You are on page 1of 14

ABOUT THOMAS KUHN

Thomas Samuel Kuhn was an American physicist and philosopher who wrote extensively on


the history of science and developed several important notions in the sociology and philosophy
of science.

Kuhn was born in Cincinnati, Ohio to Samuel L. Kuhn, an industrial engineer, and Minette
Stroock Kuhn. He obtained his B.Sc. degree in physics from Harvard University in 1943,
and M.S. and Ph.D. degrees in physics in 1946 and 1949, respectively. He later taught a course
in the history of science at Harvard from 1948 until 1956 at the suggestion of the University
president James Conant. After leaving Harvard, Kuhn taught at the University of California,
Berkeley, in both the philosophy department and the history department, being named ‘Professor
of the History of Science’ in 1961. At Berkeley, he wrote and published (in 1962) his best known
and most influential work: The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.

Thomas Samuel Kuhn (1922-1996) became one of the most influential philosophers of science
of the twentieth century, perhaps the most influential—his The Structure of Scientific
Revolutions is one of the most cited academic books of all time. His contribution to the
philosophy of science marked not only a break with several key positivist doctrines but also
inaugurated a new style of philosophy of science that brought it much closer to the history of
science. His account of the development of science held that science enjoys periods of stable
growth punctuated by revisionary revolutions, to which he added the controversial
‘incommensurability thesis’, that theories from differing periods suffer from certain deep kinds
of failure of comparability.

THE DEVELOPMENT OF SCIENCE

In The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Kuhn painted a picture of the development of science


quite unlike any that had been done before. Indeed, before Kuhn, there was little by way of a
carefully considered, theoretically explained account of scientific change. Instead, there was a
conception of how science ought to develop that was a by-product of the prevailing philosophy
of science, as well as a popular, heroic view of scientific progress. According to such opinions,
science develops by the addition of new truths to the stock of old truths, or the increasing
approximation of theories to the truth, and in the odd case, the correction of past errors. Such
progress might accelerate in the hands of a particularly great scientist, but progress itself is
guaranteed by the scientific method.

According to Kuhn the development of a science is not uniform but has alternating ‘normal’ and
‘revolutionary’ (or ‘extraordinary’) phases. The revolutionary phases are not merely periods of
accelerated progress, but differ qualitatively from normal science. Normal science does resemble
the standard cumulative picture of scientific progress, on the surface at least. Kuhn describes
normal science as puzzle-solving. While this term suggests that normal science is not dramatic,
its main purpose is to convey the idea that like someone doing crossword puzzles or chess
puzzles or jigsaws, the puzzle-solver expects to have a reasonable chance of solving the puzzle,
that his doing so will depends mainly on his own ability, and that the puzzle itself and its
methods of solution will have a high degree of familiarity.

Paradigm shift (or revolutionary science) is the term used by Thomas Kuhn in his influential
book ‘The Structure of Scientific Revolutions’ to describe a change in the basic assumptions,
or paradigms, within the ruling theory of science. It is in contrast to his idea of normal science.
The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (SSR) was originally printed as an article in
The International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, published by the logical positivists of
the Vienna Circle. In this book, Kuhn argued that science does not progress via a linear
accumulation of new knowledge, but undergoes periodic revolutions, also called "paradigm
shifts" (although he did not coin the phrase), in which the nature of scientific inquiry within a
particular field is abruptly transformed.

In general, science is broken up into three distinct stages. ‘Prescience’, which lacks a central
paradigm, comes first. This is followed by ‘normal science’, when scientists attempt to enlarge
the central paradigm by ‘puzzle-solving’. Guided by the paradigm, normal science is extremely
productive: "when the paradigm is successful, the profession will have solved problems that its
members could scarcely have imagined and would never have undertaken without commitment
to the paradigm." If much of normal science relies upon a piece of equipment, normal science
will find it difficult to continue with confidence until an anomaly is addressed. A widespread
failure in such confidence Kuhn calls a ‘crisis’. The most interesting response to crisis will be
the search for a revised disciplinary matrix, a revision that will allow for the elimination of at
least the most pressing anomalies and optimally the solution of many outstanding and unsolved
puzzles. Such a revision will be a scientific revolution. 

According to Kuhn, "A paradigm is what members of a scientific community, and they alone,
share." Unlike a normal scientist, Kuhn held, "a student in the humanities has constantly before
him a number of competing and incommensurable solutions to these problems, solutions that he
must ultimately examine for himself" (The Structure of Scientific Revolutions). Once a paradigm
shift is complete, a scientist cannot, for example, reject the germ theory of disease to posit the
possibility that miasma causes disease or reject modern physics and optics to posit
that ether carries light. In contrast, a critic in the Humanities can choose to adopt an array of
stances, which may be more or less fashionable during any given period but which are all
regarded as legitimate.
THE PARADIGM CONCEPT

In 1962, Thomas Kuhn wrote ‘The Structure of Scientific Revolution’, and fathered,


defined and popularized the concept of "paradigm shift".  Kuhn argued that scientific
advancement is not evolutionary, but rather is a "series of peaceful interludes punctuated by
intellectually violent revolutions", and in those revolutions "one conceptual world view is
replaced by another".

Think of a Paradigm Shift as a change from one way of thinking to another. It's a revolution, a
transformation, a sort of metamorphosis. It just does not happen, but rather it is driven by agents
of change. For example, agriculture changed early primitive society. The primitive Indians
existed for centuries roaming the earth constantly hunting and gathering for seasonal foods and
water. However, by 2000 B.C., Middle America was a landscape of very small villages, each
surrounded by patchy fields of corn and other vegetables.

Agents of change helped create a paradigm-shift moving scientific theory from the Plolemaic
system (the earth at the center of the universe) to the Copernican system (the sun at the center of
the universe), and moving from Newtonian physics to Relativity and Quantum Physics. Both
movements eventually changed the world view. These transformations were gradual as old
beliefs were replaced by the new paradigms creating "a new gestalt".

Likewise, the printing press, the making of books and the use of vernacular language inevitably
changed the culture of people and had a direct affect on the scientific revolution. Johann
Gutenberg's invention in the 1440's of movable type was an agent of change. Books became
readily available, smaller and easier to handle and cheap to purchase. Masses of people acquired
direct access to the scriptures. Attitudes began to change as people were relieved from church
domination.

Similarly, agents of change are driving a new paradigm shift today. The signs are all around us.
For example, the introduction of the personal computer and the internet have impacted both
personal and business environments, and is a catalyst for a Paradigm Shift. Newspaper
publishing has been reshaped into Web sites, blogging, and web feeds. The Internet has enabled
or accelerated the creation of new forms of human interactions through instant messaging,
Internet forums, and social networking sites. We are shifting from a mechanistic, manufacturing,
industrial society to an organic, service based, information centered society, and increases in
technology will continue to impact globally. Change is inevitable.

A mature science, according to Kuhn, experiences alternating phases of normal science and
revolutions. In normal science, the key theories, instruments, values and metaphysical
assumptions that comprise the disciplinary matrix are kept fixed, permitting the cumulative
generation of puzzle-solutions, whereas in a scientific revolution the disciplinary matrix
undergoes revision, in order to permit the solution of the more serious anomalous puzzles that
disturbed the preceding period of normal science.

A particularly important part of Kuhn's thesis in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions focuses


upon one specific component of the disciplinary matrix. This is the consensus on exemplary
instances of scientific research. These exemplars of good science are what Kuhn refers to when
he uses the term ‘paradigm’ in a narrower sense. He cites Aristotle's analysis of motion,
Ptolemy's computations of plantery positions, Lavoisier's application of the balance, and
Maxwell's mathematization of the electromagnetic field as paradigms. Exemplary instances of
science are typically to be found in books and papers, and so Kuhn often also describes great
texts as paradigms—Ptolemy's Almagest, Lavoisier's Traité élémentaire de chimie, and
Newton's Principia Mathematica and Opticks . Such texts contain not only the key theories and
laws, but—and this is what makes them paradigms—the applications of those theories in the
solution of important problems, along with the new experimental or mathematical techniques
employed in those applications.
In the postscript to the second edition of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Kuhn says of
paradigms in this sense that they are “the most novel and least understood aspect of this book”.
Kuhn describes an immature science, in what he sometimes calls its ‘pre-paradigm’ period, as
lacking consensus. Competing schools of thought possess differing procedures, theories, even
metaphysical presuppositions. Consequently there is little opportunity for collective progress.
Even localized progress by a particular school is made difficult, since much intellectual energy is
put into arguing over the fundamentals with other schools instead of developing a research
tradition. However, progress is not impossible, and one school may make a breakthrough
whereby the shared problems of the competing schools are solved in a particularly impressive
fashion. This success draws away adherents from the other schools, and a widespread consensus
is formed around the new puzzle-solutions.

This widespread consensus now permits agreement on fundamentals. For a problem-solution will
embody particular theories, procedures and instrumentation, scientific language, metaphysics,
and so forth. Consensus on the puzzle-solution will thus bring consensus on these other aspects
of a disciplinary matrix also. The successful puzzle-solution, now a paradigm puzzle-solution,
will not solve all problems. Indeed, it will probably raise new puzzles. For example, the theories
it employs may involve a constant whose value is not known with precision; the paradigm
puzzle-solution may employ approximations that could be improved; it may suggest other
puzzles of the same kind; it may suggest new areas for investigation. Generating new puzzles is
one thing that the paradigm puzzle-solution does; helping solve them is another. In the best case,
the new puzzles raised by the paradigm puzzle-solution can be addressed and answered using
precisely the techniques that the paradigm puzzle-solution employs.

Kuhn rejected the distinction between the context of discovery and the context of justification,
and correspondingly rejected the standard account of each. As regards the context of discovery,
the standard view held that the philosophy of science had nothing to say on the issue of the
functioning of the creative imagination. But Kuhn's paradigms do provide a partial explanation,
since training with exemplars enables scientists to see new puzzle-situations in terms of familiar
puzzles and hence enables them to see potential solutions to their new puzzles.
USE OF THE TERM IN NON-SCIENTIFIC CONTEXT

Since the 1960s, the term ‘paradigm shift’ has also been used in numerous non-scientific
contexts to describe a profound change in a fundamental model or perception of events, even
though Kuhn himself restricted the use of the term to the hard sciences.

A scientific revolution occurs, according to Kuhn, when scientists encounter anomalies which
cannot be explained by the universally accepted paradigm within which scientific progress has
thereto been made. The paradigm, in Kuhn's view, is not simply the current theory, but the entire
world view in which it exists, and all of the implications which come with it. It is based on
features of landscape of knowledge that scientists can identify around them. There are anomalies
for all paradigms, Kuhn maintained, that are brushed away as acceptable levels of error, or
simply ignored and not dealt with. Rather, according to Kuhn, anomalies have various levels of
significance to the practitioners of science at the time. To put it in the context of early 20th
century physics, some scientists found the problems with calculating Mercury's perihelion more
troubling than the Michelson-Morley experiment results, and some the other way around. Kuhn's
model of scientific change differs here, and in many places, from that of the logical positivists in
that it puts an enhanced emphasis on the individual humans involved as scientists, rather than
abstracting science into a purely logical or philosophical venture.

When enough significant anomalies have accrued against a current paradigm, the scientific
discipline is thrown into a state of crisis, according to Kuhn. During this crisis, new ideas,
perhaps ones previously discarded, are tried. Eventually a new paradigm is formed, which gains
its own new followers, and an intellectual "battle" takes place between the followers of the new
paradigm and the hold-outs of the old paradigm. Again, for early 20th century physics, the
transition between the Maxwellian electromagnetic worldview and the  Einsteinian  Relativistic 
worldview was neither instantaneous nor calm, and instead involved a protracted set of "attacks,"
both with empirical data as well as rhetorical or philosophical arguments, by both sides, with the
Einsteinian theory winning out in the long-run. Again, the weighing of evidence and importance
of new data was fit through the human sieve: some scientists found the simplicity of Einstein's
equations to be most compelling, while some found them more complicated than the notion of
Maxwell's other idea which they banished. Some found Eddington's photographs of light bending
around the sun to be compelling, some questioned their accuracy and meaning.
Sometimes the convincing force is just time itself and the human toll it takes, Kuhn said, using a
quote from Max Planck: "a new scientific truth does not triumph by convincing its
opponents and making them see the light, but rather because its opponents eventually die,
and a new generation grows up that is familiar with it."

After a given discipline has changed from one paradigm to another, this is called, in Kuhn's
terminology, a scientific revolution or a paradigm shift. It is often this final conclusion, the result
of the long process that is meant when the term paradigm shift is used colloquially: simply the
(often radical) change of worldview, without reference to the specificities of Kuhn's historical
argument.

MISINTERPRETATIONS OF PARADIGM SHIFT

A common misinterpretation of paradigms is the belief that the discovery of paradigm shifts and
the dynamic nature of science (with its many opportunities for subjective judgments by
scientists) is a case for relativism: the view that all kinds of belief systems are equal, such
that magic, religious concepts or pseudoscience would be of equal working value to
truescience. Kuhn vehemently denied this interpretation and states that when a scientific
paradigm is replaced by a new one, albeit through a complex social process, the new one
is always better, not just different.

These claims of relativism are, however, tied to another claim that Kuhn did at least somewhat
endorse: that the language and theories of different paradigms cannot be translated into one
another or rationally evaluated against one another — that they are incommensurable. This gave
rise to much talk of different peoples and cultures having radically different worldviews or
conceptual schemes — so different that whether or not one was better, they could not be
understood by one another. However, the philosopher Donald Davidson published a highly
regarded essay in 1974, "On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme," arguing that the notion
that any languages or theories could be incommensurable with one another was itself incoherent.
If this is correct, Kuhn's claims must be taken in a weaker sense than they often are. Furthermore,
the hold of the Kuhnian analysis on social science has long been tenuous with the wide
application of multi-paradigmatic approaches in order to understand complex human behavior.
Paradigm shifts tend to be most dramatic in sciences that appear to be stable and mature, as in
physics at the end of the 19th century. At that time, physics seemed to be a discipline filling in
the last few details of a largely worked-out system. In 1900, Lord Kelvin famously stated, "There
is nothing new to be discovered in physics now. All that remains is more and more precise
measurement." Five years later, Albert Einstein published his paper on special relativity, which
challenged the very simple set of rules laid down by Newtonian mechanics, which had been used
to describe force and motion for over two hundred years.

In ‘The Structure of Scientific Revolutions’, Kuhn wrote, "Successive transition from one
paradigm to another via revolution is the usual developmental pattern of mature science."
Kuhn's idea was itself revolutionary in its time, as it caused a major change in the way that
academics talk about science. Thus, it could be argued that it caused or was itself part of a
"paradigm shift" in the history and sociology of science. However, Kuhn did not recognize such
a paradigm shift. Being in the social sciences, people can still use earlier ideas to discuss the
history of science.

Philosophers and historians of science, including Kuhn himself, ultimately accepted a modified
version of Kuhn's model, which synthesizes his original view with the gradualist model that
preceded it. Kuhn's original model is now generally seen as too limited.

EXAMPLES OF PARADIGM SHIFT IN NATURAL SCIENCES

Some of the "classical cases" of Kuhnian paradigm shifts in science are:

 The transition in cosmology from a Ptolemaic cosmology to a Copernican one.


 The transition in optics from geometrical optics to physical optics.
 The transition in mechanics from Aristotelian mechanics to classical mechanics.
 The acceptance of the theory of biogenesis, that all life comes from life, as opposed to the
theory of spontaneous generation which began in the 17th century and was not complete until
the 19th century with Pasteur.
 The transition between the Maxwellian Electromagnetic worldview and the  Einsteinian 
Relativistic worldview.
 The transition between the worldview of Newtonian physics and
the Einsteinian Relativistic worldview.
 The acceptance of Charles Darwin's theory of natural selection replaced Lamarckism as
the mechanism for evolution.

EXAMPLES OF PARADIGM SHIFT IN SOCIAL SCIENCES

In Kuhn's view, the existence of a single reigning paradigm is characteristic of the sciences,
while philosophy and much of social science were characterized by a "tradition of claims,
counterclaims, and debates over fundamentals." Others have applied Kuhn's concept of paradigm
shift to the social sciences.

 The movement, known as the Cognitive revolution, away from Behaviourist approaches


to psychological study and the acceptance of cognition as central to studying human
behaviour.
 The Keynesian Revolution is typically viewed as a major shift in 
macroeconomics. According to John Kenneth Galbraith, Say's Law dominated economic
thought prior to Keynes for over a century, and the shift to Keynesianism was difficult.
Economists who contradicted the law, which inferred that underemployment and
underinvestment (coupled with oversaving) were virtually impossible, risked losing their
careers. In his magnum opus, Keynes cited one of his predecessors, J. A. Hobson, who was
repeatedly denied positions at universities for his heretical theory.
 Later, the movement for Monetarism over Keynesianism marked a second divisive shift.
Monetarists held that fiscal policy was not effective for stabilizing inflation, that it was solely
a monetary phenomenon, in contrast to the Keynesian view of the time was that both fiscal
and monetary policies were important. Keynesians later adopted much of the Monetarists
view of the quantity theory of money and shifting Philips curve, theories they initially
rejected.

OTHER USES
The term "paradigm shift" has found uses in other contexts, representing the notion of a major
change in a certain thought-pattern — a radical change in personal beliefs, complex systems or
organizations, replacing the former way of thinking or organizing with a radically different way
of thinking or organizing.

IMPACT OF KUHN’S WORK

The enormous impact of Kuhn's work can be measured in the changes it brought about in the
vocabulary of the philosophy of science: besides "paradigm shift", Kuhn raised the word
"paradigm" itself from a term used in certain forms of linguistics to its current broader meaning,
coined the term "normal science" to refer to the relatively routine, day-to-day work of scientists
working within a paradigm, and was largely responsible for the use of the term "scientific
revolutions" in the plural, taking place at widely different periods of time and in different
disciplines, as opposed to a single "Scientific Revolution" in the late Renaissance. The frequent
use of the phrase "paradigm shift" has made scientists more aware of and in many cases more
receptive to paradigm changes, so that Kuhn’s analysis of the evolution of scientific views has by
itself influenced that evolution.

Kuhn's work has been extensively used in social science; for instance, in the post-
positivist/positivist debate within International Relations. Kuhn was credited as a foundational
force behind the post-Mertonian Sociology of Scientific Knowledge.

A defense Kuhn gives against the objection that his account of science from The Structure of
Scientific Revolutions results in relativism can be found in an essay by Kuhn called "Objectivity,
Value Judgment, and Theory Choice." In this essay, he reiterates five criteria from the
penultimate chapter of SSR that determine (or help determine, more properly) theory choice:

1. - Accurate - empirically adequate with experimentation and observation


2. - Consistent - internally consistent, but also externally consistent with other theories
3. - Broad Scope - a theory's consequences should extend beyond that which it was initially
designed to explain
4. - Simple - the simplest explanation, principally similar to Occam's razor
5. - Fruitful - a theory should disclose new phenomena or new relationships among
phenomena

He then went on to show how, although these criteria admittedly determine theory choice, they
are imprecise in practice and relative to individual scientists. According to Kuhn, "When
scientists must choose between competing theories, two men fully committed to the same
list of criteria for choice may nevertheless reach different conclusions." For this reason,
basically, the criteria still are not "objective" in the usual sense of the word because individual
scientists reach different conclusions with the same criteria due to valuing one criterion over
another or even adding additional criteria for selfish or other subjective reasons. Kuhn then goes
on to say, "I am suggesting, of course, that the criteria of choice with which I began function
not as rules, which determine choice, but as values, which influence it." Because Kuhn
utilizes the history of science in his account of science, his criteria or values for theory choice are
often understood as descriptive normative rules (or more properly, values) of theory choice for
the scientific community rather than prescriptive normative rules in the usual sense of the word
"criteria," although there are many varied interpretations of Kuhn's account of science.

THE POLANYI-KUHN DEBATE

Although they used different terminologies, both Kuhn and Michael Polanyi believed that
scientists' subjective experiences made science a relativistic discipline. Polanyi lectured on this
topic for decades before Kuhn published "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions."

Supporters of Polanyi charged Kuhn with plagiarism, as it was known that Kuhn attended several
of Polanyi's lectures, and that the two men had debated endlessly over the epistemology of
science before either had achieved fame. In response to these critics, Kuhn cited Polanyi in the
second edition of "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions," and the two scientists agreed to set
aside their differences in the hopes of enlightening the world to the dynamic nature of science.
Despite this intellectual alliance, Polanyi's work was constantly interpreted by others within the
framework of Kuhn's paradigm shifts, much to Polanyi's (and Kuhn's) dismay.

HONOURS
Kuhn was named a Guggenheim Fellow in 1954, and in 1982 was awarded the George Sarton
Medal by the History of Science Society. He was also awarded numerous honorary doctorates.

HISTORY OF SCIENCE

Kuhn's historical work covered several topics in the history of physics and astronomy. During
the 1950s his focus was primarily on the early theory of heat and the work of Sadie Carnot.
However, his first book concerned the Copernican revolution in planetary astronomy (1957).
This book grew out of the teaching he had done on James Conant's General Education in Science
curriculum at Harvard but also presaged some of the ideas of The Structure of Scientific
Revolutions. In detailing the problems with the Ptolemaic system and Copernicus’ solution to
them, Kuhn showed two things. First, he demonstrated that Aristotelian science was genuine
science and that those working within that tradition, in particular those working on Ptolemaic
astronomy, were engaged in an entirely reasonable and recognizably scientific project. Secondly,
Kuhn showed that Copernicus was himself far more indebted to that tradition than had typically
been recognized. Thus the popular view that Copernicus was a modern scientist who overthrew
an unscientific and long-outmoded viewpoint is mistaken both by exaggerating the difference
between Copernicus and the Ptolemaic astronomers and in underestimating the scientific
credentials of work carried out before Copernicus. This mistaken view—a product of the
distortion caused by our current state of knowledge—can be rectified only by seeing the
activities of Copernicus and his predecessors in the light of the puzzles presented to them by
tradition that they inevitably had to work with.

CRITICISM AND INFLUENCE

Kuhn's work met with a largely critical reception among philosophers. That criticism has largely
focussed on two areas. First, it has been argued that Kuhn's account of the development of
science is not entirely accurate. Secondly, critics have attacked Kuhn's notion of
incommensurability, arguing that either it does not exist or, if it does exist, it is not a significant
problem. Despite this criticism, Kuhn's work has been hugely influential, both within philosophy
and outside it.

CONCLUSION

In conclusion, for millions of years we have been evolving and will continue to do so. Change is
difficult. Human Beings resist change; however, the process has been set in motion long ago and
we will continue to co-create our own experience. Kuhn states that "awareness is prerequisite to
all acceptable changes of theory". It all begins in the mind of the person. What we perceive,
whether normal or metanormal, conscious or unconscious, are subject to the limitations and
distortions produced by our inherited and socially conditional nature. However, we are not
restricted by this for we can change. We are moving at an accelerated rate of speed and our state
of consciousness is transforming and transcending. Many are awakening as our conscious
awareness expands.

You might also like