You are on page 1of 5

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 203–207

Contents lists available at SciVerse ScienceDirect

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science


journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsa

Discussion

What’s philosophical about Kant’s philosophy of the human sciences?


Thomas Sturm
Departament de Filosofia, Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona, Edifici B, E-08193 Bellaterra (Barcelona), Spain

When citing this paper, please use the full journal title Studies in History and Philosophy of Science

1. Introduction anthropology as an empirical discipline (and, if I read him right,


even as potential science): Most of its claims are open to empirical
An author whose book gets such careful consideration as mine revision, and more than a few have been discarded. At the same
does in Katharina Kraus’s (2011) encompassing and detailed re- time, he took great philosophical care with his anthropology. But
view ought to be grateful, and indeed, I am. Naturally I feel hon- what are the philosophical concepts, considerations, and conclu-
ored by her overall positive assessment of my work. For the most sions he used? Kraus raises four pertinent worries:
part, Kraus presents my arguments correctly. There are a few
points that I would put differently, and some where I think she 1. She finds chapter 3 of my book—on Kant’s concept of science—
has misunderstood me.1 However, I shall focus on a topic of general ‘‘the most philosophical’’ part (Kraus, 2011, p. 619), because
interest that probably haunts all who seriously explore Kant’s there I deal more than elsewhere with the conceptual tools pro-
anthropology and his related writings on medicine, psychology, vided by Kant’s critical philosophy.
and history. It is this: To what extent is the philosophy that Kant in- 2. Kraus suggests (ibid. pp. 621f.) that I should have considered
vests in his thought on the human sciences guided by central doc- the option of Kant’s ‘‘transcendental psychology’’ for better
trines of his critical philosophy? More specifically, how is his understanding the demarcation between metaphysics and
‘‘empirical’’ account of human thought and action, as developed both empirical psychology analyzed in chapter 4.
in his anthropology lectures from 1772/73 to 1795/96 and in Anthro- 3. She regrets that throughout the book I neglect to connect Kant’s
pology from a Pragmatic Point of View (1798), related to the Critique of philosophy of the human sciences to his transcendental ideal-
Pure Reason? Kraus thinks that I did not give sufficient attention to ism (ibid. pp. 622, 624). That doctrine, she suggests, also under-
that relation, and raises several specific worries in this regard. I shall lies his sharp distinction between empirical psychology and
defend my view that I covered it sufficiently—and, furthermore, that metaphysics.
doing more might be damaging. 4. Finally, she finds that my discussion of freedom in chapter 8
Above I used scare quotes for empirical because Kant did not so fails to engage sufficiently with the relation between Kant’s
much develop his account on the basis of observation and experi- anthropology and his critical philosophy, which might provide
ment, but by reading and reflecting what others had already elab- a meaningful interpretation of freedom with respect to the
orated. He perused countless geographical, historical, anthropological project (ibid. p. 623).
psychological, and medical works, extracting from them examples
for his claims about the strengths and weaknesses of the human I shall deal with each of these comments in turn. In conclusion, I
mind, the relation of motivation to action, cultural customs, the will also give a general reason for why Kant maintains (at times
development of human society, and so on. Yet he viewed his considerable) distance between more specific contentions of his

E-mail address: tsturm@mpiwg-berlin.mpg.de


1
For instance: ‘‘However, Kant did not know of the results of what later became psychophysics and so he did not realize that there is indeed a way of mathematizing
psychology in terms of objective scales of intensities.’’ (p. 621) Some examples in Kant’s anthropology lectures lead me to think that this is perhaps too strong a claim, especially
his references to musical acoustics (see Sturm, 2009, p. 244). These works from the 18th century on the measurement of tonal perception are nowadays also seen as beginnings of
a quantitative psychoacoustics (I am indebted here to discussions with the historian of science Julia Kursell).—Also, I would not call the idea ‘‘idea of man’’ as an ‘‘animal
rationabile’’, which as Kraus points out correctly plays a core role in Kant’s conception of anthropology, a ‘‘metaphysical idea’’, as she also does (Kraus, 2011, p. 623). It resembles
an idea of reason and so, within a scientific context, must possess a regulative function for the unification of our knowledge about human beings as agents, but I see no use of
speaking here any further of a ‘‘metaphysical idea’’.—Kraus also claims that I refer to the ‘‘principles of homogeneity, specification and continuity, i.e. the principles of the
systematic unity of cognition’’ provided by reason as being ‘‘necessary in order to justify the transcendental principle of causality’’ (Kraus, 2011, p. 620). I do not claim that the
regulative principles of reason are necessary to ‘‘justify’’ the principle of causality as presented in the first Critique. Instead, I think that the latter principle by itself does not
provide us with any concrete empirical causal laws, or any specific causal explanation, and that the search for empirical causal laws must be guided by the regulative principles of
reason. It is well known that Kant at best tries to argue that (a) all changes have causes and (b) all such causes require some law (or some set of laws). I agree here with Guyer
(1987).

0039-3681/$ - see front matter Ó 2011 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2011.12.013
204 T. Sturm / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 203–207

critical philosophy and the philosophical considerations he puts related conclusions. This is obvious in Kant’s doctrine of the neces-
into his thought on the human sciences. To let the cat out of the sary dependence of knowledge gained through the inner sense on
bag, Kant wants anthropology to become an autonomous science, knowledge gained through the outer sense. For Kant’s anthropology,
and the philosophical presuppositions antecedent to any such spe- the claim has methodological significance: contrary to psychologists
cial science must be, he believes, as free from foreign interests and of his time (such as Johann Nicolas Tetens), Kant denied that empir-
demands as possible. ical research of the human mind should or could be pursued by
means of introspection alone. Within his critical philosophy, the
2. The philosophical backbones of Kant’s anthropology project point became important for the way in which a priori concepts and
principles of the understanding could be given real meaning:
Why, as Kraus claims, should chapter 3 be ‘‘the most philosoph- namely, first and foremost by referring to knowledge of publicly ob-
ical one’’? Kraus fails to explain herself here, but there are two servable objects, their properties and relations (B292). Despite of
obvious ways that such a claim might be taken. It might pinpoint such points of convergence, the disparate foundations and directions
the methods used in studying the history of philosophy, that is, it of the two projects cannot be overlooked.
could indicate a contrast between genuinely philosophical argu- But what is the backbone of Kant’s philosophy of the human sci-
ments and ‘‘mere’’ historical interpretation. Or it might pertain to ences, then, inasmuch as it does not involve the well-known a pri-
the very subject matter of the essay—e.g., the work of a past ori sources and tools from his critical theory of knowledge? First,
author—and thus mean that chapter 3 discusses more of Kant’s note that if the author under scrutiny were not Kant, we would
philosophy than the rest. I believe Kraus intends the latter, given be more open about what counts as a philosophical assumption
her emphasis on the fact that that chapter 3 deals most with spe- or argument with respect to the human sciences. Any reader of
cific doctrines of Kant’s critical philosophy. More specifically, she Hume, Rousseau, or Adam Smith knows what I mean. But because
emphasizes my discussion of the relevance of a priori representa- Kant himself put so much emphasis on and pride in the a priori, we
tions (the pure forms of intuition, the concepts and principles of find it hard to imagine that he might also have made different sorts
the understanding, and the ideas of reason in their regulative of contribution to the philosophy of science, including the human
use) for empirical knowledge in general and the sciences in partic- sciences. Again, I do not doubt that Kant ultimately demanded of
ular. Her verdict therefore implies that the other chapters are less all proper science that it depends on a specific a priori framework.
philosophical because they deal less with the related doctrines of This would have to have been true of his anthropology as well, if its
Kant’s critical philosophy.2 I find two things wrong with this: (i) I subsequent development had actually been as fortunate as Kant
reject the underlying assumption that Kant’s philosophical thought hoped it would (see Sturm, 2009, pp. 524f.). But because of the
on anthropology and related disciplines always had, or had to have, early state that he himself saw his anthropology as being in, some-
such a close connection to critical philosophy. (ii) The other chapters thing more basic was needed first, namely, a reasonable definition
of my book are no less philosophical than chapter 3. for that possible science (A834f./B862f.). (Most commentators on
First, as the students’ manuscripts (in Kant, 1900ff., vol. XXV) Kant’s philosophy of science overlook the fact that he was often
and Kant’s own reflections on anthropology (ibid., vol. XV) reveal, interested in improving the definitions of disciplines, and that he
much of Kant’s philosophical thinking that formed the anthropol- devised tools especially for that task.) Such a definition must be gi-
ogy lectures occurred quite remotely from his critical philosophy. ven by determining the subject matter, method(s) and goal(s) of
This should not be surprising if one takes into account certain his- the discipline in question. Moreover, a (potential or actual) sci-
torical facts that I point out in my analysis. He started to lecture on ence’s definition must be given in such a way that one can at least
anthropology in 1772/73, that is, at a time when his critical project imagine how the discipline fits into a coherent and comprehensive
was only first taking shape. The two projects developed in parallel system of all scientific disciplines. At the same time, that definition
throughout the 1770s, and several major steps in that development can initially only be preliminary. It may need refining in the course
had little if anything to do with one another. The idea of a critical of ongoing empirical research. New discoveries can lead to new in-
philosophy involved the question of how certain representations sights about the very subject matter—the concept of the object of
can be a priori and yet refer to empirical objects, a task Kant did that science—but also to insight regarding the methods and goals
not set himself before 1772. It also involved achieving clarity about that are appropriate for that new science (see Sturm, 2009, pp.
other issues, such as the role of apperception, the system of catego- 162-181).
ries, the critique of dogmatic metaphysics, and so on, all subse- Thus, Kant’s philosophy of the human sciences does not merely
quent developments of the 1770s (see Carl, 1989; Kitcher, 2011). and not even primarily consist of the application of his critical the-
The development of the anthropological project, in contrast, was ory of the a priori to these disciplines. Rather, the very project of
driven by different motives: for instance, a shift from a purely the- such a philosophy itself requires a reflection on its proper defini-
oretical toward a more (though not exclusively) practical concep- tion, which is as such logically independent of the system of a priori
tion of that discipline, something Kant began to work on around concepts and principles of knowledge (see e.g. A86f./B119). This is
1773 (X, 242).3 More specifically, as of the mid-1770s Kant spoke what I call a reflection on the ‘‘external systematicity’’ of each sci-
of a ‘‘pragmatic’’ orientation. He did not elucidate his own preferred ence. To it must be added the development of the ‘‘internal syste-
understanding of this term fully until the mid-1780s, when he came maticity’’ of each science, that is, the specific conceptual
to identify one pragmatic perspective with the cosmopolitan point of framework that constitutes and guides inquiry. But again, this
view on humanity (IV, 417 fn.; VII, 120). Below I will indicate further comes in only later.
shifts in Kant’s conception of anthropology, and in his philosophical While Kraus notes some of these points, she does not seem to
thinking about the human sciences more generally. For now my grasp their full significance and force for my study. Kant realized
claim is that fundamental assumptions implied respectively by the that all definitional components—the determination of subject
critical and the anthropological projects are very different. To be fair, matter, the method, the goal, and the fitting into a comprehensive
the projects came close at other points, sometimes even leading to system of the sciences—must be dealt with (if in a preliminary

2
Moreover, Kraus regrets that I sometimes do not go far enough in explaining Kant’s concept of science, as when I do not further explain the notion of each science requiring an
idea of reason (Kraus, 2011, p. 620). There may, indeed, be something interesting to be said here.
3
Citations from Kant refer to the volume and page number of Kant’s Gesammelte Schriften (Kant, 1900ff.), except for the Critique of Pure Reason, which is cited after the first (A)
and second (B) editions of 1781 and 1787. Translations are mine.
T. Sturm / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 203–207 205

way) when we start any new kind of scientific inquiry, and also if metaphysics. As Kraus reports, one argument that plays a certain
we wish to avoid confusing one inquiry with another (B vii; IV, role here is Kant’s claim that any empirical natural science must
265). Accordingly, he adapts each of the definitional components have a rational counterpart—in the case of empirical psychology,
in several stages throughout the years of his lectures on anthropol- a rational psychology. In the first Critique of 1781 he famously ar-
ogy, in such a way that that the conception of this discipline be- gues that the latter discipline is pseudoscience. (More specifically,
comes successively more coherent and consistent. These this act of destruction is directed at ‘‘transcendent’’ rational psy-
considerations, which I lay out in the other chapters of my book, chology. Until late in 1785 he still thinks an ‘‘immanent’’ rational
are complex and often closely related to one another. It is as if psychology, which would contain only those a priori concepts
making one move in one year of his lectures forced Kant to make and principles that are constitutive for empirical psychology, might
other moves in subsequent years. On closer examination, he exhib- be possible. Not until the Preface to the Metaphysical Foundations of
its breathtaking creativity in the process. Natural Science of 1786 does Kant claim that the prospects for the
For instance, besides the points mentioned above, Kant com- an immanent rational psychology do not look good either; see
pares his approach to existing empirical psychologies, physiological Sturm, 2009, pp. 194–196, 223–250.)
anthropologies, and the pragmatic histories of his time, which were Now, Kraus thinks that one might also deal with Kant’s views
the closest competitors for an empirical scientific account of the hu- about the relation between metaphysics and empirical psychology
man mind and behavior. He focuses frequently on the definitions in a different manner. She makes two claims here, bringing into
given for these approaches and disciplines. These discussions form play the idea, defended especially by Patricia Kitcher (1990,
the background for his own definition of his kind of anthropology as 2011), that Kant’s critical theory of knowledge requires a psycho-
an empirical study of free action, which he also distinguishes from a logical theory of mental faculties and processes, a ‘‘transcendental
genuinely ethical theory of action. For instance, the discovery that psychology’’. Kraus’s first claim regards the issue of a connection
introspection, naively understood, is not an appropriate method between the two fields: ‘‘Sturm does not consider the possibility
for psychology and/or anthropology, leads him to a search for of a transcendental psychology that Kant might have developed
new methods; and these have to be appropriate to the subject mat- in order to conceive a close relation between a transcendental ac-
ter, human action. Likewise, since action is the explanandum of the count of cognition in metaphysics and a naturalistic account of the
science he envisages, he gives a new meaning and function to the mind in empirical psychology.’’ (Kraus, 2011, p. 621) Might a ‘‘tran-
traditional architecture of the mind as consisting of several facul- scendental psychology’’ not provide the relevant a priori frame-
ties: Cognition, feeling, and desire are no longer simple distinct work for empirical psychology? Kraus’s second claim concerns
departments of the mind which one might, say, discover through the distinction between empirical psychology and metaphysics.
introspection (as Tetens thought), and perhaps trace back to a more She states that the ‘‘controversial debate about Kant’s transcenden-
basic, unified power (the Wolffian ‘‘power of representation’’). In- tal psychology in recent years clearly suggests that understanding
stead, Kant argues that these faculties are basic and hence irreduc- Kant’s demarcation between metaphysics and empirical psychol-
ible as well as complete and connected. It is here, by the way, that ogy requires not only a review of his refutation of rational psychol-
the internal system of Kant’s anthropology has to do with a priori ogy, but also a reference to his transcendental theory of inner
concepts and considerations. These are, however, barely related to experience.’’ (ibid. p. 622) There are several problems with these
what one might imagine when this terminology crops up (see two claims.
Sturm, 2009, pp. 386-394). What is perhaps even more striking First, insofar as the issue is that of a distinction between meta-
for those who cling to traditional notions of Kant is the fact that physics and empirical psychology, I do not know how this could
some of his basic, but nonetheless empirical insights regarding facts be understood better by bringing the idea of transcendental psy-
of human thought and action place constraints on the methods and chology into play. As I argue in chapter 4 (Sturm, 2009, pp. 197–
goals he views as appropriate for pragmatic anthropology. Thus, he 202), the claim of the difference between empirical psychology
notes that human beings often pretend to have a better character or and metaphysics shows up in Kant’s very first lecture on anthro-
better motives than they actually do. He also argues that human pology, given in 1772/73. He discusses it, presents an argument
conduct is often guided by rules that can be changed, either in for his distinction, and later sticks to it: Empirical psychology re-
the course of historical changes in society or, occasionally, by indi- quires empirical methods, while metaphysics consists of non-
viduals that actively reflect on the principles of their actions. Be- empirical knowledge or knowledge ‘‘from pure concepts’’ alone.
cause of these facts, human nature is not as unalterable as that of Kant’s argument is clear enough. In contrast, as Kraus acknowl-
other natural beings. The anthropologist must do justice to these edges, the question of whether Kant also pursues a transcendental
facts. For instance, he must reflect on whether an empirical account psychology is a thorny one (cf. Carl, 1989, pp. 119–126; Hatfield,
of human action can have the same law-likeness as explanations in 1990, 1992; Kitcher, 1990). So, this route might lead to explaining
natural science (Kant says no), or whether physiological explana- something less obscure by something that’s probably more ob-
tions of the mind might be relevant for pragmatic anthropology scure. Of course, one might assume for the sake of argument that
(again, Kant says no). Kant does have some sort of transcendental psychology. Then there
Such conclusions are not simply derived from observation; they might be a link or bridge between empirical psychology and meta-
operate at a second-order level; and they involve very fundamental physics. But if that were true, one would certainly not understand
issues about the various disciplines at stake. In these musings, Kant his distinction between the two disciplines any better than before.
does not mechanically apply his critical philosophy. Rather, he ac- Alternatively, if Kant does not have a transcendental psychology,
tively philosophizes about the sciences in question, about what then the situation is hardly any better. In sum, as things stand, I
they are, what they pretend to be, and what they should be. I see cannot see why one should take up the issue in the context of
no reason for viewing these considerations and conclusions as less explaining his distinction between metaphysics and empirical
philosophical than Kant’s critical assumptions and arguments. psychology.
Second, insofar as transcendental psychology is invoked to build
a connection between empirical psychology and metaphysics, or to
3. Transcendental and empirical psychology replace discarded rational psychology, this idea has its limits too.
Empirical psychology as Kant discusses it is broader in scope than
One important feature of Kant’s thought on the human sciences a theory of cognition. It also deals with feeling and desire, for in-
is the sharp line he draws between empirical psychology and stance. The same holds for Kant’s own anthropology. Transcendental
206 T. Sturm / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 203–207

psychology as Kitcher presents it is only concerned with cognition. for circumventing transcendental idealism is related to the histor-
Moreover, even if we restrict ourselves to the empirical psychology ical points already made. The argument for the demarcation be-
of cognition, the transcendental psychology we find in the Critique is tween empirical psychology and metaphysics shows up as early
not devised to ground ‘‘merely’’ such a psychology. It is supposed to as 1772/73: Empirical psychology uses empirical methods, while
explain knowledge überhaupt: all knowledge to be found inside and metaphysics requires knowledge ‘‘from pure concepts’’ alone.
outside of any special science (see also Hatfield, 1990, p. 98f.). Now, Kraus (2011, p. 622) refers to this argument, but then mis-
Third, I anticipated that readers might feel an urge to read reads it as presupposing transcendental idealism: ‘‘since Kant re-
something about the debates over transcendental psychology in a fines the distinction between these two kinds of cognition in the
book that addresses, among other things, Kant’s views about Critique of Pure Reason by introducing the doctrines of transcenden-
empirical psychology. So I took up the issue, if only briefly in a tal idealism and of empirical realism, we have to assume that these
footnote (Sturm, 2009, p. 44, fn. 31). This passage is cited but not doctrines form the basis of his argument for a demarcation be-
exploited by Kraus (2011, p. 622, fn. 25). In a nutshell, I agree with tween metaphysics and empirical psychology.’’ We do not. Kraus
Hatfield (1990) and Kitcher (1990, 2011) that one should not sim- confuses two things here: a distinction between kinds of sources
ply shrug off a (somewhat) psychologistic reading and reconstruc- of knowledge, and a distinction between candidates for the title
tion of Kant’s arguments in the Critique. Given historical changes in of an object of knowledge. The 1772/73 argument uses the former,
the concept of psychology, we might find in Kant’s critical theory of and can perfectly well do so. It does not say, or need to say, any-
knowledge methods and claims nowadays being developed by cog- thing whatsoever about whether the objects of knowledge are
nitive psychologists. But my analysis of Kant’s empirical account of appearances or things in themselves, let alone what the relation
cognition and action disappoints the expectation that they might between them is. Here an austere interpretation is not a question-
support Kitcher’s cause. To be fair, there are parallels between able way of imposing on Kant views one prefers oneself. Historical
the cognitive architecture used in the first Critique and that used standards alone demand it.
in the anthropology lectures. Self-consciousness, the senses, the
faculties of imagination, understanding, judgment, and reason are 5. Freedom in Kant’s ethics and anthropology
present here as well (see Schmidt, 2008). However, the anthropol-
ogy lectures do not deal with the tasks of transcendental philoso- My rejoinder to Kraus’ fourth worry is more conciliatory. She
phy. They never address the ‘‘guiding thread’’ of the logical forms writes: ‘‘According to Sturm, the idea of freedom that is at work
of judgment, the deduction of the categories, or proofs for the prin- in pragmatic anthropology differs from Kant’s notion of transcen-
ciples of the pure understanding. Nor do they take up what might dental freedom, as well as from the notion of the moral freedom
have been, from Kant’s point of view, a possible and related empir- of choice. Although this is a highly interesting suggestion, it would
ical task, namely a ‘‘physiological derivation’’ of our factually hav- be better to have a more extensive discussion of the underlying
ing the categories (A86/B119). This absence is particularly striking, philosophical considerations.’’ (Kraus, 2011, p. 623) I agree that
since Kant saw such an inquiry as a task for empirical accounts of there is perhaps more work to be done here. But my focus was
cognition—as something authors like Tetens had pursued (Carl, more on the philosophy of science in Kant’s anthropological pro-
1989, pp. 119–126). ject. Others have written about the relation between that project
Fourth and finally, Kraus characterizes transcendental psychol- and his ethics. Some, most notably Patrick Frierson (2003; for crit-
ogy as a ‘‘transcendental theory of inner experience’’. If that were a icism, see Sturm, 2004) have also dealt with freedom in Kant’s
characterization of transcendental psychology, then my project anthropology. I deal with both topics in chapter 8. Among other
would have fallen dead-born from the press (my apologies to Pope things, I argue for two related claims: (1) Kant has an ambitious
and Hume). If Kant’s theory of knowledge presupposes a certain notion of the ‘‘prudence’’ that his pragmatic anthropology is sup-
psychology, then it better not be psychology based on ‘‘inner expe- posed to teach: prudence is not confined to egoistic self-interest
rience’’, given all of his qualms about that notion (Sturm, 2009, pp. but covers a broader cosmopolitan point of view upon humanity.
202–223). Kitcher certainly does not commit herself to that view, (2) The widely held assumption that his pragmatic anthropology
either (Kitcher, 1990, pp. 11–29). is supposed to be some sort of empirical counterpart to, or even di-
rectly serving, his ethical theory, is misguided. The prudence
4. On how to ignore transcendental idealism meant under (1) basically consists in realizing that other human
agents can rationally reflect and change their rules of conduct. As
Turning to Kraus’ next worry, can we really interpret Kant’s phi- rational agents, we are well advised to take this point into consid-
losophy of the human sciences independently of an assumption as eration; moreover, it limits our ability to view rules of action as
crucial to his mature philosophical works as the thesis of transcen- ‘‘technical’’ rules. All of this is about what it means, from Kant’s
dental idealism? Kraus is perfectly right that I ignore that thesis. point of view, to be a human rational agent. While these consider-
She mentions it again in relation to Kant’s claim that empirical psy- ations can be relevant for ethical considerations in general, they do
chology does not belong in metaphysics, claiming that I do not not support his specific ethical theory.
‘‘recognise Kant’s transcendental idealism as an underlying pre- Concerning freedom, again, I freely admit (Sturm, 2009, p. 486)
supposition’’ for that demarcation (p. 622). Indeed, I do not. that incorporating the concept of freedom into pragmatic anthro-
The reason for this is not, as one might perhaps expect, a pref- pology comes at a price. I do not know how to make sense of the
erence for what Strawson (1966, e.g. pp. 47, 72) has called an ‘‘aus- more dubious claims of Kant’s theory of freedom. For instance, I
tere interpretation’’. Nor did I banish transcendental idealism do not see that one can save his claim that acting from a transcen-
because it is so notoriously difficult to agree on what the doctrine dentally free cause is acting from an atemporal cause. Kant never
really means. Kraus does not say whether she reads Kant in a presents this assumption in his anthropology, but anyone wishing
Strawsonian manner (things in themselves and appearances are to make coherent all the different texts in his corpus will quickly
members of two ontologically distinct worlds), or like Henry Alli- stumble over this and related claims. I think that the valuable parts
son (1983: things in themselves and appearances are the same of Kant’s theory of freedom are thoroughly compatibilist (in a more
entities, but viewed from different perspectives, depending on subtle way than Hume’s), and that for this reason we do well to
whether or not they are subject to conditions of knowledge), or take him seriously when he desires to give the notion of freedom
whether she prefers yet some other reading. Regardless, my reason a place in his empirical account of human action. One might work
T. Sturm / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 203–207 207

more on these issues, however, and perhaps even show that the tem of the categories. (Similarly, it has been shown that what Kant
gains of such an inquiry justify the undeniably high cognitive costs. does in the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science is not best
For the time being, I don’t see any such argument. But it might of understood as a mindless application of the system of categories
course be given, and then I stand prepared to concede defeat. to the concept of matter, but as a series of arguments in its own
right; see Watkins, 1998.)
6. Conclusion I find this relative distance between the projects healthy. If
Kant’s anthropology were fully impregnated with his epistemolog-
Kraus says that I ‘‘tackle certain philosophical issues in a cur- ical or ethical theories, learning from it for current philosophical
sory way’’ (Kraus, 2011, p. 624), referring to the absence of tran- questions about the human sciences might be hindered consider-
scendental idealism as well as to what she perceives as my ably by these additional stumbling blocks. It would embroil one
overly brief treatments of Kant’s critical theory of knowledge. In in conflicts a new science should avoid. If you do not see it this
contrast, I think that Kant’s philosophical dealing with the human way, perhaps you may by now feel that Kant might have done
sciences to a considerable extent follows its own path procedure so, and that he therefore kept the distance he did.4
and purpose. There is a deeper reason for this, and I am grateful
to Kraus for provoking me to express my views about this perhaps References
a bit more fully than I have done in the book.
Allison, H. (1983). Kant’s transcendental idealism. New Haven & London: Yale
Kant repeatedly demands that anthropology should become an University Press.
academic discipline of its own, freed for instance from metaphysics Carl, W. (1989). Der schweigende Kant. Göttingen: Vandenhoek & Ruprecht.
(A848f./B876f.; XXV, 7f., 243). He similarly keeps a considerable Frierson, P. (2003). Kant on freedom and moral anthropology. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
distance between his own ethics and his empirical, pragmatic Guyer, P. (1987). Kant and the claims of knowledge. New York: Cambridge University
anthropology. Just as talk of categories of the pure understanding Press.
does not arise, and talk of a pure apperception or transcendental Hatfield, G. (1990). The natural and the normative. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Hatfield, G. (1992). Empirical, rational, and transcendental psychology: Psychology
self-consciousness is briefly mentioned but also said to not prop-
as science and as philosophy. In P. Guyer (Ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Kant
erly belong to anthropology, so there is no mention of the categor- (pp. 200–227). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
ical imperative or how it might be applied to ordinary problems of Kant, I. (1781/2nd ed. 1787/1998). Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Ed. by J. Timmermann.
moral choice. Kant means it when he says that anthropology Hamburg: Meiner.
Kant, I. (1900ff). Gesammelte Schriften. Academy edition. 29 vols. Berlin: De Gruyter.
should be independent, that is, built on its own philosophical foun- Kitcher, P. (1990). Kant’s transcendental psychology. New York: Oxford University
dation and free from concerns of other sciences. True, if what Kant Press.
says about the role of the A priori in natural science (IV, 473–476) Kitcher, P. (2011). Kant’s thinker. New York: Oxford University Press.
Kraus, K. T. (2011). Kant and the ‘soft sciences’. Studies in History and Philosophy of
holds, he should make a similar demand on any anthropology that Science, 42, 618–624.
aims to become a science. The exact specification of such an appli- Schmidt, C. (2008). Kant’s transcendental and empirical psychology of cognition.
cation of the categories would be a speculative but nevertheless Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 39, 462–472.
Strawson, P. F. (1966). The bounds of sense. London: Routledge.
interesting enterprise in Kant scholarship, its starting point being Sturm, T. (2004). Freiheit versus Empirie? Patrick Frierson: Freedom and
the concept of a rational agent or action. ‘‘Application’’, by the Anthropology in Kant’s Moral Philosophy. literaturkritik.de, February 2004.
way, might perhaps not be the best word for this exercise. Given www.literaturkritik.de/public/rezension.php?rez_id=6754&ausgabe=200402.
Sturm, T. (2009). Kant und die Wissenschaften vom Menschen. Paderborn: Mentis.
how much Kant honors the autonomy of the sciences, it would Watkins, Eric. (1998). The argumentative structure of Kant’s Metaphysical
be more of an adjustment, a search for consistency between the Foundations of Natural Science. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 36, 567–593.
specific conceptual framework of anthropology and the critical sys-

4
Thanks to Katharina Kraus for various discussions, to Cynthia Klohr for linguistic assistance, and to Marina Frasca-Spada and Nick Jardine for several suggestions that helped
to improve the text. Completion of this essay was supported by the Spanish Ministry for Science and Innovation, Reference number FFI 2008-01559/FISO.

You might also like