing about freedom. Nothing is less sure. It is impossible to find a rational basis for revolutionary optimism,
I N H I S L AST INT E RV IEW ,

308

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

since what is is the present reality. And how can we lay the foundations for the future reality? Nothing allows me to do it. I am sure of one thingthat we must make a radical politics. But I am not sure that it will succeed, and there faith enters in.205 In this way Sartre could indicate in 1975 the need for freedomsaid to be felt not only by him but by every manas the possible foundation of hope regarding a sustainable future reality, denying at the same time its power to overrule pessimism. Moreover, what was called by him in 1975 the present reality was in the final interview described as this miserable ensemble which is our planet, and it was characterized as horrible, ugly, bad, without hope. Understandably, therefore, to found hope with a general claim to validity on the ground of the projection of such a desolate planetary picture would seem to constitute a prohibitive enterprise. For while in 1975 Sartre could still advocate radical politics, as something that must be made, confessing at the same time his grave doubts about its feasible success, and openly admitting that his doubts prevailing on that score could be countered only by faith, in the 1980 interview only the pure personal faithfulness to theshould befiat of hope remained to him, in reiterating that I continue to feel hope as my conception of the future. But how can one build the required objective foundation of hope for humanitys future on the subjective assertion of I feel hope? In other words, if the feasibility of succeeding on that basis is questioned, what is missing from the Sartrean conception of the world which confines himand often in a self-torturing wayto a pessimistic overall perspective, despite his passionate dedication to the cause of human emancipation throughout most of his life? The somber Sartrean vision of elusive hope that in his view must be founded, but to the very end he could not found, is closely related to the way in which he treats the relationship between freedom and necessity. In this respect the profound ambiguities of Sartres philosophical system persist not only in his early works but in all of them. This is all the more revealing because in the synthesizing works written in the 1950s and later he makes very serious attempts to overcome them, or at least to reduce them to what he considers inevitable in the present age. At the same time he is aware of the problems he leaves unresolved and goes as far as stating that he will never solve them. In a confession he says: From the period when I wrote La Nause I wanted to create a morality. My evolution consists in my no longer dreaming of doing so.206 In this respect it is necessary to single out here one of the most important aspects of this complex of problems: the role of projects in Sartres

T H E M IS S IN G DIM E NS IO N

309

philosophy. In his Critique de la raison dialectique Sartre strongly emphasizes that The simple inspection of the social field ought to have led to the discovery that the relation to ends is a permanent structure of human enterprises and that it is on the basis of this relation that real men evaluate actions, institutions, or economic constructions.207 Nobody should quarrel with these words. What needs, however, further clarification is the specific character of various kinds of relations to ends which characterize the different kinds of human activity. While it is right to criticize the reductionism of mechanistic materialism in this regard, it is very problematical to establish a direct link between the abstract generality of relations to ends and the postulated category of mere particularity: the Sartrean singularity of the individuals. There is an enormous gap between these two poles appearing again and again in Sartres philosophy. We can illustrate it with two quotations. The first reads as follows: As this impulse toward objectification assumes various forms according to the individual, as it projects us across a field of possibilities, some of which we realize to the exclusion of others, we call it also choice or freedom.208 The second quotation offers us this general conclusion: What we call freedom is the irreducibility of the cultural order to the natural order.209 The question is: can the definition of freedom as the irreducibility of the cultural order to the natural order throw light on the problem of why we realize certain possibilities at the exclusion of others? Hardly. The reference to freedom in the first quotation puts an end to further questioning, instead of illuminating the question itself. Freedom is assumed as an irreducible fact of human existence. On the other hand the idea of the singularity of the individual in no way helps to understand the cultural order, even if we accept that it is irreducible to the natural order. Apart from the fact that natural is an extremely ambiguous term in this connectionit could also mean social as opposed to the individualwe find that the Sartrean critique is made from the position of an assumption (the categorically claimed irreducibility of the cultural order) and not from the ground of a sustainable argument. Sartre often insists, rightly and with great rigor, that one should consider the real individual as the focal point of philosophy in place of abstract categories. It is, however, rather doubtful whether he lives up to his own principle when he talks about the field of possibilities. For only the abstractly postulated individual lives in the field of possibilities. The real individual has to be contented with a field of actually feasible and realizable probabilities. By contrast for Sartre to say what man is is also to say what he can

310

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

beand vice versa. . . . Thus the field of possibilities is the goal toward which the agent surpasses his objective situation.210 This is by no means a slip in Sartres philosophical conception. For him it is necessary to replace probability by possibility because of his definition of freedom as irreducibility opposed to the natural order. At the same time the Sartre of the Critique de la raison dialectique wants to circumscribe the limits of possibility in order to account for the development of the collectivity, as we have seen it discussed above. From this dual concern emerges a most ambiguous system of thought: a way of arguing which often takes away with one hand what it lays down with the other. Thus in the Sartrean philosophical universe the non-existent (ce qui manque) is given an ontological status equal to that of the objectively existent, thereby rendering the foundations of Sartres system rather problematical. As he had put it:
Therefore we must conceive of the possibility as doubly determined. On the one side it is at the very heart of the particular action, the presence of the future as that which is lacking and that which, by its very absence, reveals reality. On the other hand, it is the real and permanent future which the collectivity forever maintains and transforms.211

This ambivalence persists at all levels. Possibility often stands for the impact of the realm of manque on the natural order. However, on numerous occasions it is synonymous with concretely circumscribed and well determined probability. (Yet the proper evaluation of the category of probability is conspicuously absent from Sartres conceptual framework.) Similarly, can is interchangeably used for the real capabilities of the individual as well as for reaching ontological conclusions on the basis of an utterly abstract normativei.e. thoroughly ought-riddencan, without indicating the vital differences between the two usages. There is a basic ambiguity also as regards the concept of scarcity. It is treated both as a historical contingency and as a metaphysical absolute inherent in the ontological structure of manque. Furthermore, in Sartres conception scarcity is often entangled with the need which it negates in fact. One could avoid this entanglement only by assessing the relationship between need and scarcity in terms of the dialectical interaction of a complex system of historically created human needssome of which more fundamental than othersin the comprehensive and constantly changing framework of the community as a whole. The subjectively authenticated

T H E M IS S IN G DIM E NS IO N

311

assertions I see in myself certain needs and I continue to feel hope as my conception of the future cannot be a substitute for that. But perhaps the most significant of the Sartrean ambiguities is his conception of man. More often than not Sartre identifies man with the individual and frequently attributes to him characteristics and powers which could be validly predicated only about mankind as a whole, but not about the singular individual. Thus the famous Sartrean project becomes a somewhat derailing category in so far as it also stands for activities and comprehensive historical processes which cannot possibly be attributed to a self-conscious singular individual subject required by Sartres frame of reference. Mankind is often subsumed under the subjectivistic ontology of the Sartrean individual. This entanglement of individual and mankind systematically biassed in favor of the singular individualhas far-reaching consequences. Sartres ontology is dominated by a form of extreme dualism. (We should remember in this respect his categorial and categorical opposites: nant versus tre, manque, versus prsence, freedom versus contingency, cultural order versus the natural order, individual versus the collective, etc.all such categorial pairs of opposites are in his view irreducible.) Methodologically it is most significant that the all-important category of mediation is not elaborated by Sartre. The assumption of irreducibility functions as a surrogate in that respect, so as to link upwhile insisting on their sharp oppositionsthe categories of freedom and contingency, cultural order and natural order, etc., etc. And the ethical consequences of the subsumptive entanglement of individual and mankind are that the dream to create a morality has to be abandoned, as confessed by Sartre himself, irrespective of the vast number of pages dedicated at various times in his life to this enterprise. In other words, in such a framework of reference it is quite impossible to work out a general conception of ethics. All categories that constitute one side of his dualistic ontologyindividual, freedom, project, choice, singularity, possibility, cultural order, etc.,are impregnated with an ethical substance of approval, even if this is not always rendered explicit. The insurmountable problem in this respect is that while in actuality it is possible to find a vital ethical connection in the historically changing dialectical interaction between individual and mankind, there can be no ethical sphere left if one is simply subsumed under the other. It does not matter which of the two is subsumed under the other. An abstract collectivistic subsumption

312

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

is as unable to produce a coherent conception of ethics as the other way round. Such conceptionsboth in their individualistic and abstract collectivistic formsare characterized by the inadequate treatment of the category of mediation. As regards Sartres philosophy, since the ethical bias and schism is built into the sharply dualistic structure of existentialist ontology, subsuming mankind under the individual cannot be avoided. To politely entertain for the category of multiplicity at the time of writing the Critique the notion of mankind according to taste, as we have seen above, is not enough. Accordingly, there cannot be a sustainable moral theory within the limits of such ontology without rectifying the stipulated categorial subsumption inseparable from the sharply dualistic conceptual framework. Moreover, also the question of the relationship between possibility and probability can only be disentangled in the same dialectical framework of interrelationship in place of insuperable dualistic oppositions. For what are rather vaguely described as possibilities for the individuals considered in the abstract are in actuality already structured as a complex societal framework of more or less clearly articulated and feasible probabilities for the real individuals from the very moment when they are inserted into a historically constituted concrete community. At the same time, in so far as the particular individuals objectively belong to the historically constituted actuality of humankind, as they all do, irrespective of how conscious they might be of it, the challenges and achievements of the totality of individuals can be consideredagain in the abstracttheir shared possibilities, in virtue of the fact of such belonging. Indeed, in determinate situationsnotably in socially created moral situationsunqualified possibility (that is, possibility which is not specified in terms of concretely feasible probabilities in relation to the identifiable actual capabilities of particular individuals) becomes nevertheless the viable measure of evaluation of individual actionon the basis of some socially justifiable moral imperativerejecting the acceptability of self-excusing circumstances. However, such appeal to the concept of general possibilities invokes a normative postulate, with understandable valuational reference to mankind, and not a concrete social ontological category. As such by itself it has a limited validity in relation to the particular individual and must be complemented by the overall dialectical assessment of the historically changing social complex itself, including its more comprehensive ethical requirements of sustainability. Naturally, the projects of the particular individuals are subject to the same requirements and qualifications. Asserting, as Sartre does, that To say

T H E M IS S IN G DIM E NS IO N

313

what man is is also to say what he can be is by itself not enough. Not even if we add to it in Sartres sense the vice versa clause. For the concept of can be invoked by Sartre in this context is a normative can, very much in the Kantian mould of ought implies can be, with its reference in Kants case to the intelligible world as the ground of his categorical imperative of morality. However, in the case of the atheist existentialist Sartre the road for appealing to the idea of that intelligible world is not open.212 At the same time, Sartres goal toward which the agent surpasses his objective situation cannot be made intelligible simply in terms of the claimed field of possibilities. This categorial difficulty asserts itself in the same sense in which any appeal to normative canin the spirit of ought implies canis by itself very far from enough for surpassing the objective situation of this miserable ensemble which is our planet, in its horrible, ugly, bad state, without hope. This is why founding hope needs a more secure ground than even the noblest advocacy of the individuals deeply felt feeling and need for hope.
T H US FOR SART R E AT O NE LEVEL the insurmountable problems arise from the sharply dichotomous general categorial framework of his philosophy. But that is only a partial explanation. For not even the most general categorial setting can be generated in such a way as to be able to sustain itself on its own. Understandably, therefore, at another level Sartres insuperably dichotomous categorial network itself points to its equivalent in his social conception of the world. In that respect, again, the dichotomous opposition and in terms of societal matters by Sartre openly acknowledged contradiction takes the form of the anguished admission of failure or defeat. This is all the more significant because no one can deny Sartres fully committed search for a viable emancipatory solution and his great personal integrity. In relation to our problem we have to recall that in the important interview given to the Italian Manifesto groupafter outlining his conception of the insuperably negative implications of his own explanatory category of unavoidably detrimental institutionalization of the fused grouphe had to come to the painful conclusion that While I recognize the need of an organization, I must confess that I dont see how the problems which confront any stabilized structure could be resolved.213 Here the difficulty is that the terms of Sartres social analysis are set up in such a way that the various factors and correlations that in reality belong together, constituting different facets of fundamentally the same societal complex, are depicted by him in the form of most problematical oppositions,

314

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

generating thereby insoluble dilemmas and an unavoidable defeat. This is well illustrated by the exchange between the Manifesto group and Sartre:
MANIFESTO:

on what precise bases can one prepare a revolutionary

alternative?
SARTRE: I repeat, more on the basis of alienation than on needs. In short on the reconstruction of the individual and of freedomthe need for which is so pressing that even the most refined techniques of integration cannot afford to discount it.214

Thus Sartre in this way, in his strategic assessment of how to overcome the oppressive character of capitalist reality, sets up a totally untenable opposition between the workers alienation and their allegedly satisfied needs, thereby making it all the more difficult to envisage a practically feasible positive outcome. And here the problem is not simply that he grants far too much credibility to the fashionable but extremely superficial sociological explanation of the so-called refined techniques of integration in relation to the workers. Unfortunately it is much more serious than that. Indeed the really disturbing problem at stake is the evaluation of the viability of advanced capitalism itself and the associated postulate of working class integration which Sartre happens to share at the time to a large extent with Herbert Marcuse. For in actuality the truth of the matter is that in contrast to the undoubtedly feasible integration of some particular workers into the capitalist order, the class of laborthe structural antagonist of capital, representing the only historically sustainable hegemonic alternative to the capital systemcannot be integrated into capitals alienating and exploitative framework of societal reproduction. What makes that impossible is the underlying structural antagonism between capital and labor, emanating with insurmountable necessity from the class reality of antagonistic domination and subordination. In this discourse even the minimal plausibility of the Marcuse/Sartre type of false alternative between continuing alienation and satisfied need is established on the basis of the arbitrary compartmentalization of capitals suicidally untenable globally entrenched structural interdeterminationsupon which the elementary systemic viability of capitals one and only ruling societal metabolic order is necessarily premisedin the form of the extremely problematical separation of advanced capitalism from the socalled marginal zones and from the third world. As if the reproductive

T H E M IS S IN G DIM E NS IO N

315

order of the postulated advanced capitalism could sustain itself for any length of time, let alone indefinitely in the future, without the ongoing exploitation of the misconceived marginal zones and the imperialistically dominated third world. It is necessary to quote here in its integrality the relevant passage in which these problems are spelled out by Sartre. The revealing Manifesto interview passage in question reads as follows:
Advanced capitalism, in relation to its awareness of its own condition, and despite the enormous disparities in the distribution of income, manages to satisfy the elementary needs of the majority of the working classthere remains of course the marginal zones, 15 percent of workers in the United States, the blacks and the immigrants; there remain the elderly; there remains, on the global scale, the third world. But capitalism satisfies certain primary needs, and also satisfies certain needs which it has artificially created: for instance the need of a car. It is this situation which has caused me to revise my theory of needs, since these needs are no longer, in a situation of advanced capitalism, in systematic opposition to the system. On the contrary, they partly become, under the control of that system, an instrument of integration of the proletariat into certain processes engendered and directed by profit. The worker exhausts himself in producing a car and in earning enough to buy one; this acquisition gives him the impression of having satisfied a need. The system which exploits him provides him simultaneously with a goal and with the possibility of reaching it. The consciousness of the intolerable character of the system must therefore no longer be sought in the impossibility of satisfying elementary needs but, above all else, in the consciousness of alienationin other words, in the fact that this life is not worth living and has no meaning, that this mechanism is a deceptive mechanism, that these needs are artificially created, that they are false, that they are exhausting and only serve profit. But to unite the class on this basis is even more difficult.215

If we accept at face value this characterization of the advanced capitalist order, in that case the task of producing emancipatory consciousness is not only more difficult but quite impossible. But the dubious ground on which we can reach such an aprioristic imperatival and pessimistic/ self-defeating conclusionprescribing from the height of the intellectuals new theory of needs the abandonment by the workers of their acquisitive artificial needs, instantiated by the motor car, and their replacement

316

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

by the thoroughly abstract postulate which posits for them that this life is not worth living and has no meaning (a noble but rather abstract imperatival postulate effectively contradicted in reality by the tangible need of the members of the working class for securing the conditions of their economically sustainable existence)is both the acceptance of a set of totally untenable assertions and the equally untenable omission of some vital determining features of the actually existing capital system in its historically irreversible structural crisis. For a start, to talk about advanced capitalismwhen the capital system as a mode of social metabolic reproduction finds itself in its descending phase of historical development, and therefore is only capitalistically advanced but in no other sense at all, thereby capable of sustaining itself only in an ever more destructive and therefore ultimately also self-destructive wayis extremely problematical. Another assertion: the characterization of the overwhelming majority of humankindin the category of poverty, including the blacks and the immigrants, the elderly and on the global scale, the third worldas belonging to the marginal zones (in affinity with Marcuses outsiders), is no less untenable. For in reality it is the advanced capitalist world that constitutes the long term totally unsustainable privileged margin of the overall system, with its ruthless elementary need-denial to the greater part of the world, and not what is described by Sartre in his Manifesto interview as the marginal zones. Even with regard to the United States of America the margin of poverty is greatly underrated, at merely 15 percent. Besides, also the characterization of the workers motor cars as nothing more than purely artificial needs which only serve profit could not be more one-sided. For, in contrast to many intellectuals, not even the relatively well off particular workers, let alone the members of the class of labor as a whole, have the luxury of finding their place of work next door to their bedroom. At the same time, on the side of the astonishing omissions, some of the gravest structural contradictions and failures are missing from Sartres depiction of advanced capitalism, virtually emptying of meaning the whole concept. In this sense one of the most important substantive needs without which no societypast, present or futurecould survive, is the need for work. Both for the productively active individualsembracing all of them in a fully emancipated social orderand for society in general in its historically sustainable relationship to nature. The necessary failure to solve this fundamental structural problem, affecting all categories of work not only in the third world but even in the most privileged countries of

T H E M IS S IN G DIM E NS IO N

317

advanced capitalism, with its perilously rising unemployment, constitutes one of the absolute limits of the capital system in its entirety. Another grave problem which underscores the present and future historical unviability of capital is the calamitous shift toward the parasitic sectors of the economy like the crisis-producing adventurist speculation which plagues (as a matter of objective necessity, often misrepresented as systemically irrelevant personal failure) the financial sector and the institutionalized/legally buttressed fraudulence closely associated with itin contradistinction to the productive branches of socioeconomic life required for the satisfaction of genuine human need. This is a shift that stands in menacingly sharp contrast to the ascending phase of capitals historic development, when the prodigious systemic expansionary dynamism (including the industrial revolution) was overwhelmingly due to socially viable and further enhanceable productive achievements. We have to add to all this the massively wasteful economic burdens imposed on society in an authoritarian way by the state and the military/industrial complexwith the permanent arms industry and the corresponding warsas an integral part of the perverse economic growth of advanced organized capitalism. And to mention just one more of the catastrophic implications of advanced capitals systemic development, we must bear in mind the prohibitively wasteful global ecological encroachment of our no longer tenable mode of social metabolic reproduction on the finite planetary world,216 with its rapacious exploitation of the non-renewable material resources and the increasingly more dangerous destruction of nature. This is not being wise after the event. I wrote in the same period when Sartre gave his Manifesto interview that Another basic contradiction of the capitalist system of control is that it cannot separate advance from destruction, nor progress from wastehowever catastrophic the results. The more it unlocks the powers of productivity, the more it must unleash the powers of destruction; and the more it extends the volume of production, the more it must bury everything under mountains of suffocating waste. The concept of economy is radically incompatible with the economy of capital production which, of necessity, adds insult to injury by first using up with rapacious wastefulness the limited resources of our planet, and then further aggravates the outcome by polluting and poisoning the human environment with its mass-produced waste and effluence.217 Thus the problematical assertions and the seminally important omissions of Sartres characterization of advanced capitalism greatly weaken the power of negation of his emancipatory discourse. His dichotomous principle which repeatedly asserts the irreducibility of the cultural order

318

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

to the natural order is always on the look-out for finding solutions in terms of the cultural order, at the level of the individuals consciousness, through the committed intellectuals work of consciousness upon consciousness. He appeals to the idea that the required solution lies in increasing the consciousness of alienationthat is, in terms of his cultural orderat the same time discarding the viability of grounding the revolutionary strategy on need belonging to the natural order. Material need, that is, which is said to be already satisfied for the majority of workers, and in any case constituting a deceptive and false mechanism and an instrument of integration of the proletariat. To be sure, Sartre is deeply concerned with the challenge of addressing the issue of how to increase the consciousness of the intolerable character of the system. But, as a matter of unavoidable consideration, the leverage itself indicated as the vital condition of successthe power of the consciousness of alienation stressed by Sartrewould itself badly need some objective underpinning. Otherwise, in addition to the indicated leverages weakness of self-referential circularity, the imperatival nature of its can prevail over against the intolerable character of the system remains in dominance, as a noble but ineffective cultural advocacy. This is most problematical even in Sartres own terms of reference when, in his rather pessimistic words, the need is for defeating the both materially and culturally destructive and structurally entrenched reality of this miserable ensemble which is our planet, with its horrible, ugly, bad determinations, without hope. Accordingly, the primary question concerns thedemonstrability or notof the objectively intolerable character of the system itself. For if the demonstrable intolerability of the system is missing in substantive terms, as proclaimed by the notion of advanced capitalisms ability to satisfy material needs except in the marginal zones, then the long and patient labour in the construction of consciousness218 advocated by Sartre remains well nigh impossible. It is that objective grounding that needs to be (and in actuality can be) established in its own comprehensive terms of reference, requiring the radical demystification of the increasing destructiveness of advanced capitalism. The consciousness of the intolerable character of the system can only be built on that objective groundingwhich includes the suffering caused by advanced capitals failure to satisfy even the elementary need for food not in marginal zones but for countless millions, as clearly evidenced by food riots in many countriesso as to be able to overcome the postulated dichotomy between the cultural order and the natural order.

T H E M IS S IN G DIM E NS IO N

319

T H E M IS S ING DIM E NS IO N of the deeply committed Sartrean advocacy of emancipation is the political economic analysis of capitals historically no longer tenable social metabolic order of reproduction in its entirety in which politics must be put to its properly qualified place. However, out of all proportion, Sartres theoretical and strategic frame of reference for envisaging the necessary emancipatory change is the institutionally articulated political domain and the greatly restricted assessment of the concept of mediation inseparable from his overwhelming concentration on politics, although he paradoxically admits at the same time even in that regard his insuperable doubts in view of twentieth century political/ historical developments and the contradictory nature of the Soviet postrevolutionary system. This issue directly concerns in our time the historical viabilityor notof the fundamental social metabolic ground of capitals materially overwhelming societal reproductive order as such, which of course includes, but by no means in a dominant place within the dialectically circumscribed overall perspective, also the feasible political contribution to the required structural change. Once upon a time the question of evaluating capitals viability as a mode of social metabolic reproduction presented itself in a radically different way. In the ascending phase of capitals historical developmentapproximately up to the middle of the nineteenth centurythe objectively intolerable character of the system itself as a productive system could not be effectively raised, no matter how intolerable its impact undoubtedly happened to be on significant sections of the working population, especially on child labor. For the demonstrable and structurally irreversible unviability (and in that vital sense objective intolerability) of capitals increasingly destructive determinations, together with a scientifically assertable conception of the really feasible hegemonic historical alternative to the established system as a mode of social metabolic reproduction, was still missing in substantive terms. Indeed, as mentioned earlier, the prodigious systemic expansionary dynamism prior to the closure of capitals ascending historical phase of development carried with it socially viable and further enhanceable productive achievements. Understandably and revealingly, therefore, before the reversal of the historically ascending phase the most enlightened personifications of capitalthe utopian socialist Robert Owen of New Lanark, for instancecould still attempt to overcome the worst inhumanities of the system, like the gruesome exploitation of child labor and the productively detrimental excessive working hours of the labor force in general, in a form well containable within the confines of the capital system itself.

320

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

The objective closure of the ascending phase inevitably redefined these conditions for the worse, pushing ever more dangerously into the foreground capitals own imperative of prolonging the sustainability of unlimitable capital-expansion irrespective of the consequences, including the most absurd conceivable normality of systemic destructiveness not only in production and in inter-state relationsin the latter with the onset of monopolistic imperialism and its catastrophic global warsbut even in relation to nature: the elementary substratum of human life itself. Significantly, the intellectual consequences of this fundamental historic reversal were extremely negative, resulting in the pursuit of blatant theoretical apologetics in place of scientific truth. In Marxs words these developments sounded the knell of scientific bourgeois economy. It was thenceforth no longer a question whether this theorem or that theorem was true, but whether it was useful to capital or harmful, expedient or inexpedient, politically dangerous or not. In place of disinterested inquirers, there were hired prize-fighters; in place of genuine scientific research, the bad conscience and the evil intent of apologetics.219 This is why the concept of advanced capitalism itself must be challenged and radically demystified. For the present-day capital system is advanced only in its boundless power of destruction, including its ability to extinguish human life altogether on our planet. This is a devastatingly advanced power, by now in evidence everywhere. The capital system did not possess such powerexcept in its general tendency pointing in that fateful directionin Marxs lifetime. This is what defines in our time the objectively intolerable character of capitals social metabolic control which reached such a stage in its historical development when it must carry on maintaining itself at the cost of escalating destructiveness while inducing its hired prize-fighters to cynically preach the sermons of democracy and the claimed extension of freedom imposed through the military interventions of liberal imperialism. However, such destructiveness by its very nature is also self-defeating and calls for a rational historic alternative as the necessary objective material grounding upon which the consciousness of the intolerable character of the system can and must be erected. Paying any attention to diversionary sociological notions like the so-called refined techniques of integration in the postulated acquisitive society of advanced capitalism is totally irrelevant in that respect. As we have seen earlier, Sartre asserted that I am sure of one thingthat we must make a radical politics. But I am not sure that it will succeed.220 He was right in expressing his doubts. This had to be the case not only on account of his many disappointments in the world of politics. More importantly, he

T H E M IS S IN G DIM E NS IO N

321

expected far too much from the established institutions of politics, assigning to them the role of necessary mediation. He considered that role of mediation essential, in accordance with his general theory of the millions of individual actions which had to be somehow connected in his vision of the irreducible multiplicity of the individuals who populated his existentialistand of course also his marxisant existentialistgeneral ontological conceptual framework. In relation to hisadmittedly disappointedpolitical hope once attached to the Communist Party he insisted that
The real question is to know how to overcome the contradiction which is inherent in the very nature of the party, so that (not only in its relation with opponents and in its tasks as a fighting organization, but also in relation to the class which it represents) the party may constitute an active mediation between serialized and massified elements for the purpose of their unification.221

Sartre conceptualized in the same sense Stalins role in postrevolutionary Soviet society in his attempted work of not formally theorized but claimed real history, in the second volume of the Critique of Dialectical Reason. He raised this problem in relation to insurmountable scarcity and concluded that this scarcity of means in turn affects and defines man, if man is to be a means (in the sense in which the sovereign [in this case Stalin] serves praxis and is a mediator between groups). If it is true that there are not enough menor not the right menfor a specific undertaking, we sense through this scarcity the incarnation of the following historical truth: man, as a product of the world, is not made for man. . . . The men History makes are never entirely those needed to make History, be they even as unrivaled as Stalin or Napoleon.222 And later on in the same work we could find the following summation: the schematic circularity of the single and the multiple in the immanent field of scarcity is only the skeleton of the movement of enveloping temporalization. The concrete and absolute reality of History can be only in the singularity of the practical relations uniting singular men to the singular objectives they pursue, in the singularity of the conjuncture.223 In this way Sartres primary concern, in his attempt to make historical totalization in real history intelligible, remained the question of indicating the role of politicsreferred to in various contexts in connection with the concept of sovereigntyas the necessary form of mediation for uniting the singular men and the given individual multiplicities in the pursuit of singular objectives contained in the singularity of the given conjuncture.

322

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

This conception could not help being most problematical because of its Sartrean ontological terms of reference, even if he hopelessly attempted to counter the negative implications of this vision by his unifying postulate of the political mediation of individualistic multiplicities. Yet his formal structures of history had to remain always formal, even in the course of Sartres passionate struggle with hisunachievableaccount of real history. At times he was even willing to admit this,224 without, however, modifying in the least his inconclusively growing, even if often graphically expressive, particular variations on the same theme spelled out in the same formal categorial framework of individualistic multiplicities. Given the inherently individualistic ontological determination of such multiplicities their unification in fused groups could only be transitory and historically unsustainable. This is why he could only project the emergence of such groups from individualistic seriality only to be followed by their fateful relapse into powerless seriality in the world of fateful institutionalization. Political mediation could not significantly alter that beyond the occasionally favorable but ultimately untenable and disintegrative singular conjuncture. Thus political mediation of the serialized and massified elements could be in this Sartrean vision both advocated/asserted and, when the postulated institutional political mediation had to be frustrated so as to end in failure, as in the case of the partys self-serializing institutionalizationwhich curiously had to arise from the contradiction inherent in the partys naturealso firmly condemned/negated by the militant intellectuals direct appeal to the individuals consciousness, in somber rejection of the setting of institutionality. We have seen in the latter respect Sartres anguished but doomed direct appeal to the consciousness of the particular individuals, inviting them to reject the serializing practice of voting, so that they should be able to try, each according to his own resources, to organize the vast anti-hierarchic movement which fights institutions everywhere.225 Tellingly, however, the question of how the serialized particular individuals could fight the institutions everywhere could not be addressed by Sartre. For the way in which he defined the serialized individuals, in the spirit of his general ontological conception, made that impossible for him. They had to be condemned in view of their serial thinking in these terms:
serial thinking is born in me, thinking which is not my own thinking but that of the Other, which I am and also that of all the Others. It must be called the thinking of powerlessness, because I produce it to the degree that I am the

T H E M IS S IN G DIM E NS IO N

323

Other, an enemy of myself and of the Others, and to the degree that I carry the Other everywhere with me.226

These words of paralyzing stalemate are not the words of the young existentialist Sartre but of the militant thinker of nearly seventy years of age. Words published thirty years after Being and Nothingness and fifteen years after the Marxisant Critique of Dialectical Reason. They show Sartres great consistency as well as his continuing anguished dedication to the cause of a radical emancipatory change. But his direct appeal to individual consciousness cannot prevail, casting thereby a deeply pessimistic shadow over his final years. The main difficulty is that the millions of individual actions indicated as Sartres seminal points of reference in accounting for the intelligibility of history are in the really existing world of history always deeply embedded in objectively structured and materially mediated social complexes. That kind of embeddedness is what constitutes the capital systems structurally entrenched fundamental problem of mediation. Even the most promising political mediations can only arise from such objectively structured material ground, which under the conditions of capitals social metabolic mode of reproductive control are intelligible only as antagonistic second order mediations, with their necessarily limitedno matter how longhistorical viability. This means that we cannot discard the notion of objective historical necessity, nor should we fear that it destroys the socially understood margin of freedom. For in the Marxian sensewhich makes the vital distinction between natural necessity, like the law of gravity, and historical necessity emerging in the course of humanitys self-constitution and transformatory action, inseparably from the development of social consciousness itself the concept of historical necessity is defined not as some kind of fatality but, on the contrary, as historically confined and likewise historically overcome necessity, or vanishing necessity.227 Vanishing not in an absolute sense but according to the change of its objectively structured determinations and circumstances. Accordingly, contrary to Sartres rejection of the we-subject, as seen in different contexts in the course of this study, the historical agency of transformation cannot be the infinity of particular individuals who, as ontologically predetermined self-oriented individuals, carry with them everywhere the Other as the necessary interiorization of ontologically insurmountable scarcity, representing thereby a form of enmity toward all of the Others as well as themselves. This picture is unredeemably bleak. Likewise, the enmity

324

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

depicted in terms of the internally torn individual who is simultaneously also the antagonistic Other to the Other is equally insurmountableand bleak in its fundamental existential terms of reference, despite Sartres agonizing appeal to the individuals consciousness for a change. The power of graphic poetic depiction cannot remove the Marxisant existentialist gloom spelled out when Sartre writes about the historic movement:
Making oneself and overflowing oneself; gathering oneself only to flee oneself; having oneself determined in the present by a future determination, and thus producing oneself as a movement toward the infinite indetermination of the future; realizing development in a spiral, as a compromise between the axial line running from the need to the objective and the perpetually recommenced failure of rewinding onto oneself (i.e. unifying the multiple by a continuous displacement of quantity and scarcity); in short, at once turning and simultaneously fleeing like a slipping stitch, engendering notknowing, not-known and the uncertain.228

To overcome the paralyzing stalemate of the projected schematic circularity we need more than the category of possibility, no matter how many times multiplied. For the appeal tounrealized and in virtue of its conceptualization in terms of infinity unrealizablepossibility can only intensify the feeling of anguish when Sartre asserts that the men who will be in a position to exercise power will certainly represent a number of practical possibilities infinitely small in relation to the totalized series of possibles of that kind. And every realized possibilityif it were to be replaced in the total serieswould be separated by an infinity of possibles from the other realized possibles.229 Thus, in his own terms of reference Sartres agonizing pessimism and feeling of despair about this miserable, horrible, ugly, bad ensemble of our planet, without hope, as voiced in his last interview, is fully justified. However, founding hope, as he generously advocated and promised to the end, would require the most active contribution of the strategic Archimedian material mediatory leverage missing from the horizon of his philosophy. For only through the sustained creative application of such leverage can capitals destructive mode of social metabolic reproduction be irreversibly confined to the past.

Conclusion
The idea which I have never ceased to develop is that in the end one is always responsible for what is made of one. Even if one can do nothing else besides assume this responsibility. For I believe that a man can always make something out of what is made of him. This is the limit I would today accord to freedom: the small movement which makes of a totally conditioned social being someone who does not render back completely what his conditioning has given him. Which makes of Genet a poet when he had been rigorously conditioned to be a thief. . . . The individual interiorizes his social determinations: he interiorizes the relations of production, the family of his childhood, the historical past, the contemporary institutions, and then he re-exteriorizes these in acts and options which necessarily refer us back to them.230

SA RT R E F OR A LON G T I ME REF USED to assign any limit to freedom in his conception of the human reality. His refusal was so categorical that when he revised his views after the war, under the experience of society, he had to confess that he felt scandalized231 by the unreality of his earlier position. Nevertheless, even when he acknowledged the force of circumstance, he always continued to reassert his firm belief that one is always responsible for what is made of one. In this sense, the same way in which against the rigorous conditioning to be a thief Genet became a poet, also Sartre himselfwho was from his earliest childhood and circumstances just as

326

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

rigorously conditioned to be an accommodatory bourgeoisbecame a passionate rebel against his own class-belonging and remained one to the end of his life. In the course of the long interviews taped between 1970 and 1974 John Gerassi asked the question: I want to know, Sartre, how a bourgeois like youand you, Sartre, no matter how much you hate the bourgeoisie are still a bourgeois through and throughbecame a revolutionary?232 We have seen in this study the complex articulation of Sartres motivations and achievements in this respect which assign him a most important place in the cultural and political developments of the twentieth century. At the roots of his political stand against the social order of his own class we could find a passionate moral rebellion. This was what he stressed also in his interviews with Gerassi, insisting that My approach was always ethical. Whenever I condemned the communists or anyone else for that matter, it was always from a moral point of view.233 His moral stance could be consistently maintained by assuming responsibility both for his writings and political actions. He rejected any suggestion that there might be a contradiction between his literary work on the one hand, which had to be inserted into the existing cultural setting, and his revolutionary militancy on the other. This was the reason why he forcefully asserted that I am both a bourgeois writer like Flaubert, and a revolutionary activist like Babeuf. I assume responsibility for both.234 And he certainly assumed that responsibility with the greatest integrity. A generation earlier, when people like Lukcs became mature intellectuals, in the first decade of the twentieth century, rebels against the bourgeois order emerging from the rank of the bourgeoisie were much more frequent than by the time when Sartre became a socially committed activist during and after the second world war. Just preceding the first world war we could perceive some kind of crisis of conscience among the best intellectual representatives of the bourgeoisie, resulting in many of them joining even some revolutionary organizations in the aftermath of the Russian Revolution, in contrast to the loss of conscience and corresponding disposition to side unreservedly with the defense of capitalism by most of them who belonged to Sartres generation. This change could only underline the significance of Sartres passionate moral rebellion against his own class, in a period of history when the stakes involving the very survival of humanity were becoming acute. Sartres uncompromising rejection of the existing order and his advocacy of a very different alternative to it was often expressed in the most painful and even pessimistic self-torturing form, saying that

CO N C LU S ION

327

In each social event that is important to us, that touches us, I see the contradictionseither manifest or hardly noticed yet. I see the mistakes, the risks, everything that can prevent a situation from going in the direction of freedom. And there I am pessimistic because each time, the risks are in fact enormous. Look at Portugal, where the kind of socialism we want has a small chance now which it didnt have at all before April 25, and yet runs the greatest risk of being postponed again for a very long time. Looking at everything generally, I say to myself: Either man is finished (and in that case not only is he finished, but he has never existedhe will have been no more than a species, like the ant) or he will adapt by bringing about some form of libertarian socialism. When I think about individual social acts, I tend to think that man is finished. . . . If I am not completely pessimistic it is primarily because I sense in myself certain needs which are not only mine but the needs of every man. To express it in another way, it is the experienced certainty of my own freedom.235

Thus Sartres appeal to the experienced certainty of freedom always remained the pivotal point on his moral rebellion against the bourgeois order, even when he attempted to give its full weight to the force of circumstance. His overwhelming concentration on politics in terms of which he hoped, and pessimistically failed, to find the remedy was closely connected with the inherently moral character of his radical negation of capitalism. That was what circumscribed not only the nature of his passionate refusal and the fundamental terms of his diagnosis of the existing orderits moral untenability categorically condemned in the name of freedombut also his conception of the socialist alternative, defined by Sartre as libertarian socialism and a society without powers.236 The pessimism and despair confessed by Sartre, while reiterating with noble constancy his appeal to the idea of freedom, was inseparable from such diagnosis and projected remedy. Foras we have seen in the last chapterpolitics can be considered only a limited part of the necessary answers, in virtue of being articulated on the ground of capitals in our time fundamentally destructive material determinations. If in this sense the political domain is not set in its proper perspective, the frustration experienced by its perceived failure to produce the hoped for results, as expressed by Sartre also in the quotation in which he anticipated postponement again for a very long time, becomes overpowering. At the same time, paradoxically, the way in which these problems were approachedboth in Sartres radical moral negation of the existing order and his definition of the socialist

328

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

alternativegranted far too much to the continuing objective viability of advanced capitalism and organized capitalism. By the same token, and even more paradoxically, the objective necessitythough of course not the mechanistic determinismof the future socialist alternative was underrated, despite Sartres persistent advocacy of the emancipatory perspective. Naturally, Sartre was absolutely right in stressing that socialism is not a certainty.237 But it is very problematical that he defined socialismof course fully in the spirit of his moral negation of the existing orderas a value: it is freedom choosing itself as the goal.238 Here the point is not to deny that socialism as the commended general perspective of human emancipation is a value, which certainly it is and must continue to be. But it is also something else on the basis of which one can assert its irrepressible validity. Otherwise socialism could be simply ignored or cynically dismissed by the hired prize-fighters of capital as nothing more than a wishfully propounded but futile value, as befits the ideological dominance of the ruling order. The reason why such dismissal cannot permanently prevail is because, come what may, socialism is also the objectively one and only sustainable and in that sense objectively necessaryhistorical alternative to capitals destructive social metabolic order. In this sense socialism as the ruling orders hegemonic alternative is thecontradictorily but nonetheless objectively unfoldinghistorical necessity of our time. A necessity once undoubtedly possessed also by capitals reproductive order; in its ownnow by its incorrigible destructive determinations in objective historical terms fatefully anachronistichistorical time. Sartres radical negation of the established order, with its leverage centered on the moral and political dimension posited by him on the categorial basis of possibility, induced Sartre to demand as a general moral imperative what cannot be achieved, for the sake of realizing the society without powers advocated by him. He insisted for this reason that it is the social structure itself that must be abolished, since it permits the exercise of power.239 The problem is that the social structure itself cannot be abolished. In the case of capitals dehumanizing social structure, it can and must be radically restructured, in accordance with the requirements of historical sustainability, through the constitution and ceaseless recreation of a productively and humanly viable alternative social structure. Equally, the question of exercising power can only be decided in terms of its historical specificity and sustainability, through the shared determination and substantively equal exercise of power in a socialist global order. But what is at

CO N C LU S ION

329

stake is the constitution of a global order which cannot conceivably function without the conscious determination and emancipatory exercise of power by the social individuals for themselves. It is indeed the measure of viability of the social structure the way in which it not only permits but also facilitates that kind of exercise of power. Understandably, in the light of bitter twentieth century historical experience Sartre was deeply concerned with what he called the irreducible singularity of every man to the History which nevertheless conditions him rigorously.240 Six years earlier, when he was still engaged with the task of trying to elaborate his conception of real history in a combative mood, Sartre wrote about the vital imperative to realize the concrete universal in these terms: So we othersrats without cerebellawe are also so made that we must either die or reinvent man. . . . without us, the fabrication would take place in the dark, by tinkering and patching, if we, the debrained, were not there to repeat constantly that we must work according to principles, that it is not a matter of mending, but of measuring and constructing, and finally, that mankind will be the concrete universal, or that it will not be.241 By the time Sartre gave his lecture on Kierkegaard in Paris, in 1964, he had already abandoned writing the Critique of Dialectical Reason, but not his passionate engagement with the difficult problems of the singular universal. He tried to bring Kierkegaard and Marx together in that spirit, in the interest of the tasks that await us within the historical dialectic.242 Thus, despite the solemn centenary celebrations he did not try to hide the failures on Kierkegaards side, arguing that the Danish philosopher by
Pitting himself against Hegel, he occupied himself over-exclusively with transmitting his instituted contingency to the human adventure and, because of this, he neglected praxis, which is rationality. At a stroke, he denatured knowledge, forgetting that the world we know is the world we make. Anchorage is a fortuitous event, but the possibility and rational meaning of this chance is given by general structures of envelopment which found it and which are themselves the universalization of singular adventures by the materiality in which they are inscribed.243

But he did not stop there. After stressing the great practical risk arising from the exclusionin the name of a one-sidedly interpreted Marxthe human singularity of the concrete universal,244 he finished his lecture on Kierkegaard with these challenging questions, formulated fully in the spirit of his own philosophy: How can we conceive of History and the

330

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

transhistorical in such a way as to restore to the transcendent necessity of the historical process and to the free immanence of a historicization ceaselessly renewed their full reality and reciprocal interiority, in theory and practice? In short, how can we discover the singularity of the universal and the universalization of the singular, in each conjuncture, as indissolubly linked to each other?245 Sartre was right in leaving his questions open. For the task of providing an appropriate answer to them can only be fulfilled by the most radical emancipatory mass movement. A movement capable of qualitatively restructuring capitals hierarchically entrenched socioeconomic and cultural order in such a way as to secure, on a historically sustainable material ground, the shared determination and the substantive exercise of power by the freely associated producers on a fully equitable basis. Our most extraordinary comrade in arms, Jean-Paul Sartre, made in many different wayseven with his wake-up calls voiced in despairan immense contribution to the development of that movement.

Notes
PARTS ONE A ND TWO
1. Lalibi, interview, Le Nouvel Observateur, 19 November 1964; reprinted in Situations, VIII, 12745, quotation from p. 142. Les crits de Sartre: chronologie, bibliographie commente by Michel Contat and Michel Rybalka (Gallimard, Paris, 1970) is invaluable for all those interested in Sartres development. In addition to a complete bibliography of his works, up to 1969, it contains excellent summaries, with extracts from his numerous interviews, as well as nearly 300 pages of rare texts. Henceforth this book will be referred to as C/R. Unless otherwise stated, translations are my own. I. M. La nationalisation de la littrature (1945), Situations, II, 35, 43. And in the same article he remarks on the absurdity of being called the Master of neosurrealism who is supposed to have under his command Eluard and Picasso, while in reality I was still wearing short pants when they were already masters of themselves (ibid., p.37). Cf. Henri Lefbvre, Existentialisme et marxisme: rponse une mise au point, Action, 8 June 1945. Gabriel Marcel, Prise de position, Nouvelles Littraires, 29 October 1964. Cf. C/R , p. 329. On the occasion of the publication of Sartres Entretiens sur la politique (Gallimard, Paris, 1949) with David Rousset and Grard Rosenthal; cf. Le Figaro, 25 April 1949. Rponse Franois Mauriac, Le Figaro Littraire, 7 May 1949. The exchange started with Sartres letter dated 13 April 1967, followed by de Gaulles reply on 19 April 1967, and published in Le Monde, 25 April

2.

3. 4. 5. 6.

7. 8.

332

NOTE S TO PAG E S 1 8 3 4

9.

10. 11. 12 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. 24. 25. 26. 27. 28. 29. 30. 31. 32. 33. 34. 35. 36.

37.

1967. Sartres answer to de Gaulle took the form of an interview in Le Nouvel Observateur, 26 April3 May 1967; the whole exchange is reprinted in Situations VIII, 4257. Sartres letter to the Swedish Academy, in which he tried to prevent their decision in his favour, was later published in Le Monde, 24 October 1964. The complete text of this letter, together with an account of the debate that followed his refusal, is given in C/R, pp. 4018. Andr Breton, Le rappel de Stockholm, La Brche, December 1964. Le Figaro Littraire, 410 May 1970. Le Monde, 6 June 1970. Writing for ones age (1946), in What is Literature?, translated by Bernard Frechtman, Methuen, London, 1950, p. 238. Ibid., p. 233. Interview by Jacqueline Piatier, Le Monde, 18 April 1964. Ibid. La nationalisation de la littrature, p. 38. The purposes of writing (1959), Jean-Paul Sartre, Between Existentialism and Marxism, translated by John Matthews, NLB, London, 1974, pp. 1314. Ibid., p. 25. Ibid., p. 14. From a poem by Endre Ady (18771919). The purposes of writing, p. 26. I have discussed these problems in my book on Attila Jzsef e larte moderna, Lerici, Milano, 1964. A fragment by Attila Jzsef. The purposes of writing, p. 29. Ibid., p. 14. Interview by Christian Gisoli, Paru, December 1945. Interview by Jacques-Alain Miller, Les Cahier libres de la jeunesse, 15 February 1960. The purposes of writing, p. 19. Ibid. Cf. Dtermination et libert (1966); C/R, pp. 73545. Interview by Pierre Lorquet, Mondes Nouveaux, 21 December 1941. The purposes of writing, p. 22. Interview by Gabriel dAubarde, Les Nouvelles littraires, 1 February 1951. Rponse M. Mauriac, LObservateur, 19 March 1953 Of rats and men (1958), Jean-Paul Sartre, Situations, translated by Benita Eisler, Fawcett Publications, Greenwich, Conn., 1965, p. 242. Sartres footnote about the accidental individual refers to Marxs German Ideology. See also note 37. Marx, Critique of the Hegelian Philosophy of Right (1843), Marx & Engels, Werke, vol.1, p. 284.

N OT E S TO PAG E S 35 43

333

38. 39. 40. 41. 42. 43. 44. 45. 46. 47.

48. 49. 50.

51.

52.

53. 54. 55.

56. 57.

58

Itinerary of a thought (1969), New Left Review, Nov.Dec. 1969, p. 59. Forgers of myths: the young playwrights of France, Theatre Arts, June 1946. The purposes of writing, p. 27. propos de lexistentialisme: mise au point, Action, 29 Dec. 1944; reprinted in C/R pp. 653-8. Quotation from p. 654. Interview by Claude Sarraute, Le Monde, 17 Sept. 1959. Je-tu-il, preface to Andr Puigs novel, Linachev (The Unfinished), Gallimard, 1970; reprinted in Situations, IX, 277-315. Quotation from p. 281. Itinerary of a thought, p. 55. Interview by Gabriel dAubarde, Les Nouvelles littraires, 1 Febr. 1951. Simone de Beauvoir, La Force des choses, p. 466. To maintain a killing rhythm of work while writing his Critique of Dialectical Reason, Sartre consumes a tubeful of corydrone each day; La Force des choses, p.407. Simone de Beauvoir, Jean-Paul Sartre: strictly personal, Harpers Bazaar, January 1946; a major portion is reprinted in C/R, pp. 41820. Published in The New Ambassador / Revue Universitaire Internationale, Jan. 1927; reprinted in C/R, pp. 51730. Enqute auprs des tudiants daujourdhui, by Roland Alix, Les Nouvelles littraires, 2 Febr. 1929. Parts of Sartres letter are reprinted in Simone de Beauvoirs Memoirs of a Dutiful Daughter, Penguin edn., 1963, pp. 3423. Si grande que soit mon admiration pour Proust, il mest tout oppos: il se complait dans lanalyse, et je ne tends qu la synthse. Interview by Pierre Lorquet, Mondes Nouveaux, 21 Dec. 1944. It is perfectly true, isolated subjectivity is, in the opinion of the age, evil; but objectivity as a cure is not one whit better. The only salvation is subjectivity, i.e. God, as infinite compelling subjectivity. The Journals of Kierkegaard: 18341854, edited and translated by Alexander Dru, Fontana Books, p. 184. The paintings of Giacometti (1954), Situations (English), pp. 1245. Simone de Beauvoir, Memoirs of a Dutiful Daughter, p. 342. Jean-Paul Sartre has done the finest critical appreciation of (Csaires) Cahier as poetry, but his explanation of what he conceives Negritude to mean is a disaster. C.L.R. James, The Black Jacobins, 2nd revised edition, Vintage Books, New York, 1963, p.401. Les Temps Modernes, Dec. 1957, p. 1137. Lcrivain et sa langue (1965), interview by Pierre Verstraeten, Revue dEsthtique, July-December 1965; reprinted in Situations, IX, 4082. Quotation from p. 75. It is worth stressing that Lukcs deals in much the same way with this problem in his Correspondence with Anna Seghers. The paintings of Giacometti, p. 132; I have changed supra-determination to overdeterminationthe generally accepted term for surdetermination, which is the expression used by Sartre; cf. French edition of this essay in Situations, IV, p. 359.

334

NOTE S TO PAG E S 4 3 4 7

59. 60. 61. 62. 63.

64.

65.

66. 67.

68. 69. 70.

The paintings of Giacometti, p. 132. See C/R, p. 429. Interview by Alain Koehler, Perspectives du Thtre, MarchApril 1960. Interview by Robert Kanters, LExpress, 17 September 1959. A friend of the people, interview by Jean-Edern Hallier and Thomas Savignat, LIdiot International, reprinted in Situations, IX, , 45676 and in NLB volume, Between Existentialism and Marxism, pp. 286-98. Quotation from p. 295 of the latter. This is recognized to some extent when Sartre declares: If I had to rewrite Roads to Freedom, Id try to present every character without commentary, without showing my feelings. Interview by Jacqueline Autrusseau, Les Lettres franaises, 1723 September 1959. Nausea has been accused of being too pessimistic. But lets wait for the ending. In a forthcoming novel, which will be the continuation, the hero shall redress the machine. We shall see existence rehabilitated, and my hero act, tasting action. Interview by Claudine Chonez, Marianne, 7 December 1938. Cf. Chapter 3, Section 2. This is how Sartre describes in an interview the relationship between Being and Nothingness and Huis Clos: The story of mine about souls in torment was not symbolicI had no wish to repeat Being and Nothingness in different words. What would have been the point? I simply made up some stories with an imagination, sensibility and thought that the conception and writing of Being and Nothingness had united, integrated and organized in a certain way. The purposes of writing, p. 10. Interview by Jacqueline Autrusseau, Les Lettres franaises, 1723 September 1959. Interview by Bernard Dort, Thtre Populaire, Winter 1959. Sartre talks to Tynan, Tynan Right and Left, Longmans, London, 1967, pp. 30212. Reference is to pages 31011. Other relevant passages are as follows: the theatre is not concerned with reality: it is only concerned with truth. The cinema, on the other hand, seeks a reality which may contain moments of truth. The theatres true battlefield is that of tragedydrama which embodies a genuine myth. There is no reason why the theatre should not tell a story of love or marriage, as long as it has a quality of myth; in other words, as long as it occupies itself with something more than conjugal disagreements or lovers misunderstandings. By seeking truth through myth, and by the use of forms as non-realistic as tragedy, the theatre can stand up against the cinema (p. 304). I dont think theatre can be directly derived from political events. For instance, I would never have written Altona if it was merely a simple question of a conflict between Left and Right. For me, Altona is tied up with the whole evolution of Europe since 1945, as much with the Soviet concentration camps as with the war in Algeria. The theatre must take all these problems and transmute them into mythic form (p. 307). I am always looking for myths; in

N OT E S TO PAG E S 47 55

335

71. 72. 73. 74. 75. 76. 77. 78. 79. 80. 81.

82. 83.

84. 85. 86. 87. 88. 89. 90. 91. 92. 93. 94. 95.

other words, for subjects so sublimated that they are recognizable to everyone, without recourse to minute psychological details (p. 310). Furthermore, there are also gradations or varieties of myth on the objective to subjective scale: the work of Tennessee Williams is permeated with subjective myths (p. 308). And the whole category of myth, subjective as much as objective, is opposed to symbolism: I have not liked Becketts other plays [other than Waiting for Godot, that is] particularly Endgame, because I find the symbolism far too inflated, far too naked (p. 307). In Theatre Arts (New York), June 1946. In Le Point, January 1967. Interview by Nicole Zand, Bref, FebruaryMarch 1967. Interview by Alain Koehler, Perspectives du Thtre, March-April 1960 Itinerary of a thought, p. 56. La recherche de labsolu (1948), Situations, III, 300301. Ibid., p. 301. Masson (1960), Situations, IV, p. 389. Ibid., p. 401. La recherche de labsolu, p. 293. Les mobiles de Calder (1946), Situations, III, pp. 30811. And he writes on Giacometti that his works, constantly in the course of making, are always half-way between nothingness and being (La recherche de labsolu, p. 293.) The purposes of writing, pp. 1112. Le choix libre que lhomme fait de soi-mme sidentifie absolument avec ce quon appelle sa destine (Jean-Paul Sartre, Baudelaire, Gallimard, Paris, 1947, p. 224.) And another important passage concerning this problem: nous touchons ici au choix originel que Baudelaire a fait de lui mme, cet engagement absolu par quoi chacun dcide dans une situation particulire de ce quil sera et de ce quil est. (p.20.) Interview by Claudine Chonez, Lobservateur, 31 May 1951. Dfense de la culture franaise par la culture europenne, Politique trangere, June 1949. Interview by Franoise Erval, Combat, 3 February 1949. Interview by Alain Koehler, Perspectives du Thtre, MarchApril 1960 The purposes of writing, p. 12. Itinerary of a thought, p. 56. Lgende de la vrit, Bifur, June 1931; Reprinted in C/R, pp. 53145. Itinerary of a thought, p. 56. Interview by Claudine Chonez, Marianne, 23 November and 7 December 1938. Of rats and men, Situations, p. 245. See note 33. Sartre, Saint Genet: comdien et martyr, Gallimard, Paris, 1952, p. 536.

336

NOTE S TO PAG E S 5 6 6 5

96. 97. 98. 99. 100. 101. 102. 103.

104. 105. 106. 107. 108. 109. 110. 111. 112. 113. 114. 115.

116.

117. 118. 119. 120. 121. 122.

La nationalisation de la littrature, Situations, II, p. 53. La Libration de Paris: une semaine dApocalypse, Clarts, 24 August 1945; reprinted in C/R, pp. 65962. Gribouille, La Rue, November 1947. Limagination au pouvoir, entretien de Jean-Paul Sartre avec Daniel CohnBendit, Le Nouvel Observateur, Special Supplement, 20 May 1968. Interview by Serge Lafaurie, Le Nouvel Observateur, 17 March 1969; reprinted in Situations, VIII. Quotation from p. 254. La Libration de Paris: une semaine dApocalypse, C/R, p. 661. Dtermination et Libert, C/R, p. 745. LArt cinmatographique (1931), first published in a brochure of the Lyce de Le Havre, Distribution solennelle des prix, Le Havre, 12 July 1931; reprinted in C/R, pp. 54652. Quotation from pp. 54852. Interview by Yvon Novy, Comoedia, 24 April 1943. Quand Hollywood veut faire penserCitizen Kane dOrson Welles, LEcran franais, 1 August 1945. LArt cinmatographique, C/R, p. 551. Ibid., p. 549. Interview by Yvon Novy, Comoedia, 24 April 1943. propos de Le Bruit et la Fureurla temporalit chez Faulkner (July 1939), Situations, I, p. 68. Ibid., p. 71. Ibid., p. 72. Ibid., p. 73. Ibid. Ibid., p. 74. Lucien Goldmann has discussed in several of his works the relationship between Lukcs and Heidegger, cf. Mensch, Gemeinschaft und Welt in der Philosophie Immanuel Kants (Europa-Verlag, Zrich, 1945), Recherches dialectiques (Gallimard, Paris, 1959), and in particular his posthumous volume, Lukcs et Heidegger, ed., and with an introduction by Youssef Ishaghpour (Denol/Gonthier, Paris, 1973.) Heideggers preface to the seventh German edition of Being and Time, translated by John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson, Blackwell, Oxford, 1967, p. 17. La temporalit chez Faulkner, p. 73. Ibid., pp. 745. Ce Soir, 16 May 1938. Quand Hollywood veut faire penser . . . , cf. note 105. Quest-ce-que lexistentialisme? Bilan dune offensive, Interview by Dominique Aury, Les Lettres franaises, 24 November 1945. Interview by Jacques-Alain Miller, Les Cahiers libres de la Jeunesse, 15 February 1960.

N OT E S TO PAG E S 65 78

337

123. 124. 125. 126. 127.

128. 129. 130. 131. 132. 133. 134. 135. 136.

137.

138.

Simone de Beauvoir, La Force des choses, p. 214. Interview by Robert Kanters, LExpress, 17 September 1959. Itinerary of a thought, p. 52. Quoted by Thomas Mann in his Essay in Autobiography. The purposes of writing, p. 31. The same view is expressed in Words: I have renounced my vocation, but I have not unfrocked myself. I still write. What else can I do? Nulla dies sine linea. It is my habit and it is also my profession. For a long while I treated my pen as a sword: now I realize how helpless we are. It does not matter: I am writing, I shall write books; they are needed; they have a use all the same. Penguin edition, p. 157. Sartre quoting Isaac Deutscher in A friend of the people, pp. 2923. Ibid., pp. 2935. Itinerary of a thought, p. 51. Ibid., p. 45. A friend of the people, pp. 293 and 295. Interview by Jacqueline Piatier, Le Monde, 18 April 1964. Lange du morbide, published in La Revue sans titre, 15 January 1923. Jsus la Chouette, professeur de province, La Revue sans titre, 10 and 25 February and 10 March 1923. His Esquisse dune thorie des motions (Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions) was written in 1936 but probably revised before publication in 1939. LImagination (English title: Imagination: a psychological critique) was written in 1935 and published in 1936. And LImaginaire (English title: The Psychology of Imagination) was written and in part published in 1939, and as a book in 1940. Meanwhile Sartre was writing a treatise on phenomenological psychology which he entitled La Psych, and of which in the end he published an extract only, calling it Esquisse dune thorie phnomnologique des motions (The Emotions: Outline of a theory). Here he developed his theory of psychic objectivity, which had been sketched out in the essay on The Transcendence of the Ego. But to his way of thinking this was little more than an exercise, and after writing four hundred pages he broke off to complete his collection of stories. Simone de Beauvoir, The Prime of Life, Penguin edition, p.318. See for instance the following passage: The third reason for choosing Flaubert is that he represents a sequel to LImaginaire. You may remember that in my very early book LImaginaire I tried to show that an image is not a sensation reawakened, or reworked by the intellect, or even a former perception altered and attenuated by knowledge, but is something entirely differentan absent reality, focused in its absence through what I called an analogon; that is to say, an object which serves as an analogy and is traversed by an intention. For example, when you are going to sleep, the little dots in your eyesphosphenesmay serve as an analogy for every kind of oneiric or hypnagogic image. Between waking and sleeping some people see vague

338

NOTE S TO PAG E S 7 8 8 1

139. 140. 141. 142. 143. 144. 145. 146.

147. 148. 149.

shapes pass, which are phosphenes through which they focus on an imagined person or a thing. In LImaginaire, I tried to prove that imaginary objects imagesare an absence. In my book on Flaubert, I am studying imaginary personspeople who like Flaubert act out roles. A man is like a leak of gas, escaping into the imaginary. Flaubert did so perpetually; yet he also had to see reality because he hated it, so there is the whole question of the relationship between the real and the imaginary which I try to study in his life and work. Itinerary of a thought, p. 53. Intimacy, The Wall, The Room, Erostratus, and The Childhood of a Leader. Itinerary of a thought, p. 44. Action, 29 December 1944; reprinted in C/R, pp. 6538. A lecture delivered on 28 October 1945, and published as a volume by Nagel, Paris, 1946. Written in 1945 and published in 1946. Le R.D.R. et le problme de la libert, La Pense socialiste, Spring 1948. Faux savants ou faux livres? (1950), Situations, VI, p. 28. Pourtant, aprs avoir applaudi la victoire du militant, cest laventurier que je suivrai dans sa solitude. Il a vcu jusqueau bout une condition impossible: fuyant et cherchant la solitude, vivant pour mourir et mourant pour vivre, convincu de la vanit de laction et de sa ncessit, tentant de justifier son entreprise en lui assignant un but auquel il ne croyait pas, recherchant la totale objectivit du rsultat por la diluer dans une absolute subjectivit, voulant lchec quil refusait, refusant la victoire quil souhaitait, voulant construire sa vie comme un destin et ne se plaisant quaux moments infinitsimaux qui sparent la vie de la mort. Aucune solution de ces antinomies, aucune synthse de ces contradictoires. . . . Pourtant, au prix dune tension insupportable, cet homme les a maintenus ensemble et tous la fois, dans leur incomparabilit mme; il a t la conscience permanente de cette incompatibilit. . . . je pense quil tmoigne la fois de lexistence absolue de lhomme et de son impossibilit absolue. Mieux encore: il prouve que cest cette impossibilit dtre qui est la condition de son existence et que lhomme existe parce quil est impossible. . . . une cit socialiste o de futurs Lawrence seraient radicalement impossibles me semblerait strilise. (Portrait de laventurier, 1950, Situations, VI, pp. 2021.) It is worth remembering that in 1945, in his lecture Existentialisme est un humanisme Sartre characterized Lawrence as an existentialist. No doubt as a result of criticism received from his socialist friends, Sartre omitted such references from the published text. Saint Genet, p. 177. Ibid. A substantial part of Saint Genet appeared in 1950, in several issues of Les Temps Modernes. La bombe H, une arme contre lhistoire, Dfense de la Paix, July 1954.

N OT E S TO PAG E S 81 85

339

150. See Ce que jai vu Vienne, cest la Paix, Les Lettres franaises, 18 January 1953; and an interview by Marcel Saporta, Cuadernos Americanos, January February 1954. 151. La pense et la politique daujourdhui nous mnent au massacre parce quelles sont abstraites. . . . Chacun est lAutre, lennemi possible, on sen mfie. Il est rare, en France, mon pays, de rencontrer des hommes; on rencontre surtout des tiquettes et des noms. Ce quil y a de neuf et dadmirable dans ce congrs de la Paix, cest quil runit des hommes. . . . Nous avons rsolu, non de nous substituer nos gouvernements, mais de communiquer entre nous, sans eux. Sartres intervention at the opening session of the Vienna meeting, on 12 December 1952; published in Congrs des Peuples pour la Paix, Vienne, 1219 Dec. 1952, Paris, 1953. 152. The purposes of writing, p. 13. 153. Les Temps Modernes, February 1956. 154. Interview by Simon Blumenthal and Grard Spitzer, La Voie communiste, new series, JuneJuly 1962. 155. Les Temps Modernes, November-December 1956January 1957, pp. 577 697. 156. Itinerary of a thought, p. 46. 157. The purposes of writing, p. 9. 158. Echoing his own earlier hopes about a broadly based yet effective political rassemblement (see his participation in the RDR), he sees the militancy of La Cause du Peuple in a similar light: the militants of La Cause du Peuple do not constitute a party. It is a political group [rassemblement] which can always be dissolved. . . . This procedure allows a way out of the rigidity in which the Communist Party has imprisoned itself. . . . Today, the Maoists criticize and break out of the notion of leftism: they want to be the left and to create a broad political organization [rassemblement]. (Interview by Michel-Antoine Burnier, Actuel, No. 28, and Tout va Bien, 20 February20 March 1973; translated by Robert dAmico, Telos, Summer 1973; quotations from pp. 93 and 95 of Telos.) It does not matter here that leftism is often characterized precisely by a voluntaristic wanting to be the left which disregards the objective relation of forces. Nor are we concerned with the question whether or not the reality of French Maoism corresponds to Sartres description. What matters in this context is the reassertion of Sartres ideal of a broadly based and extremely flexible political organization: a rassemblement of individuals as opposed to a highly disciplined and structured political party. 159. Itinerary of a thought, pp. 589. 160. Of course Sartres works are inherently problematical, but not in such a way that the later works might be considered less problematical than the earlier ones. Roads to Freedom is not a more mature novel than Nausea (in the sense in which Thomas Manns Magic Mountain is incomparably more mature than his Royal Highness), nor is Critique of Dialectical Reason more mature than

340

NOTE S TO PAG E S 8 5 8 7

161. 162.

163.

164. 165. 166. 167. 168. 169.

Being and Nothingness in the field of philosophy, or The Idiot of the Family than Saint Genet in the field of biography. In the later works there are some new principles at workalongside with a great many they share with the earlier onesthat is all. It is Sartres lifework as a whole which is problematical, with its overpowering negativity, and not one or two of its limited phases that might be characterized in relation to one another in terms of radical breaks. We cannot stress enough, Sartrein some ways like Picassoproduces not so much representative works as a representative lifework. If we want a great parallel from the pastkeeping in mind, of course, all the differences and specificitieswe may think of Voltaire, with his all-embracing negativity. Situated at another juncture of great socio-historical transformation and transition, Voltaire subjects the old order to the most devastating criticism and satirequite unlike Rousseau, who organically complements his radical negativity with anticipations of a new order. As we all know well, only a tiny fraction of Voltaires immense lifework is read today. But if we try to imagine the eighteenth century without his contribution we must immediately realize how much the poorer it would be for that. Interview by Dominique Aury, Les Lettres franaises, 24 November 1945. Being and Nothingness: an essay on phenomenological ontology (1943), translated by Hazel E. Barnes, Methuen, London, 1969, pp. 526 and 529 (henceforth referred to as B & N). Interview by Robert Kanters, LExpress, 17 September 1959. The theme of being judged appears many times in Sartres writings, including an interview with Kenneth Tynan in which he says: The point is that we know we shall be judged, and not by the rules we use to judge ourselves. And he adds: In that thought there is something horrific (K. Tynan, Tynan Right and Left, 1967, p. 304.) Thus there is always something threatening, sinister, tragic on the horizon. Even when Sartre declares that he has always been an optimist, indeed too much of an optimist, he does that in conjunction with some sombre metaphysical statements, like: The Universe remains dark. We are sinister animals. And although he insists in the same interview that alienation, exploitation and hunger are the evils we should be concerned about because they relegate to the second plane the metaphysical evil, the latter remains menacingly looming in the background in the Sartrean dark Universe. (See his interview by Jacqueline Piatier, Le Monde, 18 April 1964.) La recherche de labsolu, Situations, III, p. 293. Interview by Michel-Antoine Burnier, loc. cit., p. 99. La question (1965), Thtre vivant, September 1965. Preface for Portrait of a Man Unknown by Nathalie Sarraute (1948), translated by Maria Jolas, Situations, Fawcett, Greenwich, Conn., 1965, p. 139. Ibid., p. 141. Ibid., p. 139.

N OT E S TO PAG E S 87 97

341

170. Merleau-Ponty (1961), Situations (English edition), p. 185. 171. The Problem of Method (1959), translated by Hazel E. Barnes, Methuen, London, 1963, p. 20. (Henceforth referred to as Method). 172. See the description of his prisoner of war camp experience (Chapter 1, note 18) which is used to authenticate his analysis of distance as a concept meaningful only in a human context. That he contradicts elsewhere the statement that close proximity to others in the camp was never disturbing, as the others were a part of me, only underlines the fact that such personal references do not appear in his work for the sake of their descriptive content but for their authenticating function. It does not really matter whether or not Sartre actually had the experiences he describes. What is structurally important is that his crucial theoretical propositions are coupled and integrated with existential authenticating subjective references. 173. Je le dis tout de suite: vos attaques me paraissent inspires par la mauvaise foi et lignorance. Il nest mme pas sr que vous ayez lu aucun des livres dont vous parlez. (Sartre, propos de lexistentialisme: mise au point, pp. 6534.) 174. Ses [Lukcss] arguments sont nuls et non avenus: il na pas lu Ltre et le Nant (Interview by Franois Erval, Combat, 3 February 1949). On the other hand, when the principal object of his criticism is the French C.P., Sartre completely reverses his severe judgement and refers to Lukcs in the highest terms of praise: Le seul qui tente en Europe, dexpliquer par leur causes les mouvements de pense contemporains, cest un communiste hongrois, Lukcs. (Le Rformisme et les ftiches, Les Temps Modernes, February 1956, p. 1159) 175. I have at least this in common with Hegel. You have not read either of us. You have such a mania for not going to the source. (Reply to Albert Camus, 1952), Situations, p. 66. 176. Les Temps Modernes, December 1957, p. 137. 177. Une ide fondamentale de la phnomnologie de Husserl: lIntentionnalit, (January 1939), Situations, I, p. 30. Henceforth referred to as Une ide.) 178. The Transcendence of the Ego, translated by Forrest Williams and Robert Kirkpatrick, The Noonday Press, New York, 1957, pp. 3940. 179. Ibid., pp. 878. 180. Ibid., p. 103. 181. The refutation [of solipsism] that Husserl presents in Formale und Transcendentale Logik and in Cartesianische Meditationen does not seem to us capable of unsettling a determined and intelligent solipsist. As long as the I remains a structure of consciousness, it will always remain possible to oppose consciousness, with its I, to all other existents. (Ibid., p 103.) 182. Ibid., pp. 1034. 183. Ibid., pp. 1046. 184. This is how Simone de Beauvoir describes Sartres encounter with Husserls philosophy: Sartre was coming to realize that in order to give the ideas dividing

342

NOTE S TO PAG E S 8 7 9 8

his mind some coherent organization, help was essential. The first translation of Kierkegaard appeared about this time: we had no particular incentive to read them, and left them untouched. On the other hand, Sartre was strongly attracted by what he had heard about German phenomenology. Raymond Aron was spending a year at the French Institute in Berlin and studying Husserl simultaneously with preparing a historical thesis. When he came to Paris he spoke of Husserl to Sartre. We spent an evening together at the Bec de Gaz in the Rue Montparnasse. We ordered the speciality of the house, apricot cocktails; Aron said, pointing to his glass: You see, my dear fellow, if you are a phenomenologist, you can talk about this cocktail and make philosophy out of it! Sartre turned pale with emotion at this. Here was just the thing he had been longing to achieve for yearsto describe objects just as he saw and touched them, and extract philosophy from the process. Aron convinced him that phenomenology exactly fitted in with his special preoccupation: by-passing the antithesis of idealism and realism [materialism], affirming simultaneously both the supremacy of reason and the reality of the visible world as it appears to our senses. On the Boulevard Saint-Michel Sartre purchased Lvinass book on Husserl, and was so eager to inform himself on the subject that he leafed through the volume as he walked along, without even having cut the pages. (The Prime of Life, translated by Peter Green, Penguin Edition, pp. 1356.) The contrast with Lukcs couldnt be greater. As Sartre from Raymond Aron twenty years later, Lukcs gets an enthusiastic account of phenomenology during the first world war from Max Scheler, but he reacts to it with extreme scepticism. This is how Lukcs himself describes the incident: Als mich zur Zeit des ersten Weltkrieges Scheler in Heidelberg besuchte, hatten wir hierber ein interessantes und characteristisches Gesprch. Scheler vertrat den Standpunkt, die Phnomenologie sie eine universale Methode, die alles zum intentionalen Gegenstand haben knne. Man kann zum Beispiel, fhrte Scheler aus, ber den Teufel phnomenologische Untersuchungen machen, man muss nur zunchts die Frage der Existenz des Teufels in Klammer setzen.Freilich, antwortete ich, und wenn sie dann mit dem phnomenologischen Bild ber den Teufel fertig geworden sind, dann ffnen sie die Klammerund der Teufel steht leibhaftig vor uns. Scheler lachte, zuckte mit den Achseln und antwortete nichts. (Georg Lukcs, Existentialismus oder Marxismus, Aufbau Verlag, Berlin, 1951, pp. 367. Lukcss early philosophy has been constituted on the basis of a positive response to Plato, Kant and Hegel, in accordance with his fundamental interest in finding a secure way of transcending the world of deceptive appearances while remaining on the ground of reality, and therefore the idea of phenomenological bracketing and reduction had to be totally alien to him. 185. The Psychology of Imagination, translated by Bernard Frechtman, Washington Square Press, New York, 1966, p. 233 (henceforth referred to as LImaginaire). 186. Une ide, p. 32.

N OT E S TO PAG E S 98 10 2

343

187. Ibid. 188. B & N., p. 626. 189. Eugen Fink, Die phnomenologische Philosophie Edmund Husserl in der gegewartigen Kritik, Kantstudien, 1933. 190. Transcendence, pp. 1023. 191. Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions, translated by Philip Mairet, Methuen, London, 1962, p. 81 (henceforth referred to as Emotions). 192. Imagination: a psychological critique, translated by Forrest Williams, The University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor, 1962, pp. 1413 (henceforth referred to as Imagination). 193. LImaginaire, pp. 2412. 194. Ibid., p. 243. Also, we should bear in mind the following qualifications: In an imaginary world, there is no dream of possibilities since possibilities call for a real world on the basis of which they are thought of as possibilities. Consciousness cannot get perspective on its own imaginations in order to imagine a possible sequence to the story which it is representing to itself: that would be to be awake. . . . All anticipation at a given moment of a story derives from the very fact that the anticipation appears as an episode of the story. I cannot entertain, conceive another ending. I have no choice, no recourse, I am compelled to narrate the story to myself: there is no blow for nothing. So each moment of the story occurs as having an imaginary future, but a future I cannot foresee, which will come of its own accord, in its own time, to haunt consciousness, against which consciousness will be crushed. So, contrary to what could be believed, the imaginary world occurs as a world without freedom: nor is it determined, it is the opposite of freedom, it is fatal. (Ibid., pp. 220-21) We can conclude that the dreamcontrary to Descartesdoes not at all occur as an apprehension of reality. On the contrary, it would lose all its sense, its own nature if it could posit itself as real even for a moment. It is primarily a story and our strong interest in it is of the same sort as that of the nave reader in a novel. It is lived as a fiction . . . Only it is a spellbinding fiction: consciousness . . . has become knotted. And what it lives, at the same time as the fiction apprehended as a fiction is the impossibility of emerging out of the fiction. Just as King Midas transformed everything he touched into gold, so consciousness is itself determined to transform into the imaginary everything it gets hold of: hence the fatal nature of the dream. It is the seizure of this fatality as such which has often been confused with an apprehension of the dreamed world as reality. (Ibid., p. 228) The dream is a privileged experience which can help us to conceive what a consciousness would be which would have lost its being-in-the-world and which would be, by the same token, deprived of the category of the real. (Ibid., p. 229) The last remark is particularly important for understanding Sartres way of asserting the function of the real in relation to consciousness while rejecting all deterministic accounts.

344

NOTES TO PAG E S 1 0 3 1 1 9

195. 196. 197. 198. 199. 200.

201. 202. 203. 204. 205. 206. 207. 208. 209. 210.

211.

212. 213. 214. 215. 216. 217. 218. 219. 220. 221. 222. 223. 224. 225. 226. 227. 228.

Emotions, p. 93. Imagination, pp. 156. See in particular Emotions, pp. 3248. Simone de Beauvoir, The Prime of Life, p. 128. See the last section of this chapter. For a classic analysis of these problems, see Lukcss essay on Reification and the Consciousness of the Proletariat (written in 1922, first published in 1923), History and Class Consciousness, translated by Rodney Livingstone, Merlin Press, London, 1971, pp. 83222. LImaginaire, pp. 24041. Ibid., p. 245. Ibid., p. 241. Ibid., pp. 2434. See note 212 and 214. LImaginaire, p. 241. Ibid., p. 245. Ibid., p. 244. Nausea, translated by Robert Baldick, Penguin edition, p. 22. His blue cotton shirt stands out cheerfully against a chocolate-coloured wall. That too brings on the Nausea. Or rather it is the Nausea. The Nausea isnt inside me: I can feel it over there on the wall, on the braces, everything around me. It is one with the caf, it is I who am inside it. Ibid., p. 35. The Nausea hasnt left me and I dont believe it will leave me for quite a while; but I am no longer putting up with it, it is no longer an illness or a passing fit: it is me. Ibid., p. 182. Ibid., pp. 1823. We should recall here Sartres early critique of the notion of will to power, etc., in his contribution to the student enquiry. See note 50. Nausea, pp. 18392. Emotions, p. 90. See note 163. Emotions, pp. 845. Ibid., pp. 9091. Method, p. 130. Ibid., p. 59. Ibid., p. 152. Ibid., p. 94. Ibid., p. 95. Ibid., p. 80. See in particular pp. 779 of Method. Itinerary of a thought, p. 58. Method, p. 88. Ibid., p. 78.

N OT E S TO PAG E S 119 1 30

345

229. 230. 231. 232. 233. 234. 235. 236. 237.

238. 239. 240. 241.

242. 243. 244. 245. 246. 247. 248. 249. 250. 251. 252. 253. 254.

Ibid., p. 115. Interview by Michel-Antoine Burnier, p. 99. Method, p. 90. Ibid., p. 79. There are some important changes in method in the development of Husserl and Heidegger, as well as of Merleau-Ponty. Simone de Beauvoir, The Prime of Life, p. 136. Method, p. 52. (Sartres reference is to Henri Lefbvres Perspectives de sociologie rurale, Cahiers de sociologie, 1953.) Method, p. 52. We shall define the method of the existentialist approach as a regressiveprogressive and analytic-synthetic method. It is at the same time an enriching cross-reference between the object (which contains the whole period as hierarchized specifications) and the period (which contains the object in its totalization). Ibid., p. 148. Emotions, pp. 934. Imagination, p. 128. Method, p. 135. According to Heidegger Because Marx, through his experience of the alienation of modern man, is aware of a fundamental dimension of history, the Marxist view of history is superior to all other views. (See Irving Fetscher, Marxismusstudien, in Soviet Survey, No. 33, JulySeptember 1960, p. 88.) It goes without saying, Marx did not experience alienation as the alienation of modern man, but as the alienation of man in capitalist society. Nor did he look upon alienation as a fundamental dimension of history, but as a central issue of a given phase of history which can be historically transcended. The Heideggerian idea of alienation as a fundamental dimension of history is in fact profoundly anti-historical. The concept of non-positional self-consciousness plays a very important part in Sartres thought. See in this respect also note 326. Transcendence, pp. 1056. Ibid., p. 100. Ibid. Ibid. Ibid., pp. 1012. The phenomenologist will interrogate consciousness, the human reality about emotion. Emotions, p. 26. Ibid., p. 63. Ibid., p. 78. Ibid. Ibid., p. 80. See LImaginaire, p. 199, for instance. See note 146.

346

NOTES TO PAG E S 1 3 1 1 3 7

255. Transcendence, pp. 1045. 256. Even in the Itinerary of a thought, where Sartre is critical of the extreme form in which he stressed in some earlier works mans freedom and responsibility, he reasserts this fundamental idea in a somewhat different form: the idea which I have never ceased to develop is that in the end one is always responsible for what is made of one. Even if one can do nothing else besides assume this responsibility. For I believe that a man can always make something out of what is made of him. ed. cit., p.45. 257. Emotions, pp. 235. 258. M. Rubel criticizes me for not making any allusion to this Marxist materialism in the article I wrote in 1946, Materialism and Revolution. But he himself supplies the reason for this omission. It is true that this author is directing his comments at Engels rather than at Marx. Yes, and even more at contemporary French Marxists. (Method, p. 34; see also p. 104 of Method for Sartres critique of Engels.) 259. This is one of the principal themes of Method. 260. Itinerary of a thought, p. 46. 261. . . . cela [Sartres preoccupation to provide a philosophical foundation to realism] ma permis, plus tard, dassigner certaines limites au materialisme dialectiqueen validant la dialectique historique tout en rejetant une dialetique de la nature qui rduirait lhomme, comme toute chose, un simple produit des lois physiques. (Sartre par Sartre, Situations, IX, pp. 1045.) 262. See, for instance, Mary Warnock, The Philosophy of Sartre, Hutchinson, London, 1965, Chapter 6: The radical conversion, pp. 13581. 263. Method, p. 181. 264. Marx, Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844, translated by Martin Milligan, Lawrence & Wishart, London, 1959, p. 136. 265. LAnthropologie (1966), Situations, IX, p. 93. 266. Marx, Capital, translated by Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling, vol. 1, p. 486. 267. What is Literature? p. 157. 268. Both quotations Ibid., p. 159. 269. Emotions, p. 16. 270. Both quotations Ibid., p. 51. 271. Ibid., pp. 534. 272. . . . this language produces a mythology of the unconscious which I cannot accept. I am completely in agreement with the facts of disguise and repression, as facts. But the words repression, censorship, or drivewords which express one moment a sort of finalism and the next moment a sort of mechanism, these I reject. Let us take the example of condensation, for instance, which is an ambivalent term in Freud. One can interpret it simply as a phenomenon of association, in the same way as your English philosophers and psychologists of both the 18th and 19th centuries. Two images are

N OT E S TO PAG E S 138 1 49

347

273. 274. 275. 276. 277. 278. 279. 280.

281. 282. 283. 284.

285.

286.

drawn together externally, they condense and form a third: this is classical psychological atomism. But one can also interpret the term on the contrary as expressive of a finality. Condensation occurs because two images combined answer a desire, a need. This sort of ambiguity occurs again and again in Freud. The result is a strange representation of the unconscious as a set of rigorous mechanistic determinations, in any event a causality, and at the same time as a mysterious finality, such that there are ruses of the unconscious, as there are ruses of history; yet it is impossible to reunite the two in the work of many analysts. I think that there is always a fundamental ambiguity in them; the unconscious is one moment another consciousness, and the next moment other than consciousness. What is other than consciousness then becomes simply a mechanism. (Itinerary of a thought, pp. 467.) Simone de Beauvoir, The Prime of Life, p. 128. B & N, p. 626. Simone de Beauvoir, The Prime of Life, p. 134. Ibid., p. 135. To use a later expression whichlooking back upon the existential venture sums up well the meaning of Sartres early concern too. (Method, p. 9.) Ibid., p. 10. Ibid. It is a clear example of the internal tensions of Sartres philosophy that while on page 10 of the Method he admits that the existentialist thesis holds only to the degree to which knowledge remains powerless to transform being, on page 181 he reasserts in an unqualified form the separation of being from Knowledge and, without any evidence, claims that Marx, as opposed to later marxists, holds the same existentialist view. Numbers standing alone in brackets in this chapter refer to Being and Nothingness (B & N). LExistentialisme est un humanisme, Nagel, Paris, 1946, p. 62. Ibid., p. 63. Merleau-Ponty, in Situations, p. 161. Sartres text speaks of eidetics (eidetique) and not of an eidetic imagery. I modified the translation accordingly. The Writer and his Language (an interview with Pierre Verstraeten, 1965), in Sartre, Politics and Literature, translated by J.A. Underwood, Calder and Boyars, London, 1973, p. 112. . . . philosophy is a matter of borrowing and inventing concepts which progressively, through a kind of dialectic, bring us to a broader awareness of ourselves on the experiential level. Ultimately philosophy is always designed to cancel itself out. . . . What this amounts to is that philosophy must continually be destroying itself and being reborn. Philosophy is thought in so far as thought is invariably the dead moment of praxis since, by the time it occurs, praxis is already framed. To put it another way, philosophy comes after, while none the

348

NOTES TO PAG E S 1 4 9 1 5 1

less constantly looking forward. It must not allow itself to dispose of anything other than concepts, i.e. words. Yet even so what counts in philosophys favour is the fact that those words are not completely defined. The ambiguity of the philosophical word does after all offer something which can be used to go further. It can be used in order to mystify, as Heidegger often does, but it can also be used for the purposes of prospecting, as he uses it also. . . . Philosophy is concerned with the creator of the sciences and it cannot deal with him in scientific words; it can only deal with him in ambiguous words. The Writer and his Language, pp. 11011. 287. Ibid., p. 96. 288. This is true, of course, not only of Sartres Critique of Dialectical Reason, but of his later work in general. For instance, in The Writer and his Language he takes up an important theme from B & N, without referring to it explicitly. The issue concerns the existential significance of wish: for me the concrete universal must always imply a kind of self-awareness that is other than conceptual, a kind of self-awareness that is awareness of Wish, awareness of History. Take awareness of Wish, for example. As I see it, a wish necessarily utilizes the force of need, but whereas need is a simple requirementthe need to eat, and to eat no matter what so long as it is ediblewish is on the level of Epicurus titillation, i.e. I need to eat this rather than that. As soon as I want to eat this rather than that, the thing I want to eat inevitably refers me back to the universe. Because basically if I detest oysters but love lobster, or vice versa, it is always for a reason which goes beyond oyster or lobster themselves; there are certain relationships to life, relationships to whole hosts of things, which refer us back to ourselves at the same time as referring us back to the universe. (The Writer and his Language, p. 103) The statement that our taste refers us back to ourselves and to the universe is both monumentally vague and opaque. If we want to find out the meaning of the relationship hinted at, we have to go back to B & N which gives as examples even the same type of food: To eat is to appropriate by destruction; it is at the same time to be filled up with a certain being. In a word, this synthesis signifies a certain being; and when we eat, we do not limit ourselves to knowing certain qualities of this being through taste; by tasting them we appropriate them. . . . Certain tastes give themselves all at once, some are like delayed action fuses, some release themselves by degrees, certain ones dwindle slowly until they disappear, and still others vanish at the very moment one thinks to possess them. . . . We conclude that flavour . . . has a complex architecture and differentiated matter; it is this structured matterwhich represents for us a particular type of beingthat we can assimilate or reject with nausea, according to our original project. It is not a matter of indifference whether we like oysters or clams, snails or shrimps, if only we know how to unravel the existential significance of these foods. Generally speaking there is no irreducible taste or inclination. They all represent a certain appropriative

N OT E S TO PAG E S 152 1 58

349

289. 290. 291.

292.

choice of being. It is up to existential psychoanalysis to compare and classify them. Ontology abandons us here; it has merely enabled us to determine the ultimate end of human reality, its fundamental possibilities, and the value which haunts it. (6145) As we can see the suggestion that our preference for certain types of food refers us back to ourselves and to the universe does not represent any advance on B & N. Indeed it may be argued that while in the context of Sartres existentialist theory of a symbolic appropriation of being the problem can be discussed with a high degree of suggestive particularization which aims at establishing the existentially significant identity of particular instances of action and the appropriation of being, the later work suffers from the vagueness of simply referring the issue to the poles of individuality (ourselves) and universality (the universe). Sartres greater social awareness after the war brings with it a new problem, but not necessarily its solution. For while the original formulation in B & N bypasses the problem of mediation by stipulating a direct relationship of identity between the particular examples of appropriative behaviour and the universality of a symbolic appropriation of being (there is no irreducible taste or inclination), the later work, by shifting its frame of reference in the direction of a greater social concretization, imposes upon itself the burden of providing the categories of an adequate social mediation between particularity and universality. The vagueness could be removed only by filling the rather forbidding gap between ourselves and the universe through a well defined social mediation. See in this respect section 2 of the previous chapter: In Search of the Individual: The Early Works. These expressions refer essentially to the same thing. Again we can note both the similarities with and the differences from Kant. Just as in Kant ought implies can, in Sartre the force of circumstance is never allowed to challenge the existentialist demand for authenticity. At the same time, the fact that Sartres frame of reference is existential-ontological, and not transcendental, significantly modifies the function of ought in his system. The Sartrean ought is subsumed under the general demand for authenticity which in its turn is spelled out in direct opposition to the various existing systems of value, including of course all forms of religious axiology. However, this is a much more complex problem than it would appear at first sight. See in this respect also note 312. Notice the ambiguity of syntax in this sentence, which is just as evident in the French original as in the translation: La causalit premire, cest la saisie de lapparu avant quil apparaisse, comme tant dj l dans son propre nant pour prparer son apparition. (259) The appeared is said to be already there in its own nothingness before it appears so as to prepare its (?) apparition. If it is the appeared which prepares its apparition, then it must really prepare its own apparition. The ambiguity of syntax, coupled

350

NOTES TO PAG E S 1 6 1 1 6 3

293. 294.

295.

296.

297.

with the vaguely undefined character of prepares, radically exclude any deterministic reading. This is why the appeared must first exist in the mode of its own nothingness which in its turn is called upon to prepare its own apparition as actually appeared. Such a conception of causality (as the apprehension of the preparatory, but of course not determining, function of nothingness in the apparition of the appeared) brings with it a few pages later a definition of motion as the least being of a being which can neither arrive, nor be abolished nor wholly be.(213) See the chapter on Sartres conception of the formal structures of history in Part Three. The discussion of this important issue regarding Sartres use of metaphors is far too long to be included here in a footnote. For this reason the reader can find it at the end of this chapter, under the title : A Note on Being and Nothingness. There is a great deal of uneasiness even in the inspired 1965 interview on The Writer and his Language in Sartres discussion of the relationship between philosophy and literary prose. After condemning the use of a literary turn of phrase in a philosophical work as a breach of trust in the name of strictly philosophical terms (p. 96), he goes on to contrast philosophy and prose like this: literary prose seems to me to be the still immediate, not yet selfaware, totality, and philosophy ought to be powered by the ambition to attain that awareness while disposing only of concepts. (p. 108) Yet a few pages later, in the context of dismissing Husserls idea of philosophy as a rigorous science by calling it the idea of a madman genius, but a mad idea none the less, he not only exalts ambiguity but also the literary element by saying that philosophy always contains concealed literary prose. (p. 122) And when towards the end of the interview Pierre Verstraeten tries to pin him down on some specific points, he produces some curious answers: I dont believe I ever used the word will without giving it inverted commasthat is to say theoretical inverted commas, invisible ones. (p. 122) And again: I write in so many different languages that things pass from one to another; I write the language of prose, I write the language of philosophy, I write the language of theatre, and so on. (p. 123) The latter is very true, but of course it cannot constitute an answer to the question of relationship between philosophical language and literary prose. To believe is to know that one believes, and to know that one believes is no longer to believe. Thus to believe is not to believe any longer because that is only to believethis is the unity of one and the same non-thetic self-consciousness. To be sure, we have here forced the description of the phenomenon by designating it with the word to know; non-thetic consciousness is not to know. But it is in its very translucency at the very origin of all knowing. Thus the non-thetic consciousness (of) believing is destructive of belief. (p. 69) bergreifendes Momentthe moment of overriding importance.

N OT E S TO PAG E S 164 1 76

351

298. Emotions, pp. 5961. 299. Interview by Jacques-Alain Miller, Les Cahiers Libres de la Jeunesse, 15 February 1960. 300. On page XLII of B & N Sartre insists that Necessity concerns the connection between ideal propositions, and on pages 46970 he writes that the connection between the derived possible (to resist fatigue or to give in to it) and the fundamental possible is not a connection of deducibility. It is the connection between a totality and a partial structure. The view of the total project enables one to understand the particular structure considered. But the Gestalt School has shown us that the Prgnanz of the total forms does not exclude the variability of certain secondary structures. There are certain lines which I can add or subtract from a given figure without altering its specific character. There are others, on the contrary, which cannot be added without involving the immediate disappearance of the figure and the appearance of another figure. The same thing is true with regard to the relation between the secondary possibles and the fundamental possible or the formal totality of my possibles. 301. Indeed, this hermeneutic of existence is envisaged as the sufficient foundation for an anthropology. (Emotions, pp. 245): a recurrent theme of Sartres philosophy, from the early works to his Critique of Dialectical Reason. 302. In the same way, the concept of seriality in the Critique of Dialectical Reason is not derived from the graphic situation of the bus queue; on the contrary, it produces the latter and other similar examples. 303. The idea that an organic totality transforms itself into inert matter, in accordance with the objective requirements of its location, so as to be able to function in its material environment, is an important theme in Sartres discussion of Need in his Critique of Dialectical Reason. A related idea is Sartres definition of analytical thought as thought that renders itself inert so as to be competent to deal with the inert. The Writer and his Language, p. 119. 304. Glissez, mortels, nappuyez pas. See also Sartre, Words, Penguin edition, p. 178. 305. Letter to Simone de Beauvoir, 6 January 1940, published in Magazine Littraire, No. 103104, September 1975, p. 24. 306. Sartre himself never paid much attention to such considerations (see, for instance, his encounter with Husserls thought), and it would be quite wrong to use the measure of scholarly accuracy in evaluating his work. Sartres references to other thinkers are always strictly subordinate to his own immediate concerns, and major shifts in evaluation (from an essentially negative to a highly positive and then again back to an almost completely negative assessment of Marx, for instance) are likewise the result of his changing preoccupations. Consequently our attitude toward Sartres work must hinge on the validity of his concerns inasmuch as they can be sustained

352

NOTES TO PAG E S 1 7 6 1 8 1

307. 308.

309.

310.

311.

312.

on their own ground, and should not be clouded over by our disagreement with his highly self-oriented interpretations of other thinkers. See, for instance, Klaus Hartmann, Sartres Ontology, Northwestern University Press, Evanston, 1966. There is a fairly common tendency to seek to identify free acts with voluntary acts and to restrict the deterministic explanation to the world of the passions. In short the point of view of Descartes. The Cartesian will is free, but there are passions of the soul. Again, Descartes will attempt a physiological interpretation of these passions. (441) It is not by chance that materialism is serious; it is not by chance that it is found at all times and places as the favourite doctrine of the revolutionary. This is because revolutionaries are serious. They come to know themselves first in terms of the world which oppresses them, and they wish to change this world. . . . Marx proposed the original dogma of the serious when he asserted the priority of object over subject. Man is serious when he takes himself for an object. (580) Here we can see a good example of the problem mentioned in note 306. Marx proposed nothing of the kind here attributed to him by Sartre whose strictures apply to the worst kind of vulgarization of Marxism. However, this crude distortion of Marxs thought does not affect the validity of Sartres idea that man is serious when he takes himself for an object. In contrast to Descartes physiological determinism, Later there will be an attempt to instate a purely psychological determinism. Intellectualistic analyses such as Proust, for example, attempts with respect to jealousy or snobbery can serve as illustrations for this concept of the passional mechanism. In this case it would be necessary to conceive of man as simultaneously free and determined, and the essential problem would be that of the relations between this unconditioned freedom and the determined processes of the psychic life: how will it master the passions, how will it utilize them for its own benefit. (441) Sartres Critique of Dialectical Reason is very different indeed in this respect, as we shall see in Part Three. However, no one should conclude that for this reason Critique of Dialectical Reason is a less important work. In point of fact, religious references in B & N are numerous, and none of them could be described as nihilistic. On the contrary, Sartre is anxious to account for the meaning of many religious categoriesfrom sin and original sin to pride, shame, fall from grace, ideal being, passion of Christ, etc. in terms of his own discourse, instead of just dismissing them, as a nihilist would. Notwithstanding his severe critical references to religious axiology as the loss and sacrifice of the human reality in the interest of the ens causa sui, the religious problematic constitutes a vitally important element in Sartres reasoning in Marxs sense, according to which the negation of the negation (i.e. the negation of religion as a negation and alienation of man) remains inextricably intertwined with and necessarily dependent on what

N OT E S TO PAG E S 181 1 87

353

313.

314.

315.

316.

317. 318.

it negates, in that it is unable to define the human reality in positive, selfsustaining terms. Again, this position should not be confused with nihilism. For Sartre goes on to say that this indifference does not mean that we cannot radically escape bad faith. But this supposes a self-recovery of being which was previously corrupted. This self-recovery we shall call authenticity, the description of which has no place here. (70) The difficulty with Sartres position is that since he has established the ontological primacy of bad faith over good faith, he cannot attempt a positive description of good faith and authenticity without the danger of falling into bad faith. Thus coming to grips with authenticity and good faith, in an ethics of deliverance and salvation, remains the elusive promise of some other work. the situation, the common product of the contingency of the In-itself and of freedom, is an ambiguous phenomenon in which it is impossible for the For-itself to distinguish the contribution of freedom from that of the brute existent. In fact, just as freedom is the escape from a contingency which it has to be in order to escape it, so the situation is the free coordination and the free qualification of a brute given which does not allow itself to be qualified in any way at all. (488) See also pages 4837 and 509 of B & N. . . . the fact of not being able not to be free is the facticity of freedom, and the fact of not being able not to exist is its contingency. Contingency and facticity are really one; there is a being which freedom has to be in the form of nonbeing (that is, of nihilation). To exist as the fact of freedom or to have to be a being in the midst of the world are one and the same thing, and this means that freedom is originally a relation to the given. (486) Also called unreflective consciousness, non-thetic consciousness and pre-reflective cogito. As we have seen in note 296, though this non-thetic consciousness does not give us knowledge, it is in its very translucency at the origin of all knowing. See in this respect the quotation in note 300. The past which I am, I have to be with no possibility of not being it. I assume the total responsibility for it as if I could change it, and yet I cannot be anything other than it. (116) we must proceed from this antinomy: human reality originally receives its place in the midst of things; human reality is that by which something we call place comes to things. (490) I exist my place without choice, without necessity either, as the pure absolute fact of my being-there. I am there, not here but there. This is the absolute and incomprehensible fact which is at the origin of extension and consequently of my original relations with things (with these things rather than with those). A fact of pure contingencyan absurd fact. (491) facticity is the only reality which freedom can discover . . . freedom is the apprehension of my facticity. (494) To be sure, in being born I take place, but I am responsible for the place which I take. We can see clearly here the inextricable connection of freedom

354

NOTES TO PAG E S 1 8 7 1 9 3

319.

320. 321.

322.

323.

and facticity in the situation. (495) the irremediable quality of the past comes from the actual choice of the future; . . . while freedom is the choice of an end in terms of the past, conversely the past is what it is only in relation to the end chosen. (499) A living past, a half-dead past, survivals, ambiguities, discrepancies: the ensemble of these layers of pastness is organized by the unity of my project. (500) That we choose our past in the light of a certain end, but from then on it imposes itself upon us and devours us. (503) Thus like place, the past is integrated with the situation when the For-itself by its choice of the future confers on its past facticity a value, an hierarchical order, and an urgency in terms of which this facticity motivates the act and the conduct of the For-itself. (504) Sartre is by no means embarrassed by the circularity involved. He asserts that it is in the nature of consciousness to exist in a circle, (XXIX) and in another context he defines the world as a synthetic complex of instrumental realities inasmuch as they point one to another in ever widening circles. (17) Similarly, the relations with the Other are characterized by the circle, (408) and Sartre reiterates again and again that we can never get out of the circle. (See for instance p. 412) See for instance Itinerary of a thought, New Left Review, 58, NovemberDecember 1969. Coefficient of adversitya term adopted from Gaston Bachelards LEau et les rves, ed. Jos Corti, Paris, 1942. It stands for the resistance of things or objects vis--vis human projects. In LExistentialisme est un humanisme Sartre writes that if one day men decided to establish fascism and other men were coward and crippled enough to let them do it, from that moment fascism would be the human truth, and all the worse for us. (pp.534) Despite the fact that Sartres own position is clearly visible as opposed to fascism, the underlying principle is extremely problematical. It is very similar to Bertrand Russells paradoxical predicament toward the end of his life. For having spent the greater part of his life totally relativizing value judgements as a form of emotionalism, he found his own commitment to nuclear disarmament and to many other worthy causes totally unsustainable in terms of his own philosophy. The question of a major conversion is realistically formulated in some particular contexts. For instance, when Sartre writes: There is no doubt that I could have done otherwise, but that is not the problem. It ought to be formulated rather like this: could I have done otherwise without perceptibly modifying the organic totality of the project which I am? . . . at what price? (456) And later on, writing about yielding to fatigue, he makes the point that This does not imply that I must necessarily stop but merely that I can refuse to stop only by a radical conversion of my being-in-the-world; that is, by an abrupt metamorphosis of my initial projecti.e. by another choice of myself and of my ends. Moreover, this modification is always possible. (464) This

N OT E S TO PAG E S 194 2 01

355

324.

325. 326. 327. 328.

329.

330.

is all very clear and feasible, in that the radical conversion in question only implies switching from one set of personal policies and strategies to another while many of the particular projects can belong to both, in accordance with the principle of Prgnanz which defines the relationship between the secondary possibles and the fundamental possible. However, there is a world of difference between this kind of radical conversion and the one merely postulated in the apocalyptic footnote on the ethics of salvation. Sartre quite openly acknowledged his own anarchistic libertarianism in some interviews. Simone de Beauvoirs description of their experience in a caf in Rouen (see note 275) when they decided that the proletarian struggle was not their struggle, is highly relevant in this respect, though of course the roots of such a decision go much further back in the past. In B & N Sartre attributes anarchism to the bourgeoisie: the weakness of the oppressing class lies in the fact that although it has at its disposal precise and rigorous means for coercion, it is within itself profoundly anarchistic. The bourgeois is . . . a consciousness which does not recognize its belonging to a class. (428) See for instance Sartres ontological proof on page XXXVII of B & N. In this respect see my essay on Marxs relation to philosophy in my book on Philosophy, Ideology and Social Science, Harvester/Wheatsheaf, 1986. Situations, I, p. 32. The same epistemological optimism is in evidence in The Transcendence of the Ego. By contrast now the crowd becomes a monstrous materiality and the helpless individual is depicted as submerged in the crowd-instrument by the look of the leader. (422) In his essay on Sartres existentialism Marcuse writes: It was said in a note in Ltre et le Nant that a morality of liberation and deliverance was possible, but that it would require a radical conversion. Sartres writings and the stands he has taken over the last two decades are a conversion of this kind. (Studies in Critical Philosophy, NLB, London, 1972, p. 189) This may be true of Sartre personally, but such a personal conversion (if we may describe Sartres development in those terms) does not resolve the contradiction between the postulated ethics of deliverance and salvation, and the ontological structure of being as articulated in B & N. The fact that the myth of Medusa (430) is turned the other way round in order to fit the theory (for in the original it is not the mythical Others look at me which causes my petrification but my own forbidden look at Medusa) need not worry us unduly. Much more important is the general use to which the claimed symbolic relations are put. Ultimately they all hinge on the question of appropriation: on Sartres individualism preventing him from conceiving appropriation in other than symbolic terms since a full appropriation in relation to the isolated individual is clearly inconceivable. This position is mythically projected into a past which precedes the division of labour, and there we meet Sartres existentialist version of the Robinsonade which is

356

NOTES TO PAG E S 2 0 3 2 0 7

331. 332. 333. 334. 335. 336.

337.

338.

designed to bring production in line with appropriation as individualistic, and as such ontologically fundamental. We are presented with a fictitious armchair anthropology, in the name of an ontological description of the fundamental relations, and we end up with a perverse conclusion which identifies luxury as closest to original ownership: originally it is I who make myself the object which I want to possess. My bow and arrows [Friday comes later] . . . Division of labour can dim this original relation but cannot make it disappear. Luxury is a degradation of it; in the primitive form of luxury I possess an object which I have had made (done) for myself by people belonging to me (slaves, servants born in the home). Luxury therefore is the form of ownership closest to primitive ownership. (589) See Marxs discussion of these problems in The German Ideology, especially pages 8486. Ibid., especially pages 78, 86, 87, 88. This perpetual Third should not be confused with the absolute Third, nor with the neutral Third. (429) See Marxs discussion of the class for-itself in his Introduction to the Critique of the Hegelian Philosophy of Right. See my essay on Contingent and necessary class consciousness, in Aspects of History and Class Consciousness, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 1971. See Marxs discussion of generations of men inheriting determinate conditions of existence and proceeding from there toward their transformation, in The Poverty of Philosophy, 1847 In B & N Sartre is very critical of Paul Bourgets Essai de Psychologie Contemporaine: G. Flaubert, saying that such a psychological analysis proceeds from the postulate that an individual fact is produced by the intersection of abstract, universal laws. The fact to be explainedwhich is here the literary disposition of young Flaubertis resolved into a combination of typical, abstract desires such as we meet in the average adolescent. What is concrete here is only their combination; in themselves they are only possible patterns. The abstract then is by hypothesis prior to the concrete, and the concrete is only an organization of abstract qualities: the individual is only the intersection of universal schemata. Butaside from the logical absurdity of such a postulate we see clearly in the example chosen, that it simply fails to explain what makes the individuality of the project under consideration. . . . In addition this method rejects the pure individual who has been banished from the pure subjectivity of Flaubert into the external circumstances of his life. (5589) Later he addresses the same criticism to Marxism in general. In my book on Flaubert, I am studying imaginary personspeople who like Flaubert act out roles. A man is like a leak of gas, escaping into the imaginary. Flaubert did so perpetually; . . . Writing on Flaubert is enough for me by way of fictionit might indeed be called a novel. Only I would like people to say that it was a true novel. I try to achieve a certain level of comprehension of

N OT E S TO PAG E S 207 2 25

357

Flaubert by means of hypotheses. Thus I use fictionguided and controlled, but nonetheless fictionto explore why, let us say, Flaubert wrote one thing on the 15th March and the exact opposite on the 21st March, to the same correspondent, without worrying about the contradiction. My hypotheses are in this sense a sort of invention of the personage. (Itinerary of a thought, loc. Cit., pages 53 and 55.) Many years earlier, in Nausea, very similar ideas are put forward by Roquentin in his reflections on the problems of a biography which he plans to write about Rollebon: Well, yes: he may have done all that, but there is no proof that he did: I am beginning to believe that nothing can ever be proved. These are reasonable hypotheses which take the fact into account: but I am only too well aware that they come from me, that they are simply a way of unifying my knowledge. Not a single glimmer comes from Rollebons direction. Slow, lazy, sulky, the facts adapt themselves at a pinch to the order I wish to give them, but it remains outside of them. I have the impression of doing a work of pure imagination. And even so, I am certain that characters in a novel would appear more realistic. (p.26) 339. This project is spelled out in a fairly detailed form in B & N, (55962) in the context of existential psychoanalysis. And Sartre concludes: This psychoanalysis has not yet found its Freud. At most we can find the foreshadowing of it in certain particularly successful biographies. We hope to be able to attempt elsewhere two examples in relation to Flaubert and Dostoevsky. (575) 340. In this sense the particularization is in fact the most abstract of all possible generalizations since it aims at establishing a symbolic relationship of identity between the incomparably unique and the ontological absolute, a priori excluding all categories of social mediation which belong to the sphere of the strictly psychological experience of historic man immersed in a working universe of alienated objectification on the surface of being. 341. Anybody who can lump together Marx, Halbwachs and de Manas Sartre does in B & N, (513) in the name of an alleged inferiority complex demonstrates a singular incomprehension of Marx. Likewise in his description of Marx as the originator of the dogma of seriousness mentioned above.

PA RT THRE E
1. Itinerary of a thought, p. 44. Sartre wanted to do much more. He tried to establish contact with the Communist resistance movement, for the purpose of taking part in it, but the party spread around him the rumor that he was an agent provocateur. This may have been due to his close friendship (in fact since childhood) with Paul Nizan, who resigned from the French CP in protest against the Molotov-Ribbentrop Pact between Germany and Stalins Russia in 1939. Nizan was killed at the front, in May 1940, and Sartre passionately defended him in 1947 against slander voiced by the communists. Sartre also

358

NOTES TO PAG E S 2 2 5 2 3 1

2. 3. 4. 5. 6.

7. 8. 9. 10. 11. 12. 13.

14. 15. 16. 17. 18.

19.

wrote a moving introduction in 1960 to Nizans republished volume of essays entitled Aden Arabie. The Rassemblement Dmocratique Rvolutionnaire. See note 3 in Part One. Condemned in such terms by Fadeev. See note No. 4 in Part One. I can fully recommend reading Staughton Lynds article which deliberately addresses itself to one of the most controversial aspects of this complex of problems. It was published in Monthly Review (February 2011, pp. 4353) under the title: Is There Anything More to Say About the Rosenberg Case? Sartres powerful condemnation of the Rosenbergs executionentitled Les Animaux malades de la ragewas first published in Libration, 22 June 1953, and subsequently in many other places. It is now easily accessible on pages 704708 of the Contat/Rybalka volume. See Sartres interview referred to in note 154 of Part One. See Sartres interview on Masses, Spontaneity, Party given in August 1969 to the Italian Il Manifesto group to which we must return in Chapter 9. Sartre, Le rformisme et les ftiches, Les Temps Modernes, No. 122, February 1956, pp. 1153-64. Ibid., p. 1155. Ibid. Le Fantme de Stalin, Les Temps Modernes, Numbers 129130131, NovemberDecember 1956, January 1957, pp. 577697. See C/R, p. 309. Questions de mthode, Les Temps Modernes, No. 139, September 1957, pp. 338417, No. 140, October 1957, pp. 658698. This Problem of Method was later incorporated into the original French edition of Sartres Critique of Dialectical Reason by Gallimard in Paris in 1960. See notes 235240 attached to Chapter 4 of Part One. See Henri Lefbvre, Existentialisme et marxisme: rponse une mise au point, Action, 8 June 1945 See C/R p. 311. Quoted in Lukcs Gyrgy politikai vgrendelete (Gyrgy Lukcss political testament), Trsadalmi Szemle, April 1990, p. 84. The reader can find in note 223 attached to Part Two of my book: Beyond Capital the report on how this public break happened under the conditions of their detention in Rumania. It was communicated to me in December 1990 by someone who was an eyewitness to Lukcss public break with Zoltn Sznt. This eyewitness was Mikls Vsrhelyi, one of Imre Nagys best friends and closest political advisers, who had to spend several years in prison after Prime Minister Nagys execution on the order of the Soviet Authorities. I saw on his desk neatly laid out a dozen or so beautifully hand-written pages of one of the early chapters of his Critique of Dialectical Reason which he was working on at the time.

N OT E S TO PAG E S 231 2 35

359

20.

21. 22.

23.

24. 25.

26.

27. 28. 29. 30. 31.

32. 33. 34. 35.

In contrast to their past disagreements, Sartre and Lukcs had a very friendly encounter in Helsinki in June 1955. As we have seen in a passage referred to in note 174 of Part Two above, Sartre wrote about Lukcs in the highest terms of praise in his article on Le Rformisme et les ftiches, published in Les Temps Modernes in February 1956. My letter to Lukcs from Paris was posted to him on 29 November 1957. It is in the Lukcs Archive in Budapest. We conversed also about this book and the motivation as well as the circumstances of its writing. For Die Gegenwartsbedeutung des kritischen Realismus was in part written during Lukcss deportation to Rumania. The English translation of the book was published by The Merlin Press, London, in 1962, under the title: The Meaning of Contemporary Realism. The fully accurateby Lukcs programmatically chosenEnglish title of this book should have been: The Contemporary Significance of Critical Realism. Evidently, such an ongoing working relationship with Sartre would have been also a great political support to Lukcs under the conditions of the sharp attacks which he had to endure in that period. This was an important part of my concerns. Lukcs, Letter to Istvn Mszros, 23 February 1958. This defense of History and Class Consciousness against the dogmatic attacks by Lszl Rudas and Abram Deborin was written by Lukcs in Vienna, and its title is Chvostismus und Dialektik (in English Tailism/Suivism and Dialectic). The text resurfaced from a Russian Archive of the Comintern only seventy years later, in the mid 1990s. First published, with a brief Preface by Sartre, in 1947, by ditions Myrte, Paris. It was republished in a much more popular form by ditions du Seuil, Paris, in 1965. ditions de Minuit, Paris, 1958. See Sartre, Il faut rtablir la justice, interview by G. A. Astre, Action, 24 January 1952. See Sartres Introduction to the book LAffair Henri Martin, published by Gallimard in Paris, in 1953. See Sartres article: M. Pinay prpare le chemin dune dictature, Libration, 16 October 1952. See in this respect the article: Jean-Paul Sartre ouvre un dialogue, in Peuple du Monde, No. 11, 1819 June 1949. Peuple du Monde was a monthly supplement of the journal Combat, edited by Camus. Claude Lefort was a close friend and political soulmate of Merleau-Ponty. The first article was published in Les Temps Modernes in July 1952. Sartre, The Communists and Peace: With an Answer to Claude Lefort, Hamish Hamilton, London, 1969, pp. 11819. Translated by Irene Clephane. See chapter 5 of Merleau-Pontys book, Les Aventures de la dialectique, published by Gallimard, Paris, in the spring of 1955, and in English by

360

NOTES TO PAG E S 2 3 6 2 4 3

36. 37.

38. 39. 40. 41.

42. 43.

44.

45. 46. 47.

48. 49.

50.

Heinemann, London, in 1973. Sartres break with Raymond Aron was of an earlier date, on the ground of Arons enthusiastic support for the Atlanticist perspective and of his subservience to American political and military domination. See my discussion of Merleau-Ponty and the League of Abandoned Hope in my book: The Power of Ideology. The illusions attached to the hoped for but never realized political success of the R.D.R. were projecting precisely an electoral umbrella formation made up from such an agglomeration of isolated individuals, which was of course expected to include, utterly in vain, a great number of French working class people. Sartre, Notebooks for an Ethics, translated by David Pellauer, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London, 1992, p. 472. Sartre, La bombe H, une arme contre lhistoire, Dfense de la Paix, July 1954. Sartre, interviewed by Benny Lvy, Le Nouvel Observateur, March 1980. In fact in an interview given to Madeleine Chapsal in 1959 Sartre optimistically asserted that The first volume will be published within a month, and the second within a year. See The Purposes of writing, in Jean-Paul Sartre, Between Existentialism and Marxism, NLB, London, 1974, p. 9. Jean-Paul Sartre, Critique of Dialectical Reason. Theory of Practical Ensembles, NLB, London, 1976, pp. 6971. Sartres emphases. We must recall that Sartres Critique of Dialectical Reason was conceived and written in the aftermath of some major upheavals in Eastern Europe, particularly in Poland and Hungary. See my detailed analysis of Sartres overall trajectory as a great intellectual of the twentieth century in Parts One and Two of my book: The work of Sartre: Search for Freedom, first published by The Harvester Press, Brighton, 1979. Sartre, Critique, NLB edition, p. 36. Sartres emphases. Sartre, Itinerary of a thought, New Left Review, November-December 1969, pp. 5859. Sartre actually admitted in the 1969 interview that in his most detailed interpretation and reconstruction of Flauberts life, running into several thousands of pages, he had to inventas if he was writing a novelthe person at the centre of his monumental enquiry. Istvn Mszros, The Work of Sartre: Search for Freedom, pp. 8687. As he had put it in the first volume of the Critique: I regard Marxism as the untranscendable philosophy for our time, and I believe that the ideology of existence, along with its comprehensive method, is an enclave within Marxism itself, both produced and rejected by Marxism. p. 822. See his interview by Michel Contat: Self-Portrait at Seventy, first published in Le Nouvel Observateur, June and July 1975. In English reproduced in the volume: Jean-Paul Sartre, Sartre in the Seventies: Interviews and Essays, Andre Deutsch Ltd., London, 1978. See in particular page 60 of this volume.

N OT E S TO PAG E S 243 2 50

361

51. 52.

53. 54. 55. 56. 57. 58. 59.

60. 61. 62. 63.

64. 65. 66.

67.

See pages 5961 of the same book. Although, primarily for political reasons, he tried to qualify in this work the retained elements of the existentialist ontological orientation as an ideological enclave only, the truth of the matter is that it was incomparably more decisive than just an enclave. Sartre, Critique, p. 125. Ibid., p. 36. Ibid., pp. 1312. Calling himself marxisant at the time was Sartre himself. Sartre, Critique, p. 133. On the historical problem of antagonistic second order mediations see especially Section 8.6 of my book on The Social Determination of Method. The perilous implication of certain types of transformations, under the irrational and destructive imperatives of uncontrollable capital-accumulation, is not that they modify the relationship of human beings to naturewhich is characteristic of the whole of human historybut that they do it in a most inappropriate, simultaneously destructive and self-destructive way. Sartre, Critique, p. 132. Sartre, Critique, p. 125. We must return to the intricate problems of scarcity later in this chapter and more extensively in chapter 8. Toward the end of Sartres most revealing and moving interview conducted by Michel Contat in 1975, the interviewer puts to him that In general, your political statements are optimistic, even though in private you are very pessimistic. This is how Sartre responds to Contats observation: Yes, I am. . . . If I am not completely pessimistic it is primarily because I see in myself certain needs which are not only mine but the needs of every man. To express it another way, it is the experienced certainty of my own freedom . . . But it is true that either man crumblesand then all one could say is that during the twenty thousand years in which there have been men, a few of them tried to create man and failedor else this revolution succeeds and creates man by bringing about freedom. Nothing is less sure. . . . It is impossible to find a rational basis for revolutionary optimism, since what is is the present reality. And how can we lay the foundations for the future reality? Nothing allows me to do it. See pages 8385 of the interview quoted in note 10 of this chapter. Freedom must revolt against forms of alienation, Ibid., p. 88. Sartre, Critique, p. 131. In English it is published in, and quoted from, the volume: Jean-Paul Sartre, Sartre in the Seventies: Interviews and Essays, Andre Deutsch Ltd., London, 1978, pp.198210. As Sartre himself expressed this in his interview conducted by Michel Contat: This was the period in which I broke with the Communists after

362

NOTES TO PAG E S 2 5 0 2 5 4

68.

69. 70. 71. 72.

73. 74. 75. 76.

77. 78. 79. 80.

Budapest. . . . Writing the Critique of Dialectical Reason represented for me a way of settling my account with my own thought beyond the Communist Partys sphere of influence over thought. Sartre in the Seventies, p. 18. The analysis of the nature and contradictions of the Soviet type post-capitalist experience under Stalin is attempted by Sartre in the second volume of the Critique in the same formal categorial framework. This is why Sartres long descriptions of the chosen particular political events and conflicts tend to go around in circles, repeating at every new turn the same generic assertions about the used formal structures. This is, above all, what denies him the possibility of bringing to the fore in the necessary categorial terms the underlying material structural determinations which would encapsulate the salient characteristics of the historical totalization that must prevail under the circumstances of the post-capitalist capital system, in view of the pursued modality of social metabolic reproduction oriented toward, and likewise constrained by, the politically enforced extraction of surplus labor, in sharp contrast to its primarily economic extraction in the form of surplus value asserting itself even under the greater part of the monopolistic phase of capitalism. Until, that is, hybridization, with direct political involvement and massive financial support provided by the state out of general taxation for the military/industrial complex and for rescuing private capitalist enterprise from ever-escalating bankruptcy begins to create some major, and potentially insuperable, complications. Sartre in the Seventies, pp. 2012. Ibid., p. 203. Ibid., p. 210. Jean-Paul Sartre, Masses, Spontaneity, Party, The Socialist Register, 1970, p. 245. Originally published as Classe e partito. Il rischio della spontaneit, la logica dellistituzione, Il Manifesto, No. 4, September 1969. Page 204 of Sartre in the Seventies. Lide neuve de mai 1968, observations reported by Serge Lafaurie, Le Nouvel Observateur, 26 June2 July 1968. We should recall in this respect his answer given to Michel Contat quoted in note No. 23 above. See on this issue several chapters of my book on Social Structure and Forms of Consciousness, especially Chapters 3, 7, and 8 of volume one: The Social Determination of Method. That is, the relatively shortlived French political movement calling itself Revolutionary Democratic Assembly. See Revolutionary democrats, Sartres interview by Mary Burnet, New York Herald Tribune, 2 June 1948. Sartre, Le R.D.R. et le problme de la libert, La Pense socialiste, No. 19, Spring 1948, p. 5. Rousseau, The Social Contract, Everyman edition, p. 78.

N OT E S TO PAG E S 254 2 59

363

81.

82.

83. 84.

85. 86. 87. 88.

He writes in 1972: Even though I have always protested against the bourgeoisie, my works are addressed to it, are written in its language . . . Now, we must say that this work [on Flaubert], assuming that it has some value, by its very nature represents the age-old bourgeois swindle of the people. The book ties me to bourgeois readers. Through it, I am still bourgeois and will remain so as long as I continue to work on it. However, another side of myself, which rejects my ideological interests, is fighting against my identity as a classic intellectual. Sartre in the Seventies, p. 185. As we have seen earlier, the necessary critique of capitalshistorically specificantagonistic second order mediations is absent from Sartres lifework. This is due to a large extent to his concern to give an existentialist ontological underpinning to some of the key categories adopted also in his marxisant existentialist phase of development. Sartre, Critique, p. 35. In the eternalizing ideology of the established mode of production the necessary historical limitations of the capital system are denied already at the classical phase of political economy (and philosophy) conceived from capitals standpoint, and of course in the most blatant way in the descending phase of capitalist development. Yet the uncomfortable truth is that in all human history prior to the unfolding of capitals mode of societal reproduction there never existed a mode of production which could not function at all without imposing, at whatever cost, its imperative of unlimitable expansion. Naturally, this unique historical condition carries the gravest implications for the future. Sartre in the Seventies, p. 85. Marcuse, Freedom and the Historical Alternative, in Herbert Marcuse, Studies in Critical Philosophy, N.L.B., London, 1972, p. 223. Sartre, The Maoists in France, Sartre in the Seventies, p. 171. Already in his optimistic phase Marcuse is trying to model his vision on Kantian ideas in the form of the work of a supra-individual historical Subjectivity in the individualjust as the Kantian categories are the syntheses of a transcendental Ego in the empirical Ego. (Op. cit. in note No. 46, p. 217.) And he adds a few lines further on: Kants transcendental construction of experience may well furnish the model for the historical construction of experience. (Ibid., p. 218.) However, in Marcuses final years pessimism becomes overwhelming. We are told by him that The world is not made for man, and it has not become more human. (Marcuse, Die Permanenz der Kunst, Carl Hanser Verlag, Mnchen, 1977, p. 53.) In this sense Marcuse presents the bleakest possible picture by saying that in reality evil triumphs, leaving to the individual nothing but the islands of good to which one can escape for short periods of time. (Ibid.) Accordingly, Kant reappears in this totally pessimistic vision, quoted to sustain Marcuses explicitly desperate hope attached to art as a regulative idea [Kant] in the struggle in despair for the transformation of the world. (Ibid., p.74.)

364

NOTES TO PAG E S 2 5 9 2 6 0

89.

90. 91.

92.

93. 94.

In his optimistic years Marcuse insisted that the utopian possibilities which he advocated and whose success he projected without a sustainable social analysis, were inherent in the technical and technological forces of advanced capitalism on the basis of which one could terminate poverty and scarcity within a very foreseeable future. (Marcuse, An Essay on Liberation, Allen Lane/The Penguin Press, London, 1960, p. 4.) He also told his readers that this qualitative change must occur in the needs, in the infrastructure of man (Ibid.), altering people to the point that the stipulated moral ought of the rebellion would then have taken root in the very nature, the biology of the individual (Ibid., p. 5.), establishing in the organism itself the institutional basis for freedom (Ibid., p. 10.) and the biological need for freedom. (Ibid., p. 52.) These hopes and expectations, as we can see, directly linked an overgenerous belief in the technical and technological transformatory power of advanced capitalism with the wishful postulate of the biological need for freedom. Marcuses disappointment, therefore, had to be quite devastating after the failure of his expectations. One should not forget the immense brutality of primitive accumulation under Henry VIII. and other great rulers in the early stages of capitalist development, whose unspeakable inhumanity induced Thomas More to say in his Utopia (1516) that sheep are eating men in the interest of the unfolding profitable enterprise of wool production. Sartre in the Seventies, p. 203. To use Max Webers capital-apologetic terms. On this issue see Section 2.7 (Formal Rationality and Substantive Irrationality) in my book, The Social Determination of Method. See p. 628 of Being and Nothingness, Methuen & Co., London, 1958. The fragments of Sartres ethical work written in 1947 and 1948 were published under the title: Notebooks for an Ethics, University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London, 1992, (583 pages), and the French original by Gallimard, Paris, in 1983. Sartre interviewed by Simon Blumenthal and Grard Spitzer in La Voie communiste, JuneJuly 1962. The subsequent transformation of thefor a long time dogmatic Stalinist French Communist Party first into an unprincipled social democratic formation, providing active support for President Mitterrands capitulatory government, and then into a neoliberal force in full complicity with the established order, provided a most unhappy confirmation of Sartres skeptical judgement. I wrote at the time when the unprincipled departure of some of the major communist partiesin their more remote past committed to a Marxist strategic transformation of societystarted to take place that: When a once important historical force, the French Communist Party, reduces itself to the role of a fig leaf, in order to hide the non-existent endowments of Franois Mitterrand as a socialist, no one should be surprised that a commensurate

N OT E S TO PAG E S 261 2 71

365

95. 96. 97. 98.

99. 100. 101. 102.

103. 104. 105. 106. 107. 108. 109. 110. 111. 112. 113. 114. 115. 116. 117.

shrinkage takes place not only in its electoral fortunes but, more importantly, in its impact on the unfolding social developments. (Istvn Mszros, The Power of Ideology, Harvester/Wheatsheaf, London, and New York University Press, New York, 1989, p.53.) Sartre, Saint Genet: Actor and Martyr, George Braziller, New York, 1963 (published in French in 1952), p. 186. Including Franois Mauriac and Gabriel Marcel. His lost writings on the problems of ethics alone, pursued again and again in different periods of his life, are said to amount to at least 2000 pages. See Sartre, Dtermination et Libert, a lecture delivered at the Gramsci Institute in Rome on 25 May 1964, reproduced in Les crits de Sartre: Chronologie, Bibliographie comment by Michel Contat and Michel Rybalka, Gallimard, Paris, 1970, pp. 73545. Kant, Theory and Practice , in Carl J. Friedrich (ed.), Immanuel Kants Moral and Political Writings, Random House, New York, 1949, pp. 41516. Rousseau, A Discourse on Political Economy, Everyman edition, p. 254. Ibid., p. 234. This is how Sartre generously praised the Maoists, in the spirit of his own, for a long time idealized, conception of what a revolutionary movement of committed individuals should be like: The militants of La Cause du Peuple do not constitute a party. It is a political group [rassemblement] which can always be dissolved. . . . This procedure allows a way out of the rigidity in which the Communist Party has imprisoned itself. Today the Maoists criticize and break out of the notion of leftism: they want to be the left and to create a broad political organization . Sartre interviewed by Michel-Antoine Burnier, Actuel, No. 28, and Tout va Bien, 20 February20 March 1973. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, pp. 4229. Ibid., p. 429. Sartre, Critique, p. 64. Ibid., p. 125. Ibid., p. 814. Sartre, Critique, pp. 81415. Sartres emphases. See Sartre, Itinerary of a thought, New Left Review, November-December 1969, p. 59. Sartre, Critique, pp. 81617. Ibid., p. 818. Ibid. Ibid., p. 125. Ibid., p. 816. Sartre in the Seventies, pp. 2425. Marx, Notes on Bakunins book: Statehood and Anarchy, MECW, vol. 24, p. 521. Ibid., p. 518.

366

NOTES TO PAG E S 2 7 1 2 7 9

118. It is revealing that in his critique of the serialized voters Sartre equates, most problematically, their abstract possibility with a claimed sovereigntyconstituting power. He writes: When I vote, I abdicate my powerthat is, the possibility everyone has of joining others to form a sovereign group. (Sartre in the Seventies, p. 204.) Of course in the circumstances of Pompidous relatively undisturbed France, way after the defeat of Mai 1968 which contributed to the consolidation of the Gaullist system, the possibility of joining others to form a sovereign group advocated by Sartre is a purely abstract possibility. Under the conditions of a massive and intensifying socioeconomic crisis such abstract possibilities may well become concrete possibilities, leading to significant historical change. But it is extremely problematical to call abstract possibilities real powers in the absence of such a major socioeconomic crisis, as Sartre called it in 1973. 119. In fact that is the basis on which the classical left parties can be, and should be, legitimately questioned for their strategic inadequacy, and not for their alleged nineteenth century political attachment. 120. The Dialectic of Structure and History, Monthly Review Press, New york, 2011. See in particular Section 4.4, concerned with The Radical Transformation of the Legal and Political Superstructure. 121. In accord with the Marxian concept of the bergreifendes Moment, i.e. the factor of overriding importance under a given set of circumstances. 122. Marxs circular addressed to the Federal Council of the Romance Switzerland, Documents of the First International, Lawrence & Wishart, London, n.d., vol. 3, p. 361. 123. Rosa Luxemburg, Reform or Revolution, Pathfinder Press, New York, 1970, p. 50. 124. Rosa Luxemburg, The Junius Pamphlet, A Young Socialist Publication, Colombo, 1967, p. 62. 125. The main reason offered by Sartre in 1975 for abandoning the Critique of Dialectical Reason was that in the case of the Critique there is the additional problem of time, since I would have to go back to studying history. (Sartre in the Seventies, p. 75.) Undoubtedly the historical knowledge mastered by any particular thinker is a contributory factor in this respect. But only contingently. The necessities lie elsewhere. The much more serious impediments in Sartres case, imposing insurmountable difficulties on his projected Critique, were not due to the limitations of his historical knowledge but primarily to his marxisant existentialist ontological approach to the problems of intelligibility in the dialectically unfolding history of humanity. 126. Marx, Grundrisse, p. 171. 127. Le structuralisme en personne, see Jean-Marie Auzias, Clefs pour le structuralisme, Seghers, Paris, 1967, p. 85. 128. LExpress va plus loin avec Claude Lvi-Strauss, a major interview published by LExpress, 1521 March 1971, p.61.

N OT E S TO PAG E S 279 2 80

367

129. Of course the ultra-eclectic opportunist Jrgen Habermas must join in the fashionable scramble for the invention of catchy post labels, talking in a most pretentious and confused way even about post-history. He writes: Hegels concept of the ethical totality . . . is no longer an appropriate model for the mediatized class structure of organized, advanced capitalism. The suspended dialectic of the ethical generates the peculiar semblance of posthistoire.. . . For the leading productive forcecontrolled scientific-technical progress itselfhas now become the basis of legitimation. Yet this new form of legitimation has cast off the old shape of ideology. J. Habermas, Toward a Rational Society, Heinemann, London, 1971, pp. 110-11. The words posthistoire and ideology are italicized by Habermas. For a detailed discussion of his work see Sections 1.2 and 3.4 of my book, The Power of Ideology, Harvester/Wheatsheaf, London, and New York University Press, 1989. 130. Not surprisingly, the wide-ranging promotion of structuralism was associated with empire-building and a search for respectable ancestors, from linguistics to ethnography. Even Jacob Grimm was adopted as a distinguished structuralist ancestor. Thus we could read about him in a book on linguistics that His language lacks precision and he was guilty of gross inconsistencies, but his intent is clear. He was far, far ahead of his time. He was, in fact, one of the first structuralists. John T. Waterman, Perspectives in Linguistic, University of Chicago Press, 1963, p. 82. 131. For a documented discussion of these problems see my book: Philosophy, Ideology and Social Science: Essays in Negation and Affirmation, Wheatsheaf Books, Brighton, 1986, and in particular its Introduction and the chapter on Ideology and Social Science, pp. ix-xix and 156; the latter first published in 1972. 132. Characteristically, Auzias praised structuralism personified by saying that: Structuralism is not an imperialism! It wants to be scientific: and it is. . . . Lvi-Strauss thought is satisfied with applying itself to the human sciences, and exclusively to them, eminently and insistently refusing by his own rigorous practice any concession to ideology, no matter under what kind of philosophy it might hide itself. Jean-Marie Auzias, Op. cit., pp. 1011. 133. See in this respect one of the seminal passages of Lvi-Strauss wide-ranging interview given to LExpress in March 1971, as quoted in Section 8.6 of The Social Determination of Method. In that interview he was asserting that: Today the greater peril for humanity does not come from the activities of a regime, a party, a group, or a class. It comes from humanity itself in its entirety; a humanity which reveals itself to be its own worst enemy and, alas, at the same time, also the worst enemy of the rest of the creation. 134. As we know, Marx forcefully underlined already in one of his earliest works that We know only one science, the science of history (MECW, vol. 5, p. 28; Marxs emphases), insisting in the same spirit about the vital importance of history throughout his life.

368

NOTES TO PAG E S 2 8 1 2 8 5

135. See Les structures lmentaires de la parent, Paris, 1949. See also: Mythologiques, vol. 1: Le cru et le cuit, Paris, 1964; vol. 2: Du miel aux cendres, Paris, 1966; vol. 3: Lorigine des manires de table, Paris, 1968. 136. Tellingly, as noted by the English anthropologist Edmund Leach, LviStrauss monumental discussion of American indian myths does not carry the title of Mythologies but that of Mythologiques; which means: the Logics of Myth. See Edmund Leachs book in the Fontana Modern Masters series, Lvi-Strauss, Fontana/Collins, London, 1970, p. 10. 137. A book translated into English under the title: The Savage Mind, George Weidenfeld and Nicholson Ltd., London, 1966. 138. See LExpress va plus loin avec Claude Lvi-Strauss, LExpress, 1521 March 1971, p. 66. 139. Sir Lewis Namier, Vanished Supremacies: Essays on European History, 1812 1918, Penguin Books, Harmondsworth, 1962, p. 203. 140. 1971 interview, p. 66. 141. Joseph Arthur Comte de Gobineau, 18161882, the racist orientalist author of The Inequality of Human Races and Les religions et les philosophies dans lAsie central, was a friend and for some time also the Secretary to Alexis de Tocqueville in his Foreign Ministry, and a member of the French diplomatic service between 184977. He was also the inventor of the myth of the superman. 142. The revealing utopia aimed at perpetuating capitals established reproductive order, with at least a modicum of doubt about its realizability, was propounded in the nineteenth century also by the liberal thinker John Stuart Mill, who advocated the institution of the stationary state of the economy in his Principles of Political Economy. 143. See note 93 above. 144. LExpress va plus loin avec Claude Lvi-Strauss, Op. cit., p. 66. 145. Ibid., p. 61. 146. This is how Descartes had put it in his Discourse on Method: I perceived it to be possible to arrive at knowledge highly useful in life; and in room of the speculative philosophy usually taught in the schools, to discover a practical [philosophy] by means of which . . . we might also apply them to all the uses to which they are adapted, and thus render ourselves the lords and possessors of nature. Everyman Edition, p. 49. 147. Lvi-Strauss, The Savage Mind, p. 26162. 148. Marx, Grundrisse, p. 105. 149. See note 94. 150. A relevant connection in this respect is that The Savage Mind is dedicated to Maurice Merleau-Ponty who vehemently attacked Sartre for his alleged ultrabolshevism in Les Aventures de la dialectique. 151. Lvi-Strauss, The Savage Mind, p. 256. 152. Ibid., p. 254. 153. Ibid.

N OT E S TO PAG E S 285 2 90

369

154. Ibid. 155. Je mefforce moi-mme de faire oeuvre scientifique. Mais je ne peux mempcher de penser que la science serait plus aimable si elle ne servait rien. Page 66 of LExpress va plus loin avec Claude Lvi-Strauss. 156. See Hayeks Road to Serfdom, discussed in Chapter 4. of Beyond Capital. 157. Edmund Leach, Op. cit., pp. 1920. 158. Nest-ce pas trs ractionnaire, entre guillemets, ce que vous dites l? p. 66. 159. Ibid. 160. Ibid., p. 65. 161. As we are constantly told even today, nothing could be more ideally equilibrating in due courseprovided that we are able and willing to suffer long enough with patience the unavoidably disruptive and creatively destructive crisis periods of the systemthan the capitalist exchange relations embodied in the market, even in the historical period of its globalization. Appropriately, in Lvi-Strauss view the great passage for North American indians from nature to culture has been accomplished through the establishment of commerce. (See 1971 interview, p. 65.) Also, in the societies without writing idealized by him, the embodiment of the exchange relations in the elementary structures of kinship is the common denominator of politics, the law, and the economy. Ibid., p. 63. 162. 1971 interview, p. 61. 163. Ibid. 164. Ibid., p. 63. 165. That is, the historically constituted human subject who could remedy at least in principle the situation by appropriately confronting the problems and contradictions of the real world, including its own, now antagonistically selfmediating but transcendable negative relationship to nature, so as to transform the earlier discussed constraints of historical necessity into a progressively vanishing necessity in accordance with human need. 166. 1971 interview, p. 60. 167. Ibid., p. 66. 168. In fact Sartres apartment was bombed not once but twice. 169. Lvi-Strauss March 1971 interview, p. 66. 170. Marx, Grundrisse, p. 331. 171. Ibid., pp. 8788. 172. Of course what really decides the matter is what, when, where and how the human beings exchange in their specific kind of exchange relationships in which they engage not only among themselves but also with nature. 173. It is worth recalling again that according to one of the greatest political economists of all times, Adam Smith, the bourgeois societal reproductive order is constituted as the natural system of perfect liberty and justice. 174. As such, the second order mediations are by no means necessarily/aprioristically antagonistic. Indeed, the constitution of the exchange relationship between

370

NOTES TO PAG E S 2 9 1 3 0 3

175. 176. 177. 178.

179. 180. 181.

182. 183. 184. 185. 186. 187. 188. 189. 190. 191. 192. 193.

194. 195. 196.

humanity and nature and among the individuals themselves in the form of antagonistic second order mediations is intelligible only as an inherently historical category, which implies their historical transcendability. Sartre rightly criticizes structuralism for never showing how History produces the structures. Situations IX, Gallimard, Paris, 1972, p. 86. Marx, Grundrisse, pp. 9596. Marx, Grundrisse, p. 88. This is done even by the idealist philosopher, Hegel, with his revealingpurely ideological way of doing it in defense of the most iniquitous determinations of the established orderas we have seen it discussed in chapter 6 of The Dialectic of Structure and History. Hegel, The Philosophy of Right, p. 17. Ibid., p. 222. As Marx made it very clear, in his sharp critique of the approach which postulated the idea of the nature-determined and necessarily warring isolated individuality as the fictitious foundation of human nature from which the political apologetics of an absolutely permanent bourgeois state order could be readily derived: Human nature is the true community of men. The disastrous isolation from this essential nature is incomparably more universal, more intolerable, more dreadful, and more contradictory than isolation from the political community. Marx, Critical Marginal Notes on the Article by a Prussian, MECW, vol. 3, p. 205. MECW, vol. 3, p. 205. Marx, Theses on Feuerbach. Sartre, Critique of Dialectical Reason, p. 125. Ibid., pp. 13132. Ibid., p. 133. Sartre, Critique of Dialectical Reason, vol. 2, Verso, London, 1991, p. 424. Ibid., pp. 2122. Marx, Grundrisse, p. 88. Sartre, op. cit., p. 23. Ibid., p. 26. Ibid., pp. 2728. C. B. Macpherson, A political theory of property, in Macpherson, Democratic Theory: Essays in Retrieval, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1973, p. 138. John Maynard Keynes was rhetorically anticipatingin one of his Essays in Persuasionthe realization of the ideal conditions of abundance in the capitalist Millennium by the year 2030. But that view, voiced in a lecture in 1930, was not to be taken too seriously. Herbert Marcuse, An Essay on Liberation, Allen Lane The Penguin Press, London, 1969, p. 4. Ibid., p. 5. Ibid. p. 19.

N OT E S TO PAG E S 303 3 13

371

197. We may well recall the views of Habermasone of the most fashionable eclectic opportunist mystifiers in this fieldwho postulates the scientization of technology when in reality so much damage is generated by the fetishistic technologization of science in the service of destructive production. 198. Marcuse, Ibid., p. 7. 199. Marx, Capital, vol. 1, p. 152. 200. It is most relevant here that If capital increases from 100 to 1,000, then 1,000 is now the point of departure, from which the increase has to begin; the tenfold multiplication, by 1,000%, counts for nothing; profit and interest themselves become capital in turn. What appeared as surplus-value now appears as simple presupposition etc., as included in its simple composition. Marx, Grundrisse, p. 335. Emphases by Marx. 201. The man of scarcity, seeking his abundance, seeks it as a determination of scarcity. Not abundance for all, but his own, hence the deprivation of all. Sartre, Critique, vol. 2, p. 421. 202. Ibid., p. 437. 203. Marx, Grundrisse, p. 528. 204. See Sartres interview in Le Nouvel Observateur, March 1980. 205. Sartre, Self-Portrait at Seventy, Le Nouvel Observateur, June and July 1975. In English in Sartre in the Seventies: Interviews and Essays, Andre Deutsch Ltd., London, 1978, pages 8385. 206. From an Interview with Sartre reported in Encounter, No. 62, June 1964. 207. In English this part of Sartres Critique was published as a separate volume. It is quoted from page 157 of this volume: Sartre, The Problem of Method, Methuen & Co., London, 1963. In French original p. 98. 208. Ibid., p 151. In French p. 95. 209. Ibid., p. 152. In French p. 96. 210. Ibid., p 93. In French p. 64. 211. Ibid., p. 94. In French p. 65. That which is lacking (ce qui manque) is italicized by Sartre. 212. It appears only as a somewhat nostalgic and unresolved paradoxical admission in Words when Sartre says: I depend only on those who depend only on God, and I do not believe in God. Try and sort this out! Certainly Sartre himself never sorted it out. But nothing is more self-servingly absurd than Gabriel Marcels earlier quoted denunciation of Sartre as a systematic blasphemist and the patented corruptor of youth. On the contrary, Sartre would wish to challenge the youth in the spirit of the highest moral imperatives about the imperiled destiny of the world and their own responsibility in it, in tune with the Kantian can which constitutes the insuperable moral tension of his philosophy, with the explicit admission of faith and the need for hope inseparable from it. What he cannot provideno matter how much he would like, and despite his repeated promises, spelled out even in terms of the positively oriented radical conversion toward the

372

NOTES TO PAG E S 3 1 3 3 2 0

213. 214. 215. 216.

217.

218. 219. 220.

end of Being and Nothingnessis the non-religious grounding of such faith and hope. Sartres interview given to the Italian Manifesto group, published in The Socialist Register, 1970, p. 245. Ibid., p. 242. The Socialist Register, 1970, pp. 2389. The gravity of this problem can no longer be ignored. To realize its magnitude it is enough to quote a passage from an excellent book which offers a comprehensive account of the unfolding process of planetary destructiveness as a result of crossing some prohibitive thresholds and boundaries put into relief by environmental science: these thresholds have in some cases already been crossed and in other cases will soon be crossed with the continuation of business as usual. Moreover, this can be attributed in each and every case to a primary cause: the current pattern of global socioeconomic development, that is, the capitalist mode of production and its expansionary tendencies. The whole problem can be called the global ecological rift, referring to the overall break in the human relation to nature arising from an alienated system of capital accumulation without end. All of this suggests that the use of the term Anthropocene to describe a new geological epoch, displacing the Holocene, is both a description of a new burden falling on humanity and a recognition of an immense crisisa potential terminal event in geological evolution that could destroy the world as we know it. On the one hand, there has been a great acceleration of the human impact on the planetary system since the Industrial Revolution, and particularly since 1945to the point that biogeochemical cycles, the atmosphere, the ocean, and the earth system as a whole, can no longer be seen as largely impervious to the human economy. On the other hand, the current course on which the world is headed could be described not so much as the appearance of a stable new geological epoch (the Anthropocene), as an end-Holocene, or more ominously, end-Quarternary, terminal event, which is a way of referring to the mass extinctions that often separate geological eras. Planetery boundaries and tipping points, leading to the irreversible degradation of the conditions of life on Earth, may soon be reached, science tells us, with a continuation of todays business as usual. The Anthropocene may be the shortest flicker in geological time, soon snuffed out. John Bellamy Foster, Brett Clark, and Richard York, The Ecological Rift: Capitalisms War on the Earth, Monthly Review Press, New York, 2010, pp. 1819. See my Isaac Deutscher Memorial Lecture, The Necessity of Social Control, delivered at the London School of Economics on January 26, 1971. Italics in the original. Sartre, Ibid., p. 239. Marx, Capital, vol. 1, p. 14. Sartre in the Seventies, p. 85.

N OT E S TO PAG E S 320 3 30

373

221. 222. 223. 224.

225. 226. 227. 228. 229. 230. 231. 232.

233. 234. 235. 236. 237. 238. 239. 240. 241. 242. 243. 244. 245.

Sartres Manifesto interview, The Socialist Register, 1970, pp. 2367. Sartres Critique of Dialectical Reason, vol. 2, pp. 23031. Ibid., p. 335. Thus he conceded in the unfinishable second volume that this wholly formal characterization of the totalizing movement has been madeas a pure, empty abstractionfrom a standpoint of quasi-exteriority. Sartres Critique of Dialectical Reason, vol. 2, p. 335. Sartre in the Seventies, p. 210. Ibid., pp. 201-2. In Marxs words eine verschwindende Notwendigkeit. Sartres Critique of Dialectical Reason, vol. 2, pp. 234. Ibid., p. 220. Sartre, Itinerary of a Thought, p. 45. Ibid., p. 44. Joseph L. Walsh, Conversations with a Bourgeois Revolutionary, Monthly Review, June 2010. (Walshs review article of John Gerassis book: Talking with Sartre: Conversations and Debates, Yale University Press, New Haven, CT, 2009) Walsh quoting these words from Gerassis book. Ibid. Sartre in the Seventies, p. 83. See in this respect Chapter 6 above and the discussion of the relevant passages from pages 2425 of Sartre in the Seventies. Sartre in the Seventies, p. 84. Ibid. Ibid., p. 52. Kierkegaard: the Singular Universal, in Jean-Paul Sartre, Between Existentialism and Marxism, N.L.B., London, 1974, p.168. Sartre, Des rats et des hommes, Situations, IV, Gallimard, Paris, 1964, pp. 656. Sartre, Kierkegaard: the Singular Universal, p. 169 Ibid., p. 168. The words praxis and knowledge are italicized by Sartre. Ibid., p. 169. Ibid.

This page intentionally left blank

Index
Ady, Endre, 332n21 Alix, Roland, 333n50 Alleg,Henri, 232 Althusser, Louis, 202 Anouilh, Jean, 47 Aron,Raymond, 121, 280, 342n184, 360n35 Astre, G. A., 359n28 Auriol,Vincent, 18, 233 Aury, Dominique, 336n121, 340n161 Autrusseau, Jacqueline, 334n68 Auzias, Jean-Marie, 366n127, 367n132 Babeuf, Franois-Nol, 326 Bachelard, Gaston, 354n321 Bakunin, Mikhail, 271, 365n116 Baldick, Robert, 344n209 Barnes, Hazel E., 340n162 Baudelaire, Charles, 67, 80, 86, 335n83 Beckett, Samuel, 335n70 Bergson, Henri, 59, 73, 98, 107 Blumenthal, Simon, 339n154, 364n93 Bosch, Hieronymous, 41 Bourget, Paul, 356n337 Brecht, Bertolt, 27, 4849, 55, 83 Breton,Andr, 18, 332n8 Brunschwicg, Lon, 91 Burnet, Mary, 362n78 Burnier, Michel-Antoine, 339n158, 340n165, 365n102 Calder, Alexander, 49, 335n81 Camus, Albert, 41, 47, 81, 92, 94, 235, 341n175, 359n31 Csaire, Aim, 333n55 Chapsal, Madeleine, 82, 360n41

376

INDEX

Chonez, Claudine, 334n65, 335n84, 335n92 Churchill, Winston, 16 Clark, Brett, 372n216 Clephane, Irene, 359n34 Cohn-Bendit, Daniel, 336n99 Contat,Michel, 229, 269, 307, 331n1, 358n6, 360n50, 361n63, 361n67, 362n75, 365n98 dAmico, Robert, 339n158 dAubarde, Gabriel, 332n34, 333n45 Davis,Gary, 234 deBeauvoir,Simone, 38, 41, 47, 65, 78, 92, 121, 13739, 175, 230, 333n46, 333n48, 333n50, 333n54, 337n123, 337n137, 341n184, 344n198, 345n234, 347n273, 347n275, 351n305, 355n324 de Gaulle, Charles, 18, 23334, 331n8 de Man, Paul, 357n341 de Tocqueville, Alexis, 368n141 Deborin Abram, 359n25 Debray,Rgis, 83 Descartes, Ren, 180, 282, 352n308, 352n310, 368n146 Deutscher,Isaac, 69, 337n128, 372n217 Dort, Bernard, 334n69 Dostoevsky, Fyodor, 193 Dru, Alexander, 333n52

Duclos, Jacques, 234 Drer, Albrecht, 100 Eisler, Benita, 332n36 luard, Paul, 331n2 Engels, Friedrich, 132, 346n258 Epicurus, 348n288 Erval,Franois, 38, 335n86 Fadeev, Alexander, 17, 358n4 Faulkner, William, 11, 5962, 78, 126, 12829, 336n109, 336n117 Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 18 Fink, Eugen, 99, 343n189 Flaubert, Gustave, 3335, 5152, 67, 7274, 78, 82, 84, 86, 93, 122, 165, 178, 207, 242, 326, 337n138, 356n337, 356n338, 357n339, 360n47, 363n81 Foster, John Bellamy, 372n216 Frechtman, Bernard, 332n13 Friedrich, Carl J., 365n99 Freud, Sigmund, 136, 346n272, 357n339 Fuk, Julius, 86 Gance,Abel, 58 Genet, Jean, 33-36, 5455, 67, 81, 86, 93, 325 Gerassi,John, 326, 373n233 Giacometti, Alberto, 26, 40, 4243, 4849, 52, 55, 58, 86, 92, 333n53, 333n58, 334n59, 335n81

I N DEX

377

Gide, Andr, 193 Giscard dEstaing, Valry, 18 Gisoli, Christian, 332n27 Gobineau, Joseph Arthur Comte de, 281, 368n141 Goethe, Johann W. von, 21, 69, 71 Goldman, Lucien, 336n115 Gorbachev, Mikhail, 9 Gorz, Andr, 52, 83 Gramsci, Antonio, 365n98 Grimm Jacob, 367n130 Gurin,Daniel, 42, 94 Habermas, Jrgen, 367n129, 371n197 Halbwachs, Maurice, 357n341 Hallier, Jean-Edern, 334n63 Hamilton, Hamish, 235, 359n34 Hartmann, Klaus, 352n307 Hayek,Friedrich von, 286, 369n156 Hegel, Georg W. F., 24, 33-34, 37, 50, 71, 109, 140, 174, 195-198, 202, 205, 207, 259, 262, 265, 296, 329, 341n175, 342n184, 367n129, 370n178180 Heidegger, Martin, 3637, 6061, 106-107, 11617, 121, 126, 174, 178, 191, 336n115116, 345n241, 348n286 Hikmet, Nzm, 86 Hobbes, Thomas, 198 Hoffmann, E. Th. A., 45 Husserl, Edmund, 96-103, 105, 113, 12122, 14447, 170,

197, 256, 341n177, 341n181, 341n184, 343n189, 350n295, 351n306 Ionesco, Eugne, 47 Ishaghpour, Youssef, 336n115 James, C. L. R., 333n55 Jeanson,Francis, 230, 232 Jolas, Maria, 340n167 Jzsef, Attila, 23, 332n23-24 Kdr,Jnos, 229 Kafka, Franz, 33, 45, 52 Kant, Immanuel, 28, 53, 131, 14447, 153, 18991, 259, 26162, 313, 342n184, 349n291, 363n88, 365n99 Kanters, Robert, 334n62, 337n124, 340n163 Keynes, John Maynard, 370n193 Khrushchev,Nikita, 228 Kierkegaard, Sren, 36, 40, 140, 154, 329, 333n52, 342n184, 373n240, 373n242 Koehler, Alain, 334n61, 335n74, 335n87 Lafaurie, Serge, 336n100, 362n74 Lawrence, T. E., 80, 338n146 Le Lap,Alain, 234 Leach,Edmund, 286, 368n136, 369n157 Lefbvre,Henri, 12223, 22829, 331n3, 345n235, 358n15

378

INDEX

Lefort, Claude, 359n32, 359n34 Lenin, Vladimir, 36, 68 Lvi-Strauss, Claude, 27994, 366n128, 367n13233, 368n136, 368n138, 368n144, 368n147, 368n151, 369n155, 369n161, 369n169 Lvinas, Emmanuel, 121, 342n184 Lvy, Benny, 360n40 Livingstone, Rodney, 344n200, Locke, John, 192 Lorquet, Pierre, 332n32, 333n51 Lukcs, Gyrgy, 5960, 71, 94, 126, 209, 22931, 326, 333n57, 336n115, 341n174, 342n184, 344n200, 358n17, 358n18, 359n2025 Luxemburg,Rosa, 27273, 366n123124 Lynd, Staughton, 358n6 Macpherson,C. B., 302303, 370n193 Macquarie, John, 336n116 Mairet, Philip, 343n191 Mallarm, Stphane, 35, 67, 81, 86 Malle, Louis, 19 Malraux, Andr, 17 Mann,Thomas, 26-27, 337n126, 339n160 Marcel,Gabriel, 16, 331n4, 365n96, 371n212 Marcuse, Herbert, 25860, 263, 302304, 314, 316, 355n329,

363n86, 363n88, 370n194 196, 371n198 Martin,Henri, 18, 233, 359n29 Marx, Karl, 34, 36, 37, 68, 75, 109, 119, 13234,175 76,180, 195, 202, 208, 271, 272, 27475, 27778, 27980, 282, 284, 28789, 29394, 297, 320, 329, 332n37, 345n241, 346n258, 346n264, 346n266, 347n280, 351n306, 352n309, 352n312, 355n326, 356n331, 356n334, 356n336, 357n341, 367n134, 370n176 177, 370n181, 370n183, 370n189, 371n200, 356n331, n334, n336, 351n306, 352n309, 352n312, 365n116, 366n122, 366n126, 367n134, 368n148, 369n170, 370n176177, 370n181, 370n183, 370n189, 371n199200, 371n203, 372n219, 373n227 Masson, Andr, 4849, 335n78 Matthews, John, 332n18 Mauriac, Franois, 1819, 331n7, 332n35, 365n96 Merleau-Ponty,Maurice, 18, 41, 52, 81, 83, 92, 121, 23536, 341n170, 345n233, 347n284, 359n32, 359n35, 360n36, 368n150 Mszros, Istvn, 355n326, 356n335, 359n24, 360n36, 360n48, 361n58, 364n91,

I N DEX

379

365n94, 367n131, 372n217 Michel,Georges, 47 Mill, John Stuart, 368n142 Miller, Jacques-Alain, 332n28, 336n122, 351n299 Milligan, Martin, 346n264 Mitterrand, Franois, 364n94 Molotov, Vyacheslav, 357n1 Moore, Henry, 74 More, Thomas, 364n89 Nagy,Imre, 229-230, 358n18 Namier, Lewis, 281, 368n139 Nizan, Paul, 52, 64, 83, 86, 92, 126, 357n1 Novy, Yvon, 336n104, 336n108 Owen,Robert, 319 Parsons, Talcott, 280 Pascal, Blaise, 178, 181 Pellauer, David, 360n38 Petfi, Sndor, 12 Piatier, Jacqueline, 332n15, 337n133, 340n163 Picasso, Pablo, 26-27, 76, 331n2, 340n160 Pinay, Antoine, 359n30 Pius XII (pope), 1617 Plato, 342n184 Politzer, Georges, 12526 Pompidou, Georges, 366n118 Proust, Marcel, 26-27, 40, 59, 98, 180, 333n51, 352n310 Puig, Andr, 333n43

Ranke, Leopold Von, 70, 281 Ribbentrop, Joachim von, 357n1 Ricardo, David, 289 Robbe-Grillet, Alain, 21 Robinson, Edward, 336n116 Rosenberg, Julius and Ethel, 358n6 Rosenthal, Grard, 331n6 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 25354, 262, 340n160, 362n80, 365n100 Rousset, David, 331n6 Rubel, Maximilien, 346n258 Rudas, Lszl, 359n25 Russell, Bertrand, 18, 233, 354n322 Rybalka, Michel, 331n1, 358n6, 365n98 Sagan,Franoise, 3738 Saporta, Marcel, 339n150 Sarraute, Claude, 333n42 Sarraute,Nathalie, 92, 340n167 Savignat, Thomas, 334n63 Scheler, Max, 342n184 Schiller, Friedrich, 33 Seghers, Anna, 333n57 Simmel, Georg, 126 Smith, Adam, 262, 369n173 Spinoza, Baruch, 96 Spitzer, Grard, 339n154, 364n93 Stalin, Joseph, 1617, 82, 84, 209, 227-228, 321, 357n1, 358n12, 362n68 Stendhal, 200

380

TH E WOR K OF SARTR E

Stphane,Roger, 80 Strindberg, August, 48 Sznt,Zoltn, 230, 358n18 Thatcher, Margaret, 9 Tintoretto, 35 Titian, 41 Tynan, Kenneth, 4748, 334n70, 340n163 Underwood, J. A., 347n285

Villon, Franois, 33 Voltaire, 340n160 Walsh, Joseph L., 373n232234 Warnock, Mary, 346n262 Waterman, John T., 367n130 Weber,Max, 126, 280, 364n91 Welles,Orson, 58, 65, 336n105 Williams, Forrest, 343n192 Williams, Tennessee, 335n70 York, Richard, 372n216

Vsrhelyi, Mikls, 358n18 Verstraeten, Pierre, 333n57, 347n285, 350n295

Zand, Nicole, 335n73 Zola, mile, 65

You might also like