You are on page 1of 12

9/25/2019 Rothbardian Welfare Economics | Mises Wire

(/)

SUPPORT MISES 
MAKE A DONATION (https://mises.org/giving/now)

MISES WIRE

GET NEWS AND ARTICLES


✉ IN YOUR INBOX (/about-
mises/subscribe)

A A
Rothbardian Welfare Economics
TAGS Free Markets (/topics/free-markets), Other Schools of Thought (/austrian-school/other-schools-thought),
Philosophy and Methodology (/austrian-school/philosophy-and-methodology)

2 HOURS AGO • Ohad Osterreicher (https://mises.org/profile/ohad-osterreicher)

Every economics undergraduate is taught that economics is a positive science.


Introductory textbooks always take the space to emphasize that the economist
qua economist can never establish ethical judgments. In his capacity as a social
scientist investigating economic problems, he can only describe and explain the
0 COMMENTS (/WIRE/ROTHBARDIAN-WELFARE- world as it is, never as it ought to be.
ECONOMICS#DISQUS_THREAD)

For example, basic economics teaches us that fixing the price of milk below the price that would have been established on
the free market, will lead to a shortage. Likewise, setting wages above market clearing prices will bring about involuntary
unemployment. These propositions say nothing about the desirability of their consequences. They are wertfrei
(https://wiki.mises.org/wiki/Wertfrei).

(https://mises.org/giving/campaigns/thank-you-supporting-our-fall-campaign-12)But then a different question arises: can


economics tell us the effect that a particular change will have on social welfare? Can it establish when "social utility" is
maximized, and if so, how do we arrive there? If the answer to these questions is affirmative, it would seem that prima
facie the economist could nevertheless make political-ethical statements without violating the value-free character of his
science.

The branch of economics that deals with these questions is known as welfare economics. It is an arcane subfield that
historically went through rough patches, ups and downs, premature deaths, and several reincarnations. In what follows, we
will briefly outline the evolution of welfare economics up to the time of Rothbard's contribution, discuss its implications, and

https://mises.org/wire/rothbardian-welfare-economics 1/12
9/25/2019 Rothbardian Welfare Economics | Mises Wire

review the critiques charged against it.

Background

The classical economists like Smith, Ricardo, and Mill had a primitive, pre-
subjective conception of welfare. They argued that one should adopt
those public policies that aim to maximize physical output (usually
referred to as "Bushels of Corn"). Based upon their positive analysis, the
way to achieve this goal was straightforward
(https://www.amazon.com/Theories-Welfare-Economics-Hla-
Myint/dp/0678000697): promote the scope of the division of labor to the
greatest possible extent and accumulate the largest amount of capital.1

While the classical economists were mostly correct in their analysis of the effects of the division of labor and capital
accumulation, they erred in thinking that the physical results alone could furnish them with justification for their policies. For
the subjectivist, neoclassical economist the fault in their thinking is obvious: welfare is not dependent upon the objective,
physical amount of consumer goods in society; it is rather a function of people's preferences and their ability to satisfy them.

It is quite possible that more consumer goods, all other things being equal, can mean a higher level of welfare, but these
goods must come at a cost. If the cost to produce them, e.g., forgone leisure, is of higher value than the needs that these
goods will satisfy, then more goods would lead to less welfare.

Moreover, following the reasoning of the classical economists, one would think that it is possible to increase social welfare by
forcing people to work more than they wish to, or by transferring wealth from poor individuals with high time preference to
wealthy individuals with lower time preference, thus increasing the total amount of capital.

The Rejection of Old Welfare Theory

With the arrival of the marginal revolution and its emphasis upon the subjective, individualistic conception of welfare,
Classical Welfare Economics was rejected. Instead, neoclassical economists, led by Pigou, Edgeworth, and Marshall, utilized
the new value theory and the Law of Diminishing Marginal Utility (LDMU) to develop what came to be known as Old Welfare
economics. The main argument was that since everyone has a diminishing utility of money, the marginal utility of income of
a rich person is smaller than that of a poor person. Therefore, a transfer of income from the rich to the poor, given that it
would not overly hamper production, will increase "total utility," and is thus economically legitimized.

If this argument sounds familiar, it is no accident. Politicians and economists appeal to this line of reasoning even to this day.
Recently, Paul Krugman used it (https://www.nytimes.com/2019/01/05/opinion/alexandria-ocasio-cortez-tax-policy-
dance.html) to support the attempt by U.S representative Alexandria Ocasio-Cortez to introduce a higher top marginal
income tax rate.

This argument might seem convincing at first glance, so it is worthwhile to spell out precisely the assumptions it involves.
First, the Old Welfare theorists assumed that all people have the same capacity for satisfaction. They admitted that this was
no more than a metaphysical presupposition, but it was a reasonable starting point and mostly harmless. Second, and of
much greater importance, was the assumption of cardinal utility. Following the pioneers of the marginal revolution, Jevons
and Walras, the Old Welfare theorists understood utility as a quantifiable physiological magnitude that has an existence
beyond the choice of the individual.2 They thought that this quantity lends itself to mathematical operations and
aggregation. Under this assumption, Interpersonal Utility Comparisons (IUC) are permissible, and therefore, it makes sense to
conclude that "total utility" has increased, even if some people are worse off.

https://mises.org/wire/rothbardian-welfare-economics 2/12
9/25/2019 Rothbardian Welfare Economics | Mises Wire

The endeavors of the Old Welfare theorists came to an abrupt end with Lionel Robbins's demonstration of the futility of IUC.
Robbins showed (https://mises.org/library/essay-nature-and-significance-economic-science) that these economists erred in
extending the LDMU beyond its proper field, for the LDMU applies only to the economizing individual in employing means
to satisfy his ends. We can speak of an individual ranking goods on his value scale and the diminishing utility of additional
units. We can explain an exchange by referring to the opposing ranking of the goods on the individuals' value scales. It is an
entirely different thing, however, to compare this value rank between individuals. Furthermore, since there is no objective
unit of measurement for utility, it is impermissible to speak of quantitative differences in satisfaction. Thus, Robbins
concluded, the argument advanced by the Old Welfare theorists is nothing but an ethical judgment, and as such, must be
excluded from the economic science.

Barred from making IUC, economists were forced to adopt the so-called Unanimity or Pareto Rule
(https://www.amazon.com/Manual-Political-Economy-Vilfredo-Pareto/dp/0678008817). The Pareto Rule, first developed by
Italian economist Vilfredo Pareto in 1906, maintains that we can speak of increasing social utility only when one individual is
better off without causing another to be worse off. When a change brings this about, it is called Pareto-Superior. When there
are no more Pareto-Superior moves left, the situation is called Pareto Optimality; otherwise, the situation is Pareto Inferior.3

The Pareto Rule stood as the test which all statements concerning social welfare must pass if they are to remain value-free. If
two individuals partake in a trade or an individual acts without harming anyone else, then the economist would be
permitted in deducing that social welfare has indeed increased. However, if a group of individuals gains at the expense of
another group, as happens with all state interventions, then the economist cannot conclude anything meaningful about
social welfare.

It is this constraint that the New Welfare Economics of the mid-twentieth century sought to evade and instead made an
economic case for state intervention. Two different paths were taken to this end: the first, associated with Harvard University,
trivialized the Pareto Rule by incorporating it into a general equilibrium framework. The second, emerging from London
School of Economics, circumvented the rule with the help of the Compensation Principle. The first path led to the
development of the social welfare function (SWF) and the concept of market failure, the second to the Kaldor-Hicks
Compensation Criterion.4

The social welfare function was first pioneered (https://en-


econ.tau.ac.il/sites/economy_en.tau.ac.il/files/media_server/Economics/grad/mini%20courses/David%20Colander/Bergson.pdf ) by
American economist Abram Bergson5 and later developed by Paul Samuelson.6 This approach trivialized the Pareto Rule by
adopting the Pareto Optimality version of it, thus focusing on the static, end-state market outcome. By establishing several
efficiency conditions, the SWF would derive an Optimal Pareto equilibrium which maximized social welfare. Failure to
achieve this maximum could be then used to justify state intervention.7

This procedure is analogous to finding the optimal consumer goods bundle for an individual's utility function subject to a
budget constraint. Only that instead of an individual's indifference curve and a budget constraint, a social indifference curve
is maximized at the point of tangency with a so-called Utility Possibility Frontier, similar to a Production Possibility Frontier.

Right from the start, the SWF went through harsh criticism by fellow neoclassical economists, mostly because it failed to
eliminate cardinal utility and IUC from its analysis. However, the final nail in the coffin came with Kenneth Arrow's famous
"Impossibility Theorem."8 Arrow demonstrated that it is impossible to construct a SWF that simultaneously satisfies several
elementary conditions. Hence, there is no method of aggregating individual preferences which leads to a consistent social
preferences scale. The SWF had to be abandoned.

https://mises.org/wire/rothbardian-welfare-economics 3/12
9/25/2019 Rothbardian Welfare Economics | Mises Wire

The market failure approach had a much more fruitful existence. This relies on the so-called first and second Fundamental
Welfare Theorems. The first welfare theorem states that under the assumption of perfect competition,9 the market will
inevitably arrive at a Pareto Optimal equilibrium. The second theorem (https://read.dukeupress.edu/hope/article-
abstract/39/2/185/12328/The-Fundamental-Theorems-of-Modern-Welfare) states that allowing for an initial transfer of
income between individuals and then letting the market run its course, the market would still reach a Pareto Optimum.10

The appeal of this approach lies in the fact that economists could then point to cases in the real world where the market fails
to achieve this result. Throughout the latter half of the twentieth century, hundreds of papers were published on this topic,
each trying to find new types of market failures, and calling for state intervention to fix them. Among the cases of market
failure that have survived in the literature up to this day are public goods, asymmetric information, natural monopoly, and
externalities.

Alongside the Harvard approach, LSE economists John Hicks and Nicholas Kaldor developed the "Compensation Criterion."
This criterion states that we may speak of increasing social welfare when the winners can hypothetically compensate the
losers and remain better off. That this compensation need not actually take place is irrelevant. Economists could utilize
(https://www.jstor.org/stable/2225023) this criterion to recommend certain policies without involving value judgments yet
remain within the Pareto Rule.11

A classic example frequently used to illustrate the superiority of the Compensation Criterion over the Pareto Rule was that of
the repeal of the Corn Law in the nineteenth century. Economists have pointed out that it would be impossible for the
economist qua economist to support this kind of measure. Despite obviously making everyone better off in the long run,
abolishing the tariff would have hurt the short-run interests of the landlords. Hence, Kaldor and Hicks argued, the
Compensation Principle avoids this pitfall by only asking that the gains be hypothetically distributed among the losers.

Rothbard Enters the Scene

This was the state of welfare economics when Murray Rothbard arrived on the scene with his seminal article "Toward a
Reconstruction of Utility and Welfare Economics (https://www.google.com/search?
client=safari&rls=en&q=Toward+a+Reconstruction+of+Utility+and+Welfare+Economics&ie=UTF-8&oe=UTF-8)." There was
at the time but a few dying theories scattered around without any viable future in sight. Rothbard's solution for the revival of
the field was simple yet profound. It consisted of placing the Pareto Rule within the constraint of demonstrated preference.
The notion of demonstrated preference is straightforward: the economist can only know of the individual's preferences
through their actions. Every action implies a choice; when an individual chooses A over B, he demonstrates that he prefers A.
The economist cannot deduce from this how much does the individual prefers A, for this is purely subjective and ordinal and
is not revealed to him through action. Moreover, under demonstrated preference, it is impermissible to construct
hypothetical value scales that contradict the preferences which individuals themselves make known in action.

As Rothbard went on to show, the implications of confining welfare economics within demonstrated preference were far-
reaching. First, the whole focus on conditions of Pareto Optimality was fallacious. Since the never-never land of perfect
competition could not materialize in the real world, it is thus futile to analyze changes in social welfare under these ideal
conditions. On the contrary, preference can only be demonstrated in real-world markets, where actors are neither price
takers nor omniscient. Hence, complaints about producers selling products at above marginal costs, asymmetric information,
and natural monopolies, are irrelevant.

Instead, welfare economics teaches us that by participating in the free market, both parties to every exchange demonstrate
that they expect to benefit themselves. In other words, every voluntary exchange increases utility in the ex-ante sense.
According to Rothbard, then, at every point in time, by going from one Pareto-Superior move to another, the free market
maximizes social welfare.

https://mises.org/wire/rothbardian-welfare-economics 4/12
9/25/2019 Rothbardian Welfare Economics | Mises Wire

Furthermore, restricting statements about social welfare to demonstrated preference illustrates the absurdity of the
Compensation Criterion. If no actual compensation from the gainers to the losers takes place, then the economist cannot
conclude anything meaningful about social welfare. He cannot know whether people actually prefer the new situation to the
old one. However, if the compensation really did happen, given that it was made voluntarily, then the Compensation
Criterion merely collapses into the old and familiar Pareto Rule.

In the aftermath of Rothbard's article, several economists have criticized his thesis. First, it was argued that Rothbard's
approach still fails to solve the problem of escaping from the status quo, as in the example of the repeal of the Corn Law. The
landlords, it is said, preferred having the tariff in place, as demonstrated by their vocal opposition to Parliament's decision.
However, it is wrong to assert that this opposition shows that the landlord's welfare was reduced after the change. As far as
the economist knows, the landlords could be lying or just playing a game. What the economist can observe, however, is that
after the laws were repealed, the landlords reentered voluntary contracts, demonstrating they were benefiting from the free
market. Therefore, in the new state of affairs, all parties mutually gained; as opposed to the old state of affairs, where the
welfare of the rest of the population was reduced due to the tariff.

In his controversial article (http://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/download?doi=10.1.1.592.2632&rep=rep1&type=pdf ),


economist Bryan Caplan objected that the same argument above could be pointed against Rothbard's thesis. Regarding the
claim that the emotions of a third party cannot invalidate the conclusion that each voluntary exchange increases social
welfare, since (as Caplan quotes Rothbard) "even if he publishes a pamphlet denouncing these exchanges, we have no
ironclad proof that this is not a joke or a deliberate lie," Caplan writes:

"Rothbard could have taken this principle further. When two people sign a contract, do they
actually demonstrate their preference for the terms of the contract? Perhaps they merely
demonstrate their preference for signing their name on the piece of paper in front of them.
There is no "ironclad proof" that the signing of one's name on a piece of paper is not a joke,
or an effort to improve one's penmanship."

However, signing a contract is not just penmanship or a game; it is rather, as Walter Block points out
(https://mises.org/library/austrian-theorizing-recalling-foundations), a binding activity that transfers ownership of goods
from one person to another. It, therefore, obligates the person to act according to the terms of the contract. Thus, a person
entering a legal agreement cannot be said to engage in play.

In addition, economist Roy Cardato has argued (https://mises.org/library/efficiency-and-externalities-open-ended-


universe) that Rothbard is mistaken in focusing on utility ex-ante alone. In reality, people may have false expectations of the
future and thus can and do lose utility in the ex-post: "Rothbard's welfare economics... ignores the fact that preferences are
expressed sequentially through time, as part of a general set of goal-oriented activities."

Although Cardato is correct in his observation, he is mistaken in thinking that this poses a problem to Rothbard. First, as
economists, we cannot infer anything about ex-post utility from demonstrated preference. This knowledge is barred to us. It
is, therefore, irrelevant for all welfare economics, not just Rothbard's. Second, as Austrian economics teaches us, the
unhampered market is the best institution for mitigating errors and thus maximizing ex-post utility. The market has a built-in
mechanism for eliminating unsuccessful entrepreneurs and unwanted products. It is certainly possible that a consumer may
be unsatisfied with a single purchase, but it is hard to imagine that the seller of the product would stay in business for long.

https://mises.org/wire/rothbardian-welfare-economics 5/12
9/25/2019 Rothbardian Welfare Economics | Mises Wire

Lastly, Cardato misunderstood Rothbard's objective. Rothbard did not try to create a whole ethical or philosophical basis for
the free market with his welfare economics. This could be found in his natural law theory (https://mises.org/library/ethics-
liberty) of property rights. Instead, he only set out to show how demonstrated preference can be utilized to salvage this field
from pure ruin, providing us with a framework upon which ethical claims could be based.12

Now just one last obstacle remained for Rothbard. The First Welfare Theorem, if it can fit into Rothbard's analysis, would not
apply to the unreachable state of perfect competition. Instead, it would apply to real-world markets, stating that the free
market ensures the highest level of welfare possible, compared to other actual institutional systems. However, the Second
Welfare Theorem was left untouched by Rothbard. Economists could still advocate for a single lump-sum transfer of income
to achieve their preferred state of equality, and then let the market run its course.13

It was left to Rothbard's protégé, Hans Hoppe, to find the solution. Hoppe pointed (https://mises.org/library/review-man-
economy-and-liberty-essays-honor-murray-n-rothbard)out that the New Welfare economists were entangled in a logical
contradiction. On the one hand, they accepted the social welfare consequences of voluntary exchange from the individuals'
point of view. Thus implicitly embracing the principle of self-ownership. But on the hand, they refused to accept its logical
consequence — the Lockean principle of homesteading and acquisition.

If welfare economics must start from the undeniable fact of self-ownership, then it must apply the Pareto Rule both to the
use of property and its acquisition. As Hoppe wrote (https://mises.org/library/review-man-economy-and-liberty-essays-
honor-murray-n-rothbard):

"a person's original appropriation of unowned resources, as demonstrated by this very


action, increases his utility (at least ex-ante). At the same time, it makes no one worse off,
because in appropriating them he takes nothing away from others. For obviously, others
could have homesteaded these resources, too, if only they had perceived them as scarce. But
they did not actually do so, which demonstrates that they attached no value to them
whatsoever, and hence they cannot be said to have lost any utility on account of this act.
Proceeding from this Pareto-optimal basis, then, any further act of production, utilizing
homesteaded resources, is equally Pareto optimal on demonstrated preference grounds…
And finally, every voluntary exchange starting from this basis must also be regarded as a
Pareto-optimal change, because it can only take place if both parties expect to benefit from
it."

Conclusion

Rothbard, probably against the wish of his fellow economists, succeeded in reconstructing welfare economic by confining it
to the Pareto Rule and demonstrated preference. He showed that the free market, i.e., the network of voluntary interactions
between individuals, always produces the greatest degree of social welfare possible. Government intervention, on the other
hand, could never be justified in terms of welfare. And while Rothbard’s contribution probably ranks among his least-known
achievements, it is truly a tour de force and another tribute to his great originality and talent as an economist.

Originally published at AustroLibertarian.com (http://austrolibertarian.com) | Subscribe to Austro-Libertarian Magazine here


(https://www.austrolibertarian.com/magazine)

https://mises.org/wire/rothbardian-welfare-economics 6/12
9/25/2019 Rothbardian Welfare Economics | Mises Wire

1. Hla Myint, Theories of Welfare Economics (London, U.K.: Longmans, Green and Co. 1948), p. 12.
2. "But to the preceding generation of economists, interindividual comparisons of utility were made almost without question; to a man like
Edgeworth, steeped as he was in the Utilitarian tradition, individual utility — nay social utility — was as real as his morning jam. And with Marshall
the apostrophe in consumers' surplus was always after the s." Paul Samuelson, Foundations of Economic Analysis (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1947), p. 225.
3. Vilfredo Pareto, Manual of Political Economy (New York: Augustus M. Kelley, [1906] 1971).
4. Jeffrey Herbener, "The Pareto Rule and Welfare Economics," (https://mises.org/library/pareto-rule-and-welfare-economics) Review of Austrian
Economics 10 (1997): 86.
5. Abram Bergson, "A Reformulation of Certain Aspects of Welfare Economics," Quarterly Journal of Economics 70, no. 2 (February 1938): 310–34.
6. Paul Samuelson, Foundations of Economic Analysis (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1947), pp. 219-229.
7. The procedure is analogous to finding the optimal consumer goods bundle for an individual's utility function subject to a budget constraint. Only
that instead of an individual's indifference curve and a budget constraint, a social indifference curve is maximized at the point of tangency with a so-
called Utility Possibility Frontier, similar to a Production Possibility Frontier.
8. Kenneth Arrow, Social Choice and Individual Values, 2nd ed. (New York: John Wiley and Sons. [I951] 1963).
9. The model of perfect competition consists of the following three assumptions: all actors are price taker, i.e., cannot influence the market price, no
transaction costs, and homogenous product.
10. Mark Blaug, “The Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics, Historically Considered,” History of Political Economy 39, no. 2 (2007): 185–207.
11. John Hicks, "The Foundations of Welfare Economics," Economic Journal 49, no. 196 (December 1939): 696–712.
12. David Gordon, "Toward a Deconstruction of Utility and Welfare Economics (https://mises.org/library/toward-deconstruction-utility-and-welfare-
economics)," Review of Austrian Economics 6, no. 2 (1993): 103–4.
13. Jeffrey Herbener, “Hoppe in One Lesson, Illustrated in Welfare Economics (http://mises.org/library/hoppe-one-lesson-illustrated-welfare-
economics),” Property, Freedom, Society (Auburn, Ala.: Mises Institute, 2016) pp. 301–08.

Ohad Osterreicher is studying undergraduate economics at the University of Bayreuth, Germany. An avid fan of the Austrian
school, he runs a large Austro-libertarian online community on social media.

(//creativecommons.org/licences/by-nc-nd/4.0/)

(https://mises.org/fall2019)

Note: The views expressed on Mises.org are not necessarily those of the Mises Institute.

When commenting, please post a concise, civil, and informative comment. Full comment policy here (https://mises.org/policy-
commenting-misesorg)

ADD COMMENT

https://mises.org/wire/rothbardian-welfare-economics 7/12
9/25/2019 Rothbardian Welfare Economics | Mises Wire

0 Comments Mises Institute 


1 Login

 Recommend t Tweet f Share Sort by Best

Start the discussion…

LOG IN WITH
OR SIGN UP WITH DISQUS ?

Name

Be the first to comment.

ALSO ON MISES INSTITUTE

Negative Interest Rates are the Price We Pay for August Money-Supply Growth Rate Falls to 12-
Central Banks Year Low
59 comments • 6 days ago 7 comments • 6 days ago
Dwain Dibley — No it's true, banks do not need Snirate snigs — Why does this growth not match at
money prior to creating a 'loan'. Banks generate all what Robert Wenzel reports on EPJ daily alert?
deposits as loans based upon the liquidity provided How are the methods different?

El socialismo no tiene nada de natural Climate Justice has Little to Do with Real Justice
1 comment • 8 days ago 20 comments • 20 hours ago
Miguel Gonzalez (Multipal) — Brutal. :V Terrance Ramirez — Climate change and global
warming/cooling are not lies. Catastrophic
anthropogenic climate change (or CACC for short) is.

✉ Subscribe d Add Disqus to your siteAdd DisqusAdd 🔒 Disqus' Privacy PolicyPrivacy PolicyPrivacy

WHAT IS MISES WIRE?

Mises Wire offers contemporary news and opinion through the lens of Austrian economics and libertarian political economy.

Submitting articles to Mises Wire (https://mises.org/about-mises/daily-article-submission-guidelines)

Reprints, Permissions & Copyrights (https://mises.org/reprints-permissions-mises-wire-articles)

The views expressed on Mises Wire and mises.org are not necessarily those of the Mises Institute.

(https://mises.org/feed/rss.xml)

MOST POPULAR WIRE ARTICLES

https://mises.org/wire/rothbardian-welfare-economics 8/12
9/25/2019 Rothbardian Welfare Economics | Mises Wire

What "Climate Justice" Really Means (/wire/what-climate-justice-really-means) Kai Weiss


"Climate justice" would bring with it mass unemployment and major economic distress. Activists ignore the true costs, while
discounting market solutions.
Artificial Intelligence and Super-Powered Economic Errors (/wire/artificial-intelligence-and-super-powered-economic-
errors) Christian Hubbs
Kai-Fu Lee’s new book AI Superpowers offers many insights into the development of of AI, but too much of the book is spent chasing
economic phantoms.
Kamala Harris and the Cult of the Presidency (/wire/kamala-harris-and-cult-presidency) Tyler Curtis
Kamala Harris has promised to rule by decree if elected president. For her, Congress is little more than an advisory committee. The
average voter, of course, ranks even lower than that.
Bringing the Truth (/wire/bringing-truth) Jeff Deist
The best people in the world support the Mises Institute. Will you join them?
The False Promise of Canada's Health Care System (/wire/false-promise-canadas-health-care-system) Lee Friday
In Canada, it is estimated that between 25,456 and 63,090 Canadian women may have died as a result of increased wait times between
1993 and 2009.

MEET THE WRITER

Ohad Osterreicher (/profile/ohad-osterreicher)

Ohad Osterreicher is studying undergraduate economics at the University of Bayreuth, Germany. An avid fan...

(https://mises.org/press-room)

(https://mises.org/library/mises-weekends)

MEET OUR WIRE CONTRIBUTORS

https://mises.org/wire/rothbardian-welfare-economics 9/12
9/25/2019 Rothbardian Welfare Economics | Mises Wire

Timothy D. Terrell (/profile/timothy-d-terrell)

Timothy Terrell is professor of economics at Wofford College in Spartanburg, South


Carolina. He is assistant editor...

MORE (/BLOG/MISES-WIRE-BLOGGERS)

BOOKS LIBRARY

Man, Economy, and State, with Power and Market 4. A Conversation With Jeff Deist (/library/4-
(/library/man-economy-and-state-power-and-market) conversation-jeff-deist)

Rothbard provides a sweeping presentation of Austrian In this episode, Bob talks to Mises Institute president Jeff Deist.
economic theory.

 BROWSE BOOKS (/LIBRARY/BOOKS)  BROWSE LIBRARY (/LIBRARY)

MISES WEEKENDS COURSES

Daniel Lacalle on the Biggest Bubble of All Why Capitalism?


(/library/daniel-lacalle-biggest-bubble-all) (https://versal.com/referral/6c95f26f1b30aaa884f5b001918

Daniel Lacalle and Jeff Deist discuss why all of us have a stake Taught by Dr. David Gordon, this course explores how
in seeing central bank balance sheets shrink. capitalism lifts people from poverty to plenty.

https://mises.org/wire/rothbardian-welfare-economics 10/12
9/25/2019 Rothbardian Welfare Economics | Mises Wire

 BROWSE MISES WEEKENDS (/LIBRARY/MISES-  BROWSE COURSES (/FREE-MARKETS?TYPE=COURSE)


WEEKENDS)

TOPICS AUSTRIAN SCHOOL


Big Government (/topics/big- Labor and Wages (/topics/labor- Austrian Economics Overview Money and Banking (/austrian-
government) and-wages) (/austrian-school/austrian- school/money-and-banking)
Biographies Legal System (/topics/legal- economics-overview) Money Supply (/austrian-
(/topics/biographies) system) Business Cycles (/austrian- school/money-supply)
Book Reviews (/topics/book- Media and Culture school/business-cycles) Monopoly and Competition
reviews) (/topics/media-and-culture) Calculation and Knowledge (/austrian-school/monopoly-
Booms and Busts Money and Banks (/austrian-school/calculation- and-competition)
(/topics/booms-and-busts) (/topics/money-and-banks) and-knowledge) Other Schools of Thought
Bureaucracy and Regulation Poverty (/topics/poverty) Capital and Interest Theory (/austrian-school/other-schools-
(/topics/bureaucracy-and- Protectionism and Free Trade (/austrian-school/capital-and- thought)
regulation) (/topics/protectionism-and-free- interest-theory) Philosophy and Methodology
Corporate Welfare trade) Entrepreneurship (/austrian- (/austrian-school/philosophy-
(/topics/corporate-welfare) Socialism (/topics/socialism) school/entrepreneurship) and-methodology)
Cronyism and Corporatism Strategy (/topics/strategy) Fiscal Theory (/austrian- Political Theory (/austrian-
(/topics/cronyism-and- Swiss Watch (/topics/swiss- school/fiscal-theory) school/political-theory)
corporatism) watch) Gold Standard (/austrian- Praxeology (/austrian-
Decentralization and Secession Taxes and Spending school/gold-standard) school/praxeology)
(/topics/decentralization-and- (/topics/taxes-and-spending) History of the Austrian School of Prices (/austrian-school/prices)
secession) The Entrepreneur Economics (/austrian- Private Property (/austrian-
Education (/topics/education) (/topics/entrepreneur) school/history-austrian-school- school/private-property)
Financial Markets The Environment economics) Production Theory (/austrian-
(/topics/financial-markets) (/topics/environment) Interventionism (/austrian- school/production-theory)
Free Markets (/topics/free- The Fed (/topics/fed) school/interventionism) Subjectivism (/austrian-
markets) The Police State (/topics/police- Monetary Theory (/austrian- school/subjectivism)
From the Archives state) school/monetary-theory) Value and Exchange (/austrian-
(/topics/archives) U.S. Economy (/topics/us- school/value-and-exchange)
Global Economy (/topics/global- economy)
economy) U.S. History (/topics/us-history)
Health (/topics/health) War and Foreign Policy
Immigration (/topics/war-and-foreign-policy)
(/topics/immigration) World History (/topics/world-
history)

BROWSE LIBRARY ABOUT THE MISES INSTITUTE

Who is Ludwig von Mises? (/profile/ludwig-von-mises) Fellowships & Independent Research (/about-mises/fellowships)
What is the Mises Institute? (/about-mises/what-is-the-mises-Institute)
https://mises.org/wire/rothbardian-welfare-economics 11/12
9/25/2019 Rothbardian Welfare Economics | Mises Wire

What is the Austrian School of Economics? (/what-austrian- Become a Member (/giving/membership)


economics) Mises Events (/events)
Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics (/library/quarterly-journal- Press Room (/press-room)
austrian-economics) Mises Publications (/library/institute-publications)
The Austrian (/library/austrian) Online Learning (https://academy.mises.org)
Mises Wire (/wire) Mises Bookstore (https://store.mises.org)
Mises Weekends (/library/human-action-podcast) Faculty & Staff (/faculty-staff )
Mises View (/library/mises-view) Finances and Board (/about-mises/add-board-and-finance)
Journals & Publications (/library/journals) Subscribe to Email Lists (/about-mises/subscribe)
Homeschool Resources (/homeschool-resources) Support Mises (/giving)
Resources for the Economist (/resources-economist) Privacy Statement (/privacy-statement)
Resources for Students (/student-resources) Contact Us (/contact)

CONTACT US

518 West Magnolia Avenue


Auburn, Alabama 36832-4501

PHONE 334.321.2100 (tel:1-334-321-2100) | FAX 334.321.2119


Email Us (/contact)

✉ GET NEWS AND ARTICLES IN YOUR INBOX (/about-mises/subscribe) Tu ne cede malis,


sed contra audentior ito

STAY CONNECTED


     (https://mises.org/about/social/media/rss-
(https://mises.org/about/social/media/facebook)
(https://mises.org/about/social/media/twitter)
(https://mises.org/about/social/media/instagram)
(https://mises.org/about/social/media/itunes)
(https://mises.org/about/social/media/youtube)
feed)

Website powered by Mises Institute donors

(https://www.charitynavigator.org/index.cfm?bay=search.summary&orgid=6221)

Mises Institute is a tax-exempt 501(c)(3) nonprofit organization. Contributions are tax-deductible to the full extent the law allows. Tax ID# 52-
1263436

https://mises.org/wire/rothbardian-welfare-economics 12/12

You might also like