You are on page 1of 20

Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Search SKIP TO CONTENT

ABCDEFGHIJKLMNOPQRSTUVWXYZ

Social Contract Theory

Social contract theory, nearly as old as philosophy itself, is the view that persons' moral and/or
political obligations are dependent upon a contract or agreement among them to form the society in
which they live. Socrates uses something quite like a social contract argument to explain to Crito
why he must remain in prison and accept the death penalty. However, social contract theory is
rightly associated with modern moral and political theory and is given its first full exposition and
defense by Thomas Hobbes. After Hobbes, John Locke and Jean-Jacques Rousseau are the best
known proponents of this enormously influential theory, which has been one of the most dominant
theories within moral and political theory throughout the history of the modern West. In the
twentieth century, moral and political theory regained philosophical momentum as a result of John
Rawls’ Kantian version of social contract theory, and was followed by new analyses of the subject by
David Gauthier and others. More recently, philosophers from different perspectives have offered
new criticisms of social contract theory. In particular, feminists and race-conscious philosophers
have argued that social contract theory is at least an incomplete picture of our moral and political
lives, and may in fact camouflage some of the ways in which the contract is itself parasitical upon the
subjugations of classes of persons.

Table of Contents

Socrates' Argument

Modern Social Contract Theory

Thomas Hobbes

John Locke

Jean-Jacques Rousseau

More Recent Social Contract Theories

John Rawls' A Theory of Justice

David Gauthier

Contemporary Critiques of Social Contract Theory

Feminist Arguments

The Sexual Contract

The Nature of the Liberal Individual

Arguing from Care


Race-Conscious Argument

Conclusion

References and Further Reading

1. Socrates' Argument

In the early Platonic dialogue, Crito, Socrates makes a compelling argument as to why he must stay
in prison and accept the death penalty, rather than escape and go into exile in another Greek city.
He personifies the Laws of Athens, and, speaking in their voice, explains that he has acquired an
overwhelming obligation to obey the Laws because they have made his entire way of life, and even
the fact of his very existence, possible. They made it possible for his mother and father to marry, and
therefore to have legitimate children, including himself. Having been born, the city of Athens,
through its laws, then required that his father care for and educate him. Socrates' life and the way in
which that life has flourished in Athens are each dependent upon the Laws. Importantly, however,
this relationship between citizens and the Laws of the city are not coerced. Citizens, once they have
grown up, and have seen how the city conducts itself, can choose whether to leave, taking their
property with them, or stay. Staying implies an agreement to abide by the Laws and accept the
punishments that they mete out. And, having made an agreement that is itself just, Socrates asserts
that he must keep to this agreement that he has made and obey the Laws, in this case, by staying
and accepting the death penalty. Importantly, the contract described by Socrates is an implicit one:
it is implied by his choice to stay in Athens, even though he is free to leave.

In Plato's most well-known dialogue, Republic, social contract theory is represented again, although
this time less favorably. In Book II, Glaucon offers a candidate for an answer to the question "what is
justice?" by representing a social contract explanation for the nature of justice. What men would
most want is to be able to commit injustices against others without the fear of reprisal, and what
they most want to avoid is being treated unjustly by others without being able to do injustice in
return. Justice then, he says, is the conventional result of the laws and covenants that men make in
order to avoid these extremes. Being unable to commit injustice with impunity (as those who wear
the ring of Gyges would), and fearing becoming victims themselves, men decide that it is in their
interests to submit themselves to the convention of justice. Socrates rejects this view, and most of
the rest of the dialogue centers on showing that justice is worth having for its own sake, and that the
just man is the happy man. So, from Socrates’ point of view, justice has a value that greatly exceeds
the prudential value that Glaucon assigns to it.

These views, in the Crito and the Republic, might seem at first glance inconsistent: in the former
dialogue Socrates uses a social contract type of argument to show why it is just for him to remain in
prison, whereas in the latter he rejects social contract as the source of justice. These two views are,
however, reconcilable. From Socrates' point of view, a just man is one who will, among other things,
recognize his obligation to the state by obeying its laws. The state is the morally and politically most
fundamental entity, and as such deserves our highest allegiance and deepest respect. Just men know
this and act accordingly. Justice, however, is more than simply obeying laws in exchange for others
obeying them as well. Justice is the state of a well-regulated soul, and so the just man will also
necessarily be the happy man. So, justice is more than the simple reciprocal obedience to law, as
Glaucon suggests, but it does nonetheless include obedience to the state and the laws that sustain
it. So in the end, although Plato is perhaps the first philosopher to offer a representation of the
argument at the heart of social contract theory, Socrates ultimately rejects the idea that social
contract is the original source of justice.

2. Modern Social Contract Theory

a. Thomas Hobbes

Thomas Hobbes, 1588-1679, lived during the most crucial period of early modern England's history:
the English Civil War, waged from 1642-1648. To describe this conflict in the most general of terms,
it was a clash between the King and his supporters, the Monarchists, who preferred the traditional
authority of a monarch, and the Parliamentarians, most notably led by Oliver Cromwell, who
demanded more power for the quasi-democratic institution of Parliament. Hobbes represents a
compromise between these two factions. On the one hand he rejects the theory of the Divine Right
of Kings, which is most eloquently expressed by Robert Filmer in his Patriarcha or the Natural Power
of Kings, (although it would be left to John Locke to refute Filmer directly). Filmer’s view held that a
king’s authority was invested in him (or, presumably, her) by God, that such authority was absolute,
and therefore that the basis of political obligation lay in our obligation to obey God absolutely.
According to this view, then, political obligation is subsumed under religious obligation. On the other
hand, Hobbes also rejects the early democratic view, taken up by the Parliamentarians, that power
ought to be shared between Parliament and the King. In rejecting both these views, Hobbes occupies
the ground of one is who both radical and conservative. He argues, radically for his times, that
political authority and obligation are based on the individual self-interests of members of society
who are understood to be equal to one another, with no single individual invested with any essential
authority to rule over the rest, while at the same time maintaining the conservative position that the
monarch, which he called the Sovereign, must be ceded absolute authority if society is to survive.

Hobbes' political theory is best understood if taken in two parts: his theory of human motivation,
Psychological Egoism, and his theory of the social contract, founded on the hypothetical State of
Nature. Hobbes has, first and foremost, a particular theory of human nature, which gives rise to a
particular view of morality and politics, as developed in his philosophical masterpiece, Leviathan,
published in 1651. The Scientific Revolution, with its important new discoveries that the universe
could be both described and predicted in accordance with universal laws of nature, greatly
influenced Hobbes. He sought to provide a theory of human nature that would parallel the
discoveries being made in the sciences of the inanimate universe. His psychological theory is
therefore informed by mechanism, the general view that everything in the universe is produced by
nothing other than matter in motion. According to Hobbes, this extends to human behavior. Human
macro-behavior can be aptly described as the effect of certain kinds of micro-behavior, even though
some of this latter behavior is invisible to us. So, such behaviors as walking, talking, and the like are
themselves produced by other actions inside of us. And these other actions are themselves caused
by the interaction of our bodies with other bodies, human or otherwise, which create in us certain
chains of causes and effects, and which eventually give rise to the human behavior that we can
plainly observe. We, including all of our actions and choices, are then, according to this view, as
explainable in terms of universal laws of nature as are the motions of heavenly bodies. The gradual
disintegration of memory, for example, can be explained by inertia. As we are presented with ever
more sensory information, the residue of earlier impressions ‘slows down' over time. From Hobbes’
point of view, we are essentially very complicated organic machines, responding to the stimuli of the
world mechanistically and in accordance with universal laws of human nature.

In Hobbes' view, this mechanistic quality of human psychology implies the subjective nature of
normative claims. ‘Love’ and ‘hate’, for instance, are just words we use to describe the things we are
drawn to and repelled by, respectively. So, too, the terms ‘good’ and ‘bad’ have no meaning other
than to describe our appetites and aversions. Moral terms do not, therefore, describe some
objective state of affairs, but are rather reflections of individual tastes and preferences.

In addition to Subjectivism, Hobbes also infers from his mechanistic theory of human nature that
humans are necessarily and exclusively self-interested. All men pursue only what they perceive to be
in their own individually considered best interests - they respond mechanistically by being drawn to
that which they desire and repelled by that to which they are averse. This is a universal claim: it is
meant to cover all human actions under all circumstances – in society or out of it, with regard to
strangers and friends alike, with regard to small ends and the most generalized of human desires,
such as the desire for power and status. Everything we do is motivated solely by the desire to better
our own situations, and satisfy as many of our own, individually considered desires as possible. We
are infinitely appetitive and only genuinely concerned with our own selves. According to Hobbes,
even the reason that adults care for small children can be explicated in terms of the adults' own self-
interest (he claims that in saving an infant by caring for it, we become the recipient of a strong sense
of obligation in one who has been helped to survive rather than allowed to die).

In addition to being exclusively self-interested, Hobbes also argues that human beings are
reasonable. They have in them the rational capacity to pursue their desires as efficiently and
maximally as possible. Their reason does not, given the subjective nature of value, evaluate their
given ends, rather it merely acts as "Scouts, and Spies, to range abroad, and find the way to the
things Desired" (139). Rationality is purely instrumental. It can add and subtract, and compare sums
one to another, and thereby endows us with the capacity to formulate the best means to whatever
ends we might happen to have.

From these premises of human nature, Hobbes goes on to construct a provocative and compelling
argument for why we ought to be willing to submit ourselves to political authority. He does this by
imagining persons in a situation prior to the establishment of society, the State of Nature.

According to Hobbes, the justification for political obligation is this: given that men are naturally self-
interested, yet they are rational, they will choose to submit to the authority of a Sovereign in order
to be able to live in a civil society, which is conducive to their own interests. Hobbes argues for this
by imagining men in their natural state, or in other words, the State of Nature. In the State of
Nature, which is purely hypothetical according to Hobbes, men are naturally and exclusively self-
interested, they are more or less equal to one another, (even the strongest man can be killed in his
sleep), there are limited resources, and yet there is no power able to force men to cooperate. Given
these conditions in the State of Nature, Hobbes concludes that the State of Nature would be
unbearably brutal. In the State of Nature, every person is always in fear of losing his life to another.
They have no capacity to ensure the long-term satisfaction of their needs or desires. No long-term or
complex cooperation is possible because the State of Nature can be aptly described as a state of
utter distrust. Given Hobbes' reasonable assumption that most people want first and foremost to
avoid their own deaths, he concludes that the State of Nature is the worst possible situation in which
men can find themselves. It is the state of perpetual and unavoidable war.

The situation is not, however, hopeless. Because men are reasonable, they can see their way out of
such a state by recognizing the laws of nature, which show them the means by which to escape the
State of Nature and create a civil society. The first and most important law of nature commands that
each man be willing to pursue peace when others are willing to do the same, all the while retaining
the right to continue to pursue war when others do not pursue peace. Being reasonable, and
recognizing the rationality of this basic precept of reason, men can be expected to construct a Social
Contract that will afford them a life other than that available to them in the State of Nature. This
contract is constituted by two distinguishable contracts. First, they must agree to establish society by
collectively and reciprocally renouncing the rights they had against one another in the State of
Nature. Second, they must imbue some one person or assembly of persons with the authority and
power to enforce the initial contract. In other words, to ensure their escape from the State of
Nature, they must both agree to live together under common laws, and create an enforcement
mechanism for the social contract and the laws that constitute it. Since the sovereign is invested
with the authority and power to mete out punishments for breaches of the contract which are worse
than not being able to act as one pleases, men have good, albeit self-interested, reason to adjust
themselves to the artifice of morality in general, and justice in particular. Society becomes possible
because, whereas in the State of Nature there was no power able to "overawe them all", now there
is an artificially and conventionally superior and more powerful person who can force men to
cooperate. While living under the authority of a Sovereign can be harsh (Hobbes argues that because
men's passions can be expected to overwhelm their reason, the Sovereign must have absolute
authority in order for the contract to be successful) it is at least better than living in the State of
Nature. And, no matter how much we may object to how poorly a Sovereign manages the affairs of
the state and regulates our own lives, we are never justified in resisting his power because it is the
only thing which stands between us and what we most want to avoid, the State of Nature.

According to this argument, morality, politics, society, and everything that comes along with it, all of
which Hobbes calls ‘commodious living' are purely conventional. Prior to the establishment of the
basic social contract, according to which men agree to live together and the contract to embody a
Sovereign with absolute authority, nothing is immoral or unjust - anything goes. After these
contracts are established, however, then society becomes possible, and people can be expected to
keep their promises, cooperate with one another, and so on. The Social Contract is the most
fundamental source of all that is good and that which we depend upon to live well. Our choice is
either to abide by the terms of the contract, or return to the State of Nature, which Hobbes argues
no reasonable person could possibly prefer.
Given his rather severe view of human nature, Hobbes nonetheless manages to create an argument
that makes civil society, along with all its advantages, possible. Within the context of the political
events of his England, he also managed to argue for a continuation of the traditional form of
authority that his society had long since enjoyed, while nonetheless placing it on what he saw as a
far more acceptable foundation.

b. John Locke

For Hobbes, the necessity of an absolute authority, in the form of a Sovereign, followed from the
utter brutality of the State of Nature. The State of Nature was completely intolerable, and so rational
men would be willing to submit themselves even to absolute authority in order to escape it. For John
Locke, 1632-1704, the State of Nature is a very different type of place, and so his argument
concerning the social contract and the nature of men's relationship to authority are consequently
quite different. While Locke uses Hobbes’ methodological device of the State of Nature, as do
virtually all social contract theorists, he uses it to a quite different end. Locke’s arguments for the
social contract, and for the right of citizens to revolt against their king were enormously influential
on the democratic revolutions that followed, especially on Thomas Jefferson, and the founders of
the United States.

Locke's most important and influential political writings are contained in his Two Treatises on
Government. The first treatise is concerned almost exclusively with refuting the argument of Robert
Filmer’s Patriarcha, that political authority was derived from religious authority, also known by the
description of the Divine Right of Kings, which was a very dominant theory in seventeenth-century
England. The second treatise contains Locke’s own constructive view of the aims and justification for
civil government, and is titled "An Essay Concerning the True Original Extent and End of Civil
Government".

According to Locke, the State of Nature, the natural condition of mankind, is a state of perfect and
complete liberty to conduct one's life as one best sees fit, free from the interference of others. This
does not mean, however, that it is a state of license: one is not free to do anything at all one pleases,
or even anything that one judges to be in one’s interest. The State of Nature, although a state
wherein there is no civil authority or government to punish people for transgressions against laws, is
not a state without morality. The State of Nature is pre-political, but it is not pre-moral. Persons are
assumed to be equal to one another in such a state, and therefore equally capable of discovering
and being bound by the Law of Nature. The Law of Nature, which is on Locke’s view the basis of all
morality, and given to us by God, commands that we not harm others with regards to their "life,
health, liberty, or possessions" (par. 6). Because we all belong equally to God, and because we
cannot take away that which is rightfully His, we are prohibited from harming one another. So, the
State of Nature is a state of liberty where persons are free to pursue their own interests and plans,
free from interference, and, because of the Law of Nature and the restrictions that it imposes upon
persons, it is relatively peaceful.
The State of Nature therefore, is not the same as the state of war, as it is according to Hobbes. It
can, however devolve into a state of war, in particular, a state of war over property disputes.
Whereas the State of Nature is the state of liberty where persons recognize the Law of Nature and
therefore do not harm one another, the state of war begins between two or more men once one
man declares war on another, by stealing from him, or by trying to make him his slave. Since in the
State of Nature there is no civil power to whom men can appeal, and since the Law of Nature allows
them to defend their own lives, they may then kill those who would bring force against them. Since
the State of Nature lacks civil authority, once war begins it is likely to continue. And this is one of the
strongest reasons that men have to abandon the State of Nature by contracting together to form
civil government.

Property plays an essential role in Locke's argument for civil government and the contract that
establishes it. According to Locke, private property is created when a person mixes his labor with the
raw materials of nature. So, for example, when one tills a piece of land in nature, and makes it into a
piece of farmland, which produces food, then one has a claim to own that piece of land and the food
produced upon it. (This led Locke to conclude that America didn’t really belong to the natives who
lived there, because they were, on his view, failing to utilize the basic material of nature. In other
words, they didn’t farm it, so they had no legitimate claim to it, and others could therefore justifiably
appropriate it.) Given the implications of the Law of Nature, there are limits as to how much
property one can own: one is not allowed to take more from nature than one can use, thereby
leaving others without enough for themselves. Because nature is given to all of mankind by God for
its common subsistence, one cannot take more than his own fair share. Property is the linchpin of
Locke’s argument for the social contract and civil government because it is the protection of their
property, including their property in their own bodies, that men seek when they decide to abandon
the State of Nature.

According to Locke, the State of Nature is not a condition of individuals, as it is for Hobbes. Rather, it
is populated by mothers and fathers with their children, or families - what he calls "conjugal society"
(par. 78). These societies are based on the voluntary agreements to care for children together, and
they are moral but not political. Political society comes into being when individual men, representing
their families, come together in the State of Nature and agree to each give up the executive power
to punish those who transgress the Law of Nature, and hand over that power to the public power of
a government. Having done this, they then become subject to the will of the majority. In other
words, by making a compact to leave the State of Nature and form society, they make “one body
politic under one government” (par. 97) and submit themselves to the will of that body. One joins
such a body, either from its beginnings, or after it has already been established by others, only by
explicit consent. Having created a political society and government through their consent, men then
gain three things which they lacked in the State of Nature: laws, judges to adjudicate laws, and the
executive power necessary to enforce these laws. Each man therefore gives over the power to
protect himself and punish transgressors of the Law of Nature to the government that he has
created through the compact.
Given that the end of "men's uniting into common-wealths"( par. 124) is the preservation of their
wealth, and preserving their lives, liberty, and well-being in general, Locke can easily imagine the
conditions under which the compact with government is destroyed, and men are justified in resisting
the authority of a civil government, such as a King. When the executive power of a government
devolves into tyranny, such as by dissolving the legislature and therefore denying the people the
ability to make laws for their own preservation, then the resulting tyrant puts himself into a State of
Nature, and specifically into a state of war with the people, and they then have the same right to
self-defense as they had before making a compact to establish society in the first place. In other
words, the justification of the authority of the executive component of government is the protection
of the people’s property and well-being, so when such protection is no longer present, or when the
king becomes a tyrant and acts against the interests of the people, they have a right, if not an
outright obligation, to resist his authority. The social compact can be dissolved and the process to
create political society begun anew.

Because Locke did not envision the State of Nature as grimly as did Hobbes, he can imagine
conditions under which one would be better off rejecting a particular civil government and returning
to the State of Nature, with the aim of constructing a better civil government in its place. It is
therefore both the view of human nature, and the nature of morality itself, which account for the
differences between Hobbes' and Locke’s views of the social contract.

c. Jean-Jacques Rousseau

Jean-Jacques Rousseau, 1712-1778, lived and wrote during what was arguably the headiest period in
the intellectual history of modern France--the Enlightenment. He was one of the bright lights of that
intellectual movement, contributing articles to the Encyclopdie of Diderot, and participating in the
salons in Paris, where the great intellectual questions of his day were pursued.

Rousseau has two distinct social contract theories. The first is found in his essay, Discourse on the
Origin and Foundations of Inequality Among Men, commonly referred to as the Second Discourse,
and is an account of the moral and political evolution of human beings over time, from a State of
Nature to modern society. As such it contains his naturalized account of the social contract, which he
sees as very problematic. The second is his normative, or idealized theory of the social contract, and
is meant to provide the means by which to alleviate the problems that modern society has created
for us, as laid out in the Second Discourse.

Rousseau wrote his Second Discourse in response to an essay contest sponsored by the Academy of
Dijon. (Rousseau had previously won the same essay contest with an earlier essay, commonly
referred to as the First Discourse.) In it he describes the historical process by which man began in a
State of Nature and over time ‘progressed' into civil society. According to Rousseau, the State of
Nature was a peaceful and quixotic time. People lived solitary, uncomplicated lives. Their few needs
were easily satisfied by nature. Because of the abundance of nature and the small size of the
population, competition was non-existent, and persons rarely even saw one another, much less had
reason for conflict or fear. Moreover, these simple, morally pure persons were naturally endowed
with the capacity for pity, and therefore were not inclined to bring harm to one another.

As time passed, however, humanity faced certain changes. As the overall population increased, the
means by which people could satisfy their needs had to change. People slowly began to live together
in small families, and then in small communities. Divisions of labor were introduced, both within and
between families, and discoveries and inventions made life easier, giving rise to leisure time. Such
leisure time inevitably led people to make comparisons between themselves and others, resulting in
public values, leading to shame and envy, pride and contempt. Most importantly however, according
to Rousseau, was the invention of private property, which constituted the pivotal moment in
humanity's evolution out of a simple, pure state into one characterized by greed, competition,
vanity, inequality, and vice. For Rousseau the invention of property constitutes humanity’s ‘fall from
grace’ out of the State of Nature.

Having introduced private property, initial conditions of inequality became more pronounced. Some
have property and others are forced to work for them, and the development of social classes begins.
Eventually, those who have property notice that it would be in their interests to create a
government that would protect private property from those who do not have it but can see that
they might be able to acquire it by force. So, government gets established, through a contract, which
purports to guarantee equality and protection for all, even though its true purpose is to fossilize the
very inequalities that private property has produced. In other words, the contract, which claims to
be in the interests of everyone equally, is really in the interests of the few who have become
stronger and richer as a result of the developments of private property. This is the naturalized social
contract, which Rousseau views as responsible for the conflict and competition from which modern
society suffers.

The normative social contract, argued for by Rousseau in The Social Contract (1762), is meant to
respond to this sorry state of affairs and to remedy the social and moral ills that have been produced
by the development of society. The distinction between history and justification, between the
factual situation of mankind and how it ought to live together, is of the utmost importance to
Rousseau. While we ought not to ignore history, nor ignore the causes of the problems we face, we
must resolve those problems through our capacity to choose how we ought to live. Might never
makes right, despite how often it pretends that it can.

The Social Contract begins with the most oft-quoted line from Rousseau: "Man was born free, and
he is everywhere in chains" (49). This claim is the conceptual bridge between the descriptive work of
the Second Discourse, and the prescriptive work that is to come. Humans are essentially free, and
were free in the State of Nature, but the ‘progress' of civilization has substituted subservience to
others for that freedom, through dependence, economic and social inequalities, and the extent to
which we judge ourselves through comparisons with others. Since a return to the State of Nature is
neither feasible nor desirable, the purpose of politics is to restore freedom to us, thereby reconciling
who we truly and essentially are with how we live together. So, this is the fundamental philosophical
problem that The Social Contract seeks to address: how can we be free and live together? Or, put
another way, how can we live together without succumbing to the force and coercion of others? We
can do so, Rousseau maintains, by submitting our individual, particular wills to the collective or
general will, created through agreement with other free and equal persons. Like Hobbes and Locke
before him, and in contrast to the ancient philosophers, all men are made by nature to be equals,
therefore no one has a natural right to govern others, and therefore the only justified authority is
the authority that is generated out of agreements or covenants.

The most basic covenant, the social pact, is the agreement to come together and form a people, a
collectivity, which by definition is more than and different from a mere aggregation of individual
interests and wills. This act, where individual persons become a people is "the real foundation of
society" (59). Through the collective renunciation of the individual rights and freedom that one has
in the State of Nature, and the transfer of these rights to the collective body, a new ‘person', as it
were, is formed. The sovereign is thus formed when free and equal persons come together and
agree to create themselves anew as a single body, directed to the good of all considered together.
So, just as individual wills are directed towards individual interests, the general will, once formed, is
directed towards the common good, understood and agreed to collectively. Included in this version
of the social contract is the idea of reciprocated duties: the sovereign is committed to the good of
the individuals who constitute it, and each individual is likewise committed to the good of the whole.
Given this, individuals cannot be given liberty to decide whether it is in their own interests to fulfill
their duties to the Sovereign, while at the same time being allowed to reap the benefits of
citizenship. They must be made to conform themselves to the general will, they must be “forced to
be free” (64).

For Rousseau, this implies an extremely strong and direct form of democracy. One cannot transfer
one's will to another, to do with as he or she sees fit, as one does in representative democracies.
Rather, the general will depends on the coming together periodically of the entire democratic body,
each and every citizen, to decide collectively, and with at least near unanimity, how to live together,
i.e., what laws to enact. As it is constituted only by individual wills, these private, individual wills
must assemble themselves regularly if the general will is to continue. One implication of this is that
the strong form of democracy which is consistent with the general will is also only possible in
relatively small states. The people must be able to identify with one another, and at least know who
each other are. They cannot live in a large area, too spread out to come together regularly, and they
cannot live in such different geographic circumstances as to be unable to be united under common
laws. (Could the present-day U.S. satisfy Rousseau’s conception of democracy? It could not. )
Although the conditions for true democracy are stringent, they are also the only means by which we
can, according to Rousseau, save ourselves, and regain the freedom to which we are naturally
entitled.

Rousseau's social contract theories together form a single, consistent view of our moral and political
situation. We are endowed with freedom and equality by nature, but our nature has been corrupted
by our contingent social history. We can overcome this corruption, however, by invoking our free
will to reconstitute ourselves politically, along strongly democratic principles, which is good for us,
both individually and collectively.
3. More Recent Social Contract Theories

a. John Rawls' A Theory of Justice

In 1972, the publication of John Rawls' extremely influential A Theory of Justice brought moral and
political philosophy back from what had been a long hiatus of philosophical consideration. Rawls’
theory relies on a Kantian understanding of persons and their capacities. For Rawls, as for Kant,
persons have the capacity to reason from a universal point of view, which in turn means that they
have the particular moral capacity of judging principles from an impartial standpoint. In A Theory of
Justice, Rawls argues that the moral and political point of view is discovered via impartiality. (It is
important to note that this view, delineated in A Theory of Justice, has undergone substantial
revisions by Rawls, and that he described his later view as "political liberalism".) He invokes this
point of view (the general view that Thomas Nagel describes as “the view from nowhere”) by
imagining persons in a hypothetical situation, the Original Position, which is characterized by the
epistemological limitation of the Veil of Ignorance. Rawls’ original position is his highly abstracted
version of the State of Nature. It is the position from which we can discover the nature of justice and
what it requires of us as individual persons and of the social institutions through which we will live
together cooperatively. In the original position, behind the veil of ignorance, one is denied any
particular knowledge of one’s circumstances, such as one’s gender, race, particular talents or
disabilities, one’s age, social status, one’s particular conception of what makes for a good life, or the
particular state of the society in which one lives. Persons are also assumed to be rational and
disinterested in one another’s well-being. These are the conditions under which, Rawls argues, one
can choose principles for a just society which are themselves chosen from initial conditions that are
inherently fair. Because no one has any of the particular knowledge he or she could use to develop
principles that favor his or her own particular circumstances, in other words the knowledge that
makes for and sustains prejudices, the principles chosen from such a perspective are necessarily fair.
For example, if one does not know whether one is female or male in the society for which one must
choose basic principles of justice, it makes no sense, from the point of view of self-interested
rationality, to endorse a principle that favors one sex at the expense of another, since, once the veil
of ignorance is lifted, one might find oneself on the losing end of such a principle. Hence Rawls
describes his theory as “justice as fairness.” Because the conditions under which the principles of
justice are discovered are basically fair, justice proceeds out of fairness.

In such a position, behind such a veil, everyone is in the same situation, and everyone is presumed to
be equally rational. Since everyone adopts the same method for choosing the basic principles for
society, everyone will occupy the same standpoint: that of the disembodied, rational, universal
human. Therefore all who consider justice from the point of view of the original position would
agree upon the same principles of justice generated out of such a thought experiment. Any one
person would reach the same conclusion as any other person concerning the most basic principles
that must regulate a just society.

The principles that persons in the Original Position, behind the Veil of Ignorance, would choose to
regulate a society at the most basic level (that is, prior even to a Constitution) are called by Rawls,
aptly enough, the Two Principles of Justice. These two principles determine the distribution of both
civil liberties and social and economic goods. The first principle states that each person in a society is
to have as much basic liberty as possible, as long as everyone is granted the same liberties. That is,
there is to be as much civil liberty as possible as long as these goods are distributed equally. (This
would, for example, preclude a scenario under which there was a greater aggregate of civil liberties
than under an alternative scenario, but under which such liberties were not distributed equally
amongst citizens.) The second principle states that while social and economic inequalities can be
just, they must be available to everyone equally (that is, no one is to be on principle denied access to
greater economic advantage) and such inequalities must be to the advantage of everyone. This
means that economic inequalities are only justified when the least advantaged member of society is
nonetheless better off than she would be under alternative arrangements. So, only if a rising tide
truly does carry all boats upward, can economic inequalities be allowed for in a just society. The
method of the original position supports this second principle, referred to as the Difference
Principle, because when we are behind the veil of ignorance, and therefore do not know what our
situation in society will be once the veil of ignorance is lifted, we will only accept principles that will
be to our advantage even if we end up in the least advantaged position in society.

These two principles are related to each other by a specific order. The first principle, distributing civil
liberties as widely as possible consistent with equality, is prior to the second principle, which
distributes social and economic goods. In other words, we cannot decide to forgo some of our civil
liberties in favor of greater economic advantage. Rather, we must satisfy the demands of the first
principle, before we move on to the second. From Rawls' point of view, this serial ordering of the
principles expresses a basic rational preference for certain kinds of goods, i.e., those embodied in
civil liberties, over other kinds of goods, i.e., economic advantage.

Having argued that any rational person inhabiting the original position and placing him or herself
behind the veil of ignorance can discover the two principles of justice, Rawls has constructed what is
perhaps the most abstract version of a social contract theory. It is highly abstract because rather
than demonstrating that we would or even have signed to a contract to establish society, it instead
shows us what we must be willing to accept as rational persons in order to be constrained by justice
and therefore capable of living in a well ordered society. The principles of justice are more
fundamental than the social contract as it has traditionally been conceived. Rather, the principles of
justice constrain that contract, and set out the limits of how we can construct society in the first
place. If we consider, for example, a constitution as the concrete expression of the social contract,
Rawls' two principles of justice delineate what such a constitution can and cannot require of us.
Rawls’ theory of justice constitutes, then, the Kantian limits upon the forms of political and social
organization that are permissible within a just society.

b. David Gauthier

In his 1986 book, Morals by Agreement, David Gauthier set out to renew Hobbesian moral and
political philosophy. In that book, he makes a strong argument that Hobbes was right: we can
understand both politics and morality as founded upon an agreement between exclusively self-
interested yet rational persons. He improves upon Hobbes' argument, however, by showing that we
can establish morality without the external enforcement mechanism of the Sovereign. Hobbes
argued that men’s passions were so strong as to make cooperation between them always in danger
of breaking down, and thus that a Sovereign was necessary to force compliance. Gauthier, however,
believes that rationality alone convinces persons not only to agree to cooperate, but to stick to their
agreements as well.

We should understand ourselves as individual Robinson Crusoes, each living on our own island, lucky
or unlucky in terms of our talents and the natural provisions of our islands, but able to enter into
negotiations and deals with one another to trade goods and services with one another. Entering into
such agreements is to our own advantage, and so rationality convinces us to both make such
agreements and stick to them as well.

Gauthier has an advantage over Hobbes when it comes to developing the argument that
cooperation between purely self-interested agents is possible. He has access to rational choice
theory and its sophisticated methodology for showing how such cooperation can arise. In particular,
he appeals to the model of the Prisoner's Dilemma to show that self-interest can be consistent with
acting cooperatively. (There is a reasonable argument to be made that we can find in Hobbes a
primitive version of the problem of the Prisoner’s Dilemma.)

According to the story of the Prisoner's Dilemma, two people have been brought in for questioning,
conducted separately, about a crime they are suspected to have committed. The police have solid
evidence of a lesser crime that they committed, but need confessions in order to convict them on
more serious charges. Each prisoner is told that if she cooperates with the police by informing on the
other prisoner, then she will be rewarded by receiving a relatively light sentence of one year in
prison, whereas her cohort will go to prison for ten years. If they both remain silent, then there will
be no such rewards, and they can each expect to receive moderate sentences of two years. And if
they both cooperate with police by informing on each other, then the police will have enough to
send each to prison for five years. The dilemma then is this: in order to serve her own interests as
well as possible, each prisoner reasons that no matter what the other does she is better off
cooperating with the police by confessing. Each reasons: "If she confesses, then I should confess,
thereby being sentenced to five years instead of ten. And if she does not confess, then I should
confess, thereby being sentenced to one year instead of two. So, no matter what she does, I should
confess." The problem is that when each reason this way, they each confess, and each goes to prison
for five years. However, had they each remained silent, thereby cooperating with each other rather
than with the police, they would have spent only two years in prison.

According to Gauthier, the important lesson of the Prisoner's Dilemma is that when one is engaged
in interaction such that others’ actions can affect one’s own interests, and vice versa, one does
better if one acts cooperatively. By acting to further the interests of the other, one serves one’s own
interests as well. We should, therefore, insofar as we are rational, develop within ourselves the
dispositions to constrain ourselves when interacting with others. We should become "constrained
maximizers" (CMs) rather remain the “straightforward maximizers” (SMs) that we would be in a
State of Nature (167).

Both SMs and CMs are exclusively self-interested and rational, but they differ with regard to
whether they take into account only strategies, or both the strategies and utilities, of whose with
whom they interact. To take into account the others' strategies is to act in accordance with how you
expect the others will act. To take into account their utilities is to consider how they will fare as a
result of your action and to allow that to affect your own actions. Both SMs and CMs take into
account the strategies of the other with whom they interact. But whereas SMs do not take into
account the utilities of those with whom they interact, CMs do. And, whereas CMs are afforded the
benefits of cooperation with others, SMs are denied such advantage. According to Gauthier, when
interacting in Prisoner’s Dilemma-like situations, where the actions of others can affect one’s own
outcome, and vice versa, rationality shows that one’s own interest is best pursued by being
cooperative, and therefore agents rationally dispose themselves to the constrain the maximization
of their own utility by adopting principles of morality. According to Gauthier, rationality is a force
strong enough to give persons internal reasons to cooperate. They do not, therefore, need Hobbes’
Sovereign with absolute authority to sustain their cooperation. The enforcement mechanism has
been internalized. "Morals by agreement" are therefore created out of the rationality of exclusively
self-interested agents.

4. Contemporary Critiques of Social Contract Theory

Given the longstanding and widespread influence that social contract theory has had, it comes as no
surprise that it is also the objects of many critiques from a variety of philosophical perspectives.
Feminists and race-conscious philosophers, in particular, have made important arguments
concerning the substance and viability of social contract theory.

a. Feminist Arguments

For the most part, feminism resists any simple or universal definition. In general though, feminists
take women's experiences seriously, as well as the impact that theories and practices have for
women’s lives. Given the pervasive influence of contract theory on social, political, and moral
philosophy, then, it is not surprising that feminists should have a great deal to say about whether
contract theory is adequate or appropriate from the point of view of taking women seriously. To
survey all of the feminist responses to social contract theory would carry us well beyond the
boundaries of the present article. I will concentrate therefore on just three of those arguments:
Carole Pateman’s argument about the relation between the contract and women’s subordination to
men, feminist arguments concerning the nature of the liberal individual, and the care argument.

i. The Sexual Contract


Carole Pateman's 1988 book, The Sexual Contract, argues that lying beneath the myth of the
idealized contract, as described by Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau, is a more fundamental contract
concerning men’s relationship to women. Contract theory represents itself as being opposed to
patriarchy and patriarchal right. (Locke’s social contract, for example, is set by him in stark contrast
to the work of Robert Filmer who argued in favor of patriarchal power.) Yet the "original pact" (2)
that precedes the social contract entered into by equals is the agreement by men to dominate and
control women. This ‘original pact’ is made by brothers, literally or metaphorically, who, after
overthrowing the rule of the father, then agree to share their domination of the women who were
previously under the exclusive control of one man, the father. The change from “classical
patriarchalism” (24) to modern patriarchy is a shift, then, in who has power over women. It is not,
however, a fundamental change in whether women are dominated by men. Men’s relationships of
power to one another change, but women’s relationship to men’s power does not. Modern
patriarchy is characterized by a contractual relationship between men, and part of that contract
involves power over women. This fact, that one form of patriarchy was not overthrown completely,
but rather was replaced with a different form, in which male power was distributed amongst more
men, rather than held by one man, is illustrated by Freud’s story of the genesis of civilization.
According to that story, a band of brothers, lorded over by a father who maintained exclusive sexual
access to the women of the tribe, kill the father, and then establish a contract among themselves to
be equal and to share the women. This is the story, whether we understand Freud’s tale to be
historically accurate or not, of modern patriarchy and its deep dependence on contract as the means
by which men control and dominate women.

Patriarchal control of women is found in at least three paradigmatic contemporary contracts: the
marriage contract, the prostitution contract, and the contract for surrogate motherhood. Each of
these contracts is concerned with men's control of women, or a particular man’s control of a
particular woman generalized. According to the terms of the marriage contract, in most states in the
U.S., a husband is accorded the right to sexual access, prohibiting the legal category of marital rape.
Prostitution is a case in point of Pateman’s claim that modern patriarchy requires equal access by
men to women, in particular sexual access, access to their bodies. And surrogate motherhood can be
understood as more of the same, although in terms of access to women’s reproductive capacities.
All these examples demonstrate that contract is the means by which women are dominated and
controlled. Contract is not the path to freedom and equality. Rather, it is one means, perhaps the
most fundamental means, by which patriarchy is upheld.

ii. The Nature of the Liberal Individual

Following Pateman's argument, a number of feminists have also called into question the very nature
of the person at the heart of contract theory. The Liberal Individual, the contractor, is represented
by the Hobbesian man, Locke’s proprietor, Rousseau’s "Noble Savage," Rawls’s person in the original
position, and Gauthier’s Robinson Crusoe. The liberal individual is purported to be universal:
raceless, sexless, classless, disembodied, and is taken to represent an abstract, generalized model of
humanity writ large. Many philosophers have argued, however, that when we look more closely at
the characteristics of the liberal individual, what we find is not a representation of universal
humanity, but a historically located, specific type of person. C.B. Macpherson, for example, has
argued that Hobbesian man is, in particular, a bourgeois man, with the characteristics we would
expect of a person during the nascent capitalism that characterized early modern Europe. Feminists
have also argued that the liberal individual is a particular, historical, and embodied person. (As have
race-conscious philosophers, such as Charles Mills, to be discussed below.) More specifically, they
have argued that the person at the heart of liberal theory, and the social contract, is gendered.
Christine Di Stefano, in her 1991 book Configurations of Masculinity, shows that a number of
historically important modern philosophers can be understood to develop their theories from within
the perspective of masculinity, as conceived of in the modern period. She argues that Hobbes’s
conception of the liberal individual, which laid the groundwork for the dominant modern conception
of the person, is particularly masculine in that it is conceived as atomistic and solitary and as not
owing any of its qualities, or even its very existence, to any other person, in particular its mother.
Hobbes’s human, is therefore, radically individual, in a way that is specifically owing to the character
of modern masculinity. Virginia Held, in her 1993 book, Feminist Morality, argues that social contract
theory implicitly relies on a conception of the person that can be best described as “economic man.”
“Economic man” is concerned first and foremost to maximize his own, individually considered
interests, and he enters into contracts as a means by which to achieve this end. “Economic man”,
however, fails to represent all persons in all times and places. In particular, it fails to adequately
represent children and those who provide them with the care they require, who have historically
been women. The model of “economic man” cannot, therefore, fairly claim to be a general
representation of all persons. Similarly, Annette Baier argues that Gauthier’s conception of the
liberal individual who enters into the social contract as a means by which to maximize his own
individually considered interests is gendered in that it does not take seriously the position of either
children or the women who most usually are responsible for caring for those children.

iii. Arguing from Care

Theorizing from within the emerging tradition of care ethics, feminist philosophers such as Baier and
Held argue that social contract theory fails as an adequate account of our moral or political
obligations. Social contract theory, in general, only goes so far as to delineate our rights and
obligations. But this may not be enough to adequately reveal the full extent of what it means to be a
moral person, and how fully to respond to others with whom one interacts through relations of
dependence. Baier argues that Gauthier, who conceives of affective bonds between persons as non-
essential and voluntary, therefore fails to represent the fullness of human psychology and
motivations. She argues that this therefore leads to a crucial flaw in social contract theory. Liberal
moral theory is in fact parasitic upon the very relations between persons from which it seeks to
liberate us. While Gauthier argues that we are freer the more that we can see affective relations as
voluntary, we must nonetheless, in the first place, be in such relationships (e.g., the mother-child
relationship) in order to develop the very capacities and qualities lauded by liberal theory. Certain
kinds of relationships of dependence, in other words, are necessary in the first place if we are to
become the very kinds of persons who are capable of entering into contracts and agreements. In a
similar vein, Held has argued that the model of "economic man" fails to capture much of what
constitutes meaningful moral relations between people. Understanding human relations in purely
contractual terms constitutes, according to her argument “an impoverished view of human
aspiration” (194). She therefore suggests that we consider other models of human relationships
when looking for insight into morality. In particular, she offers up the paradigm of the mother-child
relationship to at least supplement the model of individual self-interested agents negotiating with
one another through contracts. Such a model is more likely to match up with many of the moral
experiences of most people, especially women.

Feminist critiques of the contractarian approaches to our collective moral and political lives continue
to reverberate through social and political philosophy. One such critique, that of Carole Pateman,
has influenced philosophers writing outside of feminist traditions.

b. Race-Conscious Argument

Charles Mills' 1997 book, The Racial Contract, is a critique not only of the history of Western political
thought, institutions, and practices, but, more specifically, of the history of social contract theory. It
is inspired by Carole Pateman’s The Sexual Contract, and seeks to show that non-whites have a
similar relationship to the social contract as do women. As such, it also calls into question the
supposed universality of the liberal individual who is the agent of contract theory.

Mills' central argument is that there exists a ‘racial contract’ that is even more fundamental to
Western society than the social contract. This racial contract determines in the first place who
counts as full moral and political persons, and therefore sets the parameters of who can ‘contract in’
to the freedom and equality that the social contract promises. Some persons, in particular white
men, are full persons according to the racial contract. As such they are accorded the right to enter
into the social contract, and into particular legal contracts. They are seen as fully human and
therefore as deserving of equality and freedom. Their status as full persons accords them greater
social power. In particular, it accords them the power to make contracts, to be the subjects of the
contract, whereas other persons are denied such privilege and are relegated to the status of objects
of contracts.

This racial contract is to some extent a meta-contract, which determines the bounds of personhood
and parameters of inclusion and exclusion in all the other contracts that come after it. It manifests
itself both formally and informally. It is an agreement, originally among European men in the
beginning of the modern period, to identify themselves as ‘white' and therefore as fully human, and
to identify all others, in particular the natives with whom they were beginning to come into contact,
as ‘other’: non-white and therefore not fully human. So, race is not just a social construct, as others
have argued, it is more especially a political construct, created to serve a particular political end, and
the political purposes of a specific group. The contract allows some persons to treat other persons,
as well as the lands they inhabit, as resources to be exploited. The enslavement of millions of
Africans and the appropriation of the Americas from those who inhabited them, are examples of this
racial contract at work in history (such as Locke’s claim that Native Americans did not own the land
they lived on because they did not farm it and therefore did not own it). This contract is not
hypothetical, as Hobbes describes the one argued for in his Leviathan. This is an actual contract, or
series of contracts, made by real men of history. It is found in such documents as Papal Bulls and
Locke’s writings on Native Americans, and acted upon in such historical events as the voyages of
discovery made by Europeans and the colonization of Africa, Asia, and the Americas. The racial
contract makes possible and justifies some people, in virtue of their alleged superiority, exploiting
the peoples, lands, and resources of other races.

From Mills' perspective then, racism is not just an unhappy accident of Western democratic and
political ideals. It is not the case that we have a political system that was perfectly conceived and
unfortunately imperfectly applied. One of the reasons that we continue to think that the problem of
race in the West is relatively superficial, that it does not go all the way down, is the hold that the
idealized social contract has on our imagination. We continue to believe, according to Mills, in the
myths that social contract theory tells us - that everyone is equal, that all will be treated the same
before the law, that the Founding Fathers were committed to equality and freedom for all persons,
etc. One of the very purposes of social contract theory, then, is to keep hidden from view the true
political reality – some persons will be accorded the rights and freedoms of full persons, and the rest
will be treated as sub-persons. The racial contract informs the very structure of our political systems,
and lays the basis for the continuing racial oppression of non-whites. We cannot respond to it,
therefore, by simply adding more non-whites into the mix of our political institutions,
representation, and so on. Rather, we must reexamine our politics in general, from the point of view
of the racial contract, and start from where we are, with full knowledge of how our society has been
informed by the systematic exclusion of some persons from the realm of politics and contract. This
"naturalized" feature of the racial contract, meaning that it tells a story about who we actually are
and what is included in our history, is better, according to Mills, because it holds the promise of
making it possible for us to someday actually live up to the norms and values that are at the heart of
the Western political traditions.

5. Conclusion

Virginia Held has argued that "Contemporary Western society is in the grip of contractual thinking"
(193). Contractual models have come to inform a vast variety of relations and interaction between
persons, from students and their teachers, to authors and their readers. Given this, it would be
difficult to overestimate the effect that social contract theory has had, both within philosophy, and
on the wider culture. Social contract theory is undoubtedly with us for the foreseeable future. But so
too are the critiques of such theory, which will continue to compel us to think and rethink the nature
of both ourselves and our relations with one another.

6. References and Further Reading

Baier, Annette. 1988. "Pilgrim's Progress: Review of David Gauthier, Morals by Agreement."
Canadian Journal of Philosophy Vol. 18, No. 2. (June 1988): 315-330.

Baier, Annette. 1994. Moral Prejudices: Essays on Ethics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Braybrooke, David. 1976. "The Insoluble Problem of the Social Contract." Dialogue Vol. XV, No. 1: 3-
37.
DiStefano, Christine. 1991. Configurations of Masculinity: A Feminist Perspective on Modern Political
Theory. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

Filmer, Robert. ‘Patriarcha' and Other Writings. Cambridge University Press (1991).

Gauthier, David. 1986. Morals by Agreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Gauthier, David. 1988. "Hobbes's Social Contract." Noûs 22: 71-82.

Gauthier, David. 1990. Moral Dealing: Contract, Ethics, and Reason. Cornell: Cornell University Press.

Gauthier, David. 1991. "Why Contractarianism?" in Vallentyne 1991: 13-30.

Gilligan, Carol. 1982. In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women's Development.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Hampton, Jean. 1986. Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.

Hampton, Jean. 1993. "Feminist Contractarianism." In Antony, Louise M. and Witt, Charlotte
(Editors). 1993. A Mind of One's Own: Essays on Reason and Objectivity. Boulder CO: Westview
Press, Inc.: 1993: 227-255.

Held, Virginia. 1977. "Rationality and Reasonable Cooperation." Social Research (Winter 1977): 708-
744.

Held, Virginia. 1993. Feminist Morality: Transforming Culture, Society, and Politics. Chicago: The
University of Chicago Press.

Hobbes, Thomas. 1651a. Leviathan. C.B Macpherson (Editor). London: Penguin Books (1985)

Kavka, Gregory S. 1986. Hobbesian Moral and Political Theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Locke, John. Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration. Yale University Press
(2003).

Macpherson, C.B. 1973. Democratic Theory: Essays in Retrieval. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Mills, Charles. 1997. The Racial Contract. Cornell University Press.

Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, State and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.

Okin, Susan Moller. 1989. Justice, Gender, and the Family. New York: Basic Books.

Pateman, Carole. 1988. The Sexual Contract. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

Plato. Five Dialogues. (Trans. G.M.A. Grube) Hackett Publishing Company (1981).

Plato. Republic. (Trans. G.M.A. Grube, Revised by C.D.C. Reeve) Hackett Publishing Company (1992)

Poundstone, William. 1992. Prisoner's Dilemma: John Von Neumann, Game Theory, and the Puzzle
of the Bomb. New York: Doubleday.

Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Harvard University Press.

Rawls, John. 1993. Political Liberalism. Columbia University Press.


Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. The Basic Political Writings. (Trans. Donald A. Cress) Hackett Publishing
Company (1987).

Sandel, Michael. 1982. Liberalism and the Limits of Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Vallentyne, Peter. (Editor). 1991. Contractarianism and Rational Choice: Essays on David Gauthier's
Morals by Agreement. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Author Information

Celeste Friend

Email: cfriend@hamilton.edu

Hamilton College

U. S. A.

An encyclopedia of philosophy articles written by professional philosophers.

ABOUT

EDITORS

DESIRED ARTICLES

SUBMISSIONS

VOLUNTEER

STAY CONNECTED

BROWSE BY TOPIC

Browse by Topic

© Copyright Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy and its Authors | ISSN 2161-0002

You might also like