You are on page 1of 4

Defining learning

Annotation
disability: what place
does intelligence
testing have now?
Greg O’Brien MB ChB MD FRCPsych FRCPCH
Professor of Developmental Psychiatry, University of
Northumbria.

Correspondence to author at Northgate Hospital, Morpeth,


Northumberland, NE61 3BP, UK.

Why is it important to detect and define learning disability* in Western cultural requirements, with consequent immense
a child, and how can one do so? The answers to the first ques- implications for interpretation. These themes emphasize the
tion are, largely, not in dispute. Not only does the recognition limitations of certain approaches to intelligence testing, partic-
and definition of learning disability contribute to our under- ularly in mixed-race populations, and where applied to individ-
standing of the basis of problems in a child’s educational, uals who have not received appropriate education. According
developmental, and social progress, it also has significant to proponents of this argument, to employ intelligence testing
long-term consequences, especially where the disability is to identify a low-IQ group according to a statistically derived
more severe.1, 2 The diagnosis or medical aetiology of the cut-off point is arbitrary, and largely unhelpful. For these rea-
child’s learning disability is a significant element of the story sons, policies of mass application of generic intelligence tests
and carries major phenotypic implications, in terms of dys- within large and diverse populations such as school children
morphology, organogenesis, development, and behaviour.3, 4 have largely fallen out of favour. But those who have played
It is one thing to diagnose, say, Down syndrome, and quite down the value of intelligence testing by emphasizing the ‘arbi-
another to reach an accurate appraisal of the individual trary’ nature of cut-off scores, seem to have forgotten their
child’s intellect, developmental attainments, and capacities. derivation and the intention of the original architects of the
In turn, the definition of learning disability is not always tests. It is crucial to bear in mind that cut-off scores identify
straightforward and is sometimes quite controversial. This is lower functioning groups, and that this is based on both a theo-
partly because, traditionally, at least three different approach- retical consideration of distribution of intelligence in the popu-
es are used to define learning disability in children, and each lation as well as a century of experience.12 Also, while not even
has its inherent attractions and pitfalls. These approaches are: the most strident advocates of intelligence testing would sup-
definition by IQ alone; definition by IQ combined with social port a return to its mass application, the increasing availabili-
functioning and age at onset;5 and definition by service con- ty of specialized approaches such as Raven’s Matrices13 and
tact, the so-called ‘administrative definition’.6 Kauffman Battery14 offer a pragmatic solution to the chal-
lenges which present to testing in a variety of circumstances
Defining learning disability on the basis of IQ alone and populations. However, the identification of significant
Use of intelligence testing alone, or in isolation, for the pur- impairment of intelligence through intelligence testing has
pose of identifying learning disability has been widely long been held by many to have long-term consequences.15
employed. Indeed, intelligence testing, whether by Wechsler Recent work, in which low IQ in childhood has been reem-
Adult Intelligence Test (WAIS)7 or Wechsler Intelligence Scale phasized as one major vulnerability factor for subsequent
for Children (WISC)8 was, in part, devised for this purpose.9 delinquency, suggests that IQ alone may serve as a useful
Such an approach relies on the validity and reliability of the marker to identify those with learning disability and that this
tests in question, which has been seen both as an inherent in turn may be important as a predictor of subsequent social
attraction and a problem by different authorities.10 This has adjustment, in addition, of course, to other social and family
been a subject of controversy since the introduction of intelli- factors.16, 17
gence testing at the beginning of this century. Critics of intelli- If IQ is to be used, the cut-off point employed in most
gence testing have emphasized its shortcomings (e.g. the approaches is that at 2 standard deviations below the mean of
study by Barnett11). Test results in one child can vary accord- 100, that is, at score 70. This is the internationally accepted
ing to mood, motivation, and fatigue, while the tests them- standard, adopted within the World Health Organization
selves show prominent rehearsal/learning effects, generally (WHO) definition of mental retardation. Two other possibili-
assume a degree of literacy, and are largely framed to suit ties are frequently adopted. The first is to take those scoring 1
standard deviation below the mean, that is 85. While rarely
*UK usage. US usage: mental retardation being employed systematically, this cut off has some relevance

570 Developmental Medicine & Child Neurology 2001, 43: 570–573


for special education, where a score of this magnitude corre- The issue of definition and measurement of social function-
sponds to ‘mild learning difficulty’.18 The other possibility is ing is resolved in recent guidelines on the application of the
to concentrate on those with IQ below 50, the group who WHO ICD-10 Guide to Classification in Mental Retardation,29
were previously described as ‘the pathological group’, because which recommend the use of some standard scale, notably the
of the high prevalence of identifiable pathological causes of Vineland Scale of social adjustment.34 The use of this instru-
disabling syndromes and brain disorders in that population.19 ment yields an age-standardized quotient, which serves as a
Selection of the latter group for study is of interest, for this is a reliable and valid indicator of capacity for independent social
population with an established prevalence and set of needs.20 functioning.35 The combination of standardized intelligence
It has long been established that any individual who falls into testing, age at onset within the developmental period, and cali-
this group is substantially socially disadvantaged in terms of brated assessment of social functioning, identifies a popula-
capacity for independent functioning, and that problems are tion which is accepted by most authorities as a reliable and
likely to endure.1 While recent genetic research gives some valid indicator of learning disability.
support to this concept of a separate, pathological group of
individuals with very low intelligence,21, 22 a growing body of Defining learning disability by service contact – the
evidence emphasizes that polygenic influences are apparent ‘administrative definition’
at all levels of intelligence.3, 23 An alternative approach to the definition of learning disabili-
The consensus remains that the limitations of an approach, ty, which has some widespread support, is the so-called
which defines learning disability by intelligence testing ‘administrative definition’. According to this tradition, those
alone, override its attractions. Few authors support the con- individuals in contact with learning disability services consti-
tention that intelligence testing alone is a sufficient or practi- tute the best-fit population of people with learning disabili-
cal approach to the definition of a population of people with ty.36 In the case of children, this population would comprise
learning disability, but fewer still would contend that intelli- those receiving special education for severe learning difficul-
gence testing has no role to play here. ty. There is a potential set of logical problems here. First of
all, services vary from place to place. Different services,
Defining learning disability by IQ, social functioning, and age including schools, do not employ similar or even equivalent
at onset – the WHO approach entry criteria.37 Even where they do, entry into special educa-
The diagnostic system employed by WHO in respect of learn- tion is not a straightforward matter (nor should it be),
ing disability has three crucial elements: IQ, social functioning, depending on parental approval, availability of services, and
and age at onset.24 The IQ element is the conventional cut-off other local factors. Furthermore, individual services change
score of 70, within which mild, moderate, severe, and pro- over time. As service models are developed, refined, and
found subgroups are further sub-classified into mild learning evaluated according to changing local and national policies
disability, corresponding to IQ under 70; moderate, IQ under and perceived needs, the entry criteria for any one service
50; severe, IQ under 35, and profound, IQ under 20. Onset is will inevitably change. It is therefore most unlikely that any
said to be ‘within the developmental period’. Not being more population identified by this method will be representative
rigorously defined than this, some authorities, notably the of the total population of people with learning disability.38
American Association for Mental Retardation, have definition Does an ‘administrative definition’ of learning disability
systems in which any case with onset up to 18 years can be have any advantages? It is likely that the population defined
included.25 However, the majority of instances of acquired will be one, which fulfils certain recognizable criteria, being a
brain damage in mid childhood or later (where islets of normal smaller group within the total population of children with
functioning are common, and memory problems figure high- learning disability.39 Being readily identifiable in such a way
ly), are distinct from pre- and perinatal cases in terms of both offers some bonuses, both in terms of potential ease of fol-
nature and outcome of disability.26, 27 The customary approach low-up, and documentation prepared, particularly up to
is, therefore, to include pre- and perinatal onset individuals, point of entry into special education.40 However, the short-
plus those with onset in early childhood.28, 29 comings of the ‘administrative definition’ of learning disabil-
The inclusion of social functioning in the WHO definition of ity are striking, and include: (1) the extent to which the sample
learning disability is an important element of this approach. may not be representative of the learning disability popula-
The principle is to distinguish between ‘impairment, disabili- tion, being skewed towards more severe disability; (2) the
ty, and handicap’,5 and to stress the need for some identifiable variability of populations identified by such means, varying
social incapacity to be present, in addition to manifest learn- both longitudinally and geographically; (3) the immense diffi-
ing disability. However, the inclusion of social functioning as culties which follow from the above, with regard to replication
an element of the definition of learning disability has been of research findings, and generalizability of local data for such
the subject of some controversy. Much of this criticism cen- purposes as service planning.
tres on whether labelling people with learning disability as
having social incapacities might stigmatize the individuals New directions in the definition of learning disability
concerned.30 Another issue is the problem of social incapacity All of these three traditional approaches have their critics.
and its social context. For, any individual with a given level of Definition by IQ, definition according to WHO disability/
learning disability might well cope and function sufficiently in impairment/handicap, and definition according to service
an undemanding social situation, while that same individual contact are all said to share certain limitations. First, insuffi-
would struggle within a different setting.31 There have been cient attention is said to be given to the individual’s actual
further concerns that social functioning will inevitably be social context.41, 42 Moreover, these approaches are seen in
context dependent, rather than subject to some broadly many quarters as likely to label adversely and stigmatize the
applicable measurement system.32, 33 individuals concerned.43 For these reasons an increasingly

Annotation 571
convincing body of opinion is more concerned to stress the in the commentary on the test results. Second, intelligence
positive, functional ability of individuals, rather than their dis- testing, while helpful, is not sufficient of itself for definition.
abilities.44 In line with this thinking, efforts are being made to There must be evidence for early onset in the developmental
incorporate both positive, ability-based elements into the defi- period. Here, it is surprising in clinical practice how often the
nition of learning disability, and also to include consideration evidence is far from clear; population migration and resultant
of social context and environment.45 Some preliminary efforts variations in practice and documentation are contributory fac-
in this direction were to be found in the WHO 1996 publication tors here. However, all indications are that evidence of early
ICD-10,29 where one of the five axes employed is a general onset may become even more important in the near future, in
measure of ability. This brief (75 page) document did not attain the face of these latter secular trends. In addition to intelli-
the status of an official WHO publication. However, in 1997, a gence testing, therefore, some measure of social functioning
more radical WHO document, ICDH-2: The International should be made, such as a Vineland assessment.34 It should be
Classification of Impairments, Activities and Participation46 noted, however, that many of the same provisos that apply to
was launched in pilot form for field trials. Here, the emphasis is intelligence testing apply here. While the combination of the
changed entirely, and the individual with a disability is consid- two is quite robust, just as intelligence assessment alone is
ered in as wide a context as possible. A host of aspects of insufficient, the same applies to assessment of social function-
lifestyle and situation are included and coded in detail, the ing. Furthermore, the complexities of definition by service
thrust being to record and classify how different personal received, for example by school attended, must be considered
impediments and social influences serve to either enhance or carefully. To ignore a child’s reception into special education is
diminish the activities of which the individual is capable, that in to miss important information, whether in terms of the pre-
turn affect participation in society. This approach is intended to ceding background factors or the resultant impact of experi-
foster a new style of holistic thinking and research about dis- ence at the school. But to identify or classify a child according
ability. It is likely to succeed in this aim, although it is thought by to type of special education received, and to then go on to
some to be somewhat over-detailed and cumbersome for gen- make prognostic statements on that basis, is far from satisfac-
eral use. Regarding its use in respect of people with learning tory. Finally, there is a need to be clear about what is meant by
disability, the shift towards a more positive and inclusive style defining learning disability. Social context and obstacles to
of thinking is certainly to be welcomed. However, it is impor- integration may in a sense ‘define’ the individual’s situation.
tant to note that this document makes no attempt to provide an But an operationalized definition of learning disability, includ-
operationalized definition of learning disability. On the con- ing the consideration of intelligence, remains vital.
trary, it is stated specifically that the ICIDH-2 should be used in
conjunction with the ICD-10 definitions. Interestingly, in this Accepted for publication 20th December 2000.
most forward thinking of classification systems, it is acknowl-
edged that the traditional approach to the definition of learn-
ing disability per se remains a crucial foundation in our References
thinking and practice. These new insights challenge our think- 1. Penrose LS. (1972) The Biology of Mental Defect. London, UK:
Sidgwick and Jackson.
ing and widen our perspectives, but they do not negate our 2. O’Brien G. (2001) The adult outcome of child mental retardation.
established ideas on definition. Developmental Medicine & Child Neurology. (Forthcoming).
As yet, it is uncertain what the impact of these shifts in 3. O’Brien G, Yule W, editors. (1995a) Behavioural Phenotypes.
emphasis might be. Certainly, more emphasis on the poten- Clinics in Developmental Medicine No. 138. London: Mac Keith
tials of individuals with learning disabilities should facilitate Press.
4. Gillberg C, O’Brien G, editors. (2000) Developmental Disability
the realization of that potential through maximal develop- and Behaviour. Clinics in Developmental Medicine No. 149.
ment of their abilities. Similarly, acceptance of the influence London: Mac Keith Press.
of the social environment is crucial to the understanding of 5. World Health Organization. (1980) International Classification of
any ability or behaviour, not just the situation of the person Impairments, Disabilities, and Handicaps. Geneva, Switzerland:
World Health Organization.
with the disability. But it is uncertain how easily these 6. Richardson SA, Koller H. (1996) Twenty Two Years: causes and
insights will improve our definition of learning disability. It is consequences of mental handicaps. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
difficult to envisage how some operationalized measure of University Press.
social environment might be incorporated into our defini- 7. Wechsler D.(1997) Wechsler Adult Intelligence Test. 3rd edn.
tion system. In any event, there is now increasing acknowl- New York: The Psychological Corporation.
8. Wechsler D. (1991) Wechsler Intelligence Scale for Children. 3rd
edgement of the extent to which environmental influences edn. New York: The Psychological Corporation.
operate, and in a sense ‘define’ learning disability. 9 Zigler E, Balla D, Hoddap RM. (1984) On the definition and
classification of mental retardation. American Journal of Mental
Summary Deficiency 89: 215–30.
10. Hoddap RM, Zigler E. (1985) Placement decisions and their effects
In summary, therefore, when we endeavour to make any on the development of individuals with severe mental retardation.
statements on the presence and/or degree of learning disabil- Mental Retardation 23: 125–30.
ity in children, we need to consider carefully how we define 11. Barnett WS. (1986) Definition and classification of mental
our population. Intelligence testing, or some similar psycho- retardation: a reply to Zigler, Balla and Hoddap disorders: from
metric procedures should be available, but with two substan- infancy to adult life. American Journal of Mental Deficiency
91: 111–16
tial caveats. First, the results of the tests must be taken in the 12. Dacey CM, Nelson WM III, Stoe C, Kel J. (1999) Reliability, criterion
context of the respective test situations, and any relevant wider validity, and qualitiative comments of the fourth revision of the
child/environmental factors. In practice, where testing is car- Stanford-Binet Intelligence Scale with a young adult population
ried out by a chartered psychologist according to standard pro- with intellectual disability. Journal of Intellectual Disability
Research 43: 179–84.
tocols, these considerations are dealt with, and will be cited

572 Developmental Medicine & Child Neurology 2001, 43: 570–573


13. Raven JC. (1982) Revised Manual for Raven’s Progressive 39. Richardson SA. (1984) Institutionalisation and
Matrices and Vocabulary Scale. Windsor UK: NFER Nelson. deinstitutionalisation of children with mental retardation. In:
14. Kaufman AS, Kaufman NL. (1983) K-ABC Kaufman Assessment Stevenson HW, Siegal AE, editors. Child Development Research
Battery for Children. Circle Pines MN: American Guidance and Social Policy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Service. 40. O’Brien G, Yule W. (1995b) Methodological issues in
15. Silverstein AB. (1982) Notes on the constancy of IQ. American behavioural phenotypes research. In: O’Brien G, Yule W, editors.
Journal of Mental Deficiency 87: 227–8. Behavioural Phenotypes. Clinics in Developmental Medicine
16. Farrington D. (1994) The twelfth Jack Tizard Memorial Lecture. No. 138. London: Mac Keith Press. p 35–44.
The development of offending and antisocial behaviour from 41. Marks D. (1997) Models of Disability. Disability and
childhood: key findings from the Cambridge Study in Delinquent Rehabilitation 19: 85–91.
Development. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry 42. Tennant A .(1997) Models of disability: a clinical perspective.
36: 929–64. Disability and Rehabilitation 19: 478–9.
17. Fergusson DM, Horwood LJ. (1995) Early disruptive behaviour, 43. Imrie R. (1997) Rethinking relationships between disability,
IQ, and later achievement and delinquent behaviour. Journal of rehabilitation and society. Disability and Rehabilitation
Abnormal Child Psychology 23: 183–99. 19: 263–71.
18. Goacher B, Evans J, Welton J, Wedell K. (1988) Policy and 44. Oliver M. (1998) Disability in health practice and research.
Provision for Special Education Needs – Implementing the 1981 British Medical Journal 317: 1446–9.
Act. London, UK: Cassell. 45. Hutchinson T. (1995) The classification of disability. Archives of
19. Reid AH. (1976) Psychiatric disturbances in the mentally Disease in Childhood 73: 91–3.
handicapped. Proceedings of the Royal Society of Medicine 46. World Health Organization. (1997) ICDH-2: The International
69: 509–12. Classification of Impairments, Activities and Participation.
20. Corbett J. (1979) Psychiatric morbidity and mental retardation. In: Geneva, Switzerland: World Health Organization.
James FE, Snaith RP, editors. Psychiatric Illness and Mental
Retardation. London: Gaskel Press.
21. Gillberg C. (1992) The Emmanuel Miller Memorial Lecture 1991.
Autism and autistic-like conditions: subclasses among disorders of
empathy. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry 33: 813–42.
22. Thapar A, Gottesman II, Owen MJ, O’Donovan MC, McGufin P.
(1994) The genetics of mental retardation. British Journal of
Psychiatry 164: 7–58.
23. Plomin R. (1990) The role of inheritance in behaviour. Science
248: 183–8.
24. World Health Organization. (1992) The ICD-10 Classification of
Mental and Behavioural Disorders. Geneva, Switzerland: World
Heath Organization.
25. Grossman HJ. (1983) Classification in Mental Retardation.
Washington DC: American Association on Mental Deficiency.
26. O’Brien G. (2000) Mental retardation. In: Gillberg C, O’Brien G,
editors. Developmental Disability and Behaviour. Clinics in
Developmental Medicin, No. 149. London: Mac Keith Press.
p 12–26.
27. O’Brien G, Cheeseburgh B. (2000) Traumatic brain damage. In:
Gillberg C, O’Brien G, editors. Developmental Disability and
Behaviour. Clinics in Developmental Medicine, No. 149. London:
Mac Keith Press. p 64–76.
28. Corbett J. (1977) Studies of Mental Retardation. In: Graham PJ,
editor. Epidemiological Approaches in Child Psychiatry. London:
Academic Press.
29. World Health Organization. (1996) ICD-10 Guide to Classification
in Mental Retardation. Geneva, Switzerland: World Heath
Organization.
30. Mittler P. (1979) People Not Patients. London: Methuen.
31. Landesman-Dwyer S. (1981) Living in the community. American
Journal of Mental Deficiency 86: 223–4.
32. Department of Health. (1993) Services for People with Learning
Disabilities and Challenging Behaviour or Mental Health Needs.
London: Her Majesty’s Stationery Office.
33. Evans DW, Hoddap RM, Zigler E. (1995) Mental and chronological
age as predictors of age-appropriate leisure in children with
mental retardation. Mental Retardation
33: 120–7.
34. Sparrow SS, Balla DA, Ciccheti DV. (1984) Vineland Adaptive
Behavior Scale. Circle Pines MN: American Guidance Service.
35. Kamphaus R. (1987) Conceptual and psychometric issues in the
assessment of adaptive behaviour. Journal of Special Education
21: 27–35.
36. Richardson SA, Koller H, Katz H. (1986) A longitudinal study of
males and females in mental retardation services by ages, IQ and
placement. Journal of Mental Deficiency Research 30: 291–300.
37. Department of Health. (1995) Health of the Nation: a strategy for
people with learning disabilities. London: Her Majesty’s
Stationery Office.
38. Mansell J. (1990) The natural history of community mental
handicap teams. In: Brown S, Wistoe G, editors. The Roles and
Tasks of Community Mental Handicap Teams. Aldershot, UK:
CRSP.

Annotation 573

You might also like