You are on page 1of 52

State of Exception � Giorgio Agamben

TRANSLATED ThY KEVIN ATTELL

THE UN1VERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS

Chicago and London


j f ;i 5(c,
, f;;, l//3?,
()
<HORGH'.I AGJ,:,t Al' •1 is r,r-0t\'�$f:!f of ,ws,betks a1 the University ofVerona. Contents
He is: the iml'-or ,,f t':n rre,vim 1s f':10;(1, '.n,;:foditig :1'-s.· prcqud t0 thb <me,
lfo:r1c, Snr,:r: S1rcrd.Çn Pt:wcrand NilfF< fi[<:, td,:ishçd ia English by Stanford
l'u:h·:-oi')' Press.

K ev1r,; A TTFt;, is 1 rm-:,,1 0ctrm1l follnw i11 the f::igli,;h n�rartment at the
l!niV't'rsity of C1Hf:1tnî!1, Duvis. He is the trnnil.it0r of Giorgio Agarnben's Thr
o;,r,:· "[!.fa,: nid .�•d1wd Translator's Note vii

Thç l1uiver�i17 of Chkago Press, Chkag<.1 60637 Tbe State of Exœptiûn as a-!)aradigm of Government
The Uni·:cnit)' of Chiu1go Press, Ltd., L011don
1 Fon:e-of-� 31
© 1005 by The Universilr of Chicago
3 Iustitium 41
Ail right� r<"�erw,d. PnhJiqh1;d :wo5
Printed in the Unil'ed States of Amcrka 4 Gig:mtomàchy Concernîng a Void 52
5 Feast, Mourning, Anomie 65
14 13 12 11 10 09 08 07 06 05 l 2 J 4 5 6 A.uctoritas and Potestüs 74

fS.SN (do1h): 0 226•00924�6



Referenœs 89
1 SBN (paper): O<U6·009Z5·4 Index ofNames 93

Ori;�b1'.ly p:ih1is:1cd ao StnM di rtmr:tiMe. © 10:i3 fk•H;,ti 1k•rkghkri editorc


s.r.L, Tllrinll.

�Ag,,whrn, Gio1gio, 1942··


jSbto èi c::rth·1,·. itngli:.h]
St:>tt of�"Xz't'tlk•n ! r:foygi;, Ag1mhcn; trzmbtu! hr Kevin Artel!.
p, cm.
fodu,ks bib!ingn•ph1r 11 refen•1,ces (p, ) and index.
:rnN o-:.u.6 00924-fi (doth: ,1Jk, ty..i.per)- J;JttN 0 ➔22ihm925-4 (phk.:

nlk pafJer)
1. War ar1d emergency powelii. .z. Shte of sk>g<\ 3, War and
emergem:.:y powertt ·•-•fatmpe--Hislory. 4, ;NJr .r1d cmergcncy powers-­

United Stak�History. 5, 5:tate of si<:ge-Fnn:<pe- --Hi�tory. 6➔ State ,,f


sieg�United States-History, i, Title,
JF456,AJ4Jj 2005
321------0c22 1,004.-..:13680

@Ths> r1rc,r :1<:,:,d in !hi\ ;,n½!ic.iticli rrn:::rt� :hr mi'cim:i:n ,;,!quirements of


!ht AmJri:::,m l'fath:-.nn! St1H<<l0nl for !;.foTTT:1ti,,n Snrnccs-!\:Trri;m;1r::�·c of
Pzper for Printed; ihrm:y ;'l;';;terials, A#Sl z3.:;.L!H99i,
-,-------------------""'!!!"11"""_1_

Translator's Note

\Vherever possible, 1 have induded refürenœs to pubfühed English tn:mslatiom


of Agamben's French, German, and !talian sources in the references fü;t How*
ever, in order to maintain consistcncy in lerntinology tbrougho11t the text, and
to better ret1ect Agamben's mv::i tr;imln.tiom of thtse sources, thcpuhlished Eng�
lish versions have freqnently been modifie<l, \Vhcrcan EngHsh editfon is Hsted in
the bibliography, the first page nnmber in the text dtallon refers to the origînal�
and the second to the Engllsh edition (e.g,, [BenjarnJU 1942, 69ïl257]). Where
no English edition fa liste,.:!, the trnnslBtion is mine,
I would like to give my <leept'St thanks to Courtney Booker, David Copen�
hafcr,Samuel Gilbert, Sfrietta Slmondni, and toGiorgioAgamhen for theirgen.
erous hdp in preparing this translation,
Quare siletis jurî::tae in tmmere vestro?

[\%y are you jt1dsts sîlent about thar whkh cuncerns you?]
1 I'< The State of Exception as a Paradigm of Government

1.1 The essential contiguity between the state of exception and sov­
ereignty was established by Carl Schmitt in his book Politische Theolo­
gie (1922). Although his famous definition of the sovereign as "he who
deddes on the state of exception» has been widely commented on and
discussed) there is still no theory of the state of exception in public law,
and jurists and theorists of public law seem to regard the problem more
as a quacstio facti than as a genuine juridical problem. Not only is such
a theory deemed illegitimate by those authors who (following the an­
dent maxim according to which necessitas lcgem non habet [necessity
has no law]) affirm that the state of necessity, on which the exception
is founded, cannot have a juridical form, but it is difficult even to ar­
rive at a definition of the term given its position at the limit between
politics and law. Indeed, according to a widely held opinion, the state
of exception constitutes a "point of imbalance between public law and
political fact" (Saint-Bonnet 2001, 28) that is situated-like civil war,
insurrection and resistance-in an "arnbiguous, uncertain, borderline
fringe, at the intersection of the legal and the political" (Fontana 1999,
16). The question ofborders becomes all the more urgent: if exceptional
measures are the result of periods of political crisis and, as such, must
be understood on political and not juridico-constitutional grounds (De
Martino 1973, 320), then they find themselves in the paradoxkal position
of being juridical measures that cannot be understood in legal terms,
and the state of exception appears as the legal form of what cani:10t have
legal form. On the other hand, if the law employs the exception-that
is the suspension oflaw itself-as its original means of referring to and
encompassing lîfe, then a theory of the state of exception is the prelim­
inary condition for any definition of the relation that binds and, at the
same time, abandons the living being to law.
It is this no-man's-land between public law and political fact, and
between the juridical order and life, that the present study seeks to
2 L1tapter One 111e Statc of Except ion as a Para<ligm of Governmeut 3
1
' \: investigate. Oniy if the vdl covering this ambiguous zone is lifted will tht' state of exception appears as a th reshold of indeterminacy between
we be able to approach an understanding of the stakes involved in the democracy and ahsolutism.
differern::.e- · •Or the supposed dîfforence-betWeen the politkal and the
jurldiCa1, and belween Jaw and the living heing. And perhaps only then � The expression "global civil war"' appcars în the same ye4r (1963) in both
wiU it be possible to answer the question that never ceases to reverberate Hannah Arendt's On Rrvolution and Carl Schmitt's Theory <ift}œ R1rtfrm1.�How­
1

in the history of\Vestern poHtks: what does it mean to act potîtîcally? ever, as we Will see, the distlnction between a "real state of cx:ccptioo" ( état
Je siège effectif) and a "fictitious state nf cxœption" (üat de siège fictif) goes
1.2 One of the elements that make the state of exception so difficult back to FrC'nch puhlk law thcory and was: alreadydearly ;-1rtk11lat-ed in Theodor
to define is certainty îts dose relationship to civil war} insurrection ) ant'Î Reinadi's book De l'état de siège. Pmde historique et juridique (18$5), whkh is at
tesistauce, Because dvil war is the oppositè of normal conditions, ît Hes the origins of the Schmittian and Benjaminkm opposition between a real and
in a zone of undeddabîlitywith respectto the state of exception, which is a fictitious statc of exception. Anglo-Saxon jurisprudence prcfors to speak here
state power's immedfate rcsponse to the mostext.rcme internai conflk"ts, of «funcied ernergency."' For their part, Nazi jurists sp-oke openly of a gewolltt:
Thus, over �he course of the nventieth œntury, we have been able to Ausnahme:mstand, a "willed state of exccptfon;' "for the sake of estabfü:hing
witness a paradoxical phcnomenon that has been effectively dcfined as the Kational Sodalist State" (Werner Spohr, quote<l in Drobische and Wieland
a "legal civil war" (Schnur 1983). Let us take the case of the Nazi State. No 1993, 28).
sooner did Hitler take power { or, as we shoukl perhaps more accurately
say; no sooner was power given to him) than, on Fcbrnary 28 1 he pro­ 1.3 The immediately biopolitica] signifiœnce of the state of excep­
daimed the Dt·crce for the Protection of the People and the State, whkh tion as tlle original s lructure in whîch law encompasscs living beir1gs
suspended the articles of the Weimar Constitution conœrning personal hy means of its own suspension emerges dearly in the "mi!itary or­
libertics. The decree was never repealed; so that from a juddical stand­ dd" issued by the presi<h:nt of the United States on November 131 2001)
point the entire Third Reich can be considercd a st,1te of exception that whlch amhodzed the "indefinitc detention" and trial by "military corn~
lasted t wdve yea.rs, In this sense, modern totalitarianism can be defined missionsn (not to be confused. with the miHtary tribu.nais provided for
as the establishment, by mcans of the stare of exception, of a legal 'civil by the law of war) of nondtîzens suspected of involvement in terrorist
war that allows for the physical eliminatiün not only of political advcr­ activities.
saries but ofen tire categorîes of dtîzens who for some reason cannot be The USA Patdot Act issue<l by the U.5. Senate on October 26 1 1001,
integrated into the politkal system. Since then 1 the voluntary creation already allowed the attorney gencra.1 to 4takt• int:o custody" ,my alien
of a permanent state of emergency (thongh perhaps not declared in the suspected of activîties that endangered "the national security of the
technical sensc) has hecome one of the essential practices of contempo­ United States," but wlthin sevcn days the alien had to be either relcased
rary states, including so-called democratic ones. or charged with the violation of immigration laws or some other crimi­
Faced with the unstoPp-able progression of what has been caHed a nal offense. What is new about .President Bush•, order is that it radically
"global civil war;' the state of exception tends increasîngly to appear erases any legal status of the indîvidual. thus producing a lcgally un­
as the d·ominant paradigm of governrnent in conteiriporary politics. namable and unclassifiable being. Not only do the Taliban captured in
This transformation of a provisional and exceptional measure into a Afghanistan not enjay the status of PO\A/s as dcfined by the Geneva
technique of government threatens radîcall.y to alter-in fact, has al­ Convention, they do not evcn have the status of persons charged with
ready pa!pably altered-the structure and meaning of the traditional a crirne according to Amerkan laws. Neither prisoners nor persons ac­
distinction between constitutional forms. Indeed; from this perspet1'ive, rused, but simply "det,ünecs)" they are the abject of a pure de facto ntle>
4 Chapter One The State of Exception as a Paradîgm of Gm>ernmenl 5
of a detention that is indefinite not only in the temporal sense but in its to p ut the place.in a state of siege" (Re.inad1 1885, 109). The institution of the
very nature as welt since it is entirely removed from the law and from state of siege bas Îis origin in the Frl."nch Conslituent Assembly's decree of July
judicial oversight. The only thing to which ît could possibly be compared 8, 17911 whkh distinguished among état de paix, in w-hich mifüary authorïty and
is the legal situation of the Jews in the Nazi Lager [camps] > whoi along dvil anthority each o,;:ts in its own sphcre; état de guerre, in which civil authority
1vith thcir citizenship, had lost ever y legal identity, but at l.e ast retained must act in concert with military ;:rnthority; and élat de siège, in which "all the
their identity as Jews. As Judith Butler has effectively shown, in the de� fonctions entrusted lo lhe civil authority for" Jnaintaining order and internat
tainee at Guantânamo, bare life reaches its maximum indeterminacy. p olidng p ass lo the military commander, who exercises lhem under his exclu­
sive responsibUity" (ibid,). The decree referred only to miHtary strongholds and
1.4 The uncertainty of the concep t is exactly matd1ed by terminolog­ ports, but wHh the law of 19 Fructidor Year 5, the Directory as::imilated m1mic­
ipalities in the interior with the strong holds and� with the law of 18 Fructidor
ical uncertainty. The pr�sent study will use the syntagma staf:e of excep­
of the same year, grinted itself the right to put a dty in a state of siege. The
tion as the technical term for the consistent set of legal phenomena that
subsequenl history of the ;TI;ate of sicge is the history of lt.s graduai emancîpa­
it seeks to define. This te-rm, which is common in German theory (At4S­
tion from the wartime situation to whkh !t was odginally bound ln order to
nahmczustand, but also Notstand, "state of necessity")� is foreigo to Ital­
be us.ed as an cxlTàordinary police measure to cope tvith interna! se<litîon and
ia n and French theory, which prefer to speak of ernergency decrees and
disorder1 th.us changlng from a real, or mifüary, state nf siege to a fü=:titious, or
state ofsiege (p olitkal or fictitious, état de siège fict{(), In Anglo-Saxon
political one. In any c<1se, it fa important not to forget that the rnodern state of
theory, the terms martiaflaw and emergency power; prevaiL cx,:e,,t1c>11 is a creation of the demoi:rati<>revolutionary tradition and uot the
If, as has been suggested, terminology îs the properly poetk moment absolutist one.
of thought, then terminological choices can never be neutral. In this The idea of a suspension of the constltution was înrroduced for the fir;,,.ïtimc
sense, the choke of the term state tif exception implies a position ta.ken în the constitu1ion of n Frimaire Year S, Artkle 92. of whid1 reads, "In tht: case
on both the nature of the phenomenon that we seek to investigate and of arme<l revoh or disturbanct>s lhat wonld threa.ten tbe 5ecurity of the State, the
the logic most suîtable for undetstanding it. Thou gh the nolions of state taw can, in the places and for the tîme that lt determines, ;,uspend the nlte of
of siege and martial lav;' e.x:press a connection with the state of war that the amstltution. In such cases, thü: suspens.ion cnn be provislona!ly ded_ared by
has been hïstorkally decisive and is present to this day, they neverthe­ a of the goverrunenl if the legislative body is Îll recess, provided that this
less prove to be inadequatc to define the prnper structure of the phe­ body he corrvened as SûOO as pœsihle by an artide of the same decree." The ciiy
nomenon, and they must therefore be qualified a.s political or jictitùnis, or region in question was dedared hors la ,·onstîtution. Althongh the parndigm
terms that are themsdves misleading în some ways. 111e state ofe:xcep­ is, on the one hand (in the state of siege) the extension of the milîtary author­
tJon is not a speda1 kind oflaw {]ike the law of war); rather, insofar as it ity's -' \'a ftime powers into the dvil sphere, and on the other a su�pension of the
is a suspension of the juridical order itself, ît defines law;s thresho1d or constitution (or of tlw-se constilolional norms that protect individual liherties),
limit concept. in tinrn the two modds end up merging inro a single juridical phenomcnon that
we call the state ofexception.
� The history of the term fù:titious or politirnl statc ofsiege is instructive in this
regar<L lt goes back to the French doctdnè that-in reference to Napoleün's dè­ � The expression full powers (ph•it15 p01tvofrs), which is sometïmes used to char­
cree of December 24, 1811··-provided for the possibility of a sfate of siege that .acterize the stuu� ofexception, rcfcrB tn the c.xpansion of the powers of the gov�
the emperor could dedare whcther or not a city was actuaUy W1der attack or cnJment_, and in particules the conforral on the executive of the power to issue
directly threatened by enemy forces, "wh�never circumstancés rcquirc giving decrecs hnving the force oflaw. It d<:rives from the notion ofplenitwlo potc,�lntis,
more forces and more power to the mifüary police, without it bcing neces&1ry which was elaborated in th:1t truc and prnper laboratory of modern publiç lcgal
6 Chapter One Tl1e Stnte ofEx,;.;ption as a Paradi!;,'1ll of G-Overnment 7

!cmllnology that was canon law. TI1e prcsupposition here is that the st,ate of ex­ exœptional measure> but it also lets it:s own nature as the constitutive
ception enlails a retum to an original, plemmaric state !11 whkh the distin,:,tfon paradigm of th< juddical order corne to lighl.
aniong the differ1."!ll pmvers (legislatîve, excrntive, etc.) has not yct becn pro~ Tingsten's analysîs centers on an essentfal technkal prnblem that pro­
d\lced, As we will sec, the state of t"l:ctption constîtutes rather a kenomatic state, foundly marks the evolution of the modern parliamentary regimes: the
un emptiness of law, and the idea of an originary indisünc1ion and fuHness of delegation contained in the ''full powers" la\�S mentione<l above, and the
power must be considerc<l a legal mythologeme ùctalogous to the idea of a statc resulting extension of the exccutive's powers intô the legishi.tive sphere
ofnature (and it is nQt by chance th:H it was prcdsdy Schmitt who had recourn: through the issu an ce of tkcrecs and me-asuœs. ''Hy 'full powers laws' wc
to this mytho1ogeme). in any case, the term full power$ descrfües one of Lhe mean those laws by which an exceptiona !ly broad regulatory power is
executivc power's possible modes of action du ring the slatc of exception, but it
granted to the executivei partkularly the power lo -modify or abrogate
doès not coindde with it.
by decree the laws in forcé" {îingsten 1934, 1.3 ). Because fav,rs of this na­
t.5 Betwecn 1934 and ·1948, in the face of the collapiie of Europc's ture, which should be issued to cope with exceptional cin:.u mstances of
democracies) the theory of the stak of exception (whkh had made a necessity or emergency, conf] ict with the ftmdamcntal hierarchy of law
first, isolated appea1;ance in 1921 with Schmitt's book Dictntorship) saw and regula.tion in democratic constitutions and de!egt)te to the execu­
a moment of particular fortune, but ît is significant that this occurred tîve [gaver-no 1 a legislàtive power that shouid rest exdusively with par­
in the pseudomorphic form of a debate ovcr so-called constitutionai liament) Tingsten seeks to exumine the situation thai arose in a series
dictatorship. of countries (France1 S;;"/ltzerland1 Belglum; the United States, England,
This tenn (which German jurists had al ready used to indicate the Italy, Austria, and Gerrnany) from the sy1;te1matic expansion of execu­
emergency [ecœzionalil powers that Artide 48 of the VYeimar Constitu� tive [governamentaliJ powers during VVürld \,Ynr One, when a state of
tion granted the president of the Reîch [Hugo Preuss: Reith.sveifassungs­ siege was dedared or full pnwers laws issued in many of the warring
miiftige Diktnturl ) was taken up again and developed by l'rederick M. states (and even in neutral ones, like Switzerland), The hook goes no
Watkins ("The Problem of Constitutional Dictatorship," 1940), Carl J. fürther than recording a large numher of rnse histnrü;s; nevertheless,
Friedrkh ( Constitutional GÔvcmment and Democracy, [19,pJ 1950), and in the conclusion the author seems to realize that although a temporary
fina1ly CHnton L. Rossiter ( Constitutional Dictatorship: Crisis Gm1ern­ and controlled use of full powers is theoretkally compatible with demo­
ment in t11e Modern D'emocracies, 1948), Before them, \V\: m1.1 st also at cratîc constitutions_, "a systematic and regular e:xerdse of the institution
least mentîon the book by the Swedish jurist Herbert Tingstcn; Les pleins necessari!y leads to the 'liquidation' of democracy" (333), ln fact, the
pouvoirs, !/expansion des pouvoirs gouvernementaux pendtmt et 1:J grndual erosion of the legislative powers of parlh1ment,--,,which today
Grande Guerre (J934). VVhile these books are quite varicd and as a whole is often limited to rat.ifying measures that the executive issues thrnugh
more dependent on Schmitt's theory than a first reading might sug­ decrees having the force ofl.Jw-has si nce then become a common prac.­
gesti they are nevertheless equally important because they record for the tice. From thîs perspective, World \Var One (and the years following it)
first rime how the democratic r-egimes were transformed b'y the grad­ appear as a laboratoryfor testing ,ultl honing the function<il mechanisms
ua! expansion of the exeçutive's püwers·during the two world wars and, and apparai1ises of the state of exception as a paradigm of govemment.
more generally, by the state of exception that had accompanied and fol­ One of the essentiaI characterisrks of the sta te of exœptlon--the provi­
lowed those ,.vars. They are in some ways the heralds who announce<l sional abolition of the distinction among Iegislatîve, cx,:C\lttiv'e, and ju­
what we today have dearly bdore our eyes-namely) that since '"'the state dicîa.1 pmvers-here shows Jts u�ndency to hecome a las1ing practice of
of exception . . , has become the rule" (Ben}aniin 1942, 697/257), it 110t goven1ment.
only appears increasingly as a techn[que of government rather than an Friedr!ch's book makes much more use than îs apparent of Schmitt's
8 Chapter One The Srate offaception as a Parndigm of Govern.ment 9

theory of dktatorship, which is disrnissed in a footnote as ' a pru1i•


1
of eonstitutional government" [ 4]) and that as such it is fraught with
san tract" (Friedrich [1941] 19501 664). Schmitt's distinction betvveen dangers; ncverthelcss, it is predsely the JmmanenL neccssity of consti­
commissarial dictatorshîp and sovereign dictatorship reappears here as tntional dictatorship that he intends to demonstrate. But as he makes:
an opposîtion between constitutional dktatorship> which sceks to safe­ this attempt; he entangles himself Jn îrresnlvable contradictions. Indeed >
guard the constittitionaî order, and uncon::;titutional <lktatorship, ·whkh Schmitt's mode! (wbich he judges to be "trail-blazing, if somewhat oc•
leads to its overthroW. The impossibihty of defining and ovCrcoming the casfonal,1' and which he seeks to correct [14] ), in which the distinction
forces that determine the transition fr.om the first to the second form of between commissarial dictatorshîp and sovereign dictatorship .îs not
dktatorship (which is precisely what hap·pened} for cxample, in Ger� one of nature but of degree ( •.vith the decisive figure undoubtedly being
many) is the fundamental aporia of Friedrich's book, as it is generally the latter) i is, not so easily overcome. Althougb Rossiter provides no
of all theories of constitutional dktatorshîp. All such theories remain fewer than eleven criteria for distinguishing constitution.a) <lictatorship
prîsoner . i n the vîdous cîrcle in which the emergency rneasures they from unconstitutional dictatorship, none of them is capable either of
seek to justify in the name of defending the democratic constitution are defining a substantü11 d.ifference between the two or of ruling out the
the same ones that lea<l to lts ruin; passage from one to the other. The fact is that the two essential crite­
ria of absolute necessity and temporndness (whkh all the others corne
[T] here are no ultimate îristîtutional safeguards available for insur­
clown to in the last analysls) contradkt what Rossiter knows perfectly
ing that emergency powers be used for the purpose of preserving the
welt that is, that the state of exception has: hy now become the rule:
Constitution. Only the people's own detcrmhrntion to se1; thern so
"In the Atomic Age upon which the world is now entering, the use of
used can makc sure of that . . . All in all the quasi-dictatorial provi­
constitutional emérgency powèrS nrny wdl becom-e the rule and not the
sions of modern constitutionaJ systems, be they martial rule 1 statc of,
exception" (297); or as he says evèn more dearly at th11: end of the bl1ok,
siege) or constitutional emergency povlers, fail to ronform to any e:x­
"In describing the emergency powers of the western dcmocrades > this
acting standard of effective limitations upon a temporary concentra­
book may have given the impression that such techniques of govern­
tion of powers. Consequent1y� all these systems are Hable to be trans­
rnent as executive dictaiürshîp., the ddegation of lcgisfotive power) and
formed into totalitarian schemes if conditions becorne favorable to
lawmaking by administrative degrce were purely transitory and tempo­
it. (584)
rary in natnre. Such an impression wou1d be distïnctly misleading, . ,
In Rossiter"s book ·these aporîas explode înto open contradktions. The instruments of government depicted here as temporary 'crisis' ar­
lJniîke Tingsten and Friedrîch) Rossiter explkitly seeks to justify con­ rangements have in some countries. and mayeventual1y in all countdes,
stitutional dictatorship through a broad historical examination. His become lasting peacetime institutions1) (313), 'fhis prediction, whiçh
hypothesis here is that becattse the democratk regime, with its oom­ came eight years after- Benjamin's first formulation in the cighth the­
plex balance of power,; is conœived to function under normal drcum­ sis on the concept of hisr.ory, was undoubtedly accurate; but the words
stances, "•in tin-te of crisis a democratici constitutional government must that condude the book sound even more grotes(Jue: "No sacrifice is too
temporarily be altered to 1-vhatcver dcgrec is necessary to overcome the peril great fo� our democrncy) least of an the temporary saaifice of democ­
and re.H ore normal conditions. TI1is alteration invariably involves gov­ racy itself)l (314),
ernment of a stronger character; that îs, the government wiU have more
"'
power and the people fe-i.ver rights (Rossiter 1948) 5). Rossiter i'> aware 1.6 An examination ofhow the state of exception ts situated in the lega)
that constitntional dictatorship (that is, the state of exception) has, in tra<litions ofthe Western states reveals a division�dear in prindple1 but
fact, become a paradigm of government ("a well-established principle hazier in fact-between orders that rcgulate the state of exception in the
10 Cbupter One The Statt> of EX:'t>p(ion ,is a Panidigtn o( Govermncnt n

test of the rnnstitution or by a law and those that prefer not to regulate from the sphere of positi ve law prevailed, and the ariicle was not ap­
the problem explicitly. To the first group belong Franœ (where the mod­ proved. Howevcr, in the Constitution of the German Federal Republic
ern state of exception was born in the time of the Revolutîon) and Ger� there is an article tArticlc 20 j that unequivocall y legalizes the right of re­
manr; to the second beloog ltaly, Switzerland, Englllnd, and the United slstan-éè, stating that "against anyone who attempts to abolish t.hat order
States. Schoforshîp ii; also correspondingly dîvidcd between writers who 1 the democratic constitutîonJ, ail Germ ans have a right of resistance1 if
fuvor a constitutional or legisfativé provisjon for the state of exception no other remedies are possible."
and others (Carl Schmitt foremnst among them) who unrescrvedly crit­ The opposing arguments herc are exactly symrnetrical to the ones
idze the pretense of regula1ing by law what b)' definition cannot be put that dîvide advocates of legalizing the stale of exception in the text of
in norms l normato J. Though on the Jevel of the formai constitution the constitution or a sped_al law and those jurists who believç its nor ­
the distinction is undoubtedly important (Însofar as it presupposes 1 in mative regulation to be entirely inappropriate, Tt is certain, in a.ny case,
the latter case, that acts perfonned hy the govetnment outside of or in that if resistanœ were tù become a right or even a dt1ty (the omission
conflict with the Jaw can theoretically be considercd îllegcll and must of which coukl be punished), not only would the constitutjon end up
therefore be rectifie<l by a spccial "bill of indemnity"), on the level of positing itsdf as an ab-solu tiely untouchab]e and aU-encompassing value,
the ma terial constitution somcthing like a state of exception ex:ists in but the citizens' politkal chokes wouJd also end up being deterrnined
un the above-mentioned orders, and the history of the instîtution1 at byjuridical norms f giuridicamcntc nornum: l, The fact is that in both the
least since World War One, shows that ils development is independent right of resistance an<l th� statc of exception, what fa ultimately at issue
of its constitutional or legislative fi:.}rrtH-i.liZ-ation. Thus, Jn the Weimar is the question of the juridical significance of a sphere of action that is
Republic (where Article 48 of the constitution regolated the powers of in itself extrajuridkal. 1\vo theses are at odds here: One asserts that Jaw
the presîdent of the Reich whenever the "public security and order" [die must coind<le with the norm, and the other holds that the sphere of
ofjèntlid,e Sicherheit tmd Ordmmg] were threatened), the state of excep­ law exceed5 the norm. But in the last analysis, the tvvo positions agree
tion performc-d a surely more dedsîve fuw:tion than in Italy, where the in ruling out the existence of a sphere of human actlûn that is entirely
institution was not explîdt]y provided for> or in Frânte, whkh rcgulated œm oved from law.
it by a law and whkh also frequently had recourse to the ét,1t de siège an<l
N A BRIEfl HiS'f ORY OP THE $TATE OF EXCEPT10N, We have already seen
legislation by decrc�.
howthe statc ofs\egc had itJJ origin in France dnring the lkvolution, After being
esfablished with the Constituent Assembly's <lecree of )uly 8, 1791, it ;tçquired
1.7 The problem of the state of exœption presents dear analogies to lts proper physîognomy as état de siège fictif or état de siège politique vvith the
that of the right of resü,tance. It has been much debated, particularly Directorial law of August 27, 1797, and, finally, with Nllpolcon's dc(ree of De-~
du ring constituent asSemblies, whether the right of resistance should be cember 24, 1811.. The ides of a suspension of the constituti(:>n (of the "rule of
induded in the text of the constitution. The dtaft of the current ltal­ the constitution") had imtead been introdoced, as we have als.o sec-n, by the
ian Constitution induded ·an article that read, "When the public pow­ Constitution of 22 Frimaire Ycar 8, Article 14 of the Charte of 1814 gr:antcd the
ers violat.: the rights and fundamental libertics guaranteed by the Con­ sovereign the power to "make the, regufatiünS ;md ordirwnces neœssary for the
stitution; resjstance to .oppressîon is a right and a duty of the citizen," execution of the laws and the s.ecurity of the Stale"; because of the vagueness
This proposa!, which followed a suggestion by Giuseppe Dossetti1 one of the formula, Chateaubriand ob:,crved '-'thar h l� possible tbat one fine morn­
of the rnost prestigious of the leading Catholic figures, met with sharp ing the whole Charte \v·ill be forfeiteJ for the benl:'fit of Artidf, 14}' The state
opposition. Over the course of the debate the 01;inion that it was im­ of siege -was expressly mcntio11ed in the Acte arlrlitii:mr! tü the- Const!tntion of
possible to Jegally regulatc soincthing that_, by Jts nature, was removed April 22, 1815, which stateJ that it coul<l only be dedared with a law. Sinœ then,
u Chapter One The State of Exception as a Paradigm ùf Govern1ru-mt 13

moments of constitutional crisis in France over the course of the nineteenth 0


1934, 18). ln any case, Ît ·was dnring this pcriod that exceptional lcgisintion by
and twentieth centuries have been marked by legislatîon on the state of siege. executive [governa:tivoJ decree (which. is now perfectly familiar to us) became a
Afti:r the fol1 of the July Momm;hy, a decree Ù}' the Constituent ;\s.sembly on rcgular pr-actice in the European dcmocracies.
hme 24, 11',.j.8, put Paris in a state of siegc and assigned Gem:nü Cavaignac the Predictab!y, the expansion ofthe executive's powers into- the legislarive sphere
task of reRloring order in tbe city. Consequently, an article ;.vas induded in the continued after the end of hostilities, and it is significant 1hat military erner�
ncw constitution of N0vemher 4, 1848, establishing that the occasîons, forms, gency now ceded its place to economîc emergency (with an implicit assirnÜ<l­
and effects of the state of ;,iege wou!d be firmly set·hy a law, From this moment tion betwecn war and economics), In January 1924, at a time of serious crisfa
oui the dominant prindple in the French tradition (rhough_, as we wi!l see, not that threatened the stability of the fnmc, the Poinct1 ré govem::ncnt asked for
without fxceptlnns) has been that the power to suspend the laws can bdong füU powers over fin andal matters. Aftcr a hitter dc-bate, in whkh the opposition
only to the same power ùrnt produces them, that is, parliament (in contrast to p-ointed out that tbis ,...,as tantamount to parliament renmmdng its O\VU crm�
the German trt1dition, whkh eO.trusted this power to the head of state). The law stitutiona! powers, the law -i,\'as passed on March 22, 1;vith a four-month lirnit
of August 9, t849 (whkh was partially restricted latex by the law of April 3, 1878), on the governme.nfs spedal pmvers. Analogous mea�mes were brought to a
consequently established that a polltical state of sicge could be dedared by par­ vote in 1935 by the Laval government, which issuecl more than five hun<lred
liament (or, additionally, by the bead of state) in the case of imminent danger decrees "'liaving force of law'' in order to avoid the devaiuation of the franc.
to ex!ernal or interna! sernrity. Napoleon HI had recourse several times to this The opposition from the left, led by Léon Blum, strongly opposed this '�fasdst"
law ahd, once installed_ in power; he transferred, :in the constJtu.tînn of January practice, but it is significant that once the Lcft: took power with the l'opu!ar
1851., the exclusive power to proclaim a state of siege to the head of state:, The Pront, it as.kcd parliament in June 1937 for full powcrs in order tù dçval>Jt the
Frnnco�Prnssîan War and the insurrection of the Commune coindded with an franc, establish ex.change contrnl, and impose new taxes, As has been obscrved
unpreœdented gencralizat!on of the s.tate of exception, which was proclaimed in (Ros.siter 1948, 123), this rneant that the new pracüce of legislation by executive
forty dcpartrnents. and lasted in some of them until 1876. On the 'basis of these [gi::rvernativo] deçree1 which had been inaugur,ned during the wat, was by now a
expericnccs, and after Maç\1,ihon's faHed coup d'êtat in May i&n, the law of practiceacœpted by aU politkal sides, On June 30, 1937, the powers that had been
1849 was modified to establis.h that a state of siege coutd be dedared only with denied Blum were granted to the Chautemps govemment, in v:hich sev-eral key
a faw (or1 if the Chamb,n of Deputïes was not in s�ssion, by the head of state, minist1·\es were entrnsterl to nonsncfalists, And on April 10, 1938, Êdotwrd Dal­
who was then ohlîgated to convene parliament within two days) in the event of adier req11<-Sted and obtained from parlîament exœptiornü powers to legislate by
"imminent danger :resultîng from foreign war or anned instrrrectiod' (law of decree in order to rnpe v;ith both the lhrcat of Nazi Germany and the economic
April 3, 1878, Art. 1), crisis, It can the:refore be said that until the end of the Third Republic "the
Wmkl \Var One _coindded wiïh -a permanent sta �c of exception in the marn normal procedures of parliamentary democracy were in a statc of suspension"
jority of the, mrring countries. On August 2, 1914, President Poincaré issue-d a (124;. Vv11en wc study the birth of the so~çalled dictatori;:il regimes in Ital.y and
decree that put 1he entire .;ountry in a state of siege, and thîs decree v/as wn­ Gcrrnany, it is important not to forget this concurrent process that transformed
verled înto faw by padiament two days later. The state ofsiege ténlàÏned Jnforœ the democratic constitotlom bctween the two workl wars. Under the pressure
until Oetober 12, 1919. Although the activity ofparHament, whkh was suspended of the paradigm of the state of exception, the entire poîitico•-constitution.al Hfe
during the füst six months of thç war, reoommern:.·.ed·in January 1915, many of of Western sockties bcgan gradually to dssume a new form, wh_ich has perhaps
the laws pa:sscd were, Jn truth. pure and .simple delegations of legislat!ve power only today reached its fun deve.lopment. In December 1939, after the outbrcak
to the executivç, such as the law of February 10, 191,'l, which granted the govern� of the war, the D.1ladier govcrnment obtained the i:iower to take by dccrt·e al!
ment an a11 but absolute power to regulate hy decree the production and trade mcasures necessary to ensure the defense of the nation. Parlîame:nt remained
of fo-odstuffi. As Tingste11 has ohserved; in this way the exewtive power was ln session (except whcn it was smpended for a month ln order to deptivc the
transforrned into a legisla.tive orga.n in the material sense of the term '(Tingsten comm,mit>1 padiamentnrians of their Immnnity), but all lcgislative activîly lay
14 \.Jiapter One The State of Exception as a Paradigm of \:,-0vernment 15

firmly-in the hands of the exewtivé. By the timeJ,,farsho1 Pétain nssume<l power, ident's emcrge!'lcy f ccœzi,maiil powers rernained so indcterminate that not only
tlle French parliamcnt was a shadow of itsdf. Nevertheless, the Omstitutional did theotlsts regularly use the phrase "presi<lenti-al dictatorship'' in reference to
Ai.:t ofJulyn, 1940, grnntcd the head ofstate the powerto pnxlaim a state of sîcge Article 48, but in 1925 Schmitt could wrîte that "no constitution on earth had so
throughoul the entire national tcrrltory { which by then was partially occupied eas!!y legaJized a coup d'éiat as did the Weimar Constitution" (Sçhmitt 1995, 25).
by the German arrny), Save for a relative pause b<:tween 1925 and 1.929, the gnvernments of the Re:
In the present constitution, the state of eueption is regulat,ed by Article 16, public, �eglnning with Brüning's, mnde continuai use of Article 48, prodaiming
whkh De Gaulle had propose<l, The artide estabfühcs that the pr..�stdent of the a state of exception and bsuing emergcncy decn�es on more than two hundred
Repuhlic may take al[ nece.�sary 1�ea,,;;ures "whçn the institutions' of the Republk1 and fiftyoccasions; among other thîngs, 1hey cmployed it to imprison thomands
the JndependeiKe of the Nation, the intcgrity of i1s terri tory, or the execution of communist :militants and to set up special tribuna!s authorized to pronounœ
ofhs intcn;ational commitmcnts are seriously and imri1cdiate1)' threatened and capital sentences. On severa! üccasions, particularly in October1913, the govern­
the regular functioning of the constit!1tiomil puhlÎC powers is interrupted.''. rn ment had recourse to Article 48 to (ope wlth the faB of the mark, thus confirm­
April 1961, durîng the Aigerlan crisis, De Gaulle had œcourse to Article 16 even ing the modern tende11cy to conflate pofüîco-mfütary and eamomic crJSes.
though the functioning of the public powers had not been interrupted. Since It is well known lhat the t,st years ofthe Weimar Repnbîkpassed ent.irdy un­
thaï tîme, Artlde 16 bas never again been invoked, but, in conformîty wîth a der a regime of the state of exception; it is lcss ohvim1s lo note that Hitler could
continuing tendency în all of the Western democracies, the dedaration of the prohably not l1avefaken power had the country not heen under a regime of pres­
st:1te oft'xception has gr;cidually heen replaœd by an unprecedented gcneraliza� idential dictatorship for nearly three years and had parliamcnt been functîon­
tion of the parndigm of security as the normal technique of government ing. In Jnly 1930, the Brüning governmellt was put in the minoriîy, but Brünîng
did not resign. Insteàd, President Hindenhurg grnnted him rccourse to Article
The history of Article 4-8 of the \Vdmar Constitution is sn tîghrly woven into 4& and dissolved the Rcichstag. Fro.n thnt rnoment on, Germany in fa.et œa-sed
the history of Germany between the wars that it is lmpossible to un.:krstand
Hit1er's risc to pmvà wîthout füs.t analyzing the uses and abuses of this artiJe than twelve months in al!, while a flnctuating coafüfon of Soda} Dernücrats and
in the ye.ars bct,veen 19i9 and 193�, Jts lllirnediate prccedent wa;, Artide 68 ofthe cenhisîs stood by and watchcd a govemmcnt that by then amwered only to the
Bisman:ki;;.n Constitution, which, in cases where "public was threat� prcsident of the Reich. In 1932, Hindenburg-rerleded prcsî.dent over Hitler
ene<l in the territory of the Reich," granted the cmperor the power lü dedare and Thiilmanr.-fon:ed Brüning to rcsign and namcd the centrist vt.m Papen to
a part of the Reich to be in a state of war (Krirgs::ustaiuf), whose .:onditÎons bis post. On June 4, the Reichstag \vas dlssolved and never reconvcned until the
and limitations foHowed those set forth in the Prms-î:::m law ofJune 4, 1851. con­ advent ofNaûsm, On July 20, a stateof exception was prodaimed in the Pfussian
cerning the state of sîege. Amid the disorder and rîotin.g that followed the end territory, .and von Papen was named Reich Commissioner for Prussia-ousting
of the war, tl1e dcp\lües of the National Assembly that •Nas to vote on the 1:.ew Otto Braun's Social Democratic governmcnt.
constilu! ion (assisted by jurist� among whùm the name of Hugo Prcuss stands The state of exception in which Germany found itselfduring the Hindenburg
out) indnded 1.n artîde thargranied the president of the Reich extrcmely hroad presidencywas justi:fied hy Schmitt on a co11stit11tion,1l le-vd by the idea that the
ernergency i ecœz-io11,1liJ powers. The tcrt of Article 48 reads, ''rf security and president acted as the "guardian of the constitution" (Schmitt 1931); but the end
publk onler arc seflous!y [erhebliâ,] disturbed or threaten!!d in the German of the \Ale-imar Republic clea riy d<:mons:trates that, on the contrary, a "protected
Rekh, the pr<::siJent of the .Rcich ma.y take the measmcs neœssaryto reestablish democracy" is not a democracy at aB, and that the paradîgm of constitutional
security and pt1h1ic order, with the help of the armcd forces if required. 1b this dictatorship fonctions Ühteàd as a tt,.msitional phase that leads inevitably to the
end he may whoHy or _partially suspénd the fondamental rights [ Grundrechtej estabHshmcnt of a tota\itarian regime.
establi5hed in Articles 114, 115, 117, 118) u3, 124, and 153," The article added that Given these precedents, it 1$ understandablc thatthe constitution of the Fed­
a law would spedfy in detail the conditions and limitations under which this: eral Republic did not men.tion the stilte ot ex,:er,tw,n. Neverthcless, on Jlîne 24�
presidentiul powcr was to be exercîsed. Sinœ that Jawwas never passcd, the presM 1968, tbe "grand coalition" of Chrisfüm Democrats and Sodnl Dcmocrnts passed
16 Chaptcr One The State of F:xreption as a Paradigm of Gtwemment 17
à faw for the ami-"nd111ent of the con'ithiltion (Gesetz zur frgd11zungdes Grundge� Alhertine Sfatute (like the cmrent RepubJican Constitution) made no mention
setzes} that reintrodu,.:ed the state 1.1f exceplfon (defined as the "state ofintcrnal of the state ofexception. Neverthek:!ls, the governments of 1he kingdmn resùrtcd
necessity;' irmere Notswnd). However� wlth an unintende<l iro.ny, for the first to prodniminga state of sîege ma!1y times: in Pa!crmo and the Skilian provim·es
timc in the history of the institution, th.;, proclamation of the state of exception in 1862 and 1866, in Naple,; .in 1862, in Skily and LunigiMn in 1894, and in Naples
waS- prnvided for not slmply to safeguard public order and secmity, but to de­ and Mfüin io 1$9-8, where the repression of the disturbances wa:s p:articula.rly
fend the "lfüeral-dernocraiic constitution." By this point, protected democracy bloody and rrovoked bitter debates in parliament. The declaration of a state
had become the ruJe. on the occaRion of the carthqnakc of Mes:<lin:i and Reggio Calabria on
December 28, 1908 ls only apparently a different situation, Not only was the
01i August 31 1•;)I4, the Swiss fcderal Assernhly gnmte<l the Federal Co un-cil "the
statc of si-cgc 1,.1 ltimntcly prodaimed for reasons of publk order-that is, to sup··
unlimjte<l power to take al! measnres necessary to gu.a r;1ntee the securîty, ln�
press the robberics and looting prn-..:okC'd by thc disastcr-but from a theoretica]
tegrity, and neutràlity of Switzerland,"' This unusual act-by virtue of which a
5tandpoint, it is also sîgnificant that these ac.ts furnished the occasion that al­
non--warring state granted powers to the executive that were even vaster and
lowed S:-mti Rom;rno and other Italbn judsts to da.borate the thesis { whkh we
vaguer than those receivcd by the governments of countries directly involved in
examine in s-mnc det�dl bter) th.-1 t neœ�sity- ls the primary sourœ oflaw.
the war--is of interest because of the dehates it provokcd both in the assem­
In each of thcse cases, the state of siege was. prnd;iimed by a royT1l denee
bly itself-and in_îhe Swi.;;s Fedt:ral Court when the dtizens objected that the act
that, whfü, not requiring parliamentary rntification, was-ncYertheless ahvnys ap­
was unconstitutionaL The tenacity with whkh on this occasion the Swiss jurists
proycd by parliament, <'!S were other emergency decrees oot rl:'lated to the state
(nearly thirty years ahead of lhe theorists of ,;';(,nstitutional-dictatorsh!p) sought
ofsiegc (:n 1923 and 1924 sevcral thousand outst1indi11g faw-dccn:es fosued in the
(like Waldkirch and Burckhardt) to derive lhe legitimacy of the state of e:xœp�
prccedlng yenrs were t.hns converted into Law). ln 1926 the Fascist regime had a
tion from the. text of the constihJtion itself (specifically, Article 2, which read,
faw issued that e:xpressly regufated the matter of the law�decrees. Article 3 of
"the ain) of the Confoderation is to ensure the independenœ of the fatherland
this lnw cst:iblished that, upon deHberntion of the cmmdl of ministcrs1 1'norms
agaînst the foreigner [ and] to maintain interna! tranqulfüy and order"'), or {!ike
having forœ of iaw'' could be isst1ed by royal decree "(1) whcn the government
Hoern i 3nd Fldner) to grmmd the state of exception in a faiv- of necess.îty "inher­
ent in the very existi:nce of the State," or (like His) in a Juridkaî lacuna that the is delee'"°ted to <lo so by a lm-v w�thin the Jimits of the ddega tion, and (2) in e:x­
traon:Hnary situations, in whkh it is required for reasnns of urgent and absolok
exceptionaJ provisions mm,t fil 1, shov,m that the theory of the state of exception
is by no means -ihc cxdus.ive legacy of the antidernocratk tradition. The judgment conœrning nece:.sjty and urge1K-y is not subject to any
oversight other than parliamcnt's political oversight.'' The decrecs providcd for
In Italy the hîstory and fogal situation of the state of exception are of particular in the second dause hnd to be presented to parlîament for conversion into law;
interest with regard to legislatlon hy emcrgency execmive [gors:rnat-i 1·-i] decrees but parliament's tütal los5 of autonomy during the Fascist regime rendered this
(the so-called îaw-dccrees). Indeed, from thl'l vicwpnfot one <::0uld say th.at Italy condition superfluous.
functioned as a trne and prnper juridioo�polîtkal laborarory for organîzing the Although the Fascist governments" abuse of emergcncy decrces was so great
proœss ('whkh was aho -Occnrring to diffcdng dcgrces in otbcr European states) tllilt in 193-9 the regime itself feh -it nccessary to limil theït n:-arh, Artide 77 of
by which the h1.v,r- <lecrœ ''changed from a dcrngatory and exccptional instru­ the Repuhlican Constitution established vvith singular contimüty that '1 in ex­
ment fo-r nonnative production to an ordinary source for the production of traordfnary situations of necessity and emergency" the government wuld adop-t
law" (Fresa 1981, 156), But this also means that one of the esscntial paradigms "provisional measures baving forœ oflaw,"' ,,vhich had to be prr:sented the stlme
tbrough which democraqis transformed from par\iàmentaryto exeçntive [gov~ dey ro parliament and ,,.;hich wcnt out of effect if not conYcrted into law within
ernmnentale] was·clabornted precisE'ly by a state whose governments were often sixtr days oftheir issuance.
unstable. In ariy case, it is in this conte:xt that the emergency decrec's pertinence It is wdl known that since then the practice of executJve fgon•t114mmfnlr}
to the problcmatic sph;;:re of the statc of exception wmes dearly into vîew. The legislation by la:w-decrees has beoome the rule in It:ily, Not only have emergcncy
18 Chapt.cr One The State of Exception a:. a l"aradigm of Government 19

decrees been issued in moments of politkal crisis, thus circumventing the con� executive [governmneatali] apparatuse,� in England <1s welL [ndeed, immedîately
stitntional pdndple that the rights of the dtizens ca11 be limited only by law after tvar was dedared, the government asked pàrliàment to approve a series of
(seè,_ for example, the deçrces issued for the repressîon of lcrrorisrn: the law� ernergencr measures thnt had beeu prepared by the 1·e!ewmt ministers, and they
decree of March 28, 1978, 11. .59, converted into the law of May 21 l978, 11. 191 w1?rc passe.cl virtually without discu:>Sion. The most imponant of these acts was
[tbe so-called Moro LawL and the law-decree of December 15, 1979, 11, 625, con­ the Defon.ce of the RealmAct of August 4) 1914, known Js DORA, whid1 not only
,
verted into the law ofFebnwry 6, 1980, 11, 15), but law,,decrees now constitute granled the gnvernment quite vast powers 10 rcg11laœ the wartime cconomy) but
the nomial form of legisL1tion to such a that they have bcrn described also provided for scrious limitations on the fondamental rights of the citizcns
as "bills strengtbene<l by guarantecd t:mcrgency" (Fn:sa 1981, 152). Thîs me.ans Un particufar, granting military tribunal;; jarisdiction over dvilians). The ac tîv­
that the dernocratk principle of the separntion of powers has today collapsed ity of parliament saw a ûgnificant ec!ipse for the en tire duration of the war, just
and that the executive power has in fu.:t, at least partially, absorbed the legisl.a­ as in France. And in England too this process went bcyond the emergency of
tive power. ParHament is no longer the sovcrcign legislative body that holds the the war,_ as js shown by the approval•···-on October 29, 1920, in à time of stdkes
exclusive power to bind tl1e citîzcns by meaî1s of the law: it is limited to ratify­ and social tensions-of the Emergency Powers Act. Jndeed, Article 1 of the act
ing the decre<:s issued by the e:xecutive power. ln a technical sense, the Itafüm stated that
Republic is no longer parliamemary, hut exeo.ttivc' [govcrnamcnta1ej . And it is
significant t:hat though thi,; tramformatîon of the constitutional order (which is [i)f at any tllllc it ap pears to His Maj�sty that any action ha:,; been taken or is
today underway to l'"'t\ ,,c,;œ,c, in aU the Western democrades) is perfectly i,mmediately threatened by any persons or body of pcrsons of such a nature
well known to jnrists and politidans, it bas remained eutirely mmofü:ed hy the and on so extensive fi scale as to be cakulated, by interfering ,vith the supply
citize-ns. At the very moment whcn it would like lo give 1essons in democracy and distribntion of food, water, fuel, or Hght, or ,vith the me.ms of Joçomo­
to diffèrent traditions and cultures, the politicnl rnhure of the West does not tfon, to deprive !hc wmmunîty, or any substantial ;:mrtion of the commu­
teal ize lhat lt ha� enttl'el'f lost its canon, nily, of the essentials of life1 His Majesty may, by pr? damation (_hereinafter
referred to as a proclamation ofemerge;1cy}, decfare that a state ofemergency
Th e o:nly legal apparatus in Englami that is comparable to lhe French état de cxists,
siège goes. by the tertn martial lawi but 1.his concept is so vague that ît has bcen
rîghtly described as an "unlucky name for the justificallon by the rnmmon law Artidc 2 of the law gave His Majesty in Cu und] the powe'r to hsue regulations
of acts clone by necessity for the defcnce of the Commonwealth when the-te ant.1 to grant the exccutive the ""·"'"""' ,m <l dutfos , . , necessary for the preser­
is war within the realm" (Rossiter 19481 142). This) however, does not mean vation of the peace:' and it introduœd specialcourts ("courts of summary juris�
that something like a state of exception could not ex:ist. In the Mutiny .Acts; diction") for offendcrs. Even though the penalties imposed by these courls cou!d
tbe Crown's power to decfarc martial law was generally confined 1o times of not excecd th_re.c months in j.iil {''with orwithont hard labor*), the prindple of
war; nevertheless, it necessarily entailcd sometimes seri.ous conscqucnces for the state of excep1ion had bcen Hrmly introduced into English law.
ihe civilia.m who found thcmselves factua!Jy involved in the àrmed repression.
Thus SCTlmitt mµght to dislinguish martial law from the military tribunals and The p lacc-both logical and pragmJtic�--of a thcory of the statc of exception in
summaiy proccedîngs that at flrst applled only to soldîers, in order to conœive the Amcrican constitution is in the dia!ectic betwecn the powers of theprcsidcnr
of if as a purely foctual prn.:eeding and draw it closer to the state of exception: and those of Congrcss. This dialectic haidaken s.hape hiswricaîly (and in an
""Despitç the namc it bcars, martial law fa heithcr a right nor a Law in this si;�nse, exemplar y way already beginning with the Civil Wa.r) as a confüct over supreme
but rather a procceding guided eBscntially by the necessity t>fachleving a certain ,mthodty in an emcrgcncy situation; or, in Schrrüttiàn terms {and this is smdy
end" (Schmitt 1921, 172), significant in a country considen�d to he the cradte of democracy), as a confiict
\Vorld War One playtrl a dccisive mle in the generalizatîon of exceptlonal over sovercign dedsion.
20 Chapter One The State of Exception a,s a Paradigm of Government n

'fhe te:xtual basis of the confüct lies 6rst of ail in Artide 1 of the constitution, could do nothing but ratify the actions of the pre-sident, as it di<l on August 6,
whîch establishes that "[t]he Privilege of the Wrît of Habeas. Corpus shaH not 18fü. Strcngthened by this approval, on September 22, 1862, the pres.ident pro­
be ;,uspen<led, w1less when in Cases of RebelUon or hwàsion the publk S,:1fety daîmed th-c emancipation ofthe sîaves on Jlis authority alone and1 two days !.ner,
may require it'' but does not specîfy whkh authority has the jurisdiction to de­ generaHztd the state of exception th rm.1ghout the cntire terrHory of the United
cide on the suspension (even though prevailing opinion and the context of the States, authorizing th.i a.rre&t and trial before courts martial of "a11 Rebds and
passagè itselflead one to assume that the clause is directed at Congress and not Insurgents, their alders and abettors within the United States, and all pcrson�
the president). The second point of confücl lies jn the relatfon between another discouraging vohmteer enlistments, re�fating militia drafts, or guilty of any dis-,
passage of Artîcle 1 (whi.,:h dedarcs 1hat: the power to rleclare war and to raise loyal practice, affording aid and corn.fort to Rebels against the authorîty of the
and support the army and navy rests wilh C..:ongress) and Article 2, whkh states United States.'' By thls point, the president of ù1e United States was the holder
that " \ tJhe President shail be Con1m<1nder in Chief of the Army and Navy of the of the sovereign decision on the state of exception.
United States," According to Amerkan histùt'ians, during World \,Yar One President WoodM
Both of these problems reach their critical threshotd with the Civil War row\Vilson personally m:snmed even broaderpowers than those Abraham Lin­
(1861'71865.), Acting counter lo the text of Article 1, on April 15 1 1861, Lincoln de­ coln had daimed. Il is, however, neœssary to spedfy that instead of ignoring
creed thut an anny of sevcnty-five thousand men was to be rnised and eo,wened Congress, as Lincoln had done, Wilson preferre<l ea,;,h time to have the powers
a spcdal session of C01_1gress for July 4. In the- ten wecks that passed between in question delegated to him by Congress. In thfa regard, hls prnctice of gov­
April 15 and Jn!y 41 Jfocoln in fact acted as an abso!ute di<tator (for this reason, emment is doser to the one that would prevait in Europe in the same years, or
in his book Dictator�hip, Schmitt can rc-fcr to it as a perfect example nf com­ to the i:urrent one, which instead of dedaring the state of exception prefers to
mJssarial dictatorshlp: sec 1921; i36). On Aprll 27j wlth a tedmically evcn more have exccptional laws issued. ln any case) from 1917 to 1918, Congress npproved
sigt1ificant dccision, hc authodzed the General in Chief o( the Army to sus­ a scrïes of a<ts (fi:Üm the Espîonage Art of June 1917 to the Ovennan Act of May
pend the writ of habeas corpos whenever hc deemed it necessary along military 1918) that granted the presklent compkte co11trol over the admînistrntion of the
lin es between \-\fashington and Phlladclphia, wbere there had been disturbanœs. country and not only prohfüited dîsloyal activities (:mrh as collaboration with
Purthennore, the pn:sident's autmiorny in decidingon extnordinary measuœs the enemy and the diffusiùn of false reports), but even fnade h a crime to ''wifl­
continued even after Coogress was. co-nvened (thus� on Feb.rnary 14, 18621 Lin­ fully uUer, print, write, or puhlish any disloyal, profane, <;currilous� or abusive
coln impnsed œns0rship of the mail and auihorized the a:rrest and <letention in language about the form of govcrnment of the United States:;
mifüary prisons of persons suspected of "dîsloyal a.ad treasoùahle practkes"). Becanse the sovereign power of the president is essentfally grounded in the
In the .speech he deïivcred to Congress 1vhm it was finally convened on July emergency linked to a state of Wdf, over the course of the nventîeth cenrury the
4, the prcsident openly justified hl.$ actions as the ho!der of a snprcme power to metaphor of war bccomes an integral part of the prcsidcntîal politica1 voçabu­
lary whenever dedsJœ)s çonsidered to be ofvital importance are heing imposed,
vfolatc tbc rnm;titntîon in a situatkn1 ofnecessity, "Whether strictly legal or not;"
Thus, in 1933, Frankiin D. Roosevelt was able to assume exlraordinary power0
hcdedared, the mea.rnrcs he had adopted had becn taken "un<ler what appeared
to cope wilh the Great Deptession hy presenting his actions i.l:S those of a com­
to be a popular demand and· a public neœssity" in the ccrtainty that Congrcss
mander during a military campaigrt:
would ratify tbem. They wcre based on the conviction t:hat e1<en fundamental
law could be violated if the very existence of the union and the Juridical order
were at stake ("Are all the laws but one to go unc·xecutcd, and the Government 1 assume unhesitatingly the leadership of this great army of our people <ledi­
itself go to pieces lest that one be violated?" See Rossiter 1948, 229), cated to a disdplincd attack upon our common problems, . . . I am prepare-d
. It js obvious that in a \.vartimc situation the conflkt between the president un<ler my constitutional d-nty to recommcnd the measures that a stricken
and Congress is essentfally theoretkal Thé fact is that allhough Co-ngress was Nation in the midst of a sttkken world ma.y f<'/4lt1ire. . . . But in the event
pcrfectly aware that the constitutionaf jurisdictions had been transgressed, lt that the Congress shall fait to take �the ncœssary measuresj and in the event
n ChaptcrOne 'fhc Statc of Exccptlon as a Paradigm-of Gavernmcnt :z.3
that the national emergcncy is still critical, I shall not cvadc the cl.car course somethîng external, that is. an essemUaHy poUtical, or in any case e.x­
of duty that \Vill then confront me. I shall ask the Congress for the one re­ trajnridkal> _phenome11on. Among the formerJ some (such as Santi Ro­
maining instrument to meet the crisi�broad Executive pmver tu wage war mano; Hauriou, and MDrtati) tmderstand the statc of exception to be
against the cmergency, as great as the power that w · ould be givcn to me if we an integral part of positive law because the necessity that grounds lt acts
were in .fuçt invaded hy a foreign foc, (I�oosevdt 1938, 14--1 5) as an autonomous source of law, while othcrs (such as lioerni, Rancl­
letti, and Rossiter) conceive of it as the state's subjective {natural or
It is wdl not to forget that, from the comtitutional standpoint, the New Deal constitutional) rîght to its own preservation. Those in the latter group
was realized by <ldegating to the president (throngh a serles of statntes culmi­ (sucl1 as Biscaretti, Balladore-Pallieri, and Carré de Malberg) instead
nating in the National Recovery Att of June 16, 1933) an unlimited power io consider the state of ex<:eption and the necessity that gTounds ît to be
regulate and rnntrol cvery aspect of the cconomk Hfe of the country-a fact essentially eii- rajuridical, de facto elements i eve11 though they may have
that is in perfect ccmformfty wtth the already mentioncd parnlldism between consequcnces in the sphere of law. Julius Hatschek has summarized the
milîtary and emnomic emergcndes that charactedzes the poiitics of Ùle twen � various positions in the contras( between an objehive NotstandJtlteorie,
tieth ceutury. according to wlüch cvery act performed outside of or in confHct with
The outbreak ofWor!d Wa r Two extended these powers with the prodarna­ the Iaw in a state of ncœsshy is -contrary to law and, as sU.chi is lcgally
tion of a "limited" national emergem::y on Septexnber S, 1939, whkh became un­
chargeable; and a suhjektive Notstandstheorie, according to which emer­
limited on May 27, 1941., On Septembcr ï, 1942., while reqoe_stlng that Congrcss
gency ! eccezionari] powe-rs are grounded in 1'a -constltutional or pre-con­
rcp-ea! a law wncerning ewnomk matters, the president renewtd his cla.im to
s!itutional (natural) right" of the state (Hatschek 1923, 158ff.), regarding
sovereign powers <lming the emergency: "ln the event that the Congress should
which good faith is ennugh to guanmtee irnmunity.
fail to act, and act adequateîy, I shall acœpt lhe responsihfüty. and I will act• . . .
The simple topographkai opposition (inside/outside) implidt in
The Ameriçan people can . , , be sure that I shall not hcsHate to use every power
thi?se theories, seems lnsuffident to account for thé phenomenon that
Vested in me to aœomplish the defeat of our encmies in any part of tl1e world.
wherc our own safoty demari,<ls such defeaf' (Rossîter 1948, 268-69), The most it should e:xplaln. If the sta te of exce:ptiorls characteristic property is a
spcclacular vîofaüon of dvil rights (all the more sc-rïow, became of its soldy ( tntar or partial) su."ipensfon of the juridkal order; how can such a sus­
racüll motivation) occurred on 1:ebruary ig., 1942, with the internment of .";ev­ pension still be contained within it? How can an anomie be insaihed
enty thousand American citizens of Japanese descent who re-sided on the ½'est within rhe juridical order? And if the state of exception is in.ste"d only
Coast (along wîth fortythousand Japanese citizens wlu) Hved and worked there). a de facto situation, and is as such unrelated or contrary to Jaw, how is
President Bush's decisîon to refor to himself co11stantly as ùte ·«comman­ it possible for the order to contain a lacuna precisely where the decisive
der in Chief of the Army" after Septernber u > 2001, must be considered in the sltuatfon is concerned? And what is the meaning ofthis lacuna?
context of this prcskle11tial daim to sovereign powers in emergency situations. In truth 1 the state of exception is neither external nor înternal to
If, as we have seen, the assumptioo ,of this titlc cntaîls a direct refercnce to the
state of exception, then fü1sh is attcmpting to produce a situation in which the
[ the juridicai order, and the problem of defin -ing it concerns precisely
a thrcshold, or a zone of in<lifforencc, where lnside and outside do .not
emcrgency becomes the n.,1le 1 and the very distinction betwcen peace and war exclu<le each othcr but rathcr hlur with each other. The su,5p-ension of
(and between foxdgn and civil war) be.cornes impossible. the norm does not mean its abolirion; and the zone of anomie that ît
e-stabllshes iB not ( or at least daims not to be) unre)ated to the juridkal
1.8 The dilferences in the legal traditions correspon,I in scholarship order. Bence the interest of those theories that, lîke Scbmitt's, compli­
to the division betwcen those who seek to indude the state of excep­ cate the topographîcal opposi1ion into a more complcx topologkal re­
tion within the sphc-re of the juridical order and those who consider it lation, in which the very limit of the juridical order is ·,:tt issue. ln any
24 Chapter One The St;>tc of Exo:1:,tlon as a Paradigm of Govcrnment :l5

case, to understand the problem ofthe statc of exception, one must first and comments on this principle preciseiy in relation to the sovereigds
correctiy determine its localization ( or îllocalization), As we will see, tl1e power to grant dispensations from: the law (Primn secw1dae, q. 96, art.
conflkt ovcr the state of exœptjon presents itself essentîally as a dispute 6: utnu-n ei q ui subditur legt, liceM praeter verbti li:gîs ageri; (whether one
over its proper locus. who is subjcct to Jaw may ac! against the letter of the law] ):

1.9 A recurrent opinion posits the concept of necessity as the founda­ lf observing the letter ofthe law d0cs H()t ent,dl a1: immcdiate danger
tion of the state of exception. According to a tcnadously repeated Latin that must be dealt with at once, h is not in the power of any man to
adage (a history of the adagia's strategic fonction in legal literature has interpret what is of nse or of harm to the city; this rnn be doue only
yet to be writtèn), t1ecessitas legem non habet., ''neœssity has no lawi"' by the sovereign who, in a case of this sort) has the a_uthority lo grant
whkh is inte:rprete:d in two opposingways: "necessity does i10t recognize dispcnsations from the law. If there is, hmvever, a sudden danger, re­
any law» and ''neœssity c,reates its own faw" { néce&;ité fait loi). In both garding ·which there is no timc for recourse to a higher authority1
cases, the theory ofthe state of exception is whol!y redoœd to the theory the very necessity cardes a dispensation with it, for necessity is not
of the staHJs necessitatis, so that a ju<lgment conœrning the existence of suhject to the law f ipsa ncccssitas dispe11satfoncm habet mmexam, quia
the latter resolves the question conœrning thé legitimacy of the former. necessitas non subditur legiJ .
Therefore, any discussion of the structure and meaning of the state of Here, the theory ofnecessity is none other than a theory of the excep­
exception first requfres an analysis of the qmœpt of necessity. tion (dispensatio) by virlt1e of whkh a partkular case is released from
The principle according to whkh nect•ssitas !egt:m non habet was for­ the ohlîgation to observe the iaw, ::-Jecessity is not a source of law, nor
mnlated in Gratîan's Decretum, It appears therc Lwo times: first in the does it properly su<:pend the iaw; it merély release.,; a particular case from
gloss and then in the text The gloss (whkh refors to a passage in whkh the Hteral application of the norrn: "He who acts beyond the letter of the
Gratian limits himself to stating generically that "many tlùngs are done law ln a case of necessitydocs not judge by tll.e law itselfbut judges by the
against the rule out of necessity or for whatever other cause" [pars I. particular case, ln which he sees that the letter of the law ls not to be ob­
dist. 48] ) appears to attribute to necessity the power to render the illidt served [ non iudicat rie ipsa lege, sed fudicat de casu singulari, in_ qùo videt
licit (Si propter necessitarem aliquid fit, illud licite fit: quia quod non est verl>a legis ab5er-vamla non esse]." The ultimate f:-,round of the exception
licit11m in lege1 necessitas fodt licitum. ltem necessilas legem non habet [1f here is not necessity but the prindp]e accor<ling to whkh ''every law is
something is done out of necessîty) it is clone lidtly, sinœ what îs not ordaîned for the c.on1mon well-being of men, and only for this does it
licit in law necessity makes licit. Llkewise neœssity has no lawl ) . But the have the force and rcason of law [vim et rationem legisl; if it fails in this
regard, it has no rapadty to bind l Firtutem (}hligmuli non habet J ." Tn the

j
sense in which this should be takcn is made clearer by a later passage in
Gratiau's text concerning the celebration of the mass (pars III. dist. 1. c. case of necessity, the vis obligandi of the law fa.ils ) because in this case
11).After lrnving stated that the sacrifice must be offered on the altar or in the goa1 of _s111us hominum is lacklng. \'\lhat is <'lt issue herc is dearly not
a consecrated place 1 Gratfan adds 1 ult is pœforable not to sîng or listen to a status or sîtuation of the juridical order as such (the state of exception
the mass than to celebrate it in places where it sh-ould not be ce1ebrated, or necessity); rather1 in ead1 instance it is a question of a p:articular case
unless it happens becat,tse of a supreme necessity, for neœssity has no in which the vis and ratio of the law find no application.
laW (nisi pro summa necessitate contingat, quoniam neccssitas legem non
habet ). More than rendering the il!idt !kit, necessity acts here to justify � We find an example of the law's ceasing to app-ly ex âispet1Satione misercor­
a single, spedfic case of transgression by means of an exœption. diae [ out of a dispcnsation of mercy] in a peculiar passage from Giatian where
This is dear in Lhe way Thomas în the Swnma theologita develops the canonlst states that the Church can dect not to puni:;b a transgrc-ss.ion in
The State ofExccption as a Pa-radig1_n ofGovernment 27
a situation wherc the transgressive deed has aJrcady oc.::urred (pro everU-u rei It is interesting to analyze from this perspective the ext.reme position
[for the comequencf' of the thing] : for èxampfe in a ca&e wherc a person who of Santi Romano, a jurîst who had a considerahle influence on European
muid not accede to the epi�cnpate ha<i in fuct already been ordained -as bishop) . legal thought between the•wars. For Romano, not only is nccessity not
Paradoxkally, the law is not applied here precisely because the trnnsgressive act unrelated to the juridical order, but it ls the first ,:md origînary source' of
has effectiwly akeady heen committcd and punishing it would anyw;i_y entail law, He begins by distinguishing belween, on the one band� those who
negative consequençes for the Church. In analyzîng lhis text) Anton Schütz has see necessjty as a juridical fact or cven a-subjective right of the .state>
rightly observcd that ''in conditioning validity by factidty, in seeking conta(,i which is nltimately gfonnded as su.ch in the legislation in forœ and in
with an extrnjuridkol reality, [Gratianl prcvcnts the law from referring only to the general prindples of Iaw, and, on the other hand, those who think
the law, and thus prevents the dosure of the ,iurldi<:al (Schütz 1995, 120).
ncœssity is a mcre fact and that thcrefore the emergency [ etrczionoli]
In tl1is sensc, the medicvaf cxcepüon rcptcS:cnts an opcujng of the juridical
powers founded upon it have no basis in the legislativc system. Acco rd­
system to an ex:ternal fact, a sort of ftctio Jegis by whkh., in this case, one acts
ing tD Romano, hoth positionsi whkh agreç in their idcntifinition of the
At if the bishop had bccn legitimately eledcd. The modem sfate of exception is
juddical order [ il diritto] with the law lla legge]," are incorrect, in.,.:;ofar
instcad an attempt to indude the exception itself v.'1thin the juridkal order by
as they disavow the existence of a true and proper source of law beyond
creatîng a Z?nc of indistinction !n whid1 fact and \aw œindde.
legislation.
� \Ve find an implidt cdtique of the -�tate 0f ex1:eption in Dante\ De monnrrhia.
The neceS-sîtywith which -vve are concerned here must be Lonceîved of
Seeking to prove that Rome gained domfoion over the world not through vio­ as a state of affairs that, at 1east as a rule and in a complete and prac­
lence but iurc, Dante States that it is impossible to obtàin the end oflaw (that îs,
tkally effective way, cannol be regufated by prevîously estahlished
the common good) without lai.-v, and that therefore "whoever fn ten<ls to a<:hicve
norms. Rut if ît has no iaw1 it makes law, as another cornrnon expres­
the end of law} must proceed with htw [q11imnq,1e finem foris fotcrulit mm titre
sion has ît; which means tl1at it itself constltutes a true and proper
graditur]" Tlle ldea that a suspension of làw may be neœssary for the
source of!aw. . , . Jt can be s.1id that 11cccssity is the first ,md originary
cornmo11 good is foreign to ihe medieva[ wodJ.
source of all law, su.ch that by cornparison the others are to be con­
1.10 It is only with the moderns that the sfate of ncœssity tends to be sidered somehow derivatlve . . . . An d it i� to necessity that the origin
induded within the juridical order an<l to appear as a true and proper and legitimation of the legal institntlon par excellence, namely, the
""s tate" of the law, The principle accordtng to which neeessity de:fines a statE\ and îts constitutional order ln general, must be traœd back)
unique situation in which the law loses its vis obligandi (this is the sense when it is cstablished as a de fac to process) for example, ùn the 'A'f!Y
of the adage neœssitas h:gem non Jiabct ) L'> reversed 1 becoming the prin­ to revo]ution. Aud what occurs ln the in itial moment of a partkular
ciple according to which necessity constîtutes, so ta speak, the ultimate regime c.an also repeat itselt: though in an 1,;xceptional way and wüh
ground and very so urce of the law. This is true not. only for those writ­
ers who sought in this vvay to justify the national intercsts of one state * The nm term� here are diriltr, and lrgg,>, l:,;)th t>fwhkh nn: 1F1u!Jy trnnsldcd :in English
against another ( as in 1he forniula 1Vot kennt kî!ln Gcbot [neœssity knmvs as "lmv." VVh:lle these terms have dme t:Dnèfp;,nden,:es i=l French (dmir, loi), Spanîsh
no law] 1 used by the Prussian Chanœilor Bethmann-Hollweg and taken (d,tredw, iey), a:,d Genmm {Rerht, Gesetz}, ,;orne oft!wîr �e;:;�"' fa inevitably lost in tht'
up again in Josef Kohler's book of that titlc [1915]), hut also for those 1''"�;;g:t to EogHsh. Am,-:ing i:b::ir mon]ng.s, :Jirifi:; ç;s1Tir� �h,: s0ns� ofbw in the abstrart,
or the tnti:•e sphere ofhiw, while /cgg,; rctf'n to the �ped.fic body ofrnles that il conmmnîty
jurist.�1 from Jellinek lo Duguit1 who see necessity as the foundation of {lr ,tate con::idf'n: bindin;;, H1:re and b a fr;w (lthcr r.:ises where this distinction i� critical, 1
the validity of decrees havîng force of!aw issued by the executivc in the h;ive, follnwing the :rnthor's suggr�tinn, rrndercd diri1to as "thc- juridkal order"' and !eggc
state of exception, as "the faw.''- Trans.
28 Chapter One The State of Exception as a Para digm of Govcrnment 29

more attenuated cbaracteristics, even after the regime bas formed be classified in the category of originary juridical orders, in the now
and regulated its fondamental institu tions. (Romano 1909, 362) well-known sense given to this expression. In this sense, and within
the limits of the sphere wc have indicated, we can thus speak of a
As a figure of necessity, the state of exception therefore appears law of revolution. An examim1tion of how the rnost important rev­
(alongside revolution and the de facto establishment of a constitutional olutions, including the rnost recent ones, have unfolded would be
system) as an "illegal" but pèrfectly "juridical and consti tutional" mea­ of great interest for demonstrating the thesis that.we have advanced,
sure that is realized in the production of new norms ( or of a new juridi­ which could at first sight seem paradoxical: revolution is violence,
cal order): but it is juridically organized violence. (Romano 1983, 224)
The formula . . . according to which, in Italian law, the state of siege
Thus, in the forms of both the state of exception and revolution, the
is a measure füat is contrary to the law (let us even say illegr1l) but is
status necessitatis appe<1rs as <1n ambiguous and uncertain zone in wbich
at the same time in conformity with the unwritten positive law, and
de facto proceedings, which are in thernselves extra- or antijuri dical,
is for this reason juridical and constîtutional, seems to be the most
pass over into law, and juridical norms blur with mere fact---that is,
accurate and fitting formuh i. From both the logical and the bistorical
a threshold where fact and law seem to become undecidable. If it has
points of view, necessity's ability to overrule the law derives from its
been effectively said that in the state of exception fact is converted into
very nature and its originary character. Certainly1 the law bas by now
law ("Emergcncy is a state of fact; howcver, as the brocard fittingly says,
become the highest and most general manifestation of the juridical
e facto oritur ius [law arises from fact]" [Arangio-Ruiz 1913, 528 1 ) , the
norm, but it is an exaggeration to want to extend its dominion be­
opposite is also true, that is, that an inverse movement also acts in the
yond its own field. There are norms that cannot or should not be
state of exception, by which law is suspended and obliterated in facL
written; there are others that cannot be determined except when the
The essential point, in any case, is that a threshold of undeddability is
circumstance? arise for which they must serve. (Romano 1909, 364)
produced at which factum and ius fade into each other.
The gesture of Antigone 1 which opposed the written law to the Hence the aporias that every attempt to define necessity is unable to
agrapta nomima [unwritten laws] is here reversed and asserted in de­ resolve. If a measure taken out of neccssity is already a juridirnl norm
fense of the constituted order. But in 1944, by which time a civil war was and not simply fact, why must it be ratified and approved by a law, as
un der way in his country, the elderly j urist (who had already studied the Santi Romano (along with the majority of writers) believes it must? If it
de facto establishment of constitutional orders) returned to consider the is already law, why does it not last if it is not approved by the legislative
question of necessity, this time in relation to revolution. Although rev­ bodies? And if instead it is not law, but simply fact, why do the legal
olution is certainly a state of fa-et that "cannot be regulated in its course effects of its ratification begin not from the moment it is converted into
by those state powers that it tends to subvert and destroy" and in this law, but ,x tune [ from then] ? (Duguit rightly notes that this retroactivity
sense is by definition "antijuridical, even when it is just'' (Romano 1983, is a fiction and that ratification can produce its effects only from the
222), it can, however, appear this way only moment at which it occurs [Duguit 1930, 754] .)
But the extreme aporia against whicb the entire theory of the state
with respect to the positive law of the state against which it is di­ of necessity ultimately runs aground concerns the very nature of neces­
rected, but that does not mean that, from the very different point of sity, wbich writcrs continue more or less unconsciously to think of as an
view from which it defines itself, it is not a movement ordered and ohjective situation. This naive conception---wh ich presupposes a pure
regulated by its own law. This also means that it is an order that must factuality that the conception itself has called into question-is easily
30 Chapter One The State of Exception as a Paralligm ofGovernment 31

critiqued by those jurists who show that, far from occurring as an ob­ of exception as precisely the moment in which state and law reveal their irre-­
jective given, necessity clearly cntails a subjective judgment, and that ducible difference (in the state of exception "the state continues to exist, while
obv�ously the only circumstances that are necessary and objective are law recedes" [Schmitt 1922, 13/12]), and thus be can ground the extreme figure
those that are declared to be so. of the state of exception-sovereign dictatorship-in the pouvoir constituant,

The concept of necessity is ah entirely subjective one, relative to the 1.11 According to some writers, in the state of necessity "the judge elab­
aim that one wants to achieve. It may be said that necessity dictates orates a positive law of crisis, just as, in normal times, he fills in juridical
the issuance of a given norm, because otherwise the existing jnridi­ lacunae" (Mathiot 1956, 424). ln this way the problem of the state of
cal order is threatened with rnin; but there must be agreement on exception is put into relation with a particularly interesting problem in
the point that the existing order must be preserved. A revolution­ legal theory, that of lacunae in the juridical order [ il diritto] . At least as
ary uprising may proclaim the necessity of a new norm that annuls early as Article 4 of the Napoleonic Code ("The judge who refuses to
the existing institutions that are contrary to the new exigencies; but judge, on the prctence of silence, obscurity or insufficiency of the law,
there must be agreement in the belief t:hat the existing order must can be prosecuted on the charge of denial of justice"), in the majority
be disruptcd in observance of new exigencics. In both cases . . . the of modern legal systems the judge is obligated to pronounce judgrnent
recourse to necessity entails a moral or political (or, in any case, ex­ even in the presence of a lacuna in the law [ la legge] . In analogy with
trajuridical) evaluation, by which the j�ridical order is judged and is the princip1e according to which the law [ la legge] may have lacunae,
held to be worthy of preservation or strengthening even at the price but the juridical order [ il diritto] admits none, the state of necessity is
of its possible violation. For this reason, the principle of necessity thus interpreted as a lacuna in public law, which the executive power is
is, in every case, always a revolutionary principle. (Balladore-Pallîeri obligated to rernedy. In this way, a principle that concerns the judiciary
1970, 168) power is extended to the executive power.
But in what does the lacuna in question actually consist? 1s there truly
The attempt to resolve the State of exception into the state Of neces­ something like a lacuna in the strict sense? Here, the lacuna does not
sity thus runs up against as many and even more serious aporias of the concern a cleficiency in the text of the legislation that must be cornpleted
phenomenon that it should have explained. Not only does necessity ul­ by the judge; it concerns, rather, a suspension of the order that is in force
timately corne clown to a decision 1 but that on which it decides is, in in order to guarantee its existence. Far from being a response to a nor­
truth, something undecidable in fact: and law. mative lacuna, the state of exceptîon appears as the opening of a ficti­
tious lacun a in the order for the purpose of safeguarding the existence
�t Schmitt (who r�fers several times to Santi Romano in his writings) probably
of the norrn and its' applicability to the normal· situation. The lacuna
knew of Romano's attempt to ground the state of exception in necessity as the
is not within the law [ la legge] , but concerns its relation to reality, the
originary source of law. His theory of sovereignty as the decision on the excep­
very possibility of its application. Tt is as if the juridical order [ il diritto]
tion grants the Notstand a properly fondamental rank, one that is certainly com­
contained an essential fracture between the position of the norm and its
parable to the rank given it by Romano, who made it the originary figure of the
juridical order. Furthermore, he shares with Romano the idea that the juridical application, wh ich, in extr!me situations, can be filled only by means of
order [il diritto] is not exhausted in the law [ la legge] (it is not by chance that be the state of exception, that is, by creating a zone in which application is
cites Romano precisely in the context ofhis critique of the liberal Reclit,çstaat); suspended, but the law [ la legge], as such, remains in force.
but while the Halian jurist wholly equates the state with law, and therefore denies
all juridical relevance of the concept of constituent power, Schmitt sees the state
2 l\ Force-of-J;aw_: from any ronsîderation of law" (Schmitt 1921, and that indeed "ln
its factual substance, that is, in Jts core t it cannot take a jmidkal fom1"•
(175) . Nevertheless, it _îs essential for Schmitt that in every case some
relation to the juri<lical ordcr be ensured: "Both ç,0m mîssarial dictator­
ship nnd soveœign dictatorship eu tail a relation to a juridîcal context"
( 139); ''Because the state of exception is always something different from
2.1 111e most rigorous attempt to construct a theory of the state of anarchy and chaos, in a juridical sense, an order stlll exîsts in it> even if
exception was made by Carl Schmitt, essentiaHy in the books Dicta­ it is not a juridical ordee' (Schmitt 1922, 13/12).
torship and, one year later, Political Theology Because these hvo books TI1e specific contribution of Schmitt's theory is precisely to have
from the beginning of the 1920s describc-with a, so to speak, inter~ made such an artkulatîon between state of exception and juridical or­
ested prophesy-a paradigm (a ''form of govemment" [Schmitt 1921, der possible. It is a pa.radoxical artkulationi for what must be inscribed
151]) that has not only remained current but has today reached its full within the lm.v is something that is essentîally exterior to it, that is,
development, it is necessary at this point to pr-esent the fundamental nothtng less than the suspensîon of the jurîdkal otder itself (hence the
theses of Schmitt's theory of the state of exception, aporetïcal formulation: "ln a jurldical sense, an order stilJ exists, . . .
First a frw remark'i conœming terrninology. In the book from 1921 even if it is not a ,iurîdka1 order").
the slate of exception is prescnted through the figure of dictatorship. In Dictatorship, the operator of this imcription of an outside Q[ the
Dictatorship, however, whkh t:'ntompasses the state of siege, is essen­ law wlthin the law is, in the case of commissarial dîctatorship, the dis­
tially a «state of exception,1' and insofat as it presents itself as a "sus­ tinction between norms of law and norms of the rea1ization of law
pension of law," it comes down to ù1e pmblem of Jefining a "\:oncrcte (Rechtsvcrwirklichung) and) in the case of sovereign dictatorship_, the
exception, . . . a probiem that up to now has not been held in due con­ distinction bctween constituent power and constituted power. Indeed,
sideration by the general theory of lav/' (Schmitt 19211 xvii). Havlng because it "suspends the constitution irt concreto in order to protect its
tlms inscribed the st;:1te of exception within the c-0ntex.t of dktatorship> concrete e...xistenœ" (Schmitt t921, 136) ) commissariat dictatorship ulti­
Schmitt then' distinguishes between ''commîssarfal dictatorshipt which mately has the fonction ofcreating a state of affairs "in which the faw can
has the aim of defending or restoring the existing constitution, and be realized" (137), ln commissariat dictatorship1 the constitution can be
"sovereîgn dktatorship,i' in which> as a figure of the exception, dictator­ suspended in its application "v11itbout thereby ceasingto rcmaJn in force,
ship reaches its, so to speak1 critica1 mass or rnelting point. The terms be,c,_mse the srn;pension signifies solely a c-oncrete excepti{m" (137). On
dictatorship and statc of siege can thus dîsappcar in Politiwl Theology1 a theoreticaJ level, commissarial dictatorship am drus be wholly sub­
with the state of exception (Ausnalimezustnnd) taking their place, while sunwd in the distinctîon between the norm and the techno-practkal
the empha.sis shifts, at le--ast apparently, from a definition of the excep­ rules that govern its realization.
tion to a definîtion of sovcrefgnty. The strategy of Schmitt's lheory is The situation is diffotcnt in sovereign dictator5lüp, whkh is not lim­
therefore a two-stage strategy, whose articulations and aims we wîU have ited to suspending an exfating constitution ''on the basis of a dght that is
to understand dearfy, provided for th-erein and is therefore itselfconstitutional" (Schmitt 1921,
ln both books, the telos of the thcory is the inscription of the state of Ratheri ît aims at creatîng a state of affairs in which it becomes pos­
exception within a juridical context. Schmitt knows perfectly wcll that sible to impose a new constitution, In this case j the nperator that allows
because ît brings about a '<suspension of the entire existing jurldical or­ the state of exception to be anchored to the jurid.ical order is the dis4
der" (Schmitt 1922, 13/12_) , the state of exception scems to ''sub tract itsdf tînction bchveen conslituent power and c<.mstituted power, Consf-itucnt
34 Chapter Two Force-of-� 35
power îs not, however, "a simple question of force"; it is, rather) "a power At this point we can understand why the theory of the state of ex­
that, though it is not constituted in virtue of a constitution, is neverthe­ ception can be presented in Politirn! Thcolngy as a theory of sovereignty.
less connected to every existing constitution in such a waythat it appears The sovereign 1 who can decide on the state of exception, guarantees its
as the fmmding power, . . . and for this reason it cannot be negated even anchorage to the juridical order. But precisely because the dedsion here
if the exîsting constitution might negate it" (137), Though it js juridîcally concerns the vcry annulment of th e norm , that is, because the state ot
formless (forrnlos)) it represents a ''minimum of constitution" (145) in­ exception represents the inclusion and capture of a space that is neither
scribed within every politically decîsive action and is therefore capable outside nor inside (the space that corresponds to the annulled and sus­
of ensuring the relation between the state of exception and the juridical pcnded norm) 1 "the sovereign st.mds ou tside [steht r111ficrhalh] of the
order even in the case of sovereign dictatorship. normally valid juridical ordet\ and yet belongs [gehOrt] to it, for it is
This clarifies why in the preface Schmitt can present the "esscn­ he who is responsible for deciding whether the constitution can be sus­
tial distinction between comrnissarial dictatorShip and sovereign dic­ pended in toto" (10/7) .
tatorship" as the "chief outcome of the book," which makes the con­ lking-outsirfe, and yet bclongi11g: this is the topological structure of
cept of dictatorship "finally accessible to jurisprudential consideration" the state of exception, and only because the sovcreign, who decidcs on
(S_chmitt 1921) xviii). Indeed, what Schmitt had before bis eyes was a the exception, is, in trnth, logically defined in his being by the exception,
"c.onfosion" and "combinatîon" between the two dictatorships that he can he too be defined by the oxymoron ffstasy-bclonging.
never tired of denouncing (203 ) . Yet neither the Leninist theory and
practice of the dicta torship of the proletariat nor the gradual exacerba­ N The relatîonship between Dictatorship and Pofitirnf Thc()/ogy must be seen
tion of the use of the state of exception in the Weimar Republic was a in the light of this complex strntegy of inscribing the state of exception ·within
figure of the old cornmissarial dîctatorship; they were, rather, somethîng the law. Jurists and political philosophers have gencrnll )' directed lheir Mtention
new and more extreme, which threatened to put into question the very chiefly to the theory of sovereignty contained in the hook from 1922, without
consistency of the juridico-political order) ,md whose relation to the law realizing that this thcory acqt1ires its sen se solely on the basis of the t:heory of the
is exactly what Schmitt sought to preserve at all costs. state of exception already elaborated in Dictatorship. The rank rmd the paradox
In Political Theology) on the other hand, the operator of the inscrip­ of Schmitt's concept of sovcrcignty derive, as we have seen, from the state of
tion of the state of exception within the juridical order is the distinc­ exception, and not vice versa. And it is certainly not by chance that Schmitt had,
in the 1921. book and in previous articles, first laid out the theory and praxis
tion (which had already bcen proposed in the 1912 book Gesetz und
of the state of exception, and only later laid out his theory of sovcreignty in
Urteil) between two fundamental elements of law: norm (Norm) and
Politiml Tlicology. Therc îs no doubt that his theory of sovereignty rcpresents an
decision (Entscheidung, Dezision) . In suspending the norm, the state of
atternpt to anchorthe stote of exception unequivocallyto the juridical order, but
exception "reveals [ ojfenbart ], in absolute pnrity, a specîfically juridical
the attempt would not have been possible if the state of exception hc1d not first
forma] element: the decision" (Schmitt 1 922, 13/13). The two elements,
been articulated within the tenns and concepts ofdictatorship c1nd, so to speak,
norm and decîsion 1 thus show their autonomy. "Just as in the normal "juridicized" tl;rough reference to the Roman magistrncy and thcn through the
situation the autonomous moment of decision is reduced to a mini­ distinction between norms of law and norms of realîzation.
mum, so in the exception al situation the norm is annulled [ vernichtet] .
And yet even the exceptional situation rcmains accessible to juridical 2.2 Schmitù theory of the state of exception proceeds by establishing
knowledge, because both elements, the norm as well as the decision, 1vithin the body of the law a series of caesurae and divisions whose ends
remain with in the frarnework of the juridical [im Rahmc11 des .furistis­ do not quite meet, but which, by means of their articulation and oppo­
chen] " (13/12-13 ) . sition, allow the machine oflaw to fonction.
36 Chnpter 'I\ro

1àke on the one hand the opposition between norms of law and Jt çan generally be said that not only language and law but all social institu�
nonns of lhe realization oflaw, between the norm and its concretc ap� tic.ms have been forme<l through a proœss of desemanticization and suspen­
plkation. Commissariat dictatorship shows that the- moment of appli.ca­ sion of concrete praxis in its immediate reference to the rcal. Jusl as gram"
tion is :: rntonomous with respect to the norm as suth; and that the norm mat, in prodt1cing a speech without denotationi has isolated something like
"can be suspended, without thereby ceasing to remain in force'., (Schmitt a language from discourse, and law, in suspcnding the concrete custom and
1921, 137), Tho.t is) commis.s a.rial dictatorship represents a state of the law usage of individua!s, has been ab]c to isolate something like a norm, so tl}€
in which the law is not appiied, but remains in force, Jnstead) soverdgn patient work of civiliu.tion procecds in every domain hy separating human
dktatorship (in which the old constitu tion ho longer ex:ists and the new praxis from its concrch:' exerdse and therebycreating that ex,;:ess of sîgnifkation
one is present in the "minimal" form of con5tîtueflt power) represtmts a over denotation that Lévi-Strauss was the first to recognil.e, ln thls sen:;e, the
state of the law in which the law is applied, but is not formally in force. f!oating signifier••·-this guidin.g concept in the hnman sdences of th<: tv10ntieth
Take now the opposition betvveen riorm and dedsion. Schmitt shows centur yc---corr�:,pond:s to tbe state of exception, in tvhich the norm is in force
that they are lrreducible) in the sense that the decision can never be deM withont beiug ap1Jlied.
rived from the content of a norm without a remainder (restlos) (Schmitt
1922, 9/6). In the decision on the state of exception, the norm is sus­ 2.3 · In 1989, at the Cardozo School oîLaw in New York, Jacques Derrida
pcn<led or even annulled; but what is at issue in this suspens.ion is> onœ gave a lecture titled "Force de loi: le 'fondement mystique de l'au torité: "
again , the creation of a situation that makes the applica tion of the norm The lectu re, whkh in tn1th was a reading of Benjamin's essay "Critique
possible (''a situation in which juridica! norms can b-e valid [gelten J must of Violence:' gave rise to a wide debate among philosophers as well as
be bronght about" (1.3/13), That is, the state of exception scparates the jurisrs, but the fuel that that no one attempted to ana!yze the seeming!y
norm from its application in nrder to make its application possibie. It enigma tic formula that gave the text its 1îtle is an indica tion not only of
introduœs û zone of anonüe into the law in order to make the effedive the complete separation henveen philosophkal and leg-,;l cultures, but
regulation [ normazione; of the real possible, also of the 1atter's dedine,
We e;rn ) then, deiine the state of exception in Sdunitt1s theory as the Behind the syntagma fone of Llw stands a long tradition in Roman
place where the opposition bcttveen the norm and its reaHzalion reacbes and medieval law, where (:at least beginning ,vith Justinian's Digests, De
its greatcst intensity. It i5 a field of juridical tensions in whkh a mini~ legibus, 1.ï; legis virtus haec est: imperare, vctare; permittere, punire [The
nmm of formal beîng-in-force [vigenza] coinddes with a maximum of capacity of law is rhis: to command, to forbid, to allow, to punish ] ) it
real appHrntion) and vice_ versa. But even in this extreme znne---and, has the generic sense of effica cy, the capacity to bind . But only in the
indeed, predsely byvirtue ofit--the two elements of the law show their modern epoch, in the context of the French Revolution, does it begin
intimatt} cohesion. to indicate the supreme value of those state acts <leclared by the repre­
sentativc assemblies of the people. Thus, in Article 6 of the constitutio,1
� The structurai analogy between !anguage and law is inuminating here. Just of 1791, force de loi designates the untouchahiHty of the law, whkh even
as lingnistk dements subsist in langue wîthout any ,cal denotation, which thcy the sovereign himself can neither abrogate nor modify. In this reganl,
acquire only in actunl diso::mrse1 so in the ;,1:ate of exception the norm is in forœ modern doctrine distinguishes bet\-veen the efficacy of the law-which
without any refen:nce to reaiily, But just as concrete !inguîstic activity becomes rests absolutely with every vaJid legislative act and consists in th,• pro�
tnteUigibJe pn:dsely through the presupposition of somcthing like a languago;'\ duction of legal effects-and the force oflaw, which is instead a relative
so fa the norm ahle tu n:fer to the normal situation through the suspcnsïon of concept that expresses the position of the law or of acts comparable to it
its npplication in the state of exception. with respeét to other acts of the juridîcal order that are endm,ved with a
38 Chapter Two

forœ superior to the law (as in the case of the constitutïon) or inferior to organîzatîo-n (which acts as a sovereign dictatorship), The state of ex­
it (such as the decrees and regulations issued by the executive) ( Quadri ception is an anomie space in which what is at stake is a force of law
1979, 10 ). without hnv (whkh should therefor<: be written: force-of-Jaw.:.). Such a
The decisive point, however, is that in both modern and andent doc­ "forœ-of'...]trvft in \vh kh pole!1Jiality and act are rndirn lly sepa rated, is
trîne the syntagmaforce oflaw refus in the technical scnse not to the Iaw certninly something like a mystical element, or rather a fictio byrneans of
but to those deC:rees {which, as we indeed say, have the force oflaw) that which faw sccks to anncx i'!nom ie itself, But hfYW is it possihîe to conceive
"'
the executive power can be authorized to issue in some situations, par­ ofsuch a ''mysilcal demcnt and the way it acts in the state of exception?
ticularly in the state of exception. That is to say, the concept of ''force of This is precisely the problem lhat we must try to clarify.
law;' as a technkal legal term, defines _a separntion of the norm's vis 1J/1li­
gandi, or applicability, from its formal essence, whereby decrees ) provî­ 2.4 The concept of application is œrta inly one of the most prohlematic
sions1 and rneasures that are not forma!ly laws nevertheless acq_uire their categone, oflegal (and not on]y legal) l'heory. The question ,;,v;;is put on
"f01:ce." TI1us, when the Roman sovereign begins to acquire the power a false track hy helng related lo Kanî's theory ofjudgmcnt a-; a facuîty of
to issue acts that tend increasingJy to have the value oi: laws, Roman think:ing the partkular as contained in the genernl. ·n1e application of a
doctrine says that these acts have the "force of lav/' (Ulpîan 1 in Digests, norm wnuld thus be a �use of de-terminant judgment; in whkh the gen­
1.4-,1; quod principi placuît legis habet vigorem [because it pleased the eral (the rule) is given, and the pnrticular case is to be sub:mmed under
sovereign, it has the force oflaw] ; usîng equ iv:i]ent expressions > though it. (ln reflective judgment it is instead the particular that îs given, and the
ones that underscore the formal distfnctkm betwcen the falVS and the general rule that must be found.) Even though Kant was perfectly aware
constitution of the sovereign, Gaius -..vrites legis vireni (lbtineat [lèt it of the aporetk nature of the problcm and of the dj ffiçulty involved in
take thepiaœ oflaw] , and Pomponius writes pro lege servetur (let it serve concretely dedding bctween the two types of jndgment : as sh mvn by
for law]). his theory of the ex,rmpte as an instance of a ruk that cannot be enun­
In °0 l�r di.:;cusslon of the state of exception, ,ve have encountered 1111- ciated), the mJstake here is lhat Hte relation hetween the part:icufar case
merous ex.amples of thü confusioii betvveen acts of the executive power and the norm appea.rs as a merely logkal operation.
and acts of the legislative power; îndeed, as we have seen, such a con­ Once aga.in, the analogywith languagc is illuminatîng: In the relation
fusion defines onc-,of the essent îaJ chanicteristks of the state of exéep� berween the general and the rartk11lar (and all the more so in the case of
tion. (The ilmit case is the Nazî regime, in which) as Eichmann never the application of a ,luridk.al norm) ) tt is not only a l ogka! subsumption
tired ofrepeating, "the words of the führer have the force oflaw [ Geset­ thàt is at issue) but first and foremost the passage- from a generic propo�
zeskraft] ):' But from a tedmical standpoint the spedfic contribution of sition endowed with a merely virtual refere-nœ LO a cuncrete refrrcnœ
the state of exception is less the confusion of powers, which has been to a scg.me11t of reality (that is, nothing less than the question of the ac
ail fo� strongiy lnsisted upon, than it îs the separntion of "force oflaw» tual relation betWl"en language and world), This passage from langue to
from the htw. It defincs a "state of the law" in whkh) on the one hand, parole, or from the semiotic to th e semantk, is not -a )ogical oreratbn at
the norm îs in force [ vigeJ but is not appUed (jt has no '!force" [JO rza J) aU; rather, it alway'S eritails a practical activity, that is1 the assumption of
and, on the olher) acts tha t do not have the value [valoreJ oflaw acquire langue by onc or m0re spcnkîng st1hjc..::ts and the impkrnentati011 of that
its "force," That is to say, in extrcme situations "force of law" tloats as cornplex apparatns that Benveniste dcfined as the ennnci ative fon ction,
an indeterminate ekment that can be daimed both by the state author­ which logicians often tend to undervalue, ln the case of the }uri<lical
ity (which açts as a commîssarial dictatorship) and by a revolutionary norm, reforenèe to the concrcte case entails a «trial" that a1ways involves
40 arnptcr Two

a plurality of subjects and ultimately culminates in the pronunciation of 3 � Iustitium


a sentenœ, lhat is, an enundation wlwst� operative reference to reality
is _guarantecd hy the institut1onaJ power&.
In order to pose the prohlem of application corrcctly; it must therc­
fore first be moved from the logical sphere to the pracùcal. J\s Gadamer
has sbown (1960, 360, 395/37�•79, 418), nor only is cvery linguistk inter­
preration 'ahvays reaBy an application requiring an effective operation 3.1 TI1ere is an institution of Roman law that can în some ways be
(whkh the trad l i ion of theologkal hermeneutîcs has summarized in the -considered the archetypc of the mode-rn A11s11ahmczustand, and yet·····
maxim that Johann A. llengel placed at the beginning of his edition of indeed, perh-aps predsely for thîs rcawn-does not seem to have heen
· the New Tes lament: te totum applicn ad textmn, rem totam applica ad given sufficient attention by legal historians and theodsts of public law:
te [ apply al! of yoursdf to the tcxt; apply ail of it _to yourself!), but it the iustitimn. Because it allows us to observe the st'flte of exception in its
is also perfect!y obvions (and Schmitt had no difficulty theorizing this paradigmatic form� wc wiU use the iustittwn here as a miniature mo<lel
obvlousness) that) in th e case oflaw, the application of a norm is in no as we attempt to untangle the aporias that the modern theory of the state
way contained within the norm and éànnot be derived from it; other­ of e--.:ception cannot resolve,
wise, there woul<l have been 110 need to create the grand edHice of tdal Upon Jparning ofa situation th at endangered the Republic1 the Senate
law. Just as between hmguage and world, so behveen the norm and its w0tùd issue a scnatt1s ccmsu ltum :1!ti111um �final dccree of the Senate]
applicatîon there is no internal nexus that aJiows one to be derived im­ by whkh lt called upon the consuls {or those in Rome who :acted in
mcdiately from the other. their stead: interrex or proconsùls) and, in some çases, 'the praetor and
In this st:ns-e, the stnte of exception IS the opening of a spaœ in wh ich the tribunes of the people> and even� in ex:treme cases, all dtizens, to
application and norm reveal thcir se:paration and a pure forœ-of-]àv,( take wha tever measures they considered neœssary for the salvatfon of
realizes (thal is, applies by ceasing lo apply f dis-applicamlo] ) a norm the state (rem publimm defendrmt, opcmmque dent ne quid respublira
whose applicntîon has been suspellded. In this way; the impossible task detrùnenti capiat [Let them defend the state, and see to it that no hurm
of welding norm and reality together, and thereby cbnstituting the nor­ corne to the statel ). At the base of this semitus mnsultum was a decree
mal sphere, is carried out in the form of the �xœptfon, that is to say, by declaring a tumultus (that î�1 ;m emergenry situation in Rome re:mlting
prcsupposing their nexus. This means drnt in order to apply a norm ît is from a fureign war} insurrection, or civil w,u) i which usuaUy Jed to the
ultimateJy necessnry to suspend its appl ication, to produce an exception. proclamation of a iustitium (iustitium edicere or indiœre [ to prodaim
In every case, the state of exception marks a thr�shold at \Vhich fogjc and or dedare a iustitium] ).
praxis blur with each other and a pure violence without logo;; daim:, to 'fl1e term iustitimn-�which is constructed ex:acdy llke solstitiun1-
realize an enundation without any real reference. literally means '"standstiW' or ''suspension of the laW': i/t1tmdo ius star,
as the grnmmarfans cxplaîned etymologkally, sicut solstitium dicitur
( iustitium means "wheu the )aw stands still, just as [ the sun does inJ
the s.olstkc"); ori in the words of Aulus Gellhts, fltris quasi interstitio
quacdam et ccssatio ( as if it were an Jnterval and a sort of cessa tion of
law). The term implied, then, a suspension nût simply of the adminis­
tration of justice buL or the law as such. The meaning of this parad oxical
legal imti iution--which consists solely in the production of a juridical
42 Chapter Thrce Tmtitimn 43

void-is what we must examine here frorn both a philosophico-politiœl sches Staatsrecht, he has to con front the problem of the senatus consul­
standpoint aod from the perspective of the systematics of public law. twn 11ltiin1.11n and the state of n<>œf:sity that it presupposes, �he best he
can do is œsort to the image of the right of self-defense [ lrgiffima dtftsa 1
1-t The definition of the concept of f:u multus, partkularly in wrnparison to war (the German term for self-defcnse) No!wehr1 recaJls the tcrm for the state
(hellum), has led to debates that are not always pertinent. The conne<:tion be­ of emergency, Notstrmd): "Just as every citizen acquires a right of self.
twren the two concepts is alre<1dy present in an dent 1,ources� for exampk in the defense in those urgent situa!Jons in which the protection of the com­
p:m:ige frnm lhe Philippics (8.1) in which Ckero &tatcs that "there can be a wilr munity faHs, so there is aiso a right ofself-defense for the state and for ev­
without tumult, bu l no tumult without a war." AJl evidenœ suggests !hat this ery citizen 2s such ,vhen the community is ln danger and the mag1strat­
passngc doe6 not rnean that tumult ls a special or stron€rer form ofwar ( qthJli, ical fi.mction breaks down. Though in a certain sense it stands outside
firirles, ge.steigcrtes /Jcll11111 [see Nisscn 1877, 78]); instead, at the very momenl of of the law [ausserhalb des Rechts] , it is nevertheless necessary to make
affirming a connection bt'twecn war and tumult, it places ,m lm:dudble differ­ the essence and application of th-is right of self-defense [ Nat111ehrrcchtj
cnce between them. _J ndeed, un analysîs of the passage!i from Uvy rnncerning
intclligible 1 at ]cast to the dcgree to whkh it lends itself to a theoretical
t11rnu!t11s show� that though t11t! cause of a tumuh can be (but is not alway�}
e..xposition" Ovfommsen 1969, 1: 687-88).
an external wrir, the ter!l'.I tedmkalJy desigJJates the state of disordcr and imrest
Mommsen's affirmation of the state of exccption's extr::ijnridical
(tmnultus is related to tumor, which mean:,; '" svvdling, fermentation'') that atist'&
character and his doubts about the very possibility of presenting it the­
Îtl Rome as a rcsult of lhat event (thus the news üf a defoat in the war against
the Etrnscans gave dRe to a turnuh and 11uriam11 quw11 re tcrrorem [greuter ter­ oretkally are matched by certain heshotions and jnconsistencies in his
rer than the thing] [Livy w.�p.] in Rome), This confusion bctween cause ami discussion that are surprising in a mind such as his, which has been
effect Js dear in the definition found ill the Latin dictkmaries: hrl!Hm aliqrwd described as rather more systematic than hîstorîcal. Firsl of alJ, even
rnhitum, l]Uod ah pcrinJ!i rmigrritt;rfbî1•m hos1hnnqac 1·idnif.rrern m;1g,wm urbi though he is perfoctiy aware of Jts contiguity with the senatus mnmltum
trepîilatiLmcm inmtieb11f rany sudden WaJ' that brings great alarm to the city on ultimum; he does not examine the ius-t-hiu11-: in the section dedicated to
account of the magnitude of the danger and neamess of the mcmy1 (ForœHinYs the state of neœssity (Mommsen 1969, 1: 687--97) but in the Séction rhat
Totim T ati11itr.fis t.,xicon), Tumult ls not ''suddcn w:ir," but th,:, magno trcpîdritia deals with the magistrales' right ofveto (263ff.). Furth ermore\ though be
that it prodti..:es in Rome, ']11isis 1vhy, in otbcr cast>s, the same lerm can a!so des­ is aware that the senatus consultwn u!timul"!1 refers essentially to dvil war
ignate the disotder resulting from 'ln ITl:tcrnaJ însurrection or civij wa r. Tht• only (it is the me.ans by which "dvil Nar is prodaimed" l693] ), and though
1

po:.slhle dchnition capable of comprising all it:- known uses is the ont'- that sees he knows that the form of conscription is different în the t½'O cases
tumultus as "the G1esura by tne<1ns of whkh" from the point of view of puhlk ( 695t he does not seem to distinguish between tum11lt1-1s and state of
Iaw, e,xceptkmal mcasores may be takcn" (Nissen 1877, 76}. The rel8tion between \var { Kriegsrccht). In the last volume of the Staatsrech t, he defines the
bellum and tumultus is the s;une one that exists between war and mlHtary slate senaws consultm-n -u.ltimwn as a "quasi--dictatorshîp;'' introduced into
of siegc on the one han.I and statc of e:;;,:er•ll<m and politkal sfltic of siege ou the com;tit\Jtional system in the time of the Gracchi, and he adds that
the other, "în the 1a.st œntury of the Republ.î c, the Senate's prerogative to exercise
a law of war over the citizens was neve.r scriously contested" {3: 1243-
3,2 It Œn comc as no surprise that the reconstruction of something 44). YCt the image of a "quasi -dktatorship" (which wîll be picked up
Hke a theory of the state of exception în the Roman çonstitution has by Plaumann [19131) is entirely misîea<ling, for here not only is there
always put Roman scholars ill at ease, given that, as w;;; have secn, such no creation of a new magistra cy, but îndeed every citizen seems to be
a theory is geùcrally mîssîng frmn public law. invested with a flo,ning ,n1d anom<1lous imperium th ,:it resists definition
Jn this regard, Mommsen:,s stance is signifi,,::ant. \Vhen, in his ROmi- within the terms of the normal order,
44 Chapter Tbree Iu,tifimn 45

In his description of this state of exception, Mommsen)s acumen s:tate of necessity [ Notstt111dsrmnmando) in a zone militiac, and; Hke
manifests itself precisely at the point where it slwws its limits. He oh•• it, disappears on il& o,vn wlth the cessation of the danger. (Mommsen
serves that the pmver in question absolutely excccds the constitutional 1969, 1; 694--96)
rights of the magistrates and cann ot be examined from a juxidico-formal
point ofview. He writes, In his description of this Nr>tstnrufscommando, in whk:h any and ev­
ery citizen sccms to be invest.ed with _an imperimn that lS floating and
Jfalreadythe mention of the tribunes ofthe people and the provincial ''outside of the law," Mommsen came as dose .is he cou ld to formul:Hing
governors, who lack impcrimn or hold it only nominally, prohihits us a theory of the state of exception, but he remained on this sîde of it.
from considering thts appeal l the one contained in the senatus con­
sultum ultimum] as merely a call to the magistrates to energetically 3,3 In 1877, Adolpb Nissen1 professor at the University of Strasbourg,
exerdse füeir constitutional rights> this appcars even more dearly on pub1ished the monograph Das Iusititum. Eine Studie a/15 der riimîsc11en
the occasion when, afler the senatus consullwn provokcd by Han­ Reclttsgescfl ichte. Th\� boot which seeks to analyze a "legal institution
nibal's offensive1 aH tlH) ex:-dktators, ex-consuJsj and ex-censors as­ that has until now passed nearly unobser ved,>' is interesting for a num­
sumed imperium again and retaine<l it untii the w!thdrawal of the ber of reasons, Nissen is the first to see clearly tllia the usual undcrstand­
enemy. As the call to the ceosors also shows, this is not a case of an ing of the term as a "court holiday" ( Gerichtsfericn) is entirely insuffi­
exceptionol prorogation of a previously held office1 whkh, moreover1 dent and that, in its teéhnkal sense, it must also be distin guishe<l from
the Senate coukl not have ordcred in this f�)ffil. Rather, these sena­ its later meaning as ''publk mourntng." Let us t:akc an c:xcmphuy ,:ase of
tus consulta cannot be judged from a Juridko�formal standpoint: it a iustititlm, Lhc one Cicero describes in P!Jifippics 5.12. Confr-onted with
is necessîty that produces law, and by dedadng a state of exception the threat of Marcus Anton ins, whn is lea<lîng an army toward Rome,
[Notstand], the Senate, as the highest advisory authorHy ofthe com­ Ciœro addresses the Senate witb these words: tumultum censeo decerni,
munity, adds only the counsel tbat the now permitted and necessary imtitium indici, saga sumi dico oportere (I ass:ert that it is neces5ary to <le­
persona! defenses be expediently organized. ( 1969, 695-96 J dar� a state of tumultus; prodairn a iustitiwn, and dnn the doaks tsaga
sumere means roughly that the dti1,ens rnust take off thelr togas and
Here Mommsen reca Ils the case of a private citiz.cn 1 Sdpîo Kasica,
prepare for comhatj). Nissen readiiy demonstrates that translating iusti­
who, when confronted with the consuYs refüsal to act against Tiberlus
tium here as "court holiday,, would slmpîy make no sense; rathe r, it is
Gracchus in execution of a senatus consult11n1 ttltimwn, exdaims, " q ui
a matter ot� under exceptional conditions> puttlng aside the restrictions
rem p ublicmn salvam esse vult me sequatur! [He who tv'ishes that the
that the Jaw imposes on the acdon of the m-agistra.tes (în particular, the
state be safe, let him follow me! ] " and kills Tiberins Gracchus.
prohibitfon that the Lex Sempronio .:stublished agaînst puttîng a Roman
The imperium of these commanders in the state of exception [Not­ citizen to _death inimsu populi [without orders from the people] ). Still­
standsfeldherren] stands beside that of the consuls more or less as stand des Rcchtes, "stands lill and suspension of the law,"' is the formula
the imperium ofthe praetor or proconsul stands besidc consular im­ that, ao::ording to Nisse11 1 both defines the tcnn ii,•:,•-rttfom and tr.a:nslates
perium. . . . The power conferred here is the customary one of a com­ it to the lettcr, The iusti.Ùum "suspends the law and, in this ,vay, alJ legaî
mander, and it makcs no difference whether it is directed against an prescriptions are put out of operation. No Roman citizen, ,vh,::• ther a
enemy who lays sicge to Rome or against a citizen who rebels. . . . magistrate or a private citizen, now has lega! powers or duties" ("\lissen
Moreover, this authority of comm,md [ CommandoJ j however it may 18j7, 105), Nissen has no donbts ahout the aim of this ne-utrali z.ation
mttnifest itself, is stfü less formu!ated than the analogous power in the of the law: 1'\tVhen the law was no longer able to pt'rform its highest
46 Chapter Three Iusfitimn 47
task-to guan:mlee lhe public weJfure•-the law was abandoned in favor problem, Tiiough, likr Nissen, he dea rly sees the tight connectîon between tu­
of expediency, and just as in situations of neccssity the magistrat.es were multus and iustitium, Middell emphasîzcs the formai co.ntrast betwecn cumul�
rt?leased from Lhe restrictions of the law by a sen a tus cousultwn, so ü1 rhe tus, which is decreed by the Senate, and iusrîti11m, which must be prodaîmed
most extrerüe situations the law was set aside. Instead of transgressing it, by a magistrate. From this he concludes that Nisscn's thesis (the iustitium as a
when it became harmfül it was cleared away; it was suspended through total suspension of law) was excessive, for the magistrate could not inde-pen..
a iustitium" (98). ln other words, accor<ling to Nissen, the iustirium re­ dently release himsdf from the restrictfon..<:: of the· laws. Thus relrnbilitatln;1 the
sponds to the same 11ecŒsity that Madùavelli unequivocally indkated old intcrpretation of the iustitium as a court hollday, Midddl lets. the meaning
when, in the Discourses� he suggested "breaking" the order to save ît of thi:" instîtutio n sHp away from him. For whoever may have hecn the person
(''Iior in a repuhlic wherc such a provision is lacking 1 one must either ob­ lechnically qi1alified to proclaim a iustitium, it is certain that it \Vas ahvays and
serve the orders and be ruined, or break them and not be .ruined" [1381), only dedared ex auctoritate patmm :on the authority of the fothersl, and the
Viewing lt from the perspective ofthe state of nCcessîty (Notfall), Nis • magistrate (or mere- citizen) therefore actcd on the basis of a stale of danger
sen cm thu s interpret the senatus consuftum ultimum1 the dcdaration of th,H authorized the suspension of the la\v,
tumultus, and the iustitimn as systematically connected. The consulturn
presupposcs the twnultu.s, and the tumultus if; the sole cause of the iusti­ 3.4 Let us try to pin down the characteristics of the iustitium as they
tium. These are not catcgories of criminaI law but of constitutiona] law, emerge from Nisst.'D's monograph and, at the same time, devdop his
and tht:y designate "the caesura by rneans of \vhich; from the point of ana]yses toward a general theory of the state of exception.
view of public law. exceptional measures [Aumahmemaflregeln: may be First of aH� because it brings about a standstiU and suspension of the
talœn" (Nissen 1877, 76). enlire juridkal order, the iustitium cannot be interpreted through the
pa radlgm of dictatorship. In the Roman constitution, the dktator was
� In the syntagma senatus CMISuhmn Hltimum, the term that <listînguîshcs ît a spedfic kind of magistrate whom the consuls had chosen and whose
from other consulta fa obv[omly the ad,iectivc ultimus, which appears not to imperium, which was ex:tremely broad, ,,,r,1s conferred by a lex curiata
have r�ri ved due attention from s(holars. That th.is lerm has a technical vnlue thal defined its airns. On the contrary, in the iustitium (even in the case
1$ demo�stratec! by the fact that we fmd it repeated as a definition ofboth thesît­ where it is a dktator in office w-ho declares it) , there is no creation of
t1il tion justH}'ing the rons�tltum (senat11s consultum ultimae neœssitatù) and the
a nev.r magistracy; the unl imited power enjoyed de facto by the exis.­
vox uitima, the appeal addressed to aH citizens for the salv:ît:ion of the republk
tent magistrates iusticio indicto [the iustitiwn having been declared] re-·
(qui rc111 publicam ml-varc vuit, me sequatur).
sults not from their being invested 'w ith a dictatorial impcrium, but from
Uitimm derives from the adverb uls, which me.:ms "beyond" (as opposed to
the suspension of the laws that restrîcted their action. Both Mommsen
cis, "on this sidc"). The etymological meaning of ultimus is therefore "'what is
and Plaumann arc perfectly aware of this 1 and for this reason speak not
found ahsoiutely beyond, the most ex.treme."' U!timâ nrœssi'tas (rwœdo etyrno­
logically meam "I cannot go back") indicates a zone beyond whicb shelter and of dktatorshlp but of "quasî-dictatorship"; however, not only does the
1 1
' quasf do nothing to eliminate the arnhiguity, it in fact contributes to
safcty .,ire not possible. The scna!us conS11ltum ultiimm1 lies at such an extreme
outtr edge, but if we nüw ask ''\\'!th respect to what?" the only po8sible answer is the institution's being in terpreted according to a manifestly erroneous.
the jurklkal ordcr, whkh indeed gets -Suspended in the iustitiwn. In thîs sen.se, paradigrn.
srrta!Us ammit:1111 u!tù-1wm and iustit-ium mark the limit of the Roman consti- This is equally true for the modern s-tate of exception. The confusion
tniional order. of state of exception and dictatorship is the limitation that prevented
both Sdunill lJl 192.1 and Rossiter and Friedrich after \Norld \Var 'J\vo
� Mid<lell's monograph {1887}, publîshed in Latin (lhmtgh the modern authors from resolving the aporias of the state of except!on.-In both cases, the
are cited in German), falls far short of a profound theoretical inqui_ry into the error was self-serving, sînœ it was certainly easier to justify the &tate
48 Chapter Three Iustitium 49

of exception juridically by inscrîbing it in the prestigious tradition of magistrates) were in privato abditi, reduced to the state of private cit­
Roman dictatorship than by restoring it to its authentic ) but more ob­ izens (Livy 1,9.7); on the other hand ) Cicero writes apropos of Scipio
Scure, genealogical paradigm in Roman Iaw: the iustitium. From this Nasica's gesture that though a private citizen ) in killing Tiberius Grac­
perspective, the state of exception is not defined as a fullness of powers, chus he acted "as if he were a consul" (privatus ut si consul esset�· 1l1scu­
a pleromatic state of law) as in the dictatorial model, but as a kenomatic lan Disputations 4.23.51) . The iustitium seems to call into question the_
state, an emptiness and standstill of the law. very consistency of the public space; yet, conversely, the consistency of
the private space is also imrnediately neutralized to the same degree. ln
N , In modern public law theory, it is customary to define as dictatorships the
truth, this paradoxical coincidence ofprivate and public ) of ius civile and
totalitarian states barn out of the crisis the democracîes underwent after World
imperium, and ) in the extreme case) ofjuridical and nonjuridical, betrays
War One. Thus Hitler as well as Mussolini, Franco as well as Stalin, get indiffer­
the difficulty or impossibility of thinking an essential problem: that of
ently presented as dictators. But neither Hitler nor Mussolini can technically be
the nature of acts · committed during the iustitium. What is a hum an
dcfined as dictators. Mussolini was the head ofthe government) legally invested
with this office by the king, just as Hitler was chancellor of the Reich, named by praxis that is wholly delivered over to a juridical void? Tt is as if when
the legitimate president of the Reich. As is well known) what characterizes bath faced with the opening of a wholly anomie space for hurnan action both
the Fascist and Nazi regimes is that they allowed the ex.isting constitutions (the the ancients and moderns retreated in fright. Though bath Mommsen
Albertine Statute and the Weimar Constitution, respectively) to subsist, and­ and Nissen unequivocally affirm the iustitium's character as a juridiCal
according to a paradigm that has been acutely defined as "dual state"�they tempus mortuum, for Mommsen there still exists a Notstandsrommando,
placed beside the legal constitution a second structure, often not legally formal­ which he does not further i dentify, while for Nissen there remains a Be�
ized, that could exist alongside the other because of the state of exception. From fehl, or "unlimited command" (Nissen 1877, 105), which is matched by
a juridical stand point, the term dictatorship is entirely unsuitable for describing an equally unlimited obedience. But how ·can such a cornmand survive
such regîmes, just as, moreover, the clean opposition of democracy and dicta­ in the absence of any legal prescription or determination?
torship is misleading for any analysis of the govcrnmcntal paradigms dominant It is from this perspective that one must also view the impossibil­
today. ity (cornmon to both the ancient and modern sources) of clearly dcfin­
ing the legal consequences of those acts committed du ring the iustitium
N Though Schmitt was not a Roman scholar, he nevertheless knew of the iusti­
with the aim of saving the res publica. The question was of particular im­
tîum as a forrn of the state of exception ("martial law presupposed a sort of
portance, for it concerned whether the killing of an uncondemned ( in­
iustitîum" [Schmitt 1921, 173]), most probably from the monograph by Nissen
demnatus) Roman citizen was punishab]e or not. Apropos ofüpimius's
(who is cited in the book on dictatorship, though in relation to another text),
assassination of Caius Gracchus's followers, Cicero already describcs as
Though he shares Nissen's idea that the state of exception represents "an emptî­
"endless" ( inftn ita quaestio) the question ofv.,rhether or not a person who
ness of law" (Nissen speaks of a juridical vacuum), Schmitt prefers, apropos of
has killed a Roman citizen while acting in èxecution of a senatus consul­
the senatus consultum 11ltimum, to speak of a "quasi-dictatorship" (which sug­
gests a knowledge) if not of Plaumann's study from 1913, at least of Mommsen's tum 11Itim11111 can be punished (De oratore 2.31.134) . Nissen, for his part,
Staatsrecht). denies that either the rnagistrate who had acted in execution of a senatus
consultmn or the citizens who had followed him could be punished once
3.5 This anomie space that cornes to coïncide suddenly with the space the iustitiwn was over; but he is contradicted by the fact that Opimius
o � the city is sa peculiar that it disorients not only modern scholars but was nevertheless brought to trial (though he wàs acquitted), and Cicero
also the ancient sources thëmselves. Thus in describing the situation cre­ was sentenced to exile as a consequence of his bloody repression of the
ated by the iustitium, Livy states that the consuls (th e highest Roman Catiline conspiracy.
50 Chapter Three Tustitium 51

In trüth, the entire question is poorly put, for the aporia becomes and decision. The state of necessity is not a "state of law," but a space
clear only once we consider that because they are produccd in a juddi­ without law ( even though it is not a state of nature, but prescrits itself as
cal void, the acts committed during the i11stitî11111 are radically removed the anomie that results from the suspension oflaw).
from any juridical determination. From a legal standpoint it is possible (2) This space devoid oflaw seems, for some reason, to be so essential
to classify human actions as Jegislativei executive, or transgressive acts. to the juridirnl order that it must seek in every way to assure itself a rela­
But it is entirely clear that the magistrate or private citizen who acts dur­ tion with it, as if in order to groun d itse1 f the juridical order necess<1rily -
ing the iustitium neither executes nor transgresses a law, and even less ha<l to maintain itself in relation with an anomie. On the one hand,
does he create law. All scholars agrce on the fact that the senntus consul­ the juridical voîd at issue in th e state of exception seems ahsolutely un­
t11m ultim11111 has no positive content; it merely expresses a counsel with thinkable for the law; on the other, this unthinkable thing nevertheless
an extremely vague formula ( videant consules , . . [let the consuls see to has a decisive strategic relevance for the juridical order and must not be
it . . . ] ) that leaves the magistrate or whoever acts for him entirely free allmved to slip away at any cost.
to act as he sees fit, or even not to act at all. If we wanted at all costs to (3) The crucial prohlem connected to the suspension of the law is that
give a name to a human action performed under conditions of anomie, of the acts committed during the imtitium, the nature of which seems to
we might say that he who acts during the i11stiti11m neither executes nor escape all legal definition. Because they are neither tnmsgressive, exec­
transgress the ]aw, hut incxecutcs [ inesegue] it. His actions, in this sense, utive, nor legislative, they seem to be situated in an absolute non-place
are mere facts, the appraisal of which, once the iustitium is expired, will with respect to the law.
depend on the circumstances. But, as long as the iustitium lasts, theywill (4) The idea of a force-of-lawC is response to this t1ndcfinabil ity and
;:i

be absolutely undecidable, and the definition of their nature-whether this non-place. It is as if the suspension of law freed a force or a rnystical
executive or transgressive, and, in the extreme case, whether human, element, a sort of legal mana ( the expression is used by Wagenvoort
bestial, or divine-will lie beyond the sphere of law. to describe the Roman auctoritas [\-\Tagenvoort 1947, 106]), that both
the ruling power and its adversaries, the constituted power as well as
3.6 Let us now try to surnmarize the results of our genealogical inves­ the constituent power, seek to appropriate. Force of law that is separate
tigation of the iustitium in the form of theses. from the law, floating imperium, bcing-În••force [vigcnzn] without ap­
(1) The state of exception is not a dictatorship (whether constitu­ plication, and, more gcnerally, the idea of a sort of "degree zero" of the
tional or unconstitutional, commissarial or sovereign) but a space de­ law---all these are fictions through which law attempts to encompass
void of law, a zone of anomie in which all legal determinations�and its own absence and to appropriate the state of exception, or at least to
above all the very distinction between public and private-are deacti­ assure ltself a relation with it Though these categories (just like the con­
vated. Thus, all those theories t.hat seek to annex the state of exception cepts of mana or sacer in the anthropology and religious studies of the
immediately to the law are false; and so too are both the theory of ne­ nineteenth and tv.,re ntieth centuries) are rea lly scientific mythologemes,
cessity as the origi nary source of law and the theory that sees the state this does not mean that it is impossible or useless to analyze the fonction
of exception as the exercise of a state's right to its own defense or as the they perform in the lav/s long battlc o vcr anomie. Indeed, it is possible
restoration of an originary plerornatic state of the law ('(full powers") . that ,vhat is at issue in these ec1tegories is nothing less than the definition
But fallacious too are those theorîes, like Schmitt's, that seek to inscribe of what Schmitt calls "the political." Th e esscntial task of a theory of the
the state of exception in<lirectly within a juridical context by grounding state of exception is not simply to clarify whether it has a juridical na­
it in the division between norms of law and norms of the realization of ture or not, but to define the meaning, place, and modes of its relation
law, between constituent power and constituted power, between norm to the law.
Gigantomachy Concerning a Void 53

4 N Gigantomachy Concerning a Void containing Benjamin's essay) . As an avid reader of and contributor to
the Archil', Schmitt could not easily have missed a text like "Critique of
Violence," which, as we will sec, touched upon issues that were essen­
tial for him. Bcnjamin's interest in Schmitt's theory of sovereignty has
always been jndged as scanchl ous (Taubes once described the 1930 let­
ter to Schmitt as a "mine that can blow to pieces our conception of the -
4.1 It is from this perspective that we will now read the debate be­ intellectual history of the Weimar period" [Taubes 1987, 271 ) ; turning
tween Walter Benjamin and Carl Schmitt on the state of exception. The the scandal around ) we will try to read Schmitt's theory as a response to
exoteric dossier of this debate, which took place in various forms and Benjamin's critique of violence.
at differing levels of intensity between 1925 and 1956, is not very large:
Benjamin's citation of Political Theology in The Origin of German Tragic 4.2 The aim of the essay is to ensure the possibility of a violence ( the
Drama; the curriculum vitae of 1928 and Benjamin's letter to Schmitt German term Gcwalt also means simply "power") that lies absolutely
from December 1930 (both of which attest to an interest in and admi­ "outside" (a11jlerhalb) a nd "beyond" (jenscits) th e law and that, as sucl1,
ration for the "fascîst public law theorist" [Tiedemann, editorial note, could shatter the dialectic between lawmaking violence and law-­
in Benjamin, Gesammclte Schriften, 1 .3: 886] and have always appeared preserving violence ( rcrhtsrtzende 1tnd rech tserhaltcnde Gewalt ). Benja­
scandalous); and Schmitt's citations of and references to Benjamin in min calls this other figure of violence "pure" ( reine Gewalt) or "divin et
his book Ham/et or Hecuba, written when the Jewish philosopher had and, in the human sphere, "revolutionary." V\lhat the law can never
been dead for sixteen years. This dossier was further enlarged with the tolerate-what it feels as a threat \vith which it is impossible to corne to
pu_blication in 1988 of the letters Schmitt wrote to Hansjôrg Vîesel in tcrms-is the existence of a violence outside the law; and this îs not be­
1973, in which Schmitt states that his 1938 book on Hobbes had been cause the ends of such a violence are incompatible with l m,v, but bernuse
conceived as a "response to Benjamin [ that has] remained unnoticed" of"its mere existence outside the law" (Benjamin 1921, 1 83/239). The task
(Viesel 1988, 14; see Bredekamp's· observations, 1998, 913). ofBenjamin's critique is to provc the reality (Bcstnnd) of such a violence:
The esoteric dossier, however, is larger and has yet to be explored in "If violence is also assured a reality outside the law, as pure immediate
all its implications. Indeed, we will attempt to demonstrate that the first violence, this furnishes proof thc1t revolutionary violcnce-which is the
document that must be induded in the dossier is not Benjamin's reading name for the highest manifestation of p ure violence by man-is also
of Political Theology, but Schmitt's reading ofBenjarnin's essay "Critique possible" (202/252). The proper character'is tic of this violence is that it
of Violence" (1921). The essay was published in issue 47 of the Arch iv für neither makes nor preserves law, but deposes it (Entse tzung des Rechtes
Sozialwissenschafte n und Sozialpolitik, a journal coedited by Emil Led­ [202/251-52] ) and thus inaugufates a new historical epoch.
erer, who was then a professer at the University of Heidelberg (and later Benjamin does not name the state of exception in the essay, though
at the Ne,111 School for Social Research in New York), and who was one of he does use the term Ernstfall, which appears in Schmitt as a synonym
the people Benjamin frequented at that time. Now, not only di d Schmitt for Ausnahmezmtand, But another technical term from Schmitfs vo­
publish numerous essays and articles (încluding the first version of The cabulary is present in the text: Entsrheidung, "decision." Law, Benjamin
Concept ofthe Political) in the Archiv between 1924 and 1927, but a careful writes, "acknowledges in the 'decision' determined by place and time a
examination of the footnotes and bibliographies of his writings shows metaphysical category" (Benjamin 1921, 189/243); but this acknowledg­
that from 1.915 on Schmitt was a regular reader of the journal (he cites, ment is, in reality, only a counterpart to "the curious and at first dis­
among others, the issues immediately preceding and following the one couraging experience of the ultimate undecidability of all legal problems
54 Chapter Four Gigantomachy Concerning a Void 55

[ die seltsame und zuniichst ent11111tgende Erfahrung von def lctzlichen Un­ not be recognized as such by means of a dedsion (.Entscheidung [Ben�
entscheidbarkeit aller Rechtsprobleme] " (196/247) , jamin 1921, 203/2521 ), so too for Schmitt "it is impossible to ascertain
with compkte clarity when a situation of necessity exists, nor can one
4,3 The theory of sovereignty that Schmitt develops in his Politien/ spell out, with regard to content, what may take place in such a case
Theology can be read as a predse response to Benjamin)s essay. While when it is truly a matter of an extreme situation of necessity and of
the strategy of "Critique of Violence,, was aimed at ensurîng the ex­ how it is to be elirnim1ted" (Schmitt 1922, 9/6-7); yet ) with a stratcgic
istence of a pure and anomie violence, Schmitt instead seeks to lead inversion, this împossibility is precisely what gro unds the necessity of
such a violence back to a juridical context. The state of exception is the sovereign decision.
space în which he tries to capture Benjamin's idea of a pure violence
4.4 If these premises are accepted> then the entire exoteric debate bc­
and to in scribe anomie within the very body of the nomos. According to
twcen Benjamin and Schmitt appears in a new light. Benjamin's de­
Schmitt, there cannot be a pure violence-that is ) a violence absolutely
scription of the baroque sovercign in the Tra11crspiclb11rh can be read
outside the law-because in the state of exception it is induded in the
as a response to Schm itt's theory of sovereignty. Sam Weber h as acutely
law through its very exclusion. That is to say, the state of exception is the
observed how Benjc1min's description of the sovereign "diverges ever
device by means of which Schmitt responds to Benjamin's affirmation
so slightly, but significantly, from its ostensible theoretical source in
of a wholly anomie human action.
Schmitt" ( Weber 19921 130 ) . The hc1roquc concept of sovereignty, Ben··
The r�lation betwecn these two texts, however, is even doser than
jamin writes ) "develnps from a discussion of the state of exception> and
this. We have seen how in Political Theology Schmitt abandons the dis­
makes it the most important function of the sovereign to exclude this"
tinction between constituent and constituted power, which in the 1921
(den rmszmrhlief,en [Benjamin 1928, 245/65] ). ln substituting "to ex­
book had grounded sovereign dictatorship) and replaces it with the con­
clude" for "to decide," Benjamin surreptitiously alters Schmitt's defini­
cept of decision. This substitution acquires its strategic sense only once
tion in the very gesture ,vith ,vhich hc clc1ims to evoke it: in deciding on
it is seen as a countermove in response to Benjamin's critique. For the
the state of exception, the sovereign must not in some way includc it in
distinction between lawmaking violence and law-preserving violence­
the juridical order; he must, on the contrary, exclndc it, leave it outside
which was Benjamin's target---corresponds to the letter to Schmitt's op­
of the juridical order.
position; and it is in order to neutralize this new figure of a pure violence
The meaning of this substantial modification becomes clear only in
removed from the dialectic between constituent power and constituted
the pages thc1t foll ow, wh ere Benjamin elahorates a true and proper the­
power that Schmitt develops bis theory of sovereignty. The sovereign vi­
ory of "sovereign indecision"; but this is precisely where the interweav­
olence in Political Theology responds to the pure violence ofBenjamin)s
ing of reading and counterreading becomes tighter. While for Schmitt
essay with the figure of a power that neither makes nor preserves law, but
the decision is the nexus that unîtes sovereignty and the state of excep­
suspends it. Similarly, it is in response to Benjamin's idea of an ultimate
tion, Benjamin ironically <livi des sovereign power from its exercise and
undecidability of all legal prohlems that Schmitt affirms sovereignty as
shows that the baroque sovereign is constitutively incapable of deciding.
the place of the extreme decision. That this place is neither external
nor internai to the law-that sovereignty is, h1 this scnse, a Grcnzbegrijf The antithesis betwccn sovereign power [ Herrscherrnach t ] and the
[limit concept J.-is the necessary consequence of Schmitt's attempt to capacity to exercise it [HerrschvcrmOgcn] led to a feature pcculiar
neutralize pure violence and ensure the relation between anomie and the to the Trauerspiel which is, hmvcver, only apparently a generic fca­
juridical context. And just as pure violence, according to Benjamiri, can- ture and which can be illuminated only on the basis of the theory
56 Chaptcr Four Gigantomachy Concerning a Void 57

of sovereignty. This is the tyrant's inability to decide [Entschluflun­ this world, and from it the baroque extracts a profusion of things that
fiihigkeit] . The sovereign, who is responsible for making the deci­ until then eluded all artistic formulation . . . in order to clear an ulti­
sion on the state of exception, reveals, at the first opportmüty,-that mate heaven and enable it, as a vacuum, one day to destroy the earth
it is almost impossible for him to make a decision:' (Benjamin 1928, \Vith catastrophic violence" (246/66).
250/70-71) It is this "white eschatology"--which does not lead the earth to a r':­
<leemed. hereafter1 but consigns it to an absolutely empty sky-that con­
The division between sovereign power and the exercise of that power figures the baroque state of exception as catastrophe. And it is again this
corresponds exactlyto that between norms oflaw and norms of the real­ white eschatology t.hat shatters the correspondence between sovereignty
ization oflaw, ,vhich in Dictatorship was the foundation of comrnîssarial and transcendence, between the monarch and God, that defined the
dictatorship. In Political Thcology Schmitt responded to Benjamin's cri­ Schmittian theologico-politicaJ. While in Schmitt '(the sovereign is iden­
tique of the dialectic hetween constituent power and constituted power tified with God and occupies a position in the statc exactly analogons to
by introducing the concept of decision, and to this countermove Ben­ that attributed in the workl to the God of the Cartesian system" (Schmitt
jamin replies by bringing in Schmitt's distinction between the norm and 1922, 43/46), in Benjamin the sovereign is "confined to the world of cre­
its realization. The _sovereign, who should decide every time on the ex­ ation; he is the l ord of creatures, but he remains a creature" (Benjamin
ception, is precisely the place where the fracture that <livides the body 1928, 264/85).
of the law becomes impossible to mend: between Macht and Vcrmiigc11, This drastic redefinition of the sovereign fonction implies a different
between power and its exercise, a gap opens which no decisîon is capable situation of the state of exception. It no longer appears as the thre· shold
of filling. that guarantees the articulation hetween an inside and an outside, or be­
This is why, with a further shift) the paradigm of the state of exception tween anomie and the juridical context, by virtue of a law that is in force
is no longer the miracle ) as in Politirnl Thcology, but the catastrophe. "In in its suspension: it is ) rather, a zone of ahsolutc indeterminacy between
antithesis to the historical idea of restoration, [ the baroque] is foced with anomie and law, in which the sphere of creatures and the juridical order
the idea of catastrophe. And it is in response to this antithesis that the are caught up in a single catastrophe.
theory of the state of exception is devised" (Benjamin 1928, 246/66)
An unfortunate emendation in the text of the Ges(lmmclte Schriften 4.5 The decisive document in the Benjamin-Schmitt dossier is cer­
has prevented all the implications of this shift from being assessed. tainly the eighth thesis on the concept of hlstory, composed by Ben­
Where Benjamin's text read, Es gibt eine btirocke Eschatologie, "there jamin a few months before his death. Here we read that " [t]he tradition
is a baroque eschatology," the editors, with a singular disregard for all of the oppressed teaches us that the 'state of exception' in which we live
philological care, have corrected it to read: Es gibt keine . , . , "there is is the rule. We must attain to a concept ofh istory thJt accords wfrh this
no baroque eschatology" (Benjamin 1928, 246/66). And yet the passage fact. Tben we will clearly see that it is our task to bring about the real
. that follows is logically and syntactically consistent with the original [ ivirklich] state of exception, and this will improve our position in the
reading: "and for that very reason [ there is l a mechanism that gathers struggle against fascism" (Benjamin 1942, 697/392) .
and exalt-s all earthly creatures bcfore consigning thcm to the end [dem That the state of exception has become the rule is not a simple
Ende] ." The baroque knows an eskhaton, an end of time; but, as Ben­ intensification of what in the Tmuerspielb11ch appeared as its undecid­
jamin immediately makes clear, this eskhaton is empty. It knows neither ability. One must not forge! here that both Benjamin and Schmitt had
redemption nor a hereafter and remains immanent to thîs world: ''The before them a state-the Nazi Reich-in which the state of exception
hereafter is emptied of everything that contains the slightest breath of proclaimed in 1933 had never been repealed. From the jurist's perspec-
58 Chapter four Gigantomud,r Concemîng a Vo.id 59
tive, Gerrnany found itself tcchnically in a situation of so_vereign dicta­ "fictitious" to a state of eJcceplion that woul<l be regulated by law, with
torship, which shonld have led to the defin itîve ahol.ition of the VVeïmar the aïm of guaranteeing some degree of indfvidual rlghts and liberties.
ConStitution and the establishment of a new constitution� whose fun� ConsequentJ y> he forcefully denounccs the \-Veimar jurists' inability to
damental charncteristics Schmitt strove to define in a series of articles distinguish between the merely foctua1 action of the president of the
bctwce11 1933 and 1936. But what Schmitt could în no way acœpt 'Was that Reich under Article 48 and a procedure regulatcd by Jaw.
the stute of exception be wholly confused with the ruk. ln Dictatorship Benjamin once again reformt1hi tes the oppmitfon in order to tum
he had already stated tlrnt arriving at a correct concept of dictatorship is it back against Schm itt Xov1 tha1 nny possfüîJity of a fktitlous state of
impossible as long as every lcgal order is_scen "only as a latent and inter­ exception-in wh kh exœption and normal coridirions are temporaHy
mittent dictatorshlp'' (Schmitt 1921 , xiv). To be sure, Political Thcology and !ocally distinct- --has collapscd, the state nf e�œption ".in which we
unequivoc;,,lly acknowledged the primacy of the exception, însofar as live" is real and ahsolutely canno1 he distînguished from the rule. Every
it makes the con stitution of the normal sphere possible; but H: in th!S fiction of a nexus bctween violence an<l law disappears here: there i.s
sens<:i the rule "lives ouly by the exception" (Schmitt 1922, 15/15), '<V'hat nothing but a zone of anomit\ in •.vhkh a vio1cnœ without .iny juridical
then happens whcn exception and iule hecmne undecid,tble? form acts. The attempt of state power to ;m nex anomie through the sfute
From Schmitt\; perspective, the functioning of the juridical order ul­ of exception is unmasked by Be njamin for what it is: a fictia iuris par
timù tely rests on <1n apparalus�the sta te of exceptio n-,vhose purpose exceJlence, whkh daims to maintn in the law in its v,;-ry suspension as
is to- make the norm appl icable by te:mpora dly suspending its eflî.cacy, forœ�oi\)��- What now takes its place are civil war and revolutionary
When the exception becomes the rulc, the machine eau no longer fonc­ violence, that is, a hum an action that has shed f dep()sfo} evcry relation
tion. In this sen se, the undcddability of norm and exception fonnulated to law.
in the eighth thesis ruts Schmitfs thcory in check. Sovercign dcdsion is
no longer capable ofperformfog the task that Political Thealogr assigned 4.6 The stakes in the debate between Benjamin and Schmitt on the
ii: the rule, whkh now coincides 'With what it lives by, devours itself. Yet state of exœptînn can now be defin,:,d more cle.i rly. The di-spute takes
this confusion hetwecn the exceptlon and the rnle was precisely what the place in a zone of anomie that, on the one hand must be nrnintaîne(i in
Third Reich had concretely brought about, and the obstinacywith which rdatkm to the law at aU costs and, on the other, must be just as ünpla­
Hitler pursued the organization of hîs "dnaI state" wi thout prnmulgat­ cably relcased and freed from this relation. Th at is to say1 at issue in the
ing a new cons1itution is proof of it. (In this regard Schmitf's attempt to anomie zone is the relation betweèn violence and law-in the last anal­
de:tine the new nrnkrial tl.!fatlon betwcen the Führer and the peop1e in ysisJ the status of violence as a dpher for hurnan action. \Vhile Schmitt
the Nazi Reich was destined to fail.) attempts every time to reinscribe violence \,\'ithin a juridicnl context,
It is frorù this perspective that Benjamin's distinction în the eighth BenJamin responds to this gesture by St.�cking every titne to assure it-as
thesis between real state of exception and state of exception tout court pure violence-an exi stence outside of the law,
should be read, The distinction was 1 às we have seen, alread-y present in For reaso11S that we nmst try to dnrify> th i� ,') trnggle for anomie seems
S(hmitfs discussion of dictatorsl1ip. Schmitt borrowed füe tern1 from to be as decisive for Western politks as the gïgnn tom(lchia peri tés ou­
Theodor fü>inach's book De l'état de siège, but while Reinach, referring sias, the "bart!e of gümts conœrning b�·lng,1' t.hat defines \Veste-ru mda­
to Napoleon's decree of Deœmber 2,1, 1S1 1, opposed an Üût de siège physics. tlere, pure viülence as th e extreme political object, as the
effertif(or military) to an état de siège fictif (or political), Schmitt, in "thing" of politics, is the counterpart to pure bcing, to pure existence
bis lenaciûus critique of the lega] state f Stato di diritto J, gives the name as the ultimate metaphysical stakes; the strategy of the exception , wh ich
60 Chapter Four Gigtrntom<1chy Corwemirlg a Void 6t

must ensure the relation between anomie vîolenœ and law, is the coun­ January 1919 {that is, about a year before draftîng the essay) Ilenjamin 1
terpart to the onto-theo-logical strategy aimed at capturing pnre being in a letter to Ernst Scboen t.hat takes up and develops moti fs alrcady
in the meshes of the logos. elaborated in an artide on Stîfteri carefully defines what he means by
That is to sa.y; everyth ing happens as îfbüth law and logos needed an "purity" (Rcinheit):
anomie (or alngica] ) zonè of suspensîon in order to ground theît ref­
crence to the workl of life. Law seems able t_o subs-ist only by capturing lt is a mistake to postulate anywhere a purity that exists in itself and
anomie, jusl as languagc can snhsist only by grasping the nonlinguistic. needs only to be preserved. . . , The purity of a bdng is never uncon­
In both cases, the contlic,t seems to conœrn an empty space: on the one ditiomil or absolute; it is always suhject to a condition. This condition
hand, anomie., ,iuridkal vacuum 1 and, on th e other, pure being, devoid varies according to the being whose purity is at issnej but this cnn­
of any deter111ination or real predicate, For law, this empty space is the diti0,n never inheres in the being itself. In other 'Nords: the purity of
state of exception as fts constîtutive dimension. The relation between every (finlte) being Ü; not dependent on itseîf. . . , For na ture, hu�
norm and renlity involves the suspension of the norm, just as in ontol­ man language îs the condition of its purity that stands outside of it.
Of:>'Y the relation between language an4 world involves the suspension of (Benjamin 1966, 2061!38)
denotation in the fonn of a longue, But just as essential for the juridical
ol'<ler is lhat this zone---wherein Hes a human action wïthout relation This relational rather than suhstantial conception of pu rity îs so cs­
to the norm--colnddes with an extreme and spectral figure of the law, sentfal for Benjamin that again in the 1931 essay on Kr.ms he èan write
in which law splits in to a pure being- in-forcc fvigenza] ivithaut appli­ that "at the origin of the creature stands not purîty [Rei11htitJ but pu­
1
cation (the form of law) and a pure application without being in force: rifkatîon r Reinigung] " (Benjamin w31, .365/455). This me;ms tlrnt the
tlle for,ce-c,f-Jl�, pmi1y at issue in the 1921 essay is not a substantîal characteristic beiong­
If thls is trne 1 then the structure ofd1e state of exception is even more ing to the vioknt action in îtsdf; that îs to say, the d.iffcrencc between
cômp)ex than what we have glimpsed of it up to now1 and the positions pure violence and my thico-juri<llcal violence àoes not lie in the violence
of the two sicles that strugg]e in and for it are even more tightly wo­ it,;;elf, but in its relation to something externaL Benjamin firrnly states
ven lnto each other, And jnst as the victory of one player in a sporting what this external condition is at the beginning of the essay: "The task
match 1s not somcthing Hke an originary state of the game that must be of a critique of vl(,lencc can be s11mmarized as that of expou-nding its re­
restored, but only the stake of the game (which dœs not preexist it, but lation to law and justice." Even the criterion of the "purity" of violence
rather results fmm it) , so pnre violence (which is the name Benjamin will therefore lie in its relati-on to lav1.• (and the topic of justice in the essay
gives to human action that neither makes nor preserves law) is not an is, in fact, discmstd only in rcfotion to the ends of law).
originary figure of human action that at a certain point is captured and Benjamin's thesis is tbat while mythico-,iuridical viol ence is ahvays à
inscribe<l wlthin the juridical order (just as there is not, for speaking rneans to an en<l 1 pure violence is ncvcr simply a.means--•-whether iegiti­
man, a prelinguistlc reality that at a certain point falls into language). lt mate or illegitimatc--to an end (whether just or unjust J The critique of
ÎS; rnther, only the !':take in the conflict over the state of exception, what violence dof:'s not evaluate violence- in relation to the ends that ît pnrs.ues
results from it and, in this way only, ls s11pposed pr.ior to the law. as a me8ns 1 but seeks its ..:ri terion ''in a dl:'i-tinction vvithin the sphere of
me8 ns themselves, without regard for the ends they serve" (Benjamin
4.7 lt is therefore all the more important to understand correctly the 1921, 179/236).
meaning of the expressîon reine Geivait, "pure violence;' as the essen­ Here appears the topic-,vhkh flashes up in the text only for an in­
tial tecllnical term of Benjamin's essay, What does "pure" mean here? ln stant1 but is neverthdess sufficient to i1lumina!'e the entire piece--of
62 Chapter Four Gigantonrnchy Concerning a Void 63

violence as "pure medium;' that is, as the figure of a paradoxical "me­ the criterion of their distinction lies in the di ssolution of the relation
dialitywithout ends"-a means thêlt, though rernaining such, is consid­ between violence and law.
ered independently of the ends that it pursues. The problem, then, is not
that ofidentifyingjust ends but that of"individuating a different kind of 4.8 It is from this perspective that we m11 st read Benjamin's statement
vîolencé that certainly could not be either the legitirnate or illegitirnate in the letter to Scholem on August 11 1 1934, that "the Scripture without
means to those ends but is not related to them as means at all but in its key is not Scripture, but life" (Benjamin 1966, 618/453), as well thè
some different way [ nicht als Jvfittel zu ihnen, viclmchr irgendwie anders, one found in the essay o n Kafka, acC:ording to which "[tl he law which
sich verhalten würde]" (Benjamin ,921, ,96/247) . is studied but no longer practiccd is the gate to justice" (Benjamin 1934,
What can this other type of relation to an end be? It will be useful 437/815). The Scripture (the Torah) without its key is the cipher of the
to apply the consideratîons that we have just developed conccrning the law in the state of exception, which is in force but is not applied or is
meaning of Benjamin's term "pure" to the concept of "pure" medium applied with ôut beîng in force ( and which Scl1olem 1 not at all suspccting
as well. The medium does not owe its purity to any specific intrinsic that he shares this thesis with Schm itt, believes is sti11 lJw) . According to
property that differentiates it from juridical means, but to its relation Benjamin, this law-or, rather, this force-of.-]:m(--is no longer law but
to thern. In the essay on language1 pure language is that which is not an life, "life as it is lived;' in Kafka's novel, "in the village at the foot of the
instrument for the purpose of communication, but communicates itself hill on wbich the castle is built" (Benjamin 1966, 618/453). Kafka's most
immediately, that is, a pure an<l simple communicability; likewise, pure proper gesture consists not (as Scholem believes) in having maintained
violence is th at which does not stand in a relation of means toward an a bw thot no longer bas any meaning, but in h ,nring shown that it ceases
end, but holds itself in relation to its own medial ity. And just as pure to be law and blurs at all points with life.
language is not another language, just as it does not have a place other In the Kafk:a essay, the enigmatic image of a law that is studied but no
than that of the natural communicative languages, but reveals itself in longer pr;:1cticed corresponds, as a sort of remnant, to the unmasking of
these by exposing them as such, so pure violence is attested to only as rnythico-juri clical violence e ffectecl hy pure violence, There is, therefore,
the exposure and deposition of the relation between violence and law. still a possible figure oflaw after its nexus with violence and power has
Benjamin suggests as much imrnediately thereafter, evoking the image been deposed, but it is a law that no longer has force or application, like
of violence that, in anger, is never a means but only a man ifestation the one in which th e "new attorney," leafing through "o ur old hooks;'
( Manifestation). Wh ile violence that is a means for ma king lmv never de­ buries himself in study, or like the one that Foucault may have had in
poses its own relation with lmv and thus instates law as power (Macht), mind when he spoke of a "new law" that has been freed from all disci­
which remains "necessarily and intimately bound to it" (Benjamin 1921, pline and all relation to sovereignty.
1_98/248), pure violence exposes and severs the nexus between law and \Vhat cm hc the meaning of a law that survives its deposition in such
violence and can thus appear in the end not as violence that governs or a way? The difficulty Benjamin faces here corresponds to a problem that
executes (die schaltende) but as violence that purely acts and manifests can be formulated (and it was effectively formnlated for the first time in
( die waltende). And if the connectfon between pure violence and ju­ primitive Christianity and then lat.cr in the Marxian tradition) in these
ridical violence, between state of exception and revolutionary violence, terms: V\That becomes of the law after its messinnic fulfillment? (This
is thus made so tight that the two pfoyers focing each other across the is the controversy that opposes Paul to the Jews ofhis timc.) And what
chessboar<l of history seem always to be moving a single pawn-force­ becomes of the law in a society withot1t classes' (This is precisely the de­
of.-Jm( or pure means-what is nevertheless decisive is that in each case bate between Vyshinsky and Pasbukanis.) These are the questions tbat
64 ChaptcT Four ·

Benjamin seeks to·answer with his reading of the "nciv attorney."' Obvi� 5 � Feast, Mourning, Anomie
ously1 it is not a question here of :1 transition:11 1,hasc that ncvt'r achieves
its end:. nor of a _process of infinite deconstruction th.it) in maintain­
ing the law in a spectral Ufe, QUl no longer get to the bottom of it, 1lu:
dedsîve point here is that the law-no longer prn.ctiœd, but stuJled­
is not justkej but only the gate that leads to ît \Vhat opens a passage
tow�ird Justice is not the erasure oflaw, hut its d-eactivation and i nactivity 5.1 Roman scholars and leg;1} historians have not yet been able to find a
(înoperosîtà ]�that is> another use of the lave This is prcciscly i,.vhat the satisfactory ex:p lanatîon for the pecnliar semantic evolution that le&the
force-of]àv( ( whkh keeps the lawworking [ in opera] beyond its formal term imtitiwn-the technkal designation for the state of exception-lü
suspension) seeks to prevcnt Kaika\-; characters-and this îs why they acquire the meaning of public monrning for the death of the sovereign
interest us-have to do with this spectral figure of the law in the state or hîs close relative, Indeed, v.'1.th the end of the Republk1 iustitimn
of exception; they seek, each one following hîs or her own strategy, to ceased to me,m the suspension oflaw in order to cope ,vith a tumul1 and
"study" and deactiv;1tc it, to "play" with it. the nev..• meaning replaccd the old one so perfectly that even the mernory
One day humanity will play with law Just as children pfay with dis� of this austere institution seems to have entlre!y vanished , At the end
used objectsi 1101 in order to reston.: them to their canonial use but to of the fourth œntury CE> the grammarian Charisius could therefore
free them from it for good. \'\11lat i.s found after the law is not a more îdentify the iustitium purely and simply with luctt1s puMiws, And it is
proper ar:d orig.inal use value that precedes the law, but a new use that îs significa nt tbat after the dehate raîsed by Nïs sen's ,md Mî<ldell's mo.no­
born only after it. And usel which has been contaminated by law, must graphs, modern schofars have disrcgatded the question of the iu.stiti11111
also be freed from its own value. 1111s lfüeration is the ta.sk of stud)\ or as the state of exœption and have concentrated solely on the iustitiùm
of pby. And this stu<l ious play is the passage that allows us to arrive at as pubtk mourning. (Ironical]y evoking the term)s old meaning in his
that justice that one ofBenjamîn's posthumous fragments defines as a study of G_ennanicus's füne ral, \V!lliam Seston wmte, "the debate was
state of the world in which the world appears as a good that absolutely rather lively, hut soo n nohody thought about it any more,, [Seston ·, 962>
cannot be appropriated or made juridical (Benjamin 1992, 41). 155J.) But" how did this term that was used in public lfnv to desiguate the
suspension of law in situa tions of the moM extreme political necessity
corne to assume the more anodyne rneaning of a funeral œremony for
a death in the family?
ln an extensive study publîshed in 1980, H. S, Versnel attemptt•fl to
answer this question hy proposlng an nnalogy het ween the phenomc·nol­
ogy of monrrùng-as attested to in the most diverse places by anthro­
pologie.al rescarch-and periods of politkal crisis, in whkh social in­
stitutions and rules seems sudc1enly to dissolve. Just t1s1 1.foring periods
of anomie and crisis, normal soda} structures can collapse and social
functions and roles break down to the point where culturally condi­
tioned l�ehaviors and customs are completely overtnrned; so arc peri­
ods ofmourning usuallr -charnctedr.cd hy a suspension and alteration of
all social relations. "\:v'b.oever characlerizes the critic1l periods as . . . a
66 Chapter Five Fea,;1, M(rnming, Anomie 67
temporary substitution of order by dis.orde1\ of culture by naturel of kos­ who in his nmnograpb entitled Suicide (1:8:97) had introduœd the concept of
mos by �haos, of nomos by physis,. of etmomia by rmornia, has irnplidt!y anomie into lhe hmrnm sciences. ln out the category of "anomie sn1-
charactedzed the perlod of mourning and its manifestations" (Versnel chle" alongside the other forms of s1.1kide1 Durkheim 1H,d cst2blîshcJ a corn:-­
1980> 584--85) . According to Versnel i who here cites the analyses of the lation between the dhninution uf society's regul:1tlve influence on indivlduals
A1nerican sociologists Berger and Luckman 1 "All sodetics are construc­ and a rise in the suicide rate. This WilS hmtamO Lmt to postulating (.as he doe_�
tions jn the face of drnos. The constant possibfüty of anomie terror îs without providing any e-xplanation) a need nfhuman hdngs to be regulated in
actualized whenever the fogitimations that obscure the pre.cariousnèss their activities and passions: "What is ch:irncterislic of man is to_ he sub_ie...,i: to
are threatened or coHapse" (585). a restrnilit that is not physio1f bnt moral; that is1 social, , . . But when a society
Here, not ouly Js· the iustitium's evolution from the sta.te of exception is distnrbe-d by some painful crisis or by beneficent bnt flhrnpt transitions, iî
to public mournjng explained by the n:sembhmœ berureen the man­ fa rnomentarily incapnbk of exercising this influence; thence corne the sudden
ifestations of moumtng and those of anon.1ie ( which simply begs the :rises in the cmy2 of suî ...-ides whkh we have pointed out. , . , Anomie-, therefore,
question), but the ultima te reason for this resemblance is then sought fa a regufar and spedfü: factor in suicide in our modem sodetîes." (Durkheim
in the idea of an "anomie terror" said to cbaracterize human sodetfos 1,-897, :279-8Sh52-5S).
Thus, not only is the behv-een ano1rôe and anxiety taken for
as a whole. Such a concept (which is as inadequate to account for the
grnnted (white, :as we will see, et!U;vk,gkal and folklnüstic rcsearch shùw tht
spedfic:ity of ù1e phenomc-non as lvfarhurg thrology's tremendum and
contrary), but the possibfüty that anomie has a more inbma:tr and complrx re­
numinoswn we-re- to orient a çorrect underSta.nding ofthe divine) refers,
lation to law and the social order îs also rulcd out in adv,mcc.
in the last analysis, to the darkest spheres of psychology;
5.2 Equally inadequate are the <:ondusions of the study published by
TI1e total effocts of mouming ( especially for a ehief or king) and the
Seston a fow years 1ater. The atlthor seems to be aware of the possible
çomplete phèuomenoiogy of cyclkal tmnsitional- feaSts. . . . conform
politkal significance of the iustftium as public mourning, insofar as he
completdy lo the definitîon of anomy, . . . fEJ veryv.'here there is a
stage,s and drnm:atî:r,ç:s the funeral of the sovereign as a state of exception :
(temporary) reversai of the human to the non-human, the cultural
"In irnperfal funcrals there survives lhe mcmory of a mobilization . . . .
to the natural (viewed as i1s negative con1ra:,t) ) of kosmos to chaos and
Framîng the fnucrary rites with!n a sort of general mobilization, with
ofeunomyto anomy, , . . The feelings ofgriefand disorientation and
all civil affairs stopped and normal politkal Hfo s'uspende<l, the procla­
their individu al and collective expressi'ons arc not restricted to one
mation of the iu::titiwn tended to trnnsform the dea th of a man înto a
culture or to one type of cultural pattern. Apparently they are intrïn­
nalional calastrophe t a <lrama in which each person was involved, will­
sic features of humanity and the human conditîon, which manifest
ingly or uotn (Seston 1962, 171,-71). This intuition, however, cornes to
themselves ahove all in marginal or liminal situations, I would1 there­
nothfng, and the nexus between the nv-o forms of imtitium fa accounted
fore, gladly agree with V, W. Turner1 who) speaking of"unnatural-or
for by once presupposing that which was to be e:xpJained> that is,
rather) anti-cultural or anti-structural-•-events" în liminal situations,
an element of mourning implidt in the iustitlum from the start \ 172-73).
suggests that "perhaps Freud and Jung 1 in their different ways, have
Jt is Augusto Fraschetti's achievement to have underscored, in his
much to contdbute to the under:standîng of these nonlogical, non ­
nwnograpb on Augustus, the politirnl significancé of publk mounùng,
rational (bul not irrational) aspects of liminal sîtuatîons." (Versnel
shn\vi.ng tirnt the link between the two aspects. of the iustitiurn lies not in
1980, 604·•5)
a presun1cd character of mourning in C'Xtreme situations or anomie but
N In this neutrnlizatù:m of the juri<licul spediîcî ty of the -iustitiw-n by means of in the tumult tha l the sovereign's fün eral eau cause, Fraschetti recov­
an uncrhical psycbologistk tedu,;;tion, Versnel had heen preœded by.Durkheim, crs its origïns in the violent l'iots that had accompanied the funerals

\
68 Chapter Five
'
!\

,,

of Cacsar, which were si gnificantly described as "seditious funerals" the state of exception has become th-: ru]e) i '"c::xceptional measure'i dis­
(Fraschetti 1990, 57). Just as the iuslitium \\11lS the n,ltural response to appeared because they 1rnd bccome the rui,/' (Nissen 1877, 140). The
tumult in the Rt:pnblican era 1 "ît is clear how the ü.stitium cornes to be constitutional novehy of the prindpatc can ùms be secn as an in corpo­
îdentified with public mournîng through a similar strategy, by wh kh ration of the state of exception and anomie directly into the person of
the deaths in the dmnus Augusta are likened to civk catastro phes. , . . the sovcreign, ·who begins to free himself from atl snhordination tû th�
The upshot of this is tlrnt the bona and the ma/a of a single family corne 1aw and asserts himse.lf as legihus :iti!utus [ t1 nhonnd by the laws] ,
to be the rnncern of the res pub!ica" (57). Fraschetti readily shows how,
in conformity with this strategy, Augustus, beginning with the death of 5.3 The intimately anomie nature of tbis new figu re of supreme power
his nephe\v Marœll us, \vould prodaim n iustitium ev1:ry1îme the family appears dearly in the theory of the sovereign as '1livïng law" ( nMnM
mausoteum was opened. empsukhos), which îs ebbo-rated among the neo-Pythagoreans Ü:'l the
It is œrtainly possible to see the iu.stitium (in the sense of public same years that see the risc ofthe principate. The formub hnsileus nanws
morningî as nnthing ot,her than the sovereign's attempt to appropri­ emp5ukhos is fourni in Dîotogtm!-s's treadse on sovcrcignty, which was
ate the state of exception by trnnsforming it into a family affair. But the partially preserved by Stobaeus and 'Whose rdrvanœ to the origin of the
connection JS even more intimate and complex. modern theory of sovereignty must not h12 nnderestimated, The usual
Takei for example, Suetonius>s famous description of Augustus's phi1o1ogical myopia has preven lcd the modern editor of the trcatise
death at Nola on August 19 of the year 14 CE. The oid sovereign1 sur­ from seeing the obvious logicàl connection between this formnfo and
rounded byfriends and courtiers, has a mirror brought to him and) after the, anomie character of the sovereign; even though this connection is
having his ha.lr çombed and hîs s.agging cheeks made up, seems solely uncqnivncaUy stated in the text. The passage in questlon-corrupt in
concerned to know Whether he has acted the mimus vitae:, the "farce of part, yet nevertheless perfecdy ronsistent-is divided Jnto th rec point-;:
his life,i' well. And yet, <tlongs.ide this insistent theatrical metaphor, he (1) "The king is the most just [ dikaioMtcs I and the most is the most
stubborn1y and ahnost insolently continues to ask (identidem CXtJuir­ legal l nominuîtatos! ." (2) "\Ali thout jmttîœ no one can be king, but jus­
cn•;)--with what is not simplya pohtical metaph◊r-an iam dr. se tumul­ tice îs without Jaw f rmr:·11 11011wu dHmfostmP; Ddt11te's propos"�d insertion
tusfôrisfuisset1 ''if there wa'i now a tumult outsidc that conœrned bim.1' of the negative before dikaiosune is totatly un}ustified phUologîcallyJ ,"
The correspondence betv..een anomie and monrning becomes compre­ (3) ,;(The just is legitimate, and the king, having become the cause of the
hensiblc only in the li ght ofthe correspondenœ between the death ofthe just, is a living law" (L, Delatte 1942, 37),
soveretgn and the state of exr.ep tion, The original nexus betv✓een twtml­ That the sovereign is a living law can only mean that he is not bonnd
tus and iustitiwn is stm present, but the tumuit now coinddes '\vith the by it, that in bim the life of the lavv coincides with a total anomie. Dioto••
dealh of the sovereign, while the suspension of the law is integrated into gencs explains this a little 1ater with uneqnivocal darity: "Bcc:aust� the­
the füneral œremony. lt is as if the sovereign, who had absorbed into his king has an irresponsihle power [ a-rkhnn m111pctit.l11mon 1 and is himsclf
"august"' person all exo:ptional powers (from the tribunicîa potestas per­ a living lawi he is Hke a god among me1l' (L. Delatte 1942, 39), And yct)
petua [perpetual trilmnkial power] t0 the imperim11 proconsolarc maius predsely hecause he is iden Lîfied with the la\:v, he is hdd în refation lo
et infinitum [greater and endless proconsular imperi11m ] ) and who had, it and is indeed posited as the anornic fonnùation of the juridkal or<ler.
so to speak, become a thring iustitium, shoWed bis intimate ,momie char­ Thç identification bet\veen s.overcign and law repn:sents; that is, tbe first
acter al the moment of his death and saw tumult and anomie set free attempt to assert the anomie of the sovereign and, at the same tim;:, bis
outside of him in the city. As Nissen had intuited in a limpid formula essential link to the juddicai order, The nomos cn,p,·ukllos îs the orig­
( which is perhaps the source of Benjamin's thesis according to which inal form of the nexus that the state of exception estabHshes betweeo
70 drnpkr Fivc Fea\t, MonrnJng, Anomie 71
an outside and an inside of the law, and in this sense it constîtutrs the s.overeign is a tyrant, the magistrate is. not in c,mfonnity \Vith the law ant1
ar,,::het ype of the modern theor y of sovereignty. the communîty is 1rnhappy. {A. Debtte- 1922, 84_)
The co1rresp<m<J er1ce bctween iustitimn and mourni ng shows lts tnw
rneanjng hcrc, If the sovereign is a living nomos, and if1 ,for this reasoni By me.ans of a coinplex: strategy, which is nOt witho:it analogies to Paul's
anomie and 11m11os· perfoctly coinddc in bis person 1 then anarchy (whkh ,:;rltique of the Je,;vish t1{1mas (thi.s proxirnityis aiso at times textmll: Romans 3:21:
khOris nomou dikair,sunê; D-iotogcnes: ,mru nomott dikairmmC; and in Pseudo::
threatens to loosc itself in thcdty upon the sovereign's dealh, which is to
Archytas the law ls defined as a '"'letter," gmmma, çxactly as ln Paul), anPmic
s<1 y, whcn the nexus that joins it to the law is sevcred) must be rilualize-d
elemellts are introduced into thl'.' po!is througil the person of the sovcrcign, with
-and controlled, transforming the state of exception into public monm­
evidendyno effe.::t on the prim1Ky of the iwmo, (the sovcff'ïgn is ) Jndeed, "living
ing and monmlng into iustitium, Corresponding to the undeddability
l.av/").
of nornos and ,momie in the living body of the soverf·ign is the undc­
cidability between state of exccptfon and public mourning in the dty, 5,4 The secret solidarity between anomie and law cornes to light in an­
Refore assuming its modern form as a dedsion on the emergency, the other pht.-:nomenon, whkh represents a symmetrical and jn some ways
relation between sovereignty and state of exception appears in the form inverse figure to the lmpcrial iustitiunr Folklorists :md anthropülogi.sts
of an identHy between 1he sovereign and anomie, Because he îs•a living have long been famiHar with those periodic feasts (such as the Antheste­
law, the sovereign is intimatdy m10tn()s. Herc too the state of exception rfa and Saturnalia of the dass:ical wodd and the charivari and Ca.rnival
is th<>-secret and lruer-Hfo of the lnw, of the medievaJ and modern world) that arc charncterized by unbridled
lîcense and the suspension afül overturning of normal 1egal and social
� The thcsis that ''the sovereign is a living law" fnund ils first formulation in hierarchies. During these tèasts ( which are found with similar chan1c­
the treatisl;! by Pseud,H\n:hytas On Law and Justia, whicb was preserved for teristks in various epochs and cultures), men dress up and beh ave Hke
us by Stohaem a long with Diotogt'nes's treatise on "over<:ignty. Wbe:-her or not animals, masters serve tbeir slaves, males and females exchange roles;
· Grnppc's hypothr,sis th;n th ese rre:1tises wcrc composeà by an Alexa;1drîne Jcw and criminaJ behavior is considered lkit or, in any case, not punishable.
in the first cenlury of <rnr cra is corred1 it is certain that we arc dcaling with'r; That is) they inaugurale a perîod of anomie that breaks ,md temporarily
· group of texts thnl, tmder lhc -::ov,:r ofP!atonk and Py!hagou:JH catcgories, scck subverts the social order. Scholan hê1ve alwr1ys had dif.ficulty explain­
t(i lay the foundafüms for a conception of wn:rcignty that is cntfrely unbmmd
ing these sudden anomie explosions within welJ.-ordered socîeties and,
by laws ,md itnlf th1: a somce of lt'gitimacy In Pseudo-Archyt,1s'to tcxt this
above a!!, why the, wotùd be tolerated by both the religious and civil
is c:xpressed in rhe distînctfo:1 hctwcrn the s0vc,·e!f,c { iM;,ileus), who is the law,
authorities,
and the rnagistratc (a1·ki1{in), who ntu;;t only observe the law, 'I11t: iùcutification
Contrary to thnse intcrpret:ations that traced the anomie foasts back
betw«en rh.,,� h:w ;rn d tht: soverclgn Jeùds to rhe ,Jlvision o( the law into a hicrnr"
lo agrnrîan cycles tied to the solar co.lcndar (I\'iannhardt, Frazer) or to a
chicàUy supcrior "Hvlng" law {n011u,s. cn•f'511klrrcs) and a written law (r,mmma)
that 1S suhordinatc to it: periodk fonction of p11rification (VVestermarck}, Karl 1v1euH, with a bril�
liant intuitiot).,. instead related them to the state of suspended law that
I say th,H éVt'l"f corurnonity i:- composed of an arkhün (the magjstrate whü characterh:ed somc archaic juridicn! institutions, such as the Germanie
commitnds), one who :is comrnandcd, aml, third}y, the laws. Of thesc last, the Fricd!osigke-it or the persecution of the tvargus in andent English law.
living une ls the 5-0ve,-cigu Ow men cc1p,11kt10,, in basiirns) and the Jnanimate tn a scries of exempfary studies, he showed how the disturbances and
one is the lefü:r (gramma). The hnv hdng the fi Nt elemrnt, the king is lcgal-, violent acts meticulously listed ln medieval description s ofthe charivari
the maglsl rate 1$ in conf,,mü!y (wîth the law), the nne who is commandr.:d and other anomie phenomena precisely replicate the different phases
is frec and the entire is happy; but j( there is any deviatkm, then the of the cruel ritual in which the Friedlos and the bandit were expelled
l

72 Chapter Five Fo,,;.t, Mourning, Anomie 73


from the community, their houses unroofed and destroyed, and their the thret-hold of inùifferenœ between anomk an<l law. In showi11g the
wells poîsoncd or made brackish. The harlequinadcs described in the momnful character of every feast and rhie fies.rive character ofall 1nourn­
unprccedented chalivali of the Roman de Fauvel (Li un montret sort cul ing) law and anomie show their distance andi at the same time, their se­
au vent tLi autre rompct 1111 auve11t1 L'un rassoit fenestres et huis, /
/ cret soHdarity. It is as if the universe of huv-and more generaJly) the
L'autre getoit le sel ou puis, / L'un gctoit le bren aus visages; / Trop estoient sphere of humru1 action insofar as it has to do with law--ultimateJy
fès et smwages [One showed hïs nss to the win<l, / Another smashed a appearcd as a field of forces traversed hy t'vv'ü con_joined ;tnd opposite
root� J One broke windows and doors, / Another threw salt in the wells, tensions: one that goes frotn norm to anomiei and another that Îeads
1 And another threw fil th in faces; / Theywere trnly horrible and s,wage] ) frorn anomie to the: law and the rule. Bence a double paradigm, whkh
cease to appear as parts of an innocent pandemonium, and one after the marks the field of law with an essential amhigulty: on th l:' one haml) a
other find their counterpan and lhdr proper context in the Lex· Baiu­ normative tendency in the strkt sense i which ainrs at crystallîzing itself
variorum or in the penaI statu tes of the medieval chics. The samc can in a rigid system of norms whose connection to life is, however, prob­
be said for the acts: of h:mtssment cornmitted durfog maske<l feasts and lematk îf not impossible ( the perfoct state of law, in which everything is
children's bcgging rituals in which childrcn punished whoever denied reg1ùated by norms); and, on the other band, an anomie tendency that
their ohHgatlûn to brive a gifi with acts of violence that Halloween only leads to the state of exception or the idea of the sovereîgn as living law,
distantly recal]s, in whkh a force�of-Jàw: that is without norm acts as the pure inclusion
of life,
Charivari îs one of the many fü'U11es (whkh vary from country to
The anomie feasts dramatizc this irredudble amhiguity of juridica1
country and region to r1.-5ion) for an andent and widdy dîffused
systems and > at the same time, shmv that \,,hat is at stake jn the dfalectic
act of popu!ar justice., whkh occurred everY¼'here in similar) if not
between these two forces is the very rela tfon betw<:'e-n l;;w and life. The-y
identical fùrms. Snch forms are also used as ritual punishments in
ce-lebrate and parodirnl1y rep]kate the anomie through which the law
the cyclical mJsked foasts and their extrerne oftShoots, the traditional
applies itsdfto çhaos and to Hfo only on the condition ofmaking itself,
children's he-gging rituals; one'may therefon: immediately draw upcm
in the state of ex:cep1 ion, Hfe and living chaos. And perhaps the moment
these for an înterpretatiori of charivari-like phen.o me.na. A doser
has come to try to bctter understand the constitutive fiction that-in
analysis shows that what al firs t sight seemed simply to be rough and
bin<ling together norm and anomie, law and state of exception--also
wild acts ofharassmeut are in Lruth well-defined traditional customs
ensures the relation belween law and life.
and legal fonns1 by means of which 1 from timc immem.orfr,l� the ban
and proscription were carrîed out. (M_euD 1975, 473)
If !',4euli.'s hypothcsîs is correct 1 the ' legal anarchf' of the anomie
1

foasts does not refer back to andent agnuian rites, which in themselves
explain nothing; ralher, it brings to light in a parodie form the anomie
within the law, the st ate of emergency as the anomit.� drive c.antained in
the very heart of the nomos.
That is: to say, the ,mom ie feasts point toward a zone in which life's
maximum subjection to the 1aw is ,reversed into freedom and îiœnse,
and the most 1.mbrüllerl anomie shows Jts parodie' connectîon v.rîth the
nomos. Jn other words, they point toward the real stale of exception as
Au,;toritas am[ Pntesta� .75
6 l'Î Attctoritas and Potestas to define the president of the Reich's neutr<1l power in the state ofcxœp­
tion by dialectkally opposing auctoritas and potestas, After recalling that
hoth Bodin and Hobbes were still able to appreciatc the meanJng of the
dlstJnctioni Schmitt lamented (in words that anticipate Arendt's argu­
ment) ''th e lack of trad ition of the modern theory ofthe state1 wb ich qp­
poses authority and freedom, authority and democraçy , . . to lhe point
6,1 ln our analysls of the state of exception in Rome, we neglected ta of confming authority wüh dictatorship" (Schmitt 1931, 137). Already in
ask what was the foündation of the Senate's power to suspend the law his 1918 treatise on consti1 utional law, though without defining the op­
hy mcans of the scn,rtus ammltum ultinmm and the conscquent procla­ position, Schmitt evoked its "greM importance in the general th.:ory of
mation of a iustitium. VVhocver may have bcen the subject qualificd to the state:' and referred back to Roman law to descrfüe it ("the Senate
declare a iustitimn, it is certain that it was always dedared ex auctoritote had aurt()rittJS; on the contrary, potestas and imperium derive from the
patrum. Indeed, it is well known that in Rome the term designating the people" '. Schmitt 1928 ) 109] ).
Senate's most proper prerogative was neither impcrium nor potestas, but ln 1968, in a stu<ly of the ide.a of ,mthority pubiished ln a Fc�gabe for
auctoritas: aucioritas patru1n is the s.yntagma that defmès the spedfic Schrnitt's eighrieth year> a Spanish schoiar, }csus Fueyo, note<l t:h at the
fonction of the Sena te in the Roman constitution. modern confusion of auctoritas and potestrts ("two concepts that cxpres.s
In both the history oflaw and, more general1y, philosophy and pofüi� the orlginary sense through which the Roman people conœived their
cal theory1 all attempts to definc this category of auctoritas--•·-particu1arly comnmnal life" [Fueyo 1968, 2131 ) and their convergence in the concept
in contrast to potcstas..-seem. to run into almost insnrmountable obsta­ of sovereignty " was the cause of the phiiosophkal inèonsistency in the
des and aporias. "It is particularly difficult t'' wrote a French legal histo­ modern theory nfthe state"; :md he imme<liatel y- added 1haL lhis·confu­
rian at the beginning of the 1950s, "to brîng the various juridkaJ aspects sion ''is not only academic1 but is doseJy bound up wîth th e real process
0f the notion of aucwritas backto a unitary concept" (ti.1.agdelain 1990, thal has lc<l to the formation of the politirnl order of modernity" ( 213),
685); and; ut the end ofthat decade; HannahArcndt could open her essay What we m'ùst now try to understand is the meaning of this '-'confusion"
"What ls Authority?" with the observation that authority had "van.ished t1Jnt is hrnm<l up with the retlection and poJitîcal praxis of th e "West
from the modern world» to such an extent that in the absenœ of any "au­
thentk and indisputablë' ex.perk"llce of it, "the very term has bccome N: ft is a commonly held opinion that the concept of auctoritas is specîfically
douded by contmversy and confusion" (Arendt 1961, 91). Theœ is pcr­ Roman, jmt ris it i� cliché to refer to Dio Cassius in order to denrnnstrate its un­
t!'<lnslatabilîty intn Gretk. But dcspite wb<it is n:'peatedly daimed, Din ü1:rniHs,
haps no better confirmation of this confusion•--and of the arnbiguities
who ha<l :.n ex,:el lfnt knowledge ofRom;m law, does not say thal ùte tèr/TJ -is im­
that it cntails-than the fact that Arendt undertook her reeva luation of
possible to tnm,slate; he says, rather, that it omnot be trnns-lated krithàp-ax, "'once
autlwrily only a few years aftcr Adorno and Else Frenkel-Brunswick had
and for :111" ( hdlênisnî rwtn knthapnx od1mr.ton csti [ l?/lmrm Hisfwy 55.3,s ] ) . 11w
conducted their frontal attack on ''the authoritarîan personalîty." On the
implication here is that it n-JL1st be rendered in Greek with a differenl tcnn e:ach
other hand, in forcefully d�nouncing '"the lîherat identification of total­ tïme, depcnding on the context� whkh is obvions, giv-cn the wide f(;èd ch of the
itarianlsrn ,vith authorltarianism" (9iL Arendt probahly did not realize concept. What Dio ha.� in mind, therefore-, is not somcthing like a Roman
that she shared this dennndation with an author whom she certainly ficity of the krm but the dfffkuhy ofleading it back to a single meanlng,
disliked.
H
Indeed 1 ln 1931, in a book bearing the significant title Der . üter der 6.2 The definition of the problem is rnmplicated by the fact that the
Ver/a,sung (The guardian of the constitution) , Carl Schmitt had tried concept of twctoritas refers to a relativeîy broad juridical phenomenol-
76 Chapter Six Auctoritas and Pote.sfa$ 77

ogy) whkh conccrns both pr ivate and public law. IL wîll be best to begin It has bccn rightly notcd tlrnt auctoritns has nothing to do with repre­
our an_alysis with the former) and then to see if it is possible to lead the sentat1on ) whereby the ac1s performed by a mandatary or by a leg:11 rep­
two aspects back to unity, resentative are im p uted to the mandator. The fllfftor 1s act is not founded
In the sphere of private law1 auctoritas is the property of the auc­ upon some Sort of legaJ p ower vested in him lo act as a rep resent'ative
to,; that is, the person sui iuris (the pater familias) who intervenes--­ ( of the min or or the incompetent ) : it s priri gs directl y from bis cond.iti qn
pronouncing the tedmkal formula auctM fto rT am made auctor ]-in as pater, In the same way, the act of the seller, who intervenes as auctor
order to confer legal validity on the act of a subject who cannot inde· to defend the bu yer, has nothing to do with a right of guarantee in the
pendently bring a legally valid act into being. Thus, the auctoritas of the modern sense. Pierre Noailles, wbo had sought in the last years ofh..is Hfe
tutor makes valid the act of one who lacks this capadty1 and the auc­ to outline a unitary th:eory of rmctoritns in privnte iaw, coukl therefore
toritas of the father '\rnthorizes11-tJ1at is,, makes valîd-thc marriage of write that it is "an attribute attached to the pcrson, and originally to the
the son În potcstate. Analogously, the seller (in a moncipatio) is hound physical person, . . . the privilege, the right that belongs to a Roman,
to assist thi; buyer in confirming his tîtle of ownership in the course of under the required conditions, to serve as a foun<lation for the let;a1 sit­
a daim proceeding involving a third opposin g party. uation created by others" (Noailles 1948, 274), "Like ail the powers of
The term dcrives from the verh augeo: the auctor is is (JUi auget, archaic law;' he adds ) ''be they fomîliat prîvate> or p ublic, audoritas too
the person who augments ) increases, or perfocts the act-or the legal v.<as oriiinaHy conceivcd according to the unilateral modei of Jaw pure
situation-of someone el:;e. In the section of his Jndo-Europcwi Lan­ and sîmpll\, wil'hout obHgation or sanction" (274), And yet we need only
guage and Society dedicated to Jawi Benveniste sought to show that reflect on the formula aurtor fio (,rnd not s:imply auctor sum [I am auc­
originally the verb augeo (which, in the !ndo-European area, is signif­ tor]) to realize tllat it secms to imply not so much the voluntary exercîse
icantly related to terms that express force) "denotcs not the -increase of a rî ght a.s the actualîzntfon of an impersonal power [potenzal in the
in something which already exists but the act of produdng from one's very person of the auctor.
own breast� a creative act" (Behyeniste 1969, 1: 148/422). In truth, the
tvm meanings are not amtradktory at all in dasskal law. Indeed, the 6.3 As we have secn, in pnhlk law rmctoritas designates the most
Greco-Roman world does not know creation ex nihilo; rather. every act p roper prerogative of the Senate. The active snbjects of this preroga­
of creation always involves something else-formless matter or încom­ tive are thercfore the J>atrcs: tmctoritas patrum and patres at1ctores fiunt
plete being-that must be perfected or made to gmw. Every creation [ the fathers are made a11dors l are common formulas for expressing the
is always a cocrcation1 just as evcry author is always a coauthor. As àmstitutional function of the Sena te. Legal historians have nevertheless
Magdeiain has effectively written, ''[A}ucf<liitas is not suffü:ient in it­ always had difficulty defining this fonction. Mommsen observed that
self; whether it anthorizes or ratifies, it împlies an extraneous activity the Senate does not h:rvc an ;;iction of its own but cm act only in concert
t11at it validates" (Magdelaîn 1990, 685). lt is, then, as if for something to with the magistrnte or to com plete the dedsions of popular camitia by
exist in lav>" there must be a relationship betwee:n two elemenu ( or two ratîfying laws, The Sena te cannot express itself without being questioned
subjects): one endowed wi th a11ctoritas and one that takes the initfative hy the magistrates and can onJy request or "colmseY1-consultmn is the
in the act in the strict sense. Ifthe tvm elements or two suhjects coindde, technical term-,vithout this "counsel 1" ever being abso!utely bînding.
then the act is pcrfect. H0wever, if there is a gap or incongruity between f The formula of the scnat us co11srtlt11m is ri cis videatur; "if it seems right
them, the act must be completed wîtb auctoritas in order to be valid. } to them [i.e., the magistratesa] ''; in the cxtreme cnse of the senatus con­
But where does the "force" of the auctor come from? And what is this sultum ultimum, the formu la is slightly more emphatic: videa11t consules
power to augere?
:j [let the consuls see to h î. Mommsen expresses this pecullar character of
78 Chaptcr Six Auctoritas and Potestas 79

auctoritas when he writes that it is "less than an order and more than a the iustiti11m produces a tru.e and proper suspension of the juridical or­
counsel" (Mommsen 1969, 3: 1034). der. ln particular, the consuls arc re<luced to the condition of prîvate
It is certain, in any case) that auctoritas has nothing to do with the citizens (in privato abditi), while every private citizen acts as if he were
potestas or the imperium of the magistrates or the people. The senator invested with an imperium. With an inverse symmetry, in 2u BCE, at
is not a magistrate, and we nearly never fin d the verb iubere [to orderL Hannibal's approach, a senatm rons1rlt11111 resnscitates the imperh1m_ of
which defines the decisions of the magistrates or the people, used for the'former dictators > consul �, ,md censors· (placuit omnes qui dictatores,
his "counsels." And yet, with a strong analogy to the figure of the auctor co11s11lcs censoresve f11issc111 cum imperio esse, dance rccessisset a muris
in priva te law, the auctoritas patrum intcrvenes to ratify the decisions of hostis [It was decreed that all who had been dictators, consuls, or cen­
the popular comitia and make them fully valid. A single formula (auctor sors should have i 111perif!111, until the enemy had withdrnwn from the
fia) designates both the action of the tutor that complctcs the act of the walls] [Livy 26.10.9] ). Under extreme conditions (that is to say, under
minor and the senatorial ratification of popular decisions. The analogy the conditi ons that best de.fine it, if it is true that a legal institution's
here does not necessarily mean that the people must be considered as truest character is always defined by the excepti on and the extremc sit­
min ors un der the tutelage of the patres; rather, the essential point is that uation) auctoritas seems to act as a force tha t s11spends potestas whcre it
in this case too there is that duality of elements that in the sphere of took place and reactivates it where it was no longer in force. It is a power
private law defines the perfect legal action. Auctoritas and potestas are that suspends or reactivates law, but is not formally in force as law.
dearly distinct, and yet together they form a binary system. This relation�at once one of exclusi.on and supplementation­
betv,'een auctorîtas and potestas is also found in another institution in
N' The polemics among scholars who tend to unify the auctoritaspatrum and the which the a11ctoritas patrum once again sh mvs its peculiar fonction: the
auctor of private law under a single paradigm are easily resolved if one considers interrcgnum. Even after the end ofthe monarchy1 when, because of death
that the annlogy does not concern the individual figures, but the very structure or whatever other reason, there remained no consul or other magistrate
of the relation between the two elements whose integration constitutes the per­ in the city (except the representativcs of the pl ebs), the patres n11rtores
fect act. Jn a study from 1925 thar had a strong influence on Roman scholars, (that is, the group of senators who belonged to a consular family, as
Richard Heinze describcd the common element between the minor and the opposed to the patres conscrip ti [con script fathers] ) named an interrex
people with these words: "The minor and the people are determined to bind who ensured the continuity of pmver. The formula used ,vas n?s puhlirn
themselves in a certain direction, but their bond cannot corne into being with­
nrl patres redit rThe republic returns to the fathers ] or m1spicia ad patres
out the collahorntion of another subject" (Heinze 1925, 350 ). That îs to say, it is
redeunt [The auspices retum to the fathers] . As Magdelain has writ­
not that scholars tend to "depict public law in the light of private law" (Biscardi
ten, "During the in terrcgnum, the constitution is suspended . . . . The
1987, 119), but that there is a structural analogy that, as we will see, concerns
Republic is without magistrates, ,vithout Sennte, without popular as­
the very nature of the law. Jmidical validity is not an originary characteristic
semblies. Then the senatorüd group of the patres meets, and sovercignly
of human actions but must be conveyed to them through a "power that grants
legitimacy" (Magdelain 1990, 686). names the first interrex, who in turn sovereignly names his own succes­
sor" ( Magdelain 19901 359-60). Here too, auctoritns shows its connec­
6.4 Let us try to better define the nature of this "power that grants tion with the suspension of potcstns and, at the same timc, its capacity
legitimacy" in its relation to the potestas of the magistrates and the peo­ to ensure the functioning of the Republic un der exceptional drcum­
ple. What previous attempts to understa nd this relation have not taken stances. Once again, this prerogative rests immediately with the patres
into account is precisely that extreme figure of auctoritas that is at issue auctorcs as such. Indeed, the first interrex is not invested with the im­
in the senatus consultum 11ltimum and the iustitium. As we have seen, perium of a magistrate, but solely the auspicia (356); and in asserting
Bo Chapter Six Aurtoritns and P-Olt!Sfas 81

aguinst the p!ebians the importance of the mtspicia, Appius Claudius tas as the foundation of his st:atus as princrps-that we can beHer un­
states that they belong personaHy and exclusivefy ta the patres priva­ derstand the meaning of this uniqne prero g:atlve. It is signîfican1 that
tim: "nnbis adeo propria sunt auspicia, ut . . , privatim rmsf'icia habea­ the rehirth of modern studies of auctoritas coincides pn:dst'ly with the
mus [The auspices bdong so properly to us that . . . we have them as publication ln 1924 of the 1\tfamtmcntwn Antiochct11m1; whkh aHowed a
prîvate dtizens]" (Livy 6,41.6), The power to reactivate vacant potestas more accurnte recous:trnction of the passage in question, The issue he.re
is not a legal pnwer received frorn the people or a magistrate but springs conce-med a series of fragments of a L.ttin in:scdption conrnining ;i pas­
immediately from the persona! condition of th e pattes. sage from chapter 34 of the Réi gesta c, which was extant in its entirety
only in the Greek version, Mommsen had reconstructe<l the LaLin lext
6.5 A thir<l institution in whkh auctoritas shows its spedfic fonction in these terms: "post id ternp11s P"aestiti ornnilms dÎgnitme (:axî5rnatî),
of s'>uspen<ling law is the hostis iut!icatio. In exceptionul :;ituntions where potestatis autern nihif arnplius hr1bui ,pwm qui fiœrw1t mihi quoque in
a Roman citîzen threatened the sec.urîty of the Republic by <::onspîracy OI' nrngistmtu amicgcie [After that time I surpasscxl all ln dignifas, although
treason, he could be dedared hostis, "public enemyt hy the Senate. The I had no more potestas than those wJ10 were my colleagues in eJch mag­
hostis iudicatus was not simply Hkened to a foreign enemy, the hostis istracy],"' The An tiochean inscription shov,'cd tha t Augustus had wdtten
alicnigena1 because the latter was aJways protccted by the ius gentium not dignitate but ,mctoritme, Commenting in 192,5 on the new informa­
[law of peoples) (Nissen 1877 1 27); he was, rather� ra<licaHy deprived of tion� Heinze wrote, "Wc philologists shou!d all be ashamed for h-avlng
anylcgal status and could therefore be stripped ofhis belongings and put blindly followed lvfommsen's auth0rity: the only possible antithesis to
to dealh at any moment. \Vhat auctoritns suspends here is not sîmply the potestas--that ls, to the legal power of a magistrate--was; 111 this pas­
juridkal order) but the ius âvis, the very s'tatus of the Roman citizen, sage; not dignitas) but auctoritas" (Heinze 1,915, 348).
The relation-at onœ antagonistic and supplementary-betwcen As often happens-and. moreover, as scholars did not fail to ob­
auctoritas and potestas is -final1y shown in a tcrmino!ogical peculiarity serv�the rediscovery of the concept (no fower than fifteen important
tflat Mommsen was the first to' notice. The syntagma senatus auctoritas mm1ographs on auctoritas appeared in the following ten years) kcpt
is used in a technical sense to <l'esignnte a senatus co11suJt1fnt that, be­ pace -whh the gmwing ,veight thctt th.: authoritarian prindple was 'as­
cause it has heen opposcd by an intcrcessio, is without legal effects and smning in the pdlitical Hfe of European societies. "Auctoritas," wrote a
can therefore not be executed ( even if it was enlered as such among the German scholar in 1937, "that is, the fundamentai concept of public law
offidal acts, auctoritas perscripta ), That is, the auctoritas of the Senate in our modern authoritarian states1 can only be understood---1101: only
appears in its purest and most perspicuous form when it bas been in­ liter.:1lly but also as regards the cOntent-starting from Roman law t)fthe
validated by the pot est.as of a magistrate, v:hen it lives as mere -writing in tîme of the principate"' (Wenger 1939, 15z). And yet it is possible that this
absolute opposition to the law's being in fot<ce [vigenza], For a moment nexus hetween Roman law and out own politica[ e:Kperience is predsely
here audoritas shows its essence: the power lJwtenza] that tan at once what still remains for us to investigate.
"grant legltlmacy" and suspend law e:xhibits its most proper character
at the pofot of its greatest iegal inefficacy, lt is what remains of law Ïf 6.7 If we now return to the passage from the Res gestne, the decisive
law is wholly mspended (in this sense; in Benjamin1s readîng of Kafka's point is that here Augustus defi nes the tipecitidty of hîs rnnstituHonal
allegory, not law but lifo.-law that blurs at every point with lifo). power not in the certain terms of a potestas, whkh he says he shares.
with those who are his colleagues in the rnagîstracy, but in the vaguer
6,6 It is perb,1ps in the auttoriras principis-that is, in the moment terms of an auctoritas. The meaning of thé name "Augustus,"' which the
when Augustus, in a famous passage of the Res gestae, daims a-uctori- Senate confcrred ou him on January 16, 27 BCE, accords entirely with
82 Chapter Sb: Auctorîf(IS and PvttstJ.1s ll-3

this daim: it cornes from the sam c root as augeo and aucti:ir and, as Dio hirn something like a prîvate Hfe and domu.s. This is also the sense in
Cassius notes, "doe.s not rriean a pntestûS [dunamis ! , . . but shows the v,:hkh one must interpret the fact that a sîgnum to Vesta is dcdicated in
splendor of cmàoritas [ tën f(!U axitimntos lamprotëta1" (Roman History the house of Augustus on the Palatü1e. Fraschctti has rightly ol:;.served
53.18.2). that, given the dof'le connectîon hetween the cult of Vesta and the cult
In the edict of January 13 ofthe same ye.n, in ,Yh ich he <lccbres his in­ nf the puhlkPcnates of the Roman peoplc 1 tJ1is me.ant tlrnt the Penat"es
tentînn to rcstore the republkan constitution, Augustns defines himsclf of Augw;;tns's family wcre idenüfied with those of the Roman people
as op timi sto tf!S auctor [ am:tor of the highest standing] . As fvfagddaiu and that therefore "the private cnlts of a fomily . . , ,m d preeminently
has acutely ohserved > the term rmctor here does not have the generk communal cults in the sphere of the city (those of Vesta and the public
meaning of "founder;' but the technkal rnè;ming of "guarantor in a Penates of the Roman people) would seem in fact to become homolo­
mrmripatio,'T/ Because Augustu.s conceives of the restoratfrm of the Re­ güus in the ho use ofAugnstns" (Fraschetti 1990, 3i;9) , Unlike the Hfe of
pubHc as a transfor of the res pu Mica from his hands to those of the peo­ the common dtizcns, the '"augu.'>t" ]ife can no longer be dcfi.ned through
ple and the Senate tsee Res ge5f-r1e: 34.1 ), it is possihle that "in th e fonnnla the opposition of public and priva te.
auctor op timi status . . . the tenn auctor has a rather precise lcgal mean­
ing and refers to the idea of the trnnsfer of the res publica. . . . Augustus � lt is in this light that K:intorowicz's theory of the king\; two bodies should
would thus be the a11ctor of the rights rcudered to the people and the be t!:'read, sn that we rn1ï m«h- some refinem<-'nîs to k Kantor,.rwicz (who g1n,
Senate, Just as, in a m;mdpcition, thé mandpio dans is the ,wctor of the ertlily nndervalues the importance of the Roman prcœdcnt to the thoory !.hat
power acquired by the mancipio accipiens over thi: transferred object" he secks m recoristruct for the and French mon;m::foes) does not relate
(Magdelain 1947, 57). th.c distinction betwt"en fltfftnrit11s and Jmte�tn,; to the pn 1bkm of the kJng's two
ln any casc:1 the Roman prindpate-which we are used to descdbing hodies and thi;; prindple di.gnitas non mnfitur [ rlignitos does not die]. And yet
it is pr<:mc!y bccrnsc the sovereign w.as fin>t and forcmost the emhodîment of
with a term (emperor) thal rcf-ers back to the imperiwn of the magis­
au 11uctoritas_, and not solely of a pot(•stns, that aurtaritas was so closely hm.md
trat�i.s not a mag îstracy, but an extreme form of auctoritas. Heinze has
to his phy,;ical rerson, thus rcquJfing the complicai:cd rilua{ of constructing a
described thîs contrn.st perfectly: "Every magistracy is a preestablîshed
wax double of the sov<:Teign in the f111ms imaginariwn The end of a magistracy
form, ,vhkh the individnal en ters into and \•vhkh constüutes the source
r.s such doe!i not entai! a prnblem of bodies at all: One magistrntc suœeeds an­
of his power; tmctoritas, on the other hand, springs from the pcrson,
other tvithmit lrnving to pres11pr0se the irnmortaEty of the oflice, ûnly because,
as something that is constituted through him, Hves only in him 1 and
from the Roman princep:1 on, the <;OVt'reign exprf'sses '.m rmrtoritr15 Jn his very
disappears with him" (Heinze 1925, 356). Though Augustus receives ail pei·son, onî y beca\Jse in "aügust" life puhlic and pr1vate have en!cred into a zone
m.igistracies frorn the people and th e Senate, auctoritas is inste:i.d bound of absolute indistinction, docs it becomes 11ecessary to dh,thtgu'.sh two bodies
to his person an<l constitutes hirn as rmctor optimî status, as hc wh.o le­ in or<ler to ensme the contitiuity of dignifns (which is simply a synonpn for
gitîmat('s and gnan:mtees the whole of Roman politkal life. ,mrt(lritns ),
Bence the pecnHar status of hîs person, whkh manifcsts itself in a 10 understand modern phcnomena such as the Fascist Duce and the Nazi
fact ••1l1ose importance has not yet been fuHy appreciai-ed by sçholars, Fi1hre:; it is im110-rtant not to forger thei.r continuily with the prindpk of the
Dio Cassius informs us that Augusms "made al! ofhis house puhHc I t-ên nl!ctaritas prinripis, As. ·wc have a!rcady ohservcd, evcn thoogh Mussolini held
on:i:m edëmosiüsc pasanl . . . so as. to live at onœ in public and in pri� the office of he:,d o( the govermncnt and Hitkr that ùf ch,mœllor of thr: Re�
vate [ 11in' en tois ùiiois lumw kai en wls koinois Mkoie}" {Roman History kh (just as J\ugustus held imperl/1111 r11n:olare or pat!'strls trii11111ica) ndther the
It is the tmrtaritas that he ernbodi es 1 and not the magistrades Duce nor the F'ilhrcr represents. a constitntiono.lly defini:"<l puhlic office or mag­
with which he has been invested, that make it impossible to isolate in istracy. The quafüies of Duce or Ffih,.n· are imrne<liately brnmd to the physical
84 Chapter Six Auctoritas and Potfstas 85

person and bdong lo the biopolitkal traditlo11 of r111ctoritnç and not to the legal aJways orïginary and springs from his person; furthermore, in its i!ssence
tradition of pot('sta$. it is not coercive1 but is rather founded) as Tricpcl had already ,;;hovvn ,
on consent flnd the free acknowlcdgmcnt of a "superiority of value."
6.8 It is significant tlrnt moden1 scho!ars have been so ready to uphold Though both Triepel and De Francisci had fascist nnd Naû tech­
the daim that aurtnritas inheres lmmediately in the living person of the niques of government before their eycs, neither appears to bave h('en
pater or the princeps. VVhat \•vns dc.arly an ideology or a fictio _i ntended aware that the power they describe attains its appearanœ of original­
to ground the preemincnce or; in any case, the specific rank of auctori­ ity .from the suspension or neutrali:r.ation of the juridîcal order-that
tas in relntion to potcstas thus bccomes a figure of law)s immanence to is) ultimately, from the stnte ofex,:er•ll<m, "Charism.:{'-as its rcference
!ife, lt is not by chance that this should happen precisely in the years to Paul 's kharis (whidt Weber knew perfoctly well) could have
when the authorit.irian prindple saw an unexpectcd rebirth in Europe suggested-colncides with the neutraHzation oflaw an<l 1wt with a more
thmugh fascism and Nationa.l Sodalism. ·n1(mgh it was obvious that odgînary figure of pmver.
there cannot be some sort of eternaI human type periodkaHy embod­ ln each case, \.vhat the threc authors seem tü take for granted is that
ied in Augustus, Napoleon) or Hitler) and that there are only more or anthnritarian-charfamatic pmver springs alnmst mn gical!yfrom the very
less similar ]egal apparatuses (the statc of exception, the iustitium, the person of the Führer. Law's daim tbat it coincides at an eminent poînt
auctorïtas principis, Führertwn) that are put to use under more or Jess with life could not have been affinned more forœfutly. In thîs regard,
different drcumstauœs, the power that VVeber called «charismatic'' was ù1e !heory of mu:toritas convergcd at least in pi1rt wi1h the tradition of
nevertheless linked in 1930s GennanY {and elsewhere) to the concept jnridkai thonght that saw faw as ultinrntely identlcal with-or imme­
of auctoritas and elaborated in a theory of Führertum as die originary diately artkulated to-Hfe. Sav'1c11v s maxlm ( "'Law is nothing but Hfe
and persona] power of a leader. Thus in 1933, in a short article that seeks considered from a partkufar point of vieW") fin,:l s a çounterpart in the
to outline the fondamental concepts ofNatlünal Sodalism, Schmitt de­ twentieth century in Rudolph Srnend's thesis that "the norm receives
fines the prindple of flii/mmg tluc,ugh "the ancestral identity between the gmunds of its validity jGclwngsgnmd'. , the quality of its validity,
leader and followers" (note the use of Weberian concepts), 1938 saw the and the content of its validity front life and the seuse attributed to it,
publication of the Berlin jurist Heinrich Triepel's book Die Hegemonie, just as, inversely, Hfe mu st be underntood only in relation to its ai:;signed
whkh Schmitt quid<ly reviewe<l. ln ils first section, the book expounds a and regulated vital sense {Lebc11ssi11n]" (Smend 1956 1 300). Just as 1 în
tlwory of Fiii1rertwn as an authority founded not on a preexisting order Romantic ideology, something like a !anguage becnme fülly compre­
but on a personnl drnrisma. The F/1//rer is define<l through psychologi­ he.nsîble only in its immediate relation to a people (and vice versa) ) so
cal categories ( energetic ) conscious, and creative wHit and hîs unitywith iaw and Hfe must be tightly implicated in a redprocal grounding. The
the soda! group and the originary and personal character ofhis power dialectk of m1ctoritas and potestos expresscd precisely this implication
are strongly underscoml. (and in this sense, one can speak of an originary biopolitical charactcr
Then in 1947, the elderly Roman scholar Pietro De Francisô pub­ of the pHradîgm of auctoritas) , The norm can be applied to the normal
lished Arcana imperii, În whkh he dedic.ates a good deal of spaœ to an .situation and can be su spendcd without totally annulling the juridical
aualysis ofthe "prirnarytype" ofpower that he {seeking to distance him­ order bernuse in the form of m1rrMitas, or sovereign decision, it refers
self from füsdsm with a sort of euphemism) defines as duttus (and the immediatcly to litèj it springs from lîfe.
leader in which it is cmbodied as ductor). De Frandsci transfonns the
\.-Veberian tripartition of power (traditiona!, legal, charismatic) into a 6,9 It is perhaps possi hle at this point to look back upon the path trav­
dichotomy drawn on the opposition of anthority and povver [potest'à J , eled thus far and drnw some provi.sional con clusions from our investi­
�n1e authoritr of the ductor or the FWm.:r can never be derivatîve but is gation of the state of exception. The jurldkal system of the \,Vest ;ippears
86 Chapter Six

as a double structure, formed by two hctcrogeneous yet coordinated d­ t.îme. Indeed> the state of exception has today reache<l its m,:rximum
ernents: one that is normative and juridical in the strict sense (·which we vwrklwî<lc deployment. The normative aspect oflaw can thus be obliter­
can for convenience inscrfüe under the ru bric pntestas) and one that !s ated and contradicted with lmpunîty by a governmemal vioh:ncc tlrnt­
anomîc and metajuridkal (which we can caH by the name auctoritas) . while ig noring international faw externaHy and produdng a permanent
The normative element needs the anomie elemcnt in order to be ap­ state of exception intcrnall y-nevertl1eless still daims to be ap plying
plied, but, on the ()thcr hand, auctodtM can assert itself only in the val • th e law.
îdation or suspension of potestas. Because ît results from the <lialectk Of course, the task at han<l is not to bring the state of exception ba ck
between the.se two somewhat antagonistk yet fun ctionall y com1ected lvithin its spatiall y and temporal1r defined boundnrie:s in order to then
elementsj the ancient dwelling oflaw i.s fragile andi in strnining to main� rçaffirm the primacy of a 110rm and of rights that are themsdves ulti­
tain its ovm order, îs always already in the process ofruin and decay. The mately grounded in it. From the re,îl state of exception in which wc live,
s!ate of exception is the device tha t must nltimately articulate and hold it is not pnssib!e to return to the state of law [;;tat(I di dirirtaJ, for at issue
together the Iwo aspects of the juridico-political machine by instituting now are the very concepts of "state" and ,,;law.n But if it is possfüle to
a threshold of undeddabîlity between anomie and nomos, hetween Iife attempt to halt the machine, to show its central fiction, this js h,:cmise
and law, lx�tvveen auctoritas and potestas. It is foun ded on the essential between violence and law, het\veen iife and norm, therc is no suhstantfol
fiction accordîng to which anomie {in the form of ouctoritas, living Jaw, articulation. Alongsîde the movcmt'nt thal seeks to ke.-,..p thcrn in rela­
or the force oflaw) is still related to the juri<l ical order and the power to tion M all costs; there is a counterrnovement that) working in an inverse
sus-pend the norm lus an immediate ho-!d on lifr. As long as thè two el­ 1.Ürect.ion in law and in life> ahvays seeks to loosen vArnt has been :artifi­
ement,;; rem.ain corre1ated yct conceptually1 tempora1ly, and subjectively cially and violently linked. That is to say, in the field of tension of our
distinct (a.s in republican Rome\ contrast betweeu the Senate and the culture, two opposite force,s act:, one that institutes and makes i and one
people, or in medieval Europe's contrast hetween spiritual and 1emporal that deactivates and depose.s. The sfate of cxœp tkm is both th<> point of
i,01.vers) thdr dialectk-thouglffounded on a fi.ction-can neverthcless their maximum tension and-as it colnddes witb the ruk-that -which
function in smne vtay. But when "they tend_ to coindde în a single per­ threatens today to render them indiscernihle, To Hve in the state of ex•
son) when the state of exception, în whkh thcy are bound and hlurred ception mear:s to e..xpericnce hotb nf these possibHities a nd yet, by always
together, bccornes the rule, then the juridico-politlcal system transforms separating the two forces, ceaselessly to try to interrnp t the ,vorking of
itself into a killing machine, the machine that is leading the West toward global civil war.

6.10 The aim of this investl gntion-in the urgency of the state of ex� 6.11 If it is true that the articulatfon between life and law1 between
œption "în whkh we 1ive"-was to brîn.g to light the fiction that governs anomie and -nmnas, that is produced by the state of exception ïs effectjve
this nrcanum imperii [secret of powcrl pa.r excellence of mu timc. \-\lhat though fictional, one can still 11ot conclude from this that somewhere
the "ark" of power contains at îts œnter is the state of eiccption-but either beyond or before juridic:i ] :i pp aratuses there is an immedfatc ac •
this is: esse11tiall y an empty spàt:<:1 in which a human actj011 with no re­ œss to something whose fracture and impossible unification are repre­
lation to Jaw stands before a norm with no relation to Hfo. sented by these ap paratuses. Thcre are not first lifo as a natural biolog ..
This does not mean that the machine1 with jts empty center, is not ical g iven and anomie as the sta ( e of nature, and then their implkntion
effect ive; on tl1e contrary, what we have sought to show is p rcdsely th.at in !aw through the state of exception. On the contrary, the very pnssi­
ît has cûntinued to fonction almost without interruption from \-Vorl<l bîlîty of distinguishing life and lnw, ano n1ie: and nomos) coindde') with
\A/ar One, through fasdsm and National Sodalism, and up to our owr1 their articulation in the biopolitical machine, Barc lift! is à product of the
88 Chaptcr Six

machine and not something that preexists lt, just as law has no court in References
nature or in the divine mind. Life and law1 anomie and 1wmos, auctoritas
and potesta5i result from the fracture of something to whkh we have no
other acœss than through the fiction of their articulation and the patient
work thati by unmasking this fiction1 separates what it had daimed to
unîte. Bur disench,r ntment does not restore the enchantcd thing to its
original stale: According to the principle that purity never lies at the Ar;tt.gio-Rt;!z, Gm:txr-o. 1913. r,1i111'.":im; i di diritto C(1stit11zîonr1lf' itali1111u. Reprint, Milan:
Bocca, 1972.
origin, dîsenchantment gives it only the possibility of reaching a new
Att'ndt, H:m nab. 1961 . Betwccn Pas/ ,mr/ Futllrc. New York: Viking.
condition. J3:a!l-,ulore"Pilllin1, Giorgio. 1970. Dirittn c,mituziona!c. Milan: Ci:uffrè.
10 show law in îts nonrelation to Hfe and life in ils nonrelation to Bcngel, Johann Albm:ht. 1734. Vr.rrcdc zrir Hondausgabc des griuh ightH N. 1:
faw means to open a space between them for human action, which once Ben}amin, Wnlt(•r. 1921. Zur Kritik der G,�w;ilt. Jn Tie<lemann ,nHl Schwer,11 enhiu�er,
daimed for itself the name of "p-olîtics." Politics has suffered a lasting Gesam meftc Schriftcn, vol. 2, pt. 1. Transfated by Edrnun,l Jephu,tt as Critique :if
eclipse because it has been contaminated by law) seeing itselt: at bcst, violence. ln Sck:ted Writi11gs. vn!. 1, ;9;3-1916, ed. Man::ns Bnl!od: and Mkhstl W.
Jenning.\. C::imhridge: HnrvHd Univtn;ity Pres;:, Bdknap Press:, 1996.
as constituent pmver (that is, violence that makes law) 1 when it is not
--�. 1928. fJ•·tprimg dei, drnts:;lun ]hm2n1,,icls. In Ticdem:mn and $.:hwcppenh;tuser,
reduœd to merely the power to negotiate with the law. The only truly Gest1,n111<'hc Schrifrcn, vol. 1, pL 1. 'lramfated hy John Oshome as The ()rigili o Germ,:m
f

political action, however, is that whkh severs the nexus between vio­ 'fingk l>rama. I.ondon: Verso, 1998.
lence and law. And only beginning from the space thus opened wm it ----. 1931. Karl Knms, ln Ticdemunn :md Schweppenhânser, Gt':!amme!tc Sdnlftni, vol.
be possible to pose the question of a possible use of law after the "ieac­ 2, pt, 1. irnmlated hy t'.dn1nnd Jephœtt as Karl _Kraus. In S?ler:tc;l Writings, vol. 2,
tivation of the device that, in the state of exceptîon, tied it to lifo. We 1fu7-IJJ34, ed, Michael W: îcnnings, Howard Elfand, and Gary Smith. Cambridge:
Harmrd Utliversi1 y I'ress, Bdknap Pre;;s, 1999.
wm then have before us a "pure') law, in the scnse in which Benjamin --·- 1934. Franz Kafk:1. ln Tkdrm:mn and Schweppen{l.anscr, Gc;,,1 ,nmelte Sr:hr(ftrn,
speaks of a "pure" language and:? '"pure" violenœ. 'fo a wonl that does vnt 2, pt. t. Tnimlnted by Harry Zohr: <Vi f-r;_1 nz Kafka. ln SdectcA Writings. vol. z, ed,
notbind, tbat neither commands nor prohibits anylhing, but says only Michad \V. Jennings, Hown r<l EiLmd, and Gs1ry Smîth. Carnlni.! ge: Harvard
itselt wou]d correspond an action as pure means; which shows only it­ Gnivernity PreAA, Be!knap Prc�s, 1999.
self, witlmut any relation to an end. And, betw(�en the two, not a lost ---". 194z. Übi:r den Be_griff (Ier Geschii:hte. ln Tiedem;mn :md Schwcppenhii1JSer,
original state, but only the use and human praxis that the powers of law -Gesammelte S:-hrifr,m, vol . 1, 11t. 2. Transfatcd hy Harry Zohn ,v On the conœpl of
hJstory. In Selùttd i<\'ritings, v0L 4, 1:1}lH9.10, ed. Howard Eiland and Mkhad VV.
an'd myth had sought to c.apture in the state of exception,
Jrnt1ings, C1mhddge: ffarvmd Univcr�iry Press, Belknap Press, 1..003,
-··-. 1966. Bteife. 2 vo!s. F.d. Gernhom Scholrrn and The0do1 \-V. Adorn0, frnnkfmt am
Main: Sulwkmnp. Tnrnslilted hy iVfan fred R. J;ic<ihwn ,ind f'.\,eJrn M. Jacobson z:s The
CorrespDnd,mrc of Walter Be1rjamh1, ed. G1;-rsh0:11 Scholcm and Theodor W, ,\domo.
Chk:ago: University of Chlrnt,'O Press, 1994.
--, ,971-•89. Grsrrmmdrc .Srhriften. 7 vo!s. Ed. RolfTie<l<'lmmn ;1,-,d He.rm;;m,
Schweppenhàm.::r. Fnmkfort ::m M,1fn: Snhrkamp.
-�. ::9;;:;. No�iwn ?li dm;r 1\rbdt üb:-r die Kategorie der GeITchtigkdt. Fmnkfimer
Adorno maucr 4,
Benvrnisi-e, Émi\e. 1969. Le Fo,-,1b11!airr des itistitntùms tfido-cump,'c-:rmes. 2 voL•t Pnrl->:
Minnît Translakrl. by Ell?nbeth Palmer as Jndo- f;'uri1peim l anguag,: and S,,cif.ty. Coral
Gables, FL Univen;:ity oCtv:l irtm i Press, 1973.
90 References References 91

Biscardi, Arnaldo. 1987. A11taritas patrum: Pro/1/emi di staria del diritto p11[,l,/iro romm10. Nissen, Adolph. 1877. Dos fostitil/m. Eine Studic aw der riimiscl1c11 Rccl1 tsgcsâ1irhte.
Naples: Jovene. Leipzig: Gebhardt.
Bredebmp, Horst. 1998. Von W. Benjamin zu C. Schmitt. Deutsche Zeîtscl1riftfür No,1illcs, Pierre. 1948. Fas et Tu5. Éludes rie droit romain. Paris: Belles Lettres.
Philosophie 46. Plaum ann, Gerhard. 1913. Das sogennantc Senntm consultmn nltinmm, die Qm1sidiktatm
Delatte, Armand, 1922. Essai sur la politiq w pythagoricie1111e. Paris: Champion. der sp:itercn rOrnischen Republik. Klio 13.
Delatte, Louis. 1942. frs traités de la royauté d'Erphante, Diotogènc cl Stl1é11idns. Paris: Droz. Qnadri, Giovanni. 1979. Ln forzn di lcggC'. Milan: (;iuffrè.
De Martino, Fr:mccsrn. 1973. Storia della costitt1z1()nc romana. Naples: Jovene. Reinach, Theodor. 1885. De l'ctnt de sil'gc. Et11dc historique cl'j11rirliq11e. Paris: Pichon.
Derrida, Jacques, 1994. Force de loi. Paris: Galilée. Trnnslated by Mary Quaint;mce as Force Romano, Santi. 1909. Sui decreti-lcggc e lo stato di ,issedîo in occ;1 sione dei terremoti di
oflaw: The "mystical foundatîon of authority." Cardow Law Rei•iew 11, nos. 5 - 6 (1990). j\frssina e Reggio C1labria. In Srritti mi11ari. Vol. 1. Reprint, Milan: Giuffrè, 1990.
Drobische, Klaus, and Günther VVieland. 1993- System da NS�Konzentmtionslager ----. 1983. Frnmmenti di 1111 rlizionario gi11ridiro. Milan: Giuffrè.
1933-1939. Berlin: Alrndemie. Roosevelt, Franklin D. 1938. The PuMie Papcrs and Addresses, Vol. 2. New York: Random
Duguit, Léon. 1930. Traité de droit co11stit11tio1111c/, Vol. 3, Paris: de Boccard. House.
Du rkheim, Émile. 1897. Le Suicide. E.'t11de de sociologie. Paris: Akan. Transfated by John A. Rossiter, Clinton L. 1948. Co11.<tit11fÎ{1t11/l Dicta t(1rship: Crisis GMm1111rnt in tl1c .11,,fo dern
Spaulding and George Simpson as Suicide: A Study in Sodology. New York Free Press, Dcmocmrics. New York: Harcourt Bracc.
1951. Saint�Tlonnet, François. 2001. I'ftot d'exception. Paris: Presses UniYcrsitaires de France.
Ehrenberg, Victor. 1924. Monumentum Antiochen nm. Klio 19. Schmitt, Carl. 1921. Die Diktatur, i\fonich-leip:rig: Duncker & H11mhlot.
Fontana, Alessandro. 1999. Du droit de résistance au devoir d'insurrection. In Le droit de ---. 1922. Politisrl1e Theologic. Munich -1.cipzig: Oun chr & Humhlot; Translati'd by
résistance, ed. Jean-Claude Zancarini. Paris: ENS. (1Mrge Schwab as P()/itim! Tfteolog)'. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1985.
Fraschetti, Augusto. 1990. Roma c il principe. Rome-Bari: Laterza. ---. 1928. Vcrfnss1111gslchre. !Vlunich-1-cipzig: Dunckcr & Hrnnblot.
Fresa, Carlo. 1981. Provvisol"ietà con forza di leggc c gcstio11c degli stati di crisi. Padua: 1931 . Der Ifiitcr der Vnf11ss1 111g. Tiihingen: Mohr.
CEDAl\1, ---. 1995. Strwt, Groflrm1111, NPmos. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.
Friedrich, Carl J. [1941 ] 1950. Constitr1tiona/ G01-cr1Jme11t and Demorrary. 2nd. ed. Boston: Schnur, Roman. 1983- Rc1'0l11ti()lr 1111d \\'i·/1!,ii rgcrkricg. Berlin: Dtmckcr & Humblot.
Ginn. Schiitz, Anton. 1995. L'immarnléc conception de l'interprète rt 1'.Smergcnce du syslème
Füeyo, Jesus. 1968. Die Jdee des "Auctoritas": Genesis und Fntwicklung. In Epirrrhosis. juridique: À propos de fiction et construc1 inn en droit. Droits 21.
Fcstgabefiîr Carl Schmitt, ed. Hans Bafüm. Berlin; Duncker & Humblot. Seston, William. ·1962. Les dwvalicrs romains cl le ii1stiti11111 de Gennanicm. In Scripta
Gadamer, Hans-Georg, 1960. \\'11li rheil und Metfwde. Tübingen: Mohr. Translated hr Joel mrin. Reprint, Rome: Écok française de Rome, 1980.
\Vcinsheimer and Donald Marshall as Tmt/1 and Method. 2d rev. ed. New York: Smend, Rmlolph. 1956. fntcgrationslchrc. Tn Hm1dwiirtcrh11ch der Sozialwisse11srhaftcn. Vol.
Crossroads, 1989. 5. Stuttgnrt: Fischer; Tiihingcn: Mohr; GOttingen: Vnndcnhocck & Ruprecht.
Hatschek, Julîus. 1923. De11tsrhcs und Pre11ssîsrhes Staat.ffecht. Vol. 2. Berlin : Stilke. Tauhes, Jacob. 1987. Ad Carl Srl11nitt. Gegemtrc/1ige Ftïg1111g. Berlin: Merve-.
Heinze, Richard. 1925. Auctoritas. Hermes 60. Tingstcn, Hcrbat. 193·1· Les pleins pmll'Pirs. I.'cxprmsfon des p()111"0irs gouvernementaux
Koh\er, Josef. 1915. Not kennt kcin Gebot. Berlin-Leipzig: Rothschild. pendant et après la grande guerre. Paris: Stock.
Magdclain, André. 1947. Auctoritas principis. Paris: Belles Letters. Versnel, H. S. 1980. nestrnctinn, dcvotio, and <lespair in a sit11;1tion of nnomy: The
---. 1990. lus [111peri11111 A11ctoritas. Études de droit romain. Rome: École française de rnourning for Germnnicus in triple perspect ive. Tn Pcmmitas. St11di in onore di Angelo
Rome. Bre/ich. Rom('; Edîzioni dell'Ateneo.
Mathiot, André. 1956. La théorie des circonstances exceptionelles. In Mélanges .Mestre. Viesel, J-fansjôrg. 1988. Jawph/, der Srlnni!t. 7c!m Britfc aus Plettenherg. Berlin: Su pp ort.
Paris: n.p. \Vagenvoort, H. 1947. Roman Dy11mni.'im. O;;ford: Blackwell.
Meuli, Karl. 1 975. Gesammclte S,hrifren. 2 vols. Base\-St11ttgart: Schwabe. Watkins, Frederick M, 1940. The Prohlcm of Constitt1tion,1l Dic1aj"orship. Pu/JI/( Policy 1.
Middell, Emil. 1887. De iustitio dcq11c aliis q11i/111sdam iuris p11/Jlici romrmi 11otio11ib11s. \1\lchcr, Samuel. 1992. 1Jking exception 1·0 dccision: W. Benjamin and C. Schmit1. Tn Walter
Minden, Germany: Bruns. Benjamin. ed. Uwe Steiner. Bern: Lang.
Mommsen, Theodor. 1969. ROmisrlies Staatsrecht. 3 vols. Reprint, Graz: Akademische \Vrngcr, Leopold. 1939. ROm ischcs Recht in Amerib. ln Studi di 5/0ria e dirir-to in onorc rli
Druck. Orig. pub, 1871. Enrirn Bcsta. Vol. 1. Milan: Giuffrè.
Index

Adorno, Theodor Wiesengnmd, 74 Chantrmps, Camille, 13


Antigone, 28 Cicero, 42, 45, 49
Appius Claudius, 80
Arangio-Ruîz, Gaetano, 29 Daladier, Edonnrd, 13
Arendt, Hannah, 3, 74, 75 Dante Alighieri, 26
Angustus, 67-68, 80-83, 84 De Franciscî, Pietro, 84�85
Aulus Gellius, 41 de Gaulle, Charles, 14
Delatte, Louis, 69
Balladore--Pallîeri, Giorgio, 23, 30 De Martino, Francesco, 1
Bengel, Johann Albrecht, 40 Derrida, Jacques, 37
Benjamin, Walter, 3, 6, 9, 37, 52-64, 68-69, Dio Cassius, 75, 82
80, 88 Diotogcncs, 69--70, 71
Benveniste, Émile, 39, 76 Dossetti, Giuseppe, w
Berger, Peter L., 65 Duguit, Léon, 26, 29
Bethmann-Hollweg, The.obald Durkheim, Émile, 66--67
von, 26
Biscardi, Arnaldo, 78 Eichm:rnn, Adolf, 38
Biscaretti di Rnffia, Paolo, 23
Blum, Léon, 13 Fleiner, Fritz, 16
Bodin, Jean, 75 Fontanil, Alessandro, 1
Bonaparte, Napoleon, 4, n, 84 Forccllini, Egidio, 42
Brmm, Otto, 15 Fouc;rnlt, Michel, 63
Brcdckamp, Horst, 52 Franco, Francisco, 48
Brüning, Heinrich, 15 Fraschetti, Angns1o, 67-68, 83
Burckhardt, Walther, 16 frazer, Sir James George, 71
Bush, George W,, 3, 22 Frenkel-Brunswick, Else, 74
Butler, Judith, 4 Fresa, Carlo, 16, 18
Fre11d, Sigmund, 66
Caius Gracchus, 49 Friedrich, Carl)., 6, 7--8, 47
Carré de Malbcrg, Raymond, 23 Fueyo, Jesus, 75
Catiline, 49
Cavnîgnnc, Louis Eugène, 12 Gndnmcr, Hans-Georg, 40
Chnrisius, 65 Gaius, 38
Chnteaubriand, François René de, 11 Germ;micus, 65
94 Jndex fodex 95

Gn1ti,;,:1, 1.4, 2�26 .\fommscn, Theodor, 42-45, 47, 48, 49, Sa.ton, William, 65, 67 llipi:m,38
Gruppe, O. E, 70 77~78, 80, Rl Smend, Rudolph, 35
Mom, Aldo, 1;; Spohr, Wemer,3 Vcnme\, H. S., 65-66
tfannihal, 44, 79 Mort;_1!l, Üi$hmtino, 23 Stalin, Joseph, 48 Viesd, Hnmji'irg, 52,
H;,tschek, Julins, 25 MtJSSülini', Benito, 48, 83 Stifter, Ad"lbert 61 Vyshiosky, Andrd Yamrnrievîcli, 63
l hrnriou, ivhmrke, 2; Stohaeus, Joanncs, 69, 70
Hdm,e, Rkhar<l, 73, 81, K;,. N1r0]oon Hl (Lo\Jls Niipnkon Rorn1.pnrtc), Snctonius, 68 W:ig,:nvoùrt, iL 51
Hinrlenhmg, Paul vcrn, 1,5 12 'W.1ldkird1., Eduard Otto von, 16
His, Eduard, i6 Nfasen, Adolph, 42, 45-46, 47, 4-<'i, 4,9, 65, Tautx:s, Tawh, 53 Wü�kim, Fie-éeri�·k M.; 6
Hitler, Adolf, 2, 14, 15, 38, 48., 58, 6S"69, So 'îh:-ilm,mn, Rl.nst, 15- \V,:l:wr, M:rx, 84, &5
83, 84 Noni!les, Pierre, 77 Thom:1,s Aqninas, Saint, z4--25 Weher, SJmuel, 55
Hohhes, Thomas, 51., 75 Tiberius Gr,1;:dms, 44, 49 Wenger, Leop0hl, 81
Hoerni, Robert, 16, :,.3 Opimh1b, Lndw,, 49 Tledemlmn, Rt,lf, 51. Wcstetmarck, Edw:ml Alexander, 7:
Tingsten, Herbert, 6, 7, 12 V..'-ilsnri, Woo<lmw; :n
follinek, Gemg, 26 Paptn, Franz vnn, 15 Triepcl, l-feinrkh, 84, 85
hmg, Carl Gustav, 66 P1slmk:ink EYg:eny, 63 Turner, V. W., 66
Jmt;nhm 1, 37 Pan!, Snint 63, 71, 85
Pi!t':lin, H<-nd ?hni11pe, 14
Kafk.1, fnmz, 63. Bo Pbum:mn, nerhard, 43, 47, 48
Kant, lmnrnnncl, 39 Poincnré, Raymond, 12, 13
Kmtnrowkz, Ernst, 83 Pomponins, 38
Kohler, JoseC 26 Prt'nss, Hngo, 6, 14
Krnm,, Karl, 61 Pst·udo-Archyt::s, 70-71

L:.w;;l, Pierre, lJ
Lèderer. F:mi1, 5:1
Lcnin, Vl:vlîmir Hyi,::h, 34 R:meilctti, Oreste, 23
Lévl.-Stnmss, Ch:ude., 37 Rcinad,, Theodor, 3, 4'7, 5S
Linrnln,_Ahrnhnm, :w--21 Ron1rtno, San-:-l, 17, :1.3, 27---29, 30
Livy, 41., 48�49, 79, 80 Uonsevelt, Franklin [),, 21�22
Lutkrnann, 11rnmns, 65 Ros1iter, Clinton L., 6, 8-9, 13, 18, io, 23, 4ï

Machiavrlli, Nkcolh, 46 S<linH1onnet, Pnmçois, 1


Mad'vfahon, Maria: Rdm<i- P;,trke de, 12. S:1vigny, FrierJ;kh Karl v-nn, 85
Mag,k!:iin, André, 74-S;;: passim SdHttitt, Carl, 1, 3, 6, S, 9, 10, 15, 18, 19, 20,
h.•îJMhiitdt, Wilhdm, 71 1.!,, 30··',)l, 3:;,;,--.36, 4-0, 47, 48, 50, 51, 52-iio,
:\4-,,r,:;·d!ns, Mn,n;<; Gfandins, 68 63,74-75, 84
M,îrrns Anroniun, 45 Schrmr, Roman, &
Marx, Karl, r,3 Schoen, Ernst, 61
lvfathiot, André, 31 Scholem, nershmn, 63
Menli, Karl, 71-71. Schüt;_,, Anton, 1.6
l\lklddl, Emil, 46,�47, 65 Scipio Nasica, 44, 49

You might also like