You are on page 1of 376

A DEFENCE

OF

PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT

A DEFENCE
OF

PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT
BEING AN ESSAY ON

THE FOUNDATIONS OF BELIEF

BY

ARTHUR JAMES BALFOUR,

M.A.,

M.R

^IFOK^I^

\ \

MACMILLAN AND
1879,
The right of translation
is

CO.

reserred

'

'

70-3

'As, to the
for Religion
;

religious,

it

will

seem absurd
it

to set forth

any

justification

so, to the scientific,


last is certainly

will

seem absurd

to defend Science.
first

Yet to do the

as needful as to do the

Herbert Spencer
'A doctrine
is

first
;

received as

an

intuitive

truth,

standing beyond
rigid
is

all
;

need of demonstration

then

it

becomes the object of

demonstration

afterwards the demonstration ceases to be conclusive,

and

merely probable

and,

finally,

the effort

is

limited to demonstrating that there

reason on the other side.


stration is

In the later stages of

belief,

the

is no conclusive show of demon-

mere

bluster, or is useful only to trip


1^ i^

up an antagonist
Leslie Stephen

2 6y

\^

PREFACE
It
IS

NOT NECESSARY
its

to preface this

Essay by any
It
is

precise account of
sufficiently

scope and design.

may be
a piece

described

by saying

that

it

of destructive criticism, formed

by a

series of argu-

ments of a highly abstract character.

The

reader

who
the

is

not deterred by this description from reading


will
its

work

find,

think,

no

difficulty in

under-

standing
It

plan.

may be
in
*

convenient to mention that the

first

and sixth chapters and the Appendix have already


appeared

Mind'
in

and that the thirteenth chapter


*

was published

the

Fortnightly

Review.'

In

each case there have been some verbal alterations,


but nothing deserving the
substance.

name

of an alteration in

The

sixth chapter elicited a short reply


will

from Professor Caird, which

be found

in the

number
which
to
I

of

'Mind'
I

for this

month.

For reasons
it

there gave

have not thought


in

necessary

make any important changes

consequence of

his remarks.

VI

PREFACE.
I

must not omit

to

acknowledge the great and

unvarying kindness which

my

brother-in-law,

Mr.

Henry Sidgwick,
interest
in

has shown

in criticising the

various

portions of the Essay as they were written.

His
its

the

work, and his suggestions for


;

improvement, have both been invaluable


the

and

have
to

more reason

to

be grateful

for them,

owing

the fact that, in


differs

many

respects, his point of

view

widely from

my

own.

Whittinghame
January

1879.

*^* The original


Scepticism,'

title

of this
for

book was

'

A
me

Defence of Philosophic
that, considering

and

it

was even

a short time advertised under this


the

name.

It

was, however, pointed out to


contents, the

nature of

number of people who would read the book would probably bear an infinitely small proportion to the number of people who would read only its title, and that most of those who read
its

the

title

without reading the book would assume that by Scepticism


in matters

was meant scepticism


reasoning,
that,

of religion.

As

could deny the

accuracy neither of the premises nor of the conclusion of this piece of


I

substituted the present for the original


it

title,

in the

hope

though

is,

as

think, less accurate,

it

may

at all events prove

less misleading.

CONTENTS
PART
CHAPTER
I.

I.

PAGE

On the

Idea of a Philosophy

II.

Empirical Logic

15

III.

Induction
.
,

30
. . . .

IV. Historical Inference

45

PART
V. Introduction to

II.

Part

II

73

VI. Transcendentalism
VII.

85
.

Three Arguments from Popular Philosophy

138

VIII.

The

Authority

of

Consciousness
.
.

and
.

of
.

Original Beliefs

154'

IX. Psychological Idealism

X.
XI.

The Test

of Inconceivability

....
.

178

194
209

Mr. Spencer's Proof of Realism

Viii

CONTENTS.

PART
CHAPTER

III.

PAGE
.

XII. Science as a Logical System


XIII.

.242
. .

The Evolution of Belief

260

SUMMARY

277

PRACTICAL RESULTS
Note on the Discrepancy between Science and
Religion
.

296

^28

APPENDIX.
On the
Idea of a Philosophy of Ethics
.

.335

OF THB

''A

university'
A

DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.

PART

I.

CHAPTER
Everything
that

I.

ON THE IDEA OF A PHILOSOPHY.


we know,
or think

we know, may
may be
and
what

be classed under one of four heads, which, without


departing very widely from ordinary usage,

named

thus

Science,

Metaphysics,
is

Ethics,

Philosophy.

By Science
particular

meant

here, not only

commonly goes by that name, but also history, and


knowledge of
*

matters of fact

so that

knowledge of phenomena and the


'

relations subsist-

ing between phenomena

would be a more
for

accurate,

though
logy and
this
is

less

convenient, expression
is

what

is

intended. In Metaphysics
all

included, not only

Theoreal or

doctrines of the Absolute, but also (and


all

not necessarily the same thing)


entities

supposed knowledge of
nomenal.

which are not phe-

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

i.

What
in the

is

meant by Ethics
will

have shown at length

Appendix which

be found at the end of

the volume.
it

Here

it

is

only necessary to say that

includes, not only

what are commonly called moral


usually

systems, but also


so described.

some analogous systems not


all

Multitudes of propositions,

professing to

emour

body

knowledge belonging to one of these departare being continually put forward


for

ments,

acceptance.
(

And

as no one believes

all

of them, so

those

who

profess to act rationally

must hold that

there are grounds for rejecting the propositions they


disbelieve,
//

and

for

accepting those they believe.

The
and

systematic account of these grounds of belief


disbelief

makes up the fourth of the classes into which possible knowledge is divided, and is here
always called Philosophy.
If
It

be objected that

this

is

not the

common
difficult

meaning of the term, I reply that it would be to point out what the common meaning is.
been used, perhaps, most frequently
department of science.
absolute are also called
in

It

has

England, as
is

being equivalent to Psychology, which

properly a
after

But researches
philosophical,
is
is

the

and these

belong to ontology.

Ethics

sometimes called
sometimes called

moral philosophy, as science


natural

philosophy

while

Logic,

which

a very

common usage
would, as
I

regards as a branch of philosophy,

shall presently explain,

be included

in

it

CHAP.

I.]

ON THE IDEA OF A PHILOSOPHY.

also

by

my

definition.

So

that there cannot, on the

whole, be

much harm

in using the

term to represent
is

a definite subject of investigation for which there

no other word.
(

It follows directly

from

this definition, that

how-

ever restricted the range of possible knowledge


be, philosophy can never

may
For

be excluded from

it.

unless the restriction be purely arbitrary, there must

be reasons
that even

for

it

and
is

it is

the systematic account of

these reasons which


if it

here called philosophy.

So
is

should turn out that Metaphysics


'
'

an

illusion,

and only positive

knowledge
far

is

attain-

able, this discovery

would be so

from destroying
it

philosophy that

it is
)

only by philosophy that

could

be established.
If

mankind was in the condition of believing nothings and without a bias in any particular direction, was merely on the look-out for some legitimate creed, it would not, I conceive, be possible, a priori,
to

name any

of the positive characteristics which

the philosophy corresponding to that creed must necessarily possess.

But since

this is

by no means

the case, since everybody has a certain


scientific
beliefs,

number of

and most people have a certain number of ethical and metaphysical (theological)
ones,
it

may be

possible to describe
in a

some of the

at-

tributes

which should be found

philosophy pro-

fessing to support these provisional conclusions.

For example.

Since
B 2

no one supposes that

all

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


the propositions

[part

i.

we

believe are self-evident,

it

may
are

be assumed that the greater number of them are


legitimate inferences from propositions
self-evident.

which

And

from

this

it

follows that

philo-

sophy must consist of two main departments, one of which deals with these ultimate, or self-evident propositions, the other with
I

modes of

inference.

do not forget that some writers have held that


is

the truth of a system

to be inferred, not from


its
its

any

self-evident propositions lying at

root,

but from

the consistency and coherence of

parts,

though
self-

each of these taken by


evident.

itself is
it

by no means

Of such a system
one part
it

incorrect to say that

is

would apparently be ultimate and another


said, that the truth

derivative

ought rather to be
is

of the whole

an inference from the consistency of


is

the parts, while the .truth of the parts

an inference
this

from the truth of the whole.

But even on

theory the formula above stated holds good, for such


systems, so far from being self-contained (as
it

were)

and
a

sufficient

evidence for themselves, are

really, as

little

consideration will show, dependent for their

validity

on some such proposition as


is

this

'

all

that

is

coherent

true.*

Which
is

is

itself

again either

ulti-

mate or

derivative.

This double function


istic

an important character;

of a complete philosophy
it

let

me now

mention

another which, though


obvious,
is

would seem
It

sufficiently

continually ignored.

may be

stated

CHAP.

I.]

ON THE IDEA OF A PHILOSOPHY.


The
is

thus

' :

business of philosophy

is

to deal with

the grounds, not the causes of

belief.'

There

no

distinction

which has to be kept


this

more

steadily in

view than

between the causes


a
belief,

or antecedents which

produce

and the
enquiry

grounds or reasons which justify one.


into the first
is

The

psychological, the enquiry into the

second

is

philosophical,

and they belong therefore


to

(according to the classification just announced)


entirely distinct departments of knowledge.

No
may be
various
before

doubt, in constructing a philosophy, a pre-

vious psychological enquiry

may be

required.

It

necessary to

acquaint ourselves with the


arrive at
conviction,

modes by which we
select those

we can what we must


do,
tion
is

which are legitimate.

But
opera-

not do, and what

we

are very apt to


first

to suppose that
satisfactorily,

by performing the
all.

we

absolve ourselves from perIn the face of modern

forming the second at


discovery
progress

we made

have continually to recollect that no


in tracing the history of opinions,

no no
a
its

development of the theory of association of


application

ideas,

of the

doctrine

of evolution to mind,
for

however much they may prepare the ground


philosophy, add, or
structure.

can add, one fragment to

Thus,

it is

never a

final
it

answer to philosophy to
is

say of a particular
pirical, or,

belief,

innate, connate,

em-

a prioriy the result of inheritance, or the

'

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

i.

product of the association of ideas.


satisfied

Psychology

is

by such

replies, but(^o

rational foundation for

make psychology the philosophy, is to make a deall

partment of science support that on which


is

science

by

definition

supposed to
?

rest.

It is strictly
*

im-

possible that

any solution of the question


'

How

came I to believe this the demand Why ought


*

should completely satisfy


I

to believe

it ?

'

though,

especially in the case of derivative beliefs,

it

may go

some way towards


to

it.

In the case of what profess

be ultimate

beliefs, discussions as to their origin

are either philosophically irrelevant, or else prove to

demonstration that they are not ultimate.

This

will

perhaps be clearer

if

we

take a concrete case.

Let

us suppose that the result of a particular psychological investigation is that a certain


*

judgment,

e.g.y

Everything has a

cause,'

is

a priori'

The
it is
'

psy-.

chologist

who makes

this discovery is apt to trespass


'

on the domain of philosophy, and add,


fore true.'

thereto

Now

if

'

everything has a cause


it

is

be

accepted as true, because


that very reason
at least
it is

is

^
;

priori,^ then for

not ultimate
it

two propositions
ist, all
is
'

must be accepted before

a priori'

judgments are
judgment.

true, and, 2nd, this

an 'a priori
dis-

Both of which are assertions both

putable and disputed.


discussion
ciple
it is

So

in

loose philosophical

very

common

to

advance some prinrequiring nor

as being self-evident,

neither

possessing any justification, and immediately after-

'

CHAP.

I.]

ON THE IDEA OF A PHILOSOPHY.


in its

wards to adduce
as that
'

support some such argument


to
all

it

is

common
in

men/
it

or that

it

has
all-

been implanted
wise Creator.'

our nature by a benevolent and


is

In such cases

clear either that


nt,

the principles in

question are not self-evide

or

that the arguments used to support


fluous.
It
is

them are superfallacies as

by the consideration of such


I

these that
ultimate,

have been induced to use the word


the expression
*
'

when

a priori
'

'

might ap-

pear the most natural.


dent of experience
is
;

A priori

means indepen-

but independent of experience


*

ambiguous.

It

may mean

either that experience

has not produced the judgment in question, or that


it

furnishes no grounds for believing


is

it.

The

first

meaning
no

quite beside the purpose

philosophy has

direct concern with the origin of beliefs, which,


stated,
is

as before

part of the

subject-matter of

psychology.

The second meaning, on


it

the other

hand, while
belief,

excludes experience as a ground of


far expresses
full
'

and so

the desired idea, does


'

not express the


viz. that
all.

differentia

of ultimate beliefs

we

require no grounds for believing them at


it

On

the contrary,

sometimes seems to suggest

itself directly

as a reason for accepting a

judgment

(as if the fact

that experience did not prove anyit),

thing was a ground for believing

and sometimes

mediately, as showing that the constitution of our

mind when

in

a healthy condition impels us to

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


it,

[part

i.

believe

or that

it
;

was implanted
fact that

in

us by the

Author of our being


or bad, show,
as reasons, that the
ultimate.

which reasons, whether good


they are given
called

by the very

judgment

a priori

is

not

While, then,

it

is

evidently not the business of


for

philosophy to account

ultimate

axioms
it

and
not

modes
its

of inference,

it is

also clear (though

may be
it

hardly necessary to

make
it

the remark) that

is

business to prove them.


is

To

prove any concluobliged to perform

sion

to

show
;

that

legitimately follows from a

true premiss

so that

if

we were

this operation for

our axioms and modes of inference


received as ultimate,

before they were to be

we

should be driven either to argue in a circle or to an


infinite regress.
if

Indeed, this will sufficiently appear

we

reflect that all

we mean by
is

ultimate

is

'

inde-

pendent of

proof.'

But

if

philosophy

neither to investigate the


belief,

causes nor to prove the grounds of

what,
I

it

may be
hend
it,

asked,
is

is it

to

do

Its business, as

appre-

to disengage the latter, to distinguish

them

from what simulates to be ultimate, and to exhibit

them

in systematic order.
is

What

meant here by disengaging the grounds


if

of belief in contradistinction to proving them, will

appear more clearly


deductive logic.

we

consider what
logic,
is

is

done by

Deductive

apart from the


is (ac-

practical rules with

which

it

encumbered,

CHAP.

I.]

ON THE IDEA OF A PHILOSOPHY.

cording to the terminology here employed) neither

an art nor a science, but a systematic account of an


ultimate

mode

of inference
all

by which

it

may be
:

dis-

tinguished from

other modes, whether legitimate


it

or illegitimate, whether ultimate or derivative


therefore

is

by

definition a

branch of philosophy.

Now when

deductive logic says that any three


*

propositions which can be reduced to the form,

All

is

B, all

is

*
.

all

is B,'

are legitimately

connected as premises and conclusion, whatever

may

be their content,

it is

by no means meant that such


It

pieces of reasoning derive their validity from the


fact

of their corresponding with the formula.

simply means, to distinguish and mark off a certain

mode
of
it
;

of inference

by giving a general description

each particular example of such inference


in itself the

being

witness of

its

own

validity.

This example explains the procedure of Philosophy with regard to inferences

the
*

axioms of
procedure

mathematics furnish an
in the

illustration of its

matter of ultimate principles.

Two

hundred
one

and

forty

pence and twenty

shillings,

being each
is

equal to a pound, are equal to one another,'


of an indefinite
sitions,

number of

similar self-evident propo*

which are described by saying that

things

which are equal to the same thing are equal to one


another
;

'

but which do not require to be deduced


in
is,

from such general description


certain.

order to

make them
possible.

Such a deduction

no doubt,

10

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


may,
if I

[part

i.

I
*

please, say,

'

things which are equal,

&c/

Two

hundred and forty pence and twenty

shillings

are things which are equal, &c.,' 'therefore they are

equal to each other.'

But such a syllogism would


all

be as frivolous as Mr. Mill supposes


to
is is

syllogisms

be

and

for this reason, viz. that the conclusion

quite as obvious

and certain as the premiss which


it.

introduced to prove
It
is

conceivable, of course, that the axioms at


;

the basis of knowledge are incapable of classification


that

no two of them have anything

in

common except

the fact that they are ultimate.

In such an event

the business of philosophy will be to enumerate,


instead of describing them.

But

this

can hardly be
philosophy
speaking,

the case with


of deduction

modes of
is

inference.

The

already,

comparatively

complete

and though the same cannot be said of


it is

any other mode of inference,


that the
differs in

difficult to believe

bond connecting premises and conclusion


every case, so as to exclude the possibility

of classification.

Something very

distantly approachif

ing this state of things would exist

each depart-

ment of knowledge had a mode of reasoning peculiar to itself, as some have supposed, e.g;, theology to
have.

To
their

classify inferences

is

to exhibit
is

what

is

called

common
is

form.

And

it

plain that

if

of two

inferences,

which by
false

classification

have the same

form, one

and the other

true, the classification

CHAP

I.]

ON THE IDEA OF A PHILOSOPHY.


is

ii

which connects them

philosophically worthless.
in

There would be no use


stance,

deductive
*

logic, for in'

some syllogisms worthy and others not.


if

in

Barbara

were

trust-

It follows

from

this

very obvious remark that


to be philosophical,

every kind of

logic, if

it is

must

be formal.

The whole

object of a philosophy of
valid

inference being to

distinguish

and ultimate

inferences from those which are invalid or derivative, this

can only be done either by exhibiting the


or forms of such inferences, or (on the

common form

violent hypothesis that they

have no common forms)


instance.

by enumerating every concrete


ciate

To

enun-

a form of inference which

shall include both

valid

and invalid examples, can


interest;

at best only
it

have a
is

psychological
misleading.

philosophically,
will

only

These remarks
to

be found of imtheories of

portance

when we come

consider

inference other than syllogistic ones.

The same remark


any

applies, mutatis mutandis^ to

classification of ultimate propositions.

There

is

no ground 'a priori'

(i.e.

following

from the idea of a philosophy) for supposing that


ultimate judgments
ticular.

are
if

all

general
latter,

or

all

par-

Of course,

they are the

there must

be some legitimate mode of reasoning from particulars


I

without the help of general propositions.


I

have now, shortly and incompletely, but

hope

at sufficient length for

my

purpose, sketched out the

12

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

i.

form to which any reasonable system of belief must

be capable of being reduced.


in the

What
is

desire to

do
far

remainder of

this

essay

to

examine how

not
and

certainly every creed current

among manby educated


of

kind, nor even those which are accepted


civilised

men, but

the vast system


;

modern
This
is

physical science conforms to this standard.

only a fragment of the whole subject


if

but even

this,

pursued

in

detail,

would demand volumes

for its
inti-

complete treatment, not to speak of an author

mately acquainted with the methods and results of


every one of the sciences.
of the kind
is
I

need not say that nothing


I

aimed
they
;

at here.

propose to deal only


all

with the roots, so to speak, from which

sciences,
ulti-

however
but

far

may
;

spread their branches,


special to

mately spring

roots which are


to
all

no

science,

common

and even of
limited,
I I

this subject,

so

limited

and doubly
end

shall

not attempt a
it

complete treatment, though


ficient for the

trust

may be

suf-

in view.

Now,

there are several

ways

in
;

which the subject


all

so sketched out might be attacked


as abstract reason
is

of them, so far

concerned, equally legitimate.

We
it

might begin,

for

example, by taking science as

stands,

and tracing back each particular thread


till

of argument

we

arrived at the unproved and unit

provable belief on which

must ultimately depend.


to carry
it

Such a method would be complete, but

out would require a writer with a great deal of

CHAP.

I.]

ON THE IDEA OF A PHILOSOPHY.

13

knowledge and a reader with a great deal of


Again,

time.

we might

attempt to
all

find,

by a process of

mere

casual exploration,

the axioms which are

really self-evident,

and

all

the processes of inference


far

which are obviously sound, and then see how

dogmatic structure resting on them could be made


to

harmonise with the received body of the sciences.


is,

This method of procedure


could be
fore

however, too unsysteif it

matic to be likely to produce good results, even

made

to produce

any

results at all

thereless

incline to the

more convenient, though

ambitious plan, of starting with the clearest and most


plausible
scientific

statement of the most ordinary view of


philosophy, and seeing

how

far this will

carry us towards the goal


this fails us,
it

we

desire to reach.

When

will

then be time to examine what help

can be derived from other and less popular systems.

Now, the most ordinary view


sophy
it
I

of scientific philo-

take to be this

that science, in so far as

consists of a statement of the laws of

phenomena,
not

is

founded entirely on observation and experiment

that observation

and experiment,

in fact, furnish

only the occasions of scientific discovery, but also the


sole evidence of scientific truth,

evidence, however,
of science not only

which

is

considered by most

men

amply
large

sufficient,

but also as good as any which can


Considering, however, what a

be well imagined.

number

of persons there are


all

who suppose

themselves to derive

their

knowledge from these

\
14

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


it

[part

i.

sources,

is

somewhat remarkable
information
this feat is to

that

we

should
precise

have so

little

respecting the

method by which
first sight,

be accomplished. At

indeed, the problem

may

not seem a hard

one.

We

are

constantly drawing inferences from

experience by methods which do not appear to be

very abstruse
to

and

all

that

it

may seem

necessary
to

do

is

to extend the operation of these

methods

the utmost limits of knowledge

to

prove, in other

words, the most general propositions respecting the


course of Nature in exactly the same manner as
are accustomed to prove the

we
by

more

limited truths

which we guide our daily

life.

Whether
which
I

this

is

possible or not
in

is

the point

propose to examine
I

the next section.

And

in

doing so

cannot pursue a more convenient

course than to take as

my

text Mr. Mill's

'

Logic,'
in

which professes to solve


affirmative sense.

this initial

problem

an

CHAP.

II.]

EMPIRICAL LOGIC.

15

CHAPTER

II.

EMPIRICAL LOGIC.
There are two points of view from -which any system of logic may be criticised. We may consider, first, how far it gives a satisfactory account of those
methods of inference with which
and, secondly,
it

professes to deal
in the

how

far

it is

complete

sense of
first

dealing with

all

methods of

inference.

The

of

these conditions, of course, every logic which

is

worth

anything must

satisfy.

Mr. Mill challenges criticism


also.

under the second head


that he has told us
all

He

considers not only

about some modes of inference,


all

but that he has told us


course,

about

all

all,

that
if

is,

of

which are legitimate; so that

we

only

master his book,

we

shall

be acquainted with every

method by which mediate truths are or can be derived


from those which are immediate. This completeness of range
ever,
is

not attained, how-

by adding on new methods

to those

which have

already been reduced to system, but rather by bringing forward one single method, and announcing that
all

others are either modifications of this or are not


all.

concerned with inference at

It is in this last

way

i6

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


I

[part

i.

that Mr. Mill disposes of the syllogism.

have too
he quotes

great a regard for him, and attach too great weight


to the formidable
list

of authorities

whom

as witnesses to

its

truth

and importance,

to treat his

celebrated speculation on this subject in anything but

a serious
that
it

spirit.

At

the

same

time,

must confess

appears to

me

to originate in a misuse of lan-

guage, and to end in an important philosophic error.

This doctrine, discovered by Mr. Mill and applauded by Sir John Herschel and Professor Bain,
is,

on

its

negative side, this

There can be no inference


in

from the premises of a syllogism, because

the
is

major premiss there

is

already asserted what

afterwards asserted in the conclusion.

Now, when a
on
ing
it

logician puts

any mode of inference


does
is

its trial,
it,

he has to decide two questions concernI

and, so far as

can see, only two.


is

First,

involve a progress from what

known

to

what

not

known
is is

(the answer to this question decides


is

whether it
if is

or

not a

mode
?

of inference). Secondly,

there

a progress from the known to the unknown,


(the answer to this quesis legiti-

that progress justified

tion decides

whether the mode of inference


first

mate).
;

The

question

is,

so to speak, a question of

Fact the second question


in the case of the

is

one of Law. Now, taking


first,

Syllogism the second question

no one has everthought of denying that if,


there
is

in that form,

any inference

at

all,

it is

legitimate.

The

conclusion

may

not be inferred from the premises

CHAP.

II.]

EMPIRICAL LOGIC.
rate, if these are true, it is true.

17

but, at

any

So
is

that

the only question that remains to be decided

the

question of

fact.

Do

we, as a matter of

we employ do know or
affirmative
himself,

a syllogism, ever proceed from


think

we know

to

when what we what we do not know ?


fact,

This question can certainly only be answered


;

in the

and, indeed,

it

is

so answered by Mill

at least

by

implication.^

But, says Mr.

Mill,^ are

we warranted

in

'as-

serting a general proposition without having satisfied

ourselves of the truth of everything which


?
'

it

fairly includes

Supposing we give the expected


not

answer,

and agree that we are then Mr. Mill would go on to say


to allowing that

warranted,

this is equivalent

premiss unless

we ought not we are already


included
'

to assert

any major

acquainted with the


is

conclusion, because the conclusion

undoubtedly

something

'

fairly

in

the major premiss

and

it

is

absurd to say that a truth which

we must
be conif it

know

before

we can
it.

assert another truth can


this
I

cluded from
true that

To

reply, that

even

be

miss
that

we have no right to assert unless we previously believe


as, in

the major prethe conclusion,

is

not a matter with which logic has any concern.


point of
first

So long

fact,

we

do assert the major

premiss without
will the latter

believing the conclusion, so long

be an inference from the former, and

so long will the syllogism be the formal statement of


^

Logic, vol.

i.

p. 206.

"^

Ibid. vol.

i.

p. 207.

i8

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

i.

that inference.
at

Granted that a major premiss arrived


if it is ar-

by any process which does not independently


is

prove the conclusion


rived
at, it is in

illegitimate,

still,

no way prevented by the illegitimacy


premises,

of

its

origin from being the basis of a real inference,


in

and of one which,


correct.

relation

to

its

is

So

far,

then,

it

appears to

me
this

that

on

his

own

data Mr. Mill uses misleading language about the


functions of the syllogism
;

but

if

was

all, I

should

not so long have troubled the reader about the matter.


If

the controversy turned


'

simply on whether
or the

we

should use the word

infer

'

word

interpret/

whether we should talk of 'drawing a conclusion

from

'

or of

drawing a conclusion according


left

to,'

formula, the matter might be


cians,

to professed logi-

with only this recommendation

that

if

they
it

decide in each case on the second alternative,

would be well

to revise the

common

definition of the

word

infer.'

The
amount

really important thing

which gives a certain


Mill's theory of
all

of plausibility to Mr.
is
;

the

syllogism
particulars

the doctrine that

inference
in

is

from

and

this is

mixed up

such a manner
I

with

the

general

argument which
a
sort

have been
idea
that

discussing above, that careless readers carry away,


I

am

convinced,

of

general

it

follows

from

taking the correct

mean Mr.

Mill's

view

by

which they

of the functions of the

CHAP.

II.]

EMPIRICAL LOGIC.

19

syllogism.

The

truth

is

that Mr. Mill's criticism


it

of the ordinary theory of the syllogism, where


is

not merely verbal, so far from proving this doc-

trine,

depends on

it

for its

whole

effect.

Supposing

we know any

general proposition with the same im-

mediate certainty that

we know any

of the particular

propositions which serve as a foundation for Induction,

then,

if it

is
it

formally possible to
I

make any
suppose, be

deductions from

at all (which will not,

denied), one of these things

must be true

either by
we
or
;*

the mere act of knowing the general proposition

know
else

'everything which

it

fairly includes,' so that'


is

the deduction, though possible,

superfluous

we

can proceed by the syllogistic process from

something we know to something we do not know,

and

which,

method.

may Now, the


it

be,

can

be arrived at by

no other

first

of these alternatives certainly


I

cannot be proved, and


exaggeration that
it is

think

may

affirm without
;

extravagantly absurd

we are,
in

therefore, reduced to the second alternative,


effect

which

amounts

to this

that,

on a certain supposition

respecting the nature of our ultimate premises, the

syllogism would not only be a

mode

of inference, but

would be a formal statement of the only mode of


inference which
it

would be

in

our power to use.

The

substantial part, in short, of Mills attack


this,

on the syllogism amounts to


case where

that

in

every

we deduce

a conclusion from a general


c 2

proposition, the ultimate grounds for our believing

20

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


is

[part

i.

that conclusion

a process of inference by which

both the general proposition and the conclusion can

be co-ordinately proved on the doctrine that


doctrine, as held
I

and

this
is

again

is

founded

all

inference

from particulars.

Before following out this important philosophic

by Mr.

Mill, to

some

of

its results,

have three general remarks to make on


it

it.

Firstly,

whether

be

true or untrue,

it

does not
it

lie

within

the province of Logic either to prove


it.
'

or to assume
:

As

Mr. Mill himself very properly remarks


with their number or nature
least, has, in

With the
a direct

original data or ultimate premises of our


;
.

knowledge
in

logic,
I

way at

the sense in which

conceive the science, nothing to do.

These questions
all,

are partly not a subject of science at


that of a very different science.'^

and partly
impossible

In the second place,


it is

whether the doctrine be true or untrue,


in

any general way to prove


a

it.

It is possible

no doubt

man to go over all his beliefs in turn, and find to his own satisfaction that whenever they are not immefor
diate,

they are ultimately inferred from particulars


is

but he can hardly show that this


racteristic

a necessary cha-

of

all

conclusions.
it

Something would be

done

in this direction if

could be proved that there

was no

method known by which inferences could be drawn from general propositions unfortunately, it seems at present easier to show this
satisfactory

of particular ones.
^

Logic, vol.

i.

p. 6.

CHAP.

II.]

EMPIRICAL LOGIC.
remark
is,

21

My third

that

if

the views on ethics

expressed in the Appendix are correct, the whole of

our morality must be deduced from general propositions which are not,

and which cannot


particulars. Mill's

be,

themin-

selves inferences

from

To
is

ethical

ferences, therefore,

Mr.

theory

altogether

inapplicable.

Let

us,

however, assume with Mr. Mill that

all

our knowledge springs ultimately from


experiences,

particular

and that there

is

therefore but

one

fundamental type of inference

namely,

inference

from particulars
rules has
far in

by

'

simple enumeration'

what
is

he to give us by which we

may judge how


inferring

any given case the operation of


?

legitimately performed

We should

expect before-

hand thatWn a work on

logic, consisting of

two large
view of

volumes, and founded on this

particular

inference, the systematic account of such rules

would

form a considerable

part.

This

is

not
is

so.

What
up

Mr. Mill has to say on the subject

scattered

and down

his book, chiefly in connection with certain

concrete examples, and must be collected for pur-

poses of criticism from these


singular

so that

we have

the

phenomenon
in
is

of a

work professing

to treat

mainly of inference,
inference

which the universal type of


!

treated of only incidentally

How
mode by

this

comes about most of


:

my

readers are

probably already aware

it

is

which, according to

known that the Mr. Mill, we arrive at


well

22

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


is

[part

i.

a law of nature
*

by discovering, through one of the


that

Four Methods,'

is

causally connected in a
then,

particular instance with B,

and

by

virtue of the

law of universal causation, extending


to other times

this discovery

and other places

the general pro-

position expressing the law of causation being thus

the major premiss of the syllogism by which the

discovery

is

established.
truths,

Omitting the case of mathematical


have, therefore,
*

we

hardly any cause to employ the


'

universal type

of reasoning, except for the pur-

pose of proving the law of universal causation.


since this
is

But

not only the most important but also

the most

perfect

example of

its

application,

we

cannot do better than follow Mr. Mill's (from some


points of view rather singular) course, and examine
it

chiefly in this connection.

The
on
its

first

important thing to note

is

that the

legitimacy of this sort of reasoning does not depend


form.

Without going the length of Mr.

Mill,

and asserting that inference from


can be formally cogent,

particulars never

we may safely say

that as yet
it

neither Mr. Mill nor any one else has


is

shown how

to

be made so. Now, to say that

the legitimacy of any piece of


its

reasoning does not depend on


as saying that,
if

form

is

the
is

same

you want to know


fact

if it

correct,

you must determine the


considerations.
If
(to

by means of extraneous
in

put the matter

a more

GHAP.

II.]

EMPIRICAL LOGIC.

23

concrete way) a particular

mode

of reasoning gives
similar

me
and

A
D

as an inference from B,

and a precisely

mode

gives

me C

as an inference from
true), then,

(both

being supposed to be
or, at

if I

find that
I

is

not true,

any

rate, is

not proved,

must

have some other reason


than that
it is

for believing

to

be true

inferred from

in exactly the
is

same

manner
let

as

was from B.

So much

plain.

Now

us apply these general remarks to the particular

case of the

Law The Law of

of Universal Causation.

Universal Causation
'

is

an inference
It

from particulars
has never

by simple enumeration.'

has
;

been found a certain number of times to be true


it it

(I
I

allow this for the sake of argument),


say,

has never,

been known to be
I

false.

This

is

the statement, and as far as


statement, of
rests.^

can judge the complete


it

the inductive argument on which

But

if

we

trust as a rule to this


shall,'

same inducdistin-

tive argument,
grossly.'
It is

*we

says Mill,

in general err

clear therefore that

we must

guish the correct argument by which the

Law

of

Causation

is

proved from the incorrect arguments


;

which

it

exactly resembles

and

this

it

is

equally

clear can only

be done by means of considerations to


itself.

be found outside of the argument


these considerations
?

What

are

They can be seen on page 102 of the second volume of the Logic,' and may be paraphrased somewhat in the following way
*
:

Vol.

ii.

p. 102.

24

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


Certain sequences

[part

i.

may be

observed to be con-

stant

and invariable within

limits which,

compared
hazardous

with the total range of time and space open to

human
to

observation, are restricted.

It is

assume that these sequences


in

will

obtain

much

beyond the sphere


to

which they have been observed

be

true,

because they

may be

the result not of


'

direct causation but of

an arrangement, or
this

collo-

cation

'

of causes

and

arrangement, and con-

sequently

its effects,

may

only exist within the limits


If,

where

it

has been observed.

however,

we

sup-

pose the sphere in which

we have observed
total

such a
in pro-

sequence to
portion as
to
it

be gradually extended, then,


approaches to the

range open

human

observation, in that proportion will the

observed sequence approach the certainty and universality of a law of nature, until ultimately the

two

become

indistinguishable.

This

is

the case with the

Law

of Causation.
the objection that has to be
is

Now

made

to this

method of proof
tion at issue.

that

it

assumes the whole ques-

The

distinction

between sequences

which are the

result of direct causation

and sequences

which depend on the collocation of causes, has no meaning unless we assume a universe governed by
causation
;

and the existence of such a universe

is

the very thing

we want

to demonstrate.

Grant

all

that Mr. Mill or Mr. Bain could desire

and a great
that at every

deal

more than could be proved

grant

CHAP.

II.]

EMPIRICAL LOGIC.

25

time and in every place throughout that very Hmited


portion of time and space open to

human observation

every event has had a cause, and every cause has

been always followed by the same event, we should


still

be no nearer proving that an inference founded


likely to

on these particulars was more


than an inference

be accurate

founded on any other particu-

between the two assumed a universe of the very kind we wished to


lars, so long as the only distinction

prove.
tinction

And

this

is

precisely
It is

what Mr.
in
;

Mill's dis-

does assume.

dangerous

an ordinary
but

way

(he says) to infer from particulars


safely
if

we may

do so

our induction

is

sufficiently wide.

And
we

why

Because

we

shall

then be sure that what

have observed
causation.

is

not due to chance or the accidental

collocation of causes, but to the direct operation of

This

is

doubtless a most excellent canon

of criticism, and one which

may
'

enable us to judge

of the worth of
ation.'
it

many

inferences

by simple enumerand that


the

There

is,

however, one such inference which


of,
is

can never enable us to judge


of Causation
itself.

Law
ment
basis

This expedient
in

for placing the empirical argu-

favour of the uniformity of nature on a sure


rather clumsy, but the truth
it is
is,

may seem
for

that,
it

though not good,

as

good

as

any other which

was possible
For
in

Mr.

Mill, with his

views about the

sources of knowledge, to suggest.

a general

way we may

lay

it

down

that

26

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

i.

by informal inference we mean inference of which the truth cannot be discovered from the form, any attempt to prove a conclusion by means of such
since
inference, can only tive in

be made even apparently


:

effec-

one of three ways

Firstly,

we may

distin-

guish the legitimate from the illegitimate application


of the
itself

method by means of some


by
that method.

principle

which

is

arrived at

This
less

is

Mr.

Mill's

device,

and involves a more or


a
circle.

obvious argu-

ment
other

in

Or, secondly, our principle of dis-

tinction

may be given either a priori, or by some mode of inference. This plan, though common
is

enough,

of course

inconsistent

with

empirical

philosophy, at any rate as conceived by Mr. Mill.

Or, thirdly,

we may adopt no
all,

extraneous principle of

distinction at

but simply affirm that of two similar

cases of inferences

we

perceive one to be cogent


'
,

and the other


I

not.

am
it

not aware that any philosopher has forlast expedient.

mally adopted this


ever,
is

In reality, how-

hardly to be distinguished from those


particular experiences
*

theories according to which

are the occasions of our forming

intuitive

'

judg-

ments.

It is true that in
'

the one case the particular


reasons,'

experiences are called


*

and

in

the other
first

occasions,'

and that a system founded on the


But except
in the

would be
second
is
'

called 'empirical,'

and one founded on the

intuitional/

names there
For

no important difference between the two.

CHAP.

II.]

EMPIRICAL LOGIC.

27

why

are

we

to accept the conclusion supposed to


*

be

proved by the

reasons
?

'

Because of the cogency


at
all.

of the reasoning

Not

Precisely similar

reasoning from
leads to
*

equally true

premises

frequently

gross error.'
if

We
I

accept this example of


it,

reasoning,

we do
in

accept

in exactly
to, certain
it

the

same

way

as,

by the
;

theories

allude

judgments

are accepted

the one case


to

is

the reasoning
intuition,

which

is

known

be valid by a special
the judgment.

and

in the other
It

it is

would

not, therefore,

have been open

to

Mr.

Mill to take this view of the proof

by which the
proof
'

Law

of Causation
in form,

is

established.
'

It is in reality,
' ;

though not
anxious
is

an

intuitional

and so

he to be free from any

taint of

intuitivism,'

that of the chapter nominally devoted to proving the


law, he has thought
to disproving the
*

it

expedient to devote a quarter


'

intuitive

proofs of other people

and

if

the reader will refer to the early part of that

chapter he will see that Mr. Mill's dialectic would be


quite as effective against the particular intuitional
doctrine, which, as
I

have explained above,


it

lies

con-

cealed under an empirical disguise, as

is

against

those more usual and orthodox theories with which

we

are familiar.

In the foregoing attack on Mr.


inference, in so far, at least, as
it is

Mill's

view of

applied to the
I

proof of the law of universal causation,

have said

nothing which, as

imagine, has not, in one shape

28

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


itself to

[part

i.

or another, suggested
logic.

many

students of his

But

am

anxious to explain that the fact of


for criticism implies a recognition of

singling

him out

his merits

even more than of

his defects.
is

If his

empirical view of the universe


attack,
it

peculiarly easy to
is

is

not because his method of proof

less

satisfactory than that of other empirical philosophers,

but because he saw more clearly, or at any rate

allowed his readers to see more


that

clearly,

what

it

was

had

to

be proved, and the only method by which,


data,
If

on purely empirical
proof was possible.
failed completely),
in
it

even the semblance of


failed

he

(and

think he

was because he attempted what,


I

the present state of our knowledge, cannot,

believe, be accomplished.
It
is

impossible
if

to

deny that science

is

only
;

possible
that,
if

we assume

the law of universal causation

observation and experiment be the sole foun-

dation of knowledge, the law of universal causation

must be proved from


stated

particulars

that Mr. Mill has

(or, if you please, has avoided stating) the method of proof from particulars as ingeniously as

and that his statement (or want of statement) cannot in reality stand for a
;

can well be imagined

moment

against hostile criticism.


I

The most
I

impor-

tant of these points

have proved, as

think, in the
I

course of the preceding remarks, the rest of them

hope the reader


therefore,

will

admit without proof

and

now,

go on

to show, in a few words, that

even

CHAP.

II.]

EMPIRICAL LOGIC.
were
it

29

if

legitimate inference from particulars

possible,
is

and the law of causation were proved,

by no

means the adequate foundation for the superstructure of science which Mr. Mill, and those who accept Mr.
Mill's general line of thought,

appear to imagine.

30

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

i.

CHAPTER
INDUCTION.

III.

Admitting then

that the course of nature

is

regular,

and that every event has an antecedent upon which follows, and a consequent which init invariably
variably follows
it,

the question

still

remains,

how

are the real members of these sequences to be dis-

covered

How

can

we

single out the causes which

produce any given

effect

and the
?

effects

which are

produced by any given cause


(and
it

Mr. Mill would say

will again,

think, prove a convenient course

to begin the discussion

by examining
'

his opinion)

that the discovery

must be made by the employment

of one of his well-known

Four Methods.'
it

To

see

how

far the assertion

is

correct,

will only

be neces-

sary to quote two of them

the

first

and the second.


in

They run

as follows

If

any instance

which the

phenomenon
cumstance
only
in the in

under investigation
it

occurs,

and an
cir-

instance in which

does not occur, have every

common
;

save one, that one occurring

former

the circumstance in which alone


is

the two instances differ

the

effect,

or the cause, or

an indispensable part of the cause of the pheno-

CHAP.

III.]

INDUCTION.
'

31

And If two or more instances of the menon/ phenomenon under investigation have only one circumstance in common, the circumstance in which
alone
all

the instances agree

is

the cause (or effect)

of the given phenomenon.'

For the
difference
its

first

of these methods

the

method of

Mr.
is

Mill claims that a single instance of


sufficient to

application
;

prove a general law of

nature

and

in

a certain sense no doubt the claim


It
if
it

may be

allowed.

would certainly prove a general


could be applied
;

law of nature

is

but then

it

unfortunately never can be applied^

The

state of

the universe

never the same at two successive


Simultaneously

instants in every particular but one.

with the change falling under the special notice of


the observer, or
(if it

be a case of experiment)

in-

troduced into the phenomena by the experimenter,


there occur countless changes which he neither

knows
all

of nor produces, and which,

for

anything that the

canon

tells

us to the contrary,

may

each or

of

them be the cause of the subsequent


parallel objection

effect.

method

that of

may be brought against the second agreement. As Mr. Mill himself


method can never by a
single

explains at length, this

application prove a case of causation, owing to the


fact that the

same
;

effect is often
if

produced by more

than one cause

so that, even

two instances of a
*

phenomenon' have only one circumstance


mon, there
is

in

com-

a probability, but only a probability.

32

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


is

[part

i.

that that circumstance

the cause (or effect) of that


it

phenomenon.
instances of a

But has

ever occurred that two

phenomenon have only one circum?

stance in

common
is

We

may

safely reply, never.


difference,

As

in

the case of the


vitiated

method of

the

reasoning

by the

fact that

the universe
in

never

differs in

two successive moments

only one
fails,

particular,

so the

method of agreement
two successive

not

only for the reason given by Mr. Mill, but because


the
universe,
at

moments, never
neither the one
select-

agrees in only one particular.

And

canon nor the other shows us any grounds for


ing from

among

the countless points of difference or


is

agreement that one which


of which
I

the cause or the effect

we

are in search.
this objection as against Mill,
it

have stated

but

it

must not be supposed that

has only weight

against Mr. Mill's statement of the law of induction.


It is

equally applicable to the ordinary version of

the means whereby

obtain knowledge by experiment and observation, of which view, indeed, Mr.


Mill merely attempts a systematic exposition.
If

we

we man swallow the contents of a phial, and immediately fall down dead, we conclude that his death is
see a

the consequence of what he has drunk

and we do

so undoubtedly on the grounds stated in the canon of the Method of Difference. All other circumstances seemed to remain the

same except these


and
his

twohis drinking the

liquid

death

we

CHAR

III.]

INDUCTION.
them
off as

33

therefore pair

cause and

effect.

The
must

smallest reflection, however, shows that there

have been an

indefinite

number

of events which,

like the drinking of the liquid,

immediately preceded
not so plain
in
is

the death of the


principle

man what is which may justify us


;

*the

assuming, that
effect,

though they are antecedents of the

they are

no part of

its

cause.

Now

there are two

ways
It

in

which

this difficulty

or ambiguity in the ordinary version of inductive

reasoning

may be

met.

may,

in the first place,

be asserted, that by previous observation or experi-

ment we may, and commonly


fidence to select

do, arrive at

some

conclusions which enable us with

more or less confrom among the phenomena which


it.

precede an event the one which produced


example,

For
and

we know
in small

that there are

many drugs which


;

taken even

doses produce instant death

this is a consideration

which materially influences us


I

in affirming, in the case


tion, that

have just used

for illustra-

the drinking of the contents of the phial,

and the sudden death of the man, were not mere


coincidences, but
tion.

were events connected by causait

But though

may be

admitted that

in fact

we do

thus habitually use our knowledge of the

general laws of nature to guide us in the interpretation of particular observations or experiments, this
is

no justification of inductive methods

in the abstract,

3ince these general laws of nature must,

on any

ern-

34

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

i.

pirical theory, in the first instance

themselves have

been arrived at by induction.


that, unless

It is therefore plain

we
all

are

doomed

to

wander

in

an endless

logical circuit,

some inductions must be

valid which

derive, or at

events require, no support from any

extraneous authority.

We turn
what
in this

then to the second possible solution of

the difficulty, which might be stated perhaps some-

in error

Mr. Mill (it might be said) is way when he supposes that one properly con:

'

ducted experiment can prove a law of nature, even


if

the

method employed be the


In
all

"

Method of
If

Differ-

ence."

cases of induction

we

can do no more

than prove a certain law to be probable.


servations or experiments be
ful,
if

our ob-

numerous and successa very high one


;

the probability proved

may be

they are few and ambiguous,

slight

one

but in either case

may be a very what we prove is


it

probability

and probability alone.


If
still

This, however,

need cause us no uneasiness.


certainty
is

demonstrative

denied

us,

we may
life.'

by

this

method
require

obtain that practical certainty which


to guide us in the affairs of

is all

we

This,

imagine,

is

the

opinion

of Professor
'

Jevons, elaborated at
ciples

of Science.'

some length in The PrinThat work has no pretension


since,
if
I

to

be a complete philosophy of science,


it it

understand

rightly,

the uniformity of nature

is

assumed

in

without proof, as a necessary condi-

CHAP. HI.]

INDUCTION.
;

35

tion of inductive enquiry

but, this

assumption once
arrive at a
facts of

granted, the further steps

by which we
it

knowledge of the laws of nature from the


nature are given in detail, so that
is

directly con-

cerned with the subject-matter of

this chapter.

Now
Jevons
is

it

can hardly be doubted that Professor

correct in saying that

arrive at nothing better


in
is

by induction we can than probability and that


;

consequence a study of the theory of probability


a necessary and most important part of the phi-

losophy of science.

But

his

enthusiasm for

this

branch of the subject carries him perhaps rather


further than sober reason warrants.

Because, apart
little,

from the logic of chance


to suppose that, aided

we

can do

he seems

by the

logic of chance,

we

can do everything.

The

universe appears to him

like a gigantic ballot-box,

from which the

scientific

observer occupies himself in drawing and replacing


black and white balls
;

and because the resources

of the calculus would enable the drawer to deter-

number of draws, the chances of the next ball being black or white, even when the number of the balls in the box is infinite, he apmine, after any

pears to suppose that a similar procedure will enable


the experimenter to foretell the probability of a future

event from a study of the sequences and co-existences


of

phenomena
It

in the past.

may be

doubted, however,

how far

the universe

can be fairly assumed to resemble a ballot-box, even P 3

36

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

i.

though the
infinite.

size of the hypothetical ballot-box


it

be

And

is

still

more open

to

question

whether a legitimate application of the theory of


probability will permit us to hold scientific beliefs

with anything like the certainty which


attach to them, even granting
all

men of science

the premises which

they are in the habit of claiming.

Let

us, in

order to

make

this perfectly clear, ex-

amine a hypothetical case of induction, which we

may make

as

favourable as

we

choose.

Let us
has been
(if

imagine that two phenomena,


frequent occurrence
;

and

B, are of very

that

whenever

observed

please) that

has invariably followed it, and whenever B has been observed


it.

you
has

invariably been found to precede

Let us further

suppose that the connection between the two has

been proved both by the 'method of difference'

and

'the method

of

agreement,'

with as

much

completeness as anything can be proved by these

means.

Then, granting the principle of the uniis

formity of nature, what probability

there that

when next
it ?

shall occur

will

be found to follow

It

is

evident that unless this probability be

very high, amounting indeed almost to practical certainty, then,

either the confidence with

which we

the laws of nature is greatly exaggerated (since no law can have better experimental evidence than that which connects and

commonly regard

B), or else

some considerations not supplied by the

CHAP.

III.]

INDUCTION.

37

principle of the uniformity of nature, or the logic of


induction,
It

have been omitted from the proof.


admitted at once
that, In

may be

a world which

we assume
sequence of

to

be governed by law, the invariable

B on

is

a proof that there

is

probably

some

causal link, direct or indirect, between them.


it is

In other words,
coincidence
is

very unlikely that this constant


precise

the

work of chance. What the

numerical value of this probability

may be
It

it is

not

easy to determine, but undoubtedly


large
;

would be very

and as we are

at liberty to imagine as

many
it

coincidences as

we

please,

we may

consider
it

as

practically infinite.

This being granted,

would
most

seem
next
this

to follow that, in a uniform world, the

confident expectation might be entertained that

when

A
is,

appeared,
as
I

It

would be succeeded by B, and


It,

understand
it

the opinion of Mr. Mill


is

and Mr. Jevons, as


ordinary

certainly

the opinion of

common

sense.

It is not,

however, a con-

clusion which can be legitimately

drawn from the

premises provided for us by inductive philosophy, as


the following considerations will show.

The
precedes

fact

that in our experience

invariably

gives a certain probability In favour of

being causally connected with B.


all

But

it

gives

no probability at
cause of B.

in

favour of
that
is

A
we

being the whole


are acquainted

Every cause

with

is

complex.

But there

no process whatever
it is.

by which we can show how complex

Mr. Mill

38

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


is

[parti.

says somewhere that induction


nation
;

a process of elimiis

but he gives no method, and there


all

no

method, for eliminating

the

phenomena which
it

do not co-operate with

when

produces B.

Of

course

it

is

easy to take two cases of

and

occurring,

and

to say that the circumstances in

which the two cases differed cannot be necessary


for the production of

B by A.

But
it is

this assertion

must be

carefully qualified before

accepted.

If

we

could conceive the second case of


first

occurring to

be precisely similar to the


particulars, then, since

case except in certain


it is

follows both times,

plain

of course that these particulars are not necessary for the production of B.

But no such inference can be

made

if

the

first

case of

A occurring has some circumhas not.


It

stances which the second has not, while the second

has some which the

first

may be

that

these exceptional circumstances, though different in

each case, were in each case necessary, and that without them

B would

in neither case
will
:

have followed.
if

This piece of reasoning

perhaps be clearer
(i)

put in a more symbolic form

A happens twice,
The
a,
first

and

is

each time followed by B.


it

time
c;

it

happens

is it

accompanied only by
happens
it

b,

the

second time
X, y, z.
c, X, y,

is

accompanied only by
a, b,

It is

impossible to infer from this that


in the

were not essential factors

production

of B.

{2)

A happens twice

and

is

each time followed

by

B.

The first time it happens

it is

accompanied only

'

CHAP.

III.]

INDUCTION.

39

by

a, b, c.

panied

The second time it happens it is accomonly by b, c. From this It may be inferred with
Is

certainty that a

not necessary to the production of

B.

Now

It

Is

evident that the canon of elimination

which could be deduced from these two examples,

though logically
practice.

perfect,

can never be applied in


'

It is like
If

Mr.
it

Mill's

method of

difference

admirable

only

could be used.

Unfortunately

we know only an Infinitesimal fraction of the phenomena which accompany any cause, and even to this fraction the above canon can never be made to fit.
It invariably
it

happens that the second time

occurs

will

be accompanied by some things which did not


It

co-exist with

before,

and

will not

be accompanied
It

by some things which did


in the first of the
Is

co-exist with

before.

It

therefore occurs under the circumstances mentioned

above formulas, and no Inference


its

possible respecting the share which any of


in the

ac-

companiments have
But
assert
it

production of B.

may be

said,

'

though

it Is

impossible to

positively

which of the phenomena accomone of these phenomena only

panying
B,
still

A
If

are not necessary for the production of

we

find

occurring once In conjunction with

out of the
surely assert

many
in the

times in which
all

A
it

occurs,

we may

that In

probability

was

on that occasion no factor

production of

B.'

It is

not necessary for


it

my

purpose to dispute

this

whether

could be successfully disputed or no.

40

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


it

[part

i.

For
of

leaves altogether unsolved the further problem

how we

are to dispose of these

are always to be found in


fixed stars, for example.

phenomena which company with A the

On
?

what

principle are

we

to say that these are not necessary to

in

order

that

B may be produced
?

What is to be our method


is

of elimination here

It

cannot evidently be experi-

ment, because in this respect every experiment


identical.

For the same reason


It
;

it

cannot be obser-

vation.

can be no deduction from the theory of


the ballot-box gives us no assistance
sense,
;

probability

and common
which
does
if it

which quietly ignores the

diffi-

culty, furnishes us
it

with no hint as to the principle on

so.

Now

be admitted, as

in

theory

think

it

must be admitted, that every phenomenon which has always accompanied A is as likely as not to be an
essential part of the cause of

it

appears to follow

that our expectation that

will in the future follow

A must depend in part on our expectation that each of the phenomena which have always accompanied A
will

do so again.

But these phenomena are

in

number

infinite.

We

know, or might know, thousands of

them

yet those

we know

are entirely lost in the

vast multitude of those which

we do not know, but which we have every reason to believe exist in the
infinity of space.

Because, therefore,

we

are unable

to eliminate the

accompaniments of

which are not


to

necessary for the production of B;

we have now

CHAP.

III.]

INDUCTION.

41

face the further difficulty of determining the proba-

biHty that these accompaniments of

will co-exist

with

it

in the future.

But

this

problem puts us back

precisely

into

the

trying to escape.
traverse exactly the

In order to solve

we were we have to same ground as we had when we


position from which
it,

were enquiring
of

into the

methods by which the causes

B were

to be discovered.
still

For a case of

persist-

ence (and of course


is in

more obviously of

recurrence)

reality a case of causation.

The
its

persistence of

the planet Mars, for example, through another year

depends upon causes of which

existence at this
?

moment

is

only one.

What

are these other causes

and what

is

the probability of their being in operation


?

for another year

These are the very questions we


trying to determine the

asked when

we were

method
con-

by which the antecedents of B might be discovered,


and
for

which we could find no answer.

The

tinued existence of the planet

Mars may, for anything we know to the contrary, depend upon the continued existence of the moon, a phenomenon

which, as far as our experience goes, has always coexisted with


it.

What

then

is
?

the probability of the

moon's continuing to exist


the

About

this precisely

same

series of questions
s^-mie

may be
of

asked, meeting
unsatisfactory

with precisely the


answers.
position.

series

So

that

we

find ourselves finally in this


if

Experiment and observation,

conducted

under favourable circumstances, can determine with

42

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

i.

a probability approaching to certainty, that a phenomenon A is causally connected with a phenomenon


B.

But neither experiment nor observation can give


multitude of
is

us the smallest information as to whether any of the


infinite

phenomena which accompany

whenever B
for

produced, are or are not necessary

parts of the cause of

nor can they

tell

us

exactly the

same reason

anything

and
it,

about the

probability of a single one of these

accompaniments

of A, however well

we may be
it

acquainted with
;

continuing to accompany

in the future

still

less

can they assist us in computing the chances of the


recurrence or persistence of those essential parts of

the cause of
bers, but of

B which may

exist in indefinite

numIn
is

which we know absolutely nothing.


that the course of nature

other

words granting

uniform, no scientific methods,


principle alone, can give us

by the help of

this

any assurance that the


ourselves to have

laws of nature, which

we suppose

discovered, will continue to operate in the future.

What
It
is

additional principle,

then,

must be

esta?

blished in order that this assurance

may be

obtained

evident in a general
it

way

that the principle,

whatever
tion
;

may
is,

be,

that

it

must be a principle of eliminamust enable us to eliminate from

among the innumerable antecedents of a phenomenon those which we may be certain have nothing whatever to do with
self altogether
its

occurrence.

But

confess

my-

unable to formulate such a principle,

CHAP.

III.]

INDUCTION.
to

43

much
and

less

prove

it.

There

is,

no doubt, a

practical

instinct,

common

both to the unscientific

to the scientific observer,

which induces men

to

ignore as

much

as possible the share which either

very remote or very permanent phenomena

may

have
are

in the

production of the effects for which they


to

trying

account.

Nobody,

for

example,

seriously imagines that the existence of a star in the

Milky
before

Way
it

is

a necessary concomitant to a spark

can explode a barrel of gunpowder.


it

On

the other hand, this instinct, though


that
it

is

so strong

is

not easy gravely to discuss


it,

any theory
be trusted.

flagrantly inconsistent with

can hardly be accurately

defined,

and

certainly

cannot always

The most distant


this planet
effect
;

object that has ever been perceived


effect
is

has had some appreciable

on the

affairs

of

since
if
is

its

perception

in itself

such an
sun,

and

we

consider permanence,

the

which has accompanied every phenomenon ever


experienced,

an essential and not very remote

link in the chain of causes,

by which

all

the events

that occur

on the surface of the globe are protherefore,

duced.
It
is

evident,

that the

difliculty of

proving the uniformity of nature, and the law of universal causation,


is

not the

only obstacle

which

stands in the

way

of a satisfactory empirical philo-

sophy.

Even granting
it is

the truth of

these great

principles,

not easy to frame with their help an

44

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

i.

inductive logic, which shall really enable us to argue


to

unobserved instances

and,

shall

show
it

in the

next chapter, could say the


least,

we prove such
complete

laws,

would, to
itself to

by no means be

sufficient

by

justify us in holding the


its

scientific

creed in

ordinary shape.

CHAP.

IV.]

HISTORICAL INFERENCE.

45

CHAPTER
The proper

IV.

HISTORICAL INFERENCE.
classification of the sciences is a subject

which has of

late

engaged the attention of


is,

scientific

philosophers, and

therefore,
is

it

need not be

said,

one about which there


of which

some

difference of opinion.

Into the minutiae of this controversy, the importance


is,

perhaps, not very great,


;

do not pro-

pose to enter

but one broad division, not of the


it

sciences, indeed, but of science (for

runs across the


it

lines separating the particular sciences),

is

necesit

sary that

should recall to the reader, since

has
in

an important philosophic bearing on the subject

hand, and must be constantly kept in mind through-

out the following discussion.

Every
of

statement

concerning

phenomena

other words, every scientific proposition

in

is

of one

two kinds

It

expresses either a law or a fact


in

That anarchy ends


true or not
lution
is

despotism
;

is

a law (whether

of no

moment)

that the

French Revois

gave birth to the power of Napoleon

fact.

That

accidental variations, which are of use to the

individual in the struggle for existence, are likely to

become permanent

is

a law

that existing species are

46

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


is

[part

i.

produced by natural selection


at equal temperatures

fact.

That

all

forms of energy tend to resolve themselves into heat


is

a law

that the earth will

become an
be turned

inert mass, containing


is

no energy that can

into work,

fact.

Now,

in so far as science is

founded upon obser-

vation and experiment (and on the most extrava-

gantly a priori theory these must form an essential


part of
its

groundwork),

it is

plain that
I

all

the pro-

positions stating laws (which

will call, the abstract

part of science) must ultimately be, to a certain extent,

founded on the propositions


concrete part of science.

^tdXvcig facts
is

i.e.

on the

What
is,

perhaps

less plain,

but what

is

no

less certain,

that almost the whole


is

of our knowledge of concrete science

in like

manner

founded upon abstract science.


that are
still

As

regards facts

in

the future, this

is

sufficiently obvious.

Leaving supernatural prophecy out of account, our


sole

means of

foretelling

what

is

to
;

come depends
and
this

upon our knowledge of natural laws


is,

indeed

according to some people, the chief reason which


natural

makes

laws worth investigating.


it

little

reflection

shows that

is

equally true of facts that


facts

have already occurred, whether those

be what

are ordinarily called scientific, as, for example, the existence of the glacial epoch, or whether they are

what are

ordinarily called historical, as, for example,

the death of Julius Caesar.

Massing these together under the common name

CHAP.

IV.]

HISTORICAL INFERENCE.

47

historical,'
is

we may

say generally that a law of

nature

an essential part of every inference what-

ever by which

we arrive

at facts

which are occurring

we are immediately informed by perception or memory from which it may be deduced that every principle which
or have occurred, other than those of which
;

is

required to

establish

a law must be

required

to establish a historical fact,

though

it

does not follow,


sufficient.

of course, that these principles will be

In
in

order to determine this latter point,


strictness to

we ought
list

have before us a complete

of these
to

principles, in order that

we might apply them


But
it

cases of historical inference.

will

be more
trusted,

convenient to assume that our knowledge of the laws


of nature, as taught us by science,
is

to

be

and that the only general principle required for arriving at this knowledge is the law of universal
causation.
in

On

this

assumption (which

is

sufficiently

accordance with current philosophy) the problem


:

before us would be as follows


(ist)

Given as premises

some knowledge of existing and recent facts obtained immediately by perception or memory; (2nd) a knowledge of the abstract laws of phenomena as set forth by science (3rd) the law of causa;

tion can we deduce from these the ordinary version

of history, and,

if

not,

what additional
so,

principles will
is

be required to enable us to do
evidence on which they rest
?

and what

the

The

first

of these kinds of premises

some know-

48

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

i.

ledge of existing and recent facts


as might at
establish
first

is

not necessary,
is

appear, because
of

it

required to
these are

the laws

phenomena;

for

already assumed.

It is necessary,

rather,

because

without

it

nothing concrete could be inferred from

the abstract propositions contained under the second

and

third of the

above-mentioned heads.

The

exist-

ence and distribution of phenomena at any given


period cannot be arrived at

by a mere knowledge of

the laws of

some knowledge of the existence and distribution of phenomena at


phenomena
;

it

requires also

some other period


nomena, both

ultimately, therefore, our mediate

knowledge of the existence and distribution of phein the past

and the

future,

must depend

on some immediate knowledge of them, and we have no such immediate knowledge, except concerning the
present and perhaps the recent past.

Now, although a knowledge nomena that is, of causes and


effects

of the laws of phetheir corresponding


is

a necessary element in every inference


is

about concrete science, there


difference in the

a most important

ployed, according

way in which these laws are emas we are dealing with the futuffe^
For whereas every inference about
so every inference about the

or with the past.

the future necessarily involves at least one argument

from cause to

effect,

past necessarily involves at least one argument from


effect to cause, a distinction which, curiously
is all in

enough,

favour of that department of knowledge con-

CHAP.

IV.]

HISTORICAL INFERENCE.

49

cerning which
least

we suppose
the future.

ourselves to
It

know

the

namely,
all

seems, indeed, clear


is

enough that the ordinary view

correct,
all

and that if

we knew
them

existing causes,

and

the laws binding

to their consequents,
calculation, then,

powers of

and if we had infinite assuming the law of uni-

versal causation to be true,


into operation,

and that no new cause came

we

could forecast the whole future


'
'

of the universe.
large, perhaps, to

The ifs here are somewhat too make this very substantial comfort,
once perceive,
it

but, as the reader will at

is

by no
does

means obvious

that even

on similar terms we could


it

give a complete account of the past, because

not appear to be inconsistent with our assumptions


to suppose that

more than one


effects
^
;

set of causes could


in other
is

have produced existing


This
reflection,

words, that

more than one version of


what
to
is

history

equally possible.

then, points

out very

clearly

the

first

question

we have more

particularly

examine

namely, whether a knowledge of natural


we
is

laws such as
of causation,

possess,

combined with the principle

sufficient to enable us to

overcome
and,

the apparent ambiguity


inference

introduced into historical


plurality of causes
in
;

by the possible

if

this question

be answered

the negative,

we

shall

then have to determine whether any valid principle


can be found to
reasoning.
fill

up

this
it

gap

in

our ordinary
is

The

enquiry,
*

may be
p. 6^).

observed,

of

See note on

50

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

i.

some importance,
be determined
very

since no issue less than this has to

namely, whether a branch of science


grown
ill-considered history

of the greatest speculative interest, which has


in not

many years from an

of a few nations for a few centuries, to an account,


in outline at least, of the history of the race, of the

whole human
belongs

organic world, of the planet on which


to

we

dwell,
(I

and of the system

which

it

whether

say) this vast department of


its

knowledge

deserves to retain

position,

or should be con-

sidered as a mere collection of illustrations,


aginary, though possible, examples, of

by im-

laws work or
In order

how natural may work in the concrete. that we may attack the problem with
let

the best hope of success,


it

us begin by considering

as simplified

by

certain arbitrary limitations.

The

possibility of history, as

we have

seen, rests

on the

possibility of eliminating all sets of causes

but one of

existing effects

let

us then at

first

take into conit

sideration only one effect,


7nust

and

let

us suppose that

have been produced by one of two causes,

but might have been produced by either.


these conditions, what

Under
is

we have

to determine

the

ground which may

justify us in asserting,

as

we
our

so often do assert, that one of

them was the

actual

historical cause rather than the other.

To

fix

ideas, let us take


flints

a concrete case.

collection of

broken into shapes rudely resembling arrowis

heads

found during the course of some excava-

CHAP.

IV.]

HISTORICAL INFERENCE.

51

<f/>

tion.

No human

being (who need be considered)

doubts under these circumstances that one of tliS


causes of this striking effect was the will and intelligence of

man, though

at the

same time

it is

not

to be denied that each

one of these arrow-heads, and


which

therefore

all

of them, might be the product of that


in

unknown
this

collection of mechanical causes

case, for

convenience,

we may
is

call

accident.

Why

do we unhesitatingly
?

reject accident in favour

of intelligence
bilities
is,

The answer
in

ready.

The

proba-

are infinitely

favour of the latter that

the chances against accident are

enormously,

if

indefinitely, greater

than the chances against

intel-

ligence.
itself to

This answer, which certainly commends

common

sense, suggests, however, a further

enquiry.

On what grounds

do we form this estimate


?

of the comparative probability of the two causes


It
is

plain that

The

particular value that

we ought to have some grounds. we assign to the chance of


by mere abstract

one or other of any two possible causes being the


actual cause cannot be determined
speculation, but

must be derived from some theory


not
difficult to

respecting the conditions under which these causes

were

likely to

have acted.

It is

see

that in the

example before us these conditions are


be,
.

supposed to
obtain

on the whole, similar


It
it

to those

which

now.

is
is,

assumed that an arrow-head


merely one of an indefinite
all

shape was, as

number

of other forms,

of which ^r produced^

52

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

i.

in

equal or greater numbers, by mechanical causes,


it

and that

waSy as

it is,

a form which
is

man
it is

in

a state

of savagery finds useful, and

therefore likely to
quite true
origin are
that
this

manufacture

and on
But

this hypothesis

that the chances in favour of a

human
evident

enormous.
hypothesis
fact
;

it

is

no

less

is
it

itself

the statement of a historical

that

must, therefore, involve an inference


;

from

effects to causes

that these effects

may

again
;

be conceivably due to more than one set of causes


that

we must
in

again select one set of causes rather

than another on grounds of probability, and again be


obliged,

order to establish

that probability,

to

make a new inference from effects to causes. If, now, we imagine this process carried on indefinitely, we may suppose ourselves at last to arrive at the
deduction of the totality of causes from the totality
of effects.

Supposing, as seems likely enough, that

the totality of effects might conceivably have been

produced by more than one selection or arrangement


of causes, on what principle are

we now
?

to choose

between these conflicting


them, perhaps
select,
all
it

possibilities

Most of

except the

one we commonly

would,

can scarcely be doubted, seem in

the highest

degree extravagant
is

and

improbable.

But

their

extravagance

merely the result of the


;

manner
and as

in

which they strike on our imagination


I

for their improbability,

am

altogether at a

loss to see

how, from our principles, any estimate of

CHAP.

IV.]

HISTORICAL INFERENCE.

53

their probability at all like

what we require can be

founded.
effects,
it

Since

we

are dealing with the totality of

cannot clearly be founded on ^ny further

inference from effect to cause,


tion

and no other founda-

seems to

me

possible, except

by the intervention

of

some new
I

scientific

axiom.

am
I

afraid that this speculation


;

may seem

the

mere extravagance of scepticism


tion

and the

illustra-

am

about to give may, perhaps, strengthen

the prejudice against

my

view, though
it

hope

it

may make
telligible.

the grounds of

more

clear

and

in-

Let us suppose, then, that our only source of


information respecting the past was derived from
written

documents

that,

with

the

exception

of

what each man remembered, he knew absolutely nothing of times gone by beyond what he read in
books or MSS. professing to have been written at
the various periods of which they spoke.
further suppose that from such materials a
less consistent

Let us

more or

and plausible history has been conlet

structed,

and then

us try and determine the sort

of grounds

we have

for estimating its probable truth.

The

effects

here

are

the

books and MSS.

the causes inferred from these effects are

various

writers having access to information about different


periods,

who have

taken care to place this informarecord.

tion accurately

upon

Since there are, how-

ever, other possible causes, for example, the inven-

54

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

i.

tion

by one or more persons of a story, and the forgery of the documents required for its support, it becomes necessary to find a principle which may
enable us to choose between the rival hypotheses.

commonly said that the authenticity of any document may be shown by two kinds of evidence
It is

the external and the

internal

and since

internal

evidence would be defined as evidence drawn from


the document
itself, it

might seem natural to conit

clude that such evidence really exists, and that

might provide us with the principle of which


search.

we are

in

In strictness, however, this

is

not the case.

From

the character of any document alone no con-

clusion can be

drawn

in favour of its
its
it

genuineness,
forgery be
is

provided
admitted.

the

bare possibility of

Supposing, for example,

said that

the style and character of thought of

some book

show

it

to

have been the product of a certain age

and country

this implies
if
it

a knowledge of that age


to

and country which,

is

be admitted as

evi-

dence, must clearly be derived

from some other


;

source than the book

it

is

intended to vindicate

and

this is equally true of

any possible
for

characteristic

which can be adduced either

or against

any
the

theory respecting date of composition or authorship.


It

would appear, indeed,

at

first

sight,

as

if

contents of a book might be so unlike the sort of


things people invent, or so difficult to
consistent
if

make

self-

they were invented, that

its

genuineness

CHAP.

IV.]

HISTORICAL INFERENCE.

55

could be concluded from the mere consideration of


these peculiarities.

But even

this inference involves

some hypothesis respecting the condition


world at
the supposed date of authorship.

of the
It

sup-

poses that the ability to invent and the desire to


invent existed at that
to

time

such

degrees as
;

make

invention of this sort highly improbable

but since this estimate cannot be founded on the

document

itself

without a petitio principii,

it

must

be founded either on some hitherto undiscovered


axiom, or on other documents, or on other non-

documentary phenomena.
bilities
is
I

The

first

of these possi-

reserve for discussion later on.

The

last

excluded by hypothesis.
the
second.

There remains,

there-

fore,

But the smallest consideration

will

show that all the remarks just applied to a single document apply equally well to any number of documents taken together. Once admit the
possibility of their forgery, the improbability of

such

an event can only be deduced from


themselves deductions from
all

facts

which are
of these
in this
It

or

some
all.

documents, and which consequently cannot


matter be used as a basis of inference at

may
from
this

be

stated, therefore, generally that if

we
I

start

the arbitrary hypothesis with which


illustration,
all

began

then,

first,

it

is

quite as probable that

history should be fictitious as that


true
if
;

some

of

it

should be
corollary,

and,

secondly^ as
it

necessary

two versions of

are

mutually ex-

56

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


It

[part

i.

elusive,
likely.

is

impossible to say which

is

the

more
a

The
when

general

principle

from which

this

Is

deduction seems to me, indeed, almost self-evident


clearly stated.
It

would run thus

If

more
It

than one cause can produce a given


impossible,
to say

effect,

Is

by the mere contemplation of the


it

effect,

by what cause
Is

was probably produced.'


effects,'
'

The same
of causes.'

true of

'

groups of

and
the
'

'

groups

It is also true

of the

totality of effects,'
if
'

and the
causes

'

totality of causes.'
'

Now,
effects,
all

totality

of effects
'

means

existing

the

totality

of

Is, if

not history, at

events the necessary

foundation of history.

Therefore, the chances against


Is

any particular version of history being true


as the
It

simply

number
will

of possible versions of
fitting transition to
I

It Is

to one.^

be a

the next stage

In this discussion If

here notice the interesting

effect

which the existence of one particular cause


all

has on the validity of

historical

inferences

mean the universal first cause, whether that be the unknown x of certain philosophers, or the personal

God

of the theologians.

It is of

the essence of this idea of a First

Cause

that everything which exists

in

other words, the

whole of the premises on which we found our knowledge of history Is produced by It directly

Strictly

speaking

as the number of possible versions of

it

mmiis

unity are to one.

GHAP.

IV.]

HISTORICAL INFERENCE.
Moreover,
It
it

57

or indirectly.

is

clearly impossible
set of

to shew that, while phenomena directly.

could produce one

It

was only able

to produce

another set indirectly,

i.e.,

by means of some phe-

nomenal cause intervening.


that there
is

From
at
;

this

it

follows

no period of history
nor

which creation
I

might not have taken place


that,
if it

am

able to see
at

did take place,

it

would do so

one

period more probably than at another.

In other
there

words, whatever date in the past

we

select,

are always two causes which are equally likely to

have produced the phenomena then existing


one
is

the

phenomena which might have produced them according to known laws the other
the group of
;

is

the First Cause.

It

may be worth

noting that

these remarks are true not only of the metaphysical


substance, whether personal or not, which
origin
is

the

of

all

things,

but also of
to

any phenomena

-which

may be assumed
for

have produced the present

order of nature, but of whose laws

we

are ignorant.
that,

Supposing,

example,

it

was

shown

by

tracing back the course of events through time,

we

arrived at a point where the

recognised laws of
in

nature failed

us,^

and where we were

consequence

compelled to assume a new, and, of course, unknown


set of antecedents acting in

unknown ways

in

that

case
^

we should

not be justified in supposing that the


re-

This speculation was suggested by certain physical theories

specting the distribution of heat.

58

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


known causes failed unknown causes came

[part

i.

point where the


point where the
tion.

us was the
into opera-

The

probabiHties, in fact, are infinitely the

other way.

For

since these causes are

unknown,

we

clearly cannot say that their properties are such

as to

make

their appearance

time than at another.

more probable at one That they must appear at

some period or other is shown, according to our hypothesis, by the insufficiency of established laws but when followed up beyond a certain point
;

since, also

by hypothesis, we can predicate nothing


causes, except their existence

of these
their
it

unknown
to

and
have

power

produce the present order of nature,


likely to

would seem that they are quite as


any
other.

exercised that power at any one instant of time as


at

The

reader acquainted with

the elements

of
I

geometrical optics will see clearly the point which

am

attempting to establish,

if

he

will consider the


*

distinction

between a

real

'

and a
is

virtual
is

'

image.

spectator

whose

position

fixed

contemplating

(let

us suppose) what appears to him to be the flame

of a candle.

He
if

believes

it

to

be a candle because

the rays of light reach his eye precisely as they

would do
forming

they emanated from a candle placed


Nevertheless,

where he sees the image of the flame.


in this

very natural conclusion, he

may be

altogether in error.

Since the rays would reach his

eyes

in precisely

the

same manner, whether they came

CHAP.

IV.]

HISTORICAL INFERENCE.
real

59

from a

flame or the virtual image of a flame

produced by some optical contrivance, and since the

manner

in

which the rays reach

his

eye

is

(we

may
have

suppose) the sole ground on which he can found any


inference at
all, it is

perfectly plain that he can

no reason

for believing the

one rather than the other

to be the true object of perception.

So

it is

with us

and our inferences about the


for space, the facts

past, if

we substitute time

immediately presented to us for the

rays striking directly on the retina, and the history


of the past, as given to us

by

science, for the

image
able

of the flame.
to point to

If

we

are fortunate

we may be

an imaginary condition of the world at


period,

some given

and

say,

'

Trace out the con-

sequence of these causes according to the known


laws of nature, and you will arrive at the state of
things you

now
*

see around you,' just as

some one
accounted

might
exists,
for.'

say,

On

the supposition that a candle flame


is

your actual perception

fully

But just as

in

the

second

case a virtual
effect as the

image would have precisely the same


real image, so in the first case other

combinations of

phenomena obeying known laws, or a metaphysical first cause, or phenomena obeying unknown laws which the failure of known laws compels us to believe in, might all of them result in the existing universe.
But whereas
in the

second case the rays from the

image would not generally be the only available

means of forming a judgment respecting the

real

6o

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


we have
usually

[part

i.

nature of their origin, and

some

other independent grounds for deciding in favour of

one hypothesis rather than another,


so far as at present appears,
!^

in the first case,


so.

it is

not

Existing

facts are
facts,

our sole (particular) evidence for historic


if

^'
j

and

our general principles can get nothing

definite out of them, science at all events has nothing

further to suggest.

All

the cases

we have

so far considered have


in

these characteristics in

common that

each

we
sets

have

to choose

between two or more causes, or


are

of causes, which

the possible historical

ante-

cedents of the world as

we

see

it

that in each the


lie

causes between which our choice


causes, that
Is,

are actual^

are (by hypothesis)


;

to

have existed

and that

In

known to exist or each we have as yet


at this point

discovered no reason for preferring any one possible


alternative to

any other.

But

an

in-

teresting question suggests

Itself.

Why

should

we

retain the limitation (originally adopted In order to

simplify the investigation) stated in the second of the

preceding propositions

On what

principle
?

do we

confine our attention to actual causes

Why should
absolutely

we

not admit causes about whose existence or non-

existence now, or in past times,

we know

nothing as possible
^

historical

antecedents,

and
:

if

as

its

This use of the word 'actual is clumsy and not very accurate but meaning in this connection is clearly defined, its employment
'

will,

hope, lead to no confusion.

CHAP.

IV.]

HISTORICAL INFERENCE.

6i

we do
sion

so admit them, what effect will

the admishistorical

have on the validity of our ordinary


?

inference

The

last question, at all events,

does not

seem hard
ments

to answer.

If

we

are to admit, as ele-

in the historic

problem, an indefinite number of

such possible causes on the same footing as

we now

admit actual causes, then


initial

(if

we

are limited to our

assumptions)

all

inference with regard to the

past becomes

impossible.

We

may,

if

we
as

please,

amuse ourselves by showing how


be a
them, but

actual causes

may
see

sufficient explanation of the facts

we

we must

at the

same time admit

that the

chances are infinitely against that explanation being


the true one, and for this obvious reason
:

since
follows

every historical belief

must be founded

in the last
it

resort on an inference from

effect to cause,

that

if

there are an infinite


all

number

of causes, so far

as

we know,
them

equally possible, the chances against

any one of them


of

therefore
is

against any achcal one


infinite.
If,

being
show

the real cause are also


to exist at
all,
it

therefore, history

will

be neces-

sary to
possible

that the actual causes

are the only


is

ones, or, at all

events, that there

a very

great presumption in their favour.

We

have now considered

historic inference in the

light of four separate suppositions.

We have supposed
;

that our choice lay

ist,

between

different sets of phe-

nomenal causes whose laws are known 2nd, between a noumenal cause and phenomenal causes 3rd,
'
'

62

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

i.

between phenominal causes whose laws are known,


and phenonienal causes which are known to have
existed, but

whose laws are not known

4th,

between

causes which are

known
for

to exist, or to

have existed,

and causes which,


the contrary,

anything

we at

present

know

to

may have
;

existed in indefinite numbers.

In

all

these cases there are two alternatives prein

sented to us
accepts

each of them science unhesitatingly


rejects

one and

the other, and

in,

at all

events, most instances


choice.
I

common

sense endorses the

Nevertheless, the preceding discussion has,

hope,

made

it

plain that this course derives

no

justification

from our supposed knowledge of the ab-

stract laws connecting


in

phenomena, even when taken


supplement these grounds
which
if

connection with the law of universal causation.

It is necessary, therefore, to

of belief by
it

some other

principle or principles,

now becomes our

business to find out, and,

pos.

sible, to justify.

We

turn

first,

as

is

natural, to the
reflection

'

Uniformity
it

of Nature.'
scarcely gives
since,

But a

little

shows that

us that of which
its

we

are in search,
it

according to one of

meanings,
it is

is

in-

sufficient, while,

according to another,
If
it

not only

insufficient,
it

but untrue.

be taken to mean, as

usually

is,

that the past, the present,


in
this,

are uniform

that

the

and the future same antecedent is


it
is,

always followed by the same consequent, then

of course, one of the very assumptions with which

CHAP.

IV.]

HISTORICAL INFERENCE.
and which have
that the
left

63

we

started,

us with
If,

all

these

unsolved problems on our hands.


hand,
it

on the other

means

same consequents are always

preceded by the same antecedents,

we could, no doubt,
fatal

from

this, in

theory, construct a history of the past

precisely to the

same extent and with the same

limitations as from the converse proposition


in

we

can

theory

now

construct a history of the future.


is

But

then, unfortunately, this

opposed

to the practical

teachings of the very science in aid of which

we

appeal to
*

it,

and

is

in
'

apparent contradiction both to


experiment.'
^

observation' and to

third meaning, according to

which the Uni-

formity of Nature would imply that no supernatural


interference with the

Order of Nature,

i.e.,

with the

succession of natural causes and effects, was possible,


This may be a convenient place at which to touch on an objecwhich the reader accustomed to regard the universe from a mechanical point of view may be tempted to raise. He may say, ' I utterly deny the possible plurality of causes, on the existence of which depends so much of your argument. I hold that the world may be regarded as a system of particles obeying mechanical laws, that it is
1

tion

therefore quite as possible to reconstruct the past, as

it is

to construct
in theory,

the future, from the present

and that both operations may,

be carried out with absolute certainty.' Since, however, this theoretical possibility can never by any accident be realised in practice, it may, for my purposes, be neglected. I write for human beings with human powers of calculation. But besides this, it is by no means
proved,
I

believe, to the satisfaction of the

men

of science that the

world IS a purely mechanical system. I am, therefore, justified in assuming, with the majority of scientific philosophers, that while one kind of cause can only have one kind of effect, one kind of effect may have more than one kind of cause. The attentive reader will see that, even were this otherwise, still, so long as it is so for our powers of observation and calculation, the main argument of the chapter remains
entirely unaffected.

64

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

i.

would give a solution of the second problem, but of


the second problem only.

a principle, nor can

know of no proof of such conceive any. Hume's arguI

ment against miracles, Another general


phrase that
Nature.'
is

need not

say,

is

inapplicable.

principle

is
'

suggested

by a

sometimes used

The

Simplicity of
possible to
in

Let us examine how

far

it is

extract from this the premiss of


search.

which we are
simple,'

When we
not,
I

speak of Nature being


its

'

it is

presume, meant that


is,

laws are easily under-

stood, that

are

'

simple

'

relatively to our faculties


first
if
it

of comprehension.

In the

place,

it

is

not the
case,

case

in the

second place,

were the
it

we

should derive no assistance from


difficulty, since

in

our present

every one of the alternatives


is

we have

been weighing
other
;

as easily

understood as every
it

and

in the third place,

would involve the

hypothesis of a pre-established
the 'cosmos' and the
'

harmony between
'

microcosmos

which men of
Nor, for
'

science at least would be slow to admit.


this

same

reason, can

it

mean

that the
is,

most

simple

'

or

'

natural' explanation

that

the explanation

which,

when understood, seems,

in

some vague way,

especially to
is

commend

itself to

the investigator

always the true one

more particularly as different


views as to what
if

investigators take very different


is
*

natural.'

It is clear,

indeed, that

we

are to get
it

any assistance out of the Simplicity of Nature,

CHAP.

IV.]

HISTORICAL INFERENCE.
is

65

must be because the Simplicity of Nature


thing
'

somein

objective,'

something that can be stated


merely expresses

terms which have no reference to the


observer, something which

mind of the
the

manner

in

which natural phenomena occur.

That

Nature employs the fewest possible number of causes,


or rather kinds of cause, to produce her results (which

corresponds to the maxim,

'

that causes are not to be


')

multiplied without a reason

is

a proposition which

conforms to these conditions, and which seems to


assert a kind of simplicity.

Will

this serve

our turn

So

far

as

the fourth problem (which requires us

to decide

between known and unknown causes)


it

is

concerned,
that
If

apparently

will.

It practically tells

us

we know
do

of causes that might have produced

a given
did

result, that

these causes, or
It

some of them,
in accord-

actually

so.

therefore unquestionably

affords a solution of this

problem exactly

ance

witji the

ordinary scientific view.

If,

however,

we examine

Its

bearing on the

first

and

third problems, this does not appear to


fact.

be

altogether the

In these two cases

we

are re-

quired to choose between kinds of cause which are

by hypothesis known
of
*

to exist

so that the principle

Simplicity

'

leaves us very

much where we

were.

While, with regard to the second problem, since the


alternative there
lies

between natural and superit

natural causes, a principle which (In so far as F

says

66

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.

[part

i.

anything) gives us Information only about the former,

cannot be of much assistance.


I

may add

that,

though philosophers never hesi-

tate to appeal to the Simplicity of


suits their convenience,
I

Nature when

it

am

not aware that any of

them have thought


its reality.

fit

to supply us with a proof of

Though

there seems, then, to be no obvious or

recognised principle which will exactly serve our


purpose, there must nevertheless be

some

unformulated notion
isting historical

perhaps

which

lies

at the root of ex-

judgments, and which on analysis

may

furnish us with the principle of

which we are
a sort

in search.

Now

take this notion to be that there

is

of continuity in the course of Nature through the past

which discourages (so to speak) violent changes and


the interference of

unknown
is,

causes.

But such a

statement as
far too

it

stands

it

need hardly be observed,


re-

vague

to

have any philosophic value, and

quires a

good deal of analysis before even we come

to the question of proof.


violent
"^

To

begin with, what

is

It cannot, of course,

mean va^x^y startling,


produced

as

it

would then

refer solely to the effect

on the imagination, and could hardly be made the


foundation of a canon by which to judge the course
of Nature.
It

must, therefore, have


to
it,

meaning attached
clear that

though

at

some objective the same time it is


it

no such meaning can be given to

which

CHAP.

IV.]

HISTORICAL INFERENCE.
It
Is,

67

shall

have any absolute value.

mean, impos-

sible to say

what

is

or

is

not objectively a violent

some particular change as a standard of comparison. Now, what is this standard


change, except by taking

change

It

cannot evidently be a fixed or permaall

nent rate of change to which

others must conform,

because

if

so

it

must

either be

one of which we have

immediate knowledge, or one we have arrived at by


historical inference.
It

cannot be the second, as this

(since

we

are looking for a basis for historical inferin

ence) would involve a very obvious argument


circle.

It cannot, again,

be the

first,

because recogviolent

nised history supplies us with

many more

changes than those of which we have immediate experience, so that


it

is

impossible both that history

should be true and that historic changes should con-

form

to the standard.

A
it

meaning which promises better


first

results,

because

does not at

sight appear to suggest a fixed


:-=

standard, would be as follows

'

If there are
is

two

possible causes for any effect, that one

to

be chosen

which involves the


it

least violent change.'


is

But

this,

must be observed,

not a statement respecting


to guide the

Nature, but a

maxim intended
It

judgment
the

of the natural philosopher.


its

must, therefore, derive

authority from

some

fact in nature, exactly as

ordinary rules of induction derive their authority from


the law of universal causation.
fact
?

Now

what

is

this^i^

Our guesses

(according to this maxim) beF 2

68

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

i.

come more

accurate as they approach a certain limit.

The

smaller the change required by the conclusion,


is

the more likely

the inference on which that conclu-

sion rests to be sound.


is

But the

limit here

implied

a condition of things under which there would be


all,

no change at

a supposition which

is

absolutely
else.

incompatible with history and everything


It

must

also

be remarked that
is

'

rate of change,'

or

amount of change/
it

itself

an expression to

which
precise

is

only
;

now and then


in fact,

possible to attach a

meaning
forth.

only in those cases in which

we

are dealing with quantities, mass, velocity, force,

and so
from

Science

is,

however, so

far at present
it

being purely quantitative (whatever

may

some day become),


from being
Since, then,
it

that those notions are far indeed

sufficient to

cover the necessary ground.


for-

does not seem easy even to

mulate the axiom or axioms which are required in


addition to the law of causation to justify our ordi-

nary historic judgments,

the

second step

in

the

philosophy of the subject, by which

we seek

to

prove

or classify them (according as they are derivative or


ultimate), cannot

be attempted.

The

truth of the

matter appears to be that history rests on a kind of


scientific instinct,
is

none the

less healthy

because
is

it

not very reasonable.

This, fortunately,

quite

vigorous enough to resist the attacks of any merely


philosophic scepticism, as any one anxious to try the

experiment

may discover

for himself

provided he

will

CHAP.

IV.]

HISTORICAL INFERENCE.

69

ask the next

man

of science he meets, whether (say)

4000

B.C. is

not as Hkely as any other assignable date


of this Earth as a separate
is

for the

commencement
If the enquirer

planet.

fortunate

enough

to get

any answer

at all to so

absurd a question, he

will pro-

bably be told that no

known

causes are adequate to

the production of existing effects in so short a time.

To

which

it

may be

replied, that there

is

no

parti-

cular reason for supposing that

known

causes have

been the only ones


of science

in operation.

On

this the

man

may
to
If
I

not improbably rejoin that gratuitous

suppositions ought to be avoided

that

the deus ex

machmd
from
art.

is

be excluded as much from science as he were further asked the grounds of


his

this canon,

do not know exactly what would be


I

answer, though

know that whether he


diminished.

could find an

answer or

not, the strength of his convictions

would

not be in any

way

From
tive result.

certain

assumptions,

then,

which seem
very negaas well to
this con-

reasonable enough,

we have arrived
it

at a

Before concluding,

may be

point out certain

ways

in

which the nature of


It will

clusion reacts on the premises.

be recollected

that

we

started with the supposition that, in addition

to the law of causation,

we were
be seen

to accept the teach-

ing of science so far as particular abstract laws were


concerned.

But

it

will

at once that the evihistorical


i.e.,

dence of many of these laws

is itself

depends on the truth of the current version of

his-

70

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.

[part

i.

tory.

Of how many
it is

this

may be

said

do not en-

quire, but

obviously true of those which in any

way depend on a series of observations carried through many years, such as parts of astronomy and
sociology
(if

this

is

to

be considered a science).

It is also true

of

all

laws which are direct deductions

from the historic

facts

which alone are supposed to

exemplify them, such as parts of geology.

What,
preced-

however,

is

of perhaps

more

interest

is

the bearing

which some of the points brought out

in the

ing discussion have on the empirical evidence of the

law of universal causation.

The

nature of the process of inference by which


is
I

this great principle

proved from experience has


,

been discussed, and,


a previous chapter
;

think,

shown

to

be

invalid, in

but one remark concerning the

premises of that inference

maybe made appropriately


at the

now.

It

was pointed out

commencement of

the chapter that, though our knowledge of the laws


of nature must be founded, in part at least, on our

knowledge of
theless all our

particular matters of fact, that never-

knowledge of particular matters of fact other than those of which we have immediate experience, rfiust
in

their turn

be founded upon our

Now, it is commonly admitted that a law of nature depends for its generality upon the law of universal causation, in
other words,
solely
is

knowledge of the laws of nature.

extended to unobserved instances


that law
;

by means of

from which

it

follows,

CHAP.

IV.]

HISTORICAL INFERENCE.
is

71

that the law of universal causation

a necessary

premiss in every inference by which


historical facts.

we

arrive at

What

have been hitherto attempt-

ing to

show is,

that even assuming this premiss to be


in

true, there is

an inevitable ambiguity
to insist

the inference

what

now wish

on

is,

that whether those


is

views be true or
if

false, this at

any rate

certain, that

the law of universal causation be founded on expeall,

rience at
limited.

that experience

must be extremely
dilating

Empirical

philosophers,

on the

accumulated evidence

we have
it

for this law, are in

the habit of telling us that

is

the uncontradicted
;

result of observations extending through centuries

but they have omitted to notice, that unless


believe in the law,

we

first

we

can have no reason for be-

lieving in the observations.


will,

Turn

the matter as

we

the fact that

mankind have been observing or


It

doing anything else for centuries, cannot be to any


of us a matter of direct observation or intuition.
must, therefore, be an inference
;

and

if
it

an inference
can be
in-

from experience, the only experience


ferred from,
is

the immediate and limited experience


;

of each individual

this, therefore, either at

one

re-

move

or two,

is

the only possible empirical founda-

tion for the law of causation, or


principle.

any other general

This argument does not show, of course, that


empirical

philosophy

is
it

false
is

but

it

does show,

beyond question, that

not plausible.

What-

72

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


its

[part

i.

ever be

philosophic vakie, there

is

certainly some-

thing consolatory to

common

sense in the Idea that

our convictions rest on a broad basis of experience.

There

is

something practical

in the

very sound of a

phrase which implies a method of judging that most


satisfactorily distinguishes us

from the pre- Baconian


that this

philosophers.
*

But when
'

it

becomes evident

broad basis

Itself rests

on the exceedingly narrow

basis of individual experience,

stood that what


perceived,
in past
is

perceive,

when it is once underand remember having


all,

my sole ground for believing that people


empiricism
its

ages perceived anything at

certainly loses

much

of

Its

dignity,

though

philoit

sophic value remains, perhaps, very

much what

was

before,

CHAP,

v.]

INTRODUCTION TO PART

11.

73

PART

XL

CHAPTER

V.
IL

INTRODUCTION TO PART
In the three preceding chapters
empirical reasoning concisely, but
I

have discussed
sufficiently,

hope
I

from three different points of view.


the
first

showed, in

place, that whereas, according to this philo-

sophy,

all

our knowledge

is

derived from particulars,

that there

was nevertheless no method, or at all events no method hitherto discovered, by whicli inference from particulars was possible and that
;

Mr. Mills theory on

this subject will in

no sense
it

bear minute examination.

From

this

reasoning
is

necessarily follows that pure empiricism

not at

present a tenable system

but there

is

a kind of
for

mixed or spurious empiricism, which, taking

granted (on no very explicit or intelligible grounds)


the principle of universal causation, assumes that by

the help of this alone

we

can argue from particular

matters of fact to the general laws of phenomena.

This

imagine to be a not

uncommon view among

men

of science, and to be that formally put forward

74

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


in his
*

[part

ii.

by Mr. Jevons
large one

Principles of Science.'
this theory is

The
philo-

assumption required by

evidently a
it,

so

large, indeed, as to

make
;

sophically speaking,

nearly worthless
I

but,

even

granting that assumption,


in the
large,

showed

in the

next place,

third chapter, that

no experience, however

and no experiments, however well contrived


any reasonable assurbe repeated

and

successful, could give us

ance that the co-existences or sequences which have

been observed among phenomena


in the future.

will

This

is

as

much

as to say that induc-

tive logic (even granting the uniformity of Nature)


is

worthless, since

it

can do no more than find a rule

according to which

all

known

instances of an event

have occurred, without giving us any right to extend


this rule to instances
It

which are not known.

appears, then, that neither the

mixed and
in

in-

complete empiricism considered


still

in the third chapter,

less the

pure empiricism considered

the second
for infer-

chapter, affords us

any

satisfactory

method

ring the laws of nature from particular observations

or experiments
full

but even this does not exhibit the


scientific logic, for

weakness and inadequacy of


I

showed that, granting \k\2X we possessed a knowledge of the laws of phenomena, and granting the truth of the law of universal causain the fourth chapter

tion
it

in other

words, granting the truth of that which


in the

was shown

not be proved

it

two preceding chapters could was impossible, even on these

CHAP, v.]

INTRODUCTION TO PART
knowledge of
Its

II.

75
\

terms, to arrive at any

historical facts,

taking this expression In


alL-tfeat

widest sense as Including

has occurred outside our Individual sphere of

immediate experience.
I

have therefore stated three

distinct objections

that

may be

taken to the ordinary proof of current

scientific beliefs.

Empirical philosophy, so far as


;

can

see, gets

over none of them

though every one


philosophy of
I

of them must be got over by any system which has


pretensions
science.

to

being an
so.

adequate
It

This being

Is

not necessary,

sup-

pose, to dwell longer

on

this part of the subject,

even

if

by so doing other difficulties might be started

equally hard of solution. It will be convenient rather


to proceed at once to the next branch of the enquiry.

The

reader will recollect that in the

first

chapter

philosophy was divided into the philosophy.-o infer-

ence and the philosoplvy^f ultimate premises.


three preceding chapters
in the
still

The

may be

described as dealing
;

main with the

first

of these divisions

and we
be

require therefore to give a

more
is

particular con-

sideration to the second.

How

this subject to

approached

On

the whole, perhaps, most conif

veniently by taking the premises which,

not
at

ulti-

mate from a philosophic point of view, are


rate ultimate from a scientific point of

any
i.e.,

view

those on which science depends, but which do not

depend on science

and trying to find out the proof,

or kind of proof, of which they are susceptible.

76

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

il.

Now these premises consist (so far as


in the first place, of certain in

can judge),

unknown

principles,

shown

the third and fourth chapters to be necessary

to the validity of science, but which, since they are

unknown, need no longer detain


place, of the

us.

In the second
;

Law
;

of Universal Causation

which, as

was shown

in the

second chapter, cannot be proved

by induction

and, in the third place, of individual

or particular experiences, which (as will be


the ninth chapter, though
it

shown

in

is

here assumed) must

be supposed
It is

to refer to a persistent universe.


last

the evidence of these

two premises
chiefly

or kinds of premiss which will us


;

now

occupy

but as the discussion of this matter will oblige


to

me

deal with a great

many

dissimilar

and

dis-

connected systems,
necessary.
I

a change of method will

be

shall

make

henceforth no attempt to

link each chapter to that


it

which precedes and follows


chain.

by an argumentative
will contain

On
and
it

the contrary,

each chapter

a discussion as complete as
subject,
will

seems necessary of one

only be
it

related to the other similar chapters inasmuch as

proceeds from the same basis and leads to the same


conclusion.

Before entering, however, into this more extended

examination of the various methods by which philosophers have attempted to establish the existence of a
persistent universe governed

by

causation,

shall per-

haps be asked whether

this is a

matter which really

CHAP,

v.]

INTRODUCTION TO PART
all.

II.

77

requires proof at

Is not the belief

(it

may be

said) in the reality of such a universe

one of those
un-

truths which

lie
is
I

at the root of

all

knowledge, for
still

which proof
necessary
?

impossible, or,

if

possible,

reply that this

is

a question the true


but,

answer to which may be suggested,


person must,

from the

nature of things, cannot be demonstrated.


in

Each
mind

the last resort, decide for himself


is

whether or not any given proposition


of the kind
'ultimate.'
I

to his

have described

in the first section as


all

In this particular case

that can be

said

is that,

as a matter of fact, the law of causation


in its integrity

does not appear to be accepted


the greater part of the

by

human

race,

and that those

who do
ing
it

accept

it

seem

to feel the necessity of found:

upon some kind of proof


I

either

upon expe-

rience, which, as

have already shown, can furnish

no proof
principles

at all

or
it

upon some of the philosophical


will

which

be

my

business to examine
persistent universe,

in the sequel.

the

case

is

With regard to a somewhat different.


in
it,

Everybody

prac-

tically believes

even those who speculatively


all

question

it

but at the same time the verdict of


to

philosophy seems
its

be that the dogma asserting


be

existence

is

one which can be speculatively questherefore,


if it

tioned,

and must

true,

be capable

of

some

speculative
it

defence.

So

strations of

have been

offered, that

many demonit may well be


qualified to

assumed

that, in the

judgment of those

78

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


some demonstration
still

[part

ii.

decide,
ever,

is

required.
is

If,

how-

anyone

thinks that this

a matter which

those interested in the rational foundation of science

may be permitted to neglect, the following ations may perhaps induce him to alter his
If
is is

consideropinion.

an immediate knowledge of a persistent world


all, it

given us at
given us
fact

will

be admitted,
;

think, that
is

it

in perception

if its

existence

an

ultiit is

mate
a

which cannot and need not be proved, which we are assured by what
*

fact of

is

somewhat

absurdly called the

direct evidence of the senses.'

In other words,

we know
same
first

that there
sort of

is

a persistent

world much

in the

same

absolute assurance as

way and with the we know that we feel


immediately
?

hot or cold.

The
is,

question, therefore, which

has to be asked

What do we know

and with certainty by means of perception

The

answer suggested by the psychology of Berkeley

and

in effect amounted to this. The only know and can know immediately are things we our own sensations and ideas. Objects are merely

Hume

groups of sensations. groups of ideas


;

Imagined objects are merely


vanish
in truth

and as these pass and

away, so do the things, of which they are

the only real constituents, cease to have any but

a nominal existence.

were

affections of the mind,'

While they were real they and when they ceased

to be affections of the mind, they ceased to be anything.

CHAP,

v.]

INTRODUCTION TO PART

II.

79

The soundness

of this psychology, which,

if

true,

would completely dispose of any immediate knowledge of a persistent world,


question.
It is
is,

however, open to
dif-

maintained by thinkers of a

ferent school^ that in perceiving objects

we cannot

properly be said to perceive either sensations or


related sensations, or even facts of sensation, but only
qualities of objects
;

qualities

which are constituted

not by sensations but by relations,


therefore thought but cannot be felt.

and whjgh^ re
If this

theory

of perception Be sound,

it

is

evident that the argu-

ment

of the psychological idealist cannot be mainI

tained in the shape in which


If the world, as
it is

have just stated

it.

immediately perceived, does not


it

consist of sensations,

need not evidently be tran-

sient merely because sensations are so.

We

there-

fore
tion

have again

to ask ourselves

whether

in percep-

we

gain an assurance, both immediate and reof the existence of persistent objects f

flective,

and

to this question,
their views,
I

though without subscribing

to all

^nswer, as the^j^sydiological jded^

answered. No.
^

Cf.

Mr. Green's edition of Hume, and an

article,

published after

the greater part of this essay was written, in the Contemporary Review,

March 1878. The reader may, perhaps, be


"^

inclined hastily to imagine that an

assurance cannot be both immediate ^ reflective. This combination is, however, not only possible, but it ought to be found in all ultimate premises, and is actually found in the axioms of mathematics.

proposition of which

we have immediate
is

reflective assurance, is

one

which, after reflection,

seen to be certain without proof.

8o

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


I

[part

ii.

must here guard against a possible misconception which may be suggested by the word im'

mediate.'

In one sense of the term

all

the know-

ledge, real or supposed,

which

is

obtained by per:

ception alone

may be

called

immediate

since

know-

ledge obtained through any conscious process of


inference
is

ipso facto mediate.

Nevertheless,

we
all

cannot

properly

be

said to
reflective,

have an
of the

assurance,
truth of

both immediate and


the
facts

we immediately

perceive.
facts
is

Our

real
;

or

supposed knowledge of the


not immediate.

immediate

our

reflective assurance of the truth of these facts is cer-

tainly

If,

for

example,
its

see an

object in space,
size is obtained

my

knowledge of

real

shape and

by no piece of conscious reasoning,


Nevertheless, the reflective
is

and cannot therefore be appropriately described as


mediate or derivative.
assurance that the thing seen
actually that shape

and

size,

and not
if it

merely shaded and coloured


were, can only be arrived at

so as to look as

a more or

less elaborate process of inference,

by and

must undoubtedly therefore be looked on as mediate.


In

harmony with

this explanation
:

our original questhat

tion

would therefore run thus

Conceding
legitimate

we

immediately perceive the existence of a persisting


universe,
is

the reflective assurance that such a uniis it


(if it
?

verse exists immediate, or


at
all)

be so

only in virtue of a process of inference

To

my

thinking, the bare consideration of the problem

CHAP,

v.]

INTRODUCTION TO PART
is

II.

8i

so stated

sufficient to

show
It

that the latter alterna-

tive should

be accepted.

appears to

me

that the

immediate belief which the majority of mankind


certainly

have

in

the reality of such a universe

is

of

the

same kind

as that which they


;

had

in the

apparent

motion of the sun and stars


speculative

and

that,

on

reflection,
legiti-

doubt

is

not only possible and

mate, but
If

is

hardly to be avoided.
this statement,
I

anyone disagrees with

would

ask him

how he

deals with the admitted occurrence


?

of optical or other (so-called) illusions of the senses

In such cases the judgment revSpecting the persistence

of the object perceived


in

is

as immediate,

and

is

given
it

perception precisely in the perception


is

same way,

as

is

when

normal.

The

only difference

is

that on reflection

it is

seen to be incorrect.

And by
By showas
exists a

what method
ing
its

is its

incorrectness

shown

inconsistency with the order of nature

revealed to us by science.

But unless there

persisting universe, the order of nature, as revealed


to us

by

science,

is

a dream.
is

If therefore the existin percep-

ence of such a universe


tion,

given us merely

we can

assert that a particular object

is

transient

only by a mediate inference from an authority whose

immediate verdict

is

that

it is

persistent.
fact

True/

it

may be

replied,

'

but this

is

which presents no

difficulty.

We

are constantly correcting one obser-

vation by means of another, without concluding from


this,

that observation

is

a means of acquiring know-

'

82

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

ledge unworthy of credit.


authorities of precisely the

This show s that

wo

same kind may


latent

qualify

without destroying each other, and without giving


rise

to

any
lies

suspicions

of

contradiction.
this

In

what

the

distinction
?
'

between

case

and the one stated above


this
:

The

distinction lies in

that In the second case the scientific obser-

vations correct and can correct each other only on

the presupposition which

It

is

the business of the

perceptions in the

first

case to establish.

We

can

extract a single truth out of a series of observations

only on the supposition that they


single object,

all

deal with a

and they can only deal with a single


through at
least the

object

if

that object persists

whole period over which the observations extend.


If perceptions can correct each other only

on similar

terms,

it

would seem tolerably plain that they cannot

correct each other

when

the question In dispute

is

whether the object perceived has, or has


attribute of persistence.
If there
'

not, the

be a persistent

world, the fact

that the

evidence of our senses


its

occasionally misleads us as to

true character

may

be of small Importance.

But

if

our whole ground

for believing In the existence of a persistent

world
fact

be derived from the evidence of the senses, the


a suspicion over

that they deceive us, though only occasionally, casts


all

the rest of their testimony.

Reverting to the remarks on the psychology of


perception

made

a few pages back, the reader

may

'

CHAP,

v.]

INTRODUCTION TO PART

II.

83

perhaps say

If objects are constituted


felt,

by

relations

which are thought, not


tions

may

not one of the rela-

sistence

by which they are constituted be that very perwhose reality you tell us has to be inferred ?
in the

May
given

not the assurance that objects persist be thus


process of sense perception, though not,

strictly speaking,

derived from the evidence of the

senses

Now
ance

do not

at present

deny that such assur-

may be legitimately

attained

by reasoning on the
at

basis of the psychology

which

offers us this analysis

of the perceived object.

But without
safe,
I

present

going into

this question,

it is

suppose, to assert

that to think an object as persisting cannot


persist.

Whatever may be the

truths of which

make it we
to

are immediately assured in perception, that the object

perceived actually has any qualities


attribute to
it,

we choose

cannot be one.
into

To

suppose the con-

trary
to

is

to

fall

an error similar to that according

which the existence of


fact that existence

God was demonstrated


was part of His
is

from the

essence.
it

Grant that everything which


real, since if it

real is thought,
is

cannot be the fact that everything which


is

thought

were

so,

mistakes as to the true


;

nature of any object would be impossible


as subversive of science as

a doctrine

any form of idealism ever


course, not

devised.

These preliminary remarks have, of


G
2

been intended as even a proximate solution of any

84

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


Their object has

[part

ii.

philosophic problem.

been to

suggest doubt, not to establish scepticism.

They

have aimed

at

convincing anyone inclined to an


in his natural convictions, that the
is

easy acquiescence

reality of the subject-matter of science

not a thing

that should too readily be taken for granted.

Our

natural convictions

may be

right,

but they must be


;

shown to be right. Proof of some kind is necessary and where proof is necessary, scepticism is possible.
All that
I

here contend for

is

that a preliminary ex-

amination of what perception

tells

us

no assumption
'

being made as to the truth of any particular psychological theory,


*

and no use being made of the words


objective/ or
is noi(
'

subjective,'

external

fails
if

to

show

that scepticism
is

possible.
it

So

that

ever this

to

be established

must be by the help of

systems which, whatever be the nature of their conclusions,

cannot be accepted without criticism.

pass

now to the most

important, the most elaborate,


of these systems, which, in
it

and the most

difficult

harmony with the terminology


to call
*

employs,

venture

Transcendentalism.'

CHAP,

vi.j

TRANSCENDENTALISM.

85

CHAPTER
That
is

VI.

TRANSCENDENTALISM.
the pure empiricism
still

in

fashion

among

scientific

philosophers leads naturally to scepticism

a fact which has been familiar to certain schools of

thought ever since


stripped
of
its

Hume

presented
It
is

it

to the world

plausibilities.

hardly to be not himself

believed that so subtle a thinker did

perceive the ultimate consequences of his reasoning.

He

must have been perfectly aware that on

his

system a philosophy of science was


nevertheless, his
*

impossible

Essay on Miracles' and occasional

announcements, such as that with which he ends


his
ing,'
'

Enquiry concerning the

Human

Understand-

appear to have quite convinced natural philo

sophers that his scepticism merely undermined religion

result

which to most of them was a cause


If,

of very

moderate uneasiness.
still

however,

they

ignored, and

ignore, the wider reach of that


it

engine of destruction,
telling.

has not been for want of

Hume

himself makes no effort to conceal

it,

and the sneer with which he informs the students

86

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


is

[part

ii.

of science that theirs

the only kind of knowledge

worth pursuing,
with which he

is

scarcely less obvious than that

tells

the theologian that the most


'

solid foundations of religion are


revelation.'
is

faith

'

and

'

divine

But Hume's own

view of his position

not the only,

nor even the main, evidence for

the sceptical nature of the conclusions to which his


theories

necessarily lead.

On

that

scepticism,

as
is

we have been informed

with sufficient iteration,

founded the whole imposing structure of modern

German philosophy; and modern German philosophy, whatever be its value, is not a phenomenon
which easily escapes
it

notice.
is

If

it

gives

little

light

is

not because

it

hidden under a bushel.


its

In

all

probability, however,
it

very magnitude has pre-

vented

from materially influencing the course of


philosophy in this country
;

scientific
I

and

believe

may

almost say from permanently influencing

scientific

philosophy even in Germany.


forgiven
if,

man

may be

before seriously attempting to

master so huge a mass of metaphysics, composed of


several inconsistent systems, difficult of comprehension from their essential natures,
still

more

difficult
in-

from the extraordinary jargon under which the


genuity of

man
I

has concealed their import


if

he may
is,

be forgiven,
the time

say,

he pauses and considers whether

may
is

not be better spent in reading somelikely to understand.


It

thing he
ever,

more

howeven

unfortunate

that

this

pardonable, and

' ' ;

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.

87

laudable, caution should

have prevented so many


diffi-

people from trying to comprehend the exact


culty which

empiricism of

Kant and Kant's successors saw in the Hume, and the extremely ingenious
in

method which they adopted


for

order to avoid
it

it

when

these are understood,


is

becomes

at

once

plain that the difficulty

a real one, and that the


rate,

solution offered of
ation.

it,

at

any

deserves consider-

The
nor,

relation in
it

which Kant stands to


is
I,

Hume
said,

is
;

not a topic which


if it v/ere,

necessary for
it

me

to discuss

could

need hardly be

add

anything to what Professor Green and

Professor

Caird, not to mention previous commentators, have

already written on the subject.

What more
cendentalist

directly concerns
I

my

purpose

is

to

examine the answer which, as

suppose, a transscepticism of the

would make

to the

preceding chapters, on the only two points where


his defence of the
really

grounds of science and


ground.
I

my

attack

meet on common
'

mean

causation

and the
world.'

existence of a persistent and independent

Now
problem

the usual
is

way
*

in

which the transcendental


is

put

is,

How

knowledge possible
most

and, taking transcendentalism as an answer to


this,
it

Hume,

the usual way,

is

also the

natural,

because

was Hume's theory of the origin of knowledge


to scepticism.

which led necessarily

As, however.

S8

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


I

[part

ii.

in this essay

have put forward no theory of the


from

origin

of knowledge,

my

point of view the


'

question should

rather be stated,

How much
is

of

what pretends
such,
tract

to
?
'

be knowledge must we accept as

and why

My

business, therefore,

to ex-

from the answer which the transcendentalist


first

gives to the

enquiry, an answer which shall,

if
it

possible, satisfy the


is

second

and

for this

purpose

necessary to
in

change

the

make a slight, though only a usual mode of stating his doctrine.


first

slight,

The
I

reader will recollect, that in the

chapter

insisted

on the obvious truth that every tenable

system of knowledge must consist partly of premises

which require no proof, and partly of inferences


which are legitimately drawn from these.

What,

then, on the transcendental theory, are our premises,

and by what method do we derive from them the


required conclusion
If
?

we were simply
and
seize

to glance at transcendental
first

literature,

on the

apparent answers to
to think that

these questions,

we should be disposed
is

the philosophers of this school assume to start with

the truth of a large part of what


science,

commonly
to

called

the very thing which, according


it

my

view

of the subject,
prove.
'

is

the business of philosophy to

Respecting pure mathematical and pure


Kant,^
'

natural science,' says


exist,
it

as they certainly

do
are

may

with propriety be asked


^

how they

CritiqueJ

p. 13.

Tr.

CHAP, vl]

transcendentalism.
;

89

possible

for that they

must be possible

is

shown by

the fact of their really existing.'


'

The

question,

How

is
'

knowledge possible
to

is

not,'

says Professor Green,

be confused with the

question upon which metaphysicians are sometimes

supposed

to

waste their time,


is

Is

knowledge possible

....

Metaphysic

no superfluous labour.
is

It is

no more superfluous, indeed, than


process which without theory

any theory of a
^

we

already perform.'

Passages of

this sort

would almost lead one

to con-

clude that the business of transcendental speculation

was not
existence

to justify beliefs, but to account for their


;

to to
is

tell

us
it
:

how we do

a thing, not whether

we ought
philosophy

do

a view by which, apparently,

regarded as dealing with the laws of

thought much as physiology deals with the laws of


digestion.
If this

were

so,

transcendentalism might

be an important and useful department of science,


but
this
it

could have nothing to do with the subject of


It

essay.

would answer no doubt,


But,
in

it

would

solve

no

difficulty.

truth,

the

language

often used

by Kant and echoed above by Professor


not
incorrect,
is
is

Green,

if

certainly

misleading.

Transcendentalism

philosophical, in the sense in


to use the

which

have ventured

term

it

does

attempt to establish a creed, and, therefore, of necessity


it

indicates the nature of our premises

and the

Contemporary Review

T)tc. i^j J.

90

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


in

[part

ii.

manner

which the subordinate beHefs

may be

legitimately derived from them.

On
explicit

the

first

point

its
;

statements are not, indeed,

and categorical

but

this is

simply because,

for historical

reasons, the philosophic


it

problem has

not been presented to

exactly in the shape which

makes such statements necessary.


I

Nevertheless,

all

suppose that a transcendentalist would postulate


first

in

the

instance, or rather all that each


is

man who
is

studies his system

required to postulate,
of,

that he

knows, and

is

certain

sornethmg

he

is

conscious,

for example, or

may be

conscious, that he perceives


;

a coloured object, or a particular taste

in

other

words, he gets some knowledge, small or great, by


experie7ice.

This

very
it

moderate

concession,

then,

being

granted, as

must be granted, by the

sceptic, the

is. How can any knowledge worth speaking of be inferred from such premises ?

next question that arises

It

is

in

the

answer

to

this
in

that such

force

and
is

originality as there
really

may be
it

transcendentalism

to

be found; and

is
is

here that the

full

meaning of the question which

placed at the head


'

of that philosophy becomes manifest.

You

allow,'
'

we may suppose

a transcendentalist to say,
is

You

allow that experience

possible

you allow that

it may only be of the facts of immediate perception, can be obtained by that channel. I therefore ask you '' how that experience

some knowledge, though

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.
"

91

is

possible

in

what

it

essentially consists
I

and

whatever

fact or principle

can show to be involved


I

in that experience
if

that experience

whatever can prove must be of that you must,


is

be,
in

to

common
and
of
it

consistency, grant the reality.'


is

principle

so proved
is

said to be

transcendentally deduced,'

the validity of that deduction in the cases

causation
it

and
is

the

existence

of

a persistent

world, that

my

business

more

particularly to

examine.

The whole

value,

then, of the

transcendental

philosophy, so far as the questions raised in -this

essay are concerned, must depend on


to

its

being able

show

that the trustworthiness of these far-reaching

scientific postulates is

involved in those simple ex-

periences which everybody must allow to be valid.


If
it

cannot prove

this,

it

may

still

be a valuable
;

contribution to a possible philosophy

it

may

still

show by
nature,

its

searching analysis

all

that

is

implied in

the existence of nature, as w^e ordinarily understand

and of the sciences of nature as we are taught

to accept

them

but more than this

it

cannot do
exists,

it

cannot show either that such a nature

or that

our accounts of

it

are accurate

it

cannot, in other

words, supply us with a philosophy adequate to our


necessities.

Before going on to consider the general value


of this method, or the success of
particular instances,
it

its

application in

may be

well to give

some

92

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


its

[part

ii.

examples of
character
for

reasonings by which

its

precise

may be more
is

clearly understood.

Here,

instance,

one taken from Kant's proof of

the principle of substance

ceived by us except in

Change cannot be persubstances, and origin or


'
:

extinction in an absolute sense, that does not con-

cern merely a determination of the permanent, can-

not be a possible perception, for

it is

the very notion

of the permanent v/hich renders possible the representation (perception) of a transition from one state
into another,

and from non-being

into being,

which

consequently, can be empirically cognised only as


alternating determination of that which
is

permanent.

....

Substances
all

in the

world of phenomena are

the substratum of

determinations of time.
is

....

Accordingly, permanence

a necessary condition

under which alone phenomena, as things or objects,


are determinable in a possible experience.'
^

Now

the point of this demonstration

lies,

as the

reader will see, in showing, or attempting to show,


that experience of change
is

not possible unless

we

assume unchanging substance.


experience changes (as

Therefore,
certainly

if

we most

we can can), we

are forced also to admit the existence of that without

which change would have no meaning.

Here
Green's

is

another argument of the same kind


I

respecting causation, which


introduction
*

quote from Professor

to

Hume:
Tr.

'A

uniformity

Critique, pp. 140, 141.

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.
(i.e.,

93

which can be thus


blished
istence
is,

by a

single instance) estaIts

in the

proper sense, necessary.


its

ex-

is

not contingent on
It

being

felt

by any-

one or everyone.

does not come into being with


it.

the experiment that shows


real,

It is felt It

because

it is

not real because

it is felt.

may be
is

objected,

indeed, that the principle of the ''uniformity of nature,"

the principle that what


itself

is

fact

once

fact always,

gradually results from the observation of facts


feelings,

which are

and that thus the principle which


due
to such repetition.

enables us to dispense with the repetition of a sensible experience


is

itself

The

answer

is,

that feelings which are conceived as facts

are already conceived as constituents of a nature.

The same

presence of the thinking subject

to,

and

distinction of itself from, the feelings

which renders

them knowable
world which
is

facts, renders

them members of a
its

one throughout

changes.

In

other words, the presence of facts from which the


uniformity of nature as an abstract rule
inferred,
is

is

to

be

already the consciousness of that uni^

formity in concreto!
is,

In this extract the argument


i.e.,

that facts are unknowable,

are no facts for us,

except as members of a uniform nature.

We
;

may
is

be as
as

certain, therefore, of the uniformity of nature

we

are certain that

we

can

know

facts

which

another

way

of saying that
all.

we need have no doubt

about the matter at

Pp. 273, 274.

94

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

to

These quotations are not long enough, perhaps, do full justice to the argument of which they con-^
one statement
sort
;

tain

but they are long enough to


the argument in either case
is.

show of what

And
this
:

the essential force or point of those arguments,


first

as against the sceptic, seems at

sight to

lie

in
is

the
to

sceptic, in

questioning any principle,

shown
tion

be making an illegitimate abstraction from


because

the relations which constitute an object, an abstrac-

which

is

illegitimate,

it

renders

the

object meaningless and unthinkable.

He

has to

choose, therefore, between altogether giving


reality of the object, or

up the
be

admitting a principle implied

by one of the

relations of

which that
all

reality can

shown
do the
second.

to consist.
first
;

He
is

cannot, in

cases at least,
to

he

bound,

therefore,

do the

Now,
this

before proceeding to examine the force of


it

reasoning, as

is

employed

in

proving parti-

cular points, one difficulty

must be discussed which

attaches to

it

generally.

When
argument,

a
it

man
must

is

convinced by a transcendental
I

be, as

have explained, because


is

he perceives that a certain relation or principle


necessary to constitute
his

admitted
truth of

experience.

This

is

to

him a

fact,

the

which he

is

obliged to recognise.

But another
is

fact,

which he

may

also find
it

it

hard to dispute,

that he himself,

and, as

would appear, the majority of mankind,

; '

CHAP, vl]

transcendentalism.
this
it

95

have habitually had


consciously thinking

experience without ever


this relation
;

under
it

and

this

second

fact is

one which

does not seem easy to


shall

interpret in a

manner which

harmonise with

the general theory.

The

transcendentalist wouldj
in question
if it

no doubt, say
not always

at

once that the relation


implicitly,

had always been thought

even
;

had

come

into clear consciousness

and having

enunciated this dictum he would trouble himself no further about a matter which belonged merely to the
*

history of the individual.'


in this
is

But

if an

implicit thought

means
else,
it

connection what

it

means everywhere
is

simply a thought which

logically

bound

up

in

some other thought, and which


very definition,
is
it is

for that reason

may always be
from
this

called into existence

by

it.

Now,
a mere

plain that so long as a


exist.
It is

thought

implicit

it

does not

possibility,

which may

indeed at any

an

actuality,

and which,
;

moment become when once an actuality, may


it is

be indestructible
bility,

but which, so long as

a possi-

can be said to have existence only by a figure

of speech.
If,

therefore, this

meaning of the word


ourselves
in

implicit

be

accepteci,

we

find

difficulty.

Either an object can exist and be a reality to an


intelligence

which does not think of


as
I
I

it

under

relait,

tions which,

now

see,

are involved in

i.e.,

without which

cannot

or

else

am

in error,

now think of it as an object when I suppose myself and

96

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

other people to have ignored these relations in past


times.
If the first of these alternatives is true, the
I

whole transcendental system, as


vanishes in

understand
it

it,

smoke

if

the

second,

comes

into

apparent

conflict,

not only with science, and with the


opinions of

avowed
sophy

scientific

many

of

its

disciples,

but with the later form of the transcendental philoitself.


is

For by
in

that system the


;

development
its
till

of thought

stages

it

is

driven on by

own
the

proper nature from one stage to another


highest of them
rest
is

reached, where alone

it

can find

and

satisfaction.

But those who believe most

firmly in this theory

by no means intend

to assert as
is

a historical fact that every thinking being


lectually restless until

intel-

he has grasped the philosophy


they must rather be held to

of the Absolute.

What

mean

is,

that the inadequacy

and

self-contradiction
cate-

of a universe thought under

any of the lower


or he

gories can be demonstrated, and


to

when demonstrated
I

me

or any other thinking being,

may be

obliged to seek repose by including the contradictory

elements under some category which shall reconcile

them
as

in

a higher unity
fact,

but, they

must admit
not

that,

a matter of
to

this

demonstration has been


are

vouchsafed

few.

There

many,

for

example, who, whatever their perplexities, can find


intellectual satisfaction in
'

such a formula as this:

The

universe
itself,

is

the process whereby spirit exter-

nalises

or manifests itself in an external world,

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.
by a movement
of
at

97

that out of this externaUty,


positive

once

and negative,

sciousness of self'^

may rise to the The great body


it

highest con-

mankind

certainly prefer a contradiction


see,

which they do not


to be

to a reconciliation
;

which they do not underis

stand

and what

desire

not

shown how,
is

on transcendental grounds, such a position


able,

unten-

but how
is

its

existence, as a fact,

is

to

be con-

sistently accounted for.

The analogy of the ordinary


It is true,

logic

here misleading.

no doubt, that

we may intelligently
all

hold premises without perceiving

or any of the deductions which

may be

legiti-

mately drawn from them, and


premises in such a case,
clusion
;

that, in asserting the

we

implicitly assert the condifficulty,

but this presents no

because

it is

not the recognition of the conclusion which makes


sense of the premises.
the case
is

In transcendental reasoning

exactly the other way.

The

ground, and

the whole ground, on which

we

are forced by that

reasoning to recognise the reality of certain relations,


is,

that without those relations the object of


for
;

which we have experience would be as nothing


us
;

it

would have neither meaning nor


I

significance

and what

wish to

know

is,

how

it

happens that

there exists any object at

all

for so

many people
of
to

who
tuted.

are

wholly innocent of
it

any knowledge
said
in this

those relations by which


If

is

be

constiit

there
^

is

any value

objection,

Caird's Kant^ p. 427.

98

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


it

[part

ii.

would apparently follow from

movement or So long inference in this logic is an impossibility. so long as as the transcendentalist refuses to move he merely declines to abstract the relations by which
that

an object

is

already constituted,
;

he

stands, perhaps,

on firm ground

but directly he

tries to oblige

us

to think a thing

under new

relations,

his

method
If,

becomes either ineffective or self-destructive.


the one hand,

on

we can think
there
;

the object not under these

new

relations,

is

nothing in the method to

compel us to do so

for the

method

consists in

show-

ing that without this

new
it

relation the object


If,

would

not exist for us as thinking beings.

on the other

hand,

we

cannot think

except under these

new

re-

lations, then, either

we were not thinking it before or the relations are not new and in either case there is no inferential movement of thought from the known to the unknown. From these reflections it would appear that the
;

transcendentalist must either give


fact

up the seeming

on which
fact

his

system depends, or explain away a


is

seeming
fact
is,

which

inconsistent with
is

it.

The
is,

first

that a given relation


;

necessary to constitute
that a

a knowledge of an object
great

the second fact

many

intelligent beings,

and the transcendenlife

talist himself,

during the earlier part of his

among

the number, appear able to


tion.

know

it

out of this rela-

Now,

one solution

of this

difificulty

has been

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.
;

99

already disposed of

it

has been shown, or rather

stated (for the assertion requires no proof), that a

thought which
at
all, it is

is

merely implicit

is

really

no thought

a creation of language, which can constiit is

tute nothing because

nothing.

It
is

may however,

perhaps, be said that the thought

neither merely

implicit nor wholly explicit, but exists in a kind of

intermediate stage between nonentity and the fulness


of clear consciousness
;

a stage
'

in

which

it is

strong

enough, so to speak, to
not strong enough to be

constitute an object,' but


to the individual for

known

whom

it

performs this important function.


is

This

apparently one of the views taken by the

transcendentalist^; for

Kant
that
*

says, with the approval

of Professor Caird,
unity)

the

consciousness (of a

may be

but weak, so that

we become aware
unity

of

it

only in the result produced, and not in the act


it
;

of producing

but

that,

nevertheless, the

of consciousness must always


it

be present, though

has not clearness sufficient to

make

it

stand out'

In other words, the unity of consciousness which

is

necessary for the existence of any experience


lie

may

hidden, like a drop of


until
its

reagent,

some powerful chemical presence is made certain by the


this

analysis of

its results.

Such a theory as
its

requires us to hold that

thought may, so to speak, diminish the amount of


being
till

it

ceases

to

be known as thought,
p. 395.

See Caird's Kant,

100

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


;

[part

ii.

thought not to behave as such


first

and no doubt the

half of this statement

is

correct.

That a

seninis,

sation can be

weaker or stronger, can change

its

tensive quantity (to use the technical expression)

of course, plain.

It

can also be thought of under

more or fewer
it

relations.

And

in

both these ways

may The same may be According as we


rather than on

be said to have varying degrees of being.


said,
fix

mutatis mutandis, of thought.

our attention on the relation


related,

the things

so

we may,

suppose, say that our consciousness of the relation


increases or diminishes
;

but the utmost diminution


is

of which the consciousness


hilation,

capable without anniin its quality


;

makes no

alteration

and

if

the consciousness vanishes, the thought must vanish


too,

since,

except on some crude materialistic hypo-

thesis,

they are the same thing.

This quantitative

or intensive diminution of being, then, will not explain the apparent fact that so
feel the necessity of

many people do

not

thinking things under their sup-

posed necessary

relations.

The second manner

in

which any object of


its

thought can be imagined to vary

being depends
;

on the number of relations by which it is qualified and in this respect thought also, not less than sensation,

may be

said to increase or diminish.

Relations
is,

may
as,

be compared and classed


less

that

may
;

be

thought under relations not

than feelings
is

and

no doubt, a relation which

not so compared

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.,''

'

'

ici

and classed cannot be an object of thought, cannot be known as a relation, it may be supposed that here

we have
which
is

a definition of that intermediate


required to smooth over our
it

stage

difficulties.

Every man,
enlightened

may be

said,

really thinks objects


us,

under the relations which seem to

who have been


be necessary
;

by transcendentalism,

to

but he

is

not aware that he does

so,

because he has

not taken the trouble to consider them from the


points of view from which alone they can appear as
relations to him.

But
*

if this

be

trye,
*

what becomes
intelligi
'

of the identity of the


If relations

esse

'

and the

can exist otherwise than as they are


?

thought,

why

should not sensations do the same

Why should

not the

'

perpetual flux

'

of unrelated

objects the metaphysical spectre which the modern


transcendentalist labours so hard to lay,
say, should this not

why,
1

have a

real existence

We^
of
it

indeed, cannot in our reflective

moments think
it

except under relations which give


but once allow that an object

a kind of unity

may

exist,

but in such

a manner as to
beings,

make
is

it

nothing for us as thinking

and

this incapacity

may be

simply due to the

fact that

thought

powerless to grasp the reality of

things.

The
liarly

transcendentalist, then,
to

would seem pecuwhich

bound

admit what no philosopher, perhaps,


to deny, that thought
is

would be disposed
not

known

as thought cannot properly be said to

rp2-

A;r?5:5EKC,E

of philosophic doubt,
is

[parth.

exist at

all.

He

therefore reduced to one of

two
an

alternatives.

Either he must maintain that

it is

error of

memory and

observation to suppose that


all

every intelligence does not at

times think objects

under their necessary

relations, or else
is,

he must hold
is

that a necessary relation

not a relation that

actually required to constitute

an object for a think-

ing being, but

is

only one which, upon due reflection,


is

a thinking being

unable to

make

abstraction
is

of.

The
is

first

of these alternatives

somewhat too
which
it

violent a contradiction of that experience

the business of transcendentalism to justify, to be

seriously maintained

by transcendentalists.
fact that

Accordnecessary

ingly

we

find

them admitting the

relations are not always thought as qualifying the

object they are

supposed to constitute

in

other

words, accepting the second of the alternatives mentioned above, but at the

same time declining any

responsibility concerning a circumstance which, ac-

cording to them, has to do only w4th the history of


the individMal.
*

The

''

think,"

'

says

Kant
'

(I

am

quoting Proac-

fessor Caird's translation),

must be capable of

companying
thought

all

my

ideas, for otherwise

something

would be presented
;

to
is

my mind
the

which could not be


as to say that
it

and that

same thing
Again,
*

the idea would be either impossible, or, at least,

would be nothing

for me.'

All ideas have

a necessary reference to a possible empirical con-

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.

103

sciousness

....
.

but, again, all empirical conscious-

ness has a necessary reference to a transcendental


consciousness.
.
.

The mere

idea "

I," in

reference
it

to all other ideas (whose collective unity


possible),
is

makes
This

the transcendental consciousness.

idea

may be clear (empiric consciousness) or obscure. This we do not need to consider at present, nor even
it

whether

actually exists at
all
it

all

but the possibility


rests necessarily

of the logical form of

knowledge

on the reference of
faculty!
'

and

this

apperception as a
Professor
is

In other words,* says


this passage,
*

Caird,

commenting on

Kant

here examin-

ing what elements are involved in knowledge, and


therefore does not need to consider

how

far the clear

consciousness of them

is

developed

in the individual,

nor indeed whether


sensitive being

tJie

individual ever actually deveall.

lopes that consciousness at

The

individual (the

who becomes

the subject of

knowmerely

ledge)

may be

at different stages

on the way

to clear

self-consciousness.

He may be sensitive with


:

the dawning of consciousness

he

may

be conscious
;

of

objects,

but not distinctly self-conscious

or,

he

may be
to have

clearly conscious of the

identity of self in

relation to the objects.

Thus we can imagine him


has not distinctly
self; or

many perceptions, which he

combined with the idea of


suppose him
their
life)

we may even
period of
all,

(like children in the earliest

not to have risen to the idea of self at

to the separation of the ego from the act

whereby

104

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


is

[part

ii.

/the object

determined.

But we cannot imagine


for such ideas

ihim to have any ideas which are incapable of being

Icombined with the idea of


Joe ideas

self,

would

incapable of being thought, incapable of


intelligible contents of conscious"

forming part of the


ness
;

they would be for us a thinking being,

as

good as nothing."
critical

Though,
all

therefore,

we

can think

of an experience in which

the elements which the

philosopher distinguishes are not consciously

or separately present to the individual,

we

cannot

think of an experience which does not imply


all.'
^

them
in

From

these extracts
latest

it

would appear that both

Kant and Kant's


^thinking that
all

expositor are agreed

that

is

required to constitute a

perception

in

other words, an experience is not

that the object of that perception should actually

be

/thought in the relations which


sary to

we

are told are necesit

make

it

an

object,

but only that

should be

capable of being so thought.

But with such an adwhich thought


to

mission the whole transcendental argument appears


to

me

to vanish

away.

The

rules

was supposed

to impress

upon Nature, according

which Nature must be, because without them she would be nothing to us as thinking beings, these

rules

turn out, after

all,

to

be only of subjective

validity.
flective

They

are the casual necessities of our re:

moments unmeaning to us

necessities

which would have been

in
*

our childhood, of which the mass

Phil, of Kant^ p. 396.

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.
conscious,

105

of

mankind are never

and from which we


truth)

ourselves are absolved during a large portion of our


lives.

To

argue from these necessities to the


is

of things

merely to repeat the old fallacy abouD


if

innate ideas in another form, for

thought does not^


in

make experience (and


gible

it

appears that
it

any

intelli-

meaning of that expression


is

does not), then

there

no reason

for

supposing that experience need

conform to thought.

The

net result of this discussion appears, then,

to be that, according to transcendentalism, relations

are involved in experience in at least two ways, the


difference

between which, though


is

it

is

never recog-

nised

by that philosophy,

exceedingly important.

According

to the first way,

an explicit consciousness
is

of the relation in question

a necessary element in
it

every possible experience

without

the experience

would be
it,
'

'

nothing to us as thinking beings,' and by

therefore, the experience

may very

fairly

be said

>^

to

be

constituted.'

But the number of

relations,

necessary in this sense, cannot be large, even ac-

cording to the transcendentalists themselves

nor can

the necessity ever be established by argument, since

the mere fact that

somebody who knows the meanit,

ing of the words he uses disputes

proves that

it

does not

exist.

If

man

does not find that a


is

particular relation, about which there


is

a question,

involved in his experience, an argument founded


is

on the circumstance that no experience

possible


A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,
is

io6

[part

ii.

which

not in fact constituted by an explicit conis

sciousness of such a relation,

not likely to convince


that

him

that
is

proof

The mere consideration proof impossible. makes required


it

is

there.

The second way

in

which a transcendentalist
differs

re-

gards relations as involved in experience

from
;

that just discussed in several important particulars


for

whereas

in that the explicit consciousness of the

relation
all

was required
is

to constitute the object, in this

that

required

is

that the object

must be capable
It is plainly

of being thought under the relation.

incorrect to describe the relation in this last case as


*

constituting the object

'

it

cannot even be said

that the capability of being thought under the relation necessarily constitutes
it
;

for,

according to the
'

transcendentalist,

'

esse
is,

'

is

equivalent to
it

intelligi

'

that

is,

an object

as

is

apprehended by a
is

thinking being, and since a thinking being can, as


admitted, apprehend
it

without in

all

cases perceiv-

ing the capability, this cannot be required to render


the object
lations
is

real.

As far then as this second class


in

of re-

concerned, the transcendentalisms argument

seems involved

something
in

like fatal inconsistency.

Because he finds himself,


*

bringing an object into

clear consciousness,' unable to


relation,

make
this

abstraction of
incapacity into
;

a certain

he elevates

a universal and necessary characteristic of objects


while at the same time admitting that other

intelli-

gences and his own intelligence at other times have

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.
had objects presented
to

107

actually

them without

this

characteristic.

Enough has perhaps been


objection
(if It

said about this general


to the transcendental

be an objection)

method, and

it is

now time

to follow the philosophers

who employ it, in their special endeavours to show that when the nature of experience Is once brought
to the
rate,
'

clear consciousness

'

of the reader, he, at any

can be in no further doubt as to the necessity

of regarding objects in space as persistent and inde-

pendent, and

all

objects whatever as subject to the

law of universal causation.


Kant's refutation of Idealism was only introduced
into the second edition of the
*

Critique,'

and was the


edition of

main occasion of Schopenhauer's assertion that Kant

had changed
that

his

view between the

first

work and the second, respecting the external


I

world.

understand,

however, that
;

this

is

not

admitted by his later


'

critics

that they regard the


itself,

Refutation

'

as

satisfactory In

and as harIts

monising with the general course of


speculations
;

author's

tained

in

It

and that the proof of realism conIs the one on which they would be

disposed to
to criticise
I
*

rely.

As

such, therefore,

am

forced

It.

say forced,' because


I

It is

somewhat unwillingly
an
is

that

go

to

Kant

direct for the statement of

argument, partly because there

never any security

that his disciples will admit that his reasoning in

any

io8

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


is

[part

ii.

particular case

in

consonance with the rest of his


is

system

partly because his obscurity

so great that

his critics are as likely to

be attacked for not under-

standing his

arguments as for not having answered


suddenly converted
his expo-

them, a proceeding by which what was intended to

be a philosophic discussion
into a historical one.
sition are so great that

is

Yet the defects of


no care

will really avert this

danger

for

he has contrived to state a theory

of

great difficulty in itself,

and of which
all

his

own grasp

does not appear to have been at


sure

times perfectly

in

language which always seems to be strug-

gling to express a
quite clear,

meaning which

it

can never get

and which possesses

in

an astonishing

degree the peculiarity of being technical without


being precise.
As, however,
I

am
is

not acquainted with any neo-

Kantian statement of the transcendental argument

on

this subject,
;

it

to

Kant himself
formal
is

that

must
of

appeal

and, fortunately, the

refutation

Idealism which he has advanced

so short (apart
it

from the elucidatory notes) that


It

runs as follows

can quote

entire.

Theorem.
*

ness

The simple but empirically determined consciousof my own existence proves the existence of ex-

ternal objects in space'


1

The

translation here referred to

is

Mr. Meiklejohn's.

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.

109

Proof.
'

am

conscious of

my own

existence as deter-

mined

in time.

All determinations in regard to time

pre-suppose the existence of something permanent in


perception.

But
in

this

permanent something cannot

be something
something.

me, for the very reason that

my

ex-

istence in time

is itself

determined by this permanent

It

follows that the perception of this


is

permanent existence

possible only through a thing

without me, and not through the mere representation


of a thing without me.

Consequently, the deteris

mination of

my

existence in time

possible only

through the existence of real things external to me.

Now,

consciousness in time

is

necessarily connected

with the consciousness of the possibility of this determination in time.


ness in time
is

Hence

it

follows that conscious-

necessarily connected also with the

existence of things

without me, inasmuch as the


is

existence of these things

the condition of deter-

mination in time.
of

That
is

is

to say, the consciousness

my own

existence

at the

same time an imme-

diate consciousness of the existence of other things

without me.'

This proof,
i.e.,

it

will

be observed,
is

is

transcendental,
that an ex-

its

method of procedure

to

show
[that,

perience which

we
^

certainly

have
167.

namely, of

CritiqueJ

tr. p.

no A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

the series of our mental states as they occur in time]


is

impossible, unless the thing to be proved [which

is

stated (though, as

we

shall see, inadequately stated)

to be the existence of external objects in space]

be ad-

mittedFirst,

And

the demonstration consists of two steps.

it is

asserted that the experience of a succesis

sion of things in time


to

impossible except in relation


in

something permanent, or
is

other words, that the

perception of change
the

inconceivable, unless

we

at

same time perceive something which does not

change.

And

in

the second place,

Kant goes on
in this
*

to .say, that since that


is

which changes
self),

case
'

myself (my phenomenal each

since the

things

iwhich succeed

other in

time are

my own
is,

Imental states, the unchanging object to which they

are referred must be outside myself

that

must

be the external object whose existence was to be


proved.
one,
it

So

can

we immediately perceive the only be on condition that we immediately


that
if

perceive the other also.

Such

is

the formal answer which


;

Kant has given


only that he

to Idealism

but

it

is

not in this

way

has treated the question, since


*

in his

proof of the
'

principle of substance

'

[which precedes the

refu-

tation' in the

'Critique,'] he has brought forward


if

arguments which,

sound, would seem to render


'

any further

'

refutation

superfluous.

For, the

First
in all
;

Analogy of Experience'

asserts this,
is

'That

changes of phenomena substance

permanent

and

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.
is

m
it is)

the quantum thereof in nature

neither increased

nor diminished.'

And
if it is
is

as

by substance Kant means


I

something which,

not (as

think

exactlyis

equivalent to what

commonly
is

called matter,
is

at
;

any

rate the
this

genus of which matter


proposition
in

one species

clearly

absolutely
in

inconsistent
I

with Idealism
term.
If

the
is

sense

which

use the

matter

to be thought of as

permanent

and

indestructible,

we

are clearly under the necesis

sity of thinking that there

in nature

something be-

sides the fleeting succession of our conscious states.

The
I

proof of this Principle of Substance, which

give partly in Kant's words, partly in Professor

Caird's,
this

way
:

and partly
*

in

my

own, runs somewhat


exist in time.

in
is

All

phenomena

Change
But

only conceivable in an unchanging time.

this

time
tion,

is

not,
is

and cannot

be, itself

an object of percep-

but

rather a form given to the relations of

perception which supposes that they are otherwise


related.

They must be
all

otherwise related as deter-

minations of a permanent substance.


are in one time, so

As
in

all

times

changes must be

one per-

manent

object.
is

The

conception of the permanence


all

of the object

implied in

determinations of

its

changes.

Change involves

that one

mode

of exist-

ence follows another

mode

of existence in an object

recognised as the same.


changes, changes only in
^

Therefore a thing which


its

states or accidents, not

Critique, p. 136.

'

112

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

in its substance.

An
is

experience of absolute anniimpossible, for


it

hilation or creation

would be an

experience of two events so absolutely separated

from each other that they could not even be referred The First Analogy,' therefore, is a to one time.'
*

deduction from the possibility of experience, and-^


requires no empirical proof.

When

a philosopher

was asked,

'

What

is

the weight of

smoke

?
'

he

answered, 'Subtract from the weight of the burnt

wood
will

the weight of the remaining ashes, and you

have the weight of the smoke.'


it

Thus, he prein fire the

sumed
of
it

to

be incontrovertible that even

matter (substance) does not perish, but only the form

undergoes a change.^
reader will at once perceive that .while there
that
is

The
is
*

much

common

to the

Refutation

'

and the

First Analogy,' there are

trines peculiar to each,

some arguments and doca fact which makes the satis;

factory discussion of the question rather difficult

because,

while

it

is

impossible to
it

arguments as

identical,

is

the two somewhat clumsy and


treat

would lead

to a

good deal of

repetition to consider

them altogether separately. The most convenient


first

course,

perhaps, will be
in

to consider the points

which are to be found

both, and then to proceed with the examination of


their mutual relationship

and with what

is

special to

each of them.

Cf.

Kant, Critique^

p.

136

Caird, p. 453.

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.
first

113

The
*

difficulty,

then,

which occurs to me,


feel, refers
is

and which, perhaps, others may


transcendental
necessity
'

to that

which

the very pith


in the

and marrow of the whole demonstration, both


'

Refutation

'

and

in the
*

First Analogy.'

Is

it

really
*

true that change

is

nothing to us as thinking beings


it

except

we

conceive

in relation to
?

a permanent and

unchanging substance
I
I

For

my part, however much


'

try to bring the matter into


feel

clear consciousness,'

myself bound by no such necessity.

For

though change
for

may perhaps be
calls
*

unthinkable, except

what Professor Green


and though
to
'

combining,' and,

therefore, to a certain extent a


ness,'
it

persisting conscious-

may have no meaning


is
'

out of
^

relation

that which

not-change,' this

not-

change by no means implies permanent substance.

On

the contrary, the smallest recognisable persis-

tence through time would

seem enough
;

to
I

make
cannot
its

change in time

intelligible

by contrast
fact

and

help thinking that the opposite opinion derives


chief
plausibility

from the
is

that

in

ordinary
;

language permanence

the antithesis to change

whence
tives

it

is

rashly

assumed

that they are correlain

which imply each other


It

the

system of

nature.

has to be noted also, that Kant, in his

proof of the analogy, makes a remark (quoted and

approved by Professor Caird) which almost seems


to

concede

this
is

very point, for he says,


:

Only the

permanent

subject to change
I

the mutable suffers

114

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


;

[part

ii.

no change, but rather alternation

that

is,
^

when

certain determinations cease, others begin.'

Now
word
is

there can be no objection, of course, from a philosophical point of view, to an author defining a
in

any sense he pleases

what

is

not permissible

to

make such a

definition
;

the basis of an argument

to matters of fact

yet the above passage suggests

the idea that Kant's proof of the permanence of

substance

is

not altogether free from this vice.

If

(by definition) change can only occur in the permanent, the fact that there is

change
is

is

no doubt a
But\
this

conclusive proof that there


the

'

permanent.'
in

question then arises,


?

is

there change
is

sense

How

do we know that there

anything

more than

alternation which (by definition) can take


?

place in the mutable

All transcendental arguments


*

convince by threats.
say,
'

Allow

my

conclusion,' they

or

will

prove to you that you must surrender


beliefs.'

one of your own cherished


the threat
is

But

in this

case

hardly calculated to frighten the most

timid philosopher.

There must be a permanent, say


;

the transcendentalistS; or there can be no change

but this surely

is

no very serious calamity,

if

we

are
I

allowed to keep alternation, which seems to me,


confess, a

very good substitute, and one with Avhich

the ordinary

To

those

man may very well content himself. who agree with the preceding account

of our intellectual necessities,


^

who can

either conceive

Critiqjie, p. 140.

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.

115

change without permanence, or are content to get


along with the help of
solutely fatal to the
in the
' '

alternation,'

it

will

seem ab-

whole Kantian argument, both


'

First

Analogy

and the
it

'

Refutation/

To

those

who do

not agree,

will

only be a difficulty in

so far as the existence of any

mind unconscious of
the
disI

transcendental necessities
transcendental theory,cussed.

is

inconsistent with

point

have already

But

let

us pass over

this,

and

grant, for the

sake of argument, that change


succession of our mental
states

in general,
in

or the

particular,

can

only be perceived in relation to a permanent something


;

then

ask (and this

is

the next most obvious

objection) why, in

order to obtain this permanent

something, should
the reader
supplies,
is

we go
'

to external matter

As
*

aware, the

pure

eg-o

of apperception

on the Kantian system, the unity

in refe-

rence to which alone the unorganised multiplicity of


perception becomes a possible experience
;

and

it

seems hard to understand why that which supplies


unity to multiplicity
to succession.
objection,

may
to

not also supply permanence


indeed, anticipated this
;

Kant

has,
it

and replied

but as
I

understand the
reply,
I

objection

much

better than

do the
latter,
'

will

content myself with giving the


phrase, in Kant's
'

without para-

own words

We

find,'

he says,

that

we

possess nothing permanent that can corre-

spond and be submitted to the conception of a


substance
as
intuition,

except matter.
I

In

ii6

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


/,

[part

ii.

the representation

the consciousness of myself,

is

not an intuition, but a merely intellectual representation

produced by the spontaneous activity of a


It follows,

thinking subject.

that this
Its

has not any

predicate of intuition, which, in

character of per-

manence, could serve as correlate to the determination of time In the internal sense. In the
as impenetrability
Is
^

same way

the correlate of matter as an

empirical intuition.'

Though
'

do not profess altogether


it
is,

to

understand
it,

this reasoning,

at all events, clear


Is

from

that

the permanent

'

whose existence
;

demonstrated
Is

must be an object of perception


the

a fact which

also evident from various passages In the proof of


*

First Analogy,' as, for instance, this

' :

Time

itself

cannot be an object of perception.


is

It

follows

that in objects of perception, that

in

phenomena,
^

there

must be found a substratum,' &c.


see indeed

It

is
i

difficult to

how

that which

Is

a quantity,

incapable of either increase or diminution, can be

other than an object of perception


events, be a concept
;

it
I

cannot, at
think,

all

and we may,

assume

from the whole tenor of Kant's argument, as well as from his categorical assertions, that the substance of which he speaks is a phenomenal ^Atng: But If it
be perceived, and
to be found
?

if it

be a phenomenon, where

is It

In the perpetual flux of nature,


persist for a time, but
3

where
(to all

objects
'

do indeed

where

Critique, p. i68.

Critique, p. 137.

CHAP, vl]

transcendentalism.
is

T17

appearance) nothing

eternal,

who
?

has had expe-

By a dialectical process, probably familiar to the reader, we may with much plausibility reduce what we perceive in an
rience of this unchanging existence

object to a collection of related attributes, not one of

which

is

the object

itself,

but

all

of which are the


object.
'

changing attributes or accidents of the


if

But
of

this

process be legitimate, the


is

'

substratum

these accidents
at all events,
is

either never perceived at

all, or,

only

known
it is

as a relation.

In neither

case can

it

be the permanent of which Kant speaks,


first

since in the

case

not an object of immediate


it

perception

in the
all.

second
'

can hardly be regarded


replied),

as an object at

But

(it

may perhaps be

by a remarkable coincidence, science has established by a wide induction the very truth which Kant attempts to prove a priori.
us that matter
that
is

When men
it is

of science

tell

indestructible,

to

be presumed

they attach some meaning

to the phrase,

and

are referring neither to a metaphysical substance nor


to an evanescent appearance.

When Kant

uses the

same phrase,
the

may be supposed that he refers to same object.' For my own part, I confess to a
it

rooted distrust of

these

remarkable coincidences

between the

results
;

of scientific

experiment and

a priori speculation

nor does a closer examination


It

of this particular case tend to allay the feeling.


is

true,

no doubt, that science asserts matter to be


;

indestructible

but what

is

the exact meaning of the

ii8

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


and what
is its

[part

ii.

phrase,

evidence

Can we perceive
all

any thread of

identity running through

the various

changes which (what

we

describe as) one substance

may undergo ? To a certain extent science assures There are two, though, so far as I us that we can.
know, only two attributes of matter, namely,
tion to a
its rela-

moving
put

force

and

its

power of

attracting

and being attracted by


alter
*
;

other matter, which never


strictly, if

or, to

it

more
'

we

take a certain

area of observation

(say a closed vessel) out of


it

which matter cannot pass and into which


enter, then,

cannot
the

whatever changes occur within

this,

matter there, whether always the same or not, never


varies in respect of these

two

properties.

But

it

has to be observed, that though


velocity

we

can
fact

directly perceive both

and weight, the

that there are

unchanging relations between a given

portion of matter and a given force, or between two


portions of given matter, can only be established

by an elaborate process of inference involving a large number of assumptions. It might, therefore,


be plausibly contended that though they are perceived,
\ki\x permanence is

not, so that

they cannot

properly be said to form any permanent element in


perception.

Passing over this possible objection,

however, and, granting for the sake of argument,


that

we

directly perceive

the permanence of these


it

two properties of matter,

is

still

clear, that since

these are the only two properties of which

we

can

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.

119

say as much, either they must constitute matter, or


matter, in so far as
it

is

permanent, cannot be an
first

object

of perception.

The
these

alternation

is

in-

admissible,
relations

because

properties

are

merely

between certain portions of matter and The second would seem to be something else.
inconsistent with the Kantian proof.

The

reader will understand that

am

not here

contending that Kant's conclusion

is

inconsistent
is

with science, or that the scientific inference


either in
its
:

wrong,
is

method or

its

results.

My

point

rather

this

Though
its

Kant does

not, of course,

conclude to the necessary permanence of matter

merely from
theless
to
its

permanence
in

in perception,

never-

permanence
in

perception would seem

be involved

his proof.
so

Now
it
;

assert that
is

what we perceive, in
either not matter or
tain that
scientific
is

far as

is perceived,

not permanent

and

main-

an examination of that part of the ordinary


or empirical proof which

bears on the

question really confirms this view.


It

may

perhaps be thought (and some of Kant's

expressions countenance the view) that he means to

say no more than that

we

perceive the permanent


its

substance by means of certain of


this

accidents.
First,

But
is

seems

to raise

new

difficulties.

how

the phenomenal substance thus mediately known, to

be distinguished from the


if it

z^^//;;^^;/^/

substance which,

be known at

all, is

known

precisely in the

same

I20

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

way
or

Why should we suppose to Why should we suppose space


?
it ?

be
it

in

time

to

be a

quantity

And

how,

finally,

can

we
is

say with any


at

meaning, that such a substance


all ?

phenomenal

To

put the matter


that
*

in

one sentence
in

when
/

Kant says

all

determination

regard to time

presupposes the existence of something permanent


in perception,' if his assertion is to
it

be taken

literally,
is

is

in contradiction with experience, for there in perception, unless

nothing permanent

we choose
and other

to describe the relations of matter to force

gravitating matter in that

hand, he means that

way if, on the other what we perceive indicates the


:

existence of something permanent, he has


to prove the
fact,

first

got

and has then got


reality
is

to

show

that the
is

permanent
identical

whose

thus

established

with the external


sense
;

world of science and


point out
^

common
be said

and

lastly, to

how we can
which
its

to

be

'

immediately conscious'
through,

of that

we

only

know

and

by means

of,

attributes.

Such, then, are the chief objections which, as


think, apply with equal force to the
'

First

Analogy'

and the
any

'

Refutation.'

Before going on to explain


either, let

difficulties,

which are special to

me
ex-

point out a curious consequence which


tracted from
together.
^

may be

the

two demonstrations

considered

Critiqtie^ p. 167.

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM;
'

X2t

Kant's argument in the


it

Refutation

'

consisted,

will

be recollected)

in

showing that we could have

no experience of our own changing mental states


unless

we perceived some permanent object outside us


'

while in the

First Analogy,' his


all

argument involved
itself never

the assertion that


tions of

changes are but the determina-

some permanent substance, which


According to the
'

changes.
fore,

First Analogy,' therestates,

our changing mental

like
or,

all

other

changes, must be determinations,

as they are
;

usually called, accidents, of a permanent substance


while, according to the
*

Refutation,' this

permanent

substance must be an object of perception indepen-

dent of us and outside us


matter.

in

space

in

other words,
propositions

Between
to

them

these

two

would seem

furnish

a complete transcendental
as

proof that our conscious states must be thought

mere accidents
far

of a material substance

so that the

crude materialism of certain modern physiologists,

from being the rash conclusion of an unphilosophic


is

empiricism,
critical

demonstrable a priori by approved


!

methods

The
'

only further remark


'

have to make on the

First

Analogy

is

of the nature, perhaps, of a verbal


as
if it

criticism.

Kant speaks throughout of matter


nor diminished.

were a

definite quantity in nature, a quantity

which

could neither be increased


this

But

would seem

to be inconsistent with his theory


is

that a

vacuum

impossible, because

if

matter

is

122

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


is,

[part

ii.

wherever space

it

must, one should think, be not A

less impossible to conceive the first as a totality


it

than
'

is

to conceive the
'

second
'

and the words

in/

crease
ingless

and
in
is

diminution

must be altogether meanto

their

application

a quantity whose Kant's expression,


/

amount
held to

necessarily indefinite.
is

therefore,

a somewhat loose one, and he must be|


that matter exists,

mean simply
it

and that no/


I

portion of

can be created or destroyed.

may

vacuum he points out that matter may be a quantity in more than one way, but that neither in the First Analogy nor the Refutation does he explicitly tell us in which way
add, that in his discussion of a
*
'

'

it is

incapable of diminution.

It

would be

interest-

ing to

know

this, in

order that his results might be


results at which,

compared with the


methods,

by very

different

men
I

of science have arrived.


*

My
tion,'

concluding criticism refers to the

Refuta-

and

and

to

must ask the reader to turn back to it, compare the thing which Kant announces his
In the
is

intention of proving with the thing he professes to

have proved.
demonstrated
in

Theorem,' the thing to be

the
*

existence of external objects

space
is

in the

Proof,' the thing actually


'

demonme'

strated

the existence of

in
'

real things external to

that

is,

things which are not themselves something


so,

me, though of course their representations are

without

me

'

being evidently equivalent to

'

other

than

my

conscious states, as determined in time.'

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.
these two expressions really meant the
further refutation of Idealism

123

Now
thing,

if

same

any

would be
for a

perfectly superfluous.

No human

being that under-

stood the meaning of his

own words would


in

moment deny
his body.
in

that there

were objects

space,

and

therefore without

him

in the

sense of being outside


is

The

real question

this-

Does
?

being

space and outside the body imply that the exis

tended and external object

outside the mind, and

other than one of a series of conscious states


realist asserts that
it

The
it

does, the idealist asserts that

does not

and

to assume, as
is

that the one proposition

Kant appears to do, very much the same as


intention
is

the other
at
issue.

is,

in reality,

to

beg the whole question


merely

For unless Kant's

to demonstrate the existence of

extended objects,

which
it

it is
I

equally unnecessary and impossible to do,

must,

suppose, be to

show that

their existence

is

independent of their being perceived


it

neither
in

beginning with
to

nor perishing with

it;

and

order

do

this

he must prove, from his point of view,

two

things.

The
the

first

of these

is,

that the
is

con-

sciousness of one's
possible on

own
i.e.,

existence in time
that

only

supposition

something perindependent

manent
second
thing

exists outside,
is,

other than, one's self; the

that

this

permanent and
identical with
first

is in

any sense

extended matter.
I

The

evidence for the


;

of these positions

have
is

already considered

the evidence for the second

124

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


explicitly stated
it
;

[part

ii.

nowhere

but

cannot help suspect-

ing (though

omitted to
into

seems scarcely credible) that Kant provide any, though a temporary lapse
that
at

the

common though absurd assumption


in

'outside'
all

one

sense

is

equivalent
'

to,

or,

events, necessarily implies,


difficulty

outside

'

in the other.^
feel in

With the

which most philosophers


that

understanding

how

which

is

an

immediate

object of perception can be other than zn co7isciousness,

a difficulty which

is

certainly not lessened

by

the Kantian theory of space,

Kant himself makes


the transcen-

no attempt

to deal.

turn

now from

dental proof of an external world to the transcendental proof of the law of Causation.

In his proof of the law of Causation, contained


in the
'

Second Analogy of Experience,' Kant,


the one on which he

if

understand him rightly, adopts two lines of argu-

ment
stress

appears to lay most


itself

being consistent neither with


In
discussing
it

nor with

the

other.

am

unfortunately

deprived of the assistance of Professor Caird, who,


in the exercise of his

discretion as an expositor of

the

Critical
it.

Philosophy, has
will

chosen practically to

ignore

not venture to determine whether

^ I do not of course suppose that Professor Caird and the NeoKanlians are guilty of the confusion of thought which I here attribute

to Kant.

But (as I explained above) since they appear to be content with the argument in the form in which Kant left it since at all events they have not, so far as I know, thought fit to provide a corrected version of it, I am not only justified, but compelled, to
;

treat

it

as

if it

were an authentic exposition of their views.

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.

125

in so

doing he has or has not somewhat transgressed

even the very wide Hmits imposed on him by the


plan of his work
;

but lest the reader should imagine

that the absence of the


state
in
'

argument
ask

am

about to

from the commentary, implies


original,
^

its

non-existence
consult

the

will

him
it

to

the
attri-

Critique,'

and see whether


range of the

may

not be

buted to Kant with as much plausibility as any


the whole
follows
*

in

Critique.'

It

runs

as

give

it

partly in
italics

my own

words, partly in
:

Our apprehension of the manifold of phenomena is But sometimes we regard this always successive.' manifold of phenomena as constituting an object
Kant's, though the
'

are always mine

(say a house), sometimes as a series of events (as

when a
to

ship

is

seen to float

down a

river).

Subjec-

tively, in

apprehension, these two series would seem


;

be of the same'^kind

objectively, as every

one

knows, we widely distinguish them.

We

no more
if

suppose that the upper story of the house,


begin looking at
it

we

at the top,

is

a phenomenon pre-

ceding

in
is

time the ground


at the

floor,

than

we suppose
perceive the

the ship

same time
in

at

two

different places

on the

river.

Yet

consciousness

we

ground
perceive

floor

after the upper

perceive the ship lower


it

higher up.
is

requires solution

this
1

we down the river after we The problem then that How do we distinguish, as
story, exactly as
seq.

Page 142

126

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


experience

[part

ii.

in

we

certainly do distinguish, the first


?

series

from the second

And
them

Kant's answer
if

is

that

we

can only distinguish


first

we

regard the

order of the

series as arbitrary,
rule.
'

and that of the

second as subject to a

In the former example

my

perceptions in the apprehension of the house


at the roof
;

might begin
or vice versa

and end

at the foundation,
in

or

might apprehend the manifold

this empirical intuition

by going from

right to left

or from

left to right.

Accordingly, in the series of

these perceptions, there

was no determined order


In

which necessitated
in

my

beginning at a certain point

order empirically to connect the manifold.'


is

the second case the order

objective

it

in

no way

depends on the mode


sent
it
;

in

which we choose
if

to repre-

and

this

can only be

we suppose

that

it

occurs in conformity with a rule or law.

And
'

this

becomes

at

once apparent,

if

for

an instant we try

and imagine the contrary


this

to be the case.

Let us

suppose that nothing precedes an event upon which


event must follow in conformity with a
rule.

All sequence of perception would then exist only in

apprehension, that
tive,

is to say,

would

be merely subjec-

and

it

could not thereby be objectively deterto precede

mined what thing ought


to follow in perception.

and what ought

In such a case

we

should

have nothing but a play of representation, which would possess no application to any object. That is to say, it would not be possible through perception

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.

127

to

distinguish

one phenomenon from another, as


;

regards relation of time

because the succession

in

the act of apprehension would always be of the


sort,

same

and therefore there would be nothing


to

in the

phenomenon
And,

determine the succession, and to

render a certain
in this case,
I

sequence

objectively necessary.

cannot say that two states in a

phenomenon

follow one

upon the

other, but only Ihat

one apprehension follows upon another.

But

this

is

merely subjective, and does not determine an object,

and consequently cannot be held


of an object

to

be a cognition

not

even

in

the phenomenal world.

when we know in experience that something happens, we always suppose that someAccordingly,
thing precedes, whereupon
it

follows in conformity
I

with a

rule.
it

For otherwise
follows
;

could not say of the

object that

because the mere succession in


be not determined by

my

apprehension^ if

it

a rule in

relation to something preceding, does not authorise

succession in the object.


to a rule, according to

Only, therefore, in reference

which phenomena are deteris,

mined

in

their sequence, that


state,

as they happen,

by the preceding
under

can

make my
;

subjective
it is

synthesis of apprehension objective


this presupposition that
is

and

only

even the experience

of an event

possible.'

Starting then from the succession in apprehension,

or the

subjective succession

of phenomena,

Kant had

to distinguish

from it first, the objective

128

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


which constitutes a thing
;

[part

ii.

coexistence

in

space

house, a tree, and so forth


seqtcence

and

second, the objective

which constitutes a series of events.

As

pointed out in the section on the independent world,

he does

not, so far as

know, furnish any principle

of objective coexistence, but in the law of causation

he finds the principle of objective sequence.


put
it

Or, to

in

a transcendental form, he holds that the


is

experience of (objective) events

only possible

If

we presuppose
tainly

the law of causation, and as

we

cer-

have such an experience, &c.


as a proof of the law of universal
I

Now, regarded
causation, the

argument

have just stated


first place.

is

scarcely

worth
after

criticising.

In the

Professor Caird,
is

Schopenhauer, admits that the conclusion


If
is
it
'

inconsistent with one of the premises.


said to prove that sequence in the object

can be
accordfirst
;

ing to a

rule,'

It

is

only by showing in the


is

instance that sequence in the subject

arbitrary

so that the causation proved


versal.

is

at all events not uniit

But, in the second place,


Is

does not prove,

or attempt to prove, that there

actually an objec-

tive sequence according to a necessary rule, but only

that if there

is

an objective sequence,

it

must be

according to a necessary rule,


it

because otherwise

could not be distinguished from the subjective

sequence.

Now these are very different propositions

and the second or conditional one might be admitted


to its full extent, without admitting the truth of the

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.
is

129

first

or unconditional one, which

for

purposes of
required.

science the proposition for which proof

is

The second
of the
first,

proof which Kant gives of the prinis

ciple of causality

so hidden

away

in the recesses

that

some doubt might perhaps be thrown


to put
it

on whether he intended formally


a proof at
tion to
all.

forward as

The
first

fact that

it is

in direct contradic-

the

proof,

does not perhaps go


this point
;

far

towards helping us to a decision on


in any case the matter
I

but

is

not of

much

importance, as

am more

concerned with the meaning which the

post-Kantians extract from his writings, than with


that which he himself intended to put into them.

The
if
it

first

proof attempted to show that the expe-

rience of an objective sequence

was only possible


proof

was distinguished from a subjective sequence


to a rule.

by being according

The second

at-

tempts to show that no sequence can be experienced


except on the same terms.
It is plain, therefore, that

the second proof aims at demonstrating a causation

which

is

universal,

and which cannot,

therefore,

be

reconciled with the partial causation contemplated

by

the
it is

first.

It

only remains for us to examine whether


I

more

satisfactory.
^
:

give

it

entire in Professor

Caird's
'

words

The judgment
For time
1

of sequence

cannot be

made

without the presupposition of the judgment of causality.


is

a mere form of the relation of

Phil, of Kant^ pp. 454-5.

I30

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


and cannot be perceived by
itself.

[part

ii.

things,

Only when

we have connected
think of

events with each other can

we

them

as in time.

And

the connection must

be such, that the


in the

different elements of the manifold

of the events are determined in relation to each other,

same way as the

different

moments

in

time are
it

determined

in relation to each other.

But

is

evi-

dent that the


in relation to

moments
i.e.,

of time are so determined

each other that


that

we can

only put them

into

one order

we

can proceed from the but not vice

previous to the subsequent moment,


versa.

Now,

if

objects or events cannot be dated in


it

relation to time, but only in relation to each other,

follows that they cannot be represented as in time at


all,

unless they have an irreversible order

or, in

other

words, unless they are so related according to a


universal rule,
else

when one

thing

is

posited something

must necessarily be posited


implied

in consequence.
in time,

In

every representation of events as


supposition
is
;

this pre^

and the denial of causality


all

necessarily involves the denial of


time.'
It

succession in

appears to be asserted in this proof that

we

cannot conceive succession, unless


there
is

we suppose
fit
'

that

a necessary order in

phenomena
time.

to enable
into the

them, so to speak, to correspond with and


necessary order
in

the

moments of

Events

are determined in relation to each other in the


\i.e.,
I

same

suppose, some corresponding] way, as different

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.

131

moments
But
in

are determined in relation to each other.'


I

so far as

can attach any definite meaning

to these

words

at

all,

they seem to distinguish two

things which are really the same, and to confound

two things which are


events and the
*

really distinct.
'

The

'

order

'

of

moments if we assert that two events succeed each other, we are describing precisely the same relationship between them as when we assert that two moments succeed each other. When, on the other hand, we assert that one event is the cause of another, we assert not only this actual sucorder of
;

are not two kinds

of order, but one kind

and

cession, but also,

by

implication, a similar succession

whenever an event resembling the cause or first term But this in the relationship may happen to occur.
relationship
it

is

so far independent of time, that though


in

must occur
it

some time,

it

may

occur in any time,


relation be-

and

in

no way corresponds with the

tween actual successive events or successive moments which can never be repeated, because the related
terms can never recur.
followed by event

Event

and moment a are


b.

B and moment
if

This happens
;

once actually and,

you

please, necessarily

but

it

never happens again.


past as certainly as the

The
be

events vanish into the


in

moments

which they occur,


But
all this

and they can as

little

recalled.

has

nothing to do with causation.

What

the principle of
is,

causation, strictly speaking, asserts

not that

if

event

recurs

it

will

be followed by event B, for


K
2

132

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

event

cannot possibly recur

but that

If

an event
will

similar to

recurs,
:

an event similar to
this

cer-

tainly follow

and how

second hypothetical as-

sertion

is

involved in the categorical assertion of a

simple historical succession between actual concrete

events and moments, altogether passes


standing.

my

under-

The

transcendental view appears to be, that beis

cause there

a necessary order between successive

moments, therefore there must be a necessary order


between successive events
sity
;

and

this desired neces-

can only be found in the principle of causation.


if

But

there
still

was no

causality at

all,

the order of events


little
is

would

be just as much or just as

necessary

as the order of

moments.
it

An
does.
it

event

what
is

it

is

because
it is

it

happens when
it

moment

what

because

occurs

when

does.

Neither the one

nor the other could occur at any other time, simply

because by so doing

it

would cease
is

to

be

itself

It is
all

true of course (and this

no doubt the cause of

the confusion) that

we

habitually talk of the

same

event as occurring at different times, while

we make

no such assertion respecting particular moments.


But
this is

simply because the whole essence of a


the time at which
that this
it'

moment
whereas

consists in
it is

occurs,

commonly the case


all
it is

is

the least

interesting of

the relations which constitute an


therefore most often

event,

and the one of which

convenient to

make

abstraction.

Nor

is

it

to the

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.

133

purpose to say that events cannot be dated

in rela;

tion to time, but only in relation to other events

because

in

every sense in which this can be asserted


it

of particular events,
particular

can likewise be asserted of


therefore, this fact necesI

moments.

If,

sitates causation in the

one case (which, however,


it

deny),
is

it

must necessitate

also in the other

which

absurd.

Other objections besides these might no doubt be


taken against particular points
in the
it is

transcendental
to

proof, but the best refutation of


its

be found

in

own

version of
is

its

general nature and object.

That object
succession
is

simply to show that a clear idea of

impossible, except to those

who

first

regard phenomena
to the principle

as necessarily connected according


;

of causation

which, again,

is

as

much

as to say that

by

far the larger part of

mankind
I

have no clear idea of succession say the larger part of mankind,


bered that
those
in that

at
it

all.

And when

must be rememall

majority are included not only

who do

not believe in the universality of cauall

sation,

but also almost

those

who do

since

will

make bold to say that the greater number however much they turn their minds to the
principle of cause

of these,

nature of

succession in time, do not find involved therein the

and

effect.

This necessity, then,


if it
is

under which the transcendentalists labour,


to

be of

'

objective

'

application,
all,

and

is

to

have any

philosophic value at

requires us to believe that

134

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


is,

[part

ii.

mankind has been, and


ideas,

suffering under a very


its

singular illusion respecting the clearness of

own
be so

on a point which

is

commonly thought
This by

to

simple as to defy further analysis.


sufficiently

itself is

hard to believe

and the

difficulty

does

not diminish

more

closely.

oblige us to

when we come to examine the matter For what does the supposed necessity hold ? That when we perceive two
first
is

events in succession, the

the cause of the

second

Not

at

all.

But that when we perceive


somewhere a
cause possibly (indeed, pro-

two events

in succession, there exists

cause for the second


bably) of which

a
are,

we

and

shall

remain for ever,

ignorant

So

that

what the transcendental doctrine

comes

to

is this,

that

we can
is

have, and do have, an

idea of succession which

not causal, but that


'

we

cannot have such idea, at least in


ness,'

clear conscious-

which does not involve the idea of some other


is

succession which

indeed causal, but one element


be, quite
I

of which

is,

or

may

unknown

to us

On
Kuno

the whole, then,

cannot agree with Herr


'^

Fischer that Kant's 'giant strength


in this

has been

very happily employed


doctrine of causation
attack
;

attempt to place the


sceptical
all

beyond the reach of


it

on the contrary,

seems

to

me

that

the

difficulties
all

inherent in the transcendental method, and

the confusion and obscurity which are so often

to be

met with

in
^

Kant's use of that method, are


i

Fischer's Kant, p.

rS.

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.

135

strikingly exhibited in his treatment of this central

and important
that
it

principle.

It

is

commonly
is

asserted

was Hume's theory


which suggested
to

(that our expectation or

belief in the uniformity of

Nature

the result of

habit)

Kant

the necessity of

finding

some more
it

solid basis

on which to rest our


If so,
it

systematic knowledge of phenomena.

is

unfortunate that

should be precisely at this point

that the ingenious

and important method of

proof,

which

it

is

his chief glory to

have invented, most


had
all

obviously and completely breaks down.


I

have only

to point out, in conclusion, that

the transcendental demonstration been as sound in


its

parts as
it

Herr Kuno Fischer and Professor Caird


to be, the thing

suppose

proved

is

not sufficient

by

itself to

serve as a basis for scientific induction.

All that

Kant can be

said,

on the most favourable


is

view of

his reasoning, to

have established

that,

own words, 'the phenomena in the past determine all the phenomena in succeeding time
to use his
'
;

or,

as Professor Caird phrases

it,

'the subsequent

state of the

world

is

the effect of the previous state/

But something more than a fixed relation between


the totality of
totality of

phenomena at one instant and the phenomena at the next instant, is required
'

before

we

can, in the scientific sense of the expression,

assert that these are

laws of nature.'

A law of nature
totality of

refers to a fixed relation, not

between the

phenomena, but between extremely small portions of


136

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


;

[part

ii.

that totality

and

it

asserts a fixed connection, not

between individual concrete phenomena, but between Now by no known process classes of phenomena.
of logic can
that
'

we

extract from the general proposition,


is

the subsequent state of the world

the effect

of the previous state,' any evidence that such laws as

these exist at
proposition

all;

and what

is

more, this general


true,

might be perfectly
all

and yet the and purposes,

course of nature might be, to

intents

absolutely irregular, even to an intelligence which,

very unlike our own, was able to grasp phenomena


in their totality at
rity
in
'

any given moment.

For regula'

is

an expression absolutely inapplicable to


is

series,

which there
for

no kind of repetition

and we have

no reason
science

supposing

from the
at

point of view of

we have every
which
it

reason for no^ supposing

that the world will ever return exactly to the


state in
If,

was

same some previous moment.


for

therefore,

we have grounds

believing that

the states of the universe at two successive instants


are connected only as wholes, and not necessarily

by

means

of

independent causal links between their

separate parts, then of such a universe

we

could say,

perhaps, that

its

course through time was determined^

but
it

we

could not say that

be possible for

was regular, nor would a mind, however gifted, to infer, by


it

any known process of reasoning,


past.
If
I

its

future from

its

may judg'e from a phrase

of Professor Caird's,

CHAP.

VI.]

TRANSCENDENTALISM.
for

137

he holds a different opinion,

he appears to think

that the existence of causal links

between individual

phenomena

follows necessarily from the fact of a

causal connection
at different times.

between the
'

totality of

phenomena
'

To

find,'

he

says,^

the special

threads of causality which connect the sequent states


of objects
is

of course a matter of careful observation


Bi^^ in asserting sequence

and experiment.

we have

already by implication asserted that the threads are


there.'
I

do not know whether the implication here


is

spoken of
neither

transcendental.

Its

nature

is

developed
unas'

by Kant nor by
it

himself,
'

and

my own

sisted efforts to find

in the

clear consciousness

of

sequence have, as perhaps was natural, met with no


success.

But

if it is
I

not transcendental, certainly

it is

not empirical.

showed

before, that, admitting the

existence of these causal threads, experience alone

could never show their precise nature

still

less,

if

we do
prove

not admit their existence, can experience alone


it.

It is not,

however, necessary to waste the

reader's time in establishing this point.

The

trans-

cendentalist would be ready to admit

it

without de-

monstration, since,

if

he allowed that experience was


sufficiency in other cases

a sufficient ground of belief in this case, he would


find
it

hard to deny

its

while,

on the empiricist's view of the question


sufficiently

have

dwelt in the earlier chapters of this

essay.
1

p. 459.

138

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

CHAPTER

VIL

THREE ARGUMENTS FROM POPULAR PHILOSOPHY.


In this chapter
I

propose to examine the philosophic

value of three arguments


respectively, the
*

which

may be

called,

Argument from general

consent,'

the
y

Argument from success in practice,' and the Argument from common sense."' These arguments are not, perhaps, as a general
'

''

rule,

put forward as

final

and conclusive grounds of


to philo-

belief

by writers having much pretension


;

sophic insight

but they

fill

so important a place
are, as

among
fact,

the reasons

by which men

a matter of

convinced, they constitute such a large part of

actual popular philosophy, that they require

some

notice in this essay.


It
is

not necessary to remind the reader of a

truth which has been already stated, that in discuss-

ing them no attempt can legitimately be

made

to

demonstrate their insufficiency to furnish a basis of


philosophic certitude.

Neither this attribute, nor

its

converse can, from the nature of things, be demonstrated of


sible to

any argument whatever.


is

It

is

as impos-

prove that a belief

not to be accepted as

CHAP.

VII.]

POPULAR PHILOSOPHIC ARGUMENTS.

139

one of the ultimate data of knowledge, as to prove This is a point the that it is to be so accepted.
decision of which

must

in

all

cases

be

left

to

each man's individual judgment; and the duty of


the philosopher can go no further than to

make
it

the decision as easy as possible, and to see that


is

really given
first

on the main question


at
least,

at issue, and, in
If the

the

instance

on that alone.

verdict be given in the affirmative,

and the

belief in

question
it

is

pronounced true and also ultimate, then


in the

will

be necessary,

second place, to enquire


;

i.e., what conclusions how much ground it covers we may draw from it, and what proportion these conclusions bear to the total number of beliefs we

desire to establish.

In conformity with this plan,


first

let

us discuss in the

place that particular argument from authority


I

which

have called the 'Argument from general


It will

consent'
that

be admitted,

suppose, at once,

any one who regards the general consent of


as a final

mankind
that

ground of

belief

must

hold,

ist,

some

of his particular beliefs

either are, or

may be deduced

from, propositions assented to


;

by

the generality of mankind


sitions assented to
true.

and, 2nd, that propo-

by the generality of mankind are


of these positions.
it,

Now
I

with regard to the

first

would ask any one who holds

whether he

is

immediately convinced of the fact that mankind


A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,
[part

140

ii.

assent generally to any given proposition, or whether


.he arrives at that conviction
'ing
?
If,

by a process of reasonat all events,

as

is

more than probable, he adopts the


by so doing he admits,
which are not which

latter alternative,

that he believes S07ne propositions

proved by general consent


These,

all

those, namely,

are required to establish the fact that this general

consent
of the

exists.

it

is

to be presumed, are

same general character as those which are required to establish any other historical fact, and
consist in the first place of evidence, oral

and docu-

mentary, and in the second place, of those general


principles which, as the reader
is

already aware, are

required before any general induction can be based

on these or any other

particulars.
fact

Before, therefore,
(if fact it

any use can be made of the


*

be) that

by the generality of mankind are true,' we must both believe a large number of statements because they are assented to, not by
propositions assented to

the generality, but by a very small fraction of mankind,

and and

also accept a large

number of the very


it is
'

propositions
proof,
*

for

which we most desire to obtain


thought that the

in

favour of which

argument from general consent may legitimately

be invoked.

So much
'

for what, in
'

formal logic,

is

called the

minor premiss

of the argument under discussion.


to the
*

Let us now turn

major premiss,' which, as

has already been stated, would run in this

way

CHAP.

VII.]

POPULAR PHILOSOPHIC ARGUMENTS.


generally

141

What mankind have


true.
Is

assented

to,

is

this

an ultimate proposition

one

which we

accept as neither susceptible of proof, nor as requir-

ing proof

If

any reader

is in

doubt as to the true

reply which should be given to this enquiry, the

answer which he

feels

disposed to

make
him

to the

following question may, perhaps, help


sion.

to a deci-

Does he regard the argument from general consent as an example, and a specially perfect example, of the ordinary argument from testimony ?
If

he does, and

think he probably
is

will,

then the

proposition

we

are discussing
told,

not ultimate.

We

are

commonly

and when properly understood

the assertion
greater

is

perfectly correct, that

we

accept the
testi-

number of our beliefs on the faith of


But by
this
is

mony.

not meant, or ought not to

be meant, that the


tion
is,

real
it is

ground of accepting an
asserted.

asser-

is

the fact that

The

real

ground

or should be, the belief that our informant or in-

formants probably
willing to

know

the truth and are probably

communicate
all

it.

And

this belief itself

is

one which

would allow required evidence, and


on
reflec-

could not therefore be considered ultimate.

Now
tion,

imagine that most people


this
is

will,

admit that

true, not

only

when we

are

dealing with the opinion of this or that individual,


or

body of

individuals, but also

when we

are dealing

with

the united

testimony of mankind.

In other

142

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


i

[part

ii.

words, they will admit,


general consent
'

st,

that the

'

argument from

is

merely an instance of the ordi-

nary arguments from testimony, and, 2nd, that the ordinary arguments from testimony depend on something beyond the
fact

that certain opinions have


also to be assured, that
truthful

been

stated,

and require us
stating

the persons

them were

and well

informed.

This amounts, of course, to an admission that


the proposition
one.

we

are discussing

is

not an ultimate

Strictly speaking, therefore,

we might consider
it

the discussion at an end.


subject,
it

But before leaving the


enquiring whether
is

may be worth
i.e.,

nearly ultimate

whether, without tracing the


further back,

thread of inference
find

much

we can readily
to rest
it.

some

satisfactory

axiom on which

Have we then any


as a whole, or
(I will

reason to believe that mankind,

any section of them, are well informed

not dispute their truthfulness) respecting the


?

larger postulates of science

With regard
in their

to

man-

kind as a whole,

can only imagine two reasons


opinion

being given for putting confidence

on such a

subject.

The

first is,

that a belief gene-

rally held for

ages must in

all

probability be in har-

mony
must
*

with the experience of those


succeed,' that
is,
'

who
'
;

hold

it
is,

in practice

the other

that the universality of an opinion


it

is

a proof that

results from the


'

'

normal working of the human


is

mind

in other words,

established

by common

CHAP, vil]

popular philosophic ARGUMENTS.


meaning of
arguments,
that

143

sense, according to one

ambiguous
form

expression.

As

these

however,

part of the
will

main subject-matter of

this chapter,

and
I

be separately discussed

in their
It

proper place,

may for
fore,

the present ignore them.

remains, there-

only to consider whether a special reason exists


the opinion of

for reposing confidence in


ticular

some

par;

section

of

mankind on these
is

subjects

in

other words, whether there

any body of men who


all

hold a position towards philosophy at


ing to that

correspondto

which experts are supposed

hold

towards science, or Churches and


theology.

Popes towards

The

only persons,

suppose,

who have any


agreed
in their

claim to an authority of this kind in philosophy, are

philosophers
conclusions,

and

if

they had

all

and had forborne

to

make

public the

various lines of speculation by which they arrived


at them,
cisely
it

might have been


estimate the value

difficult,

perhaps, pre-

to

of their pretensions.
fulfilled

As, however, they have not


these conditions,

the second of

we

are compelled to judge each

man by
not

his arguments,

and are so altogether carried


;

out of the region of authority


fulfilled

and as they have


if

the first,

we

should,
to
all.

reduced to beleft
^

lieving only

what they agreed

recommend, be

without a philosophic creed at

As

is

remarked

with great force and point by Sir James Stephen,


^

Nineteenth Century^ April, 1877,

p. 290.

144

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

the bare names of Spinoza, Leibnitz, Kant, Hegel,

Descartes, Pascal, Bossuet, Voltaire, Cornte, Hobbes,

Locke, Berkeley,
to

Hume, Paley, Mill, are quite enough show how much the deepest thought, the most
the most pious feeling, the shrewdest

brilliant talents,

practical sagacity,

the most earnest and scrupulous


.

conscientiousness

have contributed to a
Sir

practical
is

agreement on
here talking,

this subject.'
I

James Stephen

ought to mention, of the founda;

tions of theology

but the remark, with one slight

omission,

is

at least as appropriate to the foundation


I

of science, with which alone

am

here concerned.

To sum
of
all

up.

The minor

premiss of the arguis

ment from general consent (and the same


without assuming many,
postulates,
to prove.
if

true

arguments from authority) cannot be proved


not
all,

of those scientific

which

it is

the business of that argument


premiss, on the other hand,

The major

of the argument cannot, any

more than the major premiss of any other argument from authority, be
regarded as an ultimate belief; and (the case of
experts being excluded)
if

we ask what proof can be


*

given of

it,

we

are reduced either to the


*

argument

from success

in practice,' or to the

argument from

common
I

sense.'

turn,

therefore, to the

first

of these

about
'

which a very few words


*

will suffice.

The Argument from

success in practice

is

no-

thing more than an appeal from the scepticism of theory

CHAP. VH.]

POPULAR PHILOSOPHIC ARGUMENTS.


which
*

145

to

the

faith
it

is

born of experience.

'

You

assert,'

says,

that no logical proof of ordinary


that

opinions can be given, and

neither

common
;

sense nor universal consent can supply a basis of


philosophical certitude.

Grant that

this is so

it

by

no means necessarily follows that men ought


subtlety of speculation, beliefs which

to give

up on a point of theory, or through some over-

work admir-

ably in practice.
doubts, after
all

However
nor

ingenious

may

be your

experience proves that they have no


;

substantial foundation

is it

any use

to say that

the uniformity of nature, or any other great principle, is

not proved to be true,


all

when every hour


it is

of

our lives shows that at

events

true

enough

for all practical purposes.'

That men ought not


grounds the
belief in
'

to give

up on speculative

the uniformity of nature, or


I

any other great


see
if his

principle,'

hold, as the reader will

patience lasts

till

the end of the volume,

with as

much

persistence as any man.

But

must
is

altogether take exception to


central point of the

the statement which

the

argument just stated, namely, that

the fact that these principles

work

in practice

is

any

ground
true.

for believing
is

them

to

be even approximately
illegiti-

This

in reality

an example of the

mate extension of a perfectly legitimate argument.


Given certain laws of nature
given that there
is

fixed plan according to which phenomena occur, and

which we

are

capable of discovering,

it

is

un-

146

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

doiibtedly true that the fact that a certain theory


*

works

in practice,'

i.e.y

agrees, so far as our experiis


;

ence goes, with the real order of things,


for putting confidence in
it

a ground

for the future

how much
Inductive

confidence

it

is

the

business

of

the

Logician to

tell us.

But the

earlier chapters of this


if

essay have been v/ritten in vain


quires to be told that experience

the

reader re-

is

altogether in-

capable of establishing the truth


truth

even the probable


It

of these
it

initial

assumptions.

cannot prove

the

wisdom of a

provisional belief in them, simply


all.

because

can prove nothing about them at

Its

oracles are not so

much ambiguous
;

in their import,

as altogether

dumb

and

certainly give

no reason-

able encouragement to the compromise (which, however,


I

myself

believe

in)

between

theoretical

scepticism and practical faith.


It is

obvious indeed that to found such a comis

promise on the teaching of experience


ing which,
if

a proceed-

the reasoning of the preceding chapters


logical

be sound, involves a
perience
attacks
;

contradiction.

Ex-

is

one of the chief


admit,
therefore,

idols

which scepticism

to

the accuracy of the

sceptical argument, but to

add that experience deit

monstrates that in practice


to say in the
isy

may be

neglected,

is

same breath
it

that the sceptical

reasonmg
proves

and that
it

is not,

sound.

If scepticism

anything,

proves that experience proves nothing.

Similar considerations

show

that no process of

'

CHAP.

VII.]

POPULAR PHILOSOPHIC ARGUMENTS.


can produce or add to philosophic

147

verification

certi-

tude.

Against the practical use and necessity of


I

verification

have not a word to

say.

It

must

always remain one of the most important instruments


for determining the laws of nature, granting that

by

any known method the determination of the laws of


nature
is

possible.
is

But

it

is

a mistake to suppose
distinction

that there

any philosophic

between

founding a belief on experience and founding a belief

on experience plus
I

verification.

Into this mistake,

cannot help thinking that Mr. G. H. Lewes has


'

fallen in his

Problems of Life and Mind.'


that

He seems

to

imagine
the
*

because knowledge of what he

calls

super-sensible,'

which

is

not derived from


'

experience, differs from knowledge of the

sensible

and

the

'

extra-sensible,'
in
is

which

is

derived

from

experience,
therefore
it

being incapable of verification, that


less

worthy

of belief
i,e.y

Whether
theology
substantial
I

a knowledge of

the super-sensible,
really rests

and metaphysics,
not argue here

on a

less

basis than science, as


;

Mr. Lewes contends,


all

will

but at

events the difference does

not depend on the fact that the theories of the one


CAN, and of the other cannot, be verified, since verification
is

not in reality a separate or distinct kind of

proof

It is

merely the name given to an observation

or experiment which, instead of suggesting a


theory, supports one already framed.
in
It

new

does not

any

essential

particular
L
2

differ

from other em-

148

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


grounds of
belief.

[part

ii.

pirical
it

Philosophically speaking,
fall

must stand with them or

with them, nor can


for a

it

afford

any independent evidence


it is

system of

which
I

itself an integral part.

now come
which

to the

'

Argument from common


it

sense,'

differs

from the two arguments that have


in

just

been discussed
least,

the fact that

constitutes,

nominally at

an essential part of an actual philo-

sophic system, and has been explicitly advanced as


furnishing a sufficiently solid basis for
belief,

not

merely by the vulgar, but by thinkers of influence

and

reputation.

Unfortunately, however, though

these thinkers have added, by the sanction of their


authority, to the dignity
'

and importance of the term


been accompanied by
in its definition.

common

sense,' this has not

any increased accuracy or clearness


been
in

In their use of the expression they have not always

agreement with themselves, with each other,


:

or with the unphilosophic majority


is

though, as

it

only with the opinions of the latter that


is

we

are

here concerned, this

not a subject which at this

moment need

detain us.
in

Now
common

when,

ordinary discussion, a belief


it

is

defended on the ground that


sense,

is

in

accordance with

what

is

frequently intended to be
I

conveyed by the argument


thing of this sort
:

imagine to be some-

'

The

belief in question

be exactly defensible on rational grounds,


that

may not we admit

we cannot

satisfactorily

support

it

by reasoning

CHAP.

VII.]

POPULAR PHILOSOPHIC ARGUMENTS.


all

149

nevertheless practically
and
all

men

micst assent to
is

it,

men

do assent to

it,

and there
I

nothing

more
plaint

to

be said about the matter.'


to

have no com-

whatever

make
is.

against any one


it

who

takes

up

this position,

provided
It
is

be understood exactly
not an argument in

what the position


favour of a belief
:

is

it

a confession that no such

argument can be found, and an assertion that we

must do without one.


either of

It

is

not a
;

philosophy,
it is

common
all

sense or anything else


philosophy.
is

rather
it

a negation of
that, directly

And
made

therefore

is is

any attempt

to raise

what

a mere dogmatic assertion to the dignity of a philosophical reason,


it

is

found necessary to buttress

it

up by various supplementary

principles, which, as

they are not always clearly distinguished from the


original

ground on which assent was demanded, are


This necessity of adding supI

apt to introduce the strangest confusion into every


part of the subject.

port to

common
it,

sense pure and simple, as

have

just described

shows

itself

in

various ways in

ordinary quasi- philosophical

discussion.

man why he
and he
is

believes the dictates of

Ask any common sense,


'

very likely to say that he does so because


else

everybody

does so (which

is

the

argument

from general consent '), or that he does so because

he and mankind
is
if,

in

general find them

the

'

argument from success

in practice.'
is

on some other occasion, he

answer which Though asked why he puts

I50

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


it

[part

ii.

confidence in these two latter arguments,

must be

admitted that he

is

very likely to say that he does

so because they are

recommended

to

him by

'

his

common

sense.'
is

But there

another argument sometimes used

to eke out the bare assertion that proof

must be

fore-

gone, which

is

so important that

it

may be doubted
title

whether

it

does not better deserve the


;

of the
it

argument from common sense


really
is

more

especially as

an argument (though not a very good one),

which the other


in this
:

way Human intelligence, like any other may machine, work rightly or wrongly. It may do
'

is

not.

It

may be

stated

somewhat

its

proper and normal work, or

it

may do something
In the former
;

altogether different and abnormal.

case
error.

we

shall obtain

from

it

truth

in the

latter,

In order, therefore, to get at the truth,

we

have only to observe what an intelligence working


normally turns out,
in

other words what

common
that.*

sense naturally believes, and to put our faith in

But then the question


ligence
*

arises
'

What
it

is

an

intel-

working normally
such a

It is

not enough to say that


in

is

an intelligence

working

way

as to perceive the truth, for,

when asked what was


reply that
it

the truth,

we

could merely

was that which an

intelligence

working

when asked what an intelligence working normally was, that it was an intelligence which perceived the truth a pair of

normally perceived to be true, and

CHAP.

VII.]

POPULAR PHILOSOPHIC ARGUMENTS.

151

statements which, taken by themselves, would not

bring us
sophy.

much nearer to the discovery of a philoNor is it of any use to say that a normal
is

intelligence

one which obeys natural laws


science
is

; not
intel-

only because,

if

to

be believed, every
that,

ligence, sane or insane, does

but because

we

should then be
ing that

in the singular position of maintain-

we know what
in
it

are natural laws by

means of
yet
is

an intelligence
because
it

whose judgment we had confidence


law.

was governed by natural


of what

Nor
is

possible to say that the question of


(indirectly)

what

normal
can be

and therefore

is
:

true,

decided by majorities however large

to

do so would
consent,'
is

be to revert to the

'

argument from general


of.

which has been already disposed


to

If

anything

be made of
it

this principle,

it

can only be by supple-

menting
design.

in

We

some form or other by the idea of must either presuppose a Creator who

constructs our Intelligences in such a

manner
is

that
true,

on the whole what they


or else

incline to believe

we must adopt

the

modern
is

substitute for

Creator, and suppose that there

some process by
to multiply

which right-thinking intelligences tend

and wrong-thinking ones


these suppositions,
there
is
it

to die out.

On

either of
fact
all
:

is

undoubtedly the

that

a considerable probability that what


is

men
but

practically agree in believing

worthy of

belief

then, not to speak of the difficulty already dwelt

on

of showing, without

2.

petitio principii,

what

It is

that

152

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


men agree
in believing,

[part

ii.

all

the question

still

remains,

what reason have we


suppositions
I

for thinking that either of these

is

true

Nobody

has as yet, so far as

know, maintained that the theory of natural selecis

tion

self-evident

and though the same cannot


of

absolutely

be

said

Theism, yet the


it

common
if

opinion seems to be that


possible,

is

desirable to have,

some kind

of proof for

the
in

existence of

a God.

In any case, as

mankind
to
it

general are not

more disposed
of

to believe the

fundamental principle
believe the fundais

Theology than they are

mental principles of Science,


further evidence to

absurd without
support of the

adduce the

first in

second.

Design, therefore, whether Theistic or atheistic,

whether depending
the
blind

on an

intelligent

Creator

or

operation

of natural

selection,
is
I

requires
?
I

proof.

And what

kind of proof

possible

have never heard of any, nor can

imagine any,

which does not depend on those very principles for which proof is required and in support of which the hypothesis of a normal intelligence con;

trived
fore,

by design was adduced. The circle, therein which the argument turns is evident. We

are required to believe in certain propositions be-

cause they are believed in by a normal intelligence

we are required to believe in the existence and testimony of a normal intelligence because intelligence is
the product of design or of something equivalent to

CHAP.

VII.]

-NATt?R27 PHILOSOPHIC ARGUMENTS. 155

design

and we are required

to believe in design

because of certain facts which can only be established


if

the propositions

we

originally set out to

prove are

true

judge,

Of the two meanings then, which, so far as I can may be attributed to the argument from common sense as it is ordinarily used, the first is not so much an answer to scepticism as an admission
'
'

that no answer

is

forthcoming

while the second

ceases to be effective as soon as the various propositions


relief,

which compose
it is

it

are

brought
it is

into

clear

plausible only so long as

confused.

154

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

CHAPTER

VIII.

THE AUTHORITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS AND OF


ORIGINAL BELIEFS.

The
I

reader may, perhaps, be surprised that hitherto

while discussing the argument from

common

sense,

have not had occasion to do more than allude to


is

the philosophic version of that argument, large as the space which


speculation.
diately
it

occupies in the

field

of English

This omission, which


has

will

be Imme-

remedied,
;

been

dictated

by several
the
the
in

reasons

among which is the circumstance that philosophy of common sense is, according to
statement of
reality not
its

most eminent modern exponent,

founded upon
:

upon consciousness

common sense at all, but common sense being merely a


mind which receives
needless to say,

name given
be such,
that this
'

to the attitude of

the verdicts of consciousness, or what are thought to


in unhesitating faith. ^
is

It is

an attitude of mind to which many


*

This refers to Sir William Hamilton's opinions as expressed in In the Lectures,' see Chap, xxxviii., he gives (after his fashion), a different account of the matter. But whatever version of his opinion be taken, it must, I believe, if clearly expressed, be substantially identical either with the theory criticised at
the
'

Dissertation on Reid.'

the beginning of this chapter

i.e.^

the theory of the' Dissertation,' or


attribute to

that dealt with at the end, which

Mr.

Mill.

CHAP.

VIII.]

AUTHORITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS,

&c.

155

philosophers lay claim whose philosophy has nothing


to

do with common sense

and the reader therefore

may
will

naturally expect that the ensuing controversy

mainly turn, not on whether


but on what
trust.
it

we ought

to trust
is

consciousness,

the

consciousness

which we ought to
though
perhaps

This statement, however,

fairly

enough

describes

the

character of Mr. Mill's polemic against Hamilton,

does not precisely indicate the point of view from

which the question


'

is

approached

in the sequel.
*

Demonstration,' says Sir William Hamilton,


last

if

proof be possible, behoves to repose at


sitions which, carrying their

on propo-

own evidence,

necessitate

their
is

own

admission.'^

Nothing can be
in the
is

truer.

This

the fundamental doctrine on which this essay rests,

and which has been repeated


to weariness.

course of

it

even

But surely

it

a strange assertion

with which to introduce a discussion on the grounds

we have
carry their
evidence,

for

believing those
evidence.'
'

propositions

'

which

own
if

If

they carry their

own

they

necessitate their

own

admission,'

what can be the use of introducing a dens ex

machind

in the

shape of consciousness

in

order to

recommend them ? There are, indeed,


which
their
lie

The
if

reason

is
is

not far to seek.


possible, beliefs

knowledge
and

at the root of all


* '

knowledge, which 'carry

own evidence
'

necessitate their

own

ad-

mission

but there are others which no doubt every


^

Dissertation on Reid,

p. 742.

156
4

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


_____

[part

ii.

_____
to
is

v^

one would wish


classes agree in
for neither of

have proved, but

for

which unfor-

tunately no proof

readily forthcoming.

These two
while

nothing but the

single fact, that


;

them can any reason be given

they differ

in

the

somewhat important
sense (as
it.

peculiarity that

whereas the self-evident^do not require proof, the beliefs

of

common

class)

cannot obtain

we might call the second The device, which, in this


was
by
sorts of belief

difficulty,

occurred to Sir William Hamilton,

partially to

amalgamate the two


of

inventing an authority which he called by the time-

honoured name
testify to

consciousness,

which

should

both of them,^ not indeed, as he admits, in

precisely the

same way, or

to precisely the

same

degree,

still

sufficiently in the

second case, as well as

in the first, to require

our assent.

To my
common
weight of
is

thinking, this idea of a faculty within the

mind, whether called conscience, consciousness, or


sense,
its

inducing the mind by the

mere

authority to accept certain propositions,


fictions
It is

one of the most singular


in

which has ever


a
fiction,

appeared, even
over, which
that, in all
is

metaphysics.

morefact,
it

particularly unfortunate

from the

cases

where

it

is

not superfluous,

is

misleading.

In the case of propositions which have


It

other evidence.

is

clearly superfluous

in

the case

of propositions having no other evidence but which


are certain
in

themselves,
'

it

is

also

superfluous

P. 744.

CHAP.

VIII.]

AUTHORITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS,

&c.

157

while in the case of propositions which have neither


external evidence nor internal certainty,
ing,
it is

mislead-

since

it

can, as

shall presently

show, only

simulate
original
I

the appearance

of

an independent and

ground of

belief.

may be

told,

indeed, that the

consciousness

which Sir William Hamilton and many other philosophers set up as the
final

arbiter of truth
is

is

no

separate faculty within the mind, but

co-extensive

with the mind

itself.

If this

were

so, their

theory
it

might be much more tenable psychologically, but

would be much
it

less tenable philosophically,

than

was

before.

They would be

guiltless of
;

founding
but they

their philosophy

on an imaginary faculty

would,
single
it

on the other hand, be deprived of any

and supreme authority on which


all.

to found

at

It

may be
a*s

readily admitted that, with-

out doing violence to established usage, consciousness

might be used

a general

name

for
;

mental pheno-

mena, or our apprehension of them


case
it

but
it

in

that

ought not to be regarded, any more than


from the several particulars
'

other general names, as denoting anything separate

and

distinct

describes.

Though, doubtless, the


every such phenomenon

'

in relation to
is

which

all

mental phenomena are apprehended


is

a unity, yet

distinct

from every other,


for

and consciousness,

if it

be used as a general term


is

describing these phenomena,

a unity only

in

the

sense of being one

name which belongs

to a great


A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,
things,

158

[part

ii.

many

and

in this

sense

it

is

evident that

it

cannot be regarded as a single authority.

This
be,

is

equally true

if

consciousness

is

taken to

as

it

might perhaps be maintained that Sir


in this

William Hamilton

connection intends

it

to be,

a general name for our acts of intuitive judgment. This use of the word certainly excludes the notion
of consciousness being set up as a kind of separate
faculty,

but then

it

also excludes the idea of con-

sciousness testifying to anything.


criterion for the truth of intuitive

Either there

is

no

judgments,
;

in

which
/

case consciousness cannot be that criterion


is

or there
/

criterion,

in

which case

it

must be something

more than a general name by which those judgments


are described.

In the

first case,^

much

of Sir William

Hamilton's language must be regarded as metaphorical,


it

and some of

it

as erroneous

in the

second case,
to

would seem that


I

he

stands

committed

doctrine (which,
to

believe,

he

really held), according

which consciousness

is

regarded as a kind of

judge whose veracity and whose competence are


equally above suspicion.

Now,

it is

evident that a theory of this


is

sort,

by

which consciousness
popular morality
do, just as

raised to a position in philoin

sophy similar to that which conscience occupies


this telling us

what we ought

to

that

tells

us what

we ought

to believe

cannot be proclaimed without immediately provok*

Cf. Lectures, p.

5.

CHAP.

VIII.]

AUTHORITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS,
:

&c.

159

ing three questions


exist
?

First,

Does such an authority

Second,

Why
it tell

ought

we
it

to
?

beHeve
I

it ?

Third,
first

What

does

us to believe

waive the

of these questions, though

raises points of

much might be said, and I pass on to the second. Why ought we to believe Sir William Hamilton is in no way embarrassed it ?
great interest about which
for

an answer, indeed,
five,

in the

Dissertation
is

'

he gives
list
:

no less than
1.

of which the following

>/Uj
,J^
i

Consciousness ought to be presumed to be

true

till it is

proved to be

false.

V\/
^

2.

Some
The

of the data of consciousness cannot

b,^
/\

doubted, because the doubt would annihilate


3.

itself.^

data of consciousness have the negative


i.e.,

proof of consistency,

so far as at present appears

they have never been proved inconsistent with each


other.^
4.

If

they are untrue, then

we must have been

deliberately deceived
5.

by a perfidious Creator.^

To

doubt consciousness involves a contra-

diction.^

With regard
a creed
is

to the first of these proofs,

it is

only

necessary to say that some more solid foundation for


required than that the rules of debate,

according to Sir William Hamilton's interpretation


of them, throw the burden of proof on the objector.

The second
'

proof

is

not strictly speaking a proof


'

Pp. 743, 745. ^ Pp. 743, 745-

P. 744.
'

'

P. 745-

P- 754.

i6o

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.is

[part

ii.

that the authority of consciousness


it is

to

be trusted

rather, in so far as

it

is

sound, an assertion that


is

in

some

cases that authority


its

not required

that
it

certain of

utterances are intrinsically certain.


first, is

The

third proof, like the

of too negative
at

a character to

make

it

worth while discussing


it

any length

at the best,

only removes a hypo-

thetical objection.

The fourth

proof has been,

imagine, sufficiently

dealt with in the remarks

made above in the

course of

the discussion on the ordinary view of the argument

from
will

common
fifth

sense.^
in Mill's
'

Some additional
Examination,'

observations

be found

p. 164.

The

argument has the peculiarity of not


unsound, but of being so on

only being

intrinsically

the evidence of Sir William Hamilton himself, given

a few pages previously.

On

p.

754 he asserts that

to doubt the truth of consciousness


to

when
'

it

testifies
its

what he elsewhere
is

calls

a fact
*

beyond

own

ideal existence,'
last

tantamount to
belief
is

believing that the

ground of

all

not to be believed, which


p.

is self -contradictory!

While, on
*

744, he assures
in this

us truly enough that


. .
.

doubt does not

case

refute

itself.

// is not suicidal by self-contra-

diction!

If self-contradiction is suicidal, the vitality

of Sir William Hamilton's


ticular

opinions

on

this

par-

point can hardly be such as to

make any

lengthened discussion of them necessary.^


*

See ante,

p. 151.

Vide

Mill's

Examination of Hmnilton,

p. 158.

CHAP.

VIII.]

AUTHORITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS,
proofs,
it

&c.

i6i

These

will

be recollected, are proofs

at the second

remove of judgments which, though


'

they were originally pronounced to


evidence
are
*

carry their

own

and

to

necessitate their

own

admission,'

many
first

of them, in reality, open to doubt.

We
called

are

called

upon

to believe these truths


:

on the

authority of consciousness

and we are now

upon

to believe

the authority of consciousness on

the strength of the five somewhat inadequate reasons.

But now the question

arises,

By what means

are

we

to discover the
?

judgments to which conscious-

ness certifies
question.

Instead, however, of answering this

Sir

William

Hamilton

answers

quite

another one, namely.

What

are the marks by which


?

we may

discover those judgments which are original


it

Whence,
and that

would appear, that he considers that

all

deliverances of consciousness are original judgments,


all

original

judgments are deliverances of

consciousness.

Before examining what grounds he

may have
much

for such

an opinion,
'

must say one word


round which

on the meaning of the word

original,'

confusion has arisen in connection with this

subject in the writings of


'

judgment,

The word original,' may be legitimately used


distinct,
It

more than one author. when applied to a belief or


in

two senses,
either

which are perfectly


always

though they are not


that
is

distinguished.
first

may mean

which stands

in

order of logic, that which

premiss, but not a conclusion, or that which stands

i62

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


in

[part

ii.

first

order of time, that which (to put


in the chain of

it

more
not a

strictly),

phenomena governed by
a
cause, but
all
is

psychological laws,
product.
rest

may be

When

it is

said that

proof must finally

on

original propositions
is

which are not themselves

proved, the term


it

used

in its first
is

meaning

when
intelli-

is

said that 'necessity

a criterion which will

enable us to distinguish an original datum of

gence from a result of generalisation and custom,'^


it is

used in

its

second meaning.
it

Mr.
in the

Mill, as will

appear

directly, habitually uses

second sense,

and seemed
In
I

to think that

Hamilton did the same.

this, I think,

he was mistaken.

Hamilton used

it,

believe, in both senses (though without distinguish-

ing between them), and, on the whole,

more
to

fre-

quently in the

first

sense than in the second.

On what
original

grounds

then

(to

return

our

argument) does Sir William Hamilton identify our

judgments (according to either


'original')

definition of

the

word
?

with the deliverances of consciousI

ness

He gives

no reason himself; and as

know

nothing but what can be gathered from his writings


respecting the nature of that internal authority, not

even the
any.

fact of its existence, this omission,


it

am

unable to supply

But

is

evident, destroys the

value of the whole argument from

common

sense.

Grant that consciousness

is

shown

to be trustworthy

by the

five
^

arguments, and that original judgments


Cf.

Hamilton's Lectures, pp. 268, 270.


''

CHAP.

VIII.J

AUTHORITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS,

&c.

163

may be
by
unless

recognised by the four marks^ enumerated

Sir William Hamilton,

how

are

we advanced,
judgments are

we know
Perhaps
I

that

the

original

identical with those

which are
shall

certified

by consciousemployed

ness

be told that their identity

follows from the definition of the terms

that original judgments

and deliverances of con-

same thing, because the two expressions mean the same thing or to put it techsciousness must be the
;

nically, that their ^<?-notation

cannot be different since


If this really

their con-x\.oX2X\ovi
it

is

identical.

be

so,

is

plain that Sir William


'

Hamilton used one or


'

other of the terms


in

consciousness

and

original
I

an altogether

different sense
If

from that which

have supposed.
'

we

are to identify in meaning


'

deliverance of consciousness

with what

is

properly

an original judgment, then consciousness cannot be

an authoritative faculty
are to identify
'

if,

on the other hand, we


'

original

judgment
then
'

with judgment

delivered

by

authority,

original

judgment

must
logic,

signify

something different from either ^^^5^/ in

ox first in causation.

On

the

first
is

of these

suppositions,
its

consciousness

dethroned from

by which dignity, and


for certain

serves merely to furnish a general

name

of our convictions (those namely which are original),


I

wish to

know what

is

meant by such an assertion


of,

as this

that

consciousness assures us
^

or gives

Dissertation, P 754

i64

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

testimony
thing

own existence, and beyond its own existence?^


to, its
it

also to
If this

someis

not

language gratuitously metaphorical,


that consciousness
is

clearly implies

an authority which can give


;

us two kinds of information

information,

namely,

about

itself,

which Hamilton says we cannot doubt,


else,

and information about something


us

which he

tells

we can

doubt.

What, again,

is

meant by

telling

us that 'the credibility of consciousness

must be

determined by the same maxims as the credibility of

any other witness'^ if consciousness be a mere And, finally, what plausibility unity ? fictitious
remains
in the

reasons by which Hamilton tries to


is

persuade us that consciousness

veracious

If

consciousness be an authority implanted in us for

our guidance, there

may be some

reason (on the

Theistic hypothesis of the universe) for supposing


that
it
it is

inconsistent with the Divine veracity that

should be otherwise than trustworthy.


for

But what

shadow of reason can there be

making the Deity

specially responsible for certain beliefs solely because

they do not happen to be produced by

known
?

psychological laws, or because no other reason for

accepting them happens to be forthcoming

And

why are

such laws to be presumed true


false, like

till

they are

proved to be
able witness

the utterances of a respect-

who

has never been detected in an


if

untruth
*

These reasons are bad

the
P. 749.

common

Cf. Dissertation, p. 745.

CHAP,

viii.]

AUTHORITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS,
is

&c.

165

sense philosophy

founded upon the existence of


;

a single subjective authority


founded, they cease,
I

but

if

it

is

not so

think,

even to be specious.

The
ton's

difficulties

on the opposite view of Hamilless serious.

meaning are perhaps not


to

He

never scruples

talk

of

fundamental
bases
of

beliefs,^

primary

beliefs,^

original

knowledge,^

original (as
&c.,

opposed

to derivation) convictions,"^ &c.,

when an argument founded


*

solely

upon the

authority of consciousness would


talk of
is

require

him

to
it

the deliveran.ee of consciousness.'

And
all

hardly conceivable that he should so far ignore


these

the proper use of language as to employ

terms, every one of which naturally implies originality in

one of

its

two legitimate meanings, as merely

signifying that which emanates from consciousness

regarded as a subjective authority.


I

believe,

then,

that

in

his exposition
is

of the
;

common
I

sense philosophy there

an ambiguity but
is

further hold that this ambiguity

essential to the
I

plausibility of that celebrated

system, otherwise

should not have so long detained the reader over


the matter.
ton
one.

Tl^e problem that Sir William Hamilto

desired

solve

was a

perfectly

legitimate

He

found certain

beliefs,

those

respecting

the existence of our actual conscious state, which no


sceptic

had questioned.
*

He

found others whose


' '

P. 743P. 743.

P. 742.
P. 754.

'

i66

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOtfBT.


it

[part

ii.

truth

was scarcely
which

less desirable to raise

beyond
at
?

suspicion,

scepticism

had

made,
to

least
It

theoretically doubtful.

What was
as
it

be done

seemed as impossible to find anything like a reason


for these

convictions

was

to give

them up

because no reason was forthcoming.

The Kantian

device for getting over the difficulty never seems to

have been understood by him


the beliefs were innate was

merely to say that


but the scheme

out of fashion since


left

Locke
which

nothing therefore was

have just been considering.

Ask a common
all

sense philosopher of the Hamlltonian school what

he believes, and he

tells

you that he believes

the original convictions of

mankind
tells

ask him
that
It

why
beIt

he believes them, and he

you

Is

cause they are deliverances of consciousness.


is

because

some of the
not, considered

original

convictions

of

mankind are
sciousness

by themselves, beyond
authority of con;

the reach of scepticism, that the


is

invoked

in their behalf

it is

because

no mere
faculty

reflection

on the nature of that imaginary


are
Its

can
it

make known what


is

deliver-

ances, that

necessary to take for granted that

they are Identical with the original convictions of

mankind.

Some

of the confusion and ambiguity

incident to Hamilton's exposition of the theory are

therefore really necessary to

its plausibility.

If

you

improve his statement, you destroy


always supposing that his system
is

his
I

system

as

have repre-

CHAP.

VIII.]

AUTHORITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS,

&c.

167

sented

it.

On

this point,

however,

admit
it,

may-

have been mistaken.


is

Mr.
be,

Mill's version of

which
;

very
to

different,
this,

may

after

all,

the correct one


say,

and

which,

strange to

he not only

attributed to

Reid, to Hamilton, and to the philo-

sophic world at large, but also fully accepted himself,


I

now

address myself.

To many the
graph
will

last

sentence of the preceding para-

seem a paradox.

That Mr.

Mill,

who

has criticised the Hamiltonian theories at length,

and who
Sense

in the chapter

devoted to the
declared
that

Common
he

Philosophy,'
differed

has

and
he

Hamilton

on the most important question


that

about which

philosophers were divided,

should really hold the philosophic opinions which

he attributes to
prise.
It
is,

his opponent,

may

easily excite sur-

nevertheless, true.

He

agreed with
to

what he considered the philosophy of Hamilton


be
;

and where he

differed

from him was not on a

point of philosophy, but on a question

whose

interest,

which

admit to be great,

is

almost purely psycho-

logical.

His theory was

this.

The

premises^ of

all

knowledge consist of immediate and

intuitive beliefs.

Some
those

of these immediate and intuitive beliefs are

we have
1

concerning our

own

actual subjective

Examination of Hamilton,

p. 151.

i68

A. DE:fe:NCE:
^

OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

II.

states

but there are, or


credit,^

may

be, others not less


*

worthy of

which are described as


in
^

facts

which have been


ning,'
*

consciousness from the begin*

the original elements of mind,'

our original
exist,

beliefs.'^

That these judgments,


to think

if

they

are

to

be trusted he did not doubt himself, and he


that

seemed
to him,

no other philosopher could

have doubted.

The

real difficulty arises, according

when

the question comes to be discussed as


original beliefs are
:

to

what these

and

it

was on

this

point that

he thought the philosophic world was

divided into two great parties, according as they

pursued one or other of two methods, which he

names respectively the psychological and the


spective.

intro-

The former of these consists in rejecting from among the list of apparently original beliefs all
those to which the operation
of the law

of the

association of ideas or (I presume)


logical law,

any other psychowould give an appearance of immediatethe


latter,

ness

or

necessity:

in

accepting these

attributes as conclusive proof that the convictions to

which they belonged were part of the original furniture of the mind.
If the

philosophic

world really were divided

mainly on

this point, the small progress that philo-

sophy has made would cease


in reality, the
*

to

be surprising.

For,

question
'^

is

one

chiefly of psychological

P.

1.

51.

P. 172.
P. 178.

P. 157.

P. 173.

CHAP.

VIII.]

AUTHORITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS,
little

&c.

i6g

interest,

and has

direct bearing

on philosophy

properly understood.
fact, I

As a

matter of mere historic

should be unwilling to admit that the marks


original

by which

judgments are to be discerned


battle-

have been universally considered the chief

ground of philosophy, though

this

is

not the occasion


I

on which to discuss the question.

am

rather con-

cerned with discovering whether Mr. Mill's view of


the foundation of knowledge, taken even in connection with the psychological
solid philosophical results.

method, can furnish any

But before doing


effectively,
it is

so,

or rather in order to do so

necessary to determine in what sense

he uses the word consciousness.


the ultimate beliefs which

As we have

seen,

may

or rather must be

accepted with confidence are, according to him, of

two kinds

the beliefs

we have

respecting our

own

actual mental states,

and the

beliefs, if any,

which

are part of the original furniture of the mind.


frequently asserts that
belief

He

we

hold both these kinds of

on the authority of consciousness.

Are we
I

then to attribute to him the theory which


attributed to Sir William

have
I

Hamilton

the

theory,

mean, that consciousness

is

an internal witness which

must be distinguished
statements to which
it

like other witnesses


certifies ?
I

from the

think not.

He

used the language

in this

respect of the

common

sense philosophy, language sanctioned by general


philosophic tradition
;

but as the

fiction

suggested

I70

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


it

[part

ii.

by
will

is

not in any

way

necessary to his system,

it

be more convenient to assume that he did not


it.

believe In

The
as
I

reason

why an

authoritative con-

sciousness

is

a necessary part of the

common

sense

philosophy

is,

have explained above, because

the aim of that philosophy was to obtain proof for


certain

judgments about which scepticism


all

is

possible.
if

Mr. Mill was of opinion that


such
exist,

original beliefs,

stand on the same level of certainty as


:

our beliefs respecting our actual states of mind

and

about these he was of opinion that scepticism was


impossible.
that

Now

it

is

evidently superfluous to say


conscious-

we

believe that

ness

tells

us that

we feel cold because we feel cold. Even If


it

these two
of,

statements asserted different things instead

as

they really do, the same thing,

is

obvious that

what

in point of

form appears here as the premiss

can add nothing to the certainty of what in point of

form appears here as the conclusion


anything which
feelings
it is

and thus
In

to

adduce the testimony of consciousness


is

favour of

as

certain

as

our Immediate

must always be superfluous.


Mr.

Moreover,

not, according to
is

Mill, consciousness

whose

authority

thus indisputable, whatever occasional


to the contrary, but only con^
*

phrases

may imply
'

sciousness

in its pristine purity,'


:

before

Its

original
its

revelations have been overlaid

'

consciousness in

developed, and therefore corrupted condition, being

P. 171.

CHAP.

VIII.]

AUTHORITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS,

&c.

171

capable apparently of any amount of deception.


that
if

So
the

we

are to credit

him with the

'

independent
all

authority' theory of consciousness, besides

other difficulties in the

way

of that theory which

have been, or might


to

be, enumerated,

he would have

overcome the presumption which Sir William


-^

Hamilton says

must

lie

against any witness deIf,

tected in error \falsus in uno.falsus in 07nnibics.


in addition to all these objections,
it is

recollected that

the theistic or teleological assumption, which really


lies at

the root of the

common

sense philosophy, was


it

wholly foreign to Mr. Mill's modes of thought,


will

be admitted,

think, that

am

not illegitimately
if I

improving the substance of his teaching

venture

always to describe as 'original beliefs' or 'judgments,'

what he occasionally
*

calls
'

the
or
*

'

revelations

of consciousness,' or the

genuine

original de-

liverances of consciousness.'

The
let
'

nature of his theory being thus determined,


its

us next turn to the question of

value.
first

Could we try the experiment of the

confirst

sciousness in any infant,' says Mr. Mill,^ 'its


reception of the impression

we

call external,

what-

ever was present in that

first

consciousness would be
(^.e.y

the genuine testimony of consciousness"


as
I

would,
'

should say, be an original judgment),


entitled to credit,

and

would be as much would be as


^

indeed there
it,

little

possibility of discrediting
2

as our
.

Dissertation on Reid, p. 746.

p^ j^^^

172

A DEFENCE OF PHlLOSOPMtC DOUBT:

[partis

sensations themselves.

But we have no means of


direct

now

ascertaining

by

evidence whether

we

were conscious of outward

and

external

objects

when we

first

opened our eyes

to the light.
is

That
in

a belief or knowledge of such objects


consciousness
muscles,
is

our

now whenever we
for

use our eyes or


it

no reason

concluding that

was
any

there from

the beginning, until


it

we have

settled the
If

question whether

was brought

in since.

mode can be

pointed out in which within the comit

pass of possibility
the hypothesis

might have been brought

in,

must be examined and disproved


consciousness.

before
tion
is

we

are entitled to conclude that the convicof

an original deliverance

The proof that any


or Principles of

of the alleged Universal Beliefs,

Common

Sense, are affirmations of


:

consciousness, supposes two things


exist,

that the beliefs

and that there are no means by which they


this

could have been acquired.'

From

very remarkable extract, which con-

tains explicitly or implicitly the

whole psychological

theory of ultimate beliefs


explain,
it

have just endeavoured to

is

clear, as

before stated, that a belief

may

be either of the highest conceivable certainty,


all,

or of no certainty at

according as

it

has or has
:

not been in consciousness from the beginning

i.e,,

according to whether pyschological laws have not


or have been concerned in
its

production.
this

The

grounds,

however,

on

which

very singular

CHAP.

VIII.]

AUTHORITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS,
is

&c.

173

doctrine

based are not so

plain.

Why

are our

earliest beliefs elevated to this exceptional dignity?

Why are we

to regard infants as (at least potentially)


in

occupying the place


Councils and
faith
?

matters of reason which


in

Popes have claimed


if

matters of
this

And

infants are to
into

be credited with

unerring

insight

the

mysteries which have


to
if

puzzled philosophers, are


to the lower animals
?

we

deny the same


are,

gift
?

And

we
;

why

are

we

These are some of the means the only


and so
duced.
cal

first

questions which the

pyschological theory suggests


ones.
Beliefs

but they are by no

which have been the


association of ideas,

product of pyschological laws


forth

are,

it

appears, on a

much lower

level

of certainty than those which have not been so pro-

But why has the action of those pyschologi-

laws so

much more

pernicious an effect upon their


?

products than the operation of any other laws

Mr.

Mill and the thinkers of his school would be the last

persons to deny that the most original of

all beliefs,

those which have been in consciousness since conciousness was, are


are
still

produced by some laws.


fortunate
in

Why
their

these laws

so

much more

operation than those which, by a conventional classification,

are regarded as specially mental, that

we

may

regard their results as

having attained
I

'

the cer-

tainty which

we

call perfect.'^

neither Mr. Mill nor the great

tell, and body of philosophers

cannot

P. 152.

174

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

which according to him shares his opinion on point, appear willing or able to do so.

this

Now
ation of

let

us turn for a

moment from

the consider-

how we know
in the
first

that beliefs which are original

are specially certain, to the question of


to

how we come

know

instance that they are original.

In their

mode

of dealing with this problem lay, in

Mr.

Mill's opinion, the special glory of the school to


It consisted,

which he belonged.
ing to pyschology
'

he thought,

in adapt-

the

known and approved methods


more particularly
in

of physical science,'^ and

bringing
*

to light the original elements of consciousness

as

residual

phenomena, by a previous study of the


Against
pyschological method/
I

modes

of generation of the mental facts which are


^

not original.'

this

when confined
say.
I

to pyschology,

have not a word


it

to
all

am

perfectly ready to admit that

has

the merits which

may
is,

appertain to the
'
;

'

known and
but what
I

approved methods of physical science


wish to point out
pyschology,
the
first
it

that though

it

may

give us a
In of

can never give us a philosophy.

place, the

known and approved methods


it is

physical science unfortunately take for granted


of the judgments which

most
is

the pressing business of


it

philosophy to establish, and which therefore,


evident, cannot be proved

by

that

method without
if

arguing

in

circle.

In the second place, even

these scientific assumptions were established by


'

some

P. 173.

""

Ibid.

CHAP.

VIII.]

AUTHORITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS,
still

&c.

175

Other means,

no

belief

shown by
us,

this

method

to

be original can be ultimate for


the fact
is
is

simply because

one that has to be shown.

Grant that

it

original,

and then, may


but as

be,

'

there would be as
as our sensations

little

possibility of discrediting
'
;

It

themselves

we can never know


much

that

It

was
fact

original without a previous argument, the fact,


It

If

be,

does not help us

nearer to the founda-

tions of a creed.

To
But

Mr.

Mill's hypothetical

baby

no doubt

its

first

impressions
to us

ground of belief
of the

may supply a solid who have to arrive at a


science,' this

knowledge of what these are by the laborious use


'

approved methods of physical


Is,

circumstance
value,

philosophically speaking, of small


little

and can afford us but

consolation.

There seem,
original beliefs.
for

therefore, to be three fatal objec-

tions to a philosophy founded

upon the authority


is

of,

In the

first

place, there

no ground

supposing that original beliefs are particularly


serve as the foundation of a creed
is
;

fitted to

in the

second place, .there

no ground for supposing that

acquired beliefs are particularly unsulted for such a

purpose

and, in the third place,

it

Is

Impossible to

determine what beliefs are original and what are


acquired without assuming the truth of
positions

many

pro-

whose only evidence can on

this

theory be

that they are original.


I

shall,

perhaps, be told that though Mr. Mill

attaches

In

theory this absolute certitude to our

176

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


beliefs,

[part

ii.

original

yet that

in

practice

he supposed

himself to require as a foundation for his inferred


beliefs

no immediate knowledge but that which the


its
is

mind has of
deny that
it

own

states.

admit the
It

fact,

but

any defence.

relieves him,

no

doubt, from the charge of practically committing the


logical error pointed out in

my

third objection, but

at the cost of falling into


still.

one of greater magnitude

He

cannot be accused of founding his creed

on judgments proved by the psychological method


to

be

original,

and therefore
method,
in

true,

simply because
opinion,

the psychological

his

showed

that no judgments are original.

His philosophy of

ultimate beliefs, therefore,


if

was not only unsound, but


useless.

sound

it

would have been

My

complaint

against him, however, does not end there.

That

the philosophy which

he speculatively maintained

should be incapable of solving the problems which

most press

for solution is bad,

but

it

is

worse that

the philosophy to which he adhered in practice should

ignore the very existence of these problems.

And

here

think Sir William Hamilton

is

greatly his

superior.

The Common Sense

Philosophy, whatever
all

be

its

shortcomings, and they are many, was at

events constructed with a view to our actual necessities.

It

recognised,
fact

in

a more or less confused

manner, the
truth

that

most of the judgments whose


sort of proof for

we

habitually
;

assume are not beyond the reach

of scepticism

that

some

them

is

CHAP.

VIII.]

AUTHORITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS,

&c.

177

therefore required, and that none of the usual proofs

from experience are sound.


consciousness whose veracity

The
is

hypothesis of a

in

some way

in-

volved

in that of the Deity, in their favour, is

and which

shall give its

testimony

not one perhaps very

well calculated to stand hostile criticism, but at


rate, if true,
it

any

would go some way towards solving

the difficulty.

To

the psychological school, on the

other hand,
there

it

hardly seems to have occurred that

was a

difficulty to

be solved.

Their psycho^

logy so overshadows their philosophy that

they have once discovered to their


a thing

when satisfaction how

came

to be believed, they

seem comparatively
If only

indifferent as to the
far,

more important questions of how


to

and why,

it
'

ought

be believed.

they

can apply the

approved methods of physical science'

to the discovery of the genesis of mental

phenomena,
difficulties

they take a very optimistic view of the

which attach

to the proof of the principles


*

on which
*

the legitimate application of the

approved methods

must
cussed

finally

depend.

One example

of their easy

acceptance of insufficient proof

when

I have already diswas dealing with the law of Universal

Causation.
difficulties

A still

more remarkable case of ignoring


in the criticism

remains to be treated of

which follows on the psychological theory of the


external world.

178

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

CHAPTER
Berkeleian Idealism
haps, most quickly

IX.
~

PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM.
is

of

all

speculative theories

concerning the external world the one which, per-

and

philosophic enquirer.

commends itself to the The greater number of persons


easily

who dabble
so

in

such subjects have been idealists at


lives if they

one period of their


;

have not remained


call

and many more, who would not

themselves

idealists,

are nevertheless of opinion that though the


is

existence of matter
is

a thing to be believed
it is

in, it

not a thing which

possible to prove.

The

causes of this popularity are, no doubt, in part, the

extreme simplicity of the reasoning on which the


theory
rests, in

part

its

extreme

plausibility, in part,
is

perhaps, the nature of the result which

commonly

thought to be speculatively interesting without being


practically inconvenient.

For

it

has to be observed,

that the true idealist that his system,


contradicts

is

not necessarily of opinion

properly understood, in any


sense.
;

way

common

It destroys,

no doubt, a
is

belief in substance

but then substance

a meta:

physical

phantom conjured up by a vain philosophy

CHAP.
(-

IX.]

PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM.
life it

179

the Matter of ordinary

supposes
I

itself to

leave

untouched.

That the things

see with

my

eyes
I

and touch with

my

hands do

exist, really exist,

make

not the least question.

The

only thing whose

existence

we deny

is

that which philosophers call

Matter, or corporeal substance.


this there is

And
it.' ^
'

in

doing of

no damage done
says

to the rest of
I

mankind,
with

who,

daresay, will never miss

affirm,

confidence,'
(i.e.,

Mr.

Mill,

'that

this

conception

the idealistic one) of matter includes the whole


to
it

by the common world, apart from philosophical and sometimes from theological,
meaning attached
theories.''^

But though

idealist philosophers

have said
Plain

this,

the world has never believed them.

men have
question

continued to think that something more

is in

than a metaphysical invention, about which they


neither

know nor

care anything

and that

in losing

substance they would lose something essential to


their idea of the

scheme

of the universe.
I

This

is

an opinion which

also share

and

it

is

to Idealism considered
this point of

from

this point of view,


I

and

view alone, that

wish to direct the

reader's attention in this chapter.


fore, at least,

There

are, there-

two important controversies connected


I

with this theory which

shall not discuss,

shall

not discuss either the real nature of the object of


^

Berkeley, Principles of Human Knowledge^ Part


2

i.

35.

Examination of Hamilton^

p. 227,

i8o

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


is

[part

ii.

perception, which

what

especially occupied Berke-

ley, nor the psychological account of the origin of

our

belief

in

matter,
I

which

is

what

especially

interested Mr. Mill.

am

prepared, for the sake of

argument, to assume, with the former, that

we know
and senneither a

and can know


sations,^

directly only our

own

ideas

and with the

latter that

any

belief in the
is

existence of an external reality which sensation nor a possibility of sensation,


of the laws of the association of ideas.
is

the product
is

There

also

a third subject which


dealing with

shall

absolve myself from

mean

the constructive side of Beris

keley's philosophy.

As

well known, he replaced

the material world by the Divine


in this the

Mind
this
it,

and found

permanent substance which ordinary men


But though
theory
yet
it

sought

for in matter.

is

as

good as many which have succeeded


not
fulfil

does

the conditions which limit the discussions


:

in this essay

it

has had no appreciable influence on


speculation.
I

the current of

modern English
on one
side,

shall,

therefore, put this

and

shall confine

my

criticisms to the Idealistic

Theory, on what

may be

called

its

negative or destructive side.


thesis
it is
I

The
one, and
if

wish to maintain
:

is

a very simple

this

Received science cannot be true


:

the idealistic account of the universe be accurate


is

nor

the
;

discrepancy between
is

the

two merely
and can be

verbal

it

fundamental and

essential,
'

Berkeley usually describes them both as

ideas.'

CHAP.

IX.]

PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM.
artifices of

i8i

bridged over by no mere

terminology.
I I

That there
no proof.

is

a verbal discrepancy requires,

imagine,

Natural science (of which alone


the

am here
of

speaking) assumes

Independent

existence

matter
this

In all its utterances.


Is

theory which denies

independent existence

undoubtedly therefore
;

In />rimd /acze contrdidiction

with Natural science and


Is,

the question

we have

to determine

whether under
or
Is

this superficial contradiction there

is

not a real

and substantial harmony.


confounding with
liable to

Now we

must beware of
it is

this question

another with which

be mixed up

namely, whether

Idealism

is

or
If

is

not consistent with our ordinary experience.

we admit the legitimacy of the Ideal psychology if we admit that objects as perceived may be resolved
into ideas or sensations, there
last
is

no doubt that

this

question must be answered In the affirmative.


is,

That

we may suppose

Idealism to be true without

being obliged to suppose that


hear, or feel

we should

either see,

under any circumstances what we should


if

not see, hear, or feel

independent matter existed.

Supposing, therefore, that Science consisted in


nothing more than a series of propositions asserting
what, under given conditions, our experience would
be, there
it

might be no fundamental discord between


If,

and Idealism.
'

for

example, as Berkeley de-

clares,^

the question whether the earth


In reality to
^

moves or
to wit,

no,

amounts

no more than

this

Principles of Human Knowledge^

58.

i82

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


to

[part

ii.

"

whether we have reason

conclude from what has


if

been observed by astronomers, that


in

we were

placed

such and such a position and distance both from

the earth and sun

we

should perceive the former to

move/'

'

&c.,

no doubt astronomy and the theory But

under discussion might easily be harmonised.


in truth Science

much more than this. It tells us not only what we should perceive if we were rightly circumstanced to perceive it, but also how it comes about that we should perceive that particular
does
thing and no other, and what
it is

that

would hapus that

pen or has happened whether we or anybody else


were there
which was
to perceive
it

or not.

It tells

perceiving organisms were


itself

evolved from a world

neither perceiving nor perceived,

and

that processes take place within that world which,


like the

elements of which

it

is

composed, are too


in

subtle to be
cases, to

apprehended by sense, or even,


in imagination.

some
it

be represented

In short,

asserts the existence of a vast machinery,

composed
figured,

of that

inert, senseless,

extended,

solid,

moveable substance existing without the mind,' which


Berkeley declares
^

to be a contradiction in terms,
infinite

and which causes, among an


effects,

number

of other

our perception of

itself.

If this

be not

in direct irreconcilable contradiction

with a theory which

asserts

the

existence of no

causes besides spirits and no effects besides ideas,


*

Principles of Human

K7tow ledge,

67.

CHAP.

IX.]

PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM.

183

then such a thing as contradiction does not exist in


the world.
is still

But

if

(which

hardly think) any reader

unconvinced on

this point, let

him

try to state

the doctrine of Evolution in ideal language

withThe
mind
*

out of course postulating the Deity,

whom

Berkeley

would have introduced


attempt
will,
I

to save the situation.

think, leave
is

no doubt on

his

that Mr. Spencer

right

when he
'

declares that

if

Idealism be true. Evolution

(for

Evolution

we may
remarks
in the

read Science)

'

is

a dream.*

Perhaps
I

It

will

be objected that

In these

have only dealt with Psychological Idealism


In

form

which Berkeley
It

left it

and that

have not
I

done

justice to

even
all

in this

shape, since

have

omitted to consider

the constructive part which,


little

though
Its

It

has received

attention subsequently,
I

originator considered essential to his scheme.

am

quite prepared to admit that there

Is

some

force

In these criticisms,

and

also that Berkeley's version

of the system

Is

the less likely to be In

harmony
his
'

with Science, from the fact that he seems to have

regarded

the
*

scientific

hypothesis
'

of

own
to

day

the

corpuscular philosophy

and

the me-

chanical

principles

which

have

been
Mr.

applied

accounting for phenomena,'


approval.^
is

with
to

a very lukewarm
Mill,

Let us turn then


all

above

things

the

philosopher

of

who men of

science,

and observe whether


1

his statement of the


^

Principles of Hjiman

Knowledge

50.

84

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


is

[part

il-

case

more agreeable

to ordinary science

than that

of his theological predecessor.

At

first

sight there

seems a promise of reconciliation

in his

language, for

verbally at least, he recognises the existence of a

permanent something which may serve as a substitute

for

matten

The

external

world which

is

dealt with

by natural science

consisted, according to
to

Berkeley, in ideas.
sists

According

Mr. Mill

it

con-

of sensations and permanent possibilities of sen-

sation.^

An
;

object

when

it

is

perceived

may be may

resolved into sensations phis permanent possibilities


of sensation

an object when

it is

not perceived

be resolved into permanent


alone.

possibilities of sensation

What

sensations

mean

is

tolerably plain, whether

the partial resolution of a perceived object into

them
perif

be legitimate or not
sensation
?

But what are

possibilities of

And

in

what sense can they be

manent

Mr. Mill habitually speaks of them as


in the

they could exist


entities exist.

same sense

in

which positive

But
is

this surely is
till

an entire delusion.
actuality.

A
It

possibiHty

nothing

it

becomes an

will be something, or

future time, but, until

may be something at some then, it is nothing. You may


it

verbally indeed give a kind of present being to a


future sensation
exists now.

by saying that the


is

possibility of

it

But there
this phrase.
*

no

reality in

nature corre-

sponding to

sensation must either be


p. 248.

Examination of Hamilton^

CHAP.

IX.

PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM.
;

185

or not be
is not.

and

if it is

only a possibility,

it

certainly

universe therefore which consists of such

possibilities is

a universe which for the present does


all
;

not exist at

it

is

a verbal

fiction,

and cannot

form the subject-matter of any science deserving the

name.

Mr. O'Hanlon, whose criticism on


nately,
nation,'
I

Mill, unfortu*

only

know from

the note in Mill's

Examitaken,
per-

from which the following extract


these

is

states

the difficulty in

terms

'
:

Your

manent
are not

possibilities of sensation are, so


felt,

long as they

nothing actual.
them,
'

Yet you speak of change


evident, though this

taking place in

and that independently of


it

our consciousness

^
;

and

is

Mr. O'Hanlon does not add, that unless change


in

something outside

consciousness

be possible,

science, as

we know
meet
this
'

it,

cannot
?

exist.

How
refers

does
'

Mr.

Mill

objection
to

He
is

his

young antagonist generally


subject in the
text
;

what

said on the
I

from which, as far as

able to judge, the following quotation

am may be most

conveniently selected as containing the essence of

what Mr.
his answer.

Mill
'

would have us understand to be

If

body altogether
is

is

only conceived

as a

power of exciting

sensations, the action of

one

body upon another

simply the modification by one


;

such power of the sensations excited by another


to use a different expression, the joint action of
^

or,

two

Examination of Hamilton,

p. 251, note.

i86

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


It is

[part

ix.

powers of exciting sensations.

easy for anyone


will

competent to such enquiries who


attempt,
to

make

the

understand how one group

of possi-

bilities of sensation can be conceived as destroying

or modifying another such group.'


is

Undoubtedly

it

easy to understand
is

this, if
first

by

possibility of sen-

sation

meant
But

(as

the
to

sentence in the above


sen-

extract
sation.
idealist,

would seem
if

show) power of exciting


this,

Mr. Mill meant


realist.

he was not an

but a

He

must have held that

besides sensations there were permanent powers of

producing sensations

manent

possibilities of sensation
if

inaccurately described as perwhich are to be


all,
' '

distinguished,

they are to be distinguished at


differences from the

by very subtle

substances

of

certain metaphysicians.

As, however, there can be


idealist,

no doubt that Mr. Mill considered himself an

we must suppose
and that
the
'

that

he adopted

this realistic

theory
;

only under the pressure of an immediate objection


in his

ordinary
'

moments he conceived
possibility
it

that

permanence of a

might

satisfy the

requirements of Science since

was a permanence,
it

and the requirements of Idealism since


the permanence of a possibility.

was only
little

Let us look a

more
If

into this matter.

we

say that a barrel of gunpowder constitutes

the permanent possibility of an explosion, what do

we mean ? We mean that in we find a large number of the

a barrel of gunpowder
conditions of an explo-


PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM.

CHAP.

IX.

187

slon in a permanent form,

and that the other con-

ditions necessary to that effect

may

at

any moment

be supplied.

It

is

perfectly accurate to talk of a

permanent
sensation

possibility of sensation in the


is,

same sense

as equivalent, that

to a set of

permanent causes of

by which, when they are properly supplesensation will


actually be produced.
belief in

mented by causes which are not permanent, but only


occasional, a

But though

Scieruce

may be consistent with a


possibilities, the
is

a world composed of such


of Idealism certainly
not.

teaching

Again, the permanence attributed to the possibilities

of sensation might be a permanence

not of the
If

conditions

by which sensations are produced but

of the laws which regulate their production.

we

conceive a being whose states of mind at successive

moments should occur

strictly in

accordance with law,

but with law acting only between his states of mind,

we
*

might, perhaps, say (though the expression would

not be a happy one) that a given law constitutes a

permanent

possibility'

of his having a particular


exist-

sensation.

But a theory, which should admit the

ence of nothing permanent except


it

in this sense, though would be entirely consistent with Idealism, would

unfortunately be altogether at variance with Science.


'

For any

statement,' says Mr. Mill,^

which can
in

be made concerning material phenomena


the Realistic theory, there
^

terms of

is

an equivalent meaning
p. 246.

Examinatio7i of Hamiltoji,


i88

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part u.

in

terms of sensation and possibilities of sensation.'


this
is.

Let us see how

Here
I

is

a proposition which
:

may The
'

prove convenient for purposes of illustration


candle at which

am

looking produces in

me

certain sensations of light, colour,


in

and shape.'

Stated

terms of the Psychological Theory


:

would run
duce

this proposition

'

The group

of sensation and of perma-

nent possibilities of sensation


in

known

as a candle pro-

me

certain sensations of light, &c.'


is

Now
is,

the
like

candle,

which

here asserted to be a cause,

other perceived objects, constituted (on the Psychological hypothesis)

by two elements
effect

viz.

sensations
of these
not.

and

possibilities of sensation.

Are both
?

necessary

to

produce the
zs

Certainly

One

of them

the

effect.

The

sensations which

the candle produces are part of the candle.

What

produces the sensations must, therefore, be the other


part of the cause
tion.

namely, the
and
to be in

possibilities of sensa-

But the

possibilities of sensation are, ipso facto,

not in

my consciousness,

(to avoid side issues)

we

may suppose them not


So that, though
the cause of
idealistic in its terms,

anybody

else's either.

starting from a proposition professedly

we

are forced to conclude that


colour, &c.,
is
!

my sensation of

something

out

of,

and independent of consciousness

This
that
^

may be

true, but, again,

must point out


it is

it is

not Idealism.
I

On

the contrary,

a kind

Of course

am

spch an expression as

not responsible for the psychology which renders sensation of shape ' permissible.
'

CHAP.

IX.

}^

PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM.
Realism
(as

189

of Transfigured
say), of

Mr. Spencer would

a particularly absurd type.

For we might

imagine a being so endowed that he could perceive


at

one moment every quality of the candle, which


in that case,
;

would

it

is

evident, consist entirely of


all

sensations

the possibilities of sensation being

conall

verted into actualities.

He

might also perceive

the physiological changes which are the necessary

antecedents of these sensations, and which would

thereby in the same


selves.

way become
clearly

sensations themto say of

Now

it

would

be erroneous

such a being that the immediate causes of the sensations

which constitute

his perception of the candle

were permanent
hypothesis
actualities)
;

possibilities of sensation (since

by

the

possibilities are all


it

converted into

and

would

clearly

be absurd to say that


;

these sensations were self caused

and

it

would be
any
I

altogether impossible to say that they were not caused


at
all.

What

fourth reply could be given on

theory which was both idealistic and scientific

am

unable to imagine.
result
:

So

that

we come

to this final

that

if

we

take a plain scientific proposition

asserting the action of external bodies, or

what are
in

commonly thought
the
first place,

to be- such,
it

on mind, we can,

only express

in

terms of possibilities

of sensation
tion
;

by

attributing to these a realistic significa-

and

in the

second place

if,

as

we have

a perfect

right to do,
all

we

conceive such possibilities of sensation


actualities,

converted into

we cannot

express the
all.

proposition in terms of the psychological theory at

190

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


*

[part

ii.

But,' the
*

reader may, perhaps, be Indined to

say,

these difficulties are just what might have been

expected.
proposition
tion

The
are

various renderings of the original


all

absurd,

because that proposi-

was an absurd one


I if

to start with.'
;

Extremely
but not at
all

absurd
absurd,

admit,

if

Idealism be true
so.

Science be

And

that

is

just the point.


it

Science cannot get on for an hour unless


to

be allowed

employ propositions of

this kind,

which assert the


Idealism, in the,

action of

some x upon the mind.


x, or in

hands of a true follower of Berkeley, would either

deny the existence of the


the Divine Spirit
;

would

identify

it

with

and

both cases would

make

received Science impossible.

Natural Realism again

would

identify the

x
all

both with the immediate object

of perception and with independent and extended


matter, and, like
present, at

other realistic systems, would

any

rate,

an appearance of harmony with

Scientific doctrine.

But when we ask the Psychodeal with

logical school

how they

the x,

we

can

extract from their teaching nothing but confusion.

They

give us to understand that they are idealists,

that in their opinion the world consists of nothing

besides sensations and possibilities of sensation

and

we

readily accept this as the true idealistic identifica-

tion of the real with the felt.


this identification is consistent

But on asking how


with a science which

nominally at least postulates a world independent of


mind,

we

find that they are forced to convert their

CHAP.

IX.]

PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM.

191

possibilities into objects

which exist without being

perceived, which can act as causes, which can suffer

change, and which are therefore as Httle ideal as the

most vehement
'But how,'
it

realist

need

desire.
*

may be asked,

if

there

is this

radical

discrepancy between Idealism and Science, happens


it

that so

many

philosophers have accepted the


cast speculative doubts
for the

first,

and yet have never


second
?

upon the
fact

How
a

do you account

that

neither Berkeley nor Mill (to

go no

further) ever

detected

difficulty which,
?
'

if it

exists

at

all,

is
I

sufficiently obvious

One

reason of this oversight

take to be that Idealists have occupied themselves

more with showing


consistent Science.

that their particular system


it

was

consistent with ordinary experience than that

was
of

with the more

remote

conclusions

The

sort of objection

which they chiefly

anticipated, and with reason, was that of the persons

who thought

that

a disbelief in matter ought to

take the form of running up against posts or tumbling


into the water;

and so much of

this objection de-

pends on a gross misconception, that the grain of truth which lies hid in it is easily overlooked.
I

have already pointed out two further reasons


in

which,

the case

of

Berkeley, go far

towards

accounting for his insensibility to a difficulty with

which he several times formally professes to

deal.

The

first

is,

that his scientific beliefs were certainly


Is,

lukewarm, and probably heterodox; the second

192

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

that his theology supplied the basis of a possible,

though not of any

actual, science of

phenomena, by
In Mr. Mill's

providing a permanent thinking substance in place


of the matter which he destroyed.

case neither of these reasons hold good.


tific

His scienwhile
it

faith

was fervent and orthodox

is

generally understood that his theological creed, what-

ever

may have been

its

precise nature, did not at

all

events include a belief in an Infinite

Mind who should

be the immediate cause of

all

our sensations.

Mr.

Mill,

however, had sources of error peculiar

to himself.

As

stated in the last chapter, one of

the disturbing elements in his philosophy, which no

doubt largely affected his views on


subject,

this

particular
in the

was the overpowering


truth.
'

interest

he took

genesis of a belief to the exclusion of a thorough

examination into

its

Thus

the main part of

the space devoted (in his


ton') to the Psychological

Examination of Hamiltheory of the external

world

is

occupied, not with discussing the general

philosophic ground and bearings of Idealism, but


in

showing how a

belief in matter originally

into existence.

But, besides this

came more general cause


fallen into, since

of error, there was another special to this question

which Mr. Mill should not have


is

it-

one of a kind he was particularly fond of preaching

against

mean

the error of supposing that because

there exists in language a name, that therefore there

must

exist in

Nature something corresponding to the

CHAP.

IX.]

PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM.
Because
it

193

name.

is

allowable to speak of a

'

per-

manent

possibility,'

he permitted himself too easily

to think that a world consisting of possibilities of

sensation and these alone, could in any real sense be

permanent,

or, as I

should prefer to say, persistent.


has been sufficiently shown,
It,
I

That

this is not so

hope, in the preceding pages.

therefore, only

remains for those

who

accept Idealism as the one

possible theory of the material world consistent with

Psychological analysis, to choose between the results


of Internal

and those of External observation on

the one hand, or on the other boldly to adopt a creed

which

is

avowedly inconsistent with


I

itself.

In the next two chapters


as
it

shall

examine, so far

is

necessary for

my

purpose, the philosophy of

a thinker,

who though
I

in

a popular discourse he

is

frequently associated w^th Mr. Mill on the points

with which

am

concerned, resembles him but

little

in his teaching.

194

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

UNIVERSITY
CHAPTER
X.

THE TEST OF INCONCEIVABILITY.


Mr. Spencer's theory of the grounds
that of Sir William Hamilton,
with,
is

of belief, like

intimately

bound up
view to

and seems
of,

chiefly constructed with a

the proof

the reality of the external world.


I

For

the moment, however,

shall deal with

It

separately,

reserving

till

the next section any reflections which


to in

may. be suggested by the use he has put it supporting the doctrine of what he calls, not
propriately,
'

inap-

Transfigured Realism.'

Sir William Hamilton, as


his initial assumptions
ness.

we have
his

seen, accepts

on

t^ie

authority of Conscious-

Mr.

Mill

again

expresses

readiness to
to

accept any belief which can be


*

shown
'

have been
until

in

Consciousness from the beginning

though

that (in his opinion


occurs,
is

apparently) improbable event

content to base his creed on the immediate


its

knowledge the mind has of


practice, therefore,
is

own

states

and

In

truly

an empiricist.
It

But Mr.

Spencer, though anxious that

should be understood

that he defends his doctrine In the interests of the

experience hypothesis,^ can hardly be described as


*

Principles of Psychology^ vol.

ii.

p. 407, note.

CHAP. X.]

THE TEST OF INCONCEIVABILITY.


in

195

an empiricist
the word
;

any but an

esoteric signification of

since even

for facts

given

in

experience

he requires a warrant, which must be more certain


than they are, because
certainty
is
it is

the test by which their

recognised.

All propositions are to be accepted as^unque


tionable

whose negative
is

is

inconceivable.^
;

Such, in

one sentence,

Mr. Spencers doctrine


is

but the

sentence, though apparently simple,

capable of
to

more than one


able, 'to

interpretation,

and points
*

more

than one possible system of philosophy.

Inconceiv-

begin with,

is

commonly, though
in

in

my opinion

very improperly, used


It

two quite

distinct senses.

may mean

either that

which cannot be believed,


Mr. Spencer^
it

or that which cannot be imagined.

protests against the idea that he uses

in the first
rightly,

or improper sense

and,
it

if I

understand him

he habitually uses

in the

second and correct one.


I

But as the point


which
*

is

somewhat important,
is

must be

permitted to give one or two of the quotations on


this

opinion

based.
is

An

inconceivable proposition

one of which

the terms cannot by any effort be brought into consciousness


asserts
in

that

relation
^

which the proposition


is

between them.'
*

It

one of which

the

subject and predicate cannot be united in the


intuition.'
^

same

And

as an example,
ii.

'

the two sides (of


'^

Principles of Psychology^ vol. 3 p^ 408.

p. 392.
-^

Ibid. p. 407.

Ibid.

196

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


in

[part

ii.

a triangle) cannot be represented

consciousness as
third

becoming equal
side,

in

their joint length to the

without the representation of a triangle being

destroyed.'

These quotations, which might


it

easily

be multiplied, would seem to make

perfectly clear

that when Mr. Spencer says a thing cannot be conceived,

he means that
in the

it

cannot be imagined or
'

re'

presented
is

mind

indeed the world


in

imagine

one which he actually uses


the other hand,
^ it
'

this connection.^

On

must be admitted that he


inconceivable
I
'

never

hesitates to use

and unthink'

able' as

synonymes so
;

that, if

interpret

him

rightly,

'unthinkable'

and 'unimaginable' must with him


is

be also synonymes, which


the best philosophical
in

not in accordance with

usage.

Again,

he quotes,

order to answer, the hackneyed instance of the

inconceivability of the antipodes

as

if

he thought
in

that the antipodes

had once been inconceivable


But
it

his sense of the word.

is

certain,

appre-

hend, that the antipodes were never unimaginable,

though they were, or are said

to

have been,

incre-

The difficulty can scarcely have been to dible. represent men standing head downwards, though it might have been to believe that, when so standing,
they would not
*

fall

off.^

Mr. Spencer's use of the

Fortnightly Review,

p. 544.

* *

Principles of Psychology, vol. ii. p. 409. Mr. Mill is not fortunate in his language on this point

am

inclined to think he held the right view.

though I See Exam, of Hamilton,


;

pp. 81, 86.

CHAP.

X.]

THE TEST OF INCONCEIVABILITY.


'

igf

word inconceivable
'

is

not then, in spite of


;

all

his

explanations, perfectly
less

unambiguous

but neverthe-

we may
refers
is

say with certainty that the word with

him

to

some mental

incapacity which
belief,

(he

asserts)

not an incapacity of

and with a

high degree of probability, that


imagination or representation.

it is

an incapacity of

After
doctrine

this

explanation,

let

us

return
it

to
will

the

under discussion, which

states,

be

recollected, that all


is

judgments the negative of which

inconceivable are to be accepted as true.

Now,
its

according to this theory, Is the inconceivability of

negative the ground on which any proposition ought


to

be accepted, or

is

it

simply an attribute which

in fact

belongs to self-evident propositions and to


?

no others
It will

Is

it

a reason, or

is

it

merely a mark

be observed that the whole nature of Mr.

Spencer's philosophy must entirely depend on which


of these alternatives he selects second, then
it

If

he

selects the
all

would only remain

to

examine

the

ultimate propositions on which his creed rests, and


to observe

whether
is

it

is

true that the negative of

each one of them


result of this

inconceivable.

But even
I

if

the

examination were to show (as

appre-

hend

it

would show) that the negative of some of


facility,

them might be conceived with the utmost


this

would

in

no way tend

to invalidate the
his creed rests
;

grounds
it

on which the remainder of

would

simply show that those grounds had been wrongly

198

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


If,

[part

ii.

described.
alternative,

on the other hand, he selects the


negative

first

and means

to assert that the inconceivais

bility of their
is

the ultimate reason which


it

to

be given

for all his beliefs, then, if


is

can be
beliefs

shown

that this

in

reality
far

no reason, the
he
is

themselves must,

so

as

concerned,

be
ob-

regarded as requiring proof, but not as


tained
it.

having

There
Spencer,

are,

think,
in

some phrases used by Mr.


the
earlier

especially

version

of his
to

argument, which might lead one for a

moment

suppose that he held to the second of these alternatives.

Nevertheless,

shall

assume that the


Postulate
or

first
it

represents his real opinion, because otherwise

is

evident that his Universal


criterion of truth could

ultimate

never be brought forward as

an argument at
opposite
is

all.

If the inconceivability of the


is

merely an attribute which

thought to

attach itself to those ultimate beliefs which neither

have nor require proof, the discovery of


in certain cases will aifect

its

absence

no belief except the one


It can, there-

which asserted
fore,

its

universal presence.

never supply an ultimate ground of conviction,


sinks
into

and

fact

of

secondary philosophic

interest!

We
the
first

must credit Mr. Spencer then with holding


alternative, which, as

the following quota-

tions

may

serve to

indicate,

undoubtedly

fits
'

in

naturally and easily with his habitual language.

To

'

CHAP.

X.]

THE TEST OF INCONCEIVABILITY.


^

199

assert,'

he

says,

'

the inconceivableness of the neis

gative (of a cognition),

at the

same time

to assert

the psychological necessity


it,

we

are under of thinking

and to give our


'

logical justification for holding it!


it

Again, ^
the

How

do we know that
to

is
?

impossible for

same thing

be and not to be
impossibility
?

What
same

is

our

criterion

of this

Can
this

Sir William

Hamilton assign any other than


ceivability
?
it

incon-

Here,

will

be observed, we have a general

statement of the theory, with a particular example


of
its

application

and from a consideration of these


to quote,
it

and of other passages, too long

would

seem

that Mr. Spencer

regards our incapacity to

perform a certain mental act as the ultimate ground

on which

all

propositions,
to

even those asserting truths


finally to

commonly thought
accepted.

be necessary, are

be

This mental
thinking,
is

act,

have already given reasons

for
;

one of imagination or representation


I

but not to enter into unnecessary controversy,


describe
it

will

in

Mr. Spencer's own words as consistIf

ing in

'

tearing^ asunder states of consciousness.'

this operation

cannot be performed
persist
in

if

the states of
spite of our

consciousness
efforts

cohering,
then,

in

to

disunite

them,

according to

Mr.

Spencer,
^

we have
'"'

not only the highest warrant which


are

Page 407, the

italics

my

own.
p. 344.

Page

425.

Fortnightly Review,

200

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

it is

possible to attain for supposing that the attri-

butes represented by these states of consciousness


coexist
in

nature,

but

warrant which, constructed as


to imagine/
If this

we have we

also
are,

the
it

highest
possible

is

be

so,

our prospects of discovering a

satisfactory philosophy

seem

small.

In what possible
it

way can

a psychological fact
'

whether
first

consists in

attempting to

tear asunder states of consciousness,'

or in anything else

afford a satisfactory warrant for

some other
a warrant

fact,

unless

we
of

take for granted


for

a very large number


is

propositions
?

which
should

very much needed


pre-established

Why
world
?

we assume
the
'

this
'

harmony between
'

subjective

and the

objective

Grant

either

some

theological postulate,

or

some law of
it

inherited aptitudes,

and the harmony may cease to


is

be surprising

but these are hypotheses which

needless to say cannot themselves afford a warrant


until
is

they

first

obtain

it.

Nor
*

is

this

all.

Not only
for holding

the mental incapacity to


'

tear asunder states of


'

consciousness

no

'

logical justification

a
in

belief, but,

on Mr. Spencer's own

principles, a belief
'

the incapacity would appear to require a

logical

justification' itself

We
is
^

are supposed by his theory

to believe that
to

'

it

impossible for the same thing

be and not to

be,'

on the ground that we cannot

conceive the opposite. But


1

how do we know
2

that

we

Psychology,

p. 425.

j^j^j

CHAP. X.]

THE TEST OF INCONCEIVABILITY.


?

201

cannot conceive the opposite


requires a warrant, or
is it

Is this a
?

beHef which
is^

not

If

it

then the

warrant must be that


conceive the opposite

we cannot
;

conceive that

we can
all
its

and as

this belief

and

successors will also require similar warrants,

we

are

committed
hand,
I

to

an

infinite

regress.

If,

on the other

it is

not a belief which requires a warrant, then

desire to

know why the


to be

belief that

'

it is
'

impossible
?

for the
I

same thing

and not
it

to

be

requires one
I

am
I

quite as certain that

is

impossible, as
;

that

cannot conceive

it
*

to

be possible

and
'

if I

am am

not expected to give a

logical justification
I

for the
I

second of these

beliefs,

see no reason
for the
first.

why

should

be expected to give one

On

Mr. Spencer's own

principle,

indeed,

the

mental fact that

we cannot

conceive the opposite of

a given proposition, in the only case in which, according to him,


is
it

can serve as a

final

ground of

certainty,

not one of which

we

can have any immediate

knowledge.

Only,
is

it

appears,

when

the proposition

whose opposite
must be
true.

inconceivable happens also to be

undecomposable,^ can

we

say with assurance that

it

So that before applying his postulate that things which to the proof of some axiom (say are equal to the same thing are equal to one an'

other
this

'

'^)

we have

to convince ourselves, first, that

is

a proposition not capable of further decom;

position

and, secondly, that


Psychology,
p.

we

are unable to con^

410.

Ibid. p. 411.

202

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


its

[part

ii.

ceive

opposite.

Surely the scepticism which

is

set at rest

by such arguments as these must be of a


;

very pecuHar complexion

for

it

must doubt that

things which are equal to the


to

same thing are equal


very easy to deter-

one another, and be certain of logical and psy-

chological facts, not to

my mind

mine, and respecting which, by Mr. Spencer's


account,

own

men have

frequently been in error.


it

These
capacity
'

objections,

will

be observed, keep their


in-

weight whatever the nature of the psychological

may be which Mr. Spencer


'

describes as an

inability to conceive the opposite

of a proposition.

Though
that,

there

is,

as

before hinted,

some

obscurity

hanging over

this point,

there can be
is,

little

doubt

at all events,

the incapacity

as has been

hitherto assumed, one of imagination or representation.

What seems more


else

doubtful
it

is

whether Mr.

Spencer does not suppose

to

be

this
it

and

at the

same time something


fully

from which

ought carelanguage

to

be distinguished.

Much

of his

suggests the idea that, in his opinion, necessities of

imagination are not merely accompaniments


causes
of,

of,

or

necessities of belief, but

are actually the


attri-

same

thing,

and that the representation of the


is

butes in one image

actually identical with the act

of believing that two attributes are united in one


object.

He

says, for instance,^

'

An

abortive effort

to conceive the negation of a proposition,


*

shows that

Psychology,

p. 425.

Italics are

my

own.

Cf. also p. 402.

CHAP,

xj

THE TEST OF INCONCEIVABILITY.


is

203

the cognition expressed

one of which the predicate


is,

invariably exists along with the subject [that

suppose, shows that


united]
;

we

cannot conceive them

dis-

and the

discovery that the predicate invariits object is

ably exists along with


this cognition is one

the discovery that


to accept!

we are compelled
incredibility

And
in-

again, in the very act of distinguishing

between

conceivability

and

he seems to suggest

the idea that they differ in degree and not in kind.^


If the

strange psychological
is

doctrine

thus

adumany

brated
justified

really

Mr.

Spencer's,

he

is

no doubt

on his own principles

in asserting that
is

proposition of which the opposite

inconceivable

must be believed, because inconceivable with him

must mean not only that which


also,

is

unimaginable, but
is

and
in

at the

same

time, that

which

absolutely

and

the extremest degree incredible.

In truth,

however, his philosophy gains nothing by a confusion

which
logy.

(if it

be

his) is a serious blot

on

his psycho-

The
it

statement that

we

are absolutely incap-

able of believing the opposite of a proposition

may
it,
;

carry with

the assurance that

we must

believe

for in reality the


I

two expressions are equivalent


to see
I

but

altogether

fail

how

it

can show us that

we

ought to believe
it

it.

doubt myself, indeed, whether

is

possible to try to believe the opposite of an


in

axiom

the sense in which

it is

possible to try to
it

imagine the state of things opposite to that which


1

Page 408.

204

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


I

[part

ii.'

asserts.

doubt,

for

example, whether

we can

seriously try to believe

that a thing can both be

and not

be,

though some sort of attempt to imagine


filled

a space at the same time

and not

filled

by an
this

object might possibly be made.

But however

may

be,

it

is

certain that the incapacity to believe


it

one thing, though


necessity/
^

may

constitute a
'

'

psychological
'

cannot give a
contradictory

logical justification

for

believing

its

and that

if it

be once

admitted that such a logical justification must be


obtained for what are
evident propositions,

commonly thought

to be selfI

we should

require, as

pointed

out before, not one, but an infinite series of justifications,

before anything could be considered as proved

at

all.

In short, whether inconceivable


(if

means un-

imaginable, unrepresentable

there

is

such a word),

unthinkable, or in the highest degree unbelievable,


its

relation

to the

theory of ultimate premises of

knowledge remains the same.

Under no circumis

stances can the recognition of the mental fact that

the opposite of a certain proposition

inconceivable

by me, be
ing
it.

to

me

a satisfactory reason for believ-

Mr. Spencer seems to be under the singular


delusion
*

that

any one declining to recognise the

Universal Postulate can consistently do this only so

long as he maintains the attitude of pure and simple


negation.

The moment he
^

asserts

anything

the

Page

407.

CHAP, x.]

THE TEST OF INCONCEIVABILITY.

205

moment he even gives a reason for his denial, he may be stopped by demanding his warrant. Against therefore " may be because," and every every entered a demurrer, until he has said why this
''
''

proposition

is

to

be accepted rather than the count-

ter-proposition.

So

that he cannot even take a step

towards justifying his scepticism respecting the Universal Postulate without, in the very act, confessing
his acceptance of it'
^

The may
it is

confusion

underlying

these remarks
;

has
if
I

already been pointed out by implication

and

venture to give an opinion on such a question,


the fundamental confusion which has vitiated
all

this portion of

Mr. Spencer s speculation.

He seems
it

to suppose that the choice lies

between founding a
order to demonstrate

creed on the Universal Postulate, and founding

upon nothing
puts

at all

and

in

the absurdity of the second alternative, he actually

himself to the trouble


calls
'

of refuting a
'

theory
'

which he
nothing

Pure Empiricism

which

tacitly

assumes that there


is

may be

a Philosophy in which
is

asserted but what

proved.'^

Whether
I

this singular

system has any objective existence


:

do not know
but

if it

has,

Mr. Spencer

may be
its

allowed
;

the credit of having effectually exposed


I

absurdity

protest against the notion that


this type,

we must choose
nor can
Page
391.
I

between a philosophy of

and one ultimately


;

based on the Universal Postulate


1

the

Page

427,

''^


2o6

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

least

imagine the dialectical process by which Mr.


*

Spencer would compel the

Metaphysicians

'

(who

come

in for so

many hard

sayings at his hands) to

regard them as the only possible alternatives.


In one of the earlier chapters of his
Analysis,' Mr.
*

General

Spencer has found

it

convenient to

give us an amended version of one of Berkeley's


dialogues.^ It will not,
ful
if,

hope, be thought disrespectI

also in the dialogue form,

give

my

idea of
'

the method in which Mr. Spencer and a


physician
'

Meta-

would discuss the necessity and

validity
this

of the Universal Postulate.

We

must suppose

imaginary individual to have so far forgotten himself


as
to

make some

positive

statement

say

that

thing must either be or not be.

Instantly^ Mr.

Spencer demands

his

warrant for the assertion, upon

which our Metaphysician would probably say


Metaphysician.
tion,

have no warrant for the asserIt

and

wish for none.


is

expresses a belief for

which no proof
is

forthcoming, and for which none

required.

Mr.
position

Spencer.
is

Still

you must say why

this pro-

to

be accepted rather than the counter-

proposition.^

Metaphysician.

Perhaps,
Certainly.
2

if

that

is

your opinion,
version

you

will

be good enough to give

me your own

of this reason.

Mr.
1

Spencer.
337.

believe that a thing


s

Page

Page 427.

ibid.

CHAP. X.]

THE TEST OF INCONCEIVABILITY.


is

207

must

either be or not be, because this

a proposp((^'^

tion of

which

cannot conceive the negation.

Metaphysician.
that
tion

Then

in

your opinion the

fact

you cannot conceive the negation of a proposiis

in all cases
^

a sufficient logical justification for

believing

it ?

Mr.

Spencer.

Well, not
^

exactly.
'

It is sufficient

only in the case of those propositions


further decomposable.'

which are not

Metaphysician.
that
all

Then

understand you to hold

propositions which are not further decom-

posable,
true
;

and whose negations are inconceivable, are


'

and that a thing must


Spencer.

either

be or not be

'

is

such a proposition.

That my opinion. Metaphysician. Without disputing your major premiss which, however, by no means commends am curious to know how you to my mind
Mr.
is

itself

arrive at the conclusion that the proposition

we

are

discussing (i) cannot be further decomposed, and

has

{2)

a negation which
Spencer.

is

inconceivable
first

.'*

Mr.

^I

arrive at the

conclusion^

by
I

a careful consideration of the proposition


arrive at the second

itself;

Metaphysician.
feel

by a process of introspection.* Speaking for myself, I do not


respecting the

more

certainty

accuracy with
I

which these operations have been performed, than


1

Page

407.

Page 410.

Pages 394-399.

Fortnightly Review, pp. 542-545.

2o8

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

did respecting the truth of the original assertion for

which you
indeed,
I

informed
feel

me

warrant was

required

do not

nearly so much.

Doubtless,

however, as you are so particular on the subject of


warrants, you have

some warrant

for

your opinions
precisely

on these points
it is ?

could you inform

me

what

shall
it

not continue
is

the

imaginary dialogue,

because

hard to think of any reply which Mr.


to this last

Spencer could make


not have about
It

demand which would


If the

a slight air of absurdity.

reader desires to bring the conversation to a proper


close,

he

will

have no
I

difficulty in filling in the


It

blank
clear

for himself

have said enough to make


Postulate does not, in

why

it is

that Mr. Spencer's elaborate discussion on

the Universal

my

opinion,
:

constitute a valuable addition to Philosophic theory

and

it

only remains to examine


is

how far
If

his particular

system of Realism, which


the Universal Postulate,
dited.
is

professedly founded on
that be discre-

tenable

This

shall

do

in the

next chapter.

CHAP.

XI.]

MR. SPENCER'S PRODF OF REALISM.

209

CHAPTER
I

XI.

MR. SPENCER'S PROOF OF REALISM.

HAVE been

In

some doubt whether, having regard


I

to the general plan of this essay,

ought or ought

not to Introduce Into

It

any

criticism

on Mr. Spencer's
gained some

Proof of Realism.

My

wish has been to consider

merely those opinions which


acceptance
these
In

have

among English

thinkers,

and
;

to criticise

their

most perfect shape

but

though,
is

doubtless, Mr. Spencer's statement of his views

the best attainable,

am

not aware that the portion

of his speculations which he himself would describe


as metaphysical
ditions,
in
fulfils

the

first

of the

above confol-

having obtained

any philosophic
metaphysics

lowing.

But though Mr. Spencer's


not perhaps

'

have

commanded much
is

assent, his general

theory of the universe, which logically depends on


his metaphysics,

accepted in

its

main outline by

so

many

thinkers in this country, and occupies so


field

Important a space In the


that a sort of reflected

of general speculation,
Is

importance

shed over his

defence of the foundations on which the Imposing


superstructure
finally
rests. It

may, therefore, be

2IO

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

convenient to state some of the reasons which exist


for thinking that the defence
is

hardly as effective as
it.

Mr. Spencer seems to consider Mr. Spencer sees


clearly,

more

clearly perhaps

than other philosophers with


allied, that

whom
if

he

is

nearly
is

the question of the external world

fundamental one for Science, or,


at all events for Evolution.
'

not for Science,


idealist
is

Should the

be

right,'
^

he says,

'

the doctrine of Evolution

dream.'
cer

As, previous to this utterance, Mr. Spen(I


if

had written

think) five

volumes of

'

Philo-

sophy,' which,

the doctrine

of Evolution be a
it

dream, can be
clear that

little

better than waste paper,

is

he

is

bound under heavy


is

penalties to prove

that the Idealist

wrong.

Accordingly, he gives a

defence of Realism which certainly does not err on


the side of meagreness.
It consists of

some

nine-

teen chapters, occupying nearly two hundred pages,


divided,^ as the reader acquainted with Mr. Spencer's

favourite
expect,

method of arrangement
into a

will

be prepared to

into

an Introduction, an Analytical Arguproximate Analysis and an


a Synthetical Argument

ment (subdivided

ultimate Analysis), and

and enriched with even a larger number than usual


of those apologues with which Mr. Spencer so often
finds
it

convenient to prepare the minds of his

readers for the comprehension of his


speculations.
*

more abstruse

Psychology^ vol.

ii.

p. 311.

"^

Ibid. 367.

CHAP. XL]

MR. SPENCER'S PROOF OF REALISM.

21

It is

evidently impossible within the limits of

this essay to criticise so elaborate


its details.

a discussion

in all

The most

convenient plan will perhaps

be to say a few words on the substance of those


chapters which seem to
in their existing order.
call

for remark, taking

them

But before doing

this, it will

be well to determine certain preliminary points, which


will greatly facilitate the

progress of the argument.


idealists

In the

first

place,

Mr. Spencer and the

are agreed in asserting that


ceive the permanent reality
'

we do not
if

directly perexists.
'

such a thing

What we

are conscious

of,'

says Mr. Spencer,^


to

as

properties of matter, even


tance,

down

weight and

resis-

are but

subjective

affections

produced by

objective agencies which are


able.'

unknown and unknow-

In the second place, the idealist denies that there


is

any proof that

this

permanent

reality exists, while


is

Mr. Spencer asserts that there


that he
is

such proof, and

in

possession of

it.

And

in the third place,

understand Mr. Spencer

to maintain that the

unknown and unknowable, un-

perceived and unperceivable reality, varies in some


fixed relation with the
tive affection

known and perceived

subjec

which

it

produces.
to a certain

The thing to be proved being thus extent made clear, let us proceed to the
In doing so
^

proof.

shall take the liberty of omitting


Psychology, vol.
ii.

p.

493.

P 2

212

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


to

[part

ii.

any detailed reference

the

first

four

chapters

which Mr. Spencer describes as an Introduction.

My justification

for

doing this

is

that, as the object


^

of these chapters

is
I

merely to foreshadow
shall

the suc-

ceeding arguments,
to his case

overlook nothing essential


course.

by taking such a

While

my motive

for doing

it is

In the first place to

save space, and in

the second place to avoid having to enter, not merely


into

Mr. Spencer's views, but into

his

views of other

people's views.
consist in

Three out of these four chapters


Mr. Spencer
In the habit of hold-

an attack on that miscellaneous body of


is

thinkers

whom
to
'

ing

up
of

general contempt under the collective


' ;

name

Metaphysicians
Is,

and though

my

private

conviction

that could they reply they

would make
still,

very short work of some of his objections,

as

am

anxious to keep as clear as possible of historical

discussion,

and as

am

in

no way concerned
to the
in

to de-

fend the philosophers in question, the better course


will

be to proceed at once

argument, without indulging


mishing.

main body of the any preliminary skir-

Chapter V.

Is

merely explanatory of the general

arrangement of the discussion.


Chap. VI. contains
'

The Argument from


^
:

Priority,'

thus summarised by Mr. Spencer

'

In the history

of the race, as well as in the history of every mind,

Realism
1

is

the primary conception


ii.

only after
i^j^ p ^74.

it

has

Psychology, vol.

p. 367.

CHAP.

XI.]

MR. SPENCER'S PROOF OF REALISM.

213

been reached and long held without question does


it

become

possible even to frame the Idealistic con-

ception, while resting

upon the

Realistic

one

and

then, as ever after, the Idealistic conception, depend-

ing on the Realistic one, must vanish the instant the


Realistic
first

one

is

taken away.'

With regard
*

to the

of these positions, Mr. Spencer observes/ that


its

his calling in question

converse

will excite sur-

prise in the metaphysical reader,'


into astonishment
if

which

will

'

rise

he distinctly denies
is

it.'

If the

metaphysical reader
it will, I

either surprised or astonished,

apprehend, be more probably at Mr. Spen'

cer's

thinking that the assertion that


is

some form of
it

Realism
kind
'

the primary and natural belief of man-

is

relevant,

than at his thinking

true.

never heard of anybody

who supposed
illustrations,

that

the

Boys, Hottentots, and Farm-labourers, from

whom

Mr. Spencer draws his


Idealists

were either

or inferred the existence of the indepen-

dent world from the consciousness of their


sensations.

own

Nor

is

it

easy to

see

holding Mr. Spencer's views can think

how anybody it of much

importance what they thought, since their Crude

Realism

is

nearly as far
it

removed from Transfigured


*

Realism as
Spencer,^
'

is

from Idealism.

But,'

says

Mr.

Realism must be posited, before a step

can be taken towards propounding Idealism.'


in

And

the
^

succeeding paragraph he implies that the


Psychology, vol.
ii.

p. 369.

Ibid. p. 374.


A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,
[part

214

ii.

proof of Idealism logically requires us to assume the


existence of external
this
(?

Independent) objects.
if

For

statement however, which,

true,

would un-

doubtedly confute the idealist as distinguished from


the sceptic,
I

cannot find a shadow of proof, unless


I

the following extract (for the length of which


apologise)
*

must

is

to

be regarded as such.

Tell (a labourer or farmer) that the sound he

hears from the bell of the village church exists In


himself;

and that

in

the absence of

all

creatures

having ears there would be no sound.

When

his

look of blank amazement has waned, try and

make

him understand

this truth

which

is

so clear to you.
bell are

Explain that the vibrations of the


nicated to the air
as
;

commuthem

that the air communicates


;

waves or pulses

that these pulses successively

strike the

membrane

of his ear, causing

It

to vibrate

and that what

exists In the air as mechanical

movetheir

ments become^in him the sensation of sound, which


varies in pitch as these
rapidity of succession.

movements vary
him about
air,

in

And now
bell,

ask yourself,
?

What

are these things you are telling

When
?

you speak
If

to

him of the

of the
so

of the me-

chanical motions, do you

mean

many

of his Ideas

you

do,

you

fall

into the astounding absurdity of

supposing that he already has the conception you


are trying to give him.
vibrations, then,

By

the

bell,

the

air,

the

you mean just what he means

so

many

objective existences

and actions; and by

CHAP. XL]

MR. SPENCER'S PROOF OF REALISM.

215

no

possibility can

you present

to

him

this hypothesis,

that

what he knows as sound


realities.

exists in him,
In

and not
with

outside him, without postulating,

common

him, these objective

By

no possibility can
sensations,

you show him


these things
If

that he

knows only his own


to be

without supposing

him

already consciotcs 0/ all


his sensations!

and changes causing


sentence of
It,

we may judge from


last

this extract,

and especially
I

from the
italics,

which

have put

in

Mr. Spencer imagines that an Idealist


prove that
that,

sets to

work
ries,

to

we know

only our

own

sensations,

by showing

according to modern physical theo-

our sensations are produced in us by the motions


:

of objects In space

by showing,
its

for example, that

sound

Is

subjective, because

objective cause

is

vibrations,

which are something altogether


If

different
Idealist

from the sensations they produce.


really

any

argued

in this

way,

his

procedure would cercalls


^
'

tainly exhibit

what Mr. Spencer


But

a scarcely

Imaginable blindness to the contradiction between

premises and conclusion.'

never heard of such

an individual, and
representative.

if

he
^

exists,

he certainly

is

not

It Is

true that

many

Idealists

for

example, Mr.

J. S.

Mill

-have

held, in

my

opinion

erroneously, that Idealism was consistent with the

usual physical theories respecting the causes of sensation,

but they never founded their Idealism on

Psychology

vol.

ii.

p. 374.

Cf. section of this

Essay.

2i6

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

those theories, and whatever be their errors, are certainly not guilty of
' *

unimaginable blindness.'
Priority
'

The Argument from


it

may

therefore

be dismissed, because, of the two main positions of

which
is

consists,

one

is

not relevant, and the other


first

not true.

It is

not relevant to say, that the

and natural

belief of

mankind

is realistic

it is

not

true to say, that the proof of Idealism logically in-

volves Realism.

Chap. VI I. ^ contains
plicity,'

'

The Argument from Sim:

which

is

shortly this

Since

the proof of

Realism contains
of Idealism,
it
I

is

much fewer steps than the proof therefore much less likely to be

erroneous.
of reasoning

shall reserve

my remarks

on

this piece

till

we

reach Chapters XIII. and XIV.,


;

where

it

is

more elaborately repeated


that
if,

and

shall

only say here


think,^ the

as

Mr. Spencer seems


to

to

proofs

whose lengths have


all
all

be com-

pared include not only


of one view, but also

that can be said in favour

that can be said against the

other

the nineteen chapters we are now considering


The Argument from Dismay be stated thus ^ The one pro'
:

must furnish a powerful objection against the truth


of Realism.

Chap. VI 11.^ contains


tinctness.'
It

'

position of Realism

Is

presented

In vivid terms,

and

each of the
1

many

propositions of Idealism or Scepii.

Psychology, vol.
Ibid. p. 379.

p. 375.

2 4

j^j^j

p ^yj^

Ibid. p. 380.

CHAP.

XI.]

MR. SPENCER'S PROOF OF REALISM.


represented in faint terms
ergo,

217

ticism
is

is

'

Realism

to

be preferred.

Without wasting the reader's

time by disputing the major premiss of this argument,


viz.

that

the propositions

whose terms are

vividly represented are to be preferred to propositions

whose terms are


is

faintly represented

absurd
it

as this

when crudely

stated,

and

ill

as

fits

in

with our author's doctrine, that propositions are to

be accepted

in proportion to the
I

strength with which

their terms cohere}

shall content

myself with attack*

ing the minor premiss.

What,
which
is

then,

is

'

the one proposition of Realism


?

represented in vivid terms

In glancing
Realism,

through

Mr. Spencer's

defence

of

we

come

across a large

highly abstract

number of propositions of a character, and all of them equally

necessary to his system.

He

has opinions on the

nature of the connection between subject and object

proof of the existence of the object explanation of the nature of the object none of which can be
omitted without depriving
essential
his

doctrine

of

some
'^

element.

Are

these the propositions, or


in vivid

any of them, which are represented

terms

The
is

reader shall judge from one specimen.

Here
sets

an extract describing the Real, as


:

us by Mr. Spencer's Realism

it

is

put before

These several

of experiences unite to form a conception of some-^

thing beyond consciousness which


^

is

absolutely inde-

Psychology, vol.

ii.

p. 450.

2i8

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


;

[part

ii.

pendent of consciousness

which possesses power,


it

if

not Hke that of consciousness, yet equivalent to

and which remains


appearances.

fixed in the

midst of changing
indepen-

And

this conception, uniting


is

dence, permanence, and force,

the conception

we

have of
called

matter.'
this

If

the reader thinks the

ideas

up by

sentence are particularly vivid,


^

he must, as Mr. Spencer remarks


sion,

on another occa-

have *a mental structure of a very peculiar


because

kind.'

The
and

real

truth

is

that,

all

idealists

sceptics, in the exposition

and defence of

their

opinions, have indulged

in a great deal of abstract

Psychology, Mr. Spencer concludes that such speculations are

more required by their opinions than they


their opponents.

are
tity
it

by the opinions of

The quansupport of
in
I

of such speculation which he has himself found


in

necessary to give to the world

Realism should

have made him cautious

his

assertions on this point,

which

are, in fact, as

shall

presently show, founded on a misconception respect-

ing the sceptical position.

The

chapters from IX. to XI. inclusive, which


cri-

contain Mr. Spencer's account of our ultimate


terion of belief,

have been

sufficiently dealt with in

the last chapter.

Chapter XII. contains an account of the proper

mode

of comparing conclusions in those cases where


^

Psychology^

vol.

ii.

p. 327.

CHAP. XL]

MR. SPENCER'S PROOF OF REALISM.

219

both sides

make
(as

appeal to the Universal Postulate,


all

on which

Mr. Spencer thinks)

belief

and
is,

all

reasoning are ultimately founded.


the
*

His view

that

conclusion
'

which involves the postulate the


the one to be accepted
;

fewest times
I

is

and though

shall for

obvious reasons ignore that part of his reitself,

marks which assume the truth of the postulate


it

will

be well to say something respecting an arguin its

ment which

main outlines Mr. Spencer used


essentially as follows

before in Chapter VII.

This argument
piece of reasoning

is
is,

Every
more

other things being equal, to be


in inverse

trusted, roughly speaking,


its

proportion to
it is

length.

In other words, the longer


is

the

likelihood

there of error having crept in at

some

point in

its

course.
in

How far this

argument,
is

if

sound,

can be used
will

favour of Realism

a question which
present
I

be discussed immediately.

At

am

conIt

cerned with the argument considered in

itself

may be admitted
in
it is

at

once that the allegation contained

true.

It is

undoubtedly the
is

fact that of

any

two computations the shorter


correct

probably the more

other things being the same.

But then, under


?

what circumstances are other things the same

To

whom

does

it

occur to

know no
So
far as
I

other difference

between two
between

lines of
?

reasoning but the difference

their lengths

can see, to only

two

classes of people

to those

difference merely because they

who know no other know nothing about

220

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

the matter,
history

who

are absolutely Ignorant both of the


;

and of the character of the things compared

and

to those

who know something about


lines of

the subject,

but can draw no conclusions from their knowledge,


in

whose eyes both

reasoning appear equally

solid,

and the authorities


This

on both sides equally


is

worthy of deference.

not very different

from saying that the only people be convinced solely by the


plicity,'
'

who

are likely to

argument from sim-

are those

who

are either too ignorant or too

stupid to

make

use of any other.

These are

not,

imagine, the only persons


to persuade to
;

whom

Mr. Spencer desires


it is

but

it is

clear that

only in relation

them

that the comparative lengths of


^
*

two argu-

ments can be regarded as


as a

a rigorous test of the

relative validities of their conflicting conclusion,' or


*

method of ascertaining the comparative values


cognitions.'
^

of
is,

all

To

all

other people

to

all,

that

who have some


lines

opinion respecting the intrinsic


of reasoning compared

worth of the

the

relative length of those lines can at

most be only

one of the grounds on which their ultimate verdict


arises, what is to be done when the longest argument appears to be in
is
;

based

and then the question

itself

the soundest

To

judge by the confidence


In his
'

which Mr. Spencer appears to place


relative validity,' his opinion

test of
that,

would seem
2

to

be

Psycholos^yy vol.

ii.

p. 434.

Ibid.

CHAP

XI.]

MR. SPENCER'S PROOF OF REALISM.

22r

even

in that case, the conclusion arrived at


Is

by the

shortest route

to be accepted

a somewhat extrare-

vagant doctrine, according to which a long division


sum, done by a charity school-boy, would be

garded as giving

more trustworthy
to

results

than

the calculations establishing the lunar theory.


better

The
other

opinion

seems

be

that,

though,

things

being equal, the fewer steps an argument


is

consists of the less likelihood

there of one

of

them being

false

yet that, since this risk

may be
It

indefinitely diminished

by repeated examinations.
in those cases

may be

practically neglected

where

the balance of reason appears, on other grounds, to


Incline distinctly to

one side or the other.


Is

And

this

opinion,

take

it,

not only the most reasonable


Is

one

In itself,

but

is

that which

sanctioned by the

ordinary practice of mankind.

Chapter
general
'

XI 1 1,

contains

the application of the


'

test of relative validity

established In the

preceding

chapter

to

the

particular

controversy

between Realism and Scepticism.


have found reason
pretty

As, however,
the
'

we
'

for thinking that


I

test

is

nearly

worthless,

might consider myself

absolved from any obligation to consider


valid,
It

how

far, if

would

tell
;

in

favour of Mr. Spencer's parpass


this

ticular

opinions

and should therefore


it

chapter over, were

not that

It

affords a convenient

occasion for clearing up

some of the misconceptions

respecting the essential nature of the arguments to


222

[part
ii.

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

be compared, by which our author has been greatly


misled.
I

will begin, as

he does, with the

realistic
:
'

argu-

ment.

Here^

is

his

own

version of

it

Let him

(the reader) contemplate

an object this book, for


let

mstance.

Resolutely refraining from theorising,


finds.

him say what he


of

He finds

that he

is

conscious

the book as existing apart

from

himself.

Does

there enter into his consciousness any notion about


sensation
?

Not
at all

so
is

Does he perceive
is

that the thing he

conscious of

an image of the
as he refuses
feels

book?

Not

So long

to translate the fact into

any hypothesis, he
objective

simply conscious of the book, and not of an impression of the book


subjective thing.

of an
lastly,

and not of a

He

feels that this recognition of


is

the book as an external reality


act
will,

a single indivisible

And,

he

feels that,

do what he

he cannot reverse

this act

he cannot conceive

that where he sees

and feels

the book there is nothing.

Hence, while he continues looking at the book, his


belief in
it

as

an external
It

reality

possesses the

highest validity possible.


of the

has the direct guarantee


;

Universal Postulate

and

it

assumes the

Universal Postulate only once'

This very singular passage

is

immediately

fol-

lowed by three pages of argument, intended to show


^

Psychology,

vol.

ii.

p.

437

(italics

my

own).

CHAP. XI.]

MR. SPENCER'S PROOF OF REALISM.

223

that

we

can and do have a knowledge of the not-self

without having at the same time a knowledge of the


self.

How
I

this is

to

be reconciled with the

state-

ment

have

italicised

above, which asserts that in


it

looking at a book

we
;

are conscious of

as existing
it

apart from ourselves

how,

in

other words,

can be

possible to think of a thing as existing apart from

another thing, without at the same time thinking of


that other thing,
I

do not pretend
slip
:

to say.
I

Possibly

the expression
objections of
I

is

in

any

case,

pass on to

more importance.
first place,
if it

contend, then, in the


stated,

that the realistic


all

argument above
Spencer thinks
second

even
is

proved

that Mr.

it

proves,

not sufficient to establish


I

the ordinary belief in an external world.


in
tlie

contend,

place,

that the
rests

psychological facts
are,

on which the argument

when properly

understood, not inconsistent with either Idealism or


Scepticism.
if

And
is,

contend, in the third place, that


as Mr. Spencer thinks
it
is,

the argument

subit

versive of any theory of Idealism or Scepticism,

is

not less subversive of Mr. Spencer's

own

theory of

Transfigured Realism.

What
argument
terms.
'

is
?

the thing supposed to be proved by this

Mr. Spencer states

it

in

the clearest

While

(the reader) continues looking at the


it

book, his belief in


reality possesses
is
'

as an external

= independent)
imme-

the highest validity possible.' This


is

the conclusion which

so certain and so

224

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


is

[part

if-

diate that scepticism

impotent to shake

it.

But
it,

surely

it

is

evident that scepticism might admit


for the admission.
'

and not be much the worse

If

the only belief which, having


possible,'

the highest validity


sceptic,
is

must be respected by the

the

belief in the objective existence of the second

volume
single

of Mr. Spencer's Psychology (or


object),

some other

and that only so long as the reader happens


it,

to

be looking at
is

it is

plain that the field of legiti-

mate doubt

not materially limited.

So

very

modest a contribution to the Cosmos postulated by Science, Is scarcely sufficient by itself to assure us
that Evolution
this objection,

may

not, after

all,

be 'a dream.'

On

however, which deals rather with the


its

nature of the external world than with


ence,
I

independ-

do not dwell.
second objection to Mr. Spencer's
is,

My

realistic

argument

that he assumes in

It

that the idealistic

conclusion can be reached only by either ignoring or doctoring (so to speak) the facts given in percep.*
'

tion

a misconception which

think has
external.

Its

root in

the ambiguous use of the

word
self,

In this

connection external

may mean
of)

external to

(=

inde-

pendent
ternal to
is

of) the

perceiving

or

it

may mean

exIt

(= outside

the perceiving organism.


first

using the term in the

of these senses, not in

the second, that the sceptic and idealist doubt and deny respectively the existence of an external world
;

but

if

we

are rigidly

to interpret

Mr.

Spencer's

CHAP.

XI.]

MR. SPENCER'S PROOF OF REALISM.

225

language, he seems to regard these two very different


positions as equivalent.

man

looking at a book, he says,

'

cannot con-

ceive that

where he

sees
it

and

feels the book there is

nothing!
Idealism,

Nor
that

is

necessary, in the interests


it.

of

he should conceive
feels the

Of

course
;

where he sees and

book there
idealist

is

something

there
this
that,

is

the book.

The

does not deny

on the one hand, nor does he assert on the other

when he does

not see and feel the book,

it is

not

there,,

in the sense of having vanished

from

that
I

portion of space.

No

idealist seriously maintains,

should imagine, that the universe consists of


space,

infinite

empty except
to
this,

for those things

which happen
if

each

moment

be perceived.
is

But

they do not

maintain

what

the use of asserting, as against

them, that

we

cannot conceive that where


is

we

see

and

feel

a book there
third
is,

nothing
to

My

objection
that

Mr. Spencers
of
refuting

realistic
'

argument

the

mode

meta-

physicians,' for

which

in this chapter

and elsewhere
Like the

he shows a marked
himself as
*

partiality, is as effective against

it

is
'

against his opponents.


school, he constantly

common
call

sense

assumes that

the unbiassed deliverance

of consciousness (as he

would
I

it),

the unsifted opinion of the vulgar (as


it),

should rather describe

carries

with

it

some
really

peculiar weight in the controversy.


*

But, unlike the

common

sense

'

school, the opinions

which he

226

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

holds respecting the external world require us to do


as

much

violence to our ordinary beliefs as any form


'

of what he calls

Anti- Realism.'

Throughout the

whole of the Negative Justification of Realism we are allowed to suppose that the errors of metaphysicians are
beliefs
it

aberrations
artificial

from true and natural


habits of analysis
;

produced by
till

and

we come to the Positive Justification of Realism that we discover how different are the
is

not

beliefs

which are true from those which are natural


being
truly

these last

ultimately described
constituting
life,'
*

contempt-

uously
*

if

as

'

a crude realism,'

the

realism of

common

the realism of the

child

and the

rustic'

A
when

striking

example of the

facility

with which

Mr. Spencer adopts the reasoning of Crude Realism


it

happens

to suit his convenience, occurs in

the chapter

we

are considering.

His object

for the

moment
I

is

to contrast in a certain particular (which

have elsewhere shown to be immaterial) the argu-

ments used by metaphysicians and the argument by


which Realism
this
is

established.
selects, as

For the purpose of


a specimen of meta-

comparison he

physical reasoning, the


realist; as

argument of the hypothetical


realistic

a specimen of
I

reasoning,

the

argument
the

quoted above.
*

It
'

would be easy
which
2

in the

interest of the
first
1

metaphysician

to take exception to

of these selections,
ii.

Mr.
jbj^j^ p^

Spencer
^^^^

Psychology, vol.

p. 497.

CHAP. XL]

MR. SPENCER'S PROOF OF REALISM.

227

justifies

on the strange ground that Hypothetical


is
*

Realism
of
all

the

comparatively unassuming parent


;

other Anti-Realistic doctrines


particularly to insist

but what

wish

more

on now

is

the impropriety

of his attempting to refute an argument, with whose


conclusion he substantially agrees,

by means of one
His

from whose conclusions he absolutely dissents.


opinion

we know

is

that ^

'

what we are conscious of

as properties of matter, even

down

to

weight and

resistance, are but subjective affections

produced

in

us by objective agencies which are

unknown and unby no means the


indi-

knowable.'

This,

take
:

it

is

also the opinion of

the Hypothetical Realist

but

it is

opinion either of the ordinary


vidual

man, or of the

whom

Mr. Spencer represents as arriving

at a

realistic

conclusion by the simple process of looking


single object

at

some

say the
'

second volume of the

'Psychology'

with
saw)
^

an unbiassed mind.
feels that the

This percontent of
as

sonage
his

(as

we

sole

consciousness

is

the

book considered
reality.'

an

external

(= independent)
is

And

the corre-

sponding belief
has
*

one,

we

are further informed, which

the highest
is,

validity possible.'

Now
*

the ex-

ternal reality

and

unknowable' 'a
told,^

according to Mr. Spencer,

mode
all

of being,'
'

unknown as we are

elsewhere

represented to us by

an indefinable

consciousness.'

Putting

these statements to^


"

Psychology, p. 441.
Ibid. p. 437.

Ibid. p. 493. Ibid. p. 452.

228

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT, we

[part.

ii.

gether,

arrive at the conclusion that the individual


Is

looking at Mr. Spencer's book

unconscious of any

of the properties of matter, and has, as the sole content of his consciousness, an Indefinable conscious-

ness standing for an

unknown and unknowable mode


!

of being beyond consciousness

This
result
;

Is

not a very
It Is

satisfactory

or Instructive

but

one of a kind which can scarcely be

avoided by any thinker

who
is

tries to

use our ordinary


sceptic,

and natural

beliefs as

weapons against the

at the very time

when he
all

attempting to establish

a theory against which


beliefs rebel.

our ordinary and natural


the effort to upset the

To my mind

results of critical analysis

(whatever these
is

may

be)

by an appeal to uncritical opinion


in the case of the sceptical

as reasonable

view of the external


Copernican

world as

it

would be

in the case of the

theory of the Solar System, and not nearly so reasonable as of Will.


it

would be

in the case of the


this
if it

Freedom
all It

But however

may
is

be,

whether the

method be good or bad,


be applied
impartially.
It

applied

must
reject

It will

not do

to

Idealism because

is

in opposition to natural con-

victions of mankind, unless

you are prepared

to say

that you think the natural convictions of

mankind
pre-

are sound

and you cannot think that the natural

convictions of

mankind are sound unless you are


in themselves,

pared to endorse opinions which are not only unfitted to sustain criticism

but which

CHAP.

XI.]

MR. SPENCER'S PROOF OF REALISM.


If

229

would render Physical Science an absurdity.


instinctive

our

judgments are

sufficient to

prove that an

independent object

exists,

they

are sufficient to

prove that
particular

it

is

coloured,

extended,

and with a
texture.
If

weight, configuration,

and

physical science

and introspective analysis are


that colour
are, as

to

be

believed

when they show

and the prosays,

perties of matter

Mr. Spencer

'sub-

jective affections,' they


instinctive

deprive the appeal to our


all

judgments of

the weight

it

might

otherwise possess.^
* An objection substantially the same as that given in the text has been urged by Mr. H. Sidgwick in the Academy^ and Mr. Spencer has replied to it in an article afterwards re-published in the third volume of his Essays.^ His reply, which he does not, I think, seem to be quite pleased with himself, need not detain us long. It turns essentially on a distinction between the Primordial Judgment, as he calls it,^ of Crude Realism, which informs us that an object exists, and the ^M^r Judgments of Crude Realism which (as he cannot deny) tell us that it is coloured, and so forth. The first we are to believe in, whatever arguments may be brought against it, but not the second. Now on what is this distinction founded He does not formally tell us, but he gives us to understand, by his examples, that it is founded on the fact, that the judgments of the second class are, while the 'Primordial' judgment of the first class is not, capable of an 'interpretation which equally
.''

well corresponds with direct intuition, while


culties.' ^
I

it

avoids

all

the

diffi-

myself with stating one of the objections to which this doctrine seems open which, if it remains unanswered, will, however, be sufficient. Mr. Spencer admits that, according to the immediate deliverance .of Crude Realism, the external reality has the properties of matter ; but we know that according to him the properties of matter, even down to weight and resistance, are but subjective affections.' * Crude Realism is, therefore, wrong but though wrong, it arrives at its
will content
:

'

Psychology,
Ibid. p. 284.

vol.

ii.

p.

282-286.

"^

Ibid. p. 286.
Ibid. p. 493.

i30

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


I

[part

il.

have now said

not

indeed

all

that might be

said,

but all

that need

be said

in

answer to the

negative justification

of Realism.

With Chapter

XIV. begins
case.

the Positive Justification, which extends

through four chapters, and completes Mr. Spencer's

This part of his argument need

not,

however,

opinion by a single step. Mr. Spencer shows that it is wrong by a process of ' interpretation,' which is nothing else than an explanation of the usual physical theories of the origin of sensation,^ and which is
to

and complicated argument. How is this be reconciled with that theory according to which results are trustworthy according as they are arrived at by the shortest trains of
therefore an extremely long

reasoning
truth
is,

What becomes

of

'

the test of relative validity


^

'

?
'

The
and
think

that Mr. Spencer's distinction between the


is

Primordial
I

the other Judgments of Crude Realism

perfectly arbitrary, as

he

will

himself see,

if

he

tries to

show reason

for restoring the follow-

ing doctored quotation from the

of his * General have added, or substituted, are put in italics. The reader looking at a book finds that he is conscious of the book as a coloured extended object apart from himself. Does there enter into his consciousness any notion about sensation ? No Does he perceive that the thing he is conscious of is an image of the book 1 Not at all So long as he refuses to translate facts into any hypothesis, he feels simply conscious of coloured and extended object^ and not of an impression of a coloured and extended object. .... He feels that this recognition of the book as an external coloured and extended reality is a single indivisible act And, lastly, he feels that do what he will, he cannot reverse this act. .... Hence, while he continues looking at the book, his belief in it

XHIth Chapter
I

Analysis

'

to its original form.

The words

'

and extended reality possesses the highest possible has the direct guarantee of the Universal Postulate and it assumes the Universal Postulate only once.' This argument is not, as I have shown, a particularly good one but it is quite as good when devoted to proving that colour and extension (which are both, on Mr. Spencer's theory, subjective affections) are objective realities, as it is when used, as Mr. Spencer uses it, to prove that an object with (I presume) no knowable qualities, has an independent existence.
as a coloured
It

validity.

See Essays,

vol.

iii.

p. 286.

CHAP, xi.j

MR. SPENCER'S PROOF OF REALISM.


It consists in

251

detain us long.

the main of a psycho-

logical theory of the

manner
;

in

which we obtain our

ideas of Subject and Object

and a single quotation


sufficient to

from the summary^


general character.
vation
*

will

be

show

its

Simply by a process of obserour states of consciousness

we

find,

that

segregate

into

two independent aggregates, each

held together by
it.

some

principle of continuity within

The

principle of continuity forming into a

whole

the faint states of

consciousness,

moulding
is
is

and
dis-

modifying them by some unknown energy,


tinguished as the

Ego

while the Non-ego

the

principle of continuity holding together

the indefind

pendent aggregate of vivid


that while our

states.

And we

states of consciousness cohere into

these antithetical aggregates, the experiences gained

by mutual exploration of the


cohesion, that to the

limbs, establish such

principle of continuity mani-

fested in the non-ego there inevitably clings a nascent

consciousness of force, akin to the force evolved by


the principle of continuity in the ego!

There are

difficulties in

this conclusion, as, for

instance, the absence of

any reason which should

make

us identify ourselves with one of these prin'

ciples of

continuity
is

'

rather than with the others

and there

also

much
p. 487.

material for criticism in the


is

process by which the conclusion


1

arrived

at.'^

But,

Psychology, vol.
Cf. Articles

ii.

by Professor Green, Contefuporary Reviewy Dec.

1877,

March

1878.

^32

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


whole of
this

[part

ii.

in truth, the

Psychology, be

it

good or
that the
if

be

it

bad,

is

irrelevant,

and irrelevant on Mr. Spencer's


that he tells us
'

own
*

principles.

It is true
'

absolute validity
it

of Realism

will

be shown

we

find

to

be a necessary product of thought proceed-

ing according to laws that are universal,'

by which

he means,
in

suppose, that our warrant for believing


the fact that a belief in
it is

Realism

is

universally

produced by the natural operation of psychological


laws.

But

this,

which

is

merely an instance of the

persistent error

which makes Philosophy dependent


not, as
I

on Psychology, does
sent Mr. Spencer's
real
fact

understand

it,

repre-

more

deliberate opinion.
'

The
'

warrant on which he believes the


that
is

mysterious

'we have a consciousness of something


is

which
to

out of consciousness,'
it
:

that he

is

obliged

think

and the three succeeding chapters


are deit,

therefore

of psychological analysis which

voted

not to showing but showing how


to

that he ought to think


it

comes about that he

is

obliged to think

it

discuss a question
With regard
last chapter,
It
is

which even

from

his

own
is

point of view can have no philosophic


to the

interest whatever.
itself, it

'warrant'
at

the

same as that which was discussed


it

some length

in the

and no more need


'

be said about
of the negation

here.
in

the

inconceivability

W
A

'

a scarcely altered form.


point that
2

There

is

only one more


ii.

feel

in/

Psychology^ vol.

p. 445.

ibid. p. 452.

CHAP.

XI.]

MR. SPENCER'S PROOF OF REALISM.

233

clined to touch

on before we reach the


It is

final

stage of

the discussion.

a favourite practice with Mr.

Spencer, whenever he happens to disbelieve a proposition, to

inform those

who

do believe
It

it

that

it

'

can-

not be realised in thought.'


to
'

would be interesting
in

know how
'

far

he can
*

realise

thought the

mysterious
is
it

fact

of

a consciousness of something
?
'

which
people
it,

yet out of consciousness

To
:

ordinary

might be open

to say

that they believed


it

though they could not

realise

but no such

reply

seems possible

to

Mr. Spencer.

He

is

of

opinion that

we

cannot really believe a proposition

which we cannot think, and that we cannot think


a proposition unless the subject and predicate are
realised in thought.^

Now

mode
which

of being sepain

rate

from myself produces changes


is

my
I

conscious

states,'

one proposition
'

in

understand
it

him

to believe.

This mode of being, since he can believe the


subject

is

unknown and unknowable, cannot be


thought,'
is

realised

in

another.

If
its

first

proposition

without

being realised in

thought, his general theory of knowledge, and most


of the positive positions contained in the First Principles^
it

must be abandoned.
says he does believe
it is

If

he cannot believe

except on those terms, then either he


it,

when he
thought.
1

or he

is

wrong wrong when


is

he supposes that

incapable of being realised in


to

He

would seem
vol.
ii.

be

in the
2

unfortunate
^jj^ jj

Psychologyy

p. 445.

j^j^j

234

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

position of having devised a theory of

knowledge

in

the main for the purpose of establishing a realistic

system, and of having devised a realistic system

which

is

incompatible with his theory of knowledge.


is

That he

not unaware of the difficulties which

surround a theory according to which

we know

the

Unknowable,
successfully,
ciples}

admit

for

he struggles, not very


in his

to get over

them

First Prin-

by the help of such metaphorical expressions


consciousness
'

as

'

nascent

and
is

'

raw material of
holding these

thought.'

My

complaint
it

that,

opinions, he considers
to

a sufficient answer to
its

make
terms
to-

any

belief of
'

which he disapproves that


*

cannot be

realised in thought,' or
'
;

be joined

gether in consciousness

though neither Theology


I

nor Metaphysics contain, so far as


proposition of which these things can

know, any
truly

more
us

be

said than the propositions respecting the external

world,
*

which

Mr.

Spencer assures

have the

highest validity possible.'

We
last,

now come,
more
is.

in

chapter the nineteenth and

to a

precise account of

what
is

this external

world really

As

the reader
in the
;

already aware,
that
it

Mr. Spencer holds,

first

place,
in

is

unknown and
to

unknowable

and,

the

second

place, notwithstanding

some statements which seem


it

assume that

it

does not vary at alP that


relation

varies in
1

some determinate
Cf. especially, ch. iv.

to the
ii.

known

Cf. ch.

483.

CHAP.

XI.]

MR. SPENCER'S PROOF OF REALISM.

235

and knowable.
diately

The
itself

question,

therefore,
to

immehave

suggests
Mill^

how

we come
calls this

what Mr.

somewhere

prodigious

amount of knowledge respecting the Unknowable ? Grant what Mr. Spencer asks and admit that a

belief in the reality of an

independent Universe
for

is
it

valid
is

what grounds
?

have we

supposing that

precisely the kind of universe he postulates

and

no other
vary at

Why

should
?

it

vary

in

a determinate
it

relation to

phenomena

Why,
will
I

indeed, should

all ?

Perhaps Mr. Spencer


(though on what grounds

be inclined to say
that, as

do not know)

the cause of varying effects, the object must itself


vary.

But from the preceding chapter^


Conception
of
is

on the

Developed

the the
*

Object,

we have

learned that the object


tinuity,'

principle of con-

binding together the 'aggregate of our vivid

states of consciousness.'
is,
I

principle of continuity

should have thought, the unvarying element


If
it

in

the midst of incessant variations.

varies

itself,

must
'

it

not require another principle of conit,'

tinuity

to

form

as Mr. Spencer says,^


if

'

into a

whole

'

Furthermore,
?

the object varies,

does
re-

the subject vary


lation

Mr. Spencer represents the


illustration of

between the two by a diagram, which he


it.

seems to think affords a complete


It

consists of a cube (standing for the Object), a


*

Cf.

e.

g. p. 487.

Psychology, vol.

ii.

487.

236

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


and a

[part

ii.

cylinder (standing for the Subject),

reflection

of the cube on the surface of the cylinder (repre-

senting our 'vivid state of consciousness').


case the cube
cylinder
varies, the reflection

In this

varies, but the

does not vary.


in this

Are we

to
?

regard the
If so,
it

parallel as

particular

accurate

would be interesting to know on what grounds Mr.


Spencer asserts change
*

in

one of the unknown

Principles

of

Continuity,'

and denies

it

in

the

other.

Again, there seems some difliculty in understanding

how

that which

is

neither in

Space nor

Time can be
effects

a cause varying with the Phenomenal


in

which are
it,

Space and Time.


it,

Time
(it is

as

we

know
in

and Space as we know

are

stated

the First Principles^)

conceptions produced in
Since, there-

us

by some mode of the Unknowable.

fore,
is

we

are not to imagine that the


it

Unknowable

in

Time,

does not seem easy to understand


it

how

we

can imagine

as capable of

change

change
in rela-

having no meaning whatever for


tion to

us,

except

Time.

This criticism suggests the further reflection that


Mr. Spencer's Unknowable
is,

after

all,

not identical

with the subject-matter of physical science.


us take, for illustration,
position
;

Let
seven
a

some simple

scientific pro-

e.g.,

particles of matter vibrating

hundred

billions of times
*

a second produce
165.

in us

Page

CHAP.

XI.]

MR. SPENCER'S PROOF OF REALISM.


it

237

sensation of violet,' and consider


tion.

in this

connecas

The
it.

particles
it

of matter thus described

causes must,
or out of
in
it,

is

plain,
it is

be either

in

consciousness

And

also plain that they are not

except in the shape of symbolical concepts


calls
;

belonging to what Mr. Spencer


gregate of our conscious states
'

the

faint ag-

in

which condition

they cannot either be permanent or produce changes


in

the vivid aggregate of the kind required.

As

causes of sensation, they must therefore exist out of


consciousness
either be
;

whence
of

it is

evident that they must

modes

the unknowable, or else that

something besides the unknowable must exist be-

yond consciousness.
first

If

Mr. Spencer accepts the


I

of these alternatives,

desire to

know why he

chooses to describe that which exists beyond consciousness as the unknowable, seeing that most of

the knowledge which


to it;
if

we

possess professes to refer


I

he accepts the second,

desire to

know

what proof he can supply of the existence of such a knowable beyond consciousness at all.

To put the same What Science requires

difficulty

in

another form.
is

to

have proved

the exis-

tence of matter, which shall be independent of perception and sensation, shall produce perception and
sensation,
solidity,

and

shall

at the

same time possess mass,


forth.

extension,

and so
?

Is this

matter

Mr. Spencer's unknowable


In the
first

We

must answer. No.


it

place because, according to Science,

238

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


;

[part

ii.

is

decidedly knowable

in the

second place, because


is

Mr.
*

Spencer

tells

us^ that the matter which


'

extended and resistent

is

related to the
it,

unknow?

able as effect to cause.

Is

then, the
;

knowable

Again,
to

we must
*

answer.
'

No

because,
'

according

Mr. Spencer, the

objective agencies
'

which pro-

duce our
*

subjective affections

are in themselves

unknown and unknowable.'


Mr. Spencer's elaborate argument
is,

therefore,
I

altogether beside the mark.

In proving

or,

should

rather say, in attempting to prove, the existence of

the unknowable, he has aimed at the

wrong

object.

The

true state of the case


is

is

that the external world

required by Science

very much more like that


^

contemplated in the Crude Realism

(as

he con'

temptuously
it is

calls it)

of the child or the rustic


*

than

like that

propounded by the Transfigural Rea-

lism affected
fore, that the

by himself

Even

admitting,

there-

arguments establishing the

latter are

as unanswerable as he supposes

them

to

be, our

philosophic position would not be

much improved.
world
hardly save us

If the scientific creed respecting the external

be rejected, the unknowable from scepticism


cepted, the
;

will

while,

if

the scientific creed be acis

unknowable

foredoomed to the same


according
itself.'

existence of otium
to Jacobi,
If
^

cum

dignitate, which,
*

is

enjoyed by Kant's

thing in

rightly understand the line of thought taken


'^

First Principles^ pp. i66, 167.

Psychology^ vol.

ii.

p. 452.

CHAP.

XI.]

MR. SPENCER'S PROOF OF REALISM.

239

up

in

the First Principles^ Mr. Spencer would reply-

to this

by saying that matter as known by Science, may be regarded


it

to us,

and as

dealt with

as

permanent

and independent because


knowable cause which
effects of the
is

is

the effect of the un-

permanent and independent.

But, according to Mr. Spencer's doctrines, the only

unknowable of which we have imme'

diate

knowledge consist of

subjective affections,'

which are neither permanent nor independent. These


are not the subject-matter of physical science.

When

a Physicist asserts that vibrating molecules produce


the sensation of violet light, he

means

that certain

material particles which are not, which never have


been,

and which never will

be in

(human) conscious-

ness,

and which would vibrate precisely as they are

doing

now

if

(human) consciousness was destroyed,

produce certain conscious phenomena.

What Mr.
is

Spencer must think that they ought to mean by the


assertion
is,

that a

mode

of the unknowable which


I

symbolised (and, so far as


symbolised) by the
of our conscious

can

see, quite arbitrarily


'

member of the state known as


'

faint

aggregate

the concept of a
of

vibrating particle,
'

is

the

producing cause
'

member

of the vivid aggregate

known as

the sensa-

tion of violet light.

No verbal contrivance

can bridge

over the discrepancy between two statements, one


of which says that the cause of a

phenomenon

is
it

a
is

vibrating material particle, and the other that


^

First Principles^"^^1^^,

240

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

ii.

an entity possessing none of the attributes of matter, and which, since it is neither in space nor time, must be incapable of vibration.

These are propositions


and not merely the

which assert

different things,

same thing
even
if

in different

language, so that Mr. Spencer,

he had proved the truth of the second, would


required by current scientific doctrines.
final

have done nothing towards establishing a realism


such as
*

is

The

remark

to

be made/ says Mr. Spencer,^

is

that Anti- Realistic beliefs

have never been held


Nor,
venture to

at all

Berkeley was not an Idealist


Kantist'
I

Nor was Kant a


add,
is

will

Mr. Spencer a Transfigured-Realist.

With-

out doubt the natural beliefs which in his ordinary

moments hold a not


rustic,*

less

undisputed sway over the


*

philosopher than they do over the


will

child

or the

be as victorious against Mr. Spencer's

doctrines as they are against those of

any of the

metaphysicians
selves in the
*

whom

he accuses of losing them-

mazes of verbal propositions.'^


is

On

the whole, indeed, he

less

fortunate than they.

For

it is

his singular

ill

fortune to have failed with

entire completeness in all the objects

which a man

may propose

to himself in constructing a theory of

the external world.

Some may wish


some

to justify the
justify

common

sense of

mankind, some to

the

teachings of Science,

to prove the being of

a God, some to give free rein to speculation without any secondary object.
*

It

was reserved

for

Psycholo^y^ voU

ii.

p. 300.

Ibid.

CHAP. XL]

MR. SPENCER'S PROOF OF REALISM.


to elaborate

241

Mr. Spencer
of science
satisfy the

a theory which can pre-

tend to justify the assumption neither of the

man

nor of the theologian, and which will

requirements neither of the ordinary

man

nor of the philosopher.

Looking back over the nineteen chapters we have been considering, and over the earlier half of
the First Principles,
it

is

impossible not to regret


'

that the ambition to produce a

System of

Phi-

losophy

'

should have forced our author into paths

where

his

remarkable powers of mind show to com-

paratively small advantage.

Could he have been


'

content with giving to the world

Suggestions

to-

wards a theory of the Universe on the basis of the


ordinary scientific postulates,' his astonishing faculty
for collecting

from every department of knowledge


tell in

the facts which seem to

his favour

would have
sensi-

had

free scope, while his

somewhat blunted

bility in

the matter of difficulties and contradictions

might have been of actual advantage. In trespassing


on metaphysical ground, the virtues which he possesses as a thinker

his extraordinary

range of

in-

formation and his ingenuity in framing original and


suggestive hypotheses
less,

become

comparatively use-

while the robust faith in his method and results


is

by which he
be
ifi

animated, necessary as

admit

it

to

order that he

may be
is

sustained through his

protracted labours

from a speculative point of

view an almost unmixed evil


R

242

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

hi.

PART III. CHAPTER XII.


SCIENCE AS A LOGICAL SYSTEM.

The
we

reader will recollect that the only quality of obfirst

jects for the existence of which in the

instance

required proof was their persistence.

In point

of fact no philosopher has set himself to prove this

without at the same time attempting to prove

much

more, and as a necessary

result,

the foregoing exami-

nation of realistic systems has contained allusions,

more or
It is

less frequent, to other

and equally
*

essential

attributes of

what

is

called

the external world.'

now time

to desert the philosophers,


'

and to
it is

say a few words about this


dealt with

external world,' as

by Science
far

not
is

for the

purpose of deter-

mining how

Science

justified in

assuming

its

reality, for this

question has been already discussed,

but

in

order to obtain

some

idea of the general

character of the existing scientific system regarded


as a logical whole.

Granting, then, the reality of an external world,


let

us ask, in the

first

place,

what

is

its
?

real nature

according to modern scientific teaching

CHAP.

XII.]

SCIENCE AS A LOGICAL SYSTEM.


it

243

Speaking generally,

consists,

we

are told, of

atoms possessing mass, chemical


qualities
;

affinity,

and other
called

and of a universally diffused medium,

ether, which,

by means of

certain very singular pro-

perties, transmits

through space certain vibrations by


affected.
in

which these atoms are

Associated together by various laws

various

groups, these atoms constitute the solid, liquid, and

gaseous bodies scattered through space


the infinite

from among
to each

number

of which there

is

man

assigned one of especial importance to himself;

mean

his

own

organism.

The very

interesting class

of objects to which these belong, do not differ from


the rest of the material universe in the nature of
their ultimate composition.

In

many

other most im-

portant respects no doubt they do


peculiarity about

differ,

But the

them with which


is

at this

moment

we

are specially concerned

the

fact,

that they are

the immediate channels of communication between


the world
I

have just described, and the thinking


their

beings

who by
its

means are made acquainted


and
in-

directly with the appearance of that world,


directly with

true nature

and

constitution.

Before going further in the consideration of the


general system of Science,
the reader
it

may be as well

to

remind
is

how

unlike the world just described

to

the world which

we

actually perceive, or can repreI

sent by an effort of the imagination.

do not of

course

mean

to say that the

world of perception and

244

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

hi.

the world of science are numerically distinct.


Is

This

evidently not so.

When

astronomers talk of the


;

when chemists talk of elementary substances, they mean things we can touch and handle. But when they go on to
tell

moon, they mean the moon we see

us about the Intimate structure of these bodies

they are soon compelled to use words which have


only a symbolic meaning, and to refer to objects

which

(It

may

be) can be thoicght, but which cer-

tainly cannot In their real nature

be either perceived

or Imagined.

That knowledge or what passes


soon gets
In this

for

knowledge

way beyond

the data of perception


Is

and the powers of Imagination,


to the surface

a fact which comes

more prominently
I

In

Theology perhaps
Is

than In Science.
there
Is

am

not aware that this

because

these

between two great departments of knowledge. It


essential philosophic difference

any

arises rather

from the

fact that, for controversial pur-

poses.

It

has been found convenient to dwell on the


Is

circumstance that our idea of the Deity

to a certain

extent necessarily anthropomorphic, while the no less


certain,
If

somewhat

less obvious, truth that


is

our idea

of the external world

also anthropomorphic, does

not supply any ready argumentative weapon.

There
other.

are,

however, further reasons

why

this side

of the case has not received so

much

attention as the

One

of

them

is,

think,

that

any person

speculating on this subject

is

apt to slide

away from

CHAP.

XII.]

SCIENCE AS A LOGICAL SYSTEM.

245

it

into the allied but altogether distinct questions

concerning Realism and Idealism.

These are prob-

lems, however, the solution of which has no direct

bearing upon the subject

we

are

now

discussing.

Whether Realism or Idealism either of them or both of them

be

true,

whether

are consistent with

Science, this broad fact remains, that the world as

represented to us by Science can no more be perceived or imagined than the Deity as represented to
us by Theology, and that in the
second,
first

case, as in the

we must

content ourselves with symbolical

images, of which the thing


is

we can most

certainly say

that they are not only inadequate but incorrect.

This
on

is

not an assertion which in reality requires


to support
it.

much argument

Its truth is

apparent

simple inspection,

and

it

applies equally to the

two main constituents of the external world


Matter as well as to Force,

to
in
it it

To
Science

begin with the


is

latter.
all

Force according to
its

the cause of
is

motion, and

amount

any case

measured by the amount of motion


in

produces or can produce


is

a given time.

Now,
see

evident that

we come most
to

closely into contact

(so to speak) with Force, either

when we

one

body foreign

ourselves

exercising

force

upon

another, as for example, a locomotive engine pulling

a coal waggon, or when

we feel

pressure between our

bodies and some foreign substance

that,

for

ex-

ample, produced by a tight boot

(this

pressure not

246

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part hi.

being the result of energy supplied by our bodies), or

when we

exercise effort so as to produce pressure


for

between our bodies and some foreign substance,


example, by raising a weight
result of
;

which pressure
If

is

the

energy supplied by our bodies.

we

can-

not perceive force in one at least of these cases,


cannot,
I

apprehend, perceive
it

it

at all

and

if

we we

cannot perceive

at

all, it
it

will

probably be admitted

that our ideas respecting

must be purely anthropo-

morphic, and only symbolical of the reality.

Without wearying the reader by examining these


three cases in detail,
it

may be assumed,
that, as a

imagine,
fact,

without further discussion our idea of force


is

matter of

derived in the last resort entirely


:

from the second and third

so that

either felt pressure or exercised

we had never muscular effort, we


if

should be altogether unable to frame

mental

image which should

in

any way correspond with the

subject-matter of dynamics.

Does the idea


?
it

so de-

rived correspond with the reality

The common
only symbolises
it

opinion seems to be that, though

the force which acts between inanimate bodies,


resembles the force which
living organisms.
is

exerted by, or acts on,

But this, I apprehend, is incorrect. There can be no resemblance between the mental images, whether of pressure or of effort, and that
external and independent force which they are

em-

ployed to represent.

Why

should the feeling (said

to be) of pressure be like the pressure

which pro-

CHAP.

XII.]

SCIENCE AS A LOGICAL SYSTEM.


It is

247

duces

It ?

not force,

it is
:

one of the
it

effects of

force acting

on our organism

does not even vary


it,

directly with the force

which produces

but de-

pends on the part of the body affected and on other


circumstances.
effort,

Neither
it is

is

the feeHng of muscular

Force

rather one of the mental accomis

paniments of muscular action when that action

set

going by the Will.

do not even see how


:

it

can be

accurately called a cause of Force


into this

but without going

question, which

is

not material to
it

my

argu-

ment,

it

seems certain that whether


it

be cause or be
dis-

merely accompaniment,
tinct

must

at all events

from that which


then

it

causes or accompanies.
in

If

we

try

and represent to ourselves


is

imagination the reality which


assertion,
'

expressed by this

the inkstand presses on the table with a


is

force of
if

two pounds,' our idea of what


such an idea at
false for
all,

taking place,

we form

will in all probability

be entirely
first place,

two separate reasons.

In the

we

shall introduce notions of pressure

and

muscular

effort,

which have no imaginable meaning

for us, except as affections of a living organism, into

the relation which exists between portions of inani-

mate matter
force,
or,

and secondly, we

shall deal with feelif

ings of pressure and muscular effort as


at all events,

they were

resembled

force, instead of

being only

now and

then related to force, as causes,

as effects, or as accompaniments.
If

now from Force we

turn to Matter,

we

find

248

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


similar limits fixed to our

[part

hi.

somewhat
nation.

powers of imagiformwhile

It is true that

we

find

no

difificulty in
;

ing an idea of matter as matter appears to us


in the case of force, since
it

never appears to

us,

we

cannot even do this much.

But

if,

instead of framing

an idea of matter as we perceive


an idea of
it

it^

we

try to
it

frame
is,

as Science assures us that

really

we soon become
an impossibility.
kinds or degrees.

conscious that

we

are attempting

Of this
In

impossibility there are


cases, for

two

some

example,

we

may be
because

convinced that Matter has certain

qualities,

we observe

effects

which require an hypo-

thesis of this kind in order to account for them.

But

as to

what these

qualities

may

be, apart

from their

we not only cannot imagine, but we do not even know how to try and imagine. We have nothing to go upon. Our senses and our reason alike fail us and it would be more accurate perhaps to say that we
effects,
;

have no ideas corresponding to them at

all

than to

say that our ideas of them are anthropomorphic.

What,

for

example,

is

chemical affinity

What

is

the real nature of the change which takes place in a

copper wire when an


it ?

electric current passes


'^,

along

What

is

magnetism

Science has at present


:

no certain answer to give to these questions


the
true

but

there are other questions respecting matter to which

answers are known with a considerable


scientific probability,

degree of

though at the same

time they carry us not the less into regions where

CHAP.

XII.]

SCIENCE AS A LOGICAL SYSTEM.


is

249

the imagination

unable to follow them.


to

For exdoubt on

ample,

we

are required

believe (no

excellent grounds) that the


light
is

sensation of coloured

produced by material particles vibrating with

a certain rapidity, and that the varieties of colour are


the result of differences in the rapidity and combinations of these vibrations
It is

when they reach

the eye.

a necessary consequence of this doctrine, that

the vibi'ating particles must themselves be regarded


as having no colour
effect
:

their colour being

merely the

produced on our particular organism by their

rapid periodic motion acting through space by


of the diffused ether.
sufficient to

means
is

But the smallest

trial

convince us that to represent in imagiis

nation uncoloured vibrating atoms

a task

alto-

gether beyond our powers.


or
'

The

other senses, touch

the muscular sense,' through which

we

acquire a

knowledge of material

objects, are altogether incapa-

ble of supplying the elements necessary for such a

purpose, at least they are so with

me and
;

it is

of

course impossible to bring in the sense of sight to


their assistance without at the

same time representing

as coloured the things

we

are attempting to imagine.

There
heat.

is

no similar
les's

difficulty in the parallel case of

Heat, no

than

light, exists in

the material

world as a mode of motion.

Yet

it is

easy to sepa-

rate in idea the vibrating particles

from the sensation

of warmth, and to consider one as the cause of the


other.

We

are not compelled, as in the case

of

2SO

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


by the laws of imagination,
with the cause before
all.

[part hi.

light,

to

confonnd the

effect

we

can picture to our-

selves the cause of

This particular weakness or defect


of representation affects,
it

in

our power

will

be observed, our

ideas of the whole material universe.

There

is

not

a single particle of Matter which


ceive or picture to ourselves as
as a similar assertion can, as
I

we

can either per:

it

really exists

and

have shown, be made

about Force

and as

it

can be

made with

still

more

obvious truth about the more occult kinds or properties

of external objects (ether, magnetism, and so


I

forth),

think

may
I

consider the thesis which in

this

long digression

set out to prove, as sufficiently

established.

Let us now return to the proper subject of the


present chapter, namely. Science considered in
its

most general aspect as a Logical System.


real nature of the external
I

We

have
the

seen what, according to scientific teaching,

is

world

(as for

convenience
it

here
it

call

it)

and we have seen that as

really
It is

is,

can neither be perceived nor imagined.


this,

easy to conclude from

what indeed

is

patent to

everybody, that
its real

we arrive

at our actual

knowledge of
minute

nature, not immediately, but

by a process of

inference.
particles
;

That material objects


that colour
;

consist of

is

the effect of the vibration of

these particles
as through

that these vibrations are transmitted


elastic

an

and imponderable medium

CHAP.

XII.]

SCIENCE AS A LOGICAL SYSTEM.


world
is

251

that, in short, the

what

it is,

are truths which,

far

from being

intuitive,

must be considered as the


latest triumphs, of

most refined deductions, as the


scientific investigation.

What, then, are these deductions founded on

Men
point,

of science,

who

should be authorities on this

inform us that they are founded on facts


;

obtained by direct observation

and that the

facts

obtained by direct observation consist of what

we
of

can

perceive

of

the

qualities

and

behaviour

objects

whose

persistence, for the sake of argument,


to assume.
is

we are agreed
of
it

In othet words, our settled

view of the universe


hmnediately
is its
;

inferred from

what we know
it

and what we know of

imme-

diately

appearance.

Now
ing
is,

the singular thing about this sort of reason-

that unless the premises be true, there

seems

no particular ground
while
if

for accepting the conclusion


it is

the conclusion be accepted,

evident that

the premises cannot be entirely true.

Unless apbelieve
trust to

pearances are to be trusted,


in

Science

If
?

Science

is

why should we true, how can we

appearances

From the scientific point of view it may possibly be


replied, that our

immediate knowledge of the external

world

is in

part to be trusted

but only

in part.

We
;

know by direct

observation

and know truly^-of the


moving bodies
scientific inference, that

existence of extended, resisting, and

and we know, by a process of

252

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


forth,

[part iil

the qualities of colour and so

which these

extended, resisting,
possess,

and moving bodies appear to

are really the subjective effects of the inter-

action

between them and our organism.

So

that

may be said to provide us with by which we may distinguish between


Science

a criterion
that which
to be,

both seems to be and


but
is Hot.

is,

and that which seems

Now
pearance,
itself,

that

we do

in practice so

use Science to

enable us to distinguish between


is

reality

and ap-

undoubtedly the

fact.

But taken by

this

circumstance affords no real solution of

the difficulty, because the very thing


particularly to

we want more

know is, how we can thus legitimately erect Science into a judge of its own cause. The precise question which has to be answered,
and the
Insufficiency
it,

of

this,

the

first

and most
to

natural answer to

will

become obvious

anyone

who
line

reflects

on the following

series of propositions,

which extend and define the argument, whose outI

have just Indicated


Scientific

1st.

knowledge which

Is

not

imme-

diate

Is

derived by Inference from the Immediate

knowledge furnished by observations of the external


world.

(This

apprehend

Is

the view ordinarily

taken by

men

of science.)

2nd. Observations of the external world assure

us

(If

they assure us of anything) that bodies exist


resisting,

which are coloured, extended,

and so

forth.

CHAP.

XII.]

SCIENCE AS A LOGICAL SYSTEM.

253

3rd.

The

assurance
are

we

obtain by pure observais

tion that bodies

coloured,

of precisely the

same kind as is the assurance we obtain from the same source, that they are extended and resisting.
(That
this Is so

cannot of course be proved, but


reflection.)

will

be evident to everybody on
4th.

While

pure

observation

shows

this,

in-

ferences professing to be derived In the main from

pure observation show us that bodies are not coloured,


but that the appearance of colour
is

produced by

motions or other changes

In the

uncoloured particles

composing the object perceived and the organism of


the percipient.
true,

(This must be admitted

if

Science

Is

and

If It Is

derived from observation.)


this
it

5th.

From

follows that
in

some of the imis

mediate knowledge given


worthy.
6th.

observation

untrust-

According

to

(4)

there

is

nothing

In

the

observations themselves to suggest any principle of


distinction
are,

between those which, according


not, trustworthy.

to Science

and those which are


7."

Neither

Is it

possible that such a principle of


it is

distinction should

be furnished by Science, since

only

if

the principle of distinction


Is

be sound that

Science

logically justified.

It is

not admissible to

make Science depend on the principle (whatever it may be), at the same time that we make the principle
depend upon Science.
Stated in this form, the exact nature of the
diffi-

254

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


I

[part hi.

culty
is

wish to point out becomes evident


that forces itself readily
it

and

if it

not one
is

on the

attention,

this

because

does not attach to the received

theory of the causal origin of our knowledge of the


material

world (which

is

the one

that

habitually

regulates our thoughts), but only to the theory of the

from empirical data, which is not a subject with which we are usually much concerned. Let me explain. When we are occupied with the consideration of how we come to possess the knowledge we have of the external world, if we are in a scientific rather than in a metaphysical humour, we immediately and naturally look at the
logical deduction

of

scientific doctrine

question from the poipt of view of the physiology of


perception
;

and the physiology of perception,


this

in its

most general form, teaches us


diate

that the immeis

antecedent to an act of perception

some
;

definite

change
if

in the

organism of the percipient


it

and that
to
will

this

change occurs, no matter how

is

originated, the particular perception corresponding


it

occur likewise.

Now

the

same kind of

change may
causes.
If

at different times

have

different sets of

on any given occasion one of the proxithe thing perceived, then percepIf,

mate causes of the physiological change producing


the perception
tion
is

is

said to be normal.
is

on the other hand, the

thing perceived

not one of the proximate causes

of the physiological change, then


deceived by

we

are said to be

an

illusion

of the

senses.

Supposing, for

CHAP. XII.]

SCIENCE AS A LOGICAL SYSTEM.


I

255

example, that

see the

moon when
is

she

is

actually in

the field of view, and her rays are striking on


retina,

then the object seen


it,

one of the

my causes of my
to
if

seeing

and the immediate knowledge conveyed


of perception
I

me
(to

in that act

is

so far accurate.

But

take the opposite case),


that

see a ghost, then, on the

supposition

there

are

no such

things,

am

suffering under an optical delusion, since,

whatever

may be
results

the causes of the physiological change which


in

that

act of perception,

it

cannot at

all

events be the object perceived, which by hypothesis

has no existence.

This

is

the physiological theory of perception


its

looked at from
at

causal or physical side.


it

Looked

from

its

cognitive or mental side,


is,

suggests the

idea that there


verse>

on the one hand, a Material Uni;

and on the other a Mind


its

and that the Mind

obtains

information respecting the Material Uniit

verse by looking at
five senses,

through the medium of the


altogether excludes a
of what
it

a medium which
much
not

great deal, and distorts


pass.
I

allows to

am
In

here pretending to

criticise this

theory.

common
I

with most theories which give


it

an account of the origin of knowledge,


defect,

has a logical
in the

which
It

shall

attempt to explain

next
diffi-

chapter.

has

also,

no doubt, philosophical

culties peculiar to itself

But what

am

concerned

to

show here

is,

that so far from presenting

any

diffi-

culties in

the

way

of a belief according to which a

56

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


is

[part

hi.

distinction
is,

made between what appears and what


;

it

actually suggests such a belief


it is

and that therehabitually think

fore
in

not surprising that since

we
I

terms (so to speak) of this theory,


troubled by the discrepancy

we should be
to

little

have shown

exist
its

between the empirical premises of Science and


has been already pointed out that this dis-

received conclusions.
It

crepancy cannot be smoothed away by any principle supplied

by Science
But

itself,
it

except at the cost of

arguing
that the

in

circle.

may perhaps be thought

whole

scientific

doctrine of matter, and of

the methods by which the properties of matter be-

come known

to us,

may be

legitimately put forward


verification,

as a hypothesis,

and may be capable of

like other hypotheses,

by an appeal
objection
I

to experience

and that

in this

way the

have been urging

may be
Let

successfully evaded.

me

consider the subject for a

moment from
I

this point of view.

The

reasoning to which

object

asserts that the laws governing material

phenomena
that the

are inferred from the immediate knowledge of matter

given

in

perception, and at the

same time

laws so inferred show this knowledge to be in certain


particulars incorrect.

The

reasoning which

it

is

proposed to substitute for


least of the laws

this asserts that

some
in

at

governing material phenomena, and


those which
are included

more

especially

the

physiological theory of perception, are not inferred

from the knowledge given

in perception,

but are

CHAP.

XII.]

SCIENCE -AS A LOGICAL SYSTEM.

257

adopted as a hypothesis to account


such and such perceptions
exist,

for the fact, that

function which

they perform so successfully that they


cepted as to
truths.
all

may be

ac-

intents

and purposes demonstrated

This mode of establishing the laws of matter


identical in
its

is

general scope with that adopted by

certain philosophers to prove the reality of the external world


its"
;

although the difficulty which suggests


different in the
I

adoption

is

two

case^.

The
ideas,

phi-

losophers of

whom

speak were of opinion that

we
and

could perceive nothing beyond our

own

they sought to avoid an idealistic conclusion by

supposing that an objective cause was required to


account for the fact that our ideas
scientific
exist.

The
I

argument, on the other hand, with which


is

am
It

at present concerned,

not put forward in order

to avoid a psychological difficulty^ but a logical one.


is

not required because


this

introspective

analysis

shows

thing or that thing respecting the true

nature of perception, but because the conclusions of


Science,
if

made

to

depend

solely

on the immediate
not, as a

knowledge given
of
fact,

in perception,

do

matter

harmonise with their premises.


in

Now,
evadedj

order to estimate properly the value of

the argument

by which

this difficulty is

sought to he

we must

ignore the information given im-

mediately by perception respecting the nature of the


external causes

by which perception
s

is

produced.

258

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


is

[part

hi.

This

evident, because the difficulty itself arose


rest scientific

from our attempting to


this information.

doctrine

on

We
solely

are

expected, then, to found a theory re-

specting the true nature

of these external causes


i.e.,

on

the fact that their effects,

our percep-

tions, are of

such and such a character.

Now

this

undertaking
impossible
matter,
it
;

we may,
and
if

think, boldly assert to


is

be

there

any doubt about the


this single consider-

may be

set at rest

by

ation, that if
effect to

two causes capable of producing the


no possible way of deciding
(to

be accounted for (namely, our perceptions),


is

be suggested, there

between them.

Supposing, for example


it

revive

an old speculation),

was maintained that

it is

not
the

matter possessed of certain properties which

is

required cause, but the Deity acting directly on our

What reply could be made to such a supposition ? The immediate answer that rises to our lips is, that we know that matter exists, and that we have no such knowledge about the Deity. But how do we know that matter exists ? Because we perminds.
ceive
it ?

This source of knowledge


:

is

excluded by

hypothesis

nor can

imagine any other, of an

empirical kind, except the one


discussing.
It

we

are at the

must further be

recollected

moment that we

have no reason to suppose that the

limits of imagin-

ation represent on this subject the limits of possibility.

Nor

is it

practicable, as

pointed out in the

chapter on Historical

Inference,

by the mere con-

CHAP.

XII.]

SCIENCE AS A LOGICAL SYSTEM.


It is

259

templation of an effect (and


in

to this that

we
all

are

the

present case restricted) to discover


it

the

causes by which

might conceivably have been

produced, or to determine which of these possible


causes,
If,

known or unknown, actually produced it. then, we cannot argue from the mere fact that
exist, neither is
it

perceptions exist to the fact that material objects

corresponding to them

possible to

argue from the

fact that these perceptions are of

such and such a kind, to the fact that the objects


perceived have such and such qualities.
Before concluding this section,
let

me

point out
in this In

what
last

it

is

that

have

7tot

attempted to do
it,

argumentative portion of

have not

any

way been concerned


real

with theories respecting the

constitution

of matter based on metaphysical

speculation, nor has any part of the reasoning de-

pended on the truth of a


ception.
I

particular doctrine of perthat. If as


It

have simply assumed


Is

we
:

are

told Science

founded upon experience,

must be
either

founded on experience of one of two kinds

upon

that experience

which

may be

described as

the Immediate knowledge of objects given In perception, or else


else

upon the experience which

is

nothing

than our knowledge of the fact that

we have
of these

such and such perceptions.


assumptions,
I

On
;

the

first

pointed out that the conclusions of


its

Science contradicted

premises

on the second,
at

showed

that Science could

draw no conclusions

all.

s 2

26o

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part in.

CHAPTER
Ever

XIIL

THE EVOLUTION OF BELIEF}


since there has been speculation
fact

on the subject

of varieties of opinion, this


obvious, that a man's beHefs
results of antecedents

must have been

are very

much

the

and surroundings with which

they have no proper logical connection.


sons of Christians are

That the

much more often Christians, and the sons of Mahommedans much more often Mahommedans, that a man more commonly holds
the opinions of those with

whom

he

lives,

and more

commonly
\j

trusts the policy of the party with

whom
cases

he

acts,

than on the theory of probability could


In all

happen supposing that conviction was

the result of an impartial comparison of evidence,

must always have been


observer.
It

plain to the
it

most

careless

other words,

must always have been


belief

known

that there

were causes of

which were

not reasons.

The

progress of knowledge has not led us to

increase, but rather to diminish, our estimate of the

The substance of this chapter appeared originally in the FortReview of 1877, p. 698. I have attempted to cure the obscurity which some of my friends professed to find in it, at the cost of
^

nightly

little

amplification,

and

fear a certain

amount of repetition.

CHAt>. XIII.]

THE EVOLUTION OF

BELIEF.

261

part which reasons as opposed to other causes have

played

in the

formation of creeds

for

it

has shown

us that these reasons are themselves the result of


non-rational antecedents, so that even

when a man
is

attempts to form opinions only according to evidence,

what he shall regard as

evidence

settled for

him by causes over which he has no more


ticular flora
is

control

than he has over the natural forces by which a par-

produced at any particular place and


evidence for this truth
It is justified

time.

The

scientific

is

various

and overwhelming.
regard to races
toric

a posteriori with
observation, with

regard to individuals by

common

by every improvement in our hismethod and every addition to our historic


Physiology shows
the
it

knowledge.
monstrating

a priori by de-

dependence of

thought

on the

organism, and of the organism on inheritance and

environment, while

finally evolution

binds up these

detached lines of proof into an imposing and organic


whole.

But though,
doubts the
plate
it

in

the face of such evidence, nobody


I

fact,

few people,

should think, contemsuffering

habitually without

now and then


(if
I

under a sort of sceptical uneasiness


express myself),
their
in

may

so

when they

consider

its

bearing on

own

opinions.

The

multitude of beliefs which,

obedience to a mechanic and inevitable law, sway


time the minds and actions of men, and are

for a

262

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

hi.

then for ever swept away to the forgotten past,


giving place to others, as firmly trusted
in,

as false,

and as transitory as themselves, form a spectacle


which
is
is

not only

somewhat melancholy

in itself,

but

which
to the

apt to suggest uncomfortable reflections as

permanent character of the convictions we


to.
If,

ourselves happen to be attached

indeed, the

law obeyed

by

this

intellectual

dissolving

view

applied only to savages, or to the people with


opinions
plate
its

whose

we

disagreed,

we might perhaps contemis

action with a merely speculative interest.

Unfortunately, however, this

not

so.

We

are

all

involved in

its

operations, from the

most ignorant

barbarian to the most advanced thinker.


istence of

The

ex-

Comtism
it

is

explained by

it

not less than

that of fetichism,

accounts for theories of Evolution

not less than for Hindoo cosmogonies, and the


of science
is

man

as certainly under

its
is

Indian whose superstitions he


of analysis and classification.

control as was the making the subject

But

if

these

things

be

so,

wherein
?

lies
is

our
true

defence against universal scepticism


that

It

we hear on all sides of the progress ledge, that we imagine science to be as


fabric of

of
it

knowwere a
resting

which each generation lays a


laid

tier,

upon that which was

by

Its

predecessors, and

serving for a foundation for that which will be laid

by

its

successors.

But

after

all,

this

metaphor only
It is

represents an opinion

like other opinions.

the

CHAP.

XIII.]

THE EVOLUTION OF

BELIEF.

263

belief of an optimistic age,

which may seem

to future

generations no more than a transitory fashion.


last

The
suffi-

ground of

faith
is

seems cut away from beneath our


left
it

feet, if

no belief

which can be trusted

ciently for us to use

as a criterion of immutable

truth

and

if

our creed be the mere product of

irrational law,

where

is

such a belief to be found


this must,
I

train of

thought not unlike

should

imagine, have been sometimes started in the mind of

the reader
opinion.
I

when he
propose
I

reflects

on the evolution of

in this

chapter to put in a clear

form what
in

conceive to be the really solid element


if

such sceptical,

somewhat, vague, speculations.


stated thus
:

The

case
it

may be

Since

all

beliefs

are caused,

follows that those fundamental beliefs


at the root of all
I

must be caused which lie beliefs, and which are, as


chapter, the rational

other
first

explained in the

ground on which we hold them.

Now

these fundamental beliefs, being the ultimate


all

premises of

knowledge, are themselves, of course,

incapable of proof

So

that while they resemble

other beliefs in being caused, they differ from them


in this, that the causes

by which they are produced


In ordinary

are of necessity, and from the very nature of the


case,

always non-rational.

life,

when

we

perceive a non-rational cause for any opinion, as

for instance party feeling, or self-interest, or special

education,

it

makes us examine such reasons


it

as there

may be

for

with more jealous minuteness.

In

264

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


it is

[part

hi.

contrast to this,

curious and interesting to note

that the only beliefs of which, according to received


scientific theories,

we may say

with certainty that

they can have no reason, but micst have non-rational


causes, are those

on which the certitude of

all

other

beliefs finally rests.

The

upholders, however, of the

current theory of Evolution are so far from finding

any

difficulty here, that

they even refer triumphantly

to this theory of non-rational causation, as supplying

a basis of philosophical certitude to these funda-

mental
is

beliefs.

They hold
is

that though

all

opinion

the product of natural forces, the general tendency

of those forces

gradually to

make

opinion approxi-

mate
are

to truth

that in particular the opinions which


*

commonly regarded as
intuition
'

self-evident

'

and known
'

by

are really the result of reiterated and

uncontradicted
generations
;

experience
this

acting

on

successive

and that

theory of their origin

supplies a philosophic justification for believing


to

them

be

true.

This
fest

line of reasoning,
in

however, involves a maniIt

argument

circle.

cannot be that this


is

interaction

between organism and environment

reason for believing any proposition to be true which


is

required to prove that interaction.

Or

(to

put

it

more generally) no argument in favour of a system of beliefs can be drawn from the fact that, according to
that system,
its

fundamental beliefs would be

true.

From

Evolution, then, no argument can be

drawn

CHAP.

XIII.]

THE EVOLUTION OF
scientific

BELIEF.
It

265

in

favour of any

axiom.

remains to be
less

seen

whether that theory has any


belief.

negative

bearing on the philosophy of

Now

the

theory asserts this

All

phenomena

whatever are evolved by regular laws and groups


of laws from the
in time.

phenomena next preceding them


other phenomena, beliefs
;

Among

among
any-

other beliefs, fundamental beliefs.

All beliefs what-

ever being caused, the question

arises. Is there

thing in the nature of the laws according to which

they are caused which should

make them

true

To

which an evolutionist would probably reply that


there
is,

and would mention those causes

to

which
is

allusion has already

been made, whose tendency


belief

gradually

to

make
make
If
is

correspond

with

fact.

Then (we may


a nature as to

further ask) are these causes of such


all beliefs true
?

This question must undoubtedly be answered


the
negative.
'

in

any. result of 'observation and

experiment

certain, this

one

is

so

that

many
in

erroneous beliefs have existed, and do exist in the

world

so that whatever causes there

may be

operation by which true beliefs are promoted, they

must be
dency.

either

limited

in

their

operation,

or be

counteracted by other causes of an opposite ten-

Have

w^e

then any reason to suppose that

fundamental beliefs are specially subject to these


truth-producing influences, or specially exempt from
causes of error
?

This question,

apprehend, must

266

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,


in the negative.
if

[part

hi.

be answered
it

At

first sight,

indeed,

would seem as

those beliefs were specially pro-

tected from error which are the results of legitimate

reasoning.

But legitimate reasoning


if it

is

only a pro-

tection against error

proceeds from true pre-

mises,

and

it

is

clear that this particular protection


all

the

premises of
they,
'

reasoning never can possess.


?

Have

then,

any other
I

Except the

'

ten-

dency above mentioned,

must confess myself un;

able to see that they have


evolutionists)
is

so that our position (as


beliefs
all

this

From certain ultimate


all

we

infer that

an order of things exists by which

beliefs,

and therefore

ultimate beliefs, are probelief,

duced, but according to which any particular

and therefore any particular ultimate


doubtful.

belief,

must be
is

Now destructive. No

this

is

a position w^hich
beliefs,

self-

system of

giving an account

of the origin of fundamental beliefs, can be consistent


unless those fundamental beliefs are as certain

when

regarded as the result of antecedent causes, as they


are

when regarded
I

as the ground of our belief in the


It

existence and operation of those causes.

does

not follow (as


that
if,

pointed out by implication above)

according to the account of their origin given


beliefs are true,

by the system, those fundamental


that therefore they are

true

for the truth of the


beliefs,

system

is

an inference from these

and cannot
is,

therefore prove them.

What

does follow

that the

system has one of the negative conditions of truth,

CHAP.

XIII.]

THE EVOLUTION OF

BELIEF.
is

267

and

is

(so far at least as this


itself.
it

matter

concerned)

consistent with

To
there

this criticism

may

perhaps be replied, that


in

is

no contradiction involved
seems

considering a

proposition from two points of view

from

one of

which
It

it

certain,

and from the other doubtful.


in

happens every day

dealing with statements

which are established by pieces of evidence of very


different degrees of cogency.

For example, the

fact

that the three angles of a triangle are invariably equal


to

two right angles would be doubtful

if

we had no

better

means of demonstrating
pair of compasses.
it

it

than the employ-

ment of a
it

Geometrical proof, on

the other hand, makes

absolutely certain.

Will
can

be maintained that such an inconsistency,


so,

if it
?

be called

suggests any sceptical conclusion


not.

Assuredly

But there

is

no parallelism be-

tween the two

cases.

Ultimate premises are not

shown to be merely probable by one set of proofs, and shown to be certain by another. They are not shown to be certain at all. They are assumed to be
so
:

and the

first

stage of the difficulty arises from

the fact that while they are assumed without evi-

dence to be
their origin

certain, the

evidence

we

possess as to

shows that they are not


all,

certain.

If this

were

however, the

difficulty

a slight one.

We

should merely have to

would be modify our

original position,

and concede

to the sceptic that the

assurance

we

possessed respecting the validity of

268

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

hi.

our ultimate premises was not quite so strong as

we

had supposed.
difficulty arises,

It is at the

next stage that the real

when we

consider the fact that our

whole ground
doubtful
tainty.
is

for thinking these ultimate


in the last resort

premises
their cer-

founded
is

upon

This
fatal

a manifest flaw or defect, which


the validity of any system from

must be
which
it

to

cannot be removed.

The difficulty only arises, it may be obsei^ved, when we are considering our own beliefs. If I am considering the beliefs of some other person

mediaeval divine

there
I

say of some
I

is

no reason why

should

regard them as anything but the results of his time

and circumstances.
a country,
teachers,
fell

observe that he lived

in

such

under the influence of such and such


across such

came

and such

incidents,

and

then

infer,

with

much

self-contentment, that his


I

beliefs could not

have been other than they were.

may even pay them


that

the compliment of pointing out


in
I

they form a necessary stage

the general

evolution of humanity.
sider

But when
as

come

to con-

my own

beliefs

a stage

in

the general

evolution of humanity, then there emerges the contradiction

mentioned above.
of

If

they represent such

a stage,

all

them may

be,

and many of them must


in

be, false.

Why

not the particular belief


it

Evo?

lution

Because

is

scientifically

demonstrated

This only removes the


back.
It

difficulty

a stage further

must be

demonstrated ultimately from

CHAP.

XIII.]

THE EVOLUTION OF
is

BELIEF.

269

something which
undemonstrated
doubtful

not demonstrated
are

and these
rendered

behefs

necessarily

by the
if this

reflection that they

form part of the

stage in the evolution of humanity.


*

But

is

all,'

the advocates of Evolution


'

may be

inclined to reply,

you have proved nothing


to grant.
is

more than we are quite prepared


present rigorously certain

We
not at
it

concede, without difficulty, that our theory


;

and even that

can

never become so. must always attach


further,

You have shown


to our original data
;

that doubt

we

will

go
into

and admit that error may always creep


But
this

our most careful deductions.

only shows---

what nobody ever disputedthat we must content


ourselves in science, as in everything else, with some-

thing short of rigorous demonstration.

Unless you

can show us that our system has some other defect,


not necessarily incident to the work of
fallible

man,

your arguments

will

be wasted on people
I
;

who
is

in the

main agree with


it

you.'

reply that

can show that


this
:

has some other defect

and the defect


be

If

we suppose Evolution
tionist

to

become what evety evolu-

must wish
is

it

to

though

he may admit
demonstra-

that

it

not

namely, a
certain
;

solid piece of

tion resting

ment
its

it

on axiomatic premises, from that mobecomes self-contradictory. It is impossible


it

as soon as

is

because,

by the very

fact of

becoming

certain,

we

obtain demonstrative proof

that the premises of the system, and therefore the


A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,
itself, is is

2 70

[part hi.

system

uncertain.

system of which
it is

this

can be said

not merely doubtful,

incoherent.

The
abstract
is

precise nature of this objection will perhaps


if,

be more clear

instead of being put in this

its

most
it

and general form, a concrete example of

taken.

We

may

suppose, then, a conversation between


in

an Evolutionist and an Enquirer,


the former has explained
in

which,

the usual

when ways how


reached

human

beliefs, after

passing through infinite grada-

tions of diminishing error,

have

at length

the highest development they are

now

capable of in

the opinion he himself professes, the Enquirer continues the dialogue

by asking
that this development of
limits,

Enq.
beliefs

Do you suppose
now reached
?

has

its

or do you antici-

pate as great a change in the future as has occurred


in the past

EvL However views may be over


still

great

the superiority

of

my
are

those of

my

remote ancestors,

or indeed over those of

my

contemporaries
tradition, there

who
is

under the influence of

every

reason to suppose that the causes which have pro-

duced

this superiority are still in operation,

and that

we may
mankind
Enq,

look forward to a time


will

when

the opinion of

bear the same relation to ours as ours

bear to those of primitive man.

glorious

hope

One, nevertheless,

which would seem to imply that many of our pre-

CHAP.

XIII.]

THE EVOLUTION OF

BELIEF.

271

sent views are either entirely wrong, or will require

profound modification.

EvL

Doubtless. Enq. would be


It

interesting to

know which
is

of

our opinions, or which class of them,

likely to

be

improved
example,

in this
is

way

off the face of the earth.

For
that
?

the opinion you have just expressed,

that beliefs are developed according to law

is

opinion likely to be destroyed by development


Evl.
tive

To

answer your question

in the affirmaIf (as

would appear

to involve a contradiction.
is

we assume) development
sible that

truthwards,

it

is

imposin

development should produce a disbelief

development
Enq,
belief in
tible,

understand you to hold then that a


true,
it

development is
in this

and therefore indestrucfrom many of our

and that

differs

other beliefs, of which


the same.
It

we

cannot, unfortunately, say

would be important
order

grounds of
see

this distinction, in
it

know the that we might


to

how

far

was capable of general


is

application.

j5'z//. Evolution

a theory arrived at by reDoubtless,


all

ceived scientific methods.

results of
true,

which the same may be said are equally


will

and
a

be equally permanent.

Enq,

You

talk

of

scientific

methods

but
I

method must proceed on a

principle or principles.

How

do you get

at these

EvL

The

principles

you speak of

are,

sup-

272

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

hi.

pose, the assumptions which every one

must

start

from,
ledge.

who

expects to

make any

progress in know-

Enq.
are

These
therefore,

assumptions, as
scientific

understand you,
possible

what render a

method
at

They

cannot,

be

arrived

by a

scientific

method, nor can they belong to that class of beliefs


which, as you just pointed out, the progress of evolution will leave uninjured.

EvL
is,

Still

you must assume something.


the difficulty here, as
it

Enq,
that

But
you

seems to me,

if

start

from your idea of evolution, these


other beliefs not arrived at by

assumptions, like
*

all

received scientific methods,' are, or

may

be,

mere
like

transient phases in the

development of opinion,

the doctrines involved in ancestor worship or theism.

Nevertheless,

it

is

only by starting from these asto


if

sumptions that
tion at
all.

you ever get

your theory of evoluEvolution


is

In other words,

certain,

these assumptions must be certain,


as premises,
ducts.

when regarded

and uncertain when regarded as prois

This

not easy to believe.

i?z;/. Still)
thing.

you know, you must assume somea pity you cannot so

^//^.-Nevertheless,
order your assumptions

it

is

as

to

make your system

more what
his

self-consistent.

At

present you seem some-

to resemble

an astronomer who should base


real

whole theory of the

motion of the heavenly

CHAP, xiil]

the evolution OF

BELIEF.

273

bodies on the supposition that his


rest
;

own

planet was at

but should unfortunately discover that one of

the necessary conclusions from his theory was that


his planet, in
tion.

common with all the others, was Of such a one we should probably say,
were correct
if

in

moif

that

his deductions

his

premises must have

been wrong, while

his premises

were correct his

deductions must have been wrong.


;

So

far

have only considered


it

this difficulty as

it

applies to Evolution, because

seemed
It is

to

me

that

the issue to which

wished to

call attention

could

be thus most conveniently

raised.

a mistake,

however, to suppose that the


attaches to Evolution alone.

difficulty necessarily

Every theory
all beliefs

is

ob-

noxious to

it

according to which

are sup-

posed to be caused, while fundamental


caused
in

beliefs are

such a manner as to
to
:

make them

uncertain.

Now

it is

be noted that

this description is rather

wide one

and must undoubtedly be held to include

the world of Science as ordinarily conceived.

For
If

It is

plain that current scientific

methods can
is

lead to no other result than that belief

a product.
that.

experience can prove anything,


is

it

can prove

There

here none of that doubt which has been

thrown on the existence or non-existence of free will by the real or supposed discrepancy between the
deliverances of Introspective consciousness and the
verdict of ordinary historical
case,

experience.

In this
inter-

whether we consult

statistics,

whether we

^74

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT, we judge

[part

hi.

rogate consciousness, whether

of the matter

on grounds furnished by physiology, or ethnology, whatever scientific or history, or natural selection

doctrine or scientific

method be brought
Is

to bear

on

the question, but one result


beliefs,

obtained

beliefs, all

are the result of the operation of natural

causes,
certain,

and of these
I

alone.

And

since

it

is

no

less

apprehend, that these causes are of a kind


it

to throw doubts on the beliefs they produce,

follows

according to our canon, that ordinary scientific me-

thods land us in contradiction.

It

must, however,

be observed that there


convenience of

is

a justification, beyond mere

exposition, for

making Evolution
it is

especially the subject of th: criticism, because

Evolution alone which necessarily claims to regulate


the whole world of phenomena.

The

special sci-

ences
well

physics, chemistry, and so forth might very


on,

go

even

if

their
it

methods were not

uniit

versally applied, though


is

must be admitted that


But
nothing.
it,

not easy to find a principle of limitation.


is

if

Evolution

not universal,
are to be
left

it is

If certain
if
it

phenomena

outside

cannot

without contradiction and confusion explain, potentially at least,

how

the whole world as


it

it it

is

follows

necessarily from the world as

was,

certainly
its

appears to

me
its

that

it

ought to modify either

methods or

pretensions.

THE EVOLUTION OF

BELIEF.

275

NOTE.
In the preceding chapter the argument has turned
on the manner
their validity.
in

in part

which the nature of the causes of belief

in general (and therefore of ultimate beliefs)

may
to be

affect

At

first

sight there

may seem

contradiction between this portion of the argument

the general principles laid


it

down

in the first chapter.

some and For

was there pointed out that no enquiry

into the origin of

ultimate beliefs can be of any philosophic value, and the

reader

may

be tempted to interpret

this

canon into an
is

assertion that the origin of ultimate beliefs

a matter of
for

absolute philosophic

indifference
offers,

an
is

interpretation

which

my own

language

perhaps,

some excuse. Thus


It
ii>

interpreted, however, the doctrine

incorrect.

true

that the origin of ultimate beliefs never can supply

any

ground

for believing them,

simply because the fact of their

having any particular origin can only be shown by inference founded ultimately on these beliefs themselves.
it

But

is

quite possible that the converse of this proposition

may

be

true,

and that inference from ultimate

beliefs as to

their origin

may
this

furnish logical grounds for doubting or

disbelieving them.

The preceding chapter


science,

example of

drawn from actual

contains an and an imagi-

nary instance
still

may

perhaps serve to put the matter in a

more

forcible light.

We

might imagine
our ultimate

it

to be a

conclusion demonstrable from


those beliefs

beliefs,

that

were implanted

in us

by a being who had the

power, and- invariably had the wish, to deceive and mislead


us.

Now

say that under such circumstances

we should

be compelled either to think that our creed was essentially


T 2

276

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT,

[part

iii.

incoherent, or that

we had committed some blunder


dilemma which, though
in

in our

inference

and

this is the
I

a less

obvious shape,

maintain

we

are brought face to face with


applied, as
it

by the doctrine of Evolution when


applied, to our ultimate beliefs.

must be

SUMMARY.

"

277

SUMMARY.
I

HAVE now brought

to a close the long series of dis-

cussions on the speculative foundations of Science^

which began with the second chapter of


It

this

Essay.

may now be convenient

if I

endeavour, even at the

some repetition, to show by means of a concise summary the main outline of the argument of which
cost of

these discussions are the essential parts.

However
effect of
will

disjointed

and fragmentary the general


be, the attentive reader
is

what precedes may

not have failed to observe that a kind of unity

introduced into the whole by the

common
first

relation

which
In that

all
is

the other parts bear to the


laid

chapter.

down

with sufficient generality the

conditions which any system of thought must satisfy

before

it

can be regarded as reasonable

,*

while the

succeeding chapters contain an examination of


far these conditions are satisfied
If there

how

by orthodox Science.

appears but
is

little

unity in this part of the

Essay, the fact

only a reflection of the disunion

existing between the different systems of Philosophy


criticised,

which, though they

all

admit that Science

78

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


on a
solid

rests

and

rational foundation,
else.

seem

unfor-

tunately able to agree in nothing


If there
tific

was a

single recognised system of scienall its

philosophy, complete in
is,

parts

containing,
was
critic,

that

an account of the premises and modes of

inference

by which every

scientific

proposition

ultimately established
at least as the

the task of the

so far

arrangement of his work was conThis, however,

cerned, would be comparatively easy.


is

not

so.

Existing philosophies are not only various,

but they are incomplete.

They

not only treat the

same portions of the problem differently, but they none of them treat of it in all its parts. Their
attempts are fragmentary as well as inconsistent.

At what

point, then,

is

the critic to begin


first,

What

system should be examined


that system should be

and what parts of


be provisionally
is

assumed

to

sound while the


tested
?

solidity of the

remainder

being
in this

The

course that

have adopted

Essay, whether the most convenient or not, has been


to start with the ordinary Logic of Science, taking for

granted that the view which that Logic takes of the


premises of Science
the assumption as
it

is

correct,

and only modifying

was gradually found untenable.


that they consist
in

Now

the view of the premises of physical science


is,

taken by the usual Inductive logic


of observations of

what takes place


is

the external

world.

On

these

founded everything

we know

concerning the nature of the laws which obtain In

SUMMARY.
that world, including the fact that
it is

279;

governed by
is

law at

all

so that, as no general principle


I

given

(except on the transcendental theory which


later), in
first

examined

a single observation, the problem


is,

we have
this

to consider

ticulars alone.

how inference is The result of the discussion on


possible

possible from par-

point was to

show that, so
is

far as at present appears,


;

no

such inference
its

and

for

a reason which, in
in

most general expression, was given


I

the

first

chapter.^
if it is

there observed that

any kind of Logic,

to

be philosophical, must be formal.

The whole

object of a philosophy of inference being to distin-

guish valid and ultimate inferences from those which


are invalid or derivative,
either
this

can only be done,


infer-

by exhibiting the common forms of such

ences, or (on the violent hypothesis that they

have

no common forms), by enumerating every concrete


instance.

To

enunciate a form of inference which

shall include

both valid and invalid examples, can at

best have only a psychological interest*

Now,

in-

duction from particulars


includes both valid

is

a form of inference which

and

invalid examples, so that, in

accordance with the

maxim above
If

enunciated,
is

it

is

philosophically worthless.

no attempt

made

to

distinguish between the cases

where

it is

legitimate

and those where


placed in
its

it is

not,

then no confidence can be


If

conclusions.

such an attempt

is

made,

Chap.

i.

p. II.

28o

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


must be by the help of some general
principle,-

it

and in that case the inference ceases to be from


particulars.

Something, then, must be added to the knowledge

we

derive from observation to enable us to

arrive at a law of

Nature

and, further, this additional

premiss must be a general proposition.


to be
?

The

reader, recollecting that

What is we wish

it

to

keep as close as possible to the ordinary philosophy


of Science, and also to
as few as possible (seeing that

make our initial assumptions we have afterwards to


approve the
In the third chapter,
it

examine

their validity), will doubtless

choice of the law of causation.


therefore,

we

enquire

how

far

is

possible to arrive
it

at a

knowledge of the

special laws of Nature,


effects

being

conceded that similar


causes,

always follow similar


particular sequences

and that a knowledge of

and coexistences between phenomena can be derived


from observation.

The result of this enquiry was to show that, if we take some phenomenon or group of phenomena for investigation, inductive logic is
competent under favourable circumstances to prove,

with a high degree of probability, that certain of the

phenomena preceding it in time mere, and certain of them were noi, causally connected with it. But that, on the other hand, inductive logic could not show
either of these things respecting that indefinite mul-

phenomena which in experience have always been present, both when the phenomenon
titude

of

SUMMARY.

'

2^1

under investigation has occurred and also when


has not.
Since there
is

it

no apparent method by which

the effects of these persistent causes can be ehminated,

we

are for ever debarred from a theoretical


:

knowledge of any absolute law of Nature from a knowledge, I mean, of ^// the phenomena required
to produce a given result
:

and since there

is

no

assignable ground for assuming that these persistent


objects which have always accompanied,

and may
of

possibly have co-operated with, the

known cause

any

effect, will

continue to accompany them whenever

they recur, our ground for supposing that these

known

causes will in the future be followed by their accus-

tomed

consequents,

seems

in

great

measure

removed.

The

principles

on which
is

this

somewhat
:

unsatis-

factory conclusion

based are these two


anything

First,

every phenomenon which invariably precedes another

phenomenon may,
trary,

for

we know

to the con-

be part of

its

cause.

Second, the present or


furnishes no grounds
in

past existence of a
for

phenomenon
existence

anticipating

its

the future.

Of

course, in order that these principles

may be

legiti-

mately applied,
ignorance of
all

we

require to assume an absolute

the laws of Nature.

On

the con-

trary assumption, that

some of these laws are known,

we may have every

reason for thinking that certain

antecedents are not causes, and for expecting a con-

2S2

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


But

tinuance of things which have hitherto existed.

since we are examining the methods by which laws of

Nature
start

in

general are arrived

at,

we must

evidently
at yet,

by supposing that they are not arrived


principles

and on that supposition the two


stated

above

seem

to

me hard
I

to refute.

In Chapter IV.

took for granted that which in

Chapter

III.

showed could not be proved, namely,


of our knowledge of the laws

the trustworthiness

connecting phenomena, and enquired how, from laws,

we

could argue to facts

and more

especially to facts

that have already occurred.


I

pointed out that our knowledge of past events


entirely founded
;

was

upon reasoning from

effect to

cause

and that there was a prima facie


all

difficulty

attaching to

reasoning of this kind, arising from

the circumstance that


possibly
therefore,

more than one cause might


effect.

produce a given

The

problem,

which required consideration was, how to

distinguish from
possible, the
this

among

the causes which are merely

one which was actual or probable.


I

For
is

problem

could find no solution.


is

The

ordinary
to

procedure which

followed by

men

of science

estimate the comparative probabilities of the rival

hypotheses, on the basis of

some theory respecting


it is

the condition of things at the time of which they are


treating.

Now
own

this theory, if

not a mere figment

of their
torical

imagination, must, like any other his-

proposition,

be

itself

in

the

first

instance

SUMMARY.
founded upon an inference from
this process of resting
effect to cause
effect to cause.

283

But

successive inferences from

on

historical

hypotheses which can

only be justified by other inferences from effect to


cause,
is

must evidently have a


is

limit.

When

that limit

reached, what

to

be our next ground of belief?


Philosophy
is silent,

On

this point Scientific

and we

are driven to the conclusion, that

if

two or more

explanations of the universe are barely possible, they

must, for anything


equally probable
;

we

can say to the contrary, be


is

which

as

much
in

as to say, that

one version of history need not be


another, merely because
natural
it

less likely

than

seems

comparison un-

and extravagant. These remarks, of course, only hold good as bepossible.


If

tween causes which are

a cause could

not produce the effects which are our sole premises


for inferring the existence at
all,

and character of any cause


it

cadit qucsslio.
at

Supposing, therefore,

could

be shown that

any given time only one

set of facts

could result in the world as

we now see
?

it,

we should
It

know
ance.

the history of that time with a perfect assur-

Can

this

ever be shown
I

It
if

cannot.
restrict

cannot be shown,
attention to those

imagine, even

we

our

phenomena with whose laws we are

acquainted.
less

But, besides these, there

may be
that

count-

powers with the laws of whose operations we are

entirely unacquainted,

and by which
If

all

we

see

may have been

produced.

we once admit

the

284

A DEFENCE OV PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


do not know by
can have no

possibility of their existence (and 1

what authority we are to deny it), ence is thrown into confusion.


ground
for

all historical infer-

We

supposing these hypothetical powers to

begin acting at one time rather than at another,

whether they be powers which should be described


as

metaphysical,

theological, or

merely unknown.

In order, therefore, that a

man may have any rational


Cosmos
as revealed in

confidence in the history of the

the teachings of Science, he must be something

more
past

than an Agnostic.

He

must have very

solid

grounds

for believing, not only that

through the

infinite

only one series of phenomena can be assigned capable

of having produced the actual

universe,

but

that nothing besides

phenomena capable
all

of acting

on phenomena have ever existed at


solid

and these
all,

grounds of belief or disbelief must no^ be drawn


;

from history

but,

if

derived from experience at

must be derived from his own immediate observations.

Here terminated the first part of our enquiry. Its general result is to show (i) that from the particular knowledge obtained by observing the phenomena of a world assumed throughout this part of the Essay to be persistent, no scientific conclusions could be drawn and (2) that even if we suppose these phenomena to be part of a world governed by causation, we were not much advanced, and that therefore, (3) some further principles or modes of
:

SUMMARY.

-285

inference have need to be discovered before Science


is

placed on a rational foundation.


is

Of

these

'

further

principles/ since their nature


.no

altogether unknown,

more

notice has been taken.

The

second part of the Essay

was

principally

occupied in discussing various philosophic proofs of

two known assumptions on which Science proceeds


^namely, the persistence of the material universe

and

the law of universal causation.


iirst

With regard

to the

of them, though not,

think, with regard to the

second, two theories have been maintained, either of

which,
'of it

if true,

would render any philosophic defence


According
is

unnecessary.

to one, the persistence


;

of the material universe

self-evident
at the

according to
its

the other,

it

is

untrue

though
I

same time

untruth has no
iirst

scientific significance

whatever.

The
for
;

of these statements

gave some reasons


second part

doubting

in the Introduction to the

the

second

discussed at length in Chapter IX.

It will

not be necessary to recapitulate the arguI

ments by which

attempted to show that the main

systems of speculation which


precarious authority

now

hold a divided and


thinkers cannot

among English

pretend to furnish satisfactory evidence of the trustworthiness of these two scientific assumptions.
will
It

be

sufficient to

remind the reader


I

that,

in the

chapters from VI. to XI. inclusive,


less
fully

dealt

more or

with

(i)

The Kantian

or

neo- Kantian

2^6

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSt)PHIC DOUBT.


certain Trans-

argument which founds knowledge on


cendental necessities of
(2)
belief.

[Ch. VI.]

The system which

sets

up an

internal or

subjective authority
final arbiter

called Consciousness

as

the

(3)

The

[Ch. V 1 1 L] of Truth. system which finds the highest source of

certainty in our original judgments.


(4)

[Ch. VIII.]
in

The argument which

seeks either

the

opinions of mankind in general, or of

some

selected

portion of them, for an ultimate ground of belief.

[Ch. VII.]
(5)

The argument which


it
*

infers the truth of

an

opinion from the fact that

succeeds in practice.'

[Ch. VII.]
(6)

The argument which


'

infers

the truth of an

opinion from the fact that

common

sense

'

(in

the

popular acceptation of that term) supports

it.

[Ch.

VII.]
(7)

The philosophy which

declares every prois

position to be true of which the opposite


ceivable.

incon-

In addition to these discussions on various pro-

posed foundations for a creed,


second part two chapters
:

introduced into the


to refuting

one devoted

Mr. Spencer's proof of Realism [Ch. XI.], the other


to

showing that unless Realism be


false
I

true,

Science must

be

[Ch. IX.].

have purposely made these discussions personal,

in the sense of fastening

them on some

particular

SUMMARY.
individual

'

Vgy

^in

all cases,

the most distinguished recent

exponent of

his special

views

because
in
I

this

method
raise a

seems the one most certainly calculated to


clear

and

definite issue.

While

regard to the sub-

ject-matter of the criticisms,


steer

have attempted to
of,

between the opposite danger

on the one

hand, dealing with minute or verbal errors, and on


the other, of wandering off into comments upon the

whole system of an author, instead of confining myself to those parts

which are alone relevant

to the

questions at issue.

Assuming
fairly

theii that

the arguments attacked are

representative of English Philosophy at the

present time
ing, as

as
is

is,

think,

the case

and

assumsay

Lam

bound

to do, that the answers here


effective,

given to tbose arguments are


that Science

we may

a system of belief which, for anything


is

we

can allege to the contrary,

wholly without
arrived at are
rests are un-

proof.

The
;

inferences

by which

it is

erroneous
proved.

the premises on which

it

It

only remains to show that, considered as


belief,
it is

a general system of
task
is

incoherent

and

this

undertaken

in the

two chapters which together


Chapter XII.)
is

form the Third Part.

The
devoted

first

of these (namely.

is

in the

main

to

showing that there

a dis-

crepancy between the

be

its

(particular)
its

which Science asserts to premises and the facts which it


facts

puts forward as

ultimate conclusions. But besides

288

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


it is

this principal contention,

shown

incidentally that

the universe, as
is
it

it

is

represented to us by Science,

wholly unimaginable, and that our conception of


is,

what

in

Theology would be termed, purely


It

anthropomorphic.

must be noted that the uninot the metaphysical Thing-

verse here spoken of


in-itself,

is

Unknowable Reality which we are supposed by some philosophers to arrive at, if we


nor
is it

the

drive our speculative analysis sufficiently deep.

On

the contrary,
all,

it is

the subject-matter of

all,

or almost

the propositions which are put forward

by Natural

Science, and which together constitute a large part

of what

is

commonly, though not very happily, de-

scribed as Positive Knowledge.

^The chief argument of Chapter XII.


ever, only indirectly
its

is,

how-

connected with this subject,


to contrast the world as
it

principal

end being

appears with the world as Science assures us that


is,

it

and

to

show

that the scientific reasoning

which

makes our knowledge of the second depend


upon our knowledge of the
first, is

logically

inadmissible.

The
flagrant

fact that the

two are

in

contradiction

is

and undeniable as any one may see who


objects.

considers that while perception gives us immediate

knowledge of the existence of coloured


Science
tells

us that this appearance

is

really

due

either to the

vibration of uncoloured particles, or


It is also,
I

to reflection from uncoloured surfaces.

imagine, evident that no integral part of a system

SUMMARY.

289

can contradict the premises of that system without


introducing
:

confusion
finally,
it

and incoherence

into

the whole

and

must be admitted that


system does rest upon
its
it

since our actual

scientific

the data given in perception, and since


sions are in contradiction with these data,

conclu-

must be

regarded as incoherent and confused.

Some
from
outline
I

speculative arguments

fail

of their effect

their too great subtilty.

The argument whose


is

have just

briefly indicated

likely to fail

from a precisely opposite reason.


it is

When once

stated
it is

so obvious, and so readily understood, that


is

hard to believe that there

not

some recognised
difficulty
I

and equally obvious reply by which the


raises

it

may be

disposed

of.
is

If so,

however,
:

do not
on
I

know where such


pointed out
in

a reply

to be found
I

while,

the other hand, cause

may

think be

shown
I

(as

the chapter under review)

why

the

difficulty itself

may

easily escape notice.

there

explained that in our reflections upon the origin of

our knowledge of the external world

we

habitually
:

take for granted the scientific theory of perception

according to which the perceived object acts upon

our organism, which in


ceiving mind what
ject.
is

its

turn produces in the per-

called a perception of the ob-

If this theory
intelligible

be true

and

did not dispute


it is

it

as

it is

enough that the object as

per-

ceived should not exactly correspond with the object


it is,

but that

(to

speak metaphorically) the mesu

290

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.

sage sent by the latter should be altered and modified in the course of transmission.
IS

But the

difficulty

that this theory itself rests entirely

on observations
its exist-

of the external world, and therefore, though

ence quite accounts

for,

yet

it

by no means

justifies

our habitual indifference to the contradiction which


lies

between the immediate

results of these obser-

vations

and the remote conclusions which Science


In order to
this objection

draws from them.


ble

obviate a possi-

way by which
is
it

might be met,

showed, at the end of the chapter, that no advantage


that

gained for the


rests,
is

scientific

system by supposing

not on the facts given in perception, but

(which

quite another thing)


:

on the

fact that

such

and such perceptions occur


of the various things

not on the existence

perceived

crystals, metals,

planets, and so forth, but on the fact that we have

perceptions as of crystals, metals,

and

planets.

It

was

shortly pointed out that to regard the world of

Science as a hypothetical means of accounting for


the occurrence of these perceptions

and

it

is

this

which we should have to do,


our belief
in
it

if

we mean

to justify

merely by an inference founded on

the fact that these perceptions exist

would

be

simply to place

it

on a

level with

an indefinite

num-

ber of other hypotheses,

known and unknown, which


the

might be supposed

to

fulfil

same

function.

The

Thirteenth chapter, like the twelfth, dealt


in

with an inherent flaw or defect

the scientific system,

SUMMARY.
but one of a
ter.

291

much more
is

subtle

and

difficult

charac-

This flaw

due ultimately

to the fact that

may be considered from two separate It may be looked upon as a mempoints of view. ber of a logical series, or it may be looked upon as a member of a causal series. If we consider it from
every belief
the
first

of these points of view,

it

appears as a con-

clusion, as a premiss, or as

both a conclusion and a

premiss.

If

we

consider

It

from the second point of


as a cause, or as both

view,

it

appears as an

effect,

an

effect

and a
every

cause.
belief,

Now

without exception, has accord-

ing to Science got a cause.

But every belief has by


beliefs

no means got a reason, and there are some


ultimate ones on which
it

which cannot possibly have reasons, namely, those


all

others depend

these,

is

evident, must be products, but cannot be con-

clusions.

Confining our attention, then, to ultimate beliefs


considered merely as products,
that, as products,
it

becomes evident

they are in no
Infinite

way

to be distin-

guished from the


rise

multitude of beliefs which

Into

favour,

become the fashion, fall out of and are forgotten by all but the historians
notice,

of

opinion.

Like them, they are the

effects

of

material

antecedents,

the necessary results

of

primeval arrangement of atoms.

But

these,

the

reader must note, are causes which unquestionably

produce much

error,

and which
u
2

It

might be plausibly

292

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.

maintained have produced more error than truth.

There

is

consequently a distinct probability


its

though,
results

of course, one uncertain in


lief,

amount
belief,

that any bewhich

and therefore any ultimate


will

from their operation

be erroneous.

But

if

now, from looking at the question excluside,

sively from the causal

we

turn round and look


well,

at

it

from the cognitive or logical side as


difficulty.

we

become conscious of a
consists

For

in so far as

Science conforms to the ideal of a rational system,


it

of conclusions certainly

inferred

from

certain premises.

But one of the conclusions thus


is

certainly

inferred
all

(as

we have

just seen), that


;

the premises of

science are doubtful

so that the

more

certain

we choose

to consider our inferences,

the more

we

diminish the only ultimate assurance

we have
If
it

for believing

them

at

all.

be replied that

this

consequence

may be

avoided by considering the


reasonable
probable,
'

scientific
it

system

as

all

men do

actually consider

to be merely
were suddenly

answer that we cannot consider any sysif it

tem
to

to

be even probable which,


certain,

become

would be

self-contradictory,
is

and

therefore impossible.

Such a supposition

absurd.
fact,

No

conclusion less than the recognition of the


is

some fundamental error or omission in the account given by Science, and more especially by the doctrine of Evolution, of the genesis of our
that there

ultimate beliefs, will satisfy the argument

though

SUMMARY.

293

how

this

error or omission

is

to

be corrected or
our
ordinary
I

supplied
theories

without

entirely

altering

about the history of the universe,

am

unable to say.

This discussion

in

the thirteenth chapter concludes

the speculative enquiry into the nature and validity of the evidence which can be produced in favour of
the current scientific creed.
results arrived at
It
fails

At every

point,

the

have been unfavourable

to Science.

in its premises, in its inferences,

and

in its

conclusions.

The
;

first,

so far as they are known,


;

are unproved

the second are inconclusive

the third

are incoherent.

Nor am
scientific
suffer.

acquainted with any


liable,

kind of defect to which systems of belief are

under which the

system of belief

may

not

properly be said to

If the reader, in the interests of speculation (the

practical question
chapter), feels

will

be discussed

in

the

next

inclined to complain of the purely

destructive nature of the criticisms contained in the

preceding pages,
in

reply that speculation seems sadly


criticism just at the present
faith
is

want of destructive Whenever any time.


universally, there
is

held strongly and

a constant and overpowering

tendency to convert Philosophy, which should be


its

judge, into

its

servant.
;

It
it

was so formerly, when


is

Theology ruled supreme


has usurped
its

so

now

that Science

place

and

assert with

some

con-

fidence that the bias given to thought in the days of

'

394

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.

the Schoolmen through the overmastering influence of the


first

of these creeds was not a whit more perspeculation than

nicious to the cause of impartial

the bias which

it

receives at this

moment through

the influence of the second.


It is

curious to remark
in

how
the

similar are the con-

sequences of this bias

two

cases.

Philo-

sophy, or what passed for such, not only supported

Theology
but

in the
it
;

Middle Ages-^it became almost


it

identical with
it

not only supports Science now,


scientific

has almost become a


talk,

department.

To

hear some people

one would

really

suppose

that Philosophy consisted either of the

more general
in-

aspects of scientific truth or of the results obtained

by applying the
vestigation
'

'

approved methods of physical


which
!

to mind, or even,

is still

more exad-

traordinary, to the nervous system

It

may be

mitted that nothing can well be more interesting than


the treatment of the
writers as
first

of these subjects
;

by such
it

M. Comte and Mr. Spencer

though

can

hardly be necessary again to insist on the fact that no

mere generalisations within the sphere of Science,


though they may furnish materials
should term a
for a
*

Positive
I

Philosophy, can ever be expected to give us what


*

scientific one,
'

any more than a work

which, to start with, assumed the truth of the Three


Creeds,

could constitute

a rational exposition of

Christian evidences.

While, with regard to empirical


it is

psychology and empirical physiology,

only neces-

SUMMARY.
sary to remind the reader of what was
sufficient length in the first chapter,

295

shown

at

namely, that no

progress
research,

made along

these very respectable lines of


it

however much

may

increase our

know-

ledge of mind and of body, can ever produce, or even

perhaps suggest, a solid and satisfactory theory of


the grounds of belief.

Whatever be the

errors
I

and shortcomings of the


I

preceding discussions,

have,

trust, in

the course
(I

of them avoided this particular confusion

mean

between aspects of Science or parts of Science and


Philosophy) which
others.
is

the fertile cause of so

many

The

path of

my

argument has been a


on the other

narrow one, deviating neither into Science on the

one hand nor


it

into Metaphysics

and

if

seems

to run through a to lead to


it,

somewhat uninteresting
goal, yet
it,

region,

and

no desirable
I

or

something

like

must,
is

believe,

be traversed before
If speculations

intellectual repose

finally reached.

which do nothing but destroy seem to


they are,
unsatisfactory

be, as indeed

even from a speculative


not likely to be obtained

point of view, the reader must recollect that definite

and

rational certainty

is

unless

we

first

pass through a stage of definite and

rational doubt.

296

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.

%%i
\,V
^^y

LI

THE

'

\^

NIVEHSlTYj
PRACTICAL RESULTS.
The
this

reader

who
Its

has followed the long argument of


termination at the close of the pre-

Essay

to

ceding chapter,
if

may perhaps be

disposed to ask, what,

any,

is

intended to be the practical result of a


its

piece of criticism so purely destructive in


If
it

character.

is

intended to be a mere dialectical puzzle,

a mere exercise in ingenious objections, or even a


contribution of a

somewhat
it

eccentric kind towards

English Philosophy,

cannot be regarded as of much


If,

general interest outside the sphere of speculation.

on the other hand,


belief,

it

is

intended to influence actual


it

what

effect

can

have, except the produc?

tion of a universal or nearly universal scepticism

an object which can scarcely be thought worth the


trouble both writer and reader must undergo in order
to attain
it.

Before answering these objections,


out that the word
planation
is
*

must point
either the
it

scepticism
It

'

taken without ex-

ambiguous.

may mean
its

intellectual recognition of the

want of evidence, or

may mean

this together

with
critic

consequent unbelief.

Now

if

my

supposed

uses the word in the

PRACTICAL RESULTS.
second of these senses,
ask whether
this question
It

297

might be

well, before askis


if,

ing whether such scientific scepticism


it

desirable, to

is

possible

because
in

as

believe,

must be answered

the negative

if

scepticism of the far-reaching character required

by

the reasoning of this Essay can be produced by no


rigour of demonstration

we

may make
It

ourselves

easy as to any

ill

effect

which, did

exist.

It

might be

expected to produce.

The

only persons

who might

conceivably be embarrassed by the speculative conclusions


I

have so

far

attempted to establish are those

whose devotion
that

to truth takes the form of asserting

we

are in duty

bound
rest.
if it

to

make
this

the strength of

our beliefs vary exactly with the strength of the evi-

dence on which they

But

maxim, though
In the face

occasionally uttered as

were a moral law, would

no doubt be found capable of modification


of an Imperious necessity.
If,

then, scepticism in the second sense be Impos-

sible, Is

scepticism In the

first

sense

scepticism which
of any
it

merely recognises the absence of philosophical proof


or other logical defect In a system of belief

but a speculative Interest

At

first

sight

would
belief,

seem
It

not.

Scepticism which does not destroy

Is

natural to suppose, does nothing.


is

This,

how-

ever,

by no means

necessarily the case.


all

If in the

estimation of

mankind

creeds stood on a philoso-

phic equality, no doubt an attack which affected them


all

equally would probably have

little

or no prac-

298

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT. The only result


it

tical result.

could reasonably proI

duce would be general unbelief, and as


a possible frame of mind.

have just

remarked, general unbelief can hardly be regarded as

But

if in

the estimation of

mankind there

is

the greatest difference in the rela-

tive credibility of prevalent

systems of

belief, if

now

one system now another


standard of certainty,
attack, especially
if it

is

raised to the dignity of a


is

it

plain

that a sceptical

deals with the system which


in favour,

happens at the moment to be


siderable consequences

may have conleast,

consequences, at

quite

as considerable as any which considerations addressed

merely to the reason are ever likely to produce.

To judge,

then, of the true bearing of

arguments

like those contained

in the preceding chapters,

we

must look not merely

at the

arguments themselves,

but also at the general habits of thought which prevail


at the time of their publication.

We

must consider

not only the nature of the agent, but the nature of


the material on which
it is

to act.

What,

then,

is

the position actually taken up

by

various sections of educated

men (we may


?

leave

others out of account), towards the beliefs

by which

we

find

ourselves

surrounded

Which do they
questions,
it

accept,

which do they hesitate about, which do they


reject
?

altogether

These are not


it

is

needless to say, to which


or possible to give
full

is

here either necessary

answers.

But

in

a sentence

or two

can

map

out in outline the creed secretly

PRACTICAL RESULTS.
or avowedly professed

299

by the two

largest

and

most important
concerned.

classes about

whom we

need be

In the opinion of both of these, beliefs tend to


assimilate
first

themselves to one of two types.


is

The

type

that presented

by established
it

science.

The

beliefs

which conform to

would be described

as consistent

and

positive, as arrived at

by recognised
scepticism.
in

methods, and as ultimately resting on primary axioms

whose

certainty

is

beyond the reach of

An

example of the second type may be found

any

of the superstitions, religious or scientific, which are

now by
floating

universal consent regarded as the products


Beliefs of this kind

of fanciful ignorance.

form a

mass of

error,
it is
;

unorganised, unproved, and


the business of true science

inconsistent,

which

gradually to destroy

a duty which

we

are given to

understand

it is

rapidly

and

effectually accomplishing.

Our more advanced thinkers, opinion that they have now reached
from which
the whole
in the indefinite future

those who are of


the point of view
will
it

be given to

human
of

race to look back on the errors


it,

which formerly misled


distribution
beliefs

deal very shortly with the


types.

between these two

Everything which has to do with phenomena, everything which they conceive to belong either to recognised science or to scientific conjecture, they put in

the

first class

it is

either certain, or belongs to the


certain.

type of that which

is

Everything

else they

300

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


:

put in the second


untrue, or
it

it

is

either a superstition
is

and

resembles superstitions and

beyond
indi-

the reach of proof.


I

do not of course mean by these remarks

them of classing Ethics among superstitions. This would be unjust. There is no body of men more careful to let it be understood that the
rectly to accuse

course of their speculations


elevated morality.
is scientific

is

guided by the most

But they hold that Ethics either

or might be

made

so,

and they therefore


it

regard themselves as justified in putting


first

in

the

category with the rest of our certain know-

ledge.^

The second
existing beliefs

class of
I

men whose

attitude towards
is

wish to describe

much more
people

numerous
constitute

(in

England

at least) than the first class,

but much less definite


it

in its opinions.

The
all
'

who

are by no

means clear that


is
'

knowledge

excepting that which

scientific

and deals with

phenomena is either essentially incapable of proof, or else is mere superstition. On the contrary, they are
inclined to admit the existence of a sort of middle

ground, a territory where

we may provisionally place


in respect

the beliefs which, in respect of their subject-matter,

approach to the type of superstitions, while


consigned Religion.
at the

of their probable truth they resemble science.


this region is
*

To
this
dis-

But even of
for

See Appendix,

end of the volume,

a more detailed

cussion of the subject.

PRACTICAL RESULTS.
ambiguous position
its

301

tenure

is

insecure.

Should
has

criticism succeed in doing to the satisfaction of the

people whose opinions

am

describing what

it

long

done

to

the
it

satisfaction

of our advanced

thinkers, should

succeed, namely, in demonstrating


religious

an essential

Inconsistency between

and

scientific belief

then,

if

understand rightly their


rele-

canons of judgment. Religion would at once be

gated to the class at present occupied by delusions

and detected
.

superstitions.
I

It is

not to be doubted,

think, that

most of the

persons

who

speculate at

all

upon the larger problems


days everybody dabbles

now

in

debate

and

in these

more or less in such speculations belong to one of But the point the two classes I have just described.
I

especially desire to insist

on

Is

that though In the


all

first class

are to be found almost

those

who

dls-

"belleve in Religion, while the


all

second includes almost


yet, that

those

who

believe In

It

may be
infinite),

the practical differences

however great between them (and

their practical differences are in

some cases almost

they nevertheless agree in thinking that no

more

certain warrant for a creed can be found than

the fact that

Science supports

It;

no more

fatal

objection to one, than the fact that Science contradicts


it.

The
tific

result of this

is

not only that


In

we

are ex-

pected to interest ourselves

the effect which scien-

discoveries have had, or

may be

expected to

302

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.

have, on the historic evolution of religious thought,

but that
tion

it

seems to be assumed that the

logical rela-

which subsists between the doctrines of actual

science

and of actual day

religion
;

is

a fact of transcendent

theological importance
versies of the

so that the serious contro-

are, in fact, little


'

of what

is

called the

conflict

more than phases between Science and


discovery which

Religion.'

There

is

no

scientific

has not therefore an importance altogether disproportionate to


is

its

purely scientific bearing, because there

none which may not suggest or confirm a theory


with something long held
to

inconsistent

be an

essential part of Religion,

and which may not thus


prompted

become the centre of a


far

bitter controversy,

more by

theological or anti-theological zeal than

by a dispassionate love of scientific knowledge. I might insist on the evil done by such a state of
things both to Religion and to Science, but at this

moment
springs.

wish rather to enter

my

protest against

the principle from which the evil itself ultimately

Has Science any

claim to be thus set up as

the standard of belief?

Is there

any ground whatscientific teach;

ever for regarding conformity with

ing as an essential condition of truth

and non-

conformity with
error
?

it
is,

as an
it

unanswerable proof of

If there

cannot be drawn from the


itself.

nature of the scientific system


in the

We have seen
of
its

preceding pages

how a close examination

philosophical structure reveals the existence of almost

PRACTICAL RESULTS.
every possible philosophical defect.
that whether Science

303

We

have seen

be regarded from the point of


inferences, or the general rela-

view of its premises,


tion of its parts,
it is

its

found defective; and

that the ordinary proofs

we have seen which philosophers and men


fit

of science have thought

to give of

its

doctrines

are not only mutually inconsistent, but are such as

would convince nobody who did not


ever,

start (as,

how-

we

all

do

start),

with an implicit and indestruc-

tible confidence in the truth of that

which had to
th^e;
is,

be proved.
fidence.
I

am
it.

far

from complaining of
complaint rather

con-

share

My

that of

two creeds which, from a philosophical point of view, stand, so far as I can judge, upon a perfect equality,
one should be set up as a standard to which the
other must necessarily conform.

am not insensible that to some of my readers may now appear to have reached an extremity of
I

paradox

far

beyond the

limits of sober reason.

Even

the existence of thirteen chapters of argument which,

whether good or bad, are undoubtedly


fail

serious,

may

to convince

them that

am

altogether In earnest.

It

must-be admitted that such hardness of belief on

their part has

some

excuse.
Its

Science in recent times.


worlds, the

The vast extension of new conquests In old

new worlds
Its

It

has discovered to conquer,

the fruitfulness of

hypotheses, the palpable witness

which

material results

bear to the excellence of

Its

methods,

may

well lead

men

to think that the

means

304

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.

by which these triumphs have been attained are above To the reach even of the most audacious criticism.
"be told in the face of facts

Hke these that Science

stands on no higher a level of certainty than what

some people seem

to look
in

on as a dying superstition,

may

easily

excite

certain

minds a momentary

doubt as to the seriousness of the objector.


a doubt
if

Such
But
far,

is

not likely to be more than transient.

any reader, who has accompanied


it,

me

so

seriously entertains

can only invite him, since

he regards
the
fallacies

my

conclusions as absurd, to point out


vitiate the

which

reasoning on which

those conclusions are finally based.


I

have sometimes thought that the


might be conveniently

parallel be-

tween Science and Theology, regarded as systems of


belief,

illustrated

by framing
all familiar.

a refutation of the former on the model of certain


attacks

on the

latter with

which we are

We

might begin by showing how crude and connotions of primitive

tradictory are the

man, and

even of the cultivated man

In his unreflective

mo-

ments, respecting the object-matter of scientific beliefs.

We
it is

might point out the rude anthropomoranthropomortill

phism which underlies them, and show how impossible

to get altogether rid of this

phism, without refining away the object-matter


it

becomes an

unintelligible abstraction.
scientific apologists.

then turn to the

We might We should

show how the

authorities of one age differed from

PRACTICAL RESULTS.

305

those of another In their treatment of the subject,

and how the authorities of the same age

differed

among themselves
tems one
errors In detail

then

after taking

up

their sys-

after another,

and showing

their Individual

we

should comment at length on

the strange obstinacy they evinced in adhering to


their conclusions,
not.

whether they could prove them or


according to

It is at this point, perhaps, that

usage we might pay a passing tribute to morality.

With

all

the proper circumlocutions,

we should

sug-

gest that so singular an agreement respecting

some

of the most

difficult points

requiring proof, together

with so strange a divergence and so obvious a want


of cogency In the nature of the proofs offered, could

not be accounted for on any hypothesis consistent

with

the

Intellectual

honesty of

the

apologists.

Without attributing motives

to Individuals,

we should
and

hint politely, but not obscurely, that prejudice

education In some, the fear of differing from the


majority, or the fear of losing a lucrative place In
others,

had been allowed


;

to

warp the impartial course


scientific

of investigation
philosophers, in
ful

and we should lament that

many

respects so amiable

and use-

a body of men, should allow themselves so often to

violate principles
tiously

which they openly and even ostentaAfter this moral display,

avowed.

we should

turn from the philosophers

who

are occupied with

the rationale of the subject to the main body of


of science

men

who

are actually engaged in teaching and

3o6

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


Fully acknowledging their

research.

we

should yet be compelled to ask

many merits, how it comes

about that they are so ignorant of the controversies

which rage round the very foundations of their subject,

and how they can reconcile


self-respect,

it

with their intellectual

when they

are asked

some

vital

question

(say respecting the proof of the law of Universal

Causation, or the existence of the external world),


either to profess total ignorance of the subject, or to
offer in reply
It is

some shreds
is

of

worn out metaphysics

true,

they might say that a profound study of


not consistent either widi teaching
;

these subjects

or with otherwise advancing the cause of Science

but of course to this excuse


obvious rejoinder
cause of Science,
that,
it

we

should

make

the

before trying to advance the


to discover

would be as well

whether such a thing as true Science really existed. This done, we should have to analyse the actual

body of
ance
;

scientific

truth presented
its

for

our accept-

to

show how, while


its

conclusions are inin

consistent,

premises are either lost

a meta-

physical haze, or else are unfounded

and gratuitous
for

assumptions

after

which

it

would only remain


to

us to compose an eloquent peroration on the debt

which mankind owe to Science, and


masters

the great
that the

who have
it

created

it,

and

to

mourn

progress of criticism should have


to count

left

us no choice but

among

the beautiful but baseless dreams

PRACTICAL RESULTS.

307

which have so often deluded the human race with


the

phantom of

certain knowledge.

Of
parallel

course a parody

of

ought rather to say a

this sort
reflect

could serve no purpose but to


their ordinary

make people

on the boldness of
But
this alone

assumption respecting the comparative certainty of


Science and Religion.
small gain
;

would be no

since in the present state of opinion a

suspicion as to the truth of that assumption seems

the last thing that naturally suggests itself

Why

should this be so

That men of Science should


Is

exaggerate the claims of Science


donable, but

natural and par-

why

the ordinary public,

whose know-

ledge of Science

Is

confined to what they can extract

from fashionable lectures and popular handbooks,


should do
so.
It

is

not quite easy to understand.


Is

Perhaps

shall

be told that there

a very simple

explanation of this strange unanimity of opinion

namely, the fact that the opinion


reply that, even
If

Is

true.

To

this
I

we

dismiss

all

the reasons
is

have

given for thinking that the opinion


objector will
(of

not true, the

hardly assert that the general public


I

whom

alone

have been speaking) have ever


the sort of reasons
to

made themselves acquainted with


still

by which alone the opinion can be known


less that

be

true,

they have taken the trouble to weigh


While,
if it

those reasons with care.

be further sug-

gested that they are guided by an unerring instinct


in

such matters,

answer that
X
2

their instinct cannot

3o8

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


for history sufficiently

always be unerring,
that
it

shows

has not always been the same.


in

Another reason may be given, which


accounts for the
fact,

part
re-

though

after all

it

only
It

moves the

difficulty

a stage further back.


is

may
re-

be alleged that the popular opinion


flection of the

merely a

popular literature, and that the truth


I

of the assumption
rally believed
it is

am

calling in question

is

gene-

by the many who


and up
exists

read, simply because


write.

constantly asserted
is

by the few who

This
is

no doubt

accurate,

to a certain point

an

explanation.

There

now

a kind of literature,

already large and of growing importance, produced

by experts

for the benefit of those


' ;

who

desire to be

'generally informed

which, unlike most ephemeral

literature, leads public opinion rather

than follows
it

it.

Of

course the greater part of

this,

whether

consists

of handbooks or of review articles, has no bearing

whatever on the relation which ought to exist between


Religion and Science, or with the positive evidence
that

may

exist for either.

But just as popular accounts


an educated but busy public
as possible, about as
little

of chemistry, physiology, or history appear in answer


to the natural desire of
for as

much knowledge

many
:

things as possible, with as

trouble as possible

so there are easily found eminent authors anxious


to

purvey

for that apparently

increasing

class of

persons

who

aspire to be advanced thinkers,


their

but
for

who

like to

have

advanced thinking done

PRACTICAL RESULTS.
them.
ductions

309

Now
is

the very starting point of these prothe principle that Science


is

the one

thing certain, that everything which cannot be proved

by

scientific

means

is

incapable of proof, and that


inconsistent

everything which

is

with
is

Science

is

thereby disproved.

And
'

since

this

a doctrine
in

which
the
'

is

constantly reiterated, since

it is

one which

struggle for existence

has the great advantage

of being not only easily stated, but easily under-

stood

we need

not be surprised that a not very


it,

critical

public should readily believe


to
it

without taking

any great pains


evidence.

examine

into the nature of its

How

comes about that the distinguished


themselves never be troubled
solidity
is,

authors

who

so serenely take for granted this prin-

ciple of criticism should

by any suspicion as
to understand.
It

to

its

admit, harder
I

would have required,


less philosophical

should

have supposed, much

knowledge

and philosophical acumen than that possessed, for example, by Mr. Leslie Stephen or Professor
Huxley, to suggest to their minds doubts as to the
rational character of the

dogmatic system
;

in

which

they so confidently put their trust

and, once sug-

gested and unanswered, the smallest doubt should be


sufficient to

prevent them raising that system into a


all

standard by which the value of


belief

other systems of

might properly be estimated.

Without, however, making any special attack on


individuals, the nature of

my

indictment against the

3IO

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.

general body of anti-religious controversialists

may

be easily

stated.

The

force of their attack

depends

in the last resort

think they find,

upon the discrepancy they find, or between Religion and Science. It


in,

must

require, therefore, a belief

at all events, the

comparative certitude of Science.


this belief finally

On what
to
frail

does

depend

Are we

suppose that
foundation

they rest

its

whole weight on the

supplied by the contradictory fragments of Philosophy

we have been discussing through all these chapters ? Or are we to suppose that their belief is a mere
assumption, with no other recommendation than that
it is

agreeable to the spirit of the age


it

Or

are

we

to suppose that

is

established

by some

esoteric

proof,

known only

to the few,

and not yet published


?

for the benefit of the

world at large

The

first

of these alternatives implies in the thinkers of


I

whom
when

speak the existence of an easy credulity

in singular

contrast with the acute scepticism they display

dealing with beliefs they do not happen to share.

The second writers who


Reason, and

is,

think, hardly

worthy of a

class of

appeal so often

and so earnestly

to

who

particularly pride themselves

on

proportioning the strength of their convictions to the


strength of the evidence on which they rest.

But

if

the third alternative represents the real state of the


case,

we have,

think, a right to ask that the conceal-

ment which the opponents of Religion are


with so remarkable an unanimity should

practising
to

come

an

PRACTICAL RESULTS.

311

end, and that since the philosophy of Science exists,

it

should forthwith be produced for our enlightenment.


It is

but justice, however, to the philosophic and

literary advocates of

extreme

scientific pretensions,
I

to

remark that the blame which


in part

have been laying

on them should
I

be shared by theologians.

do not mean, of course, that many theologians of

repute could be found prepared to assert that Religion

must either be proved wholly by

scientific

methods, and be shown to harmonise completely


with scientific conclusions, or else be summarily
rejected
;

but

do assert that the extreme anxiety

exhibited by certain of them to establish the perfect

congruity of Science and Religion

the existence of
end of whose
or to

a whole class of
labours appears

apologists,'

the

to

be

to

explain,

explain

away, every appearance of contradiction between


the

two

are
^

facts

which

naturally

suggest

the

conclusion that the assumption


thinkers
is

made by

the Free-

a legitimate one.

Let

me

not be misunderstood.

Truth

is

one.

Therefore any attempt to reconcile inconsistent or

not easy to find a single word to describe the opponents of is altogether free from objection. Most of the terms which suggest themselves have either acquired a somewhat offensive connotation, or are inexact. One or both of these defects attaches to the words ^ Infidel,' Atheist/ ' Agnostic,' and ' Sceptic' I have
^

It is

Religion which

'

pitched upon

because, if it suggests comparisons not altogether flattering to the modern assailants of theology, on the other
'
'

Freethinker

hand, this

is

word

credits

made up for by the fact that the strict meaning of the them with a virtue to which they have no exclusive title.

312

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


is

apparently inconsistent beliefs

in itself legitimate/

and
the

in so far as apologetics
I

aim

at this

and

at nothing

more,

have not a word


in

to say against
is

them

but

manner

which the controversy

carried on,

even from the theological

side, occasionally

suggests

the idea, not only that a consistent creed embracing

both
at

scientific

and

religious doctrines

some time or other, but that it now, and by no process more elaborate than
lopping off from Religion everything which
exactly agreeable with Science.

may be made ought to be made


that of
is

not

Yet the apologists should be the


is

first

to recognise

the fact that this Procrustean method of reconciliation

not one which ought ever to be applied to their


Its

theological convictions.

very ground and

justiis

fication is the idea that enforced consistency

the

shortest road to truth.

But

if

this
?

be

so,

what are

we

to think of religious mysteries

Religious mysteries
belief

suppose to be objects of

which so nearly elude the utmost stretch of


in

our imagination, that they can be only vaguely

and imperfectly described

words

or of such a

nature that any definite attempt to express their


attributes in formulae results in a contradiction in

terms.
tion,

Brought face

to face with such a contradic-

man may pursue one

of three courses
is,

he

may

reject both

contradictories that
;

refuse to

believe in the thing described

he

may

accept one

of the contradictories, and thus escape inconsistency

PRACTICAL RESULTS.
at the cost
(it

3(3

may

be) of completeness

or he may-

accept both contradictories, thinking thereby to obtain,

under however unsatisfactory a form, the


is

fullest

measure of truth which he


This
last

at present able to grasp.

course

is

the one which in

some

cases

all

(even merely natural) theologians have pursued.


is

It

therefore a matter of surprise that so

many

of

them
itself

thinking,

as they must, that religious truth

cannot always be so expressed as to be consistent with

should argue as

if it

ought necessarily to be

expressed so as to be consistent with Science.

Perhaps the reader

may be
its

inclined to object to
if

the foregoing considerations, that


to support Religion in

they are adapted

existing shape, they are

not less well adapted to support any Religion how-

ever absurd,

or

any superstition however

gross.

Arguments against one form of

belief are rebutted,

by rendering argument against any form of belief Immunity from one kind of criticism is impossible.
obtained only by the costly process of dethroning
de facto authority in the realm of opinion,
all

and

intro-

ducing into
confusion.

it,

thereby, every species of license and

Before considering the precise extent to which


these forebodings as to the consequences of philosophic scepticism are really well founded,
I

must point
I

out that for the consequences themselves

am

in

no

way

responsible.

They

are the results of an inves-

tigation of a purely speculative character conducted

314

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


all

with

the impartiality in
I

my

power

and though

admit that

should probably never have troubled


I

myself to put them into shape, had


that

not hoped
results,

they might have some practical


if it

the

thought of those results

has prompted the comin

mencement of the undertaking has


its

no way modified
should

course.

Even, therefore,

if

my conclusions
I

tend to foster forms of belief with which neither the


Freethinkers nor
full
I

happen

to agree,

shall

expect

absolution from

a body of writers

who have

constituted themselves the especial champions of the

doctrine that no enquiry should be discouraged out

of mere apprehension of

its

consequences.
itself.
I

To

return to the objection


first

It

must be

noted, In the
practically
in strict

place, that

when

suggest that

we need

not or cannot regulate our beliefs


cri-

accordance with the results of rational

ticism,

I
I

am
It

driven to

make

the suggestion not be-

cause

have used reason more

less freely,
is

but because

have used

freely than

usual upon subjects


rule,

respecting which

people,

as

accept

their

opinion without

much

preliminary examination.

But

this unfettered use of


.irrational

Reason need only produce an

and therefore unsatisfactory and provisional

attitude of

mind when we are dealing with Science


i.e.

as a whole,

as a single system of belief;

and

it

by

no means excludes or tends

to exclude the use of


for the purparts,

Reason within that

(or

any other) system

pose of harmonising or co-ordinating

its

nor

PRACTICAL RESULTS.
even from using
for the
it

315

to

modify

details of the

system

purpose of producing as much consistency

as possible between the different creeds which

we

happen

to hold.

Any

person, therefore, taking


liberty,

my
nay

view of these questions, would be at

would be bound,
the

to regulate his beliefs within the

sphere of Science according to rational principles, to

same extent and

in

precisely the
;

same way as

the ordinary

man

of science does

the only differ-

ence between them being that the sceptical philo-

sopher does so

in the full consciousness,

and the man

of science in utter unconsciousness, that the system

he

is

dealing with

is,

as a whole, incapable of
if

any

rational defence.

Of course,

Religion

is

thought

to stand in this respect on a level with

Science (a

point which

it

has not been

my

business to discuss),

the

same remarks, miUatis mutandis, may properly


it.

be applied to
It

appears then that the practical conclusions


sceptical philosophy

draw from a
tendency to

have

little

or no

alter the internal structure of

any actual

or possible creed.

But

it

may

still

be objected that

they give free scope to the simultaneous existence


of any

number

of creeds, no matter

how

foolish or

how
that

contradictory these

may happen
it

to be.

Now

in considering this question,


I

must be recollected
to present
I

have not presented or attempted


in

any arguments

favour of Theology.
attempted
to

have
the

shown indeed,

or

show,

that

3i6

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


its

fundamental assumption of most of


altogether baseless.

assailants is

But

after such

demonstration

the positive motives which produce theological belief

remain

precisely

what they were


is

they

are

not

strengthened because Science


losophically unsound, they
if

proved to be phi-

would not be weakened


extent, therefore,

a complete philosophy of Science were to be

produced which
this

to-morrow.
attack

The

to

on Science might theoretically


is

produce a chaos of conflicting creeds


determine.
It will

easy to

preserve from destruction those

creeds and those

only which, while they have a

claim on our beliefs like that possessed by Science

and Theology,
to be, in

are, as

Theology

is

by some supposed
If there

contradiction with Science.

be

any system of belief answering to


its

this description,

adherents are welcome to any assistance they can


I

derive from the arguments of this Essay.

can
not

only say, for

my

part, that if

it

exists,

know

where

it

is

to

be found.

There
to

is

one more question suggested by what

has been said in the course of the preceding remarks,

which the reader


wish to

may

may desire an answer. He know what constitute the claims on


*

our belief which

assert to be possessed alike


I

by

Science and Theology, and which

put forward as

the sole practical foundation on which our convictions


ultimately rest.

In dealing with this subject

it

can,

suppose, be

PRACTICAL RESULTS.

317

hardly necessary to repeat what the whole tenor of


this

Essay goes

to prove, namely, that these Claims


consist, so far as Science at least

to Belief
is

do not

concerned, in reasons.

Whatever they may

be,

they are not rational grounds of conviction, raised

by
It

their

very nature above the reach of


to describe

criticism.

would be more proper

them as a

kind of inward inclination or impulse, falling far


short of

should perhaps rather say, altogether

differing In kind

from

philosophic

certitude, leav-

ing the reason therefore unsatisfied, but amounting


nevertheless to a practical
the
effects

cause of

belief,

from

of which we do not even desire to be

released.
not,

The

object of this unreasoning belief


It

is

however, as

ought to be

if

our creeds were

truly rational, the ultimate premises from

which
:

all
Is

the other elements of the creed are inferred


rather the cree
1

it

as a whole, or even certain arbitrarily


it.

selected parts of

In the case of Science, indeed,


Its

this can hardly be otherwise, since


(as

premises are
;

we have

seen) not yet properly determined

while

in so far as

they are determined, they are explicitly

known

to but

few persons

and of those few there

is

probably not one

who
it

did not believe in Science bein relation to its premises,


it,

fore he thought of

and
such

who would

not continue to believe in

if

all

thoughts were obliterated from

his mind.

The

reader may, perhaps, think that

we ought

not to rest content with anything so unsatisfactory

3i8

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


*

as this
is

Impulse.'

If so,

am
;

quite of his mind.

It

assuredly unsatisfactory

and assuredly we ought


I

not to rest content with

it.

know

of no means,

however, by which the


died,

evil

can at present be rem.ediscovery of such

and
is

am

sure that the

means tomed

not likely to be hastened by the claims to

rationality

which the assailants of Religion are accusput forth in favour of their

to

own more
this
*'

limited creed.

But perhaps
pulse
"

it

will

be

said,
is

'

Grant that

im-

of which you speak

the whole motive on


their

account of which mankind accept


beliefs, still

stock of

you have not put Science and Religion


since
it

on an
pulse"

equality,
is

is

obvious that the

*'

im-

much more
it

universal in the case of the


If the

former than

is

in the case of the latter.'

comparative universality here claimed for the Scientific

impulse

was measured by the

comparative

number of persons who accepted respectively the general body of Scientific and Religious doctrines, I
apprehend that the objection
I

have just stated


fact.

would have no standing ground on

There
it.

is,

however, a better interpretation to be put on

We

may
in

conceive the

objection

to

mean
that

that

while

nobody does or can possibly


some
scientific doctrines

exist without believing


fire

food

nourishes
those
or

among
gion,

we can find plenty of persons who have either never heard of Reliwho have persuaded themselves that

as

burns or

PRACTICAL RESULTS.
Religion
is

319

false

who
The
it

street arabs or

advanced thinkers

do not accept even the smallest and most


fact In this case is

perverted fragment of religious truth.

undoubted

but to bring

forward as an objection to
error.

my

view implies a
the

double

It implies, in the first place, that


I

impulse of which

speak

is

a logical ground for

accepting Religion or Science, as the case

may be

and

it

implies, in the second place, that this


is

supposed

ground

of the kind which

have already sufficiently


of
*

dealt with,^ under the

name

The Argument from


critic,

General Consent.'
supposes that
I

My

imaginary

in

short,

regard an ultimate impulse to believe


it
;

a creed as a reason for believing


also that this ultimate
*

and he supposes
Neither

impulse

'

is

a better reason, the

more people there are who feel


of these opinions
Is

its

influence.

accurate

on the contrary, they


I

imply a

total

misconception as to the theory


to explain.

am
re-

endeavouring

This theory

may be

garded as having two sides


other positive.
is

one
rate,
;

negative and the

The
is,

negative side, the truth of which

capable of demonstration, amounts to an asserat

tion that Religion

any

no worse

off

than

Science in the matter of proof that neither from the


fact (If fact
It

be) that Religion only imperfectly har-

monises with experience,


while

nor from the fact that

men

of science agree substantially with each

other in their methods and in their results, theolo^

Cf. ch. vii.

320

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.

glans differ profoundly from each other In both, nor

from any other known difference between the two


systems can any legitimate conclusion be drawn as
to their comparative certitude.

The

positive side,
to

on the other hand, which cannot properly be held


supply any rational ground of assent, and
Is

In

no

way
this

capable of actual
I

demonstration amounts to

that
If

and an

Indefinite

number

of other per-

sons,

we contemplate

Religion and

Science as

unproved systems of
feel

belief standing side


;

by

side,
Is,

a practical need for both

and

If

this

need

in the case of

those few and fragmentary

scientific

truths

by which we regulate our animal

actions, of

an especially imperious and indestructible character

on
be

the other hand, the need for religious truth,


It

rooted as
nature.
Is

Is

in

the loftiest region of our moral


not, If

one from which we would

we

could,

freed.

But as no legitimate argument can be


this

founded on the mere existence of


pulse,

need or Im-

so no legitimate argument can be founded

on any differences which psychological analysis may


detect between different cases of
its

manifestation.

We are
useless

in this

matter unfortunately altogether outof

side the sphere


to

Reason.

It

must always be
Impulse

discuss
is

whether a particular

towards a creed
of the

either of the right strength or


It
;

right quality to justify a belief In

be-

cause a belief can, in strictness, be justified by no


impulse, whatever be
Its

strength or whatever

Its

PRACTICAL RESULTS.
quality.

321

On
with

the

other hand,

let

no

man who
*

agrees

the reasoning of this Essay say,


in

cannot believe

any creed which


I

know

to

be

without evidence, merely because


tive

feel

a subjec-

need

for

it,'

unless he

is

prepared to limit his


metaphysical)

beliefs to those

detached
I

scientific (or

propositions which are,

apprehend, the only ones


it

he must

in practice

accept whether he likes

or not,

or unless he can find

Science which

is

some motive for believing in not an impulse and at the same


Let him,
if

time

is

not a reason.

he

will,

accept

Science and reject Religion, but

an explanation of his

him not give as behaviour an argument which


let

would be as
were engaged

appropriate
in

or inappropriate

if

he

showing why he accepted Religion

and

rejected Science.

The

doctrine that no rational justification exists


different attitude

for adopting a

towards the two

systems of

belief,

depends,

it

should be noted, not

only on the fact that

we

are without any rational

ground
fact that

for believing in Science,

but also on the

we

are without any rational ground for de-

termining the logical relation which ought to subsist

between Science and Religion.


habitually

The
is

Freethinkers

assume

that this relation

one of dependif

ence on the part of Religion, and that

there exist

any reason

for believing

it

at

all,

these reasons are

to be found scattered
trines of Science
;

up and down among the doc-

confusing apparently the historic

322

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.

reasoning by which particular religious truths are


established, with the deeper sentiments

by which
Those,

Religion
these

itself is

produced, and in the light of which

historic

reasonings are conducted.


this

however,
of
it,

who make

assumption
I

offer

no proof

nor do they, so

far as

know, even indicate


it

the kind of proof of which they conceive


susceptible.

to

be

They

accept

it,

as they accept so

many

other assumptions, not only without having any evi-

dence for
of),

it

whatever (which

should not complain

but without being apparently conscious that any


is

evidence whatever

required.

In the absence then of reason to the contrary,


I

am

content to regard the

two great creeds by


lives

which we attempt to regulate our

as

rest-

ing in the main upon separate bases.


therefore, as neither of

So

long,

them can

lay claim to phi-

losophic

probability,

discrepancies

which exist or

may

hereafter arise between

them cannot be conBut


if

sidered as bearing

more heavily against the one


a really
to

than they do against the other.


valid philosophy, which

would support Science

the exclusion of Religion, or Religion to the exclusion of Science,

were discovered, the case would and


it

be somewhat

different,

would undoubtedly be
is

difficult for that

creed which

not philosophically

established to exist beside the other while in contradiction to


ble.
it

difficult, I say,

not absolutely impossi-

In the meanwhile, unfortunately, this does not

PRACTICAL RESULTS.
seem
likely to

323

become a

practical question.
is

What

has to be determined

now

the course which ought

to be pursued with regard to discrepancies

between

systems, neither of which can be regarded as philosophically established, but neither of which can

we

consent to surrender
it

and on

this subject, of course,

is

only possible to

perhaps

make suggestions which may commend themselves to the practical inthough they cannot compel his
In

stincts of the reader,

intellectual assent.

my

judgment, then,

if

these

discrepancies are such that, they can be smoothed

away by concessions on
but
if,

either side

which do not

touch essentials, the concessions should be

made

which

is

not at present the case, consistency

can only be purchased by practically destroying one


or other of the conflicting creeds,
I

should elect
I

In

favour of inconsistency

not

because

should be

content with knowledge, which being self-contradictory must needs be in

because a logical
destruction of
all

some particulars false, but harmony obtained by the arbitrary


discordant elements

may be bought
and necessary

at far too great a


truth.
It Is

sacrifice of essential

not probable that to these opinions (whose


is,

correctness

from the nature of the


I

case, altogether

Incapable of demonstration)
of

shall obtain the assent


;

many
I

scientific

philosophers

still

less is

it

likely

that

shall

convert any of those more declared


to
2

assailants

of Theology
Y

whom

have alluded

324

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


But
If

several times in this chapter.

the arguments

of this Essay prove Insufficient (as they doubtless


will) to

Induce these writers to agree with the Theo-

logical opinions to
effect

which
In

adhere, perhaps they

may
ex-

some

alteration

the

mode
Is

In

which a perpresent

fectly

legitimate

disagreement
I

at

pressed and defended.


reason

do

not, of course, see

any

why

the Freethinkers should not continue to

derive what advantage they may, from the use of


these convenient phrases, by a judicious employ-

ment of which

It

is

possible to Imply that they are

in possession of the last secrets revealed

by Time,

while their adversaries are


toils

still

struggling in the

of ancestral

prejudice.
instance,

There need be no
to
their
*

objection taken, for

advertising

their opinions as the Indications of


results

progress,* the

of

culture,' or the offspring

of

'

advanced

thought.*
true,

The

direct facts so stated are in a sense


not, perhaps,
it

and the implications intended are


think,

very damaging to their opponents.


well,
I

if

would be the sanction of Reason were less


Invoked
In

But

often

and

less loudly

favour of opinions

with which, so far as at present appears. Reason has

very
the

little

to do.

It

would be well

If

an appeal to
call it

religious
will

need, instinct,

impulse

you

were no
in
if

what

longer openly asserted to be an

argument

favour of Theology so

practically concedes the

whole

case,

weak that it by writers who

would be puzzled

they were required to produce

PRACTICAL RESULTS.
anything better in favour of Science.

325

And

It

would

be well

If

an examination

Into the truth of Religion

were

less

persistently inculcated as a moral duty,

Incumbent

on

all

believers,

by philosophers,
Is

to

whom
at
all,

it

never seems

to occur that Religion


if

not

the only creed to which a rule of that kind,

valid

would necessarily apply.

It

is

not necessary,
in

think, that

should add

anything more

explanation of
I

my attitude towards
in

those positive beliefs which

hold

harmony

with,

though not as conclusions from,the negative


contained in the body of this Essay.
I

criticisms

am

painfully

aware of how few there

are,

even among those few

whom the dry and


does not repel,

abstruse character of the argument


are likely to be the least in symI

who

pathy with the point of view


defend.
It will

have been trying to

hardly find favour either with the

ordinary believer or with the ordinary unbeliever.

As

regards the former, indeed,

console myself

by thinking
regards the

that the only practical

end

desire

has been in their case already attained.


latter,
I

But as

am
if

afraid that

have said

nothing which they will even consider relevant to


their

own

difficulties

they have any

respecting
of

the choice of a creed.

They

either ignore or are


in

without that religious impulse,

the absence

which

it

is

useless to clear away,

by any merely

326

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


It

dialectical process, the obstructions that, did

exist,
is

would hinder

its

free development.

Their case

not one that can be reached by argument, and argu-

ment is all I have to offer. Even could I command the most fervid and persuasive eloquence, could I rouse with power the slumbering feelings which find
in

Religion their only lasting satisfaction

could

compel every reader to long earnestly and with


passion for

some

living share in that Faith


life

which

has been the spiritual

of millions ignorant alike


is

of Science and Philosophy, this

not the occasion

on which

to

do

so.

should shrink from dragging

into a controversy

pitched throughout In another


full

key, thoughts

whose

and intimate nature

it

is

given to few adequately to express, and which, were


I

one of those few, would seem strangely misplaced


dry and scholastic argument
is

at the conclusion of this

In

any

case,

however, such a task


I

beyond

my

powers, and therefore


I

cannot hope that


it

my

reasoning, even could


able, will

suppose

to

be unanswereffect

produce any but a negative


the

on those
truth
in

who approach
that indifferent

question of religious

mood which they would perhaps


as
intellectual

themselves

describe

impartiality.

There may, however, be some of another temper,

who would
all

regard Religion as the most precious of

inheritances

if

only

it

were true

who

surrender

slowly and unwillingly, to what they conceive to be

unanswerable argument, convictions with which yet

PRACTICAL RESULTS.
they can scarcely bear to part
;

327

who,

for the

sake of

Truth, are prepared to give up what they had been

wont
hope

to think of as their guide in this


In another,

life,

their

and

to take refuge in

strange substitutes for

some of the ReHgion provided by the


It is

ingenuity of these latter times.


that to
to

not impossible

some

of these, hesitating between arguments


find

which they can

no reply and a creed which

they feel to be necessary, the line of thought suggested by this chapter

may be

of service.

Should

such prove to be the case, this Essay will have an


interest

and a
I

utility

beyond that of pure Speculasatisfied.

tion

and

shall

be more than

328

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.

NOTE ON THE DISCREPANCY BETWEEN


RELIGION AND SCIENCE.
In the preceding chapter there was a good deal of
ence to the discrepancy which exists, or
exist,
is

refer-

supposed to
the

between Religion and Science.

To determine

amount of such discrepancy, or even to decide whether it has any reality or not, was in no way necessary to my main argument but it may be convenient to inactual
;

dicate in a note the general view which I should be dis-

posed to take of a question which, though


has been greatly exaggerated,
is

its

importance

not without interest.

The

discord between Science and Religion has referif

ence chiefly,

not entirely, to the interference by the

supernatural with the natural, which Religion requires us


to believe in
;

and the amount of

this discord
scientific
if

may

be

measured by the importance of the


determined at
sistent with
all

doctrines

which such a belief would require us to give up,


hazards to

we were
I

make

the two systems conshall


is

each other.

In discussing this subject,

assume, for the sake of argument, that this interference


not,

as has been often suggested, produced immediately

by

the operation of

some unknown though natural law


opinion
is

but that the

common

correct which attributes

it

to the direct action of a Supernatural Power.


tion therefore
beliefs

The quesscientific

we have

to ask,
if

is

this

What

do we contradict

we

assert that a Supernatural

Power has on various occasions


tion of natural laws
?
'

interfered with the


it

opera-

We

contradict,'

will

be replied,

RELIGION AND SCIENCE.


*the belief in the uniformity of Nature/

329
Is the belief

which

is
?

thus contradicted particularly important then to


'

Science
*

So important/ many people would answer,


at the foundation of all our scientific reasoning,

that

it lies

as well as

all

of our practical judgments/ This

understand

to be the opinion of the

two most recent assailants of


know, have touched on the sub*

Theology who, so
ject

far as I

namely, the

author of

Supernatural Religion

'

and

Mr. Leslie Stephen.

The former

of these, whose treatment


is

of the whole question suggests a suspicion that he

hardly

equal to dealing with the profounder problems which he

has undertaken to solve, Stephen, however,


is

need not further allude


to the laws of

to.
*

Mr.
If
it

may

be quoted with advantage.


*

not contrary,' he says,


shall

Nature that the

dead

be raised, or one loaf feed a thousand men, the


If such a phe-

occurrence of the fact does not prove that an Almighty

Being has suspended the laws of Nature.

nomenon

is

contrary to the laws of Nature, then a proof

that the events had occurred would establish the inference. But, on the other hand,
lieve that the evidence
it

must always be simpler


mistaken
;

to beis

is

/<?r such

a belief

obviously consistent with a belief in the uniformity of NaturCy

which
soning.

is the sole

gtiarantee {whatever

its origiii)

of our reathus im-

Really to evade Hume's reasoning

is

possible,' &c.^

From
italics, it

the sentence in this extract which I have put in

would appear that Mr. Stephen

holds,

and thinks

that

Hume

implicitly held, the doctrine that a belief in


is

occasional Divine interference


lief in

inconsistent with that beis


*

the uniformity of Nature which


I

the sole guarantee


this

of our reasoning.'

doubt whether
incorrect.

was Hume's

opinion
*

in

any case

it is

'English Thought

in the

Eighteenth Century,'

p. 341.

330

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


The scientific
belief which, with least impropriety, may-

be termed the

'

sole guarantee

'

of our reasoning,
is
;

is

that

belief in the uniformity of

Nature which

equivalent to

a belief in the law of universal causation

which again

is

equivalent to a belief that similar antecedents are always

followed

by

similar consequents.

But

this belief, as the


is

least reflection will

convince the reader,

in

no way

in-

consistent with a belief in supernatural interference.

belief in the uniformity of Nature,


efl"ects

which

is

equi-

valent to a belief that natural

are uniformly pre-

ceded by natural causes, no doubt


supernatural interference
it is
;

is

inconsistent with

but of what pieces of reasoning

our sole guarantee, except those directed to show that


interfer-

in

any given case the hypothesis of supernatural


I

ence must be rejected,


It
is

am

not able to say.

clear, then, that the

most important discrepancy


alleged to exist between

which has been, or could

be,

Science and Religion has no real existence.


great general
principle

The only
philosophers

on which

scientific

have as yet been able to


touched.

rest their scientific creed is

un-

Let us therefore now turn our attention to the

more
sider

special

and derivative doctrines of Science, and conthey are affected by a belief in supernatural

how

far

interference.

In this enquiry
distinction

it

will

be convenient to keep

in

mind a
concrete

drawn

in the fourth chapter of this essay, be-

tween what were there called the abstract and the


parts of Science.

By

the abstract parts of Science were

meant the general laws by which phenomena are connected by the concrete parts were meant (what may be
;

sufficiently described as) particular matters of fact.

Does, then. Theology require us to modify in any our beliefs concerning the abstract part of Science

way
t

RELIGION AND SCIENCE.


apprehend that
as true
it

331

does not.

Such
if

beliefs are in

themselves

and as

fully

proved
if

supernatural interference be

possible as they are

such interference be impossible.

law does not do more than state that under certain

circumstances (positive and negative) certain


will occur.

phenomena

If

on some occasions these kcumstances,_W%!i/"


interference,

owing to supernatural
that the

do not
If

occur, the

fact''iv>^^'^?^*>^

phenomena do not
will

follow proves nothing as to


law.

the truth or falsehood

of the

we
less

believe that

oxygen and hydrogen


to produce water,

combine under given conditions


none the
because

we

believe so

we

happen

also to believe that

some Supernatural Power may


insist

interpose, or has

on certain occasions interposed, to prevent


on
this point,
I

that result.
is

need not further


itself,

which

obvious enough in

and on which

believe I

am

in

agreement with Mr. Mill and others who are not commonly
suspected of a theological bias.

There remains then the concrete part of Science


matters of fact which compose history in
or
its

the

widest sense,

which belong!^ to that fraction of the future which

Science can pretend to foresee.

Now

with regard to the

former of these the question


tion

is

complicated by a considera-

which does not

affect us

when we

are dealing with

other portions of the scientific system

by the consideration,

namely, that

it

is

a matter of controversy what, in certain


scientific version of history

very pertinent particulars, the


really
is.

For the Theologians usually maintain that the


I call Historical,

kind of scientific inference which


belief in the intervention

compels a

on certain occasions of supernatural

causes

a great part of what are

commonly

called Chris-

tian evidences being indeed nothing

more than a

detailed

attempt to prove this

thesis, just as

most of the direct

attacks on Christianity are attempts to prove the precise

332

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


Now,
if

opposite.

the Theologians

are

right

in

their

opinions on this point, there can be no discrepancy whatever

between ReHgion and Science as regards matters of


because
it is

fact,

Science

itself

which compels us to accept the

account of miracles in which Religion teaches us to believe.


Before, therefore, discussing the nature

and magnitude of

the discrepancy which


it

is

supposed to exist between them,


fully into all the disputes

would seem necessary to enter

respecting the authenticity of documents, the credibility of


witnesses, the interpretation of texts, the

growth of myths,

the natural history of religions, the abstract question as to

the possibility of inferring supernatural facts from natural


data, and, in short, all the topics

which supply theological

and anti-theological
discussion.

writers
is

with so

much

material for

Such a task
on

of course impossible.

But

it

may

be worth while to note the conclusions that would


if

have to be faced

all

these disputed questions the

Theologians are wrong and the Anti-theologians are right


if

known

natural causes are able in


for the historical
if,

all cases,

without strain-

ing, to account

facts

which both sides

allow to have occurred, and

either for this, or for

some

more abstract

reason, only natural causes can rationally be


in operation.

admitted to have been

On

such a hypothesis

theological beliefs would, without doubt, modify opinions

framed out of purely


fication

scientific materials,

though the modiin their re*

may

easily be exaggerated.

Regarded

lation to us as

men, the

facts

which Theology asserts to


can

have happened are unquestionably of transcendent importance.

Regarded

in

their relation to Science, this

hardly be maintained.

As

phenqmena^ the few events


in Palestine

which are said to have occurred

and elsewhere
Be-

of a supernatural character are scarcely worth noting.

ing supernatural, they furnish no grounds either for be-

'

RELIGION AND SCIENCE.


lieving in

333

any new law of Nature or

for disbelieving
;

which we had before supposed to be established


succeeded each other since the earth came into being.
the supernatural creation of the world, then, nothing

any and
'

being few, they are lost in the mass of facts which have
Is

'

the

reader

may

be tempted to exclaim.
is

have always under-

stood

that this

a subject on which

men

of science pro*

fessed to be altogether out of their sphere.

What, then,
.?

do you say about a

belief in Providence,

and

in the possible

interference of Supernatural

Power

in

answer to prayer

These, again, are not convictions which require us to

modify our adherence to known laws.

They may

cast,

indeed, an additional shade of doubt over our expectation

of the events which are to occur in the future, as well as

over the explanation of the events which have occurred in


"

the past

and

if

our actual

scientific inferences

were

(as I

have shown

in the fourth chapter that

they are not) of a

satisfactory character

on these
I

points, this

might prove a
only

matter of some, though not,


ance.

think, of very great importis

As

it is,

however, the Supernatural Power

one of an indefinite number of known and unknown natural


powers, which

we never have

seen,

and perhaps can never


if

hope to

see,

reduced to law, and which even

we

leave
to

miraculous interference out of account would

suflfice

make demonstrative prophecy


impossibility.
It

or retrospection an absolute

would appear then that the discrepancy between


if

Religion and Science which vanishes altogether


^

we take

If the literal interpretation of the Mosaic account of the creation be accepted as an essential part of religion, no doubt the discrepancy between Religion and Science will be greater than that stated I have, however, assumed (in accordance with what I in the text.
is

to

understand to be the opinion of theological experts) that this


the case.

is

not

334

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


favourable to the
in
its

the hypothesis most

Theologians

is

comparatively insignificant
hypothesis
if

amount even on the


Freethinkers
:

most

favourable

to

the

and

many

Science,

know a great deal about and may be supposed to know something about
writers

who

certainly

Theology, are of an altogether different opinion, this may,


I

apprehend, be attributed to the fact that they approach

the question with their minds completely saturated with a

theory of the logical

relation

which Ought

to

subsist

between Religion and Science, according to which the


grounds,
if

any, for believing the

first,

are to be found,
It is not

if

anywhere, among the doctrines


to see that as
it is

of the second.

hard

on any presupposition of

this sort
is

(combined

with the assumption that Science

philosophically

established), the smallest

want of harmony between the two

systems may, or rather must, lead to the most important


consequences
rationally

mere discovery that they are not connected would remove all ground for accept:

since the

ing the dependent creed

while the least appearance of

contradiction would supply a positive ground for rejecting


it.

As, however,

have

in

the preceding chapter

suffi-

ciently expressed

my

dissent

from

this

view,

it

is
it.

not
I I

necessary that

should here any further allude to

merely desired to point out the principal reason which


believe exists for the great exaggeration which
is

occa-

sionally to be observed in the estimate of the importance

of the contradiction between current Religion and current


Science put forward by thinkers of reputation.

APP.]

THE PHILOSOPHY OF

ETHICS.

335

APPENDIX.
ON THE IDEA OF A PHILOSOPHY OF
In
in this

ETHICS.
apply the

Appendix
first

propose to extend and

remarks on the Idea of a Philosophy


the

in general contained

chapter of the Essay, to the Philosophy of


But, in order to do so,
it is

Ethics in particular.

necessary,

in the first place, to correct

an error which,

in these

days

when Science and


tensive,
is

the

Knowable
Ethics
is

are supposed to be co-ex:

natural though not the less mischievous

the
That

error I

mean by which

degraded to a mere section


first sight,

or department of Science.

At

and from some

points of view, the opinion seems plausible enough.

mankind have passed through


example)
that
I
is

many

ethical phases (for


:

a fact in history, and history belongs to science


is

hold certain moral laws to be binding


;

a fact of
is

my

mental being

and, like

all

other such facts,

dealt with

by Psychology,

also

a branch of science.
all

Physiology,

Ethnology, and other sciences


the individual and in the race
fore, that

have something to say


not unnatural, there-

concerning the origin and development of moral ideas in


;

it

is

some men

of science, impressed by these facts,

have claimed, or seemed to claim, Ethics for their own. To hold such a view would be a most unfortunate error
not to hold clearly and definitely
its

contrary

may

lead to

much

confusion

for though, as will appear, scientific laws

form necessary steps in the deduction of subordinate ethi-

336

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.

[app,

cal laws,

and though the two provinces of knowledge cannot


still

with advantage be separated in practice,

the truth

remains that

scientific

judgments and

ethical

judgments

deal with essentially different subject-matters.

Every

scientific proposition asserts

either the nature

of the relation of space or time

between phenomena which


;

have existed, do
simplifications

exist, or will exist

or defines the relations


if

of space or time which would exist

certain changes

and

were made

in the

phenomena
it

(as in ideal

geometry), or in the law governing the phenomena (as in


ideal physics).

Roughly speaking,

may

be said to state

facts or events, real or hypothetical.

An

ethical proposition,
it

on the other hand, though,


ought to speak the
I

like

every other proposition,

states a relation, does not state a


*

relation of space or time.

truth,' for

instance, does not imply that


shall

have spoken, do speak, or

speak the truth

it

asserts

no bond of causation be-

tween subject and predicate, nor any co-existence nor any


sequence.
It

does not announce an event


it

and

if

some

people would say that


fact either of the
*

stated a fact,
'

it is

not certainly a
'

external

or of the

internal

world.

One

cause, perhaps, of the constant confusion


is

between

Ethics and Science

the tendency there appears to be to

regard the psychology of the individual holding the moral

law as the subject-matter of Ethics, rather than the moral law


itself
;

to investigate the position which the belief in such


'

a proposition as

ought to speak the truth holds


'

in the
its
;

history of the race

and of the

individual,
its

its
its

causes and

accompaniments, rather than


substitute, in short,

truth or

evidence

to

Psychology or Anthropology

for Ethics.

The danger

of such confusion will partly be


in

shown by the

few remarks which,


thought begun

order to carry out the train of

in the first chapter, I

have to make on the

APP

THE PHILOSOPHY OF
:

ETHICS.
is,

337

Idea of a Philosophy of Ethics

that

on the form which


to

any

satisfactory system

of Ethics must assume^ or be able

assume, whatever be

its contents.
all

The obvious
itself,
is

truth that

knowledge

is

either certain in

or

is

derived by legitimate methods from that which

so,

has been already, perhaps, more

than sufficiently

insisted
ral, is

on

and

this,

which

is

true of knowledge in gene-

of course also true of ethical knowledge in particular.


consideration will enable us to go on, and state this
is

little

further fact, which

peculiar to Ethics.

The general probe either scientific

positions which really lie at the root

of any ethical system

must themselves
or metaphysical.

be ethical,

and can never


if
all,

In other words,

a proposition announc-

ing obligation require proof at

one term of that proof


obligation,

must always be a proposition announcing


itself requires

which

no proof
I

This truth must not be confounded

with that which

have just dwelt upon, namely, that

Science and Ethics have essentially different subject-matters.

This might be
its first

so,

and yet Ethics might be indebted


will

for all

principles to Science.

A concrete case
and

perhaps

make

clearer this
is

axiom

of ethical philosophy.

man

(let

us say)

not satisfied
a reason,

that he ought to speak the truth.


is

He demands

told that truth-telling conduces to the welfare of

society.

He
is

accepts this ground, and apparently, there-

fore, rests his ethics

on what

is

a purely scientific assertion.


fact.

But

this

not in reality the

There

is

a suppressed

premiss required to justify his conclusion, which would run

somewhat
is is

in this

way,

'

ought to do that which conduces

to the welfare of society.'


ethical.

And
is

this proposition, of course,


it

This example

not merely an illustration,


artifice

a typical case.

There

is

no

by which an

ethical

statement can be evolved from a

scientific or

metaphysical

338

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


any combination of such
it
;

[app.

proposition, or

and whenever the

reverse appears to be the fact,

will

always be found that

the assertion, which seems to be the basis of the ethical


superstructure,
is

in reality
is

merely the 'minor' of a

syllo-

gism, of which the major

the desired ethical principle.


it

If this principle be as true as


vious,
it

seems to

me

to be ob-

at

once alters our attitude towards a vast mass of


'

controversy which has encumbered the progress of moral


philosophy.

concerned

it

So far as the proof of a basis of morals is makes irrelevant all discussion on the origin of
on the nature of moral sentiments
;

moral

ideas, or

and

it

relegates to their proper sphere in Psychology or Anthro-

pology

all

discussion on

such subjects as association of

ideas, inherited instincts,

and

evolution, in so

far,

at least,

as these are supposed to


it is

refer to tiltimate

moral laws.

For

an obvious corollary from our

principle, that the origin

of an ultimate ethical belief never can supply a reason for


believing
it
;

since the origin of this belief, as of


is

mental phenomenon,

a matter to be dealt with

any other by Science


;

and

my
it

thesis

is,

that (negatively speaking) scientific truth


;

alone cannot serve as a foundation for a moral system


(to

or

put

positively), if
in

we have
it,

a moral system at

all,

there

must be contained
required.

explicitly or implicitly, at least

one ethical proposition, of which no proof can be given or


In one sense, therefore,
Ethics

all

is

'

a priori'

It is not,

and never can

be,

founded on experience.

Whether we be

Utilitarians, or Egoists, or Intuitionists,

by whatever name
series of experi-

we

call ourselves,

the rational basis of our system must be

something other than an experience or a


ences
;

for such

always belong to Science.


is

Limited indeed

the

have invariably kept

this

number of English Moralists who in view. However foreign it may

App.]

THE PHILOSOPHY OF

ETHICS.

339

be to their various systems, an enquiry into origin or into


the universality of moral ideas always appears to slip in

not in

its

proper place, as an interesting

psychological

adjunct,

but

as having an important bearing

on

the

authority of their particular principle.


result,

And

the necessary

of course, of these efforts to support ultimate princithat they cease to be ultimate, and

ples

is,

become not only


if

subordinate, but subordinate to judgments which,


citly stated,

expli-

would very

likely

appear

far

less

obvious

than they.

There

is

a whole school of Moralists, for example,

who
by
as a

find or invent a special faculty, intellectual or sensitive,

which moral truth


serious
beliefs

is

arrived at
if

who would

regard

it

blow to morality

the process

by which

ethical

were produced was found to be

common
called
'

to

many

other regions of thought.

Oddly enough, these

are the

very people whose systems are often

a priori'

Now

if

by

this

term be meant that the ordinary maxims of


appropriate enough
it is

morality are (according to these systems) independent of


experience,
it is
;

but

if it

be meant

that they are self-evident,


it

a singular misnomer.

For

is

clear that on their systems rigidly interpreted those

maxims
relation

derive their evidence, not from their

own

internal

authority, but from the fact that they bear a certain special
to our mental constitution
;

so that the ethical


is

proposition which really

something
validity of

of this sort

We
'

lies

at the root of their ethics

ought to obey

all

laws the

which

is

recognised by a special innate faculty,

whether called Conscience or otherwise.'

Now,

do not

deny that from a philosophical point of view such propositions as these are possible foundations of morals
I desire to point out
is
;

but what

that such a phrase (to take a con-

crete case) as

'

ought to speak the truth because conz 2

340

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


commands
it,'

[app.

science
ings,

may have two widely


to

different

meanand
is

and may belong

two

different

systems of Ethics,
first
'

not

commonly

distinguished.
'

According to the

most accurate meaning,


inference,

ought to speak the truth


be,
'

an

of which the major premiss must

ought to

do what conscience commands,' and being an inference, cannot obviously be an d priori law. According to the second

and inaccurate meaning,


reality received

ought to speak the truth


merits,

'

is

in

on

its

own
in,

and conscience

is

very

unnecessarily brought
or to account for or for
its

either to

add dignity to the law,

general acceptance

some other
is

extra-ethical reason.

among mankind, The first of these


it

views

open to no criticism from the point of view of


;

ethical philosophy
assailable.

so far as form

is

concerned

is

un-

But

greatly suspect that most people

who

nominally found their morality on conscience really hold


the second theory
;

and
if

in that case, as I think, their state-

ment

is

misleading,
far I

not erroneous.

So
it

have only given a negative description of the


I

nature of an ethical proposition.

have

said, indeed, that


is

announces obligation, but

this

statement

tautological

for if

we knew

in

no

difficulty in

what obligation consisted there would be stating the meaning of ethical. Beyond

this I

have only said that an ethical judgment deals with


possible to say

an essentially different subject-matter from either Science


or Metaphysics.
it

Is

it

more than

this

Is

possible to give
shall

any description of

ethical propositions
}

which

add to our knowledge of


it

their character

On

general grounds

is

plain that this can only be done,

supposing that what are commonly called ethical propositions

form part of a larger class of judgments which resemble

them

in

being neither
in

scientific

nor metaphysical, but


I

differ

from them

some other

respect.

myself hold

this to

APR]

THE PHILOSOPHY OF
case.
I

ETHICS.

341

be the

hold not only that the judgments com-

monly

called ethical (but which, in spite of the clumsiness

attendant on changing the meaning of a word in the middle


of a discussion,
I

shall

henceforward

call

moral) have the


in

two negative

characteristics

above mentioned
;

common
ethical

with a larger class of judgments

but that the distinction

between the two classes should be ignored by


philosophy, since
it

depends not on

form

'

but on

'

matter.'
I

All judgments belonging to either of these classes


henceforth
call ethical.

shall

Those commonly
;

called ethical I

shall describe as

moral

the rest are either non-moral or


then,
is is

immoral.

Every possible judgment,


;

either ethical either

or non-ethical

and every
explain

ethical

judgment

moral
view

or non-moral or immoral.
defined, let

The terminology
and
at the

thus being

me

it,

same time

my

on the subject.
If a

man

contemplates any action as one which he

chooses to perform, he must do so either because he


regards the action as one which he chooses for
itself,

or

because he expects to obtain by


chooses for
itself.

it

And

similarly, if

some object which he he contemplates any


must do so
either
itself,

object as one he chooses to obtain, he

because he regards that object as chosen for

or

because

it

may be

a means to one that


is

is.

In other words,

deliberate action

always directed mediately or immeis

diately to something which

chosen for

itself

alone
I

which
loosely

something

may

either be itself an action, or

what

term an object.
'end,'
I

Including both, then, under the term


thus:

define an ethical proposition


is

An
is

ethical
to

proposition

one which prescribes an action zvith reference


will

an

end.

Nobody

deny that

this definition

true of all
it

moral propositions (most people, indeed,


is

will think that

too obvious to need stating)

but they will probably say.

342

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


truly, that
it is

[app.

and say
sitions
is

also true of a great

many

propo-

which are not usually called moral.


distinction

Now my object
class

to

show that the

between what are usually

called moral propositions

and that larger

which

have defined above, has no philosophic import, has nothing


that
is

to

do with the grounds of obligation.


let

And

for this

purpose,

me

analyse more carefully this larger class

(which
is,

I call

ethical)

from a philosophic point of view, that

with reference to the rational foundation and connection


its parts.

of

(i)

Every proposition prescribing an action with

refer-

ence to an end, belongs either explicitly or implicitly to a

system of such propositions.


sition of

(2)

The fundamental propo-

every such system states an end, which the person

who
itself

receives that system regards as final


alone.
(3)

as chosen for
of that
{4)

The subordinate
or theological

propositions

system are deduced from the fundamental proposition by

means of

scientific

minor premises.

When

two such systems


which
'

conflict, their rival

claim can only

be decided by a judgment or proposition not contained in


either of them,
shall assert

which of these respective


[Ethics, then,

fundamental
rests

ends

shall

have precedence.

on two sorts of judgments, neither of which can be

deduced from the other, and of neither of which can any


proof be given or required.

The

first

sort declares

an end
ends
is

to be final, the second declares which of


to be preferred,
sort,
if
is

two

final

they are incompatible.

This second

of course,

not essential to an ethical system, but

can only be required when an individual regards more than

one end as
possibly
lie

final.]

(5)

No

other sort of proposition can


[This
is

at

the

root of an ethical system.

merely a restatement of the law dwelt on at the beginning


of this discussion.]


'

APP.]

THE PHILOSOPHY OF
in so

ETHICS.

343

Now

far as this

is

a complete philosophical diait

gram of every
tive

ethical system,

must show the

sort of

authority on which every ethical proposition

every impera-

must

rest.

Yet since

it is

plain that this diagram takes

no account of the differences there

and immoral ethical systems, how


affect the authority of the

(it

may be between moral may be asked) can we


This question takes us

account for the wide-spread delusion, that these differences

former

far afield into the regions of

Psychology and Anthropology,

but the answer to

it

may

perhaps be suggested as follows.

The main

reason for this error appears to be, false analogy,

unchecked by any clear apprehension of the nature of the


rational or philosophical peculiarities of an ethical system.

And

in

order to illustrate
I

this,

and

at the

same time

to

place the theory


possible,
it

am
'

defending under as strong a light as

may

be as well to examine the exact bearing

which

'

Universality

and the approval of

Conscience

(two of the chief characteristics of moral as opposed to non-

moral or immoral systems) have on obligation.

My
and
in

position, of course,

is

that they have no bearing

order to show this

offer the following analysis to


first.

the reader

taking

Universality

A
It

law

to be Universal in one of four senses.

may be said may mean (first)


bound by
I
it.

that

all

intelligences regard themselves as

This meaning we need not further consider, not only


because
it is

a scientific assertion, and therefore, as

have

shown, incapable of becoming the foundation of an ethical


system, but also because
entirely discredited.
It
is
it

is

a scientific assertion

now

quite out of fashion to maintain


in

that Morality

is

the

same

every race and every country,

and therefore
is

till,

in the revolutions of thought,

some one
further

found to re-assert
it.

this doctrine,

we need not

discuss

344

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.

[app.

The second possible meaning is, that by a universal moral law we mean one by which all intelligences ought This also we may dismiss to regard themselves as bound.
because
it

amounts
all

to saying that there

is

a moral law

which obliges
laws.
Is

intelligences to be

bound by other moral


sejtse

then that moral law Universal in the


If
it is,

we

are

discussing?

of moral laws, each

we are committed to an infinite series commanding us to be bound by the


it

preceding one.

If

is

not, then there

can be a moral

law which

(in this sense) is

not universal.

In the third place, by a universal moral law

one which we think

all

men ought

to obey.

we may mean That we do


not think
it

think this of most moral laws, and that

we do

of the other ethical laws, namely, the non-moral and the

immoral ones,
as

is

tolerably certain.

It

remains to enquire
;

whether the difference bears on obligation


it

and

this enquiry,

seems to me,

may

be settled by a very simple con-

sideration.
telligences.

All intelligences means

Me
it

and

all

other in-

The

first

of these constituent parts would be

bound by a law held by


this sense) or not.

Me
it

whether

were universal
not be

(in

The second would

bound by a

law held by
not.
this,

Me

whether

were universal

in this sense or

In other words, to be bound by a moral law (and

by the way, brings out very

clearly the difference


is

between being ethically


not to regard

bound

and legally bound)


it

exactly the same thing as to regard


it is

as binding on
else
;

you

it

as binding on
it

someone

and
;

it is

not for someone else to regard


therefore,

as binding on

you

it

has

and

it

can have, no connection with Universality

in this third sense.


It
is, of course, open to anyone to assert that he recogno imperative which is not universal (in this sense).

nises

This

may

very well be the

fact,

and

have no wish to deny

APP.]

THE PHILOSOPHY OF
I

ETHICS.

345

it.

What

deny

is,

that the connection between the


it

two

is

other than empirical and accidental, or that


place in the philosophy of obligation.

has any-

The
to the

fourth and last meaning which I am able to attach word Universal, when used of a law, is that it

signifies

that

all

people of 'well-constituted minds' do,

as a matter of fact, regard themselves as

bound by a law
'

so qualified.

Now,

if

'

well-constituted

is

defined with

reference to morality,

and means 'holding the one true


all

moral system,' a proposition that


laws are universal,
is

true or right moral


verbal.
if it

frivolous

and merely

If

it

be

defined with reference to something else

means, for

instance, sane, or well-educated, or Christian, or scientific,

or anything non-moral, then the

same arguments may be


first

used to show that universality in this sense cannot be a

ground of obligation, as
sense.

used when speaking of the

For a proposition asserting that any considerable body of men, distinguished from the rest of mankind by some non-moral attribute, hold the same moral code, is
very likely to be questionable, and being a scientific assertion,
is

quite certain to be irrelevant.


then, for

So much,
science, I

Universality.

As

regards

Con-

have shown before, that to assume a special


is

faculty which

to

announce ultimate moral laws can


it do so the more by such sanctions

add nothing
if

to their validity, nor will


its

we suppose
remorse or

authority supported

as
this

self-approval.

Conscience regarded in

way

is

not ethically to be distinguished from any


as,

external

authority,

for
it

instance,
is

the Deity,

or the

laws of the land.

Now,

plain that

no external

authority can give validity to ultimate moral laws, for the

question immediately arises,


authority
?

why

should

Only two reasons can be

given.

we obey that The first is,

346

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


it is

[app.

that

right in itself to obey; the second


it

is,

that (through

a proper use of sanctions)


obey.

will
is

be for our happiness to


a moral law, which ob-

Now, the

first

of these
its

viously does

not derive

validity

from
is

the

external

authority, because the external authority

an authority
be said of the

only by means of

it.

And
moral.'

the same

may

second reason, substituting the words 'ethical but non-

moral

'

for the

word

'

In neither case, then,

is

the

external authority the ultimate ground of obligation.

The
tives

inevitable ambiguity which arises from the


'

sudden

extension of the meaning of the word

ethical

'

to imperait,

which are immoral or non-moral, makes


I

perhaps,

desirable that

should very concisely re-state, from another


I

point of view, the main position


establish.

have been attempting to

All imperatives,

all
:

propositions prescribing
if

actions,

have

this in

common

That

they are to have any

cogency, or are to be anything but


actions they prescribe

must be

to the individual

they are regarded as binding, either


diately desirable.
directly, to
itself

empty sound, the by whom mediately or immedirectly

They must conduce,

or infor

something which he regards as of worth

alone.

The number

of things which are thus in


is,

themselves desirable or of worth to somebody or other


of course, very great.

Pleasure or happiness in the abstract,

other people's pleasure or happiness,


its

money

(irrespective of

power of giving

pleasure), power, the

love

of God,

revenge, are

some
is

of the

commonest of them, and every


sake,

one of these

regarded by some person or other as an end


its

to be attained for

own
it

and not as a means to

something

else.

Now,

is

evident that to every one of

the ultimate propositions prescribing these ends, and for

which, as the ends are ends-in-themselves, no further reason

APP.]

THE PHILOSOPHY OF

ETHICS.

347

can be given, there will belong


propositions, the reasons for

a system of dependent

which are that the actions

they prescribe conduce to the ultimate end or end-in-itself.


If,

for instance,

revenge against a particular individual


a proposition which prescribes

is for

me

an

end-in-itself,

shooting him from behind a hedge


ordinate
or

may

be one of the subto

dependent

propositions

belonging
indefinite

that

particular system.

But whereas the

number of
form,
it

such systems
is

is

thus characterised by a

common

divided

by ordinary usage
is

into three classes, the moral,

the non-moral, and the immoral, about the ^^motation of

which

there

a tolerable

agreement.

It

would be

universally admitted, for instance, that a system founded on

the happiness of others was a moral system, while one

founded on revenge
this is not

was immoral

and,

though there

would be more dispute as to the members of the non-moral


class,

a question on which
of

need detain the

reader.

The denotation then


fixed,
is

these
.''

names being
or to limit the
1

presumably

what

is

the connotation

enquiry, what

the connotation of a moral system

The
they

apparent answers are as numerous as the number of schools


of Moralists.

But however numerous they

may

be,

can

all

be divided into two classes.


the denotation
end-in-itself
;

The first class merely


words, announce the

re-state

in other

ultimate

of the system,
all.

and

so,

properly

speaking, give no answer at

A Utilitarian, for example,


greatest happiness

may

simply assert

that

the

of the
If
for

greatest

number

is

for

him the ultimate end of

action.

he stops there he evidently shows no philosophic reason


distinguishing the system he adopts from

the countless

others which exist, or have existed.

If

he attempts to give

any further

characteristic of his system, he then belongs to

the second class,

who do indeed

explain the connotation of

348

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


*

[app.

the word

moral according to their usage of


'

it,

but whose

explanations have, and can have, nothing to do with the

grounds of action or the theory of obligation.

The

sanction

of conscience^ the emotion of approval, the expectation of


reward, the feeling of good desert, glow of conscious merit
these are
all

most undoubtedly marks or


:

characteristics of

moral actions

how they came

to be so,

whether by educait

tion, association

of ideas, innate tendency, or howsoever

has happened, matters nothing whatever, except to the


psychologist
;

that they are so


is

is

certain, but the signifi-

cance of the fact

habitually misunderstood.
}

simply the causes of good action


to

Are they Then they have nothing

do with Ethics, which

is

concerned not with the causes

but with the grounds or reasons for action, and would

remain wholly unchanged

if

not a single

man

ever had
t

done or could do

right.

the fact that they are obtained

Are they the ends of action by a certain course a


}

Is

valid

reason for pursuing that course

In that case they stand


precisely the

to a person holding that opinion in


relation as

same

savage.

money does to the miser, or revenge to the They are the groundwork of an ethical system, and to state them is simply to denote what ethical system it is which is being alluded to. Are they, finally, not ends of action, but merely marks by which certain actions may be known to belong to a particular system ? In that case,
and
for that

very reason, they can have nothing to do with


Therefore,
I

the grounds or theory of obligation.


justified in asserting that
'

am

though under the general name


distinctions regarded

ethical

'

are included not only moral, but also non-moral

and immoral systems, the

from the

outside between these subdivisions are not essential, and

has no philosophic import


proved.

which

was the thing to be

App.]

THE PHILOSOPHY OF ETHICS


I

349

Before concluding these remarks,


three corollaries that

would point out

may

be drawn from them, which are


first

not without rinterest.


structive
It is true,

The

corollary

is

that

no

in-

analogy exists between Ethics and Esthetics.

no doubt, that philosophers have talked about


the Beautiful, as
if

the

Good and

they were co-ordinate


ordinary language

subjects of investigation,

and that
'

in

we

say both that a picture


action
'

'

ought to be admired, and that an


Nevertheless, reflecting
it

ought

'

to be performed.

on actual or possible
that they must be

aesthetic systems,

would seem clear


to Psy-

included
either (i)

under
to

one of four heads.


(2)

They must belong


chology, or
(3)

Ethics, or

to Metaphysics, or, lastly (4) to Metaphysics

with an ethical or psychological element superadded.


in

And

none of these cases can Esthetics be said to rank as a

parallel subject of enquiry with Ethics.

The
belongs

first

of these possibilities, namely, that Esthetics


is

to,

or

included in Ethics,

mention chiefly
art-critics

for

the sake of completeness.

Even those

whose
our

denunciations of bad taste approach most nearly to the


level of

moral reprobation, hardly maintain that


in the

it

is

duty to admire the Venus of Milo

our duty to love our neighbour.


the conclusion to be drawn
is,

If

same sense as it is any do hold this view,

not that their Esthetic

code stands on a

different,

but similar platform to their


is

Ethical code, but that their Ethical code

larger than that


their Esthetics.

of ordinary people, by the whole

amount of

According to the second of these


that ^Esthetics belongs to Psychology
;

possibilities,

namely,

Esthetics

is

merely
certain

the investigation

of the nature

and causes of peculiar


in

emotions chiefly secondary


more
to

produced

us

by

external causes, objects, or representations, and has no

do with

Ethics, either

by way of resemblance or

350

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


any other part of the science
to

[app.

contrast, than

which

it

belongs.

The

third possibility, namely, that Esthetics belongs

to Metaphysics, includes all such theories of the Beautiful

as deal exclusively with


*

'

objective standards,'
*

ideas,' or

archetypes,'

the evolution of the Idea,' or

the Perception

of the agreement of the Subject and Object,' and the like.

Taken by themselves,
physics
;

theories of this kind belong to

Meta-

but

if

there be added

any consideration of the


must belong
either to the

relation such ontological entities or processes bear to the


individual, these considerations
first

or the second of the above-mentioned possible treattherefore,

ments of Esthetics, and must,


or psychological.

be either ethical

This

is

the fourth possibility.


it

From

this concise

analysis then,

would seem
But

clear

that no analogy exists between Ethics rightly understood

and any system right or wrong of


be
so,

^Esthetics.

if

that

how comes

the existence of any analogy even to


}

have been supposed

exist an analogy between

The reply to this is, that there does some theories of Esthetics and

Ethics wrongly understood.

Some

moralists, for example,


in us

have dwelt largely on the emotion excited


actions.

by virtuous
of
these
is

And

if

the

scientific

examination

emotions really constitute the essence of Ethics, there


unquestionably an analogy between theories of the

Good

and some theories of the Beautiful.

Again,

if

ethical en-

quiries are thought to resolve themselves into researches

concerning the existence and nature of some objective


standard of right,
it is

inevitable that they should suggest,

and

it

is

probable they would resemble, those other metaobjective

physical enquiries concerning the

standard
I
I

of

beauty.

Now

it

must not be supposed that


;

pronounce
contend for

either of these investigations irrational

all

APP.]

THE PHILOSOPHY OF
;

ETHICS.

351

is

that they are not ethical


I

or,

rather (to avoid a dispute


is

about words), what

contend

for

that they have nothing,

and can have nothing,

directly to

do with Obligation.
the functions

The second
is

corollary concerns
It
is

of the
it

Moral Philosopher.

clear

from what precedes, that

not the business of the moral philosopher to account for

the origin of moral ideas, or to analyse and explain that

growth of sentiment which


which belong to Psychology.
prove the propositions which
of morals
;

collects

around

the

time-

honoured maxims of current morality.


Neither
lie

These
is

are' topics

he expected to

at the root of

any system
Nor, for the

for these are incapable of proof.

same
flict,

reason, can he justify the


final

judgments which declare

which of two
or

ends
of one

is is

to be preferred in case of conto be preferred to

how much
Nor,

how much

of

the other.

in reality,

has he any but a subordinate

part to play in expounding or deducing the derivative rules


of morality
;

and
form

for this reason.

The deduction
sarily in this
:

of any derivative rule


*

is

always necesto be

the happiness of
us say,
: *

mankind ought

promoted
piness of
it

'

(this,

let

is

the ultimate

unprovable
the hap-

foundation of the system)

monogamy promotes
: '

mankind
is

'

(this is the scientific [in

another system
therefore

might have been theological] minor premiss)


the required derivative rule.

monogamy
This
is

a system which ought to be supported;'

Now

the only

diffi-

culty in deducing this conclusion from the

first

principle of

the system

lies in

the difficulty of demonstrating the minor


it lies

premiss

in other words,

in the difficulty of a certain

sociological investigation,

which the speculative moralist as

such cannot be expected to undertake.

The important
tant duties, arise

duties of the moralist, for he has impor-

from the confused state

in

which the

352

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


mankind

[app.

greater part of
first

are with regard to their ethical

principles.

The two
do
I
is

questions each

man

has to ask

himself are
action
I
it
?

What

hold to be the ultimate ends of

and

If there

estimate them in case of conflict


will

more than one such end, how do These two questions, ?


fact,

be observed, are questions of


is

not of law

and the

duty of the moralist


fact,

to help his readers to discover the

not to force his

own view down


is

their throat

by
its

attempting a proof of that which


very nature, incapable of proof
of substituting

essentially,
all,

and by

Above

he must beware

some rude

simplification for (what

may

perhaps be) the complexity of nature, by deducing


Utilitarians do) all subordinate rules
principle,

(as the

from one fundamental


only approximately

when, it

may be,

this principle

contains actual existing ethical facts.

Since these two questions can be answered, not by


ratiocination, but only

by simple

inspection, the art of the

moralist will consist in placing before the enquirer various

problems

in

Ethics free from the misleading particulars


in

which surround them

practice.

In other words, his

method
It

will

be

casuistical,

and not dogmatic.


that, after

may

perhaps seem strange

commenting

at

some length on the prevailing confusion between Ethics and Psychology, I should now have to announce that the
business of the Ethical Philosopher (at least, so far as
principles are concerned)
is

first

as purely

psychological
I

as,

according to the two preceding paragraphs,


to be
;

make

it

out

and

it

may

seem, therefore, as

if

the difference

between

my

view and that of the Philosophers


criticise
is
is

whom

have attempted to
important.

is

by no means

essential or

This, however,

not the case.

My

complaint

against these philosophers

that they appear to suppose

that a psychological law can serve as a rational basis for

APP.]

THE PHILOSOPHY OF
;

ETHICS.

353

an ethical system

so that their chief aim often seems to

have been the estabhshment of their own particular views

on the origin and nature of our moral sentiments.

I,

on

the other hand, altogether deny the possibility of such a


basis,

and maintain that

all

that a moralist can


is,

do with
they are

regard to ethical first principles

not to prove them or


if

deduce them, but to render them explicit


implicit, clear if

they are obscure.

To do

this effectually

he must, of course, treat of ideas and motions, and his

work

will, therefore, in

some sense be undoubtedly psychostatement complete,


I

logical.

To make
by

this

should add,
is

that (as appears

my

next paragraph) there

no absur-

dity in supposing that a moralist

may
new

in the course of his


first

speculations hit on

some

entirely

principle which

he has riot held even obscurely before, but which commends


itself to his

mind
in

as soon as

it is

presented to him.
this

The

third corollary I

draw

is

that there are only


profess.

two senses

which we can rationally talk of a moral


According

system being superior to the one we


to the first sense, superior

means

superior in form,

more
in

nearly in accordance with the ideal of an ethical system


just

sketched out.
the
it

According to the second


attaches
to

sense,

which
system,

superiority

the

matter of the
is

can only mean that the system

one of which
if presented

we

are ignorant, but which

we should adopt
is

to us.

The
it

superiority indicated

a hypothetical supe-

riority.

Now
our own,

must be observed that the sense

in

which we.
which we

speak of other hypothetical systems as being superior to


is

by no means

identical with that in

speak of our

own

as being superior to that of other people.


history,

Looking back over

we

perceive a

change and

development of the moral ideas of the race

in the direction

A A

354

A DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT.


now
prevail
;

[app.

of the systems which

and
if,

this

change we
continue
false

rightly term an improvement.


past,

But

arguing from the


will

we suppose

that

this

improvement

through the indefinite future, we are misled by a


analogy.

The change may very


will

well continue, the

im-

provement certainly

not.

And

the reason

is

clear.

What we mean,
the past,
is

or ought to mean,

an approach to

by an improvement in our own standard, and since

any change
future

at all corresponding in magnitude to this in the must involve a departure from that standard, it must

necessarily be a change for the worse.

In other words,

when we

speak of another system as

we speak of a possible system which we should accept if we knew it. When we speak of our own system being superior to that of some other person, we assert the superiority unconditionbeing superior (in matter) to our own,
ally,
it

and quite irrespectively of the possible acceptance of by that other person, supposing him to be acquainted
it.

with

If then
it

we

believe that development will proceed

in the future as

has done in the past,

we must suppose

that a time will

would be as
man.
This

come when the moral ideas of the world much out of our reach, supposing them prealso true of scientific ideas

sented to us, as ours would be out of reach of primitive


is
:

but there

is

this difTerence
scientific

between them, that whereas the change

in

ideas

may be an improvement,
viz.,

that in

moral

ideas

must be a degradation.

The grounds
is,

of this dis-

tinction of course are obvious,

that the standard of

excellence in the case of scientific ideas


be, conformity to

or

is

supposed to

an infinitely complex external world

a conformity which
ideas.

may

increase with every

change

in the

The standard

of excellence, on the other hand, in

moral ideas must necessarily be conformity to our actual

APP.]

THE PHILOSOPHY OF
and
this

ETHICS.

355

ideal,

conformity must diminish with every change

in the ideas.

This point would not perhaps have been worth dwelling


on,
if
it

was not that the discussion brings into strong


so
far

relief the nature,

as

form

is

concerned, of the

criterion of right,

and

also has

some bearing on current


I

theories of optimistic evolution, with which

confess

it

does not seem possible easily to reconcile

it.

LONDON
SPOTTISWOODE

PRINTED BY

AND

CO.,

NEW-STREET

SQUARE

AND PARLIAMENT STREET

^ 6

(^

M-^
^x^

'^.

^
.a'^

*^

'^

\
<3i-

(^i^

^^
->
<*-

RETURN

TO>

CIRCULATION DEPARTMENT 202 Main Library


1

LOAN PERIOD HOME USE

^ \

'^

<?*

Tpf^

r\

You might also like