You are on page 1of 4

Bootstrap paradox

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

[hide]This article has multiple issues. Please help improve it or discuss these issues on the

This article possibly contains original research. (August 2011)


This article contains embedded lists that may be poorly defined, unverified or indiscrimin
The bootstrap paradox, or ontological paradox, is a paradox of time travel that refers to scenarios
whereby items or information are passed from the future to the past, which in turn become the same
items or information that are subsequently passed from the past to the future - this creates a
circularity of cause-effect such that the items or information have no discernible origin. Thus, the
paradox raises the ontological questions of where, when and by whom the items were created or the
information derived.
After information or an object is sent back in time, it is recovered in the present and becomes the
very object or information that was initially brought back in time in the first place. Numerous science
fiction stories are based on this paradox, which has also been the subject of serious physics articles.
[1]

The term "bootstrap paradox" refers to the expression "pulling yourself up by your bootstraps"; the
use of the term for the time-travel paradox was popularized by Robert A. Heinlein's story By His
Bootstraps.
Contents
[hide]

1 Definition

2 Examples
o

2.1 Involving information

2.2 Involving physical items

2.3 Involving people

3 In fiction

4 See also

5 References

Definition[edit]

This section does not cite any references or sources. Please help improve this sect
by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged
and removed. (August 2013)
Because of the possibility of influencing the past while time traveling, one way of explaining why
history does not change is to posit that these changes already are contained self-consistently in the
past timeline. A time traveler attempting to alter the past in this model, intentionally or not, would only

be fulfilling his or her role in creating history, not changing it. The Novikov self-consistency
principle proposes that contradictory causal loops cannot form, but that consistent ones can.
However, a scenario can occur where items or information are passed from the future to the past,
which then become the same items or information that are subsequently passed back. This not only
creates a loop, but a situation where these items have no discernible origin. Physical items are even
more problematic than pieces of information, since they should ordinarily age and increase in
entropy according to the Second law of thermodynamics. But if they age by any nonzero amount at
each cycle, they cannot be the same item to be sent back in time, creating a contradiction.
Another problem is the "reverse grandfather paradox", where whatever is sent to the past allows the
time travel in the first place (such as saving your past self's life, or sending vital information about the
time travel mechanism).
The paradox raises the ontological questions of where, when and by whom the items were created
or the information derived. Time loop logic operates on similar principles, sending the solutions to
computation problems back in time to be checked for correctness without ever being computed
"originally".
Whether or not a scenario described in this paradox would actually be possible, even if time travel
itself were possible, is not presently known.
The bootstrap paradox is similar to, but distinct from, the predestination paradox, in which individuals
or information travel back in time and ultimately trigger events they already experienced in their own
present. In the latter case, information and objects involved have definite origins.

Examples[edit]

[hide]This section has multiple issues. Please help improve it or discuss these issues on the
This section does not cite any references or sources. (August 2013)
This section possibly contains original research. (August 2012)

Involving information[edit]

On her 30th birthday, a woman who wishes to build a time machine is visited by a future
version of herself. This future self explains to her that she should not worry about designing the
time machine, as she has done it in the future. The woman receives the schematics from her
future self and starts building the time machine. Time passes until she finally completes the time
machine. She then uses it to travel back in time to her 30th birthday, where she gives the
schematics to her past self, closing the loop.

A professor travels forward in time, and reads in a physics journal about a new equation that
was recently derived. He travels back to his own time, and relates it to one of his students who
writes it up, and the article is published in the same journal which the professor reads in the
future.

A woman builds a time machine. She goes into the future and steals a valuable gadget. She
then returns and reveals the gadget to the world, claiming it as her own. Eventually, a copy of
the device ends up being the item the woman originally steals. In other words, the device is a
copy of itself and it is not possible to state where the original idea for the device came from.

A man with a time machine takes the complete plays of Shakespeare, translated into
Elizabethan English, and travels back in time to Tudor England. He then gives the plays to the
young William Shakespeare before he wrote them, telling him to publish them as his own work.

He does, and a copy of the 'original' publication is what is taken back in time. This means that
nobody wrote the plays of Shakespeare, as he essentially gave them to himself, thereby closing
the loop.

Involving physical items[edit]


An old woman gives a young man a watch; the young man then goes back in time and hands the
watch to a young woman; she later grows into the older woman who hands the watch to him. The
watch therefore has no point of origin.
A further paradox present for any physical item is that the watch should age each time around the
loop and eventually wear out. Bringing back a copy of the watch would prevent this "wearing out"
issue as would it being a "grandfather's axe".

Involving people[edit]
See also: I'm My Own Grandpa
A man travels back in time and falls in love with and marries a woman, who he later learns was his
own mother, who then gives birth to him. He is therefore his own father (and thus also his father's
father, father's father's father and so on), creating a closed loop in his ancestry and giving him no
origin for his paternal genetic material.

In fiction[edit]
The bootstrap paradox has been used in fictional stories and films. [2] In the 1980 romance
film Somewhere in Time, based on Richard Matheson's 1975 novel Bid Time Return, an elderly
woman gives a young man a pocket watch in 1972. He travels back in time to 1912 and gives the
pocket watch to her, which she carries with her until 1972 when she meets the young man and gives
the watch to him.[3] The concept is named from the Robert Heinlein story "By His Bootstraps",[2] which
is considered the "ultimate time travel paradox tale" of its time.[4] Don D'Amassa states that "The
greatest difficulty in creating a story of this type is not so much the plotting of the various times loops,
but to render them in such a way that the reader can follow the logic." [4]

See also[edit]

Grandfather paradox

Newcomb's paradox

Predestination paradox

Self-fulfilling prophecy

Strange loop

Temporal paradox

The chicken or the egg

Time travel in fiction

References[edit]
1.

Jump up^ Matt Visser (1995). Lorentzian wormholes. Bootstrap paradoxes A second class of
logical paradoxes ...

2.

^ Jump up to:a b Klosterman, Chuck (2009-10-20). Eating the Dinosaur. Simon and Schuster.
p. 60. ISBN 9781439168486. Retrieved 2 February 2013.

3.

Jump up^ Everett, Allen; Roman, Thomas (2011-12-15). Time Travel and Warp Drives: A
Scientific Guide to Shortcuts through Time and Space. University of Chicago Press.
p. 138. ISBN 9780226224985. Retrieved 3 February 2013.

4.

^ Jump up to:a b D'Ammassa, Don (2005). Encyclopedia Of Science Fiction. Infobase


Publishing. p. 67. ISBN 9780816059249. Retrieved 3 February 2013.

You might also like