You are on page 1of 47

TYRANNY OF THE FEW: THE CASE FOR COPYRIGHT BUYOUT

CHRISTOPHER H. MEREDITH

4911 Old Canton Road


Apartment 240
Jackson, Mississippi
39211

(601) 212-8845
TABLE OF CONTENTS

I. BACKGROUND AND INTRODUCTION..........................................................................................1

II. FOOD FOR THOUGHT – RIGHTS OF OWNERSHIP IN THE FRUITS OF CREATIVITY..............................2

A. The Philosophical Rationales for Recognition of Intellectual Property.....................2

1. John Locke.............................................................................................................2

2. Jeremy Bentham.....................................................................................................4

3. Friedrich Hegel......................................................................................................7

B. Legal Development of Intellectual Property Rights...................................................9

1. Competing Visions of Copyright and its Legal Evolution in England..................10

2. Copyright, the Constitution, and the Founding of the United States....................13

3. Congress and the Copyright Acts.........................................................................18

C. Foundational Socio-Economic Principles of Property Rights..................................23

1. The Commons – Tragedy or Comedy?.................................................................24

2. An Anticommons Problem?.................................................................................25

3. Free Riding and Copyright...................................................................................27

III. WHERE DO WE GO FROM HERE?....................................................................................30

A. Civil Disobedience...................................................................................................30

B. Public Buyout..........................................................................................................34

1. Michael Kremer and the Patent Buyout Proposal...............................................35

2. Open Source Software Bounties..........................................................................37

3. Copyright Buyout – A Modified Bounty System.................................................39

IV. CONCLUSION..................................................................................................................45

i
TYRANNY OF THE FEW: THE CASE FOR COPYRIGHT BUYOUT

Christopher H. Meredith†

I. BACKGROUND AND INTRODUCTION

The Constitution confers upon Congress the right “[t]o promote the Progress of

Science and useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors the

exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries.” 1 The first exercise of this

authority came in the form of the Copyright Act of 1790. Since that first foray into

federal protection of what has since been termed intellectual property, the level of

government involvement has steadily increased.

As legislative policy regarding intellectual property has evolved, it has steadily

moved away from its legal, economic, and philosophical underpinnings, causing the

concept of intellectual property to assume a life of its own. The focus has shifted from

the interests of society to the interests of authors and producers. As a result, copyright

has transformed from a necessary evil intended to achieve a greater public benefit into a

an entitlement in its own right, one that enables strong industry players to form large and

wealthy information empires.

Industry-fueled Congress has abandoned its Constitutional moorings and allowed

expanded copyright power to be wielded by interested parties rather than by the people,

as the founding fathers originally intended. Without this protection, the law allows the

public good to be sacrificed to the whims of private entities and powerful corporations.

The suggestion of this Essay is that our current copyright scheme places

† Law clerk to the Hon. Jess H. Dickinson, Mississippi Supreme Court, 2010-2011; J.D.,
Mississippi College School of Law, 2010; B.A., Biblical Studies, Belhaven University, 2004. The author
would like to acknowledge Professor Alina Ng for her thought-provoking scholarship, classroom
assignments, and insight, and his family for their support, feedback, and love.
1 U.S. CONST. art. I, § 8.

1
unnecessary and harmful restrictions on the public as a means of maximizing the profits

of a few. Because this effect is not authorized by the Constitution, the current copyright

framework is constitutionally infirm and something must be done. Part I of this essay will

review the philosophical and economic factors affecting the recognition of intellectual

property. I will apply these foundational principles to the concept of intellectual property

and discuss how they affected the development of United States copyright law. Part II will

explore possible responses to the current situation. Specifically, I will suggest the

adoption of a copyright “buyout” system by which the public will be able to push a work

into the public domain by paying to the copyright owner a set price. Such a system would

be a means of restoring to the copyright system a balance that has been lost for some

time.

II. FOOD FOR THOUGHT – RIGHTS OF OWNERSHIP IN THE FRUITS OF CREATIVITY

A. The Philosophical Rationales for Recognition of Intellectual Property

1. John Locke

Most discussions of the philosophy of intellectual property begin with the writings

of John Locke. In his Two Treatises of Government, the typical starting point for

discourses on Lockean property theory, Locke developed his now-famous rationale for the

protection of property rights.2 “[E]very man has a property in his own person. . . . The

labour of his body, and the work of his hands, we may say, are properly his.” 3

Apparently anticipating the problem of the commons, 4 Locke articulated a limitation on

this broad principle of property: “As much as any one can make use of to any advantage

2 JOHN LOCKE, TWO TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT: AND A LETTER CONCERNING TOLERATION 111 (Vail-Ballou
Press, 2003) (1690).
3 Id. at 111.
4 See infra note 126 and accompanying text.

2
of life before it spoils, so much he may by his labour fix a property in: whatever is beyond

this, is more than his share, and belongs to others.” 5

While Locke did not directly address the notion of intellectual property in his

Treatises, many modern writers have concluded that this paradigm favors strong

intellectual property laws.6 Others are not convinced that the Lockean paradigm applies

well to intellectual property.7 At the very least, there are some analytical difficulties. For

example, why does labor entitle the laborer to a common resource? 8 In some places,

Locke indicates that appropriating common resources is the only way for man to survive, 9

yet intellectual property is hardly a resource necessary for survival. 10 And what exactly

constitutes intellectual “labor” in the first place?11 There are at least four different ways

to answer the question, each with very different implications for a Lockean theory of

intellectual property.12

Whatever problems might exist for one trying to import Locken property theory

into an intellectual property paradigm, Locke was much more explicit on the issue when

writing in opposition to the Stationers' Company monopoly 13 at the end of the 17th

century. He articulated a view which bears certain similarities to current U.S. copyright

5 LOCKE, supra note 2, at 113.


6 See, e.g., Alina Ng, The Social Contract and Authorship: Allocating Entitlements in the
Copyright System, 19 FORDHAM INTELL. PROP. MEDIA & ENT. L.J. 413, 500 (2009) (“Locke's reasoning . . .
provides a unique theory of property that supports the grant of strong intellectual property rights to
creators and authors”).
7 See, e.g., William Fisher, Intellectual Property Theories, in NEW ESSAYS IN THE LEGAL AND POLITICAL

THEORY OF PROPERTY 168 (Stephen R. Munzer ed., 2001), available at


http://cyber.law.harvard.edu/people/tfisher/iptheory.pdf (surveying the numerous ambiguities that arise when
trying to apply Lockean property rationale to intellectual property and concluding that the resulting
obstacles “may well prove insurmountable”) (subsequent citations are to the PDF).
8 Id. at 22.
9 Id. at 21 (citing LOCKE, TWO TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT, supra note 2, at §§ 25-26).
10 Fisher, supra note 7, at 23.
11 Id.
12 Id. at 23-24.
13 See infra note 53 and accompanying text.

3
law:

That any person or company should have patents for the sole
printing of ancient authors is very unreasonable and injurious
to learning. And for those who purchase copies from authors
that now live and write it may be reasonable to limit their
property to a certain number of years after the death of the
author or the first printing of the book as suppose 50 or 70
years. This I am sure, ’tis very absurd and ridiculous that
anyone now living should pretend to have a property in or a
power to dispose of the property of any copies or writings of
authors who lived before printing was known and used in
Europe. 14

Locke's suggestions here include the non-protection of “ancient” writings, the

limitation of protection of works by living authors based on the date of first printing or

the death of the author, and time periods of 50 or 70 years. All of these suggestions have,

at one time or another, been features of U.S. Copyright law. 15

Nevertheless, Locke's views on printing patents differ in one key respect from

modern Copyright formulas. A printing patent as described by Locke was not an author's

right to the fruit of his intellectual labors. Instead, it was property right that vested in

printers which was predicated on their purchase of a manuscript from an author. This is

evident from the language Locke employed in the quote above. Locke's concern here was

with the “property” of “those who purchase copies from authors.”

2. Jeremy Bentham

By the early 19th century, the idea of ownership of artistic embodiment had a

14 JOHN LOCKE, Liberty of the Press (1695), in LOCKE: POLITICAL ESSAYS 329 (Mark Goldie ed., 1997),

cited in Lior Zemer, The Making of a New Copyright Lockean, 29 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 891, 901 (2006).
15 The Copyright Act of 1976 provided retroactive protection for works already under the

protection of the 1909 Act. Copyright Act of 1976 § 304(a)(1) (2009). As an outworking of this scheme,
works published prior to 1923 are not copyrightable. Until the 1976 Act, works were protected based on
the date of publication. Copyright Act of 1909 § 24. Beginning in 1978, works were protected, regardless
of the date of publication, until 50 years following the death of the author. Copyright Act of 1976 § 302(a)
(1997). Since 1998, protection now lasts for 70 years following the death of the author. Copyright Act of
1976 § 302(a) (2009). For a more detailed history of the U.S. Copyright Acts, see Section I.B.3., infra.

4
firmer place in philosophical thought. Jeremy Bentham represented a school of thought in

stark contrast to Locke. Whereas Locke held to a concept of natural law grounded in

biblical revelation, Bentham may be considered the father of hedonistic utilitarianism. 16

Because of his rejection of natural law, Bentham viewed property not as a

transcendent, fundamental right, but as a mere “creature of law.” 17 Instead of grounding

property law in revelation or nature, Bentham considered it the product of a social

contract wherein members tacitly agreed to respect one another's property expectations. 18

Eventually, the social contract was replaced by law which now represents the ultimate

grant of property protection.19 Even so, the law has an obligation to protect property

rights because, by creating property in the first place, the law has fostered man's

expectation of security.20 To fail to protect the expectations thus created would result in

“shock or disturbance,” leading to “a proportionate measure of positive evil.” 21

Unlike other philosophical systems rooted in the objective, Bentham's

utilitarianism has as its only aim “the happiness of the community as a whole.” 22 Indeed,

“it is only happiness in the aggregate which has an intrinsic value.” 23 Thus Bentham is

constantly on the defensive. For every civil enactment he favors, he must also answer any

anticipated objections; he must explain how a given law will result in the greatest

aggregate happiness of the community.

In the case of property law, Bentham identifies four “evils resulting from attacks
16 See, e.g., John G. Sprankling, Owning the Center of the Earth, 55 UCLA L. Rev. 979, 1022
(2008).
17JEREMY BENTHAM, BENTHAM'S THEORY OF LEGISLATION 145 (Charles Milner Atkinson trans., Oxford
U. Press 1914) (1802).
18 Id. at 146.
19 Id.
20 Id. at 147.
21 Id.
22 Id. at 21.
23 Id.

5
upon property.”24 First, Bentham assumed that the acquisition of property is good and

reasoned that the non-possession of property is therefore bad. 25 Second, Bentham argued

that man becomes emotionally invested in his property over time and would consequently

be “wound[ed] to the quick” if his property were taken away. 26 Third, the fear of losing

property would provide a disincentive to acquiring property and would prevent the

enjoyment of property already acquired.27 Finally, and perhaps most relevant to a

discussion of intellectual property law, Bentham argued that a failure to recognize

property would result in the “abatement of industry.”28

Even though Bentham attributed the flourishing of western civilization entirely to

legal protection of property,29 he was slightly more reticent to endorse strong intellectual

property protection. Bentham believed that “monopolies in general are pernicious

institutions.”30 Nevertheless, Bentham saw some utility in the recognition of intellectual

24 Id. at 151.
25 “If by calumnious reports you deter my friend from leaving me a legacy which I did not expect,
is not that doing me an injury? In what does the injury consist? Why, in the negative evil which results to
me from not possessing what I should have possessed but for your calumnies.” BENTHAM, THEORY OF
LEGISLATION, supra note 17, at 151.
26 BENTHAM, THEORY OF LEGISLATION, supra note 17, at 151-52. Fellow natural law skeptic Oliver

Wendell Holmes had perhaps the more well-known quote:


A thing which you have enjoyed and used as your own for a long time, whether
property or an opinion, takes root in your being and cannot be torn away
without your resenting the act and trying to defend yourself, however you came
by it. The law can ask no better justification than the deepest instincts of man.
Oliver Wendell Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 HARV. L. REV. 457, 477 (1897).
27 “Treasures are secretly conveyed away or buried: our enjoyment of them becomes sombre,

stealthy, and solitary, and is afraid to display itself lest cupidity should be apprised of the whereabouts of its
prey.” BENTHAM, THEORY OF LEGISLATION, supra note 17, at 152.
28 “If I once lose the hope of assuring to myself the product of my toil, I shall seek only to live

from day to day, and become unwilling to undergo labours for the benefit of my enemies.” BENTHAM,
THEORY OF LEGISLATION, supra note 17, at 152.
29 Reflecting on the domestication of North America, Bentham mused: “What has brought about

these wonders? What is it that has thus changed the surface of the earth? What has bestowed on man this
dominion over nature – splendid, fruitful, and complete? The beneficent genius is 'Security': security alone
has wrought this glorious change.” BENTHAM, THEORY OF LEGISLATION, supra note 17, at 156.
30 CLARE PETTITT, PATENT INVENTIONS—INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND THE VICTORIAN NOVEL 57, n. 84

(Oxford U. Press 2004) (quoting JEREMY BENTHAM, 1 JEREMY BENTHAM'S ECONOMIC WRITINGS: CRITICAL EDITION
BASED ON HIS PRINTED WORKS AND UNPRINTED MANUSCRIPTS 264 (Werner Stark ed., George Allen & Unwin Ltd.
1952)).

6
property, declaring patents “a recompense for industry and genius and ingenuity,” 31 a

position which had been advocated by James Madison not long before. 32

3. Friedrich Hegel

Hegel, a German philosopher in the tradition of Immanuel Kant, brought a more

ontologically nuanced approach to property theory. For Hegel, property is to be thought

of as a person manifesting his will upon his external environment. 33 Unlike Bentham who

considered property law to be a creature of the government, 34 Hegel viewed property as

an “absolute right” of man.35

In contrast to most of his predecessors for whom discussion of “intellectual

property” would have been anachronistic, Hegel specifically addressed “[t]he process by

which a mental possession passes into the external world and comes under the category of

a legal property.”36 In so doing, Hegel articulated concepts (if not phrases of art) that are

part and parcel of modern Copyright law. For example, Hegel may have foreshadowed

the First Sale Doctrine37 when he wrote that “the purchaser of such a product of mental

skill possesses the full use and value of his single copy, [and] he is complete and free

owner of that one copy.”38 Similarly, Hegel describes how mental property can be

acquired from others through the process of learning: “[T]hose who have worked over the

material a second time may regard as their own possession whatever money they may be

31 PETTITT, supra note 30, at 57 (citing BENTHAM, ECONOMIC WRITINGS, supra note 30, at 263).
32 See infra note 78 and accompanying text.
33 GEORG WILHELM FRIEDRICH HEGEL, THE PHILOSOPHY OF RIGHT 48 (Samuel Walter Dyde trans.,

George Bell & Sons 1896) (1821).


34 See supra note 17 and accompanying text.
35 HEGEL, PHILOSOPHY OF RIGHT, supra note 33, at 51.
36 Id.
37 “[T]he owner of a particular copy . . . lawfully made . . . is entitled, without the authority of the

copyright owner, to sell or otherwise dispose of the possession of that copy or phonorecord.” Copyright
Act of 1976 § 109(a), 17 U.S.C. § 109(a) (2009).
38 HEGEL, PHILOSOPHY OF RIGHT, supra note 33, at 73.

7
able to extract from their work, and may contend that they have a right to reproduce

it.”39 This conclusion prefigures the fair use copyright exception of “transformative

works.”40

Nevertheless, Hegel's formulation contained some limitations which could dampen

an attempt to marshal his views in favor of strong intellectual property protection. While

Hegel was concerned with protecting creative works,41 he also realized that creating a

dichotomy between a right of ownership and right of duplication posed a potential

problem.

For Hegel, partial use of a thing was distinct from ownership of a thing. 42 Since

property is, by its nature, the embodiment of a person's will in an external object, 43 how

can one person be said to own an object which is, at least in part, the embodiment of the

will of another?44 “The total use of a thing cannot be mine, while the abstract property is

somebody else's. The object would in that case contain a contradiction. It would be

39 Id. at 74.
40 “Transformative works,” as opposed to “derivative works,” as explained by the Supreme Court:
The central purpose of this investigation [into whether the use is for criticism,
or comment, or news reporting] is to see, in Justice Story's words, whether the
new work merely “supersede[s] the objects” of the original creation, [Folsom v.
Marsh, 9 F. Cas. 342, 349 (C.C. Mass. 1841)], or instead adds something new,
with a further purpose or different character, altering the first with new
expression, meaning, or message; it asks, in other words, whether and to what
extent the new work is "transformative." (citation omitted). Although such
transformative use is not absolutely necessary for a finding of fair use . . . the
goal of copyright, to promote science and the arts, is generally furthered by the
creation of transformative works. Such works thus lie at the heart of the fair
use doctrine's guarantee of breathing space within the confines of copyright . . .
and the more transformative the new work, the less will be the significance of
other factors, like commercialism, that may weigh against a finding of fair use.
Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 578–79 (1994).
41 “The primary and most important claim of trade and commerce is to give them surety against

highway robbery. In the same way the primary though merely negative demand of the sciences and arts is
to insure the workers in these fields against larceny, and give their property protection.” See HEGEL,
PHILOSOPHY OF RIGHT, supra note 33, at 74.
42 HEGEL, PHILOSOPHY OF RIGHT, supra note 33, at 65.
43 See supra note 33 and accompanying text.
44 HEGEL, PHILOSOPHY OF RIGHT, supra note 33, at 66 (“How can what is mine in one single object be

without qualification my individual exclusive will, and also be the individual exclusive will of another?”).

8
wholly penetrated by my will and yet contain something impenetrable, namely, the empty

will of another.”45

Hegel considers this problem in the context of intellectual property when

discussing the separation of an object from the power to reproduce it. 46 To solve the

problem, Hegel identifies the wealth-creation use of intellectual property as distinct from

its “natural use.”47 For example, the natural use of a book would be in reading it and

deriving enjoyment or learning from its contents. The wealth-creation use would, of

course, be manufacturing copies and selling them to the public. By drawing this

distinction in the realm of “external use,” the ownership of an object in Hegel's paradigm

is not destroyed because the owner enjoys the full realm of its natural use, even where the

artist reserves the wealth-creation use for himself.48

B. Legal Development of Intellectual Property Rights

We in twenty-first century America have inherited an evolving legal system that

traces copyright antecedents back over 500 years. By viewing this history in light of the

foregoing philosophical principles, it becomes evident how far copyright law has drifted

from its moorings.

The summary in the previous subpart spans the ferment of philosophical

development from roughly 1690 to the early 1800s. This same time period saw the birth

and infancy of the United States. Because many of the Founding Fathers were both

philosophers and statesmen, the United States Constitution was born out of legal theory

inherited from Europe as well as contemporary philosophy. Thus the Copyright Clause

45 HEGEL, PHILOSOPHY OF RIGHT, supra note 33, at 66.


46 Id. at 73.
47 Id. at 74.
48 Id.

9
bears the mark of Queen Mary as well as of Locke, Bentham, and others.

1. Competing Visions of Copyright and its Legal Evolution in England

Western civilization's first foray into copyright protection was born out of a

markedly “unAmerican” motive: government censorship. With the excommunication of

King Henry VIII in 1534, the English Reformation was in full swing. 49 By 1557, King

Henry's daughter, Queen Mary I was desperately trying to undo her father's separation of

England from the Bishop of Rome.50 In order to do this, she needed a way to control the

press,51 which the Reformers had been using to great advantage. On November 5, 1558,

less than two weeks before her death, Queen Mary introduced the Licensing Act into

Parliament that required all published works to be printed under the royal seal. 52 The

previous year, the Queen had granted a royal charter to a guild of printers and publishers

normally referred to as the Stationers' Company. 53 Combining that royal charter with the

Licensing Act resulted in a system under which only members of the Stationers' Company

could lawfully publish works in England.

The nature of the government-granted guild monopoly is important to understand.

The Stationers' Company was not chartered to protect the integrity of intellectual

property nor to compensate authors to induce them to create more works. On the

contrary, the fundamental purpose of conferring such power was to allow the British

Crown to control the press, to limit the spread of information, and to suppress material it

deemed undesirable.54 The Stationers' Company exercised this generous grant of


49 FRANCIS CHARLES MASSINGBERD, THE ENGLISH REFORMATION 281-82 (Longmans, Green, & Co. 1866)
(1842).
50 LYMAN RAY PATTERSON, COPYRIGHT IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE 29 (Vanderbilt University Press 1968).
51 Id.
52 Id. at 29-30.
53 Id. at 29. The full name of the guild is “The Worshipful Company of Stationers and Newspaper
Makers.”
54 See, e.g., PATTERSON, supra note 50, at 30 (quoting GEORGE UNWIN, THE GILDS AND COMPANIES OF

10
authority in a fairly misanthropic manner, ensuring the maximization of profits for larger,

influential guild members.55

One interesting feature of the Stationers' Company guild monopoly was that it was

not in any sense based on a concept of intellectual property. The Stationers' Company

had the exclusive right to print and publish works, but the scope of the monopoly did not

include modifications to works or the creation of what we would today call derivative

works.56 In other words, the “stationers' copyright” 57 was a privilege to print, not an

ownership of the work itself.58 In this sense, the Stationers' copyright was more limited in

scope than a modern statutory copyright, which extends to nearly every economic

advantage that can be realized from a given work.59

In other respects, however, the Stationers' copyright was a broader privilege. Most

notably, the sale of a manuscript to a printer operated as a “perpetual lease of personal

property” for the purpose of publishing.60 The physical possession of a manuscript was

LONDON 261 (Methuen & Co. 1908)) (“The amount of attention the Stationers' Company received from the
government, however, was such that no other company 'ever attained the same degree of monopoly as that
which the State thought it expedient to confer on the Stationers.' The reason for this, of course, was the
government's need to control the press.”); Lasercomb Am., Inc. v. Reynolds, 911 F.2d 970, 974 (4th Cir.
1990) (“The development of copyright law in England likewise grew out of a differentiation by Parliament
between a monopoly that restricts publication of works and a limited copyright that encourages the efforts
of authors.”); Alfred Bell & Co. v. Catalda Fine Arts, 191 F.2d 99, 100 n.3 (2d Cir. 1951) (quoting STEPHEN
P. LADAS, THE INTERNATIONAL PROTECTION OF LITERARY AND ARTISTIC PROPERTY 15 (Macmillan Co. 1938))
(observing that the early British publishing monopolies “were not granted to encourage learning or for the
benefit of authors”).
55 Glynn S. Lunney, Jr., The Death of Copyright: Digital Technology, Private Copying, and the

Digital Millennium Copyright Act, 87 VA. L. REV. 813, 815 (2001) (“[S]ecuring the profits of a favored few
within the guild seemed to be the Stationers' Company's guiding principle.”).
56 PATTERSON, supra note 50, at 10.
57 The term “copy right” is in a sense anachronistic because it did not appear in the Stationers'

Company register until 1701. PATTERSON, supra note 50, at 4 (citing III EYRE & RIVINGTON, A TRANSCRIPT OF
THE REGISTERS OF THE WORSHIPFUL COMPANY OF STATIONERS, 1640-1708 A.D. 494, 496 (1914)). The phrase
“stationers' copyright” is generally used to refer to the right to print that was created by a combination of
royal grant and the Stationers' Company's own regulations made pursuant to their monopoly. PATTERSON,
supra note 50, at 4-5.
58 PATTERSON, supra note 50, at 9.
59 Id. at 11.
60 Id. at 10.

11
the equivalent of permission to print it, creating an eventual source of tension between

authors and publishers. Could an author write a revised manuscript and sell this second

edition to a rival publisher? This was one of the issues that arose under the Stationers'

copyright which ultimately and ironically contributed to its demise.

In 1694, the Licensing Act finally expired, much to the consternation of the

Stationers.61 Feeling the need for more adequate protections and desiring a legal

recognition of a perpetual and exclusive right to publish, the Stationers' Company lobbied

Parliament for new, stronger legislation.62 What they received, however, was far different

from what they requested.63

The Statute of Anne was passed in 1709 as a direct result of the Stationers'

lobbying efforts.64 Under this new law, the rights to literary works were vested in authors

instead of publishers, and even then only for fourteen years. 65 The new statute specified

the scope of the rights granted, abolishing the self-serving private regulations of the

Stationers' Company.66 Perhaps most importantly, the Statute of Anne was a dramatic

shift away from government censorship in favor of the enrichment of the public. 67 So

important was this change that the law is actually titled: “An Act for the encouragement

of learning by vesting the 'copies' of printed books in the authors or purchasers of such

copies during the times therein mentioned.” 68 This shift in focus is perhaps the most

important effect of the Statute of Anne and the role it played in the development of

modern copyright law.


61 THOMAS EDWARD SCRUTTON, THE LAW OF COPYRIGHT 30 (William Clowes & Sons 1903) (1883).
62 Id. at 30-31.
63 PATTERSON, supra note 50, at 12.
64 SCRUTTON, supra note 61, at 31.
65 PATTERSON, supra note 50, at 13.
66 Lunney, supra note 55, at 816-17.
67 Id. at 817.
68 SCRUTTON, supra note 61, at 31.

12
2. Copyright, the Constitution, and the Founding of the United States

A “behind the scenes” look at the drafting of the United States Constitution reveals

that many of the principles discussed up to this point factored into the decisions made by

the founding fathers. By understanding some of the historical context of the drafting of

the Constitution, we may see with greater clarity how modern legislation (which still

purports to be based on the Constitution) has gotten out of step.

The United States Constitution was drafted by the Constitutional Convention, the

final, signed draft being read in Congress on September 20, 1787. 69 After it was

transmitted to the states for ratification, many delegates began to feel that it needed a bill

of rights, an enumeration of fundamental human rights which must not be infringed by

the government.70 During the time between the drafting of the Constitution and the final

ratification of the Bill of Rights in December 1791, 71 the drafters engaged in considerable

discussion regarding the content and scope of the proposed Bill of Rights.

69DAVID K. WATSON, THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES: ITS HISTORY APPLICATION AND
CONSTRUCTION 1344 (1910).
70 Id. at 1351. Justice Harlan eloquently described the process of the formation of the Bill of

Rights:
When the Constitution was adopted by the convention of 1787 and placed
before the people for their acceptance or rejection, many wise statesmen whose
patriotism no one then questioned or now questions earnestly objected to its
acceptance upon the ground that it did not contain a bill of rights guarding the
fundamental guaranties of life, liberty, and property against the unwarranted
exercise of power by the national government. But the friends of the
Constitution, believing that the failure to accept it would destroy all hope for
permanent union among the people of the original states, and following the
advice of Washington, who was the leader of the constitutional forces, met this
objection by showing that when the Constitution had been accepted by the
requisite number of states and thereby became the supreme law of the land,
such amendments could be adopted as would relieve the apprehensions of those
who deemed it necessary, by express provisions, to guard against the
infringement by the agencies of the general government of any of the essential
rights of American freemen. This view prevailed, and the implied pledge thus
given was carried out by the first Congress, which promptly adopted and
submitted to the people of the several states the first ten Amendments. These
Amendments have ever since been regarded as the national Bill of Rights.
Maxwell v. Dow, 176 U.S. 581, 606–07 (1900) (Harlan, J., dissenting).
71 WATSON, supra note 69, at 1368.

13
During this time, Thomas Jefferson and James Madison had an exchange which

has particular bearing on our discussion of copyright law. On July 31, 1788, Jefferson

wrote to Madison to register his suggestions regarding the need for a Bill of Rights. 72 By

that time, nine states had ratified the Constitution, which Jefferson referred to as “a good

canvas, on which some strokes only want retouching.”73 For Jefferson, one of the issues

in need of “retouching” was copyright protection.74 Jefferson wrote that he favored the

abolition of monopolies in all cases:75 “The saying there shall be no monopolies lessens

the incitements to ingenuity, which is spurred on by the hope of a monopoly for a limited

time, as of 14 years; but the benefit even of limited monopolies is too doubtful to be

opposed to that of their general suppression.” 76 Thus while Jefferson admitted that the

lack of copyright protection (in the form of “limited monopolies” for even 14 years)

might “lessen[] the incitements to ingenuity,” he believed that it was more important to

guarantee the people freedom from such monopolies. 77

Madison's reply to Jefferson indicates only a slightly milder position:

With regard to monopolies they are justly classed among the


greatest nuisances in government. But is it clear that as
encouragements to literary works and ingenious discoveries,
they are not too valuable to be wholly renounced? Would it
not suffice to reserve in all cases a right to the public to
abolish the privilege at a price to be specified in the grant of
it? Monopolies are sacrifices of the many to the few. Where
the power is in the few it is natural for them to sacrifice the
many to their own partialities and corruptions. Where the
72 Letter from Thomas Jefferson to James Madison (July 31, 1788), in 11:1 DOCUMENTARY HISTORY
OF THECONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA, 1786-1870, at 824 (1905).
73 Id.
74 Id. Jefferson referred to “monopolies,” a phrase which denoted not only copyright protection

but patents as well. For Bentham's use of the term, see supra note 30 and accompanying text.
75 Letter from Thomas Jefferson, supra note 72, at 824.
76 Id. at 825.
77 Jefferson's letter also addressed other issues which did ultimately find their way into the Bill of

Rights, perhaps suggesting that Jefferson believed that freedom from copyright was as fundamental a
human liberty as freedom of religion, freedom of the press, and the writ of habeas corpus.

14
power, as with us, is in the many not in the few, the danger
can not be very great that the few will be thus favored. It is
much more to be dreaded that the few will be unnecessarily
sacrificed to the many.78

At least with respect to his hesitancy to abolish copyright protection altogether,

Madison here articulates the utilitarian argument which would later be espoused by

Bentham.79 For Madison, the allowance of limited monopolies had an accompanying

benefit that militated in favor of its retention and the Constitution already had a sufficient

built-in protection against abuses.

Madison believed that the form of government created by the Constitution

obviated the need for a Bill of Rights altogether. Since the power of the government

derives from the popular will and not monarchical fiat, Madison felt it unnecessary for

the people to enumerate rights not to be trampled by the government. After all, if the

power were ever to be wrested away from the people thereby giving rise to a situation

where a Bill of Rights would be needed, would it even be effectual? As Madison put it, in

the context of a proposed prohibition of standing armies, “[s]hould an army in time of

peace be gradually established in our neighbourhood by Britain or Spain, declarations on

paper would have as little effect in preventing a standing force for the public safety.” 80

In the context of copyright protection, while Madison considered monopolies

“among the greatest nuisances in government,” he believed that the form of our fledgling

government was sufficient to prevent the inevitable abuses feared by Jefferson and

others.81 A monopoly is a “sacrifice[] of the many to the few,” meaning that the general

78 Letter from James Madison to Thomas Jefferson (Oct. 17, 1788), in 5 DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF
THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA, 1786-1870, at 90-91 (1905).
79 See, e.g., PETTITT, supra note 30 and accompanying text.
80 Letter from James Madison, supra note 78, at 90.
81 Id. at 91.

15
public must give up some of its rights in favor of the monopoly-holder. If the few

monopoly-holders wield the power of government, according to Madison, “it is natural

for them to sacrifice the many to their own partialities and corruptions.” 82 But Madison

believed that putting the power of government in the hands of the people would prevent

this unhappy outcome. As Madison explained earlier in the same letter,

Wherever the real power in a Government lies, there is the


danger of oppression. In our Government, the real power lies
in the majority of the Community, and the invasion of private
rights is chiefly to be apprehended, not from acts of
Government contrary to the sense of its constituents, but from
acts in which the Government is the mere instrument of the
major number of the constituents. . . . Wherever there is an
interest and power to do wrong, wrong will generally be
done, and not less readily by a powerful and interested party
than by a powerful and interested prince.83

Therefore, because the real power of the government lies in the many, the many are

protected from an undue invasion of their rights by the few monopoly-holders. As long

as the government is the “mere instrument of the major number of the constituents,” the

public need not fear the few. Only when the “power is in the few,” or in a “powerful and

interested party” will the people be “sacrifice[d] . . . to their own partialities and

corruptions.”

In the end, Madison's support for the so-called “copyright clause” was rooted in

social utility. Conspicuously absent is any notion of natural rights springing from a

concept of intellectual property. Although the philosophical groundwork for a moral

rights rationale existed, it is clear that the Constitutional recognition of “monopolies”

arose out of a desire to encourage literary and scientific development rather than a

recognition of a natural right of authors and inventors.


82 Id.
83 Id. at 88.

16
Although Madison's support of copyright flowed from strictly utilitarian concerns,

moral rights did play a significant part in Madison's intellectual property paradigm.

Writing in 1792, Madison explained that property “embraces everything to which a man

may attach a value and have a right, and which leaves to every one else the like

advantage.”84 He continued:

[A] man has a property in his opinions and the free


communication of them. . . . He has an equal property in the
free use of his faculties, and free choice of the objects on
which to employ them. In a word, as a man is said to have a
right to his property, he may be equally said to have a
property in his rights.85

This two-fold discussion of the use and object of one's faculties indicates that for

Madison, not only does man have the right to think, work, and communicate as he

chooses, he also has the right to think, work, and communicate about whatever he

chooses. In other words, for Madison the free use of “intellectual property” is a moral

right. Accordingly, Madison had harsh words for the government that unreasonably

inhibits this right.

That is not a just government, nor is property secure under it,


where arbitrary restrictions, exemptions, and monopolies
deny to part of its citizens that free use of their faculties and
free choice of their occupations which not only constitute
their property in the general sense of the word, but are the
means of acquiring property strictly so called.86

Taken together with his earlier writings on the copyright monopoly, these

pronouncements make clear that Madison considered arbitrary restriction of free

expression in the form of unreasonable monopolies to be an unjust infringement of a

84 4 JAMES MADISON, LETTERS AND OTHER WRITINGS OF JAMES MADISON: 1829-1836, at 478 (1884)
(emphasis original). In this respect, Madison seems to echo Locke who considered a man's property right to
not encompass hording. See supra note 5 and accompanying text.
85 Id.
86 Id. at 479.

17
human right.87

Under this paradigm, copyright is problematic for two reasons. First, the grant of

monopoly power has the distasteful tendency to concentrate power in the hands of the

privileged few if proper checks and balances are not not carefully employed. Second, by

its very nature, copyright achieves its purpose by treading upon the public's right to freely

employ its faculties as it chooses. While Madison nevertheless considered the benefits of a

conservative grant of copyright “too valuable to be wholly renounced,” 88 he made clear

that such a grant would inevitably lead to the abuses feared by Jefferson and others if the

power of the government were ever to be wielded by the “few” or a “powerful and

interested party.”89 Unfortunately, the subsequent development of U.S. Copyright law is

the story of how the power of the government gradually shifted into the hands of the few

powerful and interested parties.

3. Congress and the Copyright Acts

A utilitarian copyright system such as that of the United States must balance the

private interests of authors against the public interest of society. Too many rights in the

hands of authors restricts freedom and leads to an anticommons problem. 90 Too few

rights in the hands of authors leads to what Hegel called the “abatement of industry” 91

and a resulting paucity of creative works. Ideally, Congress should attempt to achieve a

perfect balance, giving equal weight to the rights and interests of all parties and society as

87 See also Tom W. Bell, Escape from Copyright: Market Success vs. Statutory Failure in the
Protection of Expressive Works, 69 U. CIN. L. REV. 741, 773 (2001) (“By restricting what free people do
with their voices, pens, and presses, copyright plainly falls afoul of Madison's indictment of government
monopolies.”).
88 Letter from James Madison, supra note 78, at 90.
89 Id. at 88.
90 See infra note 134 and accompanying text.
91 See supra note 28 and accompanying text.

18
a whole. In practice, however, it appears that authors92 have their thumbs on the scale.

The first Congressional exercise of the power granted by the Copyright Clause 93

was the Copyright Act of 1790.94 Mirroring the time limitations of the Statute of Anne,95

the 1790 Act granted an initial copyright term of 14 years and allowed for a renewal term

of an additional 14 years.96 Since that time, subsequent revisions of the Copyright Act

have only lengthened these time limitations and radically expanded the scope of copyright

protection.

The 1831 revision of the 1709 Act doubled the initial term to 28 years with a 14-

year renewal term.97 It also allowed an author's heirs to trigger the extension term 98 and

prevented the copying of portions of copyrighted books. 99

The next major revision was the Copyright Act of 1909. 100 In addition to

broadening the scope of works covered by copyright (even including a catch-all provision

encompassing “all writings of an author”),101 the 1909 Act extended the renewal term to

28 years (for a total protection period of 56 years). 102 The 1909 Act underwent periodic

revision. In 1971, near the end of its life, it was amended to include sound recordings as

a protected work.103 This provision was carried over into the next major iteration, the
92 Or more accurately, authorship industry lobbies.
93 U.S. CONST. art. I, § 8.
94 Copyright Act of 1790, 1 Stat. 124.
95 Copyright Act of 1709, 8 Anne, c. 19, §§ I, XI. Section I provided an initial 14-year term for

new works while section XI allowed for the 14-year renewal term.
96 1 Stat. 124 § 1.
97 4 Stat. 436 § 1.
98 4 Stat. 436 § 2.
99 4 Stat. 436 § 7. This was later removed in an 1870 revision which also prohibited the making

of a translation of a book without the author's consent. Act of July 8, 1870, §§85-111, 41st Cong., 2d
Sess., 16 Stat. 198, 212-16.
100 Copyright Act of 1909, 35 Stat. 1075.
101 35 Stat. 1075 § 4.
102 35 Stat. 1075 § 24. This section actually resulted in an even larger practical extension by

beginning the term of protection at first publication rather than initial registration of the copyright which
was typically done long before the work was ready to be published.
103 Act of October 15, 1971, Pub. L. No. 92-140, 92d Cong., 1st Sess., 85 Stat. 391.

19
Copyright Act of 1976.104

The 1976 Act introduced several revolutionary changes to the benefit of copyright

holders. Most notably, the two-tiered scheme requiring renewal was abolished in favor of

a single term beginning when the work is created and lasting the entire life of the author

plus 50 years besides.105 The 1976 Act also did away with the publication requirement of

prior acts as well as an enumeration of the types of work protected. Instead, it

encompassed any “original works of authorship fixed in any tangible medium of

expression,”106 whether published or unpublished.107

Other provisions intending to protect the public interest included the codification

of the judicially-created “fair use” exceptions,108 exemptions for public libraries,109

education and religious institutions,110 non-profit entities, and public broadcasting uses. 111

A decade after it became effective, the 1976 Act received significant amendment in

the form of the Berne Convention Implementation Act of 1988. 112 The most notable

“ground level” change wrought by this Act was the abolition of the mandatory notice

requirement for published works.113

But Congress was not done. In 1998, the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension

Act114 tacked an additional 20 years on to all existing copyrights, bringing the new

104 17 U.S.C. §§ 101-810.


105 17 U.S.C. § 302(a) (1976).
106 17 U.S.C. § 102(a).
107 17 U.S.C. § 104(a).
108 17 U.S.C. § 107.
109 17 U.S.C. § 108.
110 17 U.S.C. § 110.
111 17 U.S.C. § 118. Notably, section 118 sets up a system of “compulsory licensing” under which

Copyright Royalty Judges set fixed royalty rates for certain types of copyrighted works and such works may
be used in enumerate manners provided the royalty is paid. This system will serve as a model for the
Copyright Buyout proposal I advance in Section II-B-3 infra.
112 Act of October 31, 1988, Pub. L. No. 100-568, 100th Cong., 2d Sess., 102 Stat. 2854.
113 17 U.S.C. § 401(a) (1988).
114 Pub. L. No. 105-298, 112 Stat. 2827.

20
copyright term to its present115 duration, the life of the author plus 70 years.116

Shortly thereafter, Congress enacted the Digital Millennium Copyright Act. 117 One

of the primary effects of the DMCA was the creation of the anti-circumvention provisions

of § 1201. This section governs legal protection of technological measures that had been

developed to prevent unauthorized copying and distribution of copyrighted digital

material. It does so by prohibiting a “person” from “circumvent[ing] a technological

measure that effectively controls access” to a copyrighted work. 118 One thus runs afoul of

this section by, among other things, removing or bypassing “digital rights management”

(DRM) schemes on digital files, or by employing unauthorized means of decrypting media

sold and distributed on physical media such as DVD and Bluray Disc.

While the most obvious trend in the evolution of American Copyright law is the

ever-lengthening duration of copyright protection (see Fig. 1 below), this cursory

historical survey also reveals an alarming doctrinal shift in the legal principles

undergirding copyright law in general. The elimination of the registration requirement in

the Berne Convention Implementation Act of 1998 emphasized the ideological paradigm

shift that had been occurring since the beginning of the century, a shift away from the

utilitarian rationale held by Madison and Jefferson and toward the natural law view of

continental Europe. No longer is copyright a privilege that must be claimed by affixing

that iconic encircled letter “C.” Since 1998, simply by changing “shall” to “may,” 119

115 As of the writing of this Essay.


116 17 U.S.C. § 302(a) (2010).
117 Pub. L. 105-304, 112 Stat. 2860 (1998). The DMCA is very complex litigation designed to

implement two 1996 treaties of the World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO). Its provisions and
effects are the subject of other scholarship and this Article will not attempt to cover them all. For a more
detailed analysis of the DMCA, see Lunney, supra note 55.
118 17 U.S.C. 1201(a)(1)(A).
119 Before the Berne Convention Implementation Act of 1998, § 401(a) read in relevant part, “a

notice of copyright as provided by this section shall be placed on publicly distributed copies” of the work
(emphasis added).

21
copyright (and all its attendant restrictions and reservations) now attaches itself a priori

to every creative endeavor undertaken in the United States.

Fig. 1120

Another indication of the drift away from our Constitutional moorings has been

described by Professor Glynn Lunney who observed that the anti-circumvention

provisions of the DMCA operate as a return to the guild monopoly scheme of the

Stationers' Company heyday.121 Then, as now, a technological key was required in order

to disseminate information to the public and the government granted access to that

technology only to a select few. Then, that technology was the printing press; today, it is

decryption.122 In both instances, the power is in the few, the very scenario that Madison

and Jefferson agreed would be disastrous, but were confident could never happen in the

United States.123

120 Tom W. Bell, Trend of Maximum U.S. General Copyright Term, July 23, 2008,
http://www.tomwbell.com/writings/(C)_Term.html. The chart is licensed under a Creative Commons
Attribution-Share Alike 3.0 Unported License.
121 Lunney, supra note 55, at 819.
122 Id.
123 See supra note 78 and accompanying text.

22
So how did this happen?

Public choice theory offers a ready explanation for copyright's


steady growth. Those who create, own, and distribute
expressive works know who they are, what they want, and
how badly they want it. Unsurprisingly, such copyright
protectionists approach Congress as a well-defined, highly-
motivated, and apparently effective lobby. In contrast, those
who might benefit from a less expansive Copyright Act
typically have disparate, inchoate, slight, or non-monetized
wishes. Such anti-protectionists thus have relatively little
impact on the legislative process. In sum, copyright policy
combines all the elements of a public choice tragedy:
concentrated benefits, diffuse costs, and pervasive state
power.124

In other words, money talks. By granting authors an economic advantage in the

form of a market monopoly, copyright law (which was originally intended to exist only

for the public good) has become the primary instrumentality through which “the few”

have been able to form powerful empires and amass fantastic wealth. The incremental

and gradual expansion of this economic advantage has provided both the means and the

incentive to continually strive to further expand it. This “vicious cycle” shows no signs of

abatement.125

C. Foundational Socio-Economic Principles of Property Rights

As U.S. Copyright law has grown and expanded, so has the field of economics and

its role in legal theory and the lawmaking process. Space precludes a comprehensive

survey of all the economic forces driving modern copyright law, but several principles help

illustrate how we got where we are and what might be done about it.

1. The Commons – Tragedy or Comedy?

In 1968, renowned ecologist Garret Hardin published a highly influential article

124 Bell, supra note 87 at 786 (internal citations omitted).


125 Id. at 787.

23
entitled The Tragedy of the Commons.126 The purpose of this oft-cited article was to

illustrate how human nature cannot sustain communally-owned resources. To

demonstrate the result of under-privatization of property, Hardin asks the reader to

envision an open pasture in which all herdsmen may graze their herds freely. 127 Assuming

the herdsmen act rationally and in their own self interest, each will realize that if he adds

cattle to his herd, the cost (in terms of reduced supply) will be borne by every herdsman,

but he will reap the entire benefit of the additional cattle. 128 Since the herdsman realizes

that the benefit (to him) outweighs the cost (to him), he concludes that it is a good idea to

add an animal to his herd.129 And another, and another, and another. Since the common

pasture cannot sustain an infinite number of animals, the common resource will quickly

become exhausted as each user seeks to maximize his own advantage. 130 The answer to

the resulting “tragedy of the commons” is to parcel the communal field in such a way that

each herdsman owns his own portion. Each herdsman now reaps the benefit and bears

the whole cost of adding cattle to his herd, an effect economists refer to as “internalizing

externalities.”

One important feature of Hardin's analysis is that it is predicated on the principle

of scarcity. In a sense, the concept of scarcity is the engine that drives market economics.

Whereas supply and demand dictate the price of goods, scarcity dictates whether a thing

is a commodity at all. As Margaret Radin has put it, “[t]here will be no property in a

particular good if the good is so plentiful that everyone can take what she wants and there

126 Garrett Hardin, The Tragedy of the Commons, SCIENCE, Dec. 13, 1968, at 1243.
127 Id. at 1244.
128 Id.
129 Id.
130 Id.

24
will always be enough left.”131 In other words, if there is only so much of a thing,

property law is a necessary means of avoiding the tragedy of the commons.

When a book is printed, there are only so many physical copies in existence and

transferring them is, in an important respect, a zero-sum game. If you own a book and I

take it from you, it means that I gain and you lose. The same is not true of the story

contained within the book. If you impart the story to me, you do so without losing it

yourself. Thus information is not naturally a scarce resource. Information, ideas, and

even expressions can be multiplied infinitely, instantly, with little or no cost, and without

ever running out. Because of this, copyright law is a means of artificially creating scarcity

in order to support a market for intellectual property. 132 Far from being a tragedy of the

commons in intellectual property, as Mark Lemley has observed, “an information

commons is a 'comedy' in which everyone benefits.”133 Indeed, if there is a tragedy at all,

it arises from the inverse of the commons.

2. An Anticommons Problem?

Thirty years after Hardin's article warning against the consequences of under-

privatization appeared in Science magazine, those pages featured an article by Michigan

Law School professors Michael A. Heller and Rebecca S. Eisenberg which discussed the

opposite problem: the over-privatization of property.134 Termed the tragedy of the

anticommons, Heller and Eisenberg used the field of biomedical research to show that

when too many people have the right to exclude others from a resource, that resource can
131 Margaret Jane Radin, Property Evolving in Cyberspace, 15 J.L. & COM. 509, 515 (1996).
132 Mark A. Lemley, Property, Intellectual Property, and Free Riding, 83 TEX. L. REV. 1031, 1055
(2005) (“Intellectual property, then, is not a response to allocative distortions resulting from scarcity, as real
property law is. Rather, it is a conscious decision to create scarcity in a type of good in which it is
ordinarily absent in order to artificially boost the economic returns to innovation.”).
133 Id. at 1051.
134 Michael A. Heller & Rebecca S. Eisenberg, Can Patents Deter Innovation? The Anticommons

in Biomedical Research, SCIENCE, May 1, 1998, at 698.

25
become under-utilized, leading to socially undesirable outcomes. 135 The example given by

the authors is the proliferation of street kiosks in the shadows of vacant storefronts in

developing post-Soviet republics.136 Why would so many vendors choose to operate

flimsy street carts while the storefronts remained empty?

One reason was that the transition governments often failed


to endow any individual with a bundle of rights that
represents full ownership. Instead, fragmented rights were
distributed to various socialist-era stakeholders, including
private or quasi-private enterprises, workers' collectives,
privatization agencies, and local, regional, and federal
governments. No one could set up shop without first
collecting rights from each of the other owners.137

The obstacle of obtaining permission from numerous rights-holders is the linchpin

of the tragedy of the anticommons and has particular significance in the discussion of

intellectual property and copyright. Consider the example of the typical big-budget

motion picture. It is not uncommon for a Hollywood producer to have to obtain

intellectual property licenses from numerous people in order to create a movie. Licenses

may have to be obtained from authors of books upon which the story is based, musicians

and songwriters whose music is to be used or adapted in the film, visual artists whose

works may be in view of the camera, companies whose names or logos appear or are

mentioned, even artists upon whose magazine cover the movie poster is based. 138

But why should this be necessary? In most cases, a Hollywood motion picture will

not compete in the same market as the underlying works which must nevertheless be

licensed under to current U.S. copyright law. Even in the case of strict book-to-screen
135 Id.
136 Id.
137 Id.
138 In the case of the latter, Columbia Pictures was successfully sued by Saul Steinberg after

Columbia created a poster for the movie “Moscow on the Hudson” that appeared substantially similar to
the cover of an issue of The New Yorker that had been designed by Steinberg. Steinberg v. Columbia
Pictures Indus., Inc., 663 F. Supp. 706 (S.D.N.Y. 1987).

26
adaptations, the movie is not competing against the book for sales or market share. 139

The same is true of musical soundtracks, visual art, and other forms of copyrightable

expression. Despite the fact that the primary markets for the underlying works will

generally not be negatively impacted by their use in a motion picture, the recognition of a

right to restrict derivative works (for example) forces the producer to seek out and

negotiate with numerous individual rights-holders. The result is an entertainment

anticommons in which only the privileged few may compete.

3. Free Riding and Copyright

The tragedy of the commons provides a justification for internalizing negative

externalities through property law; that is, using the concept of ownership to get people

to bear the costs associated with their own behavior. The economic principle of free

riding deals with the inverse: internalizing positive externalities. The focus here is on

ensuring that people reap the rewards associated with their behavior, again through the

instrumentality of property law. This focus has had a profound impact on the

development of the notion of “intellectual property,” and by extension, U.S. copyright

law.

Free riding occurs when someone “obtain[s] a benefit from someone else's

investment.”140 In many contexts, the problems arising from free riding are readily
139 Indeed, movie or television adaptations of books often increase demand for the underlying
work. For a recent example, consider the fact that within four days of the release of the trailer for the
upcoming movie Scott Pilgrim vs. The World, “all six volumes of the Bryan Lee O'Malley [graphic novel
series, on which the movie is based] – including the final installment, which won't be released for another
four months – rest[ed] comfortably in Amazon.com's Top 20 Bestsellers in Graphic Novels.” Kevin
Melrose, 'Trailer effect' gives Scott Pilgrim series an Amazon sales boost,
http://robot6.comicbookresources.com/2010/03/trailer-effect-gives-scott-pilgrim-series-an-amazon-sales-
boost/ (last visited May 12, 2010). Another example involving comic book screen adaptations is the so-
called “Spidey Effect,” which describes the dramatic increase in sales of Spiderman comic books in the wake
of the 2002 movie adaptation. See Alexander Coolidge, The Spidey Effect, SARASOTA HERALD-TRIBUNE, May
10, 2002, at D1, available at http://news.google.com/newspapers?id=WEIgAAAAIBAJ&sjid=
1X8EAAAAIBAJ&pg=3981%2C4826321.
140 Lemley, supra note 132, at 1040.

27
apparent. Companies and individuals are less likely to make risky investments if

competitors can reap the benefits without paying for them. Would Coca-Cola have

developed its secret formula without the ability to prevent competitors from using it? But

in other contexts, attempts to eliminate free riding would strike the average person as

absurd. No reasonable person would expect to charge his neighbor for the benefit

received from looking at his freshly-planted flower bed. 141 Property law generally does

not allow property owners to recapture the full social value of their investments, as the

flower bed example indicates.142 So how much is enough? More importantly, how much

is too much?

In the intellectual property context, the conflict can be illustrated best with a

borrowed example, J.R.R. Tolkein's The Lord of the Rings book series.143 To the strict

utilitarian such as Bentham or Madison, it would be appropriate for Copyright law to

restrict the unauthorized copying of Tolkein's books in order to allow Tolkein to be

compensated, thus providing him with the necessary incentive to write the books in the

first place. In other words, copyright is a government-created economic monopoly to

prevent the author from having to compete with his own work.

Yet the social value of Tolkein's masterpiece is not bounded by the pages of his

books. The story has spawned numerous other works such as smash hit motion pictures,

cartoon adaptations, musical works, and even highly successful video games. 144 At the

big-picture level, these represent positive externalities that are not encompassed by a

141 Id. at 1048.


142 Id. at 1046 (“We do not permit producers to capture the full social value of their output. Nor
do we permit the owners even of real property to internalize the full positive externalities associated with
their property.”).
143 See Alina Ng, Copyright's Empire: Why the Law Matters, 11:2 MARQ. INTELL. PROP. L. REV. 337,

342-43 (2007).
144 Id.

28
simple prohibition of copying. The social value in this scenario exceeds the price the

rights-holder could recover under a simple restriction of copying. The question, therefore,

is to what degree the law should allow a rights-holder to be compensated for the full

social value of his work. To state it differently, when there is a discrepancy between the

amount of money an author can make off her work on the one hand, and what that work

is “worth” to society on the other hand, who should get the benefit of that excess value?

For the copyright protectionist concerned with minimizing or eliminating free

riding, the answer is that copyright law should allow the rights-holder to recover an

amount as close as possible to the social value of her work. 145 Professor Lemley argues

that this preoccupation with free riding has played a significant role in the inexorable

growth and expansion of U.S. copyright law.146

As should be clear by this point, the Copyright Clause was not included in the

Constitution to minimize free riding in intellectual property. Indeed, Madison and

Jefferson would likely have recoiled at the thought of copyright being used as a means of

enabling authors to commercially exploit nearly every conceivable use of their works for a

century or more.147 The expansion of copyright and the misplaced emphasis on free

145 Lemley, supra note 132, at 1041.


The way to get private parties to invest efficiently in innovation is not only
to give them exclusive ownership rights in what they produce, but to
define those rights in such a way that they permit the intellectual property
owner to capture the full social benefit of the invention. The law should
accordingly permit and even encourage mechanisms allowing intellectual
property owners to price in ways that extract consumer surplus, such as
Ramsey optimal pricing.
Id.
146 Id. at 1043 (“Courts applying the property theory of intellectual property are seeking out and

eliminating uses of a right they perceive to be free riding. . . . Even the courts that reject intellectual property
claims do so because they cannot find evidence of free riding.”).
147 Consider the fact that when Madison discussed the “public discontents resulting from the

exorbitant gains of individuals, and from the inconvenient restrictions combined with them,” (See infra note
172) he was referring to the Copyright Act of 1790 which offered a maximum of 28 years protection,
covered only books, maps, and charts, and prohibited only wholesale copying.

29
riding has turned the Constitutional rationale for copyright on its head. Madison viewed

copyright as a necessary evil that served a greater public good.148 The excess social value

was the greater good Madison had in mind, and Madison intended it to accrue to the

benefit of the people. In other words, the expansion of copyright with its attendant

emphasis on free riding destroys the social utility that the Copyright Clause was intended

to promote.149

III. WHERE DO WE GO FROM HERE?

To a certain extent, the suggestion of remedies is a futile exercise. Scholars far

more august than this Writer have identified these concerns and advocated for legislative

relief.150 Because public choice theory suggests that appeals to Congress to “roll back”

previous expansions is unlikely to be successful,151 the only viable alternatives would seem

to be either the public taking matters into its own hands, or convincing the copyright-

reliant industries that increased public access is in their best interests.

A. Civil Disobedience

Professor Glynn Lunney has analyzed many of the factors heretofore discussed and

concluded that a significant portion of the protection afforded by current copyright law is

“excess incentive” and therefore unconstitutional. 152 Accordingly, he suggests that there is
148 See supra note 87 and accompanying text.
149 See also Lunney, supra note 55, at 872.
Where copyright initially sought to protect a copyright owner against the
copying competitor in order to provide the owner with a fair opportunity
to recover the costs of her work, today it increasingly seeks to protect a
copyright owner against the loss of any opportunity to license her work in
order to permit her to capture fully the work's associated market value.
Id.
150 See, e.g., Stephen Breyer, The Uneasy Case for Copyright: A Study of Copyright in Books,

Photocopies, and Computer Programs, 84 HARV. L. REV. 281 (1970). Written during his tenure as Dean of
Harvard Law School, Justice Breyer's article preceded the Copyright Act of 1976. In his article, he analyzed
the economic factors, concluding that “although we should hesitate to abolish copyright protection, we
should equally hesitate to extend or strengthen it.” Id. at 284.
151 See supra note 124 and accompanying text.
152 Lunney, supra note 55, at 882.

30
a need for civil disobedience in the form of private copying. 153

The Constitution permits copyright protection for a specific purpose: “To promote

the Progress of Science and useful Arts.”154 The service of the public interest is therefore

the only constitutional aim of copyright law.155 Because the Constitution authorizes the

recognition of copyright as an incentive to create, the only constitutional Copyright Act is

the one that seeks to limit its protection to allowing a return only large enough to induce

the creation of the work.156 Any additional returns that are enabled by copyright

protection are “excess incentive.”157 Those works that earn only a marginal return

sufficient to induce their creation are referred to as “marginal works” and are held up as

examples of copyright doing what it is supposed to do. 158 But the majority of works are

“popular works” and all receive excess incentive to greater or lesser degrees. 159

Professor Lunney suggests that civil disobedience in the form of private copying

“enables otherwise disenfranchised consumers to express their dissatisfaction with

copyright's present scope.”160 In this respect, private copying is a form of public

pushback against the infringement of its moral rights. 161 Professor Lunney identifies a

second purpose served by private copying:

[B]y allowing individuals to determine the proper level of


protection for themselves, private copying can serve as a type
of direct democracy that avoids the agency-cost pitfalls
present when relying on a representative democratic process
153 Id. at 893.
154 U.S. CONST. art. I, § 8.
155 Lunney, supra note 55, at 817 (“Congress may enact a copyright statute, but only if, and to the

extent that, it serves the public, and not merely a private, interest.”).
156 Id. at 872-73 (“[W]en protection provides an incentive far in excess of that necessary to ensure a

work's creation, the public interest justification is far less clear.”).


157 Id. at 873.
158 Id. at 872.
159 Id.
160 Id. at 893.
161 See supra note 87 and accompanying text.

31
to determine copyright's proper scope.162

Professor Lunney identifies several “network effects” that explain why private

copying will usually only reduce the unconstitutional excess incentives and will not

threaten marginal works. The first is that popularity increases desirability. 163

[A]n important element in a work's success is whether the


work develops an audience sufficiently large to offer its
members an opportunity to share their enjoyment of the work
with each other. Once a work's audience reaches that size, the
resulting shared enjoyment reinforces the work's desirability
and enhances the work's appeal to potential new audience
members.164

The second network effect is that instances of copying are a function of

availability.165 These network effects work together in such a way that “private copying

will affect popular works disproportionately.” 166 Because an increase in popularity is

usually accompanied by an increase in excess incentive, private copying will merely serve

to allow the public to recapture some of that excess incentive which the Constitution does

not authorize anyway.167

In the eight years that have lapsed since the publication of Professor Lunney's

article, peer-to-peer (“P2P”) technology has evolved in a way that further supports his

suggestion that the incidence of private copying will more or less correspond with the

popularity of a given work. Today, the most prominent P2P technology is BitTorrent. 168

162 Lunney, supra note 55, at 893.


163 Id. at 883.
164 Id. at 884 (“[W]e should expect that a work either becomes sufficiently popular to generate a

popularity network and then becomes even more popular, or it does not and thus never will.”).
165 Id. at 883.
166 Id. at 886.
167 Id. (“[P]rivate copying is unlikely to reduce creative output. It may simply reduce the excess

incentive copyright otherwise provides for the most popular works.”)


168 Ipoque.com, Internet Study 2008/2009, http://www.ipoque.com/resources/internet-

studies/internet-study-2008_2009 (last visited May 11, 2010) (finding that the BitTorrent protocol
accounted for more traffic than any other internet protocol, with HTTP – the protocol which transmits
internet web pages – coming in second).

32
Whereas past P2P protocols focused on matching a single uploader with a single

downloader, BitTorrent allows the creation of ad hoc distributed networks (called

“trackers”) devoted to specific files or sets of files. The target file is logically divided into

numerous pieces which are separately downloaded by users and then reassembled on the

users' computer. As users connect to and disconnect from the tracker, the protocol

evaluates the distribution of the pieces throughout the network and attempts to equalize

the ratio by more rigorously propagating those pieces which are less evenly distributed

across the network. In most trackers, there is at least one user (called a “seeder”) who

already has the complete file and who is present merely to “seed” the file to the other

users.

One of the technical advantages of this system over the centralized, one-to-one

“Napster” model of yesterday is that it is possible for a complete version of a file to be

assembled by multiple users even if no single user with the complete file is present on the

network for an extended time. As long as all the users have the entire file distributed

between them, each user will eventually have the entire file.

The upshot of all this is that the structure of the BitTorrent protocol virtually

ensures that Professor Lunney is correct when he says that “popularity itself, because of

its associated network effects, leads individuals looking to engage in private copying both

to seek and to find popular works far more often than less popular works. Thus private

copying will affect popular works disproportionately.”169 Because the “health” of

BitTorrent networks is a function of the number of seeders, the more popular trackers will

always be the healthiest. By extension, the healthiest networks tend to attract more users,

a small percentage of whom in turn become seeders, and in this way the cycle continues;
169 Lunney, supra note 55, at 886.

33
popular works grow in popularity and marginal works, if they ever appear on the

network in the first place, typically languish and die. By this mechanism, the most

prominent method of private copying of copyrighted works virtually ensures that excess

incentives will be its only casualties.170

B. Public Buyout

The second suggestion is mine, and it is that we turn ad fontes to consider James

Madison's proposal that we reserve “a right to the public to abolish the privilege at a

price to be specified at the grant of it.”171 Writing approximately thirty years later, after

the conclusion of his presidency, Madison again discussed this proposal:

In all cases of monopoly, not excepting those specified in


favor of authors & inventors, it would be well to reserve to
the State, a right to terminate the monopoly by paying a
specified and reasonable sum [to the holder.] This would
guard against the public discontents resulting from the
exorbitant gains of individuals, and from the inconvenient
restrictions combined with them.172

In general, the idea is that the public can “fast-track” a work's journey to the

public domain by paying the author a “buyout” price. But how should this price be set?

Who should pay it? When should this be an option?

1. Michael Kremer and the Patent Buyout Proposal

In a 1998 article, Michael Kremer outlined a proposal for a buyout system for

patents.173 While patent law is readily distinguishable from copyright law in many key

170 Id.
171 Letter from James Madison to Thomas Jefferson, supra note 84.
172 Elizabeth Fleet, Madison's “Detached Memoranda,” 3 WM. & MARY Q. 534, 551-52 (1946).

The Detached Memoranda is a collection of Madison's miscellaneous writings produced between 1817 and
1832. Id. at 534. The manuscripts were mislaid and rediscovered in 1946. Id. at 536. Although portions
of the Detached Memoranda had been published in prior collections, the parts excerpted here were not
published until Fleet printed the Detached Memoranda it its entirety in 1946.
173 Michael Kremer, Patent Buyouts: A Mechanism for Encouraging Innovation, 113 Q. J. ECON.

1137 (1998).

34
respects, they both inhabit the sphere of “intellectual property” and therefore share many

important points of similarity.174

Under Kremer's mechanism for patent buyouts, the government identifies a patent

to be “liberated” and determines its value by means of a sealed-bid auction. 175 The

market price thus determined is then multiplied by a fixed markup value (probably “2”)

which is intended to correct for “the typical ratio of social to private value.” 176 Upon

paying this price to the patent holder, most patents would then be placed in the public

domain.177 But because the process relies upon the honest valuation of the auction

bidders, this honesty is induced by allowing a small and random number of patents to be

sold to the highest private bidder.178 In either case, the patent holder has the right to

refuse the buyout and retain the patent.179

Several considerations make it difficult to apply this system “as-is” to copyright

law. Perhaps the biggest problem is that it is much more difficult to determine the

boundaries of a copyright than it is of a patent. It is easy to identify what is covered by a

patent; it is whatever is contained in the grant from the patent office. But since copyright

no longer requires registration (let alone an application), it is more difficult to identify

which works might be subjected to this process and where the line might be drawn.

Another difficulty is created if the system depends on the government to determine

174 For example, the discussion of the “anticommons” problem in subpart I-C-2 supra relies on an

article that was originally written in the context of biomedical research patents. See Heller, supra note 134.
Kremer himself observed that the problems with patent law giving rise to his article also affect copyright
law: “Patents and copyrights create insufficient incentives for original research, since inventors cannot fully
capture consumer surplus or spillovers of their ideas to other research. Patents and copyrights also create
static distortions from monopoly pricing and encourage socially wasteful expenditures on reverse
engineering to invent around patents.” Kremer, supra note 173, at 1137.
175 Kremer, supra note 173, at 1146.
176 Id.
177 Id.
178 Id. at 1147.
179 Id.

35
which works should be bought out. In the case of pharmaceutical patents, it might be

relatively easy to identify promising patents for important and socially beneficial

medicines. But do we want the government determining what music, movies, books, and

artwork are most desirable and socially enriching? Surely this sort of “inverse

censorship” would merely replace one form of government overreaching with another.

Third, the ability of the copyright holder to reject the buyout and retain the

copyright is problematic because it could amount to the exception that swallows the rule.

As it is, the suggestion is being raised as a means of counterbalancing a powerful and

influential industry. It is unlikely to have the intended effect if the industry could opt out

of it altogether. The veto feature is more appropriate to a system intended to correct

market failures resulting from prohibitively high transaction costs. The situation here is

different. A copyright buyout would be a mechanism for protecting a positive right

reserved by society.180 It would therefore not do to allow the powerful few to “opt out”

of the exercise of that right.

Finally, the notion of a governmentally mandated transfer of a copyright from one

private entity to another carries with it an air of injustice that does not appear in the

patent context, at least not in the same way. While inventors undoubtedly have a

connection with their inventions, the subject matter of copyright law is of a kind far more

personal and intimate.181 While some might quail at the thought of their art being placed

in the public domain, the average author would doubtlessly react in horror at the prospect

of another disinterested individual obtaining the rights to her creation to commercially

180 Indeed, Madison considered copyright a socially useful privilege that nonetheless infringes upon
man's natural right to chose the object of his expression. See supra note 87 and accompanying text.
181 See, e.g., Rosemary Coombe, Challenging Paternity: Histories of Copyright, 6 YALE. J.L. &

HUMAN. 397, 404 (citing MARK ROSE, AUTHORS AND OWNERS: THE INVENTION OF COPYRIGHT (1994)) (observing
that some envision a paternal relationship between the author and his work).

36
exploit in any way imaginable, no matter what the buyout price might be.

A copyright buyout system that addresses these considerations will likely not

resemble Kremer's government auction paradigm. Instead, a successful system would

need to establish reasonable and fair buyout prices without putting the government in the

role of “art critic” and without allowing buyouts to favor private individuals or entities.

2. Open Source Software Bounties

A more appropriate model might be found in the realm of “open source” software

development. “Open source” software describes a model of community-centric software

production and development. Under a traditional commercial or proprietary model,

programmers and developers guard the software's source code and license the resulting

software under restrictive terms that forbid copying, modification, redistribution, and

other such activities. Under this model, the number of individual programmers that work

on a given project is usually small, with larger development teams usually existing in large

companies such as Microsoft or Apple. By contrast, those following the “open source”

model make the underlying source code publicly available. One of the primary purposes

of utilizing such a system is to enable wide-ranging collaboration on projects that is

generally not possible under a proprietary model. In effect, every user of open source

software can also be a contributing developer since he may view and modify the source

code, sharing his improvements and enhancements with everyone else in like manner.

One of the key features of open source software development can also be a

hindrance. Because open source software is freely available, it is not susceptible to

traditional market forces, at least not in many key respects. In the case of commercial,

proprietary software, users can express their preferences through the market, and

37
products develop according to familiar economic and market principles. The same is not

true in the realm of open source software.

If a company like Microsoft sets out to create a software product, it needs to take

into account factors such as the potential market for the product, its target audience, the

needs and desires of the target audience, similar competing products, etc. The impetus to

create such a product is usually the prospect of financial gain or increase in market share.

On the other hand, the open source developer rarely needs consider anything beyond his

own personal requirements.182 If other people have additional desires or needs, they are

free to implement them themselves, if they are able.

Because the number of people who use open source software is significantly greater

than the number of people who have the requisite knowledge and skill to modify it,

attempts have been made to incentivise the implementation of other features and

requirements. One such attempt is the “bounty” method.

While different organizations have set up bounty systems of various kinds, the

basic concept is common to all of them. Under a software bounty system, a user submits

a feature or requirement that he would like to see added to an existing program. He also

pledges a sum of money to be paid to the person who successfully implements the feature

or requirement. Other users who have the same needs or desires may also make pledges

to increase to bounty. A programmer who has the necessary skill and knowledge may

then implement the request and collect the bounty.

182 A prime example is one of the most popular open source projects, MythTV. A combination
digital media library and digital video recorder (DVR), MythTV was originally created by Isaac Richards in
2002 because Richards wanted to build his own DVR rather than paying monthly service and rental fees to
his cable company or TiVo. See Chris Barylick, MythTV Invades Realm of Cable and TiVo, WASH. POST,
March 26, 2006, available at http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/content/article/2006/03/25/
AR2006032500115.html.

38
3. Copyright Buyout – A Modified Bounty System

The goals of copyright and of a software bounty system are similar despite the fact

that these systems work at that goal from opposite ends. Both systems attempt to induce

creative production through the offer of a financial reward. The bounty system collects

the reward first, then promises it to the first successful author. Copyright provides the

author nothing up front, but grants him property rights which he may commercially

exploit as he chooses. In the case of the bounty, the would-be author knows what the

reward is and, if successful, collects it all immediately. A copyright holder is not certain

to receive a reward at all and even if he does, it is of an uncertain amount and is often

received over a long period of time. My proposed copyright buyout system would

supplement (not replace) the existing copyright system by implementing Madison's

suggestion. Allowing the public to raise funds and “claim” a work for the public domain

would ensure that authors receive just compensation while simultaneously protecting the

public's right of expression free from unreasonable restrictions regardless of how

expansive copyright protection becomes. The rest of this Paper will lay out the practical

elements of this system.

The first consideration concerns when and how works should be valued. Because

the United States no longer has a registration requirement, it is impossible to implement

Madison's suggestion literally, by determining the buyout price when the copyright is

“granted.” Also complicating matters is the fact that we cannot determine a fair price

through the use of an auction for the reasons discussed in Part III-4-A, supra.

My suggestion is that the Copyright Office be expanded and the compulsory

licensing model be adapted to determine buyout prices on a per-application basis. An

39
individual or entity wishing to initiate the buyout process with respect to a specific work

would file and submit an application to the Copyright Office. The application would

include a copy or reasonable description of the work at issue. The copyright owner

would be given reasonable notice of the proceedings. A panel of Copyright judges would

then determine the buyout price from within a statutory range by evaluating factors such

as:

• The type and nature of the work;


• The length, size, or duration of the work;
• The commercial success already enjoyed by the work; and
• The costs incurred in producing the work.

A hearing would be held in which representatives for the public and for the

copyright holder would offer arguments and evidence to help the Copyright judges make

a fair and reasonable determination. For example, if the subject of the hearing were a

very recent motion picture, the studio might present evidence of the costs it incurred in

producing the film to support a higher buyout price from within the statutory range. The

applicant might produce evidence of box office receipts to date to show how much the

copyright owner has already earned, a figure which would lower the buyout price.

In order to limit the use of the valuation process to those actually intending to

complete the buyout process, the application should be accompanied by a fee in the

amount of 50% of the statutory minimum buyout price. So if the lowest end of the price

range were $250,000, the application fee would be $125,000. 183

The next consideration is the mechanism by which the buyout is actually achieved.

Once the price is set, it is necessary to raise and distribute the funds in a fair manner. I

suggest that once the buyout price is determined, the application fee should be placed in
183
This fee would not be absorbed by the agency; rather it would be applied to the total buyout
price once it is determined.

40
an interest-bearing trust account. The buyout price must be met within two years of that

date. The application will be deemed withdrawn if, one year from date of initial

investment (i.e. the half-way point), the trust account contains less than 60% of the

buyout price, exclusive of interest.

In the event either that the buyout price is not met within two years or that the

application is abandoned, the principal investments held in trust will be returned to their

contributors. The interest will be used to pay any administrative expenses associated with

the trust and the remainder will be paid pro rata to the contributors.

In the event that the buyout price is reached in principal investments (exclusive of

interest), the balance of the account (less administrative expenses) will immediately be

paid to the copyright holder and the work specified in the application will pass into the

public domain.

This system is intended to address several issues. First, the process must be stable

if it is to induce contributors to participate. Most open source bounty systems allow

contributors to change, withdraw, or redistribute their pledges after they have been made.

This results in uncertainty and instability. Suppose person A makes a significant

contribution (50% of the total price). Person B, encouraged by the progress and wanting

to assist, makes a nominal contribution (5% of the total price). If person A then retracts

his contribution, person B may become less optimistic about achieving the goal and decide

to retract his contribution. Spread throughout a large contribution pool, it is easy to see

how the withdrawal of a “big player” can cause instability and uncertainty, perhaps

resulting in the collapse of the system. To address that, contributions may not be

retracted, but contributors are assured that they will either achieve the ultimate goal or

41
receive their money back (with interest) within a maximum of two years.

Providing that the public must raise at least 60% of the price within one year is

intended to ensure that contributor funds are not unnecessarily tied up by hopeless

applications.

The final consideration concerns how the funds are to be raised. This is perhaps

the easiest of the three phases to describe because no description is really necessary. An

application fee may be raised however the applicant likes. Once the fee is paid and the

buyout price set, contributions may be paid into the trust fund by any traditional method.

Whatever reasons people have for paying into the fund are their own. In some instances,

the entire buyout price might be funded by consumer advocacy organizations or even

industry players. In other cases, individuals might mount a yearlong grassroots internet

campaign. Perhaps some particularly anxious individuals might even stage a

“moneybomb.”184 In the end, it matters not how the money is raised, so long as it is.

One other important qualification must be made. In order to be subject to buyout,

a work must be published. While publication is no longer a requirement for copyright

protection, it must be for the buyout system. A man must be secure in his right to keep

his expressions to himself. The right of the public to employ its faculties on the object of

its choosing should be extended only as far at those objects which have been offered for

public consumption. It must not be forgotten that this proposal is being suggested as a

means of compensating for a copyright system that disproportionately favors copyright

holders and the entertainment industry. This purpose is not served by forcing the contents

of one's neighbor's desk drawer into the public domain.

184 See Wikipedia, Moneybomb, http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Moneybomb (last visited Apr. 13,


2010).

42
One final consideration bears mentioning. Adoption of a copyright buyout system

like the one outlined above would have secondary benefits that might even overshadow

the primary function of the system. That is, it would give copyright owners an incentive

to support and advocate the public interest. I envision this effect taking two forms: lower

prices and more robust fair use rights.

Suppose Universal Studios decides to produce a motion picture adaptation of

Blacksone's Commentaries. They do so with a budget of $30 million. On opening

weekend, Blackstone: The Movie exceeds studio expectations and takes in $20 million.

Believing the movie has tremendous potential as a training tool, an attorney files a buyout

application that Monday morning. At the resulting hearing, the copyright judges see

evidence that Universal spent $30 million making the movie. Judging a 40% return on

their investment to be an appropriate award, the panel would set the buyout price at $42

million. But the professor presents evidence that the work had already earned $20 million

by the date the application was filed, and this is treated as an offset, making the buyout

price $22 million. The professor then has two years to raise $22 million.

In this scenario, a high-grossing opening weekend has put the studio in a less

favorable position in the buyout process than it would otherwise have been in. Because of

this, if such a buyout system were in place, studios would need to take this added effect

into consideration when determining box office prices. If copyright owners elect to

protect themselves from a buyout by keeping consumer prices low, it makes the buyout

more difficult to achieve but the public still benefits from the lower prices. In this respect,

the copyright owner still benefits from the copyright monopoly which restricts market

competition. But the presence of a buyout system such as this would have the effect of

43
putting the public at large in the position of a competitor, thereby preventing monopoly

pricing and restoring some of the free market features.

The other secondary effect of a buyout system would be to give copyright owners

an incentive to support, rather than erode, fair use rights. Copyright owners would be

more likely to support certain “unauthorized” uses of their works if it meant fewer

participants in the buyout system. Return to the example above of Blackstone: The

Movie. The aforementioned attorney would like to show the film to his law firm and has

even considered the possibility of editing it into shorter, topical segments to be used

during CLE presentations. The first use implicates the public display right 185 while the

second use likely implicates the derivative works right.186 Knowing that these are non-

competitive uses unlikely to significantly affect its primary market, the movie studio has

an incentive to allow such uses or contend that they constitute fair use, thus eliminating

the reason for applying for a buyout in the first place. The spectre of losing the work to

the public domain could be enough to encourage the powerful industry players to self-

regulate, mitigating the public choice problems that have thus far gone largely unchecked.

IV. CONCLUSION

Intellectual property protection is a good thing, but more is not always better.

James Madison, the father of the Constitution, warned that anything more than a

conservative, utilitarian copyright scheme posed a serious risk of abuse. Copyright was

intended as a means of furthering the public good. Instead, it has become a means of

securing power and wealth for the fortunate few. Modern copyright has created what has

been aptly described as an “empire,” 187 a sobering observation given the fact that the
185 17 U.S.C. § 106(5).
186 17 U.S.C. § 106(2).
187 See Ng, Copyright's Empire, supra note 143, at 377.

44
primary purpose of the Constitution is the prevention of imperial power.

The current scope of copyright protection is not justified by the constitutional

purpose of promotion of progress. The current scheme is not mandated by economic,

legal, or philosophical principles. The evolution of U.S. Copyright law, particularly the

changes wrought in the past half-century, has been driven by an unchecked industry.

Congress has created a tyranny of the few.

Not only does the public pay the price in terms of restricted liberties, it also suffers

the inevitable decay of artistic integrity that accompanies a bottom-line mindset. By

holding out the prospect of fabulous wealth in exchange for fleeting popularity, our

current copyright paradigm may be incentivising the wrong kind of creativity. “Popular

works offer currency; great works endure. Popular works offer superficial enjoyment;

great works offer meaning. Most importantly for copyright law, popular works have

large sales great works may not.”188 Thus a would-be Shakespeare today is faced with a

choice: Should I “strive for a great work or a popular one?” 189

Public choice theory suggests that the situation will not improve unless the public

recognizes its interest, bands together, and asserts its rights. A copyright buyout scheme

serves this purpose not only by giving the public a means and a mechanism for asserting

its rights, but it provides much-needed checks on the industry itself. Perhaps like the

nation's nuclear arsenal, the deterrent effect of the possibility of buyout might even suffice

to address many of the existing problems without ever being used.

Madison proved to be right about the dangers of excessive copyright protection.

Perhaps he was also right about the solution.

188 Lunney, supra note 55, at 888.


189 Id.

45

You might also like