You are on page 1of 3

1/17/2018 Printable format for Efficiency: The Concise Encyclopedia of Economics | Library of Economics and Liberty

Printable Format for http://www.econlib.org/library/Enc/Efficiency.html

FAQ: Print Hints

Efficiency
by Paul Heyne
About the Author

T o economists, efficiency is a relationship between ends and means.


When we call a situation inefficient, we are claiming that we could
Related CEE Articles:
Energy
achieve the desired ends with less means, or that the means employed Hoover's Economic
Policies
could produce more of the ends desired. “Less” and “more” in this context
Innovation
necessarily refer to less and more value. Thus, economic efficiency is
Law and Economics
measured not by the relationship between the physical quantities of ends
Property Rights
and means, but by the relationship between the value of the ends and the
Socialism
value of the means.
Tragedy of the Commons

Terms such as “technical efficiency” or “objective efficiency” are meaningless. From Related CEE
Biographies:
a strictly technical or physical standpoint, every process is perfectly efficient. The
Frank Hyneman Knight
ratio of physical output (ends) to physical input (means) necessarily equals one, as
Adam Smith
the basic law of thermodynamics reminds us. Consider an engineer who judges one
machine more efficient than another because one produces more work output per
unit of input. The engineer is implicitly counting only the useful work done.
“Useful,” of course, is an evaluative term. Go to 1st Edition

The inescapably evaluative nature of the concept raises a fundamental question for every attempt to talk
about the efficiency of any process or institution: Whose valuations do we use, and how shall they be
weighted? Economic efficiency makes use of monetary evaluations. It refers to the relationship between
the monetary value of ends and the monetary value of means. The valuations that count are,
consequently, the valuations of those who are willing and able to support their preferences by offering
money.

From this perspective a parcel of land is used with maximum economic efficiency when it comes under
the control of the party who is willing (which implies able) to pay the largest amount of money to obtain
that control. The proof that a particular resource is being used efficiently is that no one is willing to pay
more in order to divert it to some other use.

Those who object that this is an extremely narrow definition of efficiency often fail to recognize that
every concept of efficiency has to employ some measure of value. The monetary measure used by
economics turns out to be both broad and useful. It enables us to take account of and compare the
evaluations made by many different persons and to respond appropriately.

What kind of structure should sit on the corner lot at Fifth and Main: a gas station, a condominium, a
florist shop, or a restaurant? The owner can make a defensible decision even if everyone in town has a
slightly different preference. The owner simply accepts the highest money bid that various prospective
users of the land (the florist, the restaurateur, etc.) make for it. Effective social cooperation requires
interpersonal comparisons of value, and monetary values supply us with a common denominator that
works remarkably well.

The crucial prerequisites for the generation of these monetary values are private ownership of resources
and relatively unrestricted rights to exchange ownership. When these conditions are satisfied, competing
desires to use resources establish money prices that indicate each resource’s value in its current use.

http://www.econlib.org/cgi-bin/printcee.pl 1/3
1/17/2018 Printable format for Efficiency: The Concise Encyclopedia of Economics | Library of Economics and Liberty

Those who believe that particular resources would be more valuably (more efficiently) employed in some
other way can raise the price and bid them away from the current users.

In the 1930s, for example, a small group of people who placed a high value on hawks bought a mountain
in Pennsylvania and thereby converted it from a hawk-hunting area to a hawk sanctuary. Today our laws
protect hawks and other predators, but in the 1930s hawks were in danger of extinction because they
were hunted as vermin that ate chickens. If the only option for those who formed the Hawk Mountain
Sanctuary Association in 1934 had been to persuade politicians and the public to change the laws, hawks
could well be extinct today in that area. The association was able to save the hawks because its
members demonstrated, through competing money bids, that a sanctuary was the most efficient—that
is, the monetarily most valuable—use for the mountain.

Perhaps the importance of private ownership to achieving economic efficiency can be seen most clearly
by looking at what happens when we try to work together without an effective system for assigning
monetary value to resources. Take the example of urban automobile traffic. How can we arrive at a
judgment about the overall efficiency or inefficiency of the commuting process when we have to compare
one person’s convenience with another’s delay, time saved for some with carbon monoxide inhaled by
others, one person’s intense dissatisfactions with another person’s pleasures? To find out whether Jack
values clean air more than Jill values a speedy commute requires a large set of interpersonal value
indicators. Urban commuting creates congestion as well as air pollution problems in our society because
we have not developed a workable procedure for weighing and comparing the positive and negative
evaluations of different people.

The crucial missing element is private property. Because so many of the key resources employed by
commuters are not privately owned, commuters are not required to bid for their use and to pay a price
that reflects their value to others. Users pay no money prices for resources such as urban air and urban
streets. Therefore, those goods are used as if they were free resources (see
). But their use imposes costs on all the others who have been deprived of their use. In the
absence of money prices on such scarce resources as streets and air, urban dwellers “are led by an
invisible hand to promote an end that was no part of their intention,” to apply A S ’s famous
generalization. In this case, however, the end is not the public interest but a result that no one wants.

Critics of economic efficiency contend that it is a poor guide to public policy because it ignores important
values other than money. They point out, for example, that the wealthy dowager who bids scarce milk
away from the mother of an undernourished infant in order to wash her diamonds is promoting economic
efficiency. The example is strained, not least because the pursuit of economic efficiency almost always
makes milk available to the infant as well as the dowager. Most economists would agree that such
dramatic examples can remind us that economic efficiency is not the highest good in life, but that does
not mean we should discard the concept.

The moral intuitions that enable us to arbitrate easily between the child’s hunger and the dowager’s
vanity cannot begin to resolve the myriad issues that arise every day as hundreds of millions of people
attempt to cooperate in using scarce means with varied uses to achieve diverse ends. Moreover, the
remarkable feats of social cooperation that actually make wholesome milk available to hungry infants far
removed from any cows would be impossible in the absence of the monetary values that express and
promote economic efficiency.

The social usefulness of well-defined , free exchange, and the system of relative
money prices that emerges from these conditions has perhaps been demonstrated most convincingly by
the catastrophic failure in the twentieth century of the societies that tried to function without them (see
).

About the Author

http://www.econlib.org/cgi-bin/printcee.pl 2/3
1/17/2018 Printable format for Efficiency: The Concise Encyclopedia of Economics | Library of Economics and Liberty

The late Paul Heyne was a senior lecturer in economics at the University of Washington in Seattle. He held a Ph.D. in
ethics and society from the Divinity School of the University of Chicago. He died in 2000.

Further Reading

Hayek, Friedrich A. “The Use of Knowledge in Society.” American Economic Review 35, no. 4 (1945): 519–530.
Reprinted in Hayek, Individualism and Economic Order. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1948. Available online
at: http://www.econlib.org/library/Essays/hykKnw1.html
Jouvenel, Bertrand de. “Efficiency and Amenity.” Earl Grey Memorial Lecture, delivered at King’s College, Newcastle
upon Tyne, England, 1960. Reprinted in Kenneth J. Arrow and Tibor Scitovsky, eds., Readings in Welfare Economics.
Homewood, Ill.: Richard D. Irwin, 1969. Pp. 100–112.
1923. K ,F H. “The Ethics of Competition.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 37 (1923): 579–624. Reprinted in
Knight, The Ethics of Competition and Other Essays. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1935.
Stroup, Richard L., and Jane S. Shaw. “The Free Market and the Environment.” Public Interest 97 (Fall 1989): 30–43.
Return to top

Copyright ©2008
Liberty Fund, Inc.
All Rights Reserved

http://www.econlib.org/cgi-bin/printcee.pl 3/3

You might also like