You are on page 1of 120

Maurido Beuchot, O.P.

mm

History of
Philosophy
in Colonial
Mexico
Translated by Elizabeth Millan
Foreword by Jorge J. E. Gracia

The Catholic University of America Press


Washington, i>.<:.
Contents

Prologue vii
Originally published as Historia de lafilosofia en el Mexico Colonial by Foreword: The Origins of Hispanic Philosophy xi
Editorial herder, Provenza 388, 08025 Barcelona, Spain. Copyright
© 1996. This translation published by permission. Introduction: Understanding the History of Philosophy in
Colonial Mexico 1
Copyright © 1998
The Catholic University of America Press 2 The Sixteenth Century: The Humanist Philosophers 19
All rights reserved
Printed in the United States of America 3 The Sixteenth Century: The Scholastic Philosophers 60
Franciscans / 60 Dominicans / 63
The paper used in this publication meets the minimum A U0ustin ians I 70 Jesuits 181
requirements of American National Standards for Information
Science—Permanence of Paper for Printed Library materials, ANSI 4 The Seventeenth Century 92
Z39.48-1984. "Franciscans 198 Dominicans 1101
A ugustinians 1103 Mercedarians /107
Jesuits 1107 Secular Clergy 1113
Religious Women 1125
LIBRARY OF CONGRESS CATALOGING-IN-PUBLICATION DATA
Beuchot, Mauricio. "> The Eighteenth Century 138
[Historia de la filosofia en el Mexico colonial. English] Franciscans 1140 Dominicans 1144
The history of philosophy in colonial Mexico / Mauricio Beuchot; Augustinians 1146 Carmelites 1147
translated by Elizabeth Millan; foreword by Jorge J. E. Gracia. Mercedarians 1148 Jesuits 1148
p. cm. Oratorians 1165 Secular Clergy 1173
Includes bibliographical references and index.
1. Philosophy—Mexico—History. 2. Philosophy, Mexican. << The Nineteenth Century 177
3. Mexico—Intellectual life. I. Title. I'lmtiisiiiits 1177 Dominicans 1178
BI016.B4913 1998 Jesuits 117<> Secular Clergy 1182
199'.72—dc21
98-9210
ISBN 0-8132-0906-4 (alk. paper) Hll.lloKr.iphy 185
Index i""
Prologue

There are many reasons why a study on the history of philosophy in Colo-
nial Mexico is important for the English-speaking world. First, there is a
growing interest in Hispanic issues in general, and more specifically in Mex-
ico as it is the Hispanic country closest to the United States. Moreover, the
philosophical culture of Colonial Mexico occupied a central place in the for-
mation of Mexican thought. This influence extended to some areas of what
Is now known as the United States; for example, the Franciscans and Jesuits
established missions in California, Texas, and other places.
The colonial period is, without a doubt, an important part of the cultural
heritage of Mexico. Despite this fact, many studies of Mexican thought begin
wilh the early twentieth century and positivism, which was produced in el
Porflriato, and then advance to the period of the conflicts between the liber-
als and conservatives, with the view that these conflicts were a principle fac-
IIH lor I he birth of the republic. These studies do not go back further than the
middle of the nineteenth century. Other studies take the period of indepen-
dence as their point of departure and use this period to refer us to the princi-
ples of the nineteenth century. Such approaches are useful and interesting,
I >111 they neglect three entire centuries (from 1521-1821) of philosophical
development, one of the most important periods for the formation of Mexi-
i .in thought,
Moreover, the colonial period is the period of the fusion between the
Indigenous people and the Spanish and il is the beginning of the long
proCCIS ol the formation Of mestizo culture. In addition to the peninsular

vll
viii History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Prologue ix

and indigenous populations, those of the criollos and the mestizos also grew Indigenous culture, compiling this information in order to understand better
appreciably. The criollos were Spaniards born in colonial Mexico, and the mes- the new nationality that was emerging. He also studied the colonization of
tizos were those who were both indigenous and Spanish. The latter soon some parts of Florida. Finally, in the expression of literature, we find Indige-
began to identify themselves as uniquely Mexican and to reflect upon this nous and even black and mulatto elements within the poetry of Sister Juana.
new nationality. There is an entire current of national thought dedicated to The contribution of the Jesuit Francisco Xavier Clavigero stands out; he
reflecting upon the issue of what it means to be Mexican. These thinkers re- knew various Indigenous languages and was a teacher of Indians at the Cole-
alized that the Mexicans were not only Indigenous, they were also Spanish, gio de San Xavier. He shared with Siguenza a passion for Indigenous cus-
still connected in some ways to the distant European peninsula, even if their toms, and he wrote a Historia antigua de Mexico, in which he collected numer-
home was in Mexico. ous data on the Mexicans and prepared various treatises defending the
The criollos and mestizos infused the colony with their consciousness of 'Americans' (Hispanics, Indians, etc.) from the accusations of such 'enlight-
forging a new race, a new nation. In this way, together with the philosophi- ened' thinkers as Buffon, De Pauw, Raynal, and others, who held that every-
cal reflections of the Spaniards, the reflections of the criollos and mestizos thing American was inferior to the European. According to these thinkers,
emerge. The contribution of the criollos was stronger, but the work of the the animals in Colonial Mexico included less developed animals such as lions
mestizos for the cause of the indigenous groups should not be underestimated. without manes (pumas) and dwarf camels (llamas), and the human inhabi-
Scholars have said that the colony was primarily a colony of Spaniards and tants also were considered to be inferior at such latitudes; they imagined the
criollos and that the mestizos and the Indigenous would have to wait until the land to be an area submerged in swamps and choked by impenetrable jun-
nineteenth and twentieth centuries before they would create for themselves gles. Clavigero counters all of these biased assumptions with reliable infor-
a strong presence in the history of their land. Yet this reveals a misunder- mation and careful arguments, using the best sources to express the great-
standing, for the work of the mestizos goes back to the sixteenth century. ness of Indigenous cultures, of which he felt himself to be an heir. He also
They made important contributions to the art of this period which reached wrote an interesting Historia de la Antigua California in which he narrates a
its apex in the Baroque. Even if many contributions to the thought of this part of the colonization and evangelization of these lands by the Jesuits, tes-
period were made by criollos, the Indigenous influence was not absent. The tifying to the influence that colonial thought had there.
relevance of the Indigenous for the work of the criollos is particularly strong The main current of Mexican colonial philosophy was Scholasticism. A
in their efforts to liberate themselves from their Spanish forebears. The In- si long current of Renaissance humanism also was present in sixteenth-century
digenous elements of their culture provided the criollos the means to differ- Mexican thought, sometimes in its pure form, sometimes in a mix of
entiate themselves clearly from their Spanish roots. Thus the criollos dis- Scholastic humanism. Many Scholastic thinkers were, to a greater or lesser
cussed the Indigenous elements present in their philosophy, art, and religion. degree, influenced by the Renaissance. Elements of neo-Platonism and Sto-
Beginning in the sixteenth century, there were some Indigenous writ- icism can be found as well in, for example, the work of Dr. Francisco
ers—the teachers of the Colegio de Santa Cruz de Tlatelolco, for example— I Icrnandez. Already in the seventeenth century, there is a touch of Stoicism
and, at the same time, there were some mestizos, such as Friar Diego de Val- in the poetry of Juan de Sandoval y Zapata. In the seventeenth century, one
ades, the son of a conquistador and a Tlaxcaltecan Indian. To a much greater notes the presence of hermetism, above all in the work of the Jesuit Atanasio
extent, though, was the criollos who, in addition to criollismo, defended the Kl icher. The Society of Jesus practiced quite effectively a certain syncretism
Indigenous and the mestizo. For example, at the end of the sixteenth century thai created a favorable atmosphere for the mestizaje and the Baroque. In
in Spain, Father Juan de Zapata y Sandoval, who was born in the Indies and I his way, in addition to a type of humanist Scholasticism, there was also a
taught in Valladolid, opposed the Spaniards and demanded that responsibili- baroque Scholasticism, with touches of hermetism and other currents of the
ties, positions, and offices be given to criollos, mestizos, and even to Indians, in period, and even some pure hermetism (if one can even speak of such a
this order of preference. He claimed that the Indians themselves would make Ihltig). Toward the end of the seventeenth century, the reception of modern
better bishops because they knew the language and customs of their people. philosophy and science began and, alter much opposition, it grew quite
In another case, Carlos de Slglienza y G6ngora studied many aspects of the •.Hung hy Ihe second lull' of Ihe eighteenth century. Tills reception of modern
x History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico

thought was largely the result of the efforts of the Jesuits but also of the Ora-
torians, the lay clergy, and others. The combination of these modern ideas
with the more traditional Scholastic doctrines resulted in an eclecticism, or a
modernized Scholasticism. Purely modern thinkers are not found until the
end of the eighteenth century and the beginning of the nineteenth century.
Scholasticism formed the foundation for Mexican colonial thought, and
recently, Scholasticism has received growing attention from scholars, not
only as a guide to the past but as a tool for understanding the present.
Scholastic contributions to logic, philosophy of language, metaphysics, ethics,
and other areas have found some contemporary applications. Scholastic doc-
trines have contributed interesting points of view to such diverse issues as
the problem of universals, of individuation, of justice, among others, in such
Foreword
a way that these doctrines continue to serve the present.
The Origins of Hispanic Philosophy
Jorge J. E. Gratia
Jorge J. E. Gracia

I his book fills a large gap in an important segment of the history of Western
philosophy: Latin American philosophy. This gap is largely the result of an
dltempt to view the history of philosophy in Spain, Portugal, and each of
lliclr colonies and former colonies in the New World as separate and largely
unconnected developments. This is evident in the standard general catego-
M/.nioiis according to which the philosophical thought of the mentioned ge-
">:i.i|>hical areas is divided and studied: Spanish philosophy, Portuguese phi-
losophy, Catalan philosophy, Latin American philosophy, Spanish-American
philosophy, and Ibero-American philosophy.
I he category 'Spanish philosophy' usually includes only the philosophy
ili.n has taken place in the territory occupied by the modern Spanish state,
» hcihci before or after the state was constituted in the fifteenth century as
i M-MIII ill the efforts of Ferdinand of Aragon and Isabella of Castile. Thus,
niii.i histories of Spanish philosophy discuss the thought of Roman, Islamic,
ind lewish philosophers who worked in that territory, as well as of medieval
Hid subsequent authors Who did likewise. In some cases, these accounts
tiiiurnlrate on Castlllian-speaking philosophers, and at other limes they
rtUn Include those who speak Catalan and Portuguese. They generally ig-
nore, however, the work ol Latin American authors and seldom explore the

xl
xii H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n C o l o n i a l M e x i c o Foreword xiii

close ties of those authors to philosophers working in the Iberian peninsula. 1 be ignored in an overall history of Renaissance philosophy as Beuchot makes
General histories of philosophy seldom, if ever, do justice to the historical d e a r in this book. 5 Just as with histories and studies of Renaissance thought,
relations between Iberian and Latin American philosophers nor to the phi- histories of the Counter-Reformation, late Scholastic philosophy, and so on
losophy of Latin America. 2 Indeed, it is particularly rare to find any reference generally neglect Latin America, even t h o u g h these histories do m a k e refer-
to Latin American contributions to philosophy in histories other t h a n histo- ence to Iberian contributions to philosophy. 6
3
ries of Latin American philosophy. This becomes quite evident w h e n one The general neglect of Latin American thought outside Latin American
turns to particular periods of the history of philosophy, such as the periods countries makes n o historical sense. What is particularly distressing is to see
which especially occupy Beuchot, the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. i he failure to take into account the close relations of the philosophy of Latin
This period is studied u n d er such labels as Renaissance Philosophy, Counter- America and the countries of the Iberian peninsula even within studies pro-
Reformation Philosophy, Late Scholasticism, Late Medieval Philosophy, Sec- duced in Latin America and the Iberian peninsula. For texts dislodged from
ond Scholasticism, and Silver Age of Scholasticism, to m e n t i o n just the terms I In- tradition which produced t h e m are silent, and m a n y of the texts pro-
most frequently used. Some historians may w a n t to argue that there is justi- duced by Latin American and Iberian philosophers are the product of close
fication for this oversight in some cases. Indeed, one could argue that the im- i i-l.ilions between Latin America and the Iberian peninsula. This is especially
pact of the Renaissance in Latin America came too late to be incorporated i lear in the case of Latin American Scholastics, because their link to the au-
into a general history of the Renaissance, and also that the vector of influ- lliors of the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries they emulated was medi-
ence w e n t only one way, from Europe to Latin America, and not vice versa. 4 ated by Iberian Scholastics. Alonso de la Vera Cruz (15047-1584) and Al-
It is not true, however, that the impact of European Renaissance though t on ii ii iso Briceno (15877-1669?) cannot properly be understood w h e n one does
Latin America came too late to be considered in histories of Renaissance nol lake into account the work of Iberian Thomists and Scotists o n w h o m
thought; h u m a n i s m influenced Latin American thought via Iberian thought iln-y partly relied or throug h w h o m they approached the work of Thomas
beginning in the first half of the sixteenth century. Moreover, although it is Aquinas (12257-1274) and Duns Scotus (12657-1308), as Beuchot makes
true that Latin American h u m a n i s m did not influence European humanism, i lear in this book. 7 But this problem is not restricted to this period. The work
it does nonetheless present some interesting characteristics which should not i)l some Latin Americans in the twentieth century w h o looked to Nicolai
il.uimann and M a x Scheler as intellectual mentors, for example, is incom-
1. Cf. Alain Guy, Histoire de la philosophic espagnole, 12th ed. (Toulouse: Universite de i>icln-nsible unless one keeps in mind that they first learned about t h e m
Toulouse-Le Mirail, 1985); Marcial Solana, Historia de lafilosofiaespahola: Epoca del Re-
nacimiento (sigh XVI), 3 vols. (Madrid: Real Academia de Ciencias Exactas, Fisicas y Nat- through Jose Ortega y Gasset (1883-1955). Indeed, there is an Orteguean
urales, 1941); and Jose Luis Abellan, Historia critica del pensamiento espahol, 1 vols.
(Madrid: Espasa-Calpe, 1979-91).
> lor other studies, see Jose M. Gallegos Rocafull, El pensamiento mexicano en los sig-
2. For example, Wilhelm Windelband's influential A History of Philosophy, 2 vols.
/ii.v XVI y XVII, 2d ed. (Mexico: Universidad Nacional Autonoma de Mexico, 1974);
(New York: Harper and Brothers, 1958), and W. T. Jones's extensive, multivolume A
tllllllc Furlong, Nacimiento y desarrollo de la filosofia en el Rw de La Plata, 1536-1810
History of Western Philosophy (New York: Harcourt, Brace, & World, 1952) do not make a
(llui'lios Aires: Guillermo Kraft, 1952); Alain Guy, Panorama de la philosophic Ibero-
single reference to Latin American philosophers.
\mMcaine du XVIe siecle a nos jours (Geneva: Patifio, 1989); and Gabriel Mendez Plan-
3. Even in histories of Western philosophy that take into account Iberian develop-
' .II it-. Ilumanismo mexicano del siglo XVI (Mexico: Universidad Nacional Autonoma de
ments this is true. See, for example, Frederick Copleston, A History of Philosophy (New
Mi urn, 1946).
York: Image Books, 1950). It is only recently and sporadically that general dictionaries
ft Carlo Giacon's La seconda scolastica, 2 vols. (Milan: Fratelli Bocca, 1946), and
and encyclopedias of philosophy include references to Latin American philosophy.
'.i liinill's Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy pay considerable attention to Iber-
Only general histories of philosophy produced by Latin American philosophers contain
i HI philosophy (see in particular the chapters by Charles H. Lohr and E. J. Ashworth in
materials on Latin American thought. See, for example, Jose Vasconcelos, Historia del
il» latter). Clher histories that cover the period do not do so. Cf. Norman Kretzman, et
pensamiento fUosofko (Mexico: Ediciones de la Universidad Nacional de Mexico, 1937.
ill fdv. The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
4. Among histories and studies of Renaissance thought that ignore Latin America, VI r.lly PrcSS, 19K2).
see, for example, Paul Oskar Kristeller, Renaissance Thought and Its Sources (New York:
' i Concerning Alonso de la Vera Cruz and his relations to Iberian thought, see also
Columbia University Press, 1979); Paul Oskar Kristeller, Renaissance Thought: The Classic,
W.illfi Redmond and Manikin Beuchot, Pensamiento y realidad en Pray Alonso de la Vera
Scholastic, and Humanistic Strains (New York: Harper and Brothers, 1961); and Charles B.
> nit (Mexico: Universidad Autonoma de Mexico, 1987). Concerning Briceno, see Wal-
Schmitt, et al„ eds., The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy (Cambridge: Cam-
li i I l.i 1111 is»li Bspfndoln, l:.u torno a lafilosofiaen Chile IW4-I810 (Santiago: Universidad
bridge University Press, 1988).
• ihilh.i de Chile, 1963), pp, 24 10.
xiv H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n C o l o n i a l M e x i c o Foreword xv

'color' to the Germanism of Samuel Ramos (1897-1959) and others w h o re- ever, that the use of this category does not imply that there is something pe-
8
lied o n H a r t m a n n and Scheler for m a n y of their ideas. Although this color culiar, some idiosyncratic feature or features, that characterize such philoso-
fades somewhat as Latin Americans learn German a n d become directly ac- phy throughout its history." M u c h Spanish and Latin American thought of
quainted with German texts, it never quite disappears, for the patterns of I he last one h u n d r e d years has devoted itself to the search for the uniqu e
interpretation and emphasis established at the beginning left discernible features which characterize Spanish, Latin American, and national philoso-
9
traces. phies, distinguishing t h e m from each other and from the philosophies of
The same can be said about studying Iberian philosophy apart from Latin other countries and cultures. 14 This effort, however, has been to a great ex-
American philosophy, for even cases in which the philosophy of Latin Amer- lent fruitless, for it has been difficult to identify even one feature that can
ica did not explicitly influence Iberian philosophers, the Latin American real- si'I've to characterize any of these philosophies, let alone w h a t I refer to here
ity did. Consider t h e case of Iberian philosophers from the sixteenth century, •is Hispanic philosophy. There are n o doubt certain concerns, certain ap-
such as Francisco de Vitoria (1492/3-1546). Can w e ignore the fact that proaches, and certain methods in philosophy that characterize one or m o re
m u c h of w h a t they thought about philosophically was prompted by the n e w periods of the history of Hispanic philosophy, a fact which is well established
reality they confronted as a result of the discovery? 10 Did they not see that in numerous studies. 15 But there is n o definitive evidence that indicates this
n e w reality through the eyes of those w h o lived and traveled to the colonies? may be true for all the philosophy included u n d e r the epithet 'Hispanic'.
It was Latin Americans, w h e t h e r adopted or native, w h o provided Iberian The category of Hispanic philosophy needs to be understood differently. I
philosophers of the sixteenth century with m a n y of the issues and themes propose to understand it as the philosophy produced by a group of philoso-
they were to explore. Again, this need not be restricted to that age. The most phers w h o span diverse political, territorial, linguistic, and ethnic and racial
distinguished group of Spanish philosophers in the twentieth century, the boundaries but w h o are closely tied historically. It is not language that ties
transterrados (fugitives from the Spanish Civil War), moved to Latin America
and were as influenced by the philosophers they found or helped develop I he Iberian peninsula. Its use was popularized by the members of the Generation of
there as they influenced t h e m . " 1898, a Spanish group of intellectuals who flourished at the turn of the century and
who can be considered the progenitors of modern Iberian thought. In philosophy, the
The use of the category 'Hispanic philosophy' is helpful in focusing atten- in in 'Hispanic' has been used to refer to the philosophy of Spain and Spanish America
tion on historical relations and p h e n o m e n a that are generally ignored in his- liy Eduardo Nicol. See his ProMema de la filosofia hispanica.
I l. In this I must differ with Nicol and those who have tried to see some common
tories that use other categories and divisions. 12 It should be made clear, h o w - element to all Hispanic philosophy. See Eduardo Nicol, "Meditation del propio ser: La
Insp.inidad," in Filosofia e identidad cultural en America latina, ed. Jorge J. E. Gratia and
8. Cf. Samuel Ramos's Hacia un nuevo humanismo: Programa de una antropologia filoso- Iv.m .laksic (Caracas: Monte Avila, 1988).
fica (Mexico: Fondo de Cultura Economica, 1962). 14. Ivan Jaksic and I have gathered the most important texts of this controversy
9. Cf. Francisco Romero's Theory of Man, trans. William Cooper (Berkeley: Univer- II PI n cming Latin American philosophy in the collection cited in the previous note. The
sity of California Press, 1964); and Risieri Frondizi's What Is Value? An Introduction to Ax- • onlroversy was fueled in part by the peninsular quest for a cultural ethos so evident in
iology, trans. Solomon Lipp (La Salle, 111.: Open Court, 1963). Ihc < ieneration of 1898 and in subsequent authors, and it received philosophical justi-
10. In the case of Vitoria, the discovery seems to be an important concern, as is evi- llirillon through Ortega y Gasset's perspectivism. It was explicitly formulated as the
dent in Reledio de indis (1538) and Relectio de iure belli (1539). In fact, there is substantial problem of Latin American philosophical identity by Leopoldo Zea in 1942 and, al-
evidence that colonial Latin American thinkers influenced not only Iberian authors but lliotlgh il found immediate detractors, such as Risieri Frondizi, the controversy still sur-
also European philosophers such as Descartes. See Mauricio Beuchot, "Aportaciones de vives In various forms. For Frondizi's objections, see "Hay una filosofia iberoameri-
pensadores novohispanos a la filosofia europea y universal," in Estudios de historia y irtllfl?" Realidad 3 (1948), 158-70. Zea's original article, "En torno a una filosofia
filosofia en el Mexico colonial, Mexico (UNAM, 1991), pp. 43-51. ,unci liana," and Frondizi's article are reproduced in Gratia and Jaksic, Filosofia e identi-
11. On the transterrados, see Jose Luis Abellan, Filosofia espanola en America (1936— ilthl cultural, pp. 187-207 and 211-27 respectively. Ofelia Schutte explores the issue of
1966) (Madrid: Bdiciones Guadarrama, 1967). The concern of Jose Gaos, Eduardo 11 ill in, 11 Identity in Latin America in Cultural Identity and Social Liberation in Latin Ameri-
Nicol, and other transterrados with the relation of Latin American thought to Iberian • ,iii Thought (Albany, N.Y.: SUNY Press, 1993).
thought is evident in their writings and can be explained only by the influence that I V See, for example, -Lafilosofiaen America: Trabajos presentados en el IXCongreso Inter-
Latin Americans and the Latin American reality had on them. Gaos's Historia del pen- Mmrtcano de Filosofia, 2 vols. (Caracas: Sociedad Venezolana de Filosofia, 1979); Ideas en
samiento de lengua espanola en la edad contempordnea (1744-1944) (Mexico: Seneca, 1945) IOIIIO de Latinoamirica, 2 vols. (Mexico: Oniversldad Nacional Autonoma de Mexico,
and Nicol's El problema de lafilosofiahispanica (Madrid: Editorial Tccnos, 1961) make no I 086),' Jorge I. li. Grade, ed., latin American Philosophy in the Twentieth Century (Buffalo,
sense plucked from the Latin American experience. N Y.: Prometheus Hooks, 1986); and Anu'rica Latina: Historia y destino, 2 vols. (Mexico:
12. The term 'Hispanic' is a derivative from Hispania, I he name used by Romans for I llllverildld National Autonomy de Mexico, 1992).
xvi History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Foreword xvii

these philosophers, for some of them write in Latin, whereas others write in periods or countries which more clearly have characteristics in common? In
Catalan, Spanish, or Portuguese. Nor do they come from the same country. short, what do we gain from the study of Hispanic philosophy that we do not
Some of them were born in Spain or Catalonia, but others were born in Por- already know and know better from the study of say, Spanish, Catalan, Por-
tugal and the various Spanish and Portuguese colonies and countries of Latin luguese, and Latin American philosophy? My claim is that we gain a greater
America. Indeed, in many cases they taught and wrote in lands other than understanding of the historical reality of a particular area of the history of
their native countries. Finally, they cannot be regarded as having the same philosophy that is otherwise missed.
ethnic or racial background, since their origins differ, some being European, A history of philosophy is an account of how ideas developed and thus in-
others being descendants of Africans or native Americans, and still others volves an account of how philosophers influenced each other. For an ac-
representing a mixture of various races and ethnic groups. What these count to be historical it must pay careful attention to the events and figures
philosophers have in common is not language, country, race, or ethnic back- I hat played roles in history, avoiding the introduction of artificial divisions
ground but rather a history. It is the events of that history, the historical real- among them. My claim is that the notion of a Hispanic philosophy more
ity they share, that provides the unity that brings them together. I ban any other notion reflects the historical reality of the philosophy pro-
Naturally, historical ties tend to generate common characteristics, but duced in Spain, Catalonia, Portugal, and Latin America, for it recognizes that
those characteristics may not extend beyond certain periods of time or geo- (here are no fast boundaries among the philosophers of these territories.
graphical areas. There can be continuity without commonality. A may follow Consider Francisco Suarez, who was born in Spain but taught in Portugal for
B, and B may follow C, and C may follow D, thus implying a connection be- ma ny years, and consider Antonio Rubio (1548-1615), who worked in Mex-
tween A and D, even though A may have nothing in common with D. This is ico but whose Logic became a textbook in Spain.17 More recently, the case of
the kind of unity that Hispanic philosophy has. It is not a unity of common Onega y Gasset stands out, for his influence in Latin America was perhaps
elements. Francisco Suarez (1548-1617) may not have anything in common greater than in Spain.18 These are just a few examples of the many that re-
with Francisco Romero (1891-1962), but both Suarez and Romero are tied veal the historical unity of Hispanic philosophy. To parcel out Hispanic phi-
by a series of events that places them together and separates them from losophy into various compartments according to political, territorial, racial,
Descartes, Hume, and Kant. It is not necessary, then, to find common char- i H linguistic groups is to miss many of the historical ties that bind the diverse
acteristics of all Hispanic philosophers for them to be justifiably categorized elements that make up the philosophy of Spain, Catalonia, Portugal, and
as Hispanic. What unites them is the same sort of thing that unites a family, Latin America.
as Wittgenstein would say.'6 There may not be common features among all There are still two other objections that may be raised against the use of
of them, but they belong together because somehow they are all historically I he term 'Hispanic' to characterize the philosophy of the countries of the Iber-
related, as a father is to a son, an aunt to a niece, and grandparents to grand- lan peninsula and Latin America. One may wish to object, for example, that
children. The Wittgenstenian metaphor of the family is particularly appropri- II ie I erm 'Hispanic' is not only Eurocentric but in fact indicates the relation of
ate in this case, for a history of philosophy is always the history of the philo- doniinator-dominated which for several centuries characterized the relations
sophical thought of a community. Beginning in the sixteenth century, the between the countries in the peninsula and their colonies in America. Would
Hispanic community includes not only the inhabitants of the Iberian penin- liol the use of this term, then, tend to perpetuate a spirit of domination that
sula but also those of Latin America. would stand in the way of the intellectual liberation of Latin America?
Still, one may question the need or benefit of using the category of His-
panic philosophy to study the philosophers from the Iberian peninsula and 17. Concerning Suarez, see Raoul Scorraille, Francois Suarez de la Compagnie de Jesus,
.'. vols. (Paris: P. Lethielleux, 1912). Concerning Rubio, see the appropriate sections;
Latin America. If there are no characteristics common to all Hispanic (iflllegOS Roeafull, Pensamiento mexkano, pp. 262-78; and Walter Redmond and Mauri-
philosophers, what can an account of Hispanic philosophy add to accounts of ilu lieiicliol, La Idgica mexicana en el siglo de oro (Mexico: Universidad Nacional
Aul<iiioiii.i de Mexico, 1985).
18, Ally good hislory of Latin American philosophy will reier to this influence, but
16. Ludwig J. J. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (New York: Macmillan, I here ore also mote specialized studies. See, for example, Abellan, Filosofia espanola, pp.
1953), sees. 66-67. HM ').»; ,nul .lose CiiKis, Sobiv Ortega y Gasset (Mexico: Imprenta Universilaria, 1952).
xviii History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Foreword xix

Note that this objection does not challenge the accuracy or usefulness of In response I must first agree that at least since around 1750, Latin Amer-
this term for describing the actual historical reality of Latin America. The ob- ica has been heavily influenced by the thought of philosophers from France,
jection challenges its use because it regards the term as dangerous insofar as England, and Germany. But this does not militate against the notion of a His-
it can be used to perpetuate a situation that is morally wrong and thus intol- panic philosophy for two reasons. First, because the term 'Hispanic philoso-
erable. Could the use of the expression 'Hispanic philosophy' promote the phy' used here is not meant to convey a sense of philosophical dependence
dominance of Iberian philosophy, thus leading to further intellectual en- of Latin America on the peninsula. My point in using the term does not con-
slavement in Latin America? cern philosophical dependence but historical relations in general. Second, it
My response is twofold. First I would like to respond as a historian. Even if is not only in Latin America that the influence of France, England, and Ger-
it were the case that in fact the term 'Hispanic' carried with it the kind of bag- many has been felt but also in the Iberian peninsula itself.20 In this sense,
gage that could stand in the way of the intellectual liberation of Latin Amer- I here is much that looks the same in Latin America and in the Iberian penin-
ica, still the use of the term would be justified as long as it were applied to a sula. Finally, much of the influence of the thought of French, English, and
historical period where it served to characterize accurately the historical situ- German authors, whether we Latin Americans like it or not, did come
ation. The historian is not concerned with what should have been but with llirough Iberia. The case of Ortega's introducing German thought in Ar-
what actually was the case. My claim is precisely that the history of Iberian gentina and elsewhere and the influence of the transterrados in Mexico and
and Latin American philosophy up to the present, and particularly in the pe- oilier countries should suffice as illustrations.
riod that concerns Beuchot's book, supports the use of such a term, bringing In short, the category of Hispanic philosophy is a useful one for the de-
to the fore historical connections that otherwise would remain hidden. scription and understanding of the history of the philosophical thought of
Second, although the term may at some point have been used in a way Latin America and the countries of the Iberian peninsula. Whether it will
which gave support to the objection, I do not believe that this is any longer continue to be so is, of course, a matter to be determined by the future. For
the case. As it is generally used today, I believe the term simply refers to any- I lie present it serves well the purpose of those who wish to understand the
thing that has to do with Spain, the Spanish language, Latin America, or the ihonght of the world created by the European encounter with the Americas.
Iberian peninsula.19 Thus, I do not think its use can result in the perpetuation II is important to note that it is only after 1550 that it makes sense to
of a relation of dominator-dominated in a way that would promote the con- speak of Hispanic philosophy. It does so for two reasons. First, this is the first
tinuance of a subservient role for Latin America. lime that a new intellectual unity that can be distinguished from European
The second objection is that the use of this term is misleading because it philosophy is formed by the Iberian peninsula and the Latin American
suggests that Latin American philosophy depended throughout its history on colonies. There is for the first time in history a political unity of the kingdoms
the thought of the Iberian peninsula; whereas, in fact this is not so. Indeed, ol I lie Iberian peninsula and thus of the colonies of those kingdoms. There is
so the argument goes, after the colonial period, Latin America turned toward also religious unity after the expulsion of the Muslims and the Jews. In addi-
France, England, and Germany for philosophical inspiration, ignoring what llon I here is a strong sense of mission which permeates the activities and
went on in the peninsula. ihlnking at the time. This is the period at which the international medieval
Intellectual union, which had characterized Europe for over a thousand
19. In Latin America and Spain, the term is frequently used to refer to things Span- yens, breaks up under the stresses of humanism, the Reformation, and the
ish, thus excluding the Portuguese or Brazilian; see n. 6 above. There are some sub-
groups of the Hispanic community in this country, moreover, who object to the use of political pressures exerted by modern European states. Moreover, the Iberian
the term to refer to themselves. Whether they are justified or not is irrelevant for my world, in spile ol its strong political and ideological interests in Europe, grad-
historiographical thesis. Nonetheless, it should be noted that most of the arguments ad-
duced in this direction are based on limited knowledge of the history of the Iberian ually directs its attention toward the colonies of the New World, the extraor-
peninsula or of Latin America. See "Chicanos, not Hispanics," Third World Forum (14 dinary opportunities they make available, and the enormous demands those
March 1990); Earl Shorris, "Latino Si. Hispanic, No," The New York Times (28 October
1992); Earl Shorris, Latinos: A Biography of the People (New York: W. W. Norton, 1992), colonies exert on ihe peninsula. Iberia, then, not only becomes unified in
pp. xv-xvii; and David Gonzalez, "What's the Problem with 'Hispanic,'" The New York
Times (IS November 1992). M. Sec Alii'll.iii's llistoriii eiitkii, where such iiillucmvs are recorded.
xx History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Foreword xxi

various ways but at the same time becomes increasingly separated from the Iberian and Latin American philosophers had first-hand experience in most
rest of Europe and closer to the New World. This is reflected in the intellec- cases. This lends their philosophy an autocthonous character that is missing
tual life of both the peninsula and the colonized territories and thus justifies in most subsequent Iberian and Latin American thought. Indeed, many Iber-
for the first time the category 'Hispanic'. ian and Latin American philosophers have complained repeatedly about the
Previous to 1550 it makes no sense to employ this category in historical derivative nature of more recent Iberian and Latin American philosophical
accounts. The Roman philosophers of Iberian origin, such as Seneca, be- l bought. They charge, often with reason, that philosophical thought in these
longed culturally and intellectually to a unit that was centered elsewhere areas has resulted from uncritical borrowing from non-Hispanic—European,
and extended well beyond Iberia. Likewise, Islamic philosophers of Iberian and Anglo-American sources—thus lacking originality and authenticity.22
origin, such as Averroes, belonged to a world that gravitated toward a differ- The reasons for this lack of originality and authenticity are to be found pre-
ent axis. Something similar can be said of Maimonides and other Jewish cisely in the fact that Iberian and Latin American philosophers have forgot-
philosopher-theologians of the medieval period, for their history grouped icn their roots and that philosophy must begin in human experience. It does
them in ways which had little to do with the Iberian peninsula. In the same not pay to talk about what others say if we have no first-hand experience of
manner, medieval Scholastics from the peninsula were part of the greater what gave rise to what they say. This is, of course, what makes the sixteenth
unit represented by European Scholasticism. They were at home in that phi- and early seventeenth centuries different. For the thinkers of that period
losophy and their historical and intellectual relations were not so much to were not only well-grounded historically in their intellectual traditions but
each other as to the common heritage of the age. Indeed, the agenda that concerned themselves with what they knew best. That is why they can be
moves them is centered primarily elsewhere, in Paris, Oxford, Cambridge, accurately regarded as Hispanic philosophers and why they were able to
and Rome. All this changes in the sixteenth century. Although the Iberian excel to the degree they did.
and Latin American philosophers of the time continue to address issues of The development of the kind of intellectual unity in the sixteenth century
general concern to Europeans and to be influenced by sources which origi- lhal I have used to justify the category of Hispanic philosophy can be under-
nate outside the peninsula and Latin America, there is a strong surge of in- stood if one considers the four challenges faced by the period in question: the
terest in problems and issues that arise from the historically unique situation encounter with the New World, the rise of Renaissance humanism, the
posed by the discovery, colonization, and evangelization of the New World. spread of the Reformation, and the growth of skepticism. The encounter
Moreover, there is also, in part as a result of common interests but also hav- willi the New World had a profound and lasting impact on the thinking of
ing to do with other factors, a tightening of the relations among philosophers I luropeans. It posed for Iberians in particular a set of problems that were new
of these various lands who exchange ideas and dispute among themselves in ami ihat required immediate solution. The Iberians were confronted with
ways that were not enacted before. Indeed, recent studies show a strong hillierto unknown peoples with different cultures and religious beliefs who
predilection in some of the Hispanic authors of this period for their Hispanic nonetheless possessed enormous riches and who quickly became subject to
contemporaries.21 II i n n . What were the rights of these people? Should Christianity be imposed
This leads me to the second reason why this is the first historical period mi ihern? Should they be treated as slaves? W h o was the rightful owner of
for which the term 'Hispanic philosophy' is justified. The philosophy pro- I lie riches which hitherto had belonged to t h e m ? What should the con-
duced in the Iberian countries and their colonies after 1550 and before the querors make of the natives' laws and traditions? Questions such as these
colonies' independence springs forth to a great extent as a response of a well- were raised and had to be answered concerning most aspects of the lives of
established Iberian Scholastic tradition to the issues that confront Iberian the conquered peoples, from general aspects of the relations a m o n g peoples
and Latin American intellectuals at the time and that result from the discov-
ery and colonization of the New World. It is a philosophy, then, grounded in 22, The most eloquent articulation of this criticism is provided by Augusto Salazar
linndy In his /lixisle una jilosoffa de nuestra America? (Mexico: Siglo XXI, 1968); and his
an Iberian tradition and in the consideration of issues and problems of which '•i-nliiliiy problema del peiisiiinienlo hispano-amerkano, trans. Arthur Berdtson (Lawrence:
University of Kansas Center for Latin American Studies, Occasional papers no. 16,
Itf6v),
21. See, for example, Espfndola, En tomo a lafilosofta en Chile, pp. 36-37.
xxii H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n C o l o n i a l M e x i c o Foreword xxiii

considered as nations, to particular aspects of daily living. Issues ranged from The discovery of n e w literary, philosophical, and artistic works from the an-
international mercantile laws to t h e validity of pre-Columbian marriages. cient world had given rise n o t only to a r e n e w e d interest in pagan ideas b u t
Obviously, the discovery of America represented an enormous challenge lo a change of attitude in the intellectual community that was taken by
to intellectuals in the Iberian peninsula, forcing t h e m to raise and deal with many to pose a threat to the integrity of Christianity. Humanism was consid-
issues that they had not confronted before. This oriented their thinking to- ered a threat, then, because it looked to pagan antiquity as an ideal era
ward n e w issues, away from traditionally traveled European areas and into whose values had to be emulated. The Christian Middle Ages, and in particu-
n e w territories. The impact of the discovery on philosophy was an awaken- lar Scholasticism, also had looked to antiquity for enlightenment, but the at-
ing to the need to deal with legal and ethical issues that were n e w to the liiude of the humanists was broader and less cautious. Scholastics borrowed
times and that tended both to form a core of concerns that tied Iberian and from the past selectively, filtering w h a t they borrowed throug h the sieve of
Latin American thinkers together and at the same time to distance t h e m Christian doctrine and accepting only w h a t they thought could be h a r m o -
from their European counterparts w h o had other concerns and agendas. 23 nized with that doctrine. 26 In spite of the borrowing en masse that took place
The other three challenges faced by Iberian and Latin American philoso- In Ihe thirteenth century, a suspicious attitude concerning pagan antiquity
phers and theologians at this time had a similar effect of strengthening the was never absent, as the repeated condemnations of heretical and pagan
ties amon g t h e m and distancing t h e m from the rest of Europe, supporting doctrines illustrate. 27 The humanists, by contrast, were attracted to the an-
their historical interrelations and thus the development of a Hispanic philo- cients and emulated less discriminately the forms and values of the period as
sophical universe. But this effect was not accomplished in the same way as it displayed in art and literature. Their concern with beauty, the h u m a n body,
was accomplished by the encounter with the New World. The challenges of (indent rites, literary style, and pagan religious ideas was a source of concern
humanism, the Reformation, and skepticism did not open the exploration of in ecclesiastical authorities. Although some humanists were devoted Chris-
n e w themes that would draw Iberian and Latin American philosophers I l.iiis and used their textual and linguistic skills for the service of t h e Faith,
closer. W h a t these challenges did was to alert t h e m to the need to come to- many were interested in the recovery of classical knowledge and art, not for
gether in order to collect their forces and repel those w h o m most of t h e m i he sake of enriching the Christian faith but for its o w n sake. This was cer-
perceived as enemies. The need to defend w h a t they considered to be the true tainly different from the attitude of medieval Scholastics and, moreover, ap-
Faith, to purge it from contamination by u n o r t h o d ox or dangerous doctrines, I MM red potentially dangerous to those in the Iberian peninsula and its
and to vanquish those w h o threatened it had the effect of drawing these i1 ilonles w h o wished to preserve the medieval worldview. 28
philosophers together in a way that had not happened prior to this time. 24 Another challenge, the Reformation, h a d an effect o n Iberian and Latin
The impact of h u m a n i s m o n the Iberian peninsula and its colonies was American philosophers and theologians similar to that of h u m a n i s m. Indeed,
felt quite early and, although some Iberian a n d Latin American intellectuals ii posed an even greater threat t h a n h u m a n i s m to the Church, for it was a
were receptive to humanism, the m o v e m e n t was generally perceived by ec- challenge within the Church's o w n ranks and involved theology, the
clesiastical and governmental authorities as a threat to the orthodox Faith. 25 i Ii in ill's conceptual foundation. Moreover, this rebellion against institu-
tionalized Christianity gained considerable political support in some parts
23. There is much literature on this topic. Among the most recent publications that
give an idea of the issues in question is Luciano Perefia, The Rights and Obligations of In- ill Europe. There had b e e n heretical challenges to t h e Church from within
dians and Spaniards in the New World (Salamanca: Universidad Pontificia de Salamanca 11N tanks during the Middle Ages. Large revolts had occurred in southern
and Catholic University of America Press, 1992). The issues in question were not only
fiance, as happened with the Albingensians, for example. There had also
moral and legal but extended to matters of commerce and economics. See, for exam-
ple, M. Grice-Hutchinson, The School of Salamanca. Readings in Spanish Monetary Theory,
1544-1605 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1952); and R. Sierra Bravo, El pensamiento socialy '(.. Bonaventure, Collaliones in Hexaemeron 19, in Opera omnia, vol. 5 (Ad Claras
economico de la escoldstica desde sus origenes al comienzo del catolicismo social, 2 vols. (Madrid: Aqu.is: Collegium S. Bonavenlurae, 1882-1902), p. 422.
Consejo Superior de Investigaciones Cientificas, 1975). 17. Btlenne Gilson, History of Christian Philosophy in the Middle Ages (New York: Ran-
24. Cf. Luis Gil Fernandez, Estudios de humanismo y tradition cldsica, (Madrid: Editor- ll House, 1954).
ial Complutense, 1984), pp. 15-94. .'H. The conduct nl Renaissance popes like Leo X did not help to assuage the lears of
25. J. Fuster, Reheldesy heterodoxos (Barcelona; Edlcions Ariel, 1972), p. 72. '.mil people, for a readable account of l.eo X ami oilier Renaissance popes, sec E. R.
iI beillii. The Had Popes (New York: Dorset Press, 1969).
xxiv History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Foreword xxv

been serious threats to Christianity from without, primarily from Islam. But was charged with the task of enforcing the new standards. Second, the
the Reformation was a different sort of movement for various reasons, three movement of renewal affected also the rank and file members of the Church.
of which stand out: First, it was a challenge based on criticisms concerning Among grassroots efforts the most successful was the foundation of the Soci-
the corruption prevalent at the Papal court. Second, it had strong political ety of Jesus by Ignatius of Loyola (1491-1556). This religious order became
overtones that lent it power in a way that some of the earlier reform move- the symbol of reformed Roman Catholicism and one of the most effective in-
ments had lacked. Third, it was a theological challenge arising from within struments of the Counter-Reformation.
the Church itself. These factors combined to make the Reformation a most In the Iberian peninsula and the Iberian colonies, the reaction to the use
powerful threat and one that endangered the stability and future of the of humanistic, Reformation, and skeptical ideas by the ecclesiastical estab-
Church. lishment was also quick. Humanists, reformers, and skeptics were portrayed
The final challenge which helped to draw Iberians and Latin Americans as mixtures of grammarians and heretics whose influence had to be eradi-
together is less defined than the others but not for that reason less effective. cated.31 This was achieved in various ways, including the exercise of strict
This was the rise of skepticism. Skepticism had not been strong in the Middle controls on the publication and distribution of books and the general dis-
Ages. It was known primarily through Augustine, who had argued against it couraging of book learning.32
in Contra academicos in particular. In fact, skepticism had a bad name among The intellectual climate at the time in which the Iberian thought of the
Scholastics, who used it to accuse and condemn their opponents.29 Yet, there sixteenth and seventeenth centuries flourished, therefore, was a defensive
were many Scholastics who adopted a skeptical or somewhat skeptical one. The Church was under siege and felt it had to fight its assailants. The re-
stance in order to defend those tenets of the faith that they thought could sult among Roman Catholic intellectuals was a great effort to rethink and de-
not be defended if reason were held to be the ultimate arbiter of belief. Thus, lend traditional Christian theology. Thus we find an abundance of literature
there was a background to the skepticism that developed in the sixteenth dealing with doctrinal controversies cast both in apologetic and theological
century with authors like Montaigne, and that was so decisively to affect the modes. Both modes are amply documented in the history of the Church
course of early modern philosophy. The skepticism of Montaigne, however, prior to this time, but in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries there was a
went far beyond that adopted by some Scholastics and did not aim to support it'itewed interest in them. Moreover, the polemical and defensive tone of
the Faith. Montaigne's question, Que sais-je?, combined with a tolerance of •.(ime of these writings contrasts with the tone of many earlier Scholastics.
what ecclesiastical authorities considered an easy morality, was regarded as I'IH- Iberian and Latin American thought of the period mirrors these charac-
an unwelcomed development by those who considered themselves champi- Ici islics. The effect of humanism, the Reformation, and skepticism in the six-
ons of the Christian faith.30 teenth and seventeenth centuries, then, was to make Iberian and Latin
The response of the Church to humanism, the Reformation, and skepti- American philosophers and theologians close ranks so that they might over-
cism was swift. First, there was a movement toward reform led by members i unit' these challenges to the established Church.
of the Church hierarchy which aimed to stamp out corruption and also to As noted, the attitude developed by the Roman Church in response to the
regularize Christian doctrine, rites, and laws. The most effective instruments ( hallenges of humanism, the Reformation, and skepticism was not peculiar to
used to achieve these aims were the Council of Trent (1545-1563) and the In- 11 if Iberian countries and their colonies, but the leadership of the Church's re-
quisition. The Council took care of doctrinal matters, whereas the Inquisition sponse fell largely to the Iberians—to the government of the peninsula where
.n ins were required, and to its philosophers and theologians where intellec-
29. See John Duns Scotus's charge of skepticism against Henry of Ghent. Opus ox- 11 i.il weapons were in order. Latin Americans, of course, did not participate as
oniense I, dist. 3, q. 4, a. 1. In Duns Scotus, Philosophical Writings, ed. Allan Wolter (Lon-
don: Nelson, 1963), pp. 103-6. For discussions of skeptidsm in the Middle Ages, see K.
Michalski, La philosophic au XlVe siecle. Six etudes (Frankfurt: Minerva, 1969); and 11. See mi. 24 and 25 above.
Mauricio Beuchot, "Escepticismo en la edad media: El caso de Nicolas de Autrecourt," 12. Sec M. de la I'inta I.lorcnte, l.a Inquisicidn espanolay los problemas de la culturay de
Revista Latinoamericana deFilosofia 15, 3 (1989): 307-19. III Intolenmcia (Madrid: lidicioncs Cultura llispanica, 1953-1958); M. Defourneaux, In-
30. For a treatment of the growth of the skeptical movement in the sixteenth cen- •liuuciou y cciisiini dr libros en la lispatla del sigh XVIII (Madrid: Taurus, 1973); and Vi-
tury and the beginning of the reaction to it, see Richard I'opkin, The History of Scepticism 11'iilr <i. Oucs.ida, I.il vida intelecliuil en la America espaiiola durante los sifllos XVI, XVII, y
from Erasmus to Descartes (Assen: Van Gorcum, 1964). \ VIII (Itiiciins Aires: Aruoldo Morn y llcrniano, 1910), pp. 3-33.
xxvi H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n C o l o n i a l M e x i c o Foreword xxvii

actively in this affair, but their activities were regulated to a great extent by quickly after the rise of the Jesuits and the subsequent growth of rivalry be-
w h a t was taking place in the peninsula, making t h e m dependent and sub- i ween t h e m and the Dominicans.
sidiary to it. Nowhere is this more evident, for example, t h a n in the control- The respect for well-established conceptual traditions, together with the
ling of reading materials allowed into the colonies. Although there have large literature inherited from t h e thirteent h and fourteenth centuries,
been some exaggerated claims concerning the control exercised by peninsu- helped develop, moreover, an encyclopedic attitude in which recovery and
lar authorities over the circulation of books in the New World, it is evident exposition became central to the Scholastic enterprise. Not that this attitude
that efforts were m a d e in this direction and thus that to a certain extent t h e had been lacking in earlier stages of Scholasticism. From t h e very begin-
peninsula established the intellectual parameters within which intellectuals ning, the Middle Ages displayed a concern with the recovery and preserva-
from the New World were supposed to w o r k . " This, naturally, tended to sep- IIIHI of the past. Thus w e find t h r o u g h o u t t h e period m a n y encyclopedias
arate the New World from intellectual developments occurring beyond the ol knowledge. The earliest successful attempts in this direction were De in-
Pyrenees and to tie it closely to peninsular concerns and news. stltutionedivinarum litterarum of Cassiodorus (4777-570?) and Etymologiae of
Apart from the four challenges discussed, there are two other factors that Isidore of Seville (d. 636). Both of these owed debts to earlier classical
need to be mentione d because they also helped shape the course of Iberian • rces—as is t h e case of Isidore with Suetonius Pratum, for example—and
and Latin American thought and thus the development of Hispanic philoso- both works w e r e greatly successful, t h e first owing to its elegant a n d easy
phy. These t wo factors are the relatively late emergence of Iberian Scholasti- style, and the second because of t h e mass of material it contained. 3 5 This
cism and the close relations between Church and State that developed in the kind of effort w e n t on, as is clear from the Speculum majus of Vincent of Beau-
Iberian peninsula. Vills (1190/12007-1264?), produced in the thirteent h century, and the
The relatively late emergence of Iberian Scholasticism m e a n t that this iicslia, u n d e r t a k e n by Francesc Eiximenis (1340-1409) at the end of the
m o v e m e n t was influenced by well-established traditions associated with var- Fourteenth century.
ious religious orders. From the thirteenth century onwards, religious orders, In the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, the encyclopedic emphasis on
particularly the powerful Franciscans and Dominicans, had appropriated cer- Hfltllering all available information surrounding a topic became more pro-
tain ideas and authors, a n d they promoted t h e m with extraordinary zeal. nounced. So m u c h h a d been produced, a n d it was of such high quality, that
The Franciscans devoted themselves to the study and dissemination of the II was natural for late Scholastics to feel they had to preserve it and at least
thought of Augustine (345-430) and Duns Scotus, whereas t h e Dominicans I.ike il into account in their o w n thinking. For this reason we find during the
worked u n d e r the spiritual tutelage of Thomas Aquinas and, t h r o u gh him, pci iod much that is primarily expository and m a n y works whose character is
Aristotle. This commitment to a certain set of ideas and to certain authors be- lufoi inative. This attitude is displayed even in the work of the most original
came accentuated in some writers as time w e n t on, lending the later Middle Iberian Scholastics, such as Francisco Suarez. In m a n y ways, and in spite of
Ages an overall ideological tone. There was, however, a reprieve o n this feel- llli'lr originality in m a n y areas, Suarez's Disputationes metaphysicae (1597)
ing of partisanship in the early sixteenth century, perhaps as a result of the i nnslitute an encyclopedia of metaphysics in which every topic, every au-
influence of h u m a n i s m and the overall rebellion against the excessive tech- 11101 of importance, and every relevant argument is carefully presented, ex-
nicism that characterized the practice of philosophy in most European uni- amined, and evaluated. 36 Unfortunately, this emphasis on the past some-
34
versities, and particularly in Paris, at the time. But this reprieve ended
Mllfloz Delgado, "Logica hispano-portuguesa hasta 1600 (notas bibliografico-doctri-
rl«ik".|," Kcpertorio de historia de las ciencias eclesidsticas en Espana 4 (1972): 9-122; and E. J.
33. See n. 32 above.
V.I i wnlli. Language and Logic in the Post-Medieval Period (Dordrecht-Boston: Reidel, 1974).
34. For the technical character of the philosophy of this period, see Carlos Norefia,
I Inn' were some good reasons for the criticism of humanists like Luis Vives and others.
Studies in Spanish Renaissance Thought (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1975); R. Garcia Villoslada,
La Universidad de Paris durante los estudios de Francisco de Vitoria, 0. P. (1507-1522) (Rome: II, Sec Peter L. Schmidt's "Suetons 'Pratum' seit Wessner (1917)," in The Classical
Universitas Gregoriana, 1938); V. Munoz Delgado, La logica nominalista en la universidad 11, i, lilion and llic Americas, ed. W. Haase, el al. See also Gilson, History of Christian Philoso-
de Salamanca (1510-1530); V. Munoz Delgado, "La logica en Salamanca durante la I'hvm the Middle Ages, p. 107,
primera mitad del siglo XVI," Salmantkensis 14 (1967): 171-207; V. Munoz Delgado, "La 16, oilier examples are the Ciirsus Conlmbrkensis and Juan de Santo Tomas's Cursus
Obra logica de los espafloles en Paris (1 500-1525)," BstttdtOS 26 (1970): 209-80; and V. l>hlh>wphtcui. Sec .iiilm Trentman, "Scholasticism In the Seventeenth Century," in The
• iimbrldgt History ofLater Medieval Philosophy, ed. N. Km/man, ci ,ii„ pp. 8?5-?7.
xxviii History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Foreword xxix

times obscures the brilliant contributions of the period and has mistakenly laced (the discovery, humanism, the Reformation, and skepticism), the phi-
led some historians to characterize it as sterile. losophy of this period in Iberia and its colonies developed close ties, which
The second factor that played a major role in shaping the Hispanic separated it from the rest of Europe and made it chart a course on its own,
thought of the period was the close relationship that developed between the but it also developed some characteristic features that tended to distinguish it
Roman Church and the Iberian states, particularly the Spanish state. In the from prior and subsequent European thought. It was, for example, more en-
fifteenth century the Roman Church became the state church in Spain, and cyclopedic, expository, and eclectic; it had a defensive, apologetic, and theo-
the pope granted the Spanish kings the right to appoint the highest members logical emphasis; it had the state and its power behind it and thus was partly
of the hierarchy in the country. This extraordinary development made Spain influenced by political considerations that affected the state; and it developed
a de facto theocracy in which the interests of the state and the interests of the .1 set of new issues dealing with international law and human rights.
Church were identified. It is easy to understand the reasons for this situa- For our purposes, the most significant aspect of all this is the separation of
tion. First, Spain had become the main defender of the Faith against the I lispanic philosophy from the mainstream of European thought: for in spite
threat of Islam. Having successfully expelled the Moors from Iberian soil of considerable popularity at the time, most of the Hispanic philosophers of
after a seven-hundred year struggle, Spain was in a favorable position to I his period have been largely forgotten. Suarez, Vitoria, Rubio, and some of
continue the defense of Christianity throughout the Mediterranean. More- the authors discussed in this book were common names in the philosophical
over, Spain was poised to become, and in fact did become, the first and most controversies of the time. Suarez's Disputationes metaphysicae, for example, was
powerful European modern nation. Its kings, who also became emperors of printed in more than seventeen editions outside the Iberian peninsula be-
the Holy Roman Empire for a time, controlled not only the Iberian peninsula tween 1597 and 1636, whereas Descartes's Meditations were edited only nine
but territories in Italy, France, the Netherlands, and Germany as well, and limes between 1641 and 1700.37 Yet Descartes is considered a major figure in
thus exercised extraordinary power. the history of philosophy, whereas Suarez is hardly known. Indeed, if we
Second, the Spanish struggle against Islam had been both national and were to ask the more than eleven thousand philosophers who teach in the
religious; the Spanish kings had fought in the name of the Cross both for ter- United States today to tell us a few facts about Suarez, I am sure only a couple
ritory and for the spread of Christianity. Therefore, it made sense to extend hundred, if that many, would be able to reply. Yet Suarez is without a doubt
this political, military, and religious struggle against the reformers. the most important and well-known Hispanic philosopher of the period. Only
Third, Spain had recently discovered America, and this provided an un- • i dozen American philosophers have ever heard of Briceno or Rubio.
usual opportunity for both colonization and missionary work. Since the We may ask, then, a question: Why have these philosophers been forgot-
Church had no means to organize the indoctrination of the newly discovered ten? The answer is to be found in the very points I have been making con-
lands, it was natural that the Spanish crown be entrusted with the task, en- cerning the development of Hispanic philosophy. For the reasons given, the
forcing once more the bonds that united Church and state in the peninsula. philosophy of the Iberian peninsula and its Latin American colonies became
Fourth, the preoccupation with the Reconquista had, to some extent, kept Increasingly isolated from European philosophy, thus losing the historical
Spain away from the intellectual developments associated with the early Re- lies il had had with it. Hispanic philosophy turned in upon itself, concerned
naissance, making it an ideal place of operations for the defense against hu- .ihoul the peculiar and pressing problems faced by Hispanic society, and, in
manists, reformers, and skeptics. A militant faith was needed to defeat the fcar of European developments that threatened its political and religious sta-
challenges faced by the Church, and Spain certainly had such a faith. Spain bility, it looked for support in the past. Thus, it not only became isolated from
had the faith, the power, and the means to conduct the struggle, and so it l he mainstream philosophical developments in the West but consciously re-
was to Spain that the task fell. Consequently, philosophical thought in the let led these developments in favor of its medieval foundations. The result
Iberian peninsula became subject to political influence and functioned in w.is to be expected. European philosophy continued on its own way and
many instances as a tool of the Spanish government.
*7. Sco ,1. Irlanc, "I.a proycaion sobrc Europa de una gran metali'sica, o Suarez en
As a result of the two factors identified (lale emergence of Scholasticism la lllnsoiiii en Ins (lias del B.irmco," Kuzdny I'e, niiincro cxtraordinario (1948): 236.
and close relations between Church and slate), and the four challenges it
xxx History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o

came to regard the philosophy practiced in the Iberian peninsula and its
colonies as marginal and regressive. For a while, the political and military
power of Spain insured that Iberian voices were taken seriously outside the
peninsula, but the decline in political and military power in the seventeenth
century contributed to the view of Iberian philosophy as stagnant and retro-
grade. This view slowly extended to all Hispanic philosophy and thought,
leading to the general perception that there is little of importance to be XheHistory of Philosophy
found in it.38 Thus were forgotten the original and extraordinary contribu-
tions to philosophy of the Hispanic authors of the sixteenth and seventeenth
centuries.
inColonialMexico
As to this period's enduring philosophical importance, I believe that time
will vindicate it. In my o w n experience, I have dealt with n o philosophical
issue for which I have not found m u c h help in the writings of these philoso-
phers. In areas of contemporary interest, such as semiotics, the philosophy of
language, ontology, and logic, the work of Hispanic philosophers beginning
in 1550 holds vast reservoirs of interesting, original, and valuable materials.
Most of these materials, however, are not easily accessible; they are available
only in old and difficult to find editions. And, of course, the materials are in
Latin, a language with which very few philosophers are familiar today. Thus,
the job of those w h o wish to bring to light the contributions of this period to
the history of philosophy is not easy, but I believe the enterprise should
nonetheless deliver ample rewards. Fortunately, n o w w e have a first and
firm step in this direction with the publication of Mauricio Beuchot's learned
study of the history of philosophy in colonial Mexico. Let us hope that others
follow.39

State University at Buffalo

38. Indeed, Hispanic philosophers themselves are relentless in their repetition of


this view. Cf. E. Villanueva, "Philosophical Analysis in Mexico," in Philosophical Analysis
in Latin America, ed. Jorge J. E. Gracia, et al. (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1984), p. 170, and
Salazar Bondy, "The Meaning and Problem of Hispanic American Thought," in Latin
American Philosophy in the Twentieth Century, ed. Jorge J. E. Gracia, p. 234.
39. A more extensive version of this paper was published in Review of Metaphysics 46
(1993): 475-502.1 thank the editor of the journal, Jude Dougherty, for his permission
to use parts of the article.
•§§¥• Introduction
Understanding the History of Philosophy

i n Colonial Mexico

T
o understand the history of philosophical ideas in Mexico, one
should consider the meaning of philosophical trends in Mexico. Be-
cause scholastic philosophy played a central role during colonial
nines, it will be considered in depth. The rest of this chapter presents the
\ lews lhat various historians and philosophers had of scholasticism in colo-
111.11 M e x i co and an evaluation of these views. We will thereby be engaged in
11 n- philosophy of history—the history of philosophy in colonial Mexico. Our
i|lK'Slion is: What meaning for the history of philosophy does colonial Mexi-
i ,in philosophy hold?
I ei us begin with what previous historians of the philosophy of Colonial
Mexico have said about the cultural phenomenon with which they have
dealt. I low have they evaluated the presence of scholastic philosophy and of
modern philosophy in it? We will consider diverse the opinions regarding
lliese issues.

Beginnings
II we cast to one side historians and bibliographers (such as the great
i Millars .ind Heiisi.iin) who did not consider ex professo the philosophical
2 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n C o l o n i a l M e x i c o Introduction 3

trends in New Spain, t h e n the debate of the second half of the nineteenth look at it closely, it does not destroy itself. On the contrary, it grows and per-

century between Agustin Rivera and Agustin de la Rosa can be considered as l<«.ts itself with the contingency of truth which can be found within the other

the beginning or, at least, as a n antecedent of the history—that is, historiogra- systems of thought." 5 The presence of scholastic philosophy in Mexico was,
according to Valverde, a great benefit to the country.
phy—of the philosophy of New Spain.
For Valverde, t h e colleges of the various religious orders a n d the univer-
Agustin Rivera published a work in 1885 called Lafilosofla en la Nueva Es-
slly constituted the institutional center of scholastic philosophy. Valverde
pana,1 to which h e added the significant subtitle: Disertacidn sobre el atraso de la
iMaintained that the schools provided the m e a n s through which the orders
Nueva Espana en las tiencias filosdficas. This work is a criticism of various Mexi-
rave I he Indigenous and Hispanic population a Christian world picture. 6 He
can historians: Lucas Alaman, Adolfo Llerena, Niceto de Zamacois, Ignacio
views the activities and results of the university favorably, overlooking the
Aguilar y Marocho, and others w h o expressed favorable opinions of colonial
stages of decadence the university suffered. This explains w h y Valverde does
thought. Canon Rivera viewed this as a n exaltation of Spain against Mexico
<MI| comment on the defects of scholasticism nor on the limitations it implied
and considered it his duty to counteract this 'attack' against his country. This
lot Mexico. His view can be accused of being too sympathetic.
response was answered by Canon Agustin de la Rosa in his work, La instruc-
Regarding the colleges of the religious orders, Valverde claims that almost
tion en Mexico durante su dependencia de Espana (1888). 2 In this work, de la
• vi'i y order had either its o w n school or a variation of one of the m a in philo-
Rosa disputes the view that the backward condition of science in Mexico is
sophical schools. The most important orders were the Franciscans w h o prac-
not worse t h a n the one in Spain or Europe in general. He also defends the
illi eil Scotism, the Dominicans and the Augustinians w h o practiced Thomism,
claim that m a n y colonial thinkers were not at the same level as their Euro-
Hid lhe Jesuits w h o followed the teachings of Suarez. Though each order
pean colleagues. He offers m u c h proof of this, as well as historical considera-
11 | II cscnled a distinct group of thought, there was agreement concerning the
tions regarding colonial thinkers and institutions. It was de la Rosa's purpose
luiuiiimentals of faith. Valverde locates the major differences betwee n the
not to defend Spain but rather to defend scholasticism itself, a scholasticism
MI dels in the diverse interpretations of some Aristotelian doctrines. He ex-
which h e feared was compromised in viceregal Mexico. Rivera answered
3 |ilil11is, "The talented disciples feel a great enthusiasm w h e n realizing differ-
h i m with another text, and in both texts w e find a n apologetic impetuosity
i in opinions held by wise professors about c o m m o n truths. This spirit en-
rather than a critical attitude toward the sources a n d the historical signifi-
lllllilens understanding and awakens curiosity; the students think, search,
cance of the events.
Ii .id. and consult on their o w n . It is not strange that the innate love for sci-
i nlllli Independence makes disciples daring in their ideas and not very re-
E m e t e r i o Valverde Tellez i|M'( llnl in llieir refutations; but such is the way in which intelligence is de-
(i loped, and this is following the path of philosophy." 7 Valverde is full of
Bishop Valverde Tellez, w h o devoted some space to colonial philosophy in
in.il'.r lor .ill 1 his and for the Church's efforts to promote publishing houses
two of his works, was calmer and m o re p r u d e n t t h a n either Rivera or de la
riml libraries. Perhaps this causes us to suspect him of excessive partialities
Rosa. In Apuntaciones historicas sobre lafilosofla en Mexico (1896), 4 h e demon-
In II evaluating the contributions of scholasticism to the theoretical and
strates a strong inclination for scholastic philosophy. He tells us that "[a]s a
whole and in detail, scholastic philosophy is the closest to the truth; and, if we I .i lilosoli'a cscolaslica en su conjunto y detalles, es la mas conforme a la verdad
I'M II mil.id.i, no se destruye, antes se acrece y perfecciona, con el contingente de ver-
1. Agustin Rivera, Lafilosofla en la Nueva Espana: Disertacidn sobre el atraso de la Nueva i III 111 if Ii.ill.use puede en los demas sistemas." Ibid., p. x.
Espana en lascienciasfilosdficas (Lagos: Lopez Arce, 1885). fi ll'lil . |>, 5Iff.
2. Agustin de la Rosa, La instruction en Mexico durante su dependencia de Espana I "'. ilisiipulos dolados de lalenlo y aplicacion, sientense poseidos de singular
(Guadalajara: n.p., 1888; reprint, Guadalajara: Instituto Tecnologico de Guadalajara, • iiiii'il.iniii, in,nido .idvierlcn la divergencia de opiniones entre profesores igualmente
1952). On the debate, see also J. Hernandez Luna, Dos ideas sobre lafilosofla en la Nueva | • . ,ii i 11.1 Hi- vcnl.iilcs |ior lodos reconocidas; el mismo espfritu de partido aviva el
Espana (Rivera vs. de la Rosa) (Mexico: UNAM, 1959). i un inlliiilciilii, desplcrla la ciiiiosid.id, se plensa, se indaga por propia cuenta, se lee, se
" illllrt mi es i.no que el amor inn.ilo a Li indcpciidciKia cienlflica los haga un tanto
3. See Agusli'n Rivera, Treinta sofismas y un buen argument/) del Sr. Dr. D. Agustin de la
.in ( hlir. en MIS Ideas, algo Irrcspetuosos en sus impugn.ui ones; pero asf se forman las
Rosa (Lagos: Lopez Arce, 1887). lull lliiuii I.is y nlii CS illtd.ll' pot el ciniino de l.i lilosoli'a." [bid., p. 90.
1. Valverde Telle/., Apuntaciones histdricas sobre lafilosofla cu Mexico (Mexico: Ilcrrero
linos., 1896).
4 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Introduction 5

practical training of the Mexican people, but w e can recognize some good el- only a few other sources; for example, Beristain or Antonio Caso. He quotes
ements in his point of view. admiringly from the Caso's article on Diaz de Gamarra in El Universal, from
In the Critica fllosofica, o Bibliografia de la filosofia en Mexico (1904), 8 Val- I iccember 1935. 10 In situating colonial philosophy, Vasconcelos takes into ac-
verde introduces a n u m b e r of philosophers of New Spain, compiling, for the Count the thought of those philosophers of New Spain w h o worked in the
first time, relevant bibliographical, biographical, and systematic informa- university and in the colleges of the orders. He indicates the most prominent
tion. The preference for scholasticism which was noted earlier is evident in ones and their contributions to concrete events. In general, his evaluation of
the minimal attention Valverde pays to the modernization of philosophy. ilie effects of scholasticism in Mexico is positive, albeit lacking in some nec-
For example, h e gives little attention to it w h e n discussing Gamarra, but he essary details.
recognizes that one has to be open to various n e w and different trends and
that in this case Gamarra was the most willing to introduce m o d e r n philoso-
S.imuel Ramos
phy in Mexico.
Valverde TeTlez's work is important because he gives us much information !n Samuel Ramos's Historia de la filosofia en Mexico (1985)," we encounter
about the period, and in this he was an innovator; furthermore, it is first- v .ii ions evaluative accounts of both scholastic and m o d e rn colonial philoso-
hand information that he found in archives and old libraries and even in phy. I le is severe in his treatment of scholastic philosophy and more sympa-
books he managed to gather personally. Bibliographies, as well as reliable thetic loward m o d e rn philosophy (it is evident that he does not k n o w very
and authorized histories, are other sources he used. He is, to a certain extent, ch about the former). He takes into account the philosophical work of the
the most serious pioneer in these fields of the history of colonial philosophy. .Ixlecnth century carried out in the university as well as the work that was
Above all, he is someone w h o wanted, ex professo, to write a reflective and lipi lotted by the orders. The orders were located at the universities but also at
critical history of philosophy in Mexico. Of course, as a clergyman educated " liters separate from the universities. He considers the Dominicans and the
in scholasticism, he was prejudiced or ideologized to a certain extent. But he \ MI;I isl inians as preservers of the orthodox Thomist tradition, the most power-
is the one w h o worked hardest and most seriously to trace the sources of this lul and, by and large, the official trend; the Franciscans practiced Scotism,
history. This makes him an important and notable figure in the history of v\ lili Ii had little influence. For Ramos, the Jesuits were innovators because
Mexican philosophical historiography. Hi. v defended the reformed scholasticism of Molina and Suarez. 12 But the
ileplhof Ramos's appreciation of scholasticism is questionable. What does he
Jose Vasconcelos lersland by 'reformed' scholasticism? Scholasticism, after all, u n d e r w e n t
niiiiiy reformations. H o w ' r e f o r m e d ' w a s Suarecian scholasticism? An under -
In an appendix to Historia del pensamiento filosofico (1937), Jose Vasconcelos I.Hiding of Ibis simply as a combination of traditional scholasticism with a
discusses philosophy in Mexico and devotes some space to colonial philoso- re modern version of it is clearly false. It is misleading to characterize Suare-
phy. Influenced by his strong aesthetic perspective, Vasconcelos links philoso- ••< liolastieism as t h e result ofMolina's and Suarez's personal contributions
phy with other cultural manifestations: "In all countries, great architecture Mi ll I MI i he same sort of thing was done by philosophers from other orders,
corresponds to great philosophy; and mediocre or monstrous architecture cor- ni. I n Is well known that as the most innovative of the reformers, Suarez's con-
responds to incomplete or partial philosophy." 9 Accordingly, because there H Hi in was more substantial than this. His greatest aim was an eclectic one;
was great architecture in colonial Mexico, there must have been an acceptable In tried in synthesize Thomist doctrines with Scotist ones, and both of these
philosophy. nil nominalism. 1 5 Bui these attempts do not yet a m o u n t to 'reformed
Vasconcelos owes most of his information to Valverde Tellcz and uses
in Ibid . p 545,
8. E. Valverde Tellcz, Criticafllosofica,o Bibliografia de lafilosofiaen Mexico (Mexico: ' i '•• I Ramos, Historia de lafilosofiaen Mexico, vol. 2, Obras completas (Mexico:
II I A M l''M'.|
Ilcrrcro linos., 1904).
( I ' ll>nI p I .'-I
). "|H|n uxlo pueblo, .i gran filosofia corresponde gran arqultectura, y .i lilosoli'.is
incomplci.is, p.iriicul.ircs, corresponden arquttecturas medlocrcs a monstruosas/ Vas- i '• See i M.iiinic/ Gomez, ' i v.ilu.H urn de Francisco S I U I C Pllfisofo," Cuadtrnus
concelos, Hisioriadelpensemlentofllosdfleo, p 537, iihiiHInin lie I'llosoflti I (1980) 5 25
6 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o Introduction 7

scholasticism', as Ramos, with his privileging of the m o d e r n for the sake of the seclusive, and conservative trend; its publications and teachings bogged
modern, believes. The n e w is not always better t h a n w h a t preceded it, and so down with repetitive and official dogmatism. 16 The Mexican intelligentsia
Ramos's depiction of 'reformed scholasticism' is not accurate. In it w e find him was represented by poor criollos, mestizos, and some Indians. They were con-
granting authority to t h e m o d e r n without proper justification. cerned with culture, governmental or ecclesiastic bureaucracies, and teach-
Ramos's remarks on certain historical circumstances are very clear. It is ing. Instead of devoting themselves to science, the scholastics entertained
not to be denied that scholastic philosophy was used by some people as an lliemselves in sterile disputes, formalism, and empty syllogisms, paying n o
ideological tool to subdue and stabilize oppression, but not all authors did attention at all to reality. 17 According to Ramos, the Jesuits were the only ex-
that, and m a n y of t h e m even criticized such misapplications. We cannot sep- ception, but their efforts were in vain. The members of the Society of Jesus
arate philosophy from its concrete historical situation, but w e must think were the most open to m o d e r n thought. Their material power allowed t h e m
carefully about w h a t is involved in understanding philosophy historically. lo have freedom of thought and even to introduce those political ideas that
Certainly, philosophy is not politically neutral, and this insight must be ac- prepared the ground for independence. Ramos's claim that the Jesuits were
knowledged in our study of colonial philosophy. "separated from orthodoxy w h e n they taught Suarez" is exaggerated, but it
Ramos denounces the limited freedom of the scholastics, a limitation due is h u e that the Jesuits were innovative. In Ramos's assessment of the Order,
to the strict vigilance that the Inquisition exerted on orthodoxy. As a result, Sigiienza y Gongora stands out because he maintained close ties to the Je-
Ramos claims, colonial philosophers of New Spain did not discuss concrete suits; h e h a d b e e n in t h e Order and asked to die within it.
issues but took refuge in empty theories and speculations. Ramos questions Ramos's judgments against other scholastics could appear to be out of
w h y Friar Alonso de la Veracruz's lucid mind was not more critical of this sit- place if they are not understood within a concrete historical context. Admit-
uation. 14 In fact, however, in 1561 Friar Alonso w e n t to defend the Indians icdly, there were philosophers w h o devoted themselves solely to strengthen-
before Philip II; unfortunately, because the laws of the Indies forbade Span- ing their logical and semantic instruments in order to deal with abstract and
ish or Americans living in America to write about the colony, his defense re- even pseudo-problems instead of considering with more pressing concrete
mained unpublished. We should not, on the other hand, judge Ramos's cri- problems. This happens in all periods, even in our own. And we could say it
tique of Friar Alonso too hastily, for its weaknesses may be justified. It is happens not only within scholasticism but in all philosophical trends. Never-
understandable that Ramos had not read Friar Alonso's philosophical-legal ilieless, m a n y seventeenth-century philosophers of New Spain did devote
teaching 15 because only recently did the researcher P. Burrus, w h o edited i heir studies and their talents to concrete problems. And this is true not only
those works, bring Friar Alonso's defense to light. In this defense, Friar • •I modern ones but of scholastics as well. We find in Friar J u a n de Zapata y
Alonso deals with m a n y concrete issues related to the newly formed society. Sandoval a fine example of this; h e wrote an excellent treatise on distribu-
Before these recently edited works were published, only the m o re theoreti- nve justice. 18 However, w h e n scholastic thinkers saw that a specific doctrine
cal works of Friar Alonso were widely available, and it is certain that Ramos • ould be applied to solve problems, they applied the doctrine and n o longer
only k n e w the abstract Friar Alonso of the Recognitio Summularum, Diakctica Nought to change or a m e n d the doctrine other t h a n in superficial ways. This
Resolutio, and Physica Speculatio, but not that of the Speculum Coniungiorum, De i i e,iled a conservative, even stagnant, tendency, which obviously did not en-
Dominio Infidelium, or Dubia, works in which Friar Alonso deals with more hance innovation. Change for the sake of change was not valued during this
concrete matters. In addition, recent developments have shed n e w light on period of colonial thought.
the works of other thinkers of this period; the work of Tomas de Mercado, The scholastic philosopher searched for truth, not for novelty. The modern
for example, has become a classic of economics and economic ethics. mind, which is to some extent a historicist one, thinks that everything has al-
Ramos contemplates the colonial seventeenth century as a century of in- ready been overcome, or as Hegel would say, aufgehoben. Truth is therefore
tellectual isolation and stagnation. He states that the Hapsburgs and the •.ouglil only in what is new, and innovation is valued for its o w n sake, not
Church obstructed progress, and he describes Scholasticism as a decadent,
16, Sec Ramos, Hlstoria de lafilosofla en Mexico, p. 137.
17, Ibid., p, I 19.
14. See Ramos, Wstoria de lafilosofla en Mexico, |>. I 3 3.
15. See A. Gomez Robledo, El magisterioftlosiflco-jurtdleode Alonso de la Veracruz (Mex- IK. .in,m ile Zapata y Sandoval, De Iusiiiia dlstributiva (Valllsoleti: Cristoph. Lasso
\.I,,I. 1609),
ico: I'ornin, ]')M).
8 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n C o l o n i a l M e x i c o Introduction 9

necessarily for the good it brings. The scholastic w h o finds truth in w h a t is respects, stronger and more formative; that is, more widely used, to justify
n e w tries to assimilate it. But before this, he must prove it, exercising rigor in i he movement toward independence than the doctrines of the Enlighten-
his methods. It is simplistic and easy to say that one does not change just be- ment (which are typically associated with the movements of independence). 2 2
cause one is static or fixed. Sometimes the claim is made that all conservatism Unless we w a n t to commit this error of misinterpretation by reducing a
and reluctance to change is the product of an ideological position—a conve- philosophical approach to ideology instead of explanation, w e have to judge
nient way to cover up economic, political, and social injustice. This is an i he forces and trends of history with an open mind. Ramos reduces scholasti-
oversimplification; there are cases in which a theory is preserved because it is cism to one mor e structure of colonial domination, and thus he can easily
better than a n e w one. There may be good theoretical reasons for this that discredit it. He presents scholasticism as something that justified colonial
make such conservatism legitimate. Progress in philosophy differs from domination and overlooks the struggles undertaken by m a n y scholastics (Las
progress in the empirical sciences. Empirical science regularly admits change ( asas, Zapata y Sandoval, and others, for example) against domination.
and looks forward to increases and modifications. Philosophers, in contrast, Ramos believes it is difficult to value scholasticism positively. He attrib-
depend upon earlier doctrines, often maintaining and preserving these. lltes to scholasticism the function of maintaining the laws of the Indies and
From this 'triumphant' or 'optimistic' perspective from which the past is iheir oppressive system. Scholasticism, he asserts, kept minds separated from
looked down upon, Ramos interprets the birth of m o d e rn philosophy in reality and shaped the state and Church into a power that penetrated all
Mexico as a struggle against scholasticism, with scholasticism representing i lungs. Moreover, under its influence laws came to be viewed as fixed ideas,
the oppressors' power. Mexicans discovered that scholastic philosophy could special structures that should not be changed. Under scholasticism, society
not address pressing social problems in real life, whereas m o d e rn philosophy was not viewed as a living, changing organism but as a static, unchanging
could. 19 According to Ramos, the political revolution required a philosophical ii iiclure. But this is clearly false if we bring to mind, for example, the dy-
revolution, and that is why m o d e r n philosophy was embraced. He states, namic and mutable conception of society that Saint Thomas Aquinas devel-
"The struggle against Peripateticism was dangerous and heroic: for anyone i 'i >rd of society. 23
w h o dared to attack those doctrines could be blamed of heresy and some- Ramos also claims that the dogmatic and rigid training that scholasticism
times even of rebellion. However, Charles Ill's illustrated government allowed Imparted hindered and restricted the intellectual, religious, moral, and eco-
the publication of n e w ideas and the criticism of the traditional regime." 20 nomic life of the colony. This training and the attitudes that they promoted
I iiissod from the iiterate people to the common people by means of m a n y in-
Ramos mistakenly denies that scholasticism has any value. Instead h e
li i mediaries and in this way shaped the Mexican soul. He states: "Scholastic
should have criticized its abuse; that is, its use as an ideological weapon or a
philosophy has shaped the Mexican character more or less directly. This can
substitute for or rival of empirical science. All schools of thought have used
nil he recognized by a certain lack of will, by an unconscious habit of expect-
some aspects of philosophy in the wrong way, and this misuse should be
• ui: everything from either the government or God. This weakness also partly
eliminated. However, to strip a school of thought of any value based upon
• plains the habit of imitating from other countries the ideas that should
these misuses is unjust. It was the bad use of schofasticism that gave way to
solve our problems." 24 Furthermore, scholasticism is guilty for the Mexicans'
oppression. Attributing the oppression to scholasticism amounts to a failure to
I.n I, nl empirical understanding. Ramos does acknowledge one advantage of
acknowledge the freedom and defense of justice and the h u m a n rights doc-
• Imlasticism for Mexicans; it developed logicai abilities in t h e m that in tur n
trines that scholasticism produced in abundance. 2 1 The great influence that
scholastic doctrines had u p o n the m o v e m e n ts of independence also must be 1
This has been thoroughly studied by O. C. Stoetzer, Las rakes eseoldsticas de la
recognized. Moreover, often scholastic doctrines were, in fact and in many Wtith ipdi ion de hi America espanola (Madrid: Centra de Bstudios Constitucionales, 1982).
' I Sec Saini Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, I-Il, q. 91, a. 5, ad 1; a. 6, c.; 96, a.
1
19. See Ramos, Historia de lafilosofiaen Mexico, p. 148. I q mi, a y ad 1.
20. "La lucha contra el peripaletismo era peligrosa y heroica, pues Codo aqucl que ' I la lilosoli.i escol.islica, ni.is o menus directamenle, es urio de los factores que
osaba atacar las doctrinas de la escuela se cxpom'a a ser acusado cle hcrcji'a y a voces I' MI iiiodc'lado el taiai lei iiiexicano, el cual se dislinguc lodavfa por una delta falta de
hasla dc sedition. Sin embargo, el gobicrno iluslrado do Carlos III loleid que se pub- "'"mid propla, por tin hahiio inconsclente de esperarlo todo de Dios o del gobierno.
1
ticaran las ideas nuevas y la crftica contra el regimen escolar tradlelonal." ibid., p, is.;. i ' 'I' lnlul.nl dc la propia inn i.iliva expllca lanibicn, aiuiquo solo parcialmcnte, la COS-
.'. I. Sec Silvio /aval.i, La defensa dt los derechos del hombtt en AmMca I anna (sighs XVI "Hii'ii ilc iwnai dc oiios J>.ii•.<••. el pensamiento que ha de resolver nuestros proble-
will) (Mexico; IINAM UNESCO, I'm.') llhli < •. (In II l,i imilac " K.linos. HiStoHa de /a flloSOfta en l\le\ieo. p. I S7.
10 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o Introduction 11

led to a certain clarity and precision of thought that awakened a critical spirit. support m o d e rn philosophy. They used arguments to determine w h e t h e r to
With this small concession, Ramos t h e n dismisses scholasticism. accept or reject this philosophy, and some of these arguments revealed good
Ramos's characterization of scholasticism should be questioned. Was it reasons for supporting the n e w theories. "But we cannot at all conclude from
scholasticism or the Spanish government that produced weak, passive Mexi- this that Aristotelian-Thomist philosophy rejected all scientific data or
cans? The Spanish conquerors were exposed to centuries of Catholic religion demonstration a priori. We k n o w that there were some people w h o rejected
and scholastic philosophy, and yet they were bold and enterprising; w h y .ill new thought without taking into account its truth or fafsity, perhaps be-
weren't the Mexicans? W h y weren't other countries, where scholasticism t.uise of their unjustified prejudices or seniie tendencies. Moreover, there
was practiced, also passive? Ramos uses logically flawed arguments. A trend was not m u c h interest in the renovation of systems and methods of educa-
of thought must be less passionately and more carefully evaluated; consid- i ion; this probably happened because they were not prepared for the assimi-
ered with logically sound arguments and not mere half-truths. It is easy to lation and coordination of the n e w with the everlasting in philosophy." 27
assert dogmatically that various propositions form the foundation of a given Sometimes, however, the scholastics did not find convincing enough reasons
school of thought and t h e n to trace all economic, political, and social evils of in adopt the n e w philosophy. And that is what we all demand from any
a given society to these propositions. However, Ramos's argument that scho- philosophical doctrine in order to assimilate it. We do not change our philo-
lasticism caused specific economic, political, and social ills in Mexico is not a .ii|ihical views just for the sake of novelty; this would be superficial and im-
logically sound one. Other scholars have argued that scholasticism led to I'liulcnt. Sometimes scientific discoveries were accepted while the philoso-
progress in Mexico. 25 Our search for scholarly justice compels us to evaluate phy associated with t h e m was considered unacceptable. Admittedly, there
this historical p h e n o m e n o n more carefully. was occasionally a certain opposition, intermingled with political interests.
i'.lit this was not caused by scholastic philosophy but rather by the exploita-
tion of it by some people for their own ends. Scholastics displayed a deep in-
David Mayagoitia nicst in the search for truth.

Mayagoitia studied scholastic and modern colonial philosophy within the Willi respect to the Jesuits' philosophicai endeavors, Mayagoitia describes
contexts of both the universities and the Jesuit colleges. With respect to the I tie work of the colleges, pointing out the educational system by which they
scholastic philosophy cultivated in the university, he recognizes that the most were i tiled and which prevailed in the Society everywhere, as can be seen in
important characteristic of the university was not its originality. That is one II n- Ratio Studiorum. He speaks about some prominent teachers w h o taught in
of the points we acknowledged in our discussion of Samuel Ramos's views, iln- colleges, and he stresses their success in the education of some notable
but w e also have to recognize that Mexican scholastics were as good as their (K'ople. Mayagoitia mentions the intellectual and political balance resulting
European counterparts. It is unfair to say that all of t h e m merely imitated Eu- 1111111 111 e scholastic training. This balance formed the basis of colonial institu-
ropeans. Many of them, such as Friar Alonso, Mercado, and Rubio, made llons, of their unity of faith, their peace, and their economic prosperity. (It
original contributions to uniquely American problems. ' 2 w lis also a major factor in the process of emancipation from Spain). During
i iilnnial limes, philosophy, Mayagoitia telfs us—and Ramos had afready illus-
According to Mayagoitia in his Ambiente filosofico de la Nueva Espana (1945),
ion n l I his—could reach the people, and m a n y customs and proverbs attest to
the scholastics of the university were openly suspicious of and hesitant to
I Ills "' People did spend a great deal of time on conceptismo and memorization,
lit.ll tins type of learning cannot be attributed solely to the influence of
25. See, for example, V. Mufioz Delgado, "Nominalismo, logica y humanismo," in
El erasmismo en Espana, ed. M. Revuelta Sanudo and C. Moron Arroyo (Santander: So-
ciedad Menendez Pelayo, 1986), pp. 109-74. Mufioz Delgado studies the achievements ' I "I'riii de esto en ninguna manera sc puede concluir que la filosofi'a aristotelico-
of scholastic philosophy in the area of logic and semantics and compares these to (rends IIIIIIISM in ha/aba a priori cualquier dato o deinostracion de caracter cientmco. No por
of modern thought. For another example of this type of evaluative approach, see also I'lln ili'sti cemos que hubo partlculares que Ucvadosporprejuiciospocojustificados o
Sierra Bravo, El pensamiento socialy economico de la escoldstica. The achievements and con- I'i'i inulcnclas seniles rechazasen todo lo nuevo sin preoeuparse de distinguir entre lo
tributions of scholastic philosophy in terms of justice and the common good arc ana- i nlailcm y In [also. Mas aim. sc nolo cierta llojcdad en renovar sistemas y aim meto-
lyzed in this work. ilni ilf nine.n inn pioh.ililrmriilc por no cm nnliarsr aptos para el liabajo de asimi-
26. See David Mayagoitia, Ambientefilosiflco de la Niicvn Espafla (Mexico: .his, 1945), 1
V i n n i i l i n a i inn tie In niii-vn r u n to q u e cs p c i t - n n c e n lilnsofl'a." Ibid., p . 1 1 I.
p. 106, n. 2. •!< Ibid , p. 178,
12 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o Introduction 13

scholasticism. It is also the result of the overall decadence of the Spanish Em- ones; some of t h e m were agile commentators of the texts, and some of t h e m
pire, w h e r e a sort of subtle 'conceptual Gongorism' was at its height and were enslaved by t h e texts. Yet all of t h e m were scholastics, but for different
which affected institutions in America. 29 This decadent element was never i easons. The predominan t ones were those whos e arid m e t h o d of exposition
really overcome; m a n y elements of logic and metaphysics as practiced in made it difficult to divulge very important doctrines and issues a m o ng our
Latin America carry its traces today. 30 contemporaries." 3 2 As with any school of knowledge, scholasticism came in
Because of their broad outlook, the scholastics, notes Mayagoitia, played • ill sbapes and sizes. There were those w h o used a sterile m e t h o d and doc-
an influential role in the modernization of philosophy. The missionaries nine, t h u s moving away from the Mexican reality; a n d there w e r e others
brought ideas from Europe, and they did not destroy t h e past needlessly: "It who directed and applied all of their strength and intellectual instruments to
was exactly the opposite: they w a n t e d to recover the past, to go back to t h e daily problems. This is true for all periods, even during t h e seventeenth cen-
great teachers, and vindicate t h em from all that had been unfairly attributed i in y, w h e n scholasticism seemed to be caught in a predominantly conserva-
to t h e m . They wanted to incoportate the n e w sciences into perennial phi- livc attitude.
losophy and to the teaching programs." 3 1 Mayagoitia indicates that the Je-
According to Robles, this makes it unfair to say, as Agustin Rivera did and
suits contributed to the development of philosophy in Mexico and at-
US others continue to do, that all Mexican scholasticism was decadent. Al-
tempted to rejuvenate Aristotelian-Thomist philosophy, coordinating or
i hough there were detestable scholastic works, detestable in their stifling for-
synthesizing it within m o d e r n philosophy and science. Yet this particular
malism and their false and repetitive verbose style, there were also masterly
Jesuit endeavor was a contributing factor in the Jesuits' banishment from
Works that dealt with concrete issues and contained important and relevant
Latin America.
observations. Hence Robles adds, "Let us make clear that it is both sophistic
.mil unfair to judge the scholars w h o taught and wrote in New Spain without
Oswaldo Robles IM111icr consideration: not all of t h e m were important thinkers, nor were all
abstruse and c o m m on ones." 33 He gives the example of Friar Alonso de la
Our observation that there was m u c h diversity of interests and skills to be Vera Cruz who, although not an original thinker, was an excellent peda-
found among groups of scholastic philosophers in New Spain finds its most i:>i):iie. Vera Cruz revived the Aristotelianism of old texts with practical, so-
precise formulation in these words of Oswaldo Robles in Filosofos mexkanos • id, and historical applications, thereby fostering the history of philosophy. M
delsiglo XVI (1950): "We have to say that there were very different scholas- IIlis occurred relatively early because, for example, the British colonization
tics in New Spain—and w e are talking about the three colonial centuries. bail already begun in 1587, and "Not until 1685 did the teaching of philoso-
There were Thomist, Suarecian, amd Scotist scholastics; there were deca- phy begin in North America, w h e n William Brattle gave a course on Logic
dent, rigid, purist, eclectic, innovative, and even some terribly soporific ones. n Harvard College. His course was based u p o n Cartesian principles. The
There were also some praiseworthy ones, and some paralyzed and servile n Klbook for this course circulated, in manuscript form, for half a century;

29. Ibid., pp. 181-82. I ' "Debemos declarer que entre los escolasticos de la Nueva Espana, y compren-
30. See Redmond and Beuchot, La logica mexicana. lOS <u esta alirmacion los Ires siglos coloniales, los hubo de distintos matices y de
31. "Todo lo contrario, querian resucitar el pasado, volver a los grandes maestros, diversos meritos. Los hubo tomistas, suariztas y escotistas; los hubo decadentes,
reivindicandolos de cuanto se les habia injustamente atribuido, e incorporar a la !'•'.. puristas, eclecticistas, innovadores y aun deplorable y abominablemente so-
filosofia perenne y a los programas de ensenanza las ciencias que entonces comenzaban Irmv Duos COD grandes merecimientos, otros esclerosados y serviles; unos comen-
a florecer." Mayagoitia, Ambientefilosoflcode la Nueva Espana, p. 194.32. "Debemos de- I' I dgllmente el espi'ritu de los lextos, otros esclavos de la letra. Y todos ellos eran es-
clarer que entre los escolasticos de la Nueva Espana, y comprendemos en esta afirma- iu os por diversas razoncs; pero predominaron los que lo fueron por el metodo de
cion los tres siglos coloniales, los hubo de distintos matices y de muy diversos meritos. isl( ion, de domic la tnnegable aridez de sus escritos que ha constituido el principal
Los hubo tomistas, suariztas y escotistas; los hubo decadentes, rfgidos; puristas, eclec- i. iiln para que se difundaD entre nuestros contemporaneos ideas y doctrinas de in-
ticistas, innovadores y aun deplorable y abominablementc soporiferos. Unos con iillblc Importancia." oswaldo Robles, FiMsofos mexkanos del siglo XVI (Mexico: Por-
grandes merecimientos, otros esclerosados y serviles; unos comenlando agilmi-nic el es- i •»',()». pp, g i).
pirilu de los lextos, olros esclavos de la lelra. Y todos ellos eran cscolaslkos por diversas •' I "Dejemos, rn consecuencla, bien sentado epic es soflstico e injusto hacer juicios
razoncs: pero predoininaron los que lo fueron por el mctodo de exposition, de domic la ir.iiiu Hiii rclailvamentc a los escoldsticos que enseiiaron y escrlbieron en la Nueva
tnnegable artdez de sus escritos que ha constituido el principal obstficulo para que si- <li- mi no iiiiln'. iiirinii pensadores llusires; pero tampoco fueron todos glosadores
linulan enire nuestros contemporaneos Ideas y doctrinas de Indlscutiblc Imporiancia.'' ii •. i- Indlgesios." Ibid , p 10
Oswaldo Robles, FiMsofos mexlcanos del slab XVI (Mexico: P 1930), pp, 8 9 I i Ibid p 22
14 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o Introduction 15

eventually, in 1735, it was printed in Boston. This happened almost two cen- Vicente L o m b a r d o T o l e d a no
turies after Friar Alonso had printed his lessons for the opening of the Uni-
versity of Mexico." 35 Lombardo Toledano's work on philosophy in Mexico, Las corrientes filosofi-
cas en la vida de Mexico (1963), is written from a Marxist perspective. 40 In it he
lakes on the task of searching for the social (ideological) role of t h e philoso-
Jose Maria Gallegos Rocafull
phy of New Spain. He is highly critical of schofastic philosophy as it was prac-
The most complete and erudite history of the philosophy of New Spain of liced in the university, claiming that it prepared the way for the hierarchies
the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries is found in the work of Jose Maria of I lie civil and ecclesiastic government, and it guaranteed a conservative
Gallegos Rocafull, El pensamiento mexicano en los siglos XVIy XVII (1974) .36 It is a II cud of thought: "What some historians have called the renovating contri-
well-documented and detailed work on the general thought in Mexico dur- I >n l ion of philosophy in the teachings of Friar Alonso de la Vera Cruz and his
ing these centuries, and it remains the most informative study of this period. Colleagues is, on the contrary, the regression of Spanish thought to its ortho-
Gallegos takes all previous investigations into account. Nevertheless, in his dox condition of the Middle Ages, following what had happened in events
book w e find only a few hermeneutical and evaluative assertions concerning "ii the peninsula. It is not the vivification of ideas urging t h e m forward, but
the repercussion of scholastic philosophy in Mexico. His is a study of docu- rather the going back to formalist and dogmatic scholasticism in order to face
ments that, whiie serious and detailed, is only informative. the new ideological trends of the Renaissance." 41 He has a higher opinion of
There are not m a n y instances in which h e comments upon the authors humanists such as Garces, Zumarraga, Don Vasco, and Las Casas. In contrast
he discusses in his history. For example, in one passage he says that the i" Ramos and Mayagoitia, Lombardo says that scholastic philosophy did not
courses given in arts or philosophy were not highly regarded at the univer- reach the people. He claims that "Renaissance philosophy, based upon the
sity; they were merely stepping stones to more prestigious positions. Medi- rational and critical examination of h u m a n problems, was limited to use by
ocre professors used empty rhetoric to attract attention in hopes of being i lie missionaries, and it did not reach the larger part of colonial society." 42
promoted to a better position." In another section, Gallegos Rocafull says lombardo finds a sense of nationalism not in philosophy but rather in the
that some professors did pay attention to the real problems of America, and literature of Ruiz de Alarcon and Sister Juana, among others. Lombardo finds
he praises t h e m for it.™ III Sigiienza a philosopher whose work reached the people, yet he adds that
It is evident that Gallegos Rocafull considers scholastic philosophy valu- Mgiienza was active at a time w h e n the university was in decline. The same
able. His evaluation is not partisan, however, for he does not take sides either happens with other modern Mexican philosophers: "Native Spaniards are not
for or against it. He shows himself to be a conscientious and parsimonious iln philosophers any longer. The criollos are the ones w h o now understand
historian w h o follows the documentary protocol and demonstrates, at all ili-n philosophy is a means to transform the country's situation; in the same
times, an admirable erudition. His work is the result of the direct consulta- way .is ii was used by scholastics to support the feudal and enslaving
tion of m a n y texts; he demonstrates a competence and precision in working II Kline."" Here he refers to the most important m o d e r n philosophers, such
with diverse authors and themes, as well as skill and depth as a scholar and i ' ..iiii.ii ra and the Jesuits.
thinker.™
in Vicente Lombardo Toledano, Las corrientesfilosoficasen la vida de Mexico, 2d ed.
35. "[S]61o hasta 1685 principiaba en Norteamerica la ensefianza de la filosofi'a, I Mexico: Universidad Obrera de Mexico, 1963).
cuando William Brattle explico en Harvard College un curso de logica inspirado en los II In qiir.ilgunoshistoriadores han llamado aportacion renovadora de la filosofi'a
principios cartesianos y que manuscrito circulo durante medio siglo, hasta que fue im- • II l.r. enseflanzas de fray Alonso de la Vera Cruz y sus colegas, es, por el contrario, e!
prest) en Boston en 1735, casi dos siglos despues de que nuestro fray Alonso imprim- ""•" del pensamiento espanol hacia su cauce ortodoxo de la Edad Media, sigu-
iera sus lecciones al inaugurate la Universidad de Mexico." Ibid., p. 12. I" It) que ocurrfa en la peninsula. No es la vivificacidn de las ideas lanzandolas ade-
1
36. Gallegos Rocafull, El pensamiento mexicano. All citations are from the second edi- lino l.i vuelta a la escolcistica formalista y dogmatics para enfrenlarse a las corri-
tion published in 1974. i un •. Idrnloglcas del Renacimiento/ ibid., p. 27.
37. Ibid., p. 297. i 11 |.i Hlosoffa renacentlsta, basada en el examen rational y critico de los proble-
Mi
38. Ibid., pp. 302 and 306. ' limn is, 11><• piim ip.ilinriiic patrimonlo <lc los misioneros, y tampoco alcanzci a
19. Thai brief summary of Gallegos Rocafull's work appears as a collaboration In .i\.m.i de l.i sociedadcol al " Ibid., p. 15.
acollective volume; "La Blosoffa en Mexico en los siglos xvi y xvn," in Bstudioi de histo i '• 1'1'i.in de ••(•! los espaflolcs pc lulares los flMsofos. Ahora son los criollos los
i 111>ic• 11«lc• 11 que l.i I I I U M I I I . I (•.. u n 111-.111 i n n |i 11.i• i-.I.>iiii.ii i.i .Jin.i, ,i,.|
rladelaflhsoflamMixIco, Ird cd (Mexico UNAM, 1980) pp 93 120
16 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Introduction 17

Leopoldo Zea of New Spain, and he uses it to develop a critique of the decadent aspects of
scholasticism.
Leopoldo Zea devotes some pages to colonial philosophy in his history of There was in the colony a static philosophy used to justify the power of
philosophy in Mexico, La filosofia en Mexico (1955).44 Following Ramos, he certain social groups. But why couldn't a philosophical instrument imported
thinks that scholastic philosophy was an instrument used to maintain an es- from Europe, as scholasticism was, be applied successfully to both this sort of
tablished order and deny all that was modern, thereby contributing to the problem as well as other problems facing Mexico? Undoubtedly, the (social)
passive attitude of Mexicans.45 Only clergymen had access to culture, as can sciences that came afterwards were better prepared empirically, but the prin-
be seen even in the fathers of independence. But modern philosophy, with its ciples of justice and common good that scholasticism studied in various
emphasis on freedom and political autonomy, had a great impact even on forms provided excellent theoretical support for Mexico's liberation. Yet be-
clergymen. cause these principles did not correspond with those of the government, on
Mexicans freed themselves from Spain but not from the Church. This many occasions the government obstructed their application.
emancipation had to wait until the arrival of liberalism. But modern and lib-
erating thought infiltrated the Jesuits, from Gamarra to the fathers of inde- livaluative Conclusion: The Role and Social Function of
pendence. For example, Hidalgo could have been influenced by Clavigero, Scholastic Philosophy in Mexico
and Aldama studied Gamarra's work.46
For Zea there was philosophy in Mexico, and its problems and their solu- We have discussed the role and function of scholasticism in Mexico; and
tions were uniquely Mexican. "What is not original is the means to obtain i his question is neither a matter of history, nor of historiography, but of his-
such solutions. In this case, Mexican philosophy has used an arsenal of ideas lorical hermeneutics and of the philosophy of history. To be more precise, it
offered by European culture, a culture of which she is the daughter. But such belongs to what may be called the philosophy of history in Mexico, and, to
ideas, when transported to our lands, while preserving their original form, be even more specific, to the philosophy of the history of philosophy in
have, through a transformation of content, become ours. This, I repeat, is Mexico.
what makes these problems exclusively ours."47 Let us consider one side of the matter. What did Mexicans contribute to
Zea does not deny that European theories have provided Mexico with scholastic philosophy? They contributed a philosophy that was well done
philosophical instruments for reflection. With their aid, uniquely Mexican .iiid, lurthermore, done for the good of the people and society. They passed
problems and situations have been addressed. He notes, "We do not at- 1111 11 ici r cultural products through a teaching that was critical and sometimes
tempt, as has been wrongly attempted, to impose certain philosophical con- even original. This intellectual dissemination was forceful and important.
ceptions upon Mexican reality. On the contrary, we will try to search for the Samuel Ramos and David Mayagoitia help us see this when they say that
philosophical conceptions that are suitable to this reality. Reality will not be scholasticism reached the people and offered them a structure of thought.
sacrificed for the sake of ideas, but ideas will be adapted to reality. This real- According to Ramos, this structure reached the people after having been fil-
ity, will be constituted by different and opposing interests, which will look for Icred ihrough the clergymen's preaching and was manifested in customs and
their justification in these ideas."48 Zea applies this insight to the philosophy s,lyings. Its most complicated aspect, however, was reserved for those familiar
wilh ils lechnicalities.
pais, de la rnisma manera que les sirvio a los escolasticos para sostener el regimen feu- Now we may ask: What did scholastic philosophy give the Mexicans? In
dal y esclavista." Ibid., p. 42.
44. Leopoldo Zea, Lafilosofiaen Mexico, vol. 1 (Mexico: Libro-Mex Eds., 1955). uiiiny cases, scholastic philosophy was indeed used as an ideological tool by
45. Ibid., p. 15. iliose in government to oppress, but there were also many cases in which
46. Ibid., p. 24.
47. "Lo que no ha sido original es el instrumental para obtener dichas soluciones.
En este caso se ha servido del arsenal de ideas que le ha ofrecido la Cultura Europea de Id.id niexlcaii.i unas detcrminadas concepciones lilosoficas; todo lo contrario, lo que se
la cual es hija. Pero tales ideas al ser trasladadas a estas nuestras tierras, guardando su 11.11.1 ser.i buscfir aquellas concepciones lilosolicas que convengan a esta realidad. La re-
forma de origen, se han hecho nuestras al transformar su contenido. Esle conicnido, .illil.id no ser.i sacrlliuida a las ideas, sino eslas adapladas a la realidad. Esla realidad la
vuelvo a repetirlo, es el que le da problcrnas snlamenle nueslros." Ibid., p. 9-10. hii in.ii.HI los divcisos interest's en pugna, los males huscaran en I.is ideas su propia jus-
48. "No se va a pretender, comu erroneairienle se ha prelendldo, iiiipoiier .i la real- lllli.iilon," Ibid., p. 14.
18 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico

scholasticism was used against oppression and injustice. It was used to argue
in defense of the rights of Indians, to reveal the injustices of domination. Las
Casas, a follower of Vitoria and Soto, Friar Alonso, Quiroga, and Zumarraga
are only some examples of philosophers who used scholastic doctrines to
fight injustice rather than to justify it. Other scholastic philosophers who de-
fended human rights and common economic-social welfare include Tomas
de Mercado, Pedro de Hortigosa, and Friar Francisco Jimenez. Some doc-
trines of scholastic philosophy were even used to defend the supreme values
of freedom and autonomy, as we can see in the war of independence.49 We
may say that in Mexico's colonial period we find both good and bad applica-
tions of scholastic philosophy, but that the scholastic philosophy practiced in
colonial Mexico was not inherently bad.
2 iffi The Sixteenth Century
49. See Stoetzer, Las rakes escoldsticas.
The Humanist Philosophers

General Outlook

D
uring the sixteenth century, although all scholars had a scholastic
formation, humanism became increasingly important. Thus we
can recognize two tendencies in the thought of this period, a
scholastic one and a humanist one. Of course, many thinkers showed strains
of both tendencies. Therefore, we can talk about 'scholastic' humanism and
'humanist' scholasticism. But the predominance of either trend allows us to
•.peak of two different groups of philosophers in this century: humanists and
scholastics.
The intellectual climate in Mexico permitted the existence of both groups.
I litre was not only material prosperity, but both the religious orders and the
university possessed a great wealth of knowledge. Not without a touch of
Ininy, Mateo Rosas de Oquendo sings of this:

Tanto galrin caballero,


inuchas y bizarras damas
tales bizarros al uso,
i ic.is y coslosas gains
gran suma de mercaderes
. 11 M •. aunque todoel mundo abarcan,
i DiiKi pesos de rcloj

L9
20 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o S i x t e e n t h Century: H u m a n i s t s 21

unos suben y otros bajan; The representatives in Mexico of this humanist trend of thought were
muchos doctores de borla, I riar Julian Garces, Friar Juan de Zumarraga, Friar Bartolome de las Casas,
muchos letrados de fama,
Vasco de Quiroga, and Doctor Francisco Hernandez. The reformist and uto-
licenciados canonistas
que a Bartulos aventajan; lian thought, inspired in Erasmus of Rotterdam and Constantino Ponce, was
teologos de conciencia he outstanding one in Zumarraga's philosophy. Las Casas's thought was
que la conservan y amparan . . . .' ;iiided by social experimentation and the defense of the Indians. He was con-
ei ned with ideas that pointed out man's dignity and the Gospels' strength to
A very gallant gentleman,
many and grand ladies levate m a n . Quiroga's philosophical-social thought was influenced by the
Very peculiar costumes, .line strength of the Gospels and reinforced by More's Utopia. And Doctor
rich and expensive clothes lei nandez's humanist tendency was characterized by the attention he paid
A huge number of merchants: o Greek philosophic sources. His intention was to combine Platonism, Aris-
although they sail the whole world,
olelianism, and Stoicism.
some go up and some go down,
The h u m a n i s m of these thinkers was Christian to the extent that it corn-
like weights on a clock.
Many doctors of hood and gown; lined scholasticism with radical evangelism. This Christian h u m a n i s m moved
many famous men of letters; leople to work for life because w h e n doing good in this life, they were work-
licensed canonists in: lor their o w n good in the afterlife. This is well expressed by Pedro de
who surpass Bartulos; rrejo:
and theologians with a conscience
who preserve and defend conscience itself. . . . I .i muerte se nos acerca.
Viendo ya el tiempo que pasa
de la vida,
Humanist Philosophers con bien la otra vida merca
en aquesta vida escasa
One of the important characteristics of Renaissance humanist thought was y .illigida.
the interest in emphasizing man's dignity. This interest led to the purification I,i vida se nos acaba
of scholastic teaching, removing all sorts of unnecessary and elusive ques- y nosotros no acabamos
de enlender.
tions. In light of this n e w interest, h u m a n i s m returned to both classic and
[oque el anima a la aldaba
evangelic sources. Concerning t h e classic sources, t h e humanists tried to re-
del bien, que solo llevamos
cover the correct and elegant Latin of the best Roman writers, and they did I" poder.
the same with the Greeks. With respect to the sources of Christianity, the in-
Heuli is approaching us.
tention to imitate the simplicity of the first Christians, to follow the Gospels to
Seeing now lime passing away in life,
their last consequences, to demonstrate appreciation for the Holy Fathers,
i .mi with goodness the other life
and to transform the habits of the Church were evident. This attitude brought Inning ihis present life ol need and distress.
political changes that were associated with 'Humanism.' The attempt to l ilc luings us lo an end:
transform both Church and State into an ideal of a higher virtue caused the i\c Jo mil come lo an end ol understanding.
appearance of various Utopias; Thomas More's was among the most impor- i in- soul is knocking ai the door of that good
u inc h we cannol bear wiihoui strength.
tant of these. Utopian thought found an open and fertile field of work in the
New World. Itolli cil llii'sc philosophical and religious trends converged in whal we n o w

I. Alfonso Reyes, "Rosas de Oquendo en America," in Capltulos de literature! espaflola,


lsi ser. (Mexico: La C.IS.I de Espafifl en Mexico. 1939), pp, 22 71. • Pcdrodc trcjo, CanchneroGeneral (Mexico: UNAM, 1981),p, 81,
22 Histor y of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o S i x t e e n t h Century: H u m a n i s t s 23

call humanism . This can be observed in the following Mexican humanist


philosophers. Scholastic traits in Zumarraga's philosophical-legal doctrine
We find several characteristics of Scbolaticism in Zumarraga's Segundo
parecer. Scholastic elements are evident both in the terminology and in the
Friar J u a n d e Z u m a r r a g a
development of the arguments. The work was written in response to three
Zumarraga was born sometime between the end of 1468 and the begin- questions Viceroy Antonio de Mendoza put to Zumarraga: (i) Was it fair that
ning of 1469 in Tabira de Durango, in the province of Vizcaya, Spain.' He later i here were rescue slaves (esclavos de rescate) among the Indians; (ii) Should
entered the Franciscan Order in the Monastery of Our Lady of Aranzazu, in I here be war slaves a m o n g the Indians; and (iii) Should the Indian governors
the province of Cantabria. ft is k n o w n that he was a caretaker in several who were entrusted with war declarations also be consigned to slavery and
monasteries: Abrojo, Avila, and perhaps the Monastery of San Esteban in I ii anded with iron? These were central issues, and Zumarraga sent t w o sets of
Burgos. answers to the Viceroy because he found his first set deficient.
In 1527, Zumarraga was offered and accepted the post of Bishop of Mex- Zumarraga claims that it is unjust to h a v e rescue slaves. Although slavery
ico, thereby becoming the first bishop of Mexico. He arrived in New Spain in was sometimes justified by claiming that slavery was customary a m o n g t h e
1528, but he was not consecrated until 1533. The consecration took place in Indians, the Bishop maintained that this did not justify the enslavement of
Spain, w h e r e Zumarraga had gone to respond to the accusations against him the Indians by the Spaniards. He claimed that his position was supported by
for defending the Indians. 4 He returned to Mexico in 1534 and continued to most learned and religious authors and was concordant with the spirit of
defend the rights of the Indians. His dedication to this struggle was far-reach- Si liolasticism. He writes: "There is n o law, reason, or example to justify the
ing; he founded the first college in the New World, Santa Cruz de Tlatelolco. slavery of the Indians; and our Christianity does not suffer this tyrannical
He also established the college of San Jua n de la Cruz, and he created the hos- practice because it goes against natural law and Christ's law, and so should
pital of San J u a n de Dios. He introduced the printing machine and worked for I" abolished. There is n o doubt regarding this; there is nothing m o r e to be
5
the establishment of the university. His works bear the influence of Renais-
sance h u m a n i s m . 111 response to the issue of w h e t h e r there should be war slaves among the
Indians, Zumarraga gives a negative answer, justified with six reasons. He be-
Written works >'11 is by claiming that "the war against the pagans is unfair and wicked, u n d e r

Zumarraga's works display both scholastic and humanist tendencies. His m y icrms of authority, and even m o r e so is the war against those w h o live in
Segundo parecer sobre la esclavitud (1536) is more scholastic in tone, as seen in I" an- and quiet." 8 Because t h e Indians have n o t attacked persons or their
his rejection of slavery is based upon divine law, natural law, and the rights of property, there are n o reasons w hy Indians themselves should be attacked;

m a n , all of t h e m part of the scholastic tradition during Zumarraga's time. m y attack against t h e m is unjust. Certainly, the Indians have not attacked
Both his Doctrina breve (1543-1544) and Doctrina cristiana (1546) are consid- iinyone, but they were attacked by the Spaniards; they have not stolen any-
ered humanist works; the first was influenced by Erasmus of Rotterdam and 111IIu'.. hul their possessions have been taken away; they have not assaulted

the second by Constantino Ponce. Erasmian influences can also be found in


his Regla cristiana breve (1547). 6 birvr miiy provechosa de las corns que pertenecen a la fe caiholica y a nra. cristiandad, en estilo
• ••mo pa coiiiii(n) inlelige(n)cia (Mexico: n.p., 1543); Doctrina cristiana mas cierta y ver-
I.LICIO paragentes sin erudkUny lelras (Mexico: n.p., 1546); and Regla cristiana breve, ed.
3. J. Garcia Icazbalceta, Fray Juan de Zumarraga, primer obispo y arzobispo de Mexico
i ilmrj (Mexico: Jus, 1951).
(Buenos Aires: Espasa-Calpc, 1952); F. de J. Chauvet, Fray Juan de Zumarraga (Mexico:
No hay Icy, in ra/.on, in ejcniplo, por donde estos se hagan esclavos como se
n.p., 1948).
li II en, in iiucshn cristiandad sufre lal rescate liranico y contra ley natural y de Cristo,
4. A. M. Carrefio, "Un insigne protector de los indios," in Misionerosde Mexico, (Mex-
ico: Jus, 1961), pp. 44-48. • in' ddic abollrse de] todo; y por no haber c\uc\c\ en esta primera pregunia, no bay que
5. Carrefio, "Don Fray Juan de Zumarraga y la impronia," in ibid., pp. 49 61 • ill. a ma'," ("Segundo parecer," p, 180),
6. luan dc Zumirraga, "Segundo parecer sobre la esclavitud," In Ttxtos polltkos in la H |iJ-. Injusia c Inlcuti la gucrra que se declara a los infieles, por vtrtud dc
Nueva Espafta, ed. C. Herrejon Peredo (Mexico: UNAM, 1984), pp, 173 83; Doctrina ' II a,|inri .iiiiiniil.nl. sobre lodo a oquellos que viven en pa/ y [ian<|iiilidad." Ibid.
24 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n C o l o n i a l M e x i c o Sixteenth Century: Humanist s 25

the Christian religion, either with blasphemy or persecution, but are happily and blessed n a m e of Christ, which has already been denied and taken in vain,
converted to t h e faith. So w a r against t h e m is unjust and wicked. even before they k n e w it." 13 Zumarraga finds fault with t h e royal judiciary
A second argumen t used to support this condemnation of slavery is that provisions because they were not effective in eliminating these problems.
"any law that acts against the h o n o r of God or of the Catholic Faith and its
preaching and spreading is unjust, tyrannical and violent." 9 All practices car- Humanist influences in Zumarraga
ried out within t h e context of slavery are condemned. Anything that has Although Zumarraga does not cite Erasmus directly, it has been shown
been acquired u n d e r the pretext of slavery must be returned. I hat some of his ideas were taken, occasionally wor d for word, from Eras-
Zumarraga also argues against slavery based u p o n his interpretation of mus. 14 In his Doctrina breve, of 1543-1544, the influence of Erasmus's Sn-
papal policy. He claims that the pope assigned the Indies to the king and quiridi&n o Manual del caballero cristiano, and Paracksis ad Christianae Philosophiae
queen of Spain only so that the Christian faith could be spread there, not so sludium is clearly and sometimes explicitly present.
that slavey could be practiced. Furthermore, the king of Spain was obliged to Zumarraga closely follows Erasmus in the pious and moral aspects of his
fulfill the duty given to him by the pope. The king had able ministers and ad- work, not in those doctrines that were thought doubtful or heretical. Zumar-
equate m e a n s to carry out this duty, a duty to preach the Christian faith to the raga's studies of Tostado had familiarized h i m with t h e Holy Fathers (e.g., Au-
Indians of the Colonies "in which the king was considered the supreme rep- I'.ustine and Chrysostom), and his study of Erasmus deepened this connec-
resentative to carry out such a mission." 10 This was his principal task and his i ion. The reformist parts that Zumarraga takes from Erasmus are critiques of
power over the Indians consisted solely in this. Enslaving the Indians was not some of the activities of the Church. He indicated that some of these activities
part of his duty, nor was it his right. There was only one way to preach to the were in urgent need of reform, for they violated certain ascetical and mystical
Indians and give t h e m the Evangelist faith: "in peace, instruction, goodness, beliefs. He adopts Erasmus's nostalgia for a primitive Christianty, which was
servility, and liberality." 11 This was exactly w h a t Christ and his Apostles had more simple, pure, internal, and spiritual t h a n the corrupted Christianity of
done, living perfect lives, not judging those w h o listened to the preachers and II is time. Nonetheless, he does not share Erasmus's nostalgia for ancient
not taking their possesions away from them. Finally Zumarraga contends that philosophers. Zumarraga believed that ancient philosophers were pagans,
lack of knowledge and ignorance or "completely negative infidelity" did not .iiul iheir science did not lead to salvation.
explain the lack of Christian faith among the Indians, because "from this vice '/,umarraga's Doctrina breve (1543) was prohibited by Bishop Montufar, not
of ignorance all other vices flow; such a vice is isolated, not universal, that is because of its Erasmian theses, but due to a theological reference to the blood
to say, one person does not have all the vices." 12 Therefore, the Indians can- of Christ, which, mor e t h a n heretical, was obscure and misinterpreted. 1 5
not be called savages, and naturally neither can they be called servants nor be However, the Catechism was finally published in 1546 under the title of Doct-
enslaved. uiiit cristiana. This is a book in which the presence of the Summa de doctrina
Regarding the issues related to the declaration of war, enslavement, and aisiiana by Constantino Ponce is obvious. (Ponce was burned in 1560 be-
the branding of the Indians, Zumarraga once again defends the Indians. In- i nuse he was thought to be a heretic.)
deed, he asks the king to establish a law for preaching to the Indians "for the
I V " | Y ] por amor de la sangre de Cristo derramada, que se quiten ya estas que llaman
love of the shed blood of Christ may the conquests—so called by the ambitious
li i'. mfseros ambiciosos y cobdiciosos conquistas, como de verdad sean ellas oprobiosas in-
and greedy ones—be removed; for they may truly be an injury to our faith i is de niieslra santa fe y del bendito nombre de Cristo, el cual tienen ya renegado y
hlflsfcmado estos infelices, ante que lo conozcan y les sea denuntiado." Ibid., p. 183.
H. .1. Almoina, "El erasmismo en Zumarraga," Filosofiay Letras 29 (January-March
9. "[E]s injusta, tiranica y violenta toda ley . . . que va contra el honor de Dios o de IV48): 93-126. Perhaps Almoina overemphasizes the influence of Erasmus upon
la fe catolica y de su propagation y predication." Ibid., p. 181. /nni.irraga, but we cannot make concessions to the opposing view that favors, under
10. "[P]ara los cuales se le reconoce [al rey] como duefio y superior por el supremo lllc Influence of the great reformist fervor in Spain at the time, the influence of the
vicario de Cristo en relation a dicha finalidad." Ibid. I i.nii iscans. See C. .1. Alejos Gran, "Zumarraga, Erasmo y la observancia franciscana,"
11. "[E]n paz, sabidurfa, instruction, humildad, benignidad, manscdumbrc, liberal- i tirthaglnensia, 6 (1990): 288. See also R, E. Greenleaf, Zumarraga y la inquisition mexi-
idad." Ibid., p. 182. iiina, 1336-1343 (Mexico: FCB, 1988), p. 38.
12. "|S|on dados tambien a lodos los vitios que de ella dimanan, pern de una forma IV Oswald Kobles, Plldsofos mexfcanOS del Stylo XVI (Mexico: Pomia, 1950), p. 120,
ordinaria, no universal, es deeir: no licne caila iimi lodos Ins vitios." Ibid. n 24,
26 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o S i x t e e n t h Century: H u m a n i s t s 27

The h u m a n i st influence of Erasmus in Zumarraga's Regla cristiana breve ians' and thereby justifying the mistreatment they received and their use as
(1547) is evident. In this work, any m o v e m e n t towards the relaxing of cus- slaves in the service of Spain. While Las Casas used Aristotles's work to argue
toms is resisted while, as in the earliest years of Christianity, the preaching of against Sepulveda, he also gathered support from the Gospefs and the
simplicity and virtue is proposed. In Christianity, h u m a n needs are simply Thomistic doctrine olius naturalis (also used by Francisco de Vitoria). 18
satisfied, corruption is absent, and there is a sincere asceticism according to
which one lives with t h e mystery of charity. Zumarraga says about this Humanist influences
Christian attitude: "Sweet law of love. Oh Benign Lord, h o w good you give Las Casas's training with the Dominicans was scholastic, b u t h e was also
so that our law and b o n d is sweet; our law tells m e to eat, drink, and sleep, inlluenced by the h u m a n i s t school of the Renaissance. Furthermore, h u -
and it shows m e to be as this divine will of ours. Blessed is such a Lord that manist influences were present in his earlier schooling. It is probable that he
takes o n the duties of all his servants; let the Angels give glory to such a si ndied grammar with Elio Antonio de Nebrija, w h o had already established
knowing Lord and the creator of such wise knowledge that let Him govern ,i school in Seville, the birthplace of Bartolome. 1 9 Marcel Bataillon has traced
with the tribute and pity born from the sin which can redeem t h e weight of I he influence of Erasmus on Las Casas t h r o u g h the people w h o were in the
that sin." 16 court of Charles V. The Emperor had been educated in Flanders, and he
brought several Flemish courtiers back to Spain, some of w h o m were close
lo the humanist group of Rotterdam. Among these courtiers whom
Friar B a r t o l o m e d e Las Casas
Charles V integrated into his court were Pierre Barbier, the ally to the chan-
Bartolome de Las Casas (1484-1566) was a Spanish Dominican w h o de- cellor Jean Le Savage, and Adolfo de Borgona, Master of Veere and of Bev-
fended the rights of the Indians as n o one else had done before. Philosophical cicn, w h o had been educated by Jacques Batt, one of the most intimate
anthropology, social or political philosophy, and the philosophy of law all II i e n d s of E r a s m u s . 2 0
meet in a study of his ideas. The richness of the Thomist and humanis t Marcel Bataillon sees the influence of Thomas More's Utopia in t h e social
philosophies is present in the empirical results obtained from his social exper- experiments of Las Casas; for example, w h e n he brought families of workers
iments in New Spain. His whole life was devoted to an ideological and practi- in colonize N e w Spain in a peaceful way. More's influence can also be found
cal struggle. 17 in Las Casas's attempt to attract t h e Indians to the faith by the persuasion of
Even w h e n he made errors in his social experiments, such as the bringing preaching, giving a special place to rhetoric. This replicated the way Renais-
of black slaves to New Spain to help with heavy work, Friar Bartolome always sance humanists argued against the logic and dialectics of the Scholastics. 21
demonstrated concern for the rights of the Indians. This concern is demon- Another sign of Las Casas's h u m a n i s m can be found in his study of Indian
strated most clearly in his debate with J u a n Gines de Sepulveda. Sepulveda i iiliure, and the concern and respect he shows for it. Las Casas attempted to
based his argument o n Aristotle's work, categorizing the Indians as 'barbar- understand the indigenous culture o n its o w n terms, rather t h a n o n Euro-
lie,in ones. 22
16. "Ley de amor suaue. O benigno sefior quan bien dezis que vuestra ley y yugo es
suaue, vuestra ley me manda que coma y beua y duerma, y me ensefia ser vuestra
18. R. Hernandez, "Francisco de Vitoria y Bartolome de Las Casas, primeros
diuina volutda. Bendito sea sefior que tanto cargo tiene de sus sieruos, gloria den los
iroii/.aiites de los derechos h u m a n o s , " Archivo Dominicano 4 (1983): 199-266; Mauricio
angles a tan sapientissimo sefior y criador que por tan alta sabiduria ordenasse, que con
Hruchot, "Fundamentos filosoficos de la justicia: Vitoria y Las Casas," CJDAL
tributo y pena nacida del pecado se redima el censo del mismo pecado." Zumarraga,
(Kcpublica Dominicana) afio 5, n. 11 (1985): 8.
Regla cristiana breve, pp. 109-110.
19, The leading authority o n the life of this friar speaks of this possibility. See I.
17. See Lewis Hanke, Estudios sobre Fray Bartolome de Las Casas y sobre la lucha por la
I'ruv Fernandez, Fray Bartolome de Las Casas (Caleruega: OPE, 1984), p . 20.
justicia en la conquista espahola de America (Caracas: Universidad Central de Venezuela,
.'(). Marcel Bataillon, Estudios sobre Bartolome de Las Casas (Barcelona: Peninsula,
1968); The Spanish Struggle for Justice in the Conquest of America, Philadelphia: University
I ')'/(>), |)|>. 147(1.
of Pennsylvania Press, 1949; and Bartolome de las Casas: An Interpretation of His Life and
-'. I. Mauricio Beuchot, "Aigimiciilacion, retorica y conversion en Bartolome de Las
Writings, The Hague: M. Nijhoff, 1951. See also I. Perez Fernandez, Cronologia documen-
< .i'..iv" Cuadernospara la historic! de la evangelization en Amirica Latina 4 (1989): 123-28.
tada de los viajes, estanciasy actuaciones de Fray Bartolome de Las Casas (Puerto Rico: Univer-
:,.'.. Mauricio Beuchot, "l.a actualidad de la antropolbgfa lilosolica de Fray Bar-
sidad Central de Bayamon, 1985) and Inventario documentado de los escrttos de Fray Bar-
liiliiiuc de Las Casas," Ciunlcrnos de Realidadcs Sotiales (1986): 255-65 mi. 2 7 - 2 8 .
tolome de Las Casas (Puerto Rico: Universidad Central de Bayamon, 1981).
28 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n C o l o n i a l M e x i c o Sixteenth Century: Humanist s 29

Some of those attributes are essential, others are accidental, but both e n d o w
Sources of Las Casas's philosophic theory: humans with certain rights and duties. According to Las Casas, all h u m a n s ,
experience, praxis, and argument without exception, belong to the category 'rational animal'. He writes, "All
J o h n Mair of t h e Monteagudo school of the University of Paris was the the nations of the world are composed of men, and only one definition ap-
first person to discuss the problem of the slavery of the Indians. 23 In 1510, he plies to each one of these men." 2 6 From this it follows that there are n o sub-
used Aristotle to legitimize the claim that the Indians were slaves by nature. stantial or essential differences among men; the only differences are acciden-
The Bishop J u a n de Quevedo did the same in 1519, during a debate at Barce- lal ones. 27 Each m a n has the same attributes of knowledge and will, that is, of
lona. Las Casas responded to this claim in the following way: "The philoso- rational knowledge and rational appetite. 28 Thus, the concept of man's free-
pher was a gentile, and h e is burning in hell; thus we have to use those as- dom is derived from man's rationality. 2 '
pects of his teachings which are compatible with our Catholic faith and The second trait that Las Casas attributes to man, freedom, comes from the
customs." 24 Later, Las Casas used the works of Aristotle to argue against slav- exercise of the will according to reason. Freedom results from the conjunc-
ery. Just as Aquinas and Vitoria had done, Las Casas also developed his o w n tion of reason and will in which reason enlightens will: Freedom is the con-
philosophy, one which included aspects of Christian faith. scious and responsible exercise of will. The existence of a h u m a n nature guar-
Las Casas was a secular cleric and trustee for only a short period of time antees the validity of a natural right and so of freedom. Las Casas writes,
before he enrolled in the Dominican Order in 1523. There he devoted himself "From the beginning, mankind, all men, all lands, and all other things, were
to the study of Aristotle, integrating aspects of Aristotle's philosophy with his free and allodial, due to a right of nature and people. Rational h u m a n nature
o w n ideas. We see this in his m o n u m e n t a l work, Apologetica Historia, and in endows m e n with freedom; as rational, they are born free. All m e n share this
Historia de las Indias. The latter, which he began in 1527, is a work in which he uitional nature; it follows t h e n that God did not create slaves; He conceded
integrates the ideas of Francisco de Vitoria and Domingo de Soto. equal freedom to all men." 3 0 Accordingly, m a n will be able to dominate things
inferior to himself, but never is he permitted to treat other h u m a n beings as
The theoretical basis of Las Casas's thought: •.Lives.
philosophical anthropology Las Casas also analyzes the attribute of sociability. This, according to Las
Las Casas's arguments in defense of the rights of Indians are based o n an (Lisas, is a natural characteristic of man, for only w h e n accompanied by other
anthropological-philosophical concept of the h u m a n being. This notion of people can he fulfill his needs. According to Las Casas, "all that is vital to
person results from his use of Aristotelian-Thomist philosophy and Christian h u m a n nature is naturally convenient to man." 3 1
thought. M a n is a composite of body and spiritual soul, and from this com- Religion is derived from all previous attributes. Las Casas is sure that m a n
posite there arises some essential qualities that bring with t h e m certain rights
and duties. This line of argument is consistently maintained in Las Casas's an- 26. "Todas las naciones del mundo son hombres, y de cada uno de ellos es una no
25
in.is la definition" Las Casas, Historia de las Indias, vol. 2, p. 396.
thropology, sociology, historiography, and philosophy of history. 27. This is one of the Thomistic theses Las Casas takes from Vitoria.
Las Casas bases man's attributes o n his bodily and spiritual composition. .',<S. R. J, Queralto Moreno, El pensamientofilosojko-politicode Bartolome de Las Casas
(Seville: Escuela de Estudios Hispano-Americanos, 1976), pp. 98ff.
29, Bartolome de Las Casas, Del unico modo de atraer a todos los pueblos a la verdadera
23. Lewis Hanke, Elprejuicio racial en el Nuevo Mundo (Mexico: SEP, 1974); Aristotle rtHgldn, ed, A. Millares Carlo (Mexico: FCE, 1942), pp. 28-29.
and the American Indians: A Study in Race Prejudice in the Modern World, Bloomington, Ind.: 10. "Desde el principio el genero humano, todos los hombres, todas las tierras y
Indiana University Press, 1970; and Mauricio Beuchot, "El primer planteamiento inil.is las olras cosas, por derecho natural y de gentes, fueron libres y alodiales, o sea,
teologico-juridico sobre la conquista de America: John Mair o Major," Ciencia Tomista 11.int.is y no sujetas a servidumbre. En cuanto al hombre se demuestra, porque desde el
103 (1976): 213-30. i ii ij'.ni de la naturaleza hurnana racional todos los seres humanos nacian libres. Puesto
24. "[E]l Filosofo era un gentil y esta ardiendo en los infiernos, y por ende tanto se i]UC siendo todos los hombres de igual naturaleza, no hizo Dios a un hombre siervo,
ha de usar su doctrina, cuanto con nuestra fe y costumbres de la religion catolica con- •iliici que a todos concedio Identica libertad." Bartolome de Las Casas, De regia potestate o
viniere" Bartolome de Las Casas, Historia de las Indias, vol. 3, ed. A. Millares Carlo Ikrccho dt autoditerminaddn, ed. L. Perefla (Madrid: CSIC, 1969), p. 16.
(Mexico: FCE, 1951), pp. 342H. 11. "|T|odo aquello sin ID cual no puede conscrvarse la naturaleza humana es natu-
25. H. Someda, "Bartolome de Las Casas como hisloriador," Studium 23 (1983): i.iiiiirnic convenlente .il hombre" Bartolome' <le Las Casas, Altjunosprincipios, in Trata-
137-45. ./,'v, ed, L ll.iiikc, J, Tudcl.i, .ind A. Millares Carlo, vol, 2 (Mexico: FCE, 1965), p. 1241.
30 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n C o l o n i a l M e x i c o Sixteenth Century: Humanists 31

is naturally inclined to religion. The search for truth is derived from rational- lo this word, demonstrating that the category of barbarian did not apply to
ity; the search for good is derived from freedom. From both of these, religion ihe Indians. In the exchange with Sepulveda, Las Casas proved himself to be
is derived, for religion is the search for the Ultimate Truth and for the .m able, talented, and rigorous thinker. 34 First, Las Casas showed that, given
Supreme Good, which is God. Natural reason by itself is not sufficient, and Ihe cruel and i n h u m a n e behavior of some Spaniards in their conquest of the
this is w h y revelation is necessary. The access to true faith is a right of man; Indies, the word 'barbaric' as understood by Sepulveda would be applicable
so, it follows that it is necessary to preach to the Indians. In all other aspects, to the behavior of the Spaniards as well. 35 If 'barbarian' is taken to refer to
Indians are h u m a n s in the same way as all the other peoples of the world. The I hose m e n w h o do not speak the same language as m e n from other towns or
existence of 'lesser' m e n would be a mistake of nature. And this would imply, who do n o t have their o w n language, t h e n we have a definition secundum
argues Las Casas, that nature is fundamentally wrong which in t u r n implies a quid (that is, some groups would fit this category only considered in relation
weakness of the Creator: "From which it necessarily follows that it is com- lo others). This provides, however, no legitimate right to impose slavery by
pletely impossible for one nation to be useless, or to have so little or such bar- means of the servi a natura argument. Finally, if 'barbarian' is taken to m e a n a
baric judgment, or to be lacking proper judgment, to such an extent that it is man of low instincts (cruel and ferocious), unable to govern himself, t h e n it is
unable to govern and cannot be inducted, brought to, and indoctrinated by legitimate to dominate h i m according to Aristotle's servi a natura principle.
an upstanding moral code, and thereby instructed in matters of faith and in- This last definition of 'barbarian' is precisely w h a t Sepulveda tried to show
fused with the Christian religion." 32 .uid what Las Casas fought to disprove. 36 According to Friar Bartolome, only
Therefore, the unity of the h u m a n race is essentially preserved, and there men lacking a soul are removed from any h u m a n essence and so fall outside
are only some accidental differences between peoples. These do not dissolve Ihe bounds of humanity. They are the exception to nature for nature errs
the basic unity of the h u m a n race but only show the heterogeneous condi- only in rare cases. These people are flawed because of a mistake of God. Las
tions in which h u m a n s live. In fact, all differences can be reduced to the unity i lasas writes, "Therefore, not all barbarians lack reason, nor are they natural
of fundamental equality; h u m a n duties and rights are the same for all m e n . slaves or unfit to govern themselves. For some barbarians naturally and justly
11. i ve kingdoms with jurisdictions and good laws and their reign is a legitimate
The philosophical anthropology of Las Casas political system." 37 Insofar as he denies that barbarians should be violently
in his debate with Sepulveda persecuted like savage animals, Las Casas distances himself from Aristotle's
At a conference in Valladolid in 1550, Las Casas took advantage of the con- position. He maintains, as Christ preached, that even the barbarians should
vocation of theologians called by Charles V to oppose Sepulveda and use his he attracted to natural order.
anthropological-philosophical ideas to defend the Indians against the charge Barbarism was also defined so as to include those w h o were not Christian.
of barbarism." Following Aristotle, Sepulveda argued that the Indians were These barbarians lack of knowledge revealed that they simply were n o t ac-
natural barbarians and thus had to be protected under the tutelage of the quainted with moral customs and political systems. But Las Casas argued that
Spaniards. In exchange for this protection, the Indians would have to work for
t h e m as slaves. In order to avoid the simplistic Aristotelian argument of slav- 14. See Lewis Hanke, Uno es todo el genero humano. Bstudio acerca de la querella que
'/>/'<' la capacidad intelectual y religiosa de los indigenas amerkanos sotuvieron en 1550 Bar-
ery or of the servi a natura, Las Casas wanted the term 'barbarians' to be prop- •lonte de Las Casas y Juan Gines de Sepulveda (Chiapas, Mexico: Gobierno Institucional
erly understood, and he pointed out four types or meanings that Aristotle gave el Estado, 1974), pp. 83-123; and All Mankind Is One: A Study on the Disputation between
ariolomi de las Casas and Juan Gines de Sepulveda in 1550 on the Intellectual and Religious
tipacity of the American Indians, (DeKalb: Northern Illinois University Press, 1974), pp.
32. "De lo cual se sigue necesariamente ser imposble de toda imposibilidad que una I 112.
nacion toda sea inhabil o tan de poco y barbarisimo juicio y de baja y apocada razon 15. Bartolome de las Casas, Apologia, ed. A. Losada (Madrid: Nacional, 1975), pp.
que no sepa gobernar y no pueda ser inducida y traida y adoctrinada en cualquier 'I 43. Cf. Poole, In Defense, p. 29 and pp. 41^19.
buena doctrina moral, y mayormente instruida en las cosas de la fe e imbuida en la re- 16. Las Casas, ApologHtka, pp. 436-37. Cf. Poole, InDefense, pp. 11-53.
ligion cristiana." Bartolome de Las Casas, Apologetka historic! sumaria, ed. E. O'Gorman, 17. "Por lo tamo, no lodos los barbaros carecen de razon ni son siervos por natu-
vol. 1 (Mexico: UNAM, 1967), p. 167. Cf. Bartolome de Las Casas, In Defense of the Indi- iliv.i o indignos de gobcrnarse a si mismos. Luego algunos barbaros justamente y por
ans, trans. Stafford Poole (DeKalb, 111.: Northern Illinois University Press, 1992). rituraleza tlenen relnos y dignldades teales, jurlsdlcdones y leyes buenas y su regimen
33. Queralto Moreno, Elpensamientofilosiijko-polflico, p. 1 16. nlltlco es legitime)." I ..is C.IS.IS, Apologia, p. 1 14. Poole, In Defense, p. 42.
32 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n C o l o n i a l M e x i c o Sixteenth Century: Humanists 33

the Indians could n o t be blamed for being unfamiliar with Christianity. oiher" 41 Las Casas focuses o n the social aspects of justice, t h a t is, on distribu-
Therefore, they should be brought into the faith without violence and with (ive and legal or general justice because commutative justice only considers
love. Las Casas demonstrated that the Indians were not people of low in- I lie individual.
stincts, unable and unfit to govern themselves. Therefore, the Spaniards From this concept of justice, it follows that an injustice takes place in each
could not legitimately argue that the Indians were, by nature, slaves. of the following cases: (1) w h e n , according to t h e current social order, a law
is broken; (2) w h e n a law that was abided by in the past, b u t is n o longer en-
Social philosophy and the philosophy of history forced, is abided by; and (3) w h e n a law that is not only inapplicable n o w but
Bartolome de Las Casas extended his philosophical ideas to social philoso- I hat goes against t h e current order is followed (this injustice is t h e most
phy. He examined ideas within their historical contexts and viewed society as severe). 42
a n unfolding process. In t h e beginning, races passed t h r o u g h stages of bar- According to Las Casas, w e find examples of all three types of injustices in
barism until they began to develop into civilizations. According to Las Casas, 11ic conquest of t h e Americas. First, the natural law which required Span-
we cannot at any stage speak of complete barbarism, only of degrees of it. iards to respect the freedom of Indians was not followed. Second, inapplica-
Gradually, these groups of people acquire the three degrees of prudence that ble laws were followed; this is w h y Las Casas insisted u p o n the reformation
Aristotle describes as monastic prudence, economic prudence, and political nl ihe laws of the Indies. Third, unjust laws were followed (unjust because
prudence. These correspond to the three stages in the development of civi- I I icy violated the a u t o n o m y of the Indians), a fact denounce d by m a n y mis-
lization. The first stage of this development is the individual, the second is the .icinaries.43
domestic or private stage, and the third is the social stage. 38 Some countries
have helped others in this process of development; this must always be done Mights and liberties
without violence and domination. Las Casas contends that the Spanish had Friar Bartolome's legal-political philosophy finds expression in De regia
rights over the development of Indian society only in the sphere of religious potestate.** In this work, he shows that current law establishes the state based
conversion; they h a d n o right to dominate the Indians. 39 According to him, on natural law; therefore, current law will only sanction and obey natural
the seed of faith is planted in each Indian town, and the Indians only have to l.iw. The first thing to appear as a natural right is the original freedom of
be led to the perfection of this faith; the Spanish should lead t h e m with care h u m a n beings. M a n is free, by nature or essence, and he can only lose his
and love. 40 freedom (for example, w h e n he becomes a slave) by accident: " . . . freedom
h.is been an inherent right of man, due to his rational nature, and that is w h y
Philosophical anthropology and the philosophy of law: II is a natural right. . . . That is w h y slavery does not have its origin in natural
human rights hui in accidental causes; that is, because it has been imposed or made a law." 45
Taking h u m a n nature as a base, Las Casas (as Vitoria and other Thomists According to the right to freedom m a n has had from the beginning, infe-
had done before) postulated a ius naturae or natural law u p o n which current rlor things are subject to him, and, as inferior things are allodial, m a n has the
law is based and whic h should be respected by current law. 7MS naturae corre-
sponded to iustitia, that is, justice, legal or general, that presents itself as com- •11. "|D]ary conservar en su derecho al otro" Las Casas, Del tinico modo de atraer, p. 514.
4 2. E. Ruiz Maldonado, "La justicia en la obra de fray Bartolome de las Casas," in
mutative and distributive. Within this tradition, Las Casas understood law in / Ibro Arnialdel 1SEE, vol. 4, pt. 2 (1974-1975): p. 16ff.
terms of order. Justice was understood in terms of the virtue which com- I). B. Ruiz Maldonado, "El Cardenal Cisneros, Bartolome de las Casas y la reforma
<lc Indias," in Libro AnualdelISEE, vol. 4, pt. 2 (1974-1975): pp. 119-34.
mands one to give all other people their due; justice orders man's acts accord- It. V. 1). Carro, Los postulates teologico-jurtdicos de Bartolome de las Casas. Sus aciertos,
ing to the rights of all other men, in "giving and conserving the rights of the tm olvidos y sus falias, ante los maestros Francisco de Vitoria y Domingo de Soto (Seville: Es-
i in-l.i de Bstudios Hispanoamericanos/CSIC, 1966), p. 3Iff.
•IV " . . . la libertad es un derecho inherente al hombre necesariamente y desde el
38. Las Casas, Apologetica, chap. 195-96; also Silvio Zavala, La defensa de los derechos prlnclplo de la naluialc/a rational, es por eso de derecho natural. . . . Por eso la esclav-
del hombre en America Latina, (Mexico: UNAM-UNESCO, 1982), pp. 30-40. liinl ile suyo no tiene origen en causas nalurales, sino accidentales; es decir, por haber
39. Las Casas, tinico tnodo de atraer, p. 92. .idi i Implies!,! i) en villi nl lie una lijiura jun'iliea" Las Casas, De regia potestate, p. 17.
40. Qucrallo Moreno, PewamlmtO jilosofico-polttico, pp. 102-3.
34 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Humanists 35

right to occupy them by possessing them. The first man who uses or occupies rulers. As this is a constitutional pact, no freedom is lost upon entering into
things has the right to possess them. Therefore, by the right of the first man il .*' If the ruler betrays the pact in any way, power returns to the people. This
who occupies (ius primi occupantis), men have their kingdoms and obtain ter- is one way to control the abuse of power. Finally, just as each man is free, so is
ritory for their countries. each community independent, having the right to self-rule.50
But groups only become states when they organize the political power that The common good is society's goal, and a ruler must seek this by the distri-
will have the authority to govern. When men are gathered within a society, bution of justice, and here current law and natural law meet: "Any spiritual
they cannot be left to act randomly. The social community has to be organized or temporal governor, of any group of free men, is obliged to order his regime
as a political community. An authority is necessary so that men reach their according to a common good and to govern according to this."51 The last
goal, that is, society's goal, which is human perfection in all respects. And so- clause, "en cuanto a ella misma" ("according to itself"), has a parallel in "ac-
ciety is there to ensure that men do not seek only their private benefit but also cording to its nature," that is, according to natural law. Las Casas sees author-
the common good.46 Consequently, natural right involves subjecting oneself 11 y only as a part of society (the whole to which it is subordinated). Authority
to authority. This subjugation is one of the fundamental rights of man. orders the common good, which results in the spiritual and material refine-
A ruler receives his authority from the people who elect him. Thus, if a ment of the community.
ruler opposes the people, he loses the authority the people gave to him. The The common good and justice share a relation of reciprocity. Through this
theoretical root of this fact is that no man is freer or by nature in possession of i elation, social balance and harmony are established.52 Justice produces peace
more authority than another one. Democracy is therefore a fundamental iJuit makes the pursuit of happiness possible. The demands of justice require
right of man. If there be a monarchy, it must be an elective one: "We say that dial jobs and responsibilities be distributed in a balanced manner. Following
the king is the one to whom the supreme power and authority of the govern- Aristotle, Las Casas proposes the following classification of these: peasants,
ment has been given by the people of the town, community, or kingdom."47 .ulisans, soldiers, traders, priests, and judges.

Freedom and democratic or popular authority Hifilice and the rights of man
Thus, authority's only origin is the people's vote. A governor is given Justice becomes concrete in a legal corpus or public law, that is, in laws
enough authority to govern, but he will never have more authority than the '..iiiitioned by the people's consensus, either in a direct or in an indirect way.
people, even though they are subordinated to him. In this way, the people A ruler governor is subject to those laws, and this is why he is not alone in
form the legislative and juridical structure of the regime.48 Clearly, according dictating the laws, but rather he must take the needs and wants of the people
to Las Casas's principles, a republican regime would be favored over and Into account. Justice and law are the same in a certain way, but the first is ab-
against a monarchical one. ••i i ad and the second concrete. Law channels men's actions toward the com-
Jurisdictional power rests with the people; a ruler has this only insofar as mon good and deters what is opposed to it. All individuals, even the ruler, are
he seeks the common good, and only under this condition is he authorized to •ailijecl to the law.53 With this, Las Casas sought what is called today "state of
formulate laws. Justice must always be in accordance with the common law," in which the instrument for the people to communicate with the ruler
good, and the common good, in turn, must accord with human nature. Thus, i •. i lie referendum.54 Freedom is the summum of political society. For Las Casas,
current law is based upon natural law. At the level of the people's law, which
is essentially sanctioned natural law, there is a pact between subjects and 49. Ibid., pp. 34-35.
10, On Ihis analogy between the citizen's rights and the state's rights, see Luciano
i'i irn.i Vicente, La carta de los derechos humanos segun Bartolome de Las Casas (Guatemala:
46. Las Casas, "Tratado comprobatorio delimperio soberano," in Tratados, vol. 2, pp. vento de Santo Domingo, 1978), pp. lOff.
1065-66. 11. "Ttodo Jefe esplrltual o temporal de cualquier multitud de hombres libres esta
47. "Aquel decimos ser rey a quien la suprema potestad y jurisdiction del gobierno ii!il!}(ado .1 Ordenar su regimen al (in de la multitud [that is to say, to common good], y
es cometida por el pueblo o comunidad o reino" Las Casas, "Tratado de las docc dudas," i Holiernarla en cuanto a ella misma." Las Casas, Tratados, vol. 2, p. 1257.
in Obras escogidas, ed. J. Perez de Tudela Bueso and E. Lopez Oto, vol. 5 (Madrid: UAH, •' i..is Casas, ApologCtica, vol. I, i>. 155.
1956), p. 487. •> i Las Casas, Deregla potestate, p, 17,
48. Las Casas, De regia potentate, p, 54. • I [bid., p, 53,
36 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Humanists 37

not even the Christian faith is obligatory.55 He expresses the need for material Quiroga studied law, probably at the University of Salamanca, and he be-
freedom: although goods were originally for everybody, man is at liberty to came a canon lawyer in 1515. He practiced law until 1530 in Valladolid and
possess and have his own private property.56 worked in the court there. Later he was called to serve the court of Mexico.
Something similar happens with nations. A kingdom is inalienable as a This was the second court (chronologically) that had been formed in Mexico;
whole and in its parts. The ruler cannot give away the country, or a single city, the first had not functioned properly.
or the goods of the people.57 For that reason the king could not concede hold- Quiroga arrived in Veracruz in 1531 and wrote his famous letter concern-
ings in America to the 'trustees' because that would have meant handing out ing the social experiment of the hospitals of Santa Fe. He was a dedicated
territory, or, at least, the goods of Indians. When a ruler becomes a dictator, judge of the court, and he tried to reform it so that the second court of Mexico
he acts against the common good of the people and thereby loses his author- would not have to be replaced as the first one had been. His ideas on justice
ity ipso facto. In such a case, the people must oppose him, and, given the op- and humanism can be found in his Information en Derecho (1535). In this work
portunity, remove him from power.58 According to the teachings of Aquinas, he discusses issues related to conquest, colonization, and evangelization.62
laws should evolve at the same rate as the social and political history of the In 1538, Quiroga was elected Bishop of Michoacan, and on January 16,
community. Las Casas believed that in the same way that it is possible to cor- 1539, he took possession of his see. Friar Juan de Zumarraga consecrated him
rect, adapt, or revise a law; it is possible to resist a tyrant.59 at the end of 1538 and also conferred upon him successively all of the clerical
Las Casas became interested in anthropology and sociology in order to de- degrees. Quiroga began his work at Tzintzuntzan and then went on to
velop a doctrine of freedom. Las Casas was a champion in the struggle for jus- Patzcuaro, eventually taking this as his definite see. Quiroga's activities dem-
tice and the defense of human rights (most definitely evident in the case of the onstrate a devotion to social work. In 1543, he founded the Hospital of Santa
Indians).60 He developed a doctrine of freedom that integrated anthropology Marta. This was the first in a series of planned communities, communities or-
and sociology, creating a philosophy intended to protect the dignity of man. dered according to Quiroga's humanitarian ideals. In connection with the
community of Santa Maria, he began the construction of the Cathedral of
Vasco de Quiroga Santa Maria, a very ambitious architectural project. The cathedral was to be
built in the shape of a hand, with five naves, one for each principal language.
Vasco (or Basco) de Quiroga was born in Madrigal de las Altas Torres, The city itself was planned as the fusion of two races, Indian and Spanish. It
Spain. While his date of birth is unknown, and despite one conjecture that was to be a social experiment intended to examine the results of such a fu-
marks 1470 as the year of his birth, we know that he died in 1568, and it is sion, i.e., the mestizaje. This proposal was so radical that the Viceroy of Men-
unlikely that he could have lived 95 years. Recent studies show that this birth doza opposed it and even ordered two cities built instead of one, a different
date does not correspond with his activities in New Spain and that it is more one for each race. Later Quiroga founded the College of San Nicolas for the
likely that he was born in the late 1480s.61 education of priests, thereby anticipating the idea of the seminary. Quiroga
knew several indigenous languages and translated some religious texts from
55. E. Ruiz Maldonado, "Proselitismo cristiano, libertad religiosa y justicia en la
obra de Bartolome de las Casas," Christus 469 (1974): 32-45.
the languages used at the college. Quiroga also founded a school for girls, and
56. Perefia Vicente, La carta de los derechos humanos, pp. 10-11. some other schools, both for children and adults.63
57. Las Casas, De regia potestate, pp. 58-59. This line of argument was used by the In 1543, Quiroga left for Europe to attend the Council of Trent, but strong
theorists of American independence, such as Friar Servando Teresa de Mier.
58. Las Casas, "Tratado de las doce dudas,"in Obrasescogidas, vol. 5, pp. 506 and 511. storms forced him to return. He began the trip again in 1547 and this time
59. Bartolome de Las Casas, "Memorial al rey (1543)," in Obras escogidas, vol. 5, p. reached Spain. Once there, he became active in the debates going on in Val-
198. Aquinas deals with the problem of the evolution of law in Summa Theologiae, I-II,
q. 97, a. 1. ladolid concerning the rights of Indians. He opposed Bartolome de Las Casas's
60. A. Lobato, "Dignidad del hombre y derechos humanos en Fray Bartolome de las
Casas y en la doctrina actual de la iglesia," Communio 18 (1985): 59-81.
62. P. B. Warren, Vasco de Quiroga y sus hospitales-pueblo de Santa Fe (Morelia, Mexico:
61. Francisco Miranda, "Vasco de Quiroga, artifice humanisla do Michoacan," in tiiiivcisid.nl Mlchoacana, 1977).
Humanismo y ciencia en la formacion de Mexico, ed. C. Hcrrojcin Pcredo (Zamora, (i t. R. Vilklez, Hslmlio sociopedagogico de In obra educativa de don Vasco de Quiroiia (Mcx-
Mexico: El Colegio de Michoacan, 1984), p. 1 33. Ico: n.p., 1975).
38 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o S i x t e e n t h Century: H u m a n i s t s 39

position and voted in favor of granting p e r m a n e n t territory rights to the principal function of the hospital-towns was to provide social welfare and
Spanish in the Indies. Francisco Miranda comments: eductional training. Vestiges of these programs remain in Michoacan today.
Silvio Zavala observes that "regarding the hospital-towns, Mexican historians
Concerning the concession which he had to express in the meetings of Val-
ladolid of 1550 (where the king gathered the most lucid people of his universi- agree that their development was felicitous. In his testament of 1565, Quiroga
ties and those whom, due to their experience and education, he considered ca- expressed satisfaction with their progress; in the eighteenth century, Moreno
pable of helping him to understand the problems), Don Vasco's opinion was referred to their enduring presence; and in the nineteenth century, Riva Pala-
different than Bartolome de las Casas's. Las Casas sought the complete separa- cio remarks u p o n the veneration that the Bishop still holds a m o ng the Mi-
tion of the indigenous people within the new society that was being formed in
choacan Indians, and Leon mentions the subsistence of the hosptial project." 65
the Indies. Using the human body as a metaphor for the state, Don Vasco
claimed that it was impossible to separate Indians and Spaniards. He compared A closer examination of the social context within which such programs
the Spaniards to the skeleton of the body, that is, the underlying structure of arose merits closer investigation. The hospital-towns were the result of an
the body; the Indians were the flesh, the protective covering for the underlying ideal of liberation. Quiroga's hospital-towns were part of a remaining ten-
structure. Just as the human body needs both skeleton and flesh, the new soci- dency in Latin American thought, namely, the philosophy of liberation.
ety needs both Spaniards and Indians. 64

Social-philosophical ideas of Quiroga


Because Friar Alonso de la Vera Cruz had agreed to serve as Vicar in Mi-
choacan, Quiroga was able to remain in Europe until 1553. During that time, The liberation of the Indians was a major t h e m e of Quiroga's work. In In-

he wrote about the Indians. He wanted those in positions of power, especially formation en derecho, Quiroga opposes the enslavement of the Indians. 66 He ar-

the pope, to make informed decisions with respect to the colonies. Only a few gues that the war to enslave the Indians was unfair. 67 Based u p o n Cayetano's

of the documents he composed have been recovered. During his stay in classification system, Quiroga claims that these infidels did not fall u n d e r the

Spain, Quiroga established contact with Saint Ignatius of Loyola and urged Christian king's dominion. Cayetano distinguished three groups of infidels:

h i m to send Jesuits to Mexico. (1) those w h o are Christian subjects by right and in fact; for example, the

In 1554, Quiroga returned to his see in Patzcuaro, Michoacan, remaining .lews and Moors living in Christian lands; (2) those w h o are Christian subjects

there until his death in 1565. He devoted his energies to the realization of his by right but not in fact; for example, the infidels w h o occupy lands they have

humanitiarian vision; that is, establishing hospitals and centers of training for taken away from Christians, for example the Muslims w h o occupied parts of

Indians. In 1555, he attended the first Mexican Provincial Council, where h e Spain; and (3) those w h o are not Christian subjects by right, e.g., those living

obtained permits for the construction of hospitals next to each town's church. in lands that have never belonged to Christians. 68 According to Quiroga, Indi-

He printed a catechism, promoted education, enhanced craftworks, and orga- ans belong to the third group. Therefore, it is unjust to fight against and en-

nized markets. Actively engaged in this social work, he died suddenly in Uru- slave them.

apan, o n 14 March, 1565. Quiroga maintained that the only fact that could justify a war against the

It is difficult to k n o w exactly h o w long t h e hospital-towns lasted. The Indians was their resistance to the preaching of the Gospels or an y actions

64. "Referente a su opinion sobre las encomiendas que le toca expresar en las jun- 65. "Por lo que respecta a la suerte de los hospitales-pueblo, los historiadores mexi-
tas de Valladolid de 1550, en las que el rey coiigrega a las gentes mas lucidas de sus uni- canos aceptan comunmente un desarrallo feliz; Quiroga, el primero, se mostraba satis-
versidades y a quienes cree capaces de ayudar a entender la problematica por su expe- fecho de su marcha en el testamento de 1565; en el siglo XVIII, habia Moreno de su
riencia y luces, difiere su idea de la opinion expresada por Bartolome de las Casas, perduracion; Riva Palacio admitfa en el siglo XIX la veneration de que gozaba aiin el
quien buscaba en el fondo la separation total de los indigenas dentro de la nueva so- nombre del obispo entre los indios michoacanos; Leon, liltimamente, habia con entusi-
ciedad que se iba fincando en Indias. Para Quiroga, utilizando el simil del cuerpo hu- iismo de la subsistencia de las lundaciones." Silvio Zavala, "La Utopia de Tomas Moro en
m a n e indios y espafioles como elementos de la nueva sociedad era imposible separar- l.i Nueva Espana," p. 21.
los ya; habia que favorecer el que cada uno jugara su propio papel y en su realismo ve 66. Vasco de Quiroga, Informacidn en derecho . . . sobre algunas provisiones del real Con-
la conveniencia de que tomaran los espafioles el papel rector, pero que a la inancra del sejo de Indias, ed. C. Herrejon Peredo (Mexico: SEP, 1985).
cuerpo humane ellos constituyeran el esqueleto, siendo capaces de dnr la estructura del 67. Ibid., pp. 68 II.
mismo, guardados y sustentados por los indigenas, a mancra de la came en el cuerpo <>8. T. de Vio C,irdin.il C.iyriano, In Summam Thcoloijiaim Divi Tlwmae, Romae, II-II,
humano." Miranda, "Vasco de Quiroga," pp. 142-43. q (.(., ,i. 8.
40 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o S i x t e e n t h Century: H u m a n i s t s 41

that endangered such preaching. It was, therefore, legitimate to wage war most importantly, an Indian mayor or tacatecle. A Spanish mayor w h o pos-
against the Indians because the government which had been in power before sessed m o re power t h a n all of these would represent the Royal Court, which,
the arrival of the Spaniards had been a government resistant to such preach- in turn, would represent the Spanish Throne, 7 2 Despite the fact that the
ing. According to Quiroga, there is a right (and even the obligation) to preach weight of power remained with the Spanish, this plan was never accepted.
the Gospels to the Indians, because this was the best doctrine t h e y could be Quiroga proposed a mixed government because, like Bartolome de Las
taught; and if they were opposed to such preaching or made it difficult, the Casas, h e felt that Indians had the right to rule over their land. Of t h e Indians,
Spanish were justified in their use of violence against the Indians. Violence Quiroga writes:
should always be a last resort; the preaching of the Gospels should be done
They were in almost the same state, way, and condition; not only concerning
persuasively and peacefully. But violence could be used against any regime
slaves but also the election of caciques, the men or principals who were to be
opposed to this peaceful preaching. Any regime that pursued violence against chosen; also for them being content with the little they possessed, the same ap-
the preachers of Christianity deserved violence. Following and applying plies today, although it is little, without concerning themselves of tomorrow;
Cayetano's logic, Quiroga argued that this was the case with the Indians. they had a healthy contempt and lack of interest for the things so desired and
adored in our mixed up world, the things of our world, with all the ambition,
Their regime did not permit the preaching of Christianity and so violence
the arrogance, the pomp, the vainglory, the hustle and bustle. We can clearly
against t h e m was justified. The Indian government is s h o w n to be tyrannical
see that they are not used, nor ruled, nor accustomed to this New World, but to
rather t h a n just, and, therefore, it is illegitimate. A war to liberate the Indians my way of seeing it, those people see our mixed up world of iron, steel, and
from this unjust government was justified. In fact, only if these governments things even worse. . . . "
were attacked and overthrown could the Indians be liberated.
Because Indians violently opposed the preaching of Christian doctrines, In order to m a k e a connection betwee n the Golden Age and his view of

Quiroga saw the war against t h e m as a means of pacifying them, 6 9 not as a way the position of Indians in New Spain, Quiroga cites at length passages from

to destroy them. Therefore, h e denounced and fought against the way the Lucian's Saturnales.7* He w a n t e d to establish a government for Indians that

conquest was realized. Moreover, he insisted that it was not legitimate to ini- would liberate t h e m and lead t h e m to a mor e prosperous and happ y life. In

tiate a war to implement slavery. Once again, following Cayetano,™ he says, this way, the traps of corruption into which the Spanish had fallen would be

"And of these unfaithful subjects: these Christian slaves should be freed by avoided. This n e w government would be purer and better t h a n anything be-

competent judges, better still it seems that the ones w h o are already faithful fore it, a model for t h e m u c h - n e e d e d reformation of t h e Church. Quiroga's

subjects can and should be freed; for it is worse that the faithful are oppressed humanist ideas pervaded all areas of his reformist thought, religious as well as

t h a n the barbarous and unfaithful ones: there can be nothing m o re precious political. Convinced by Thomas More's Utopia, Quiroga was certain that his

for the free m a n t h a n having freedom." 71 humanist ideals could be realized.

Vasco de Quiroga proposed, for the good of the Indians and the Spanish, a Quiroga explicitly stated that More was inspired by Lucian's Saturnaks. He

mixed policy in which material and spiritual aspects of society were shared by believed that More had used the customs presented by Lucian as a kind of

both the Indians and the Spanish. That is, there would be indigenous juries of
72. Ibid., pp. 168, 175, arid 206.
about thirty families; indigenous councils, with about four jury members; and 73. "[C]uasi el mismo estado y manera y condition; no solamente en esto de los
siervos, pero aun en la election de los caciques o senores o principales que elegian, y
69. Quiroga bases this point on Chancellor Juan Gerson. See C. Herrejon Peredo, t.unliien con el mismo contentarse con poco, y con lo de hoy, aunque sea poco, sin ser
"Fuentes patristicas, juridicas y escolasticas del pensamiento quiroguiano," in Textos solfcitos por lo de manana, y con un muy buen menosprecio y olvido de todas las otras
politicos en la Nueva Espaha (Mexico: UNAM, 1984), p. 170. cosas tan queridas y deseadas y cobdiciadas deste nuestro revoltoso mundo, cuanto por
70. Cayetano, In Summam Theologicam, II-II, q. 16, a. 8. ellos olvidadas y menospreciadas en este dorado suyo, con todas las cobdicias, ambi-
71. "Y si de los infieles siibditos esos tales siervos cristianos opresos se pueden quitar i lones, soberbias, faustos, vanaglorias, trafago y congojas de el; que claramente vemos
por jueces competentes, con mayor razon parece que se podrian y deberfan quilar de los que no hay ni se usan ni reinan ni se acostumbran entre estos naturales en este mundo
que ya son siibditos fieles; pues mas prohibido es a los fieles tener cosa opresa y mal nuevo, y a mi ver, edad dorada entre ellos, que ya es vuelta entre nosotros de hierro y
habida, que no al barbaro e inflel, mayormente libertad de hombrc librc, que dc pre- dc acero y peor " ibid., pp. 188-89.
ciosa no se puede estimar." Quiroga, Informacidn en derecho, p. 140. 74. R, Vill.isciior, "Luciano, Mom y el utopismo de Vasco de Quiroga," Cuadernos
Americana i (1942) 155-75.
42 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n C o l o n i a l M e x i c o Sixteenth Century: Humanists 43

model for the laws and order of his Utopia. Quiroga w a r n e d that several mea- w h y agriculture was to become a main occupation in t h e hospitals. There h a d
sures would have to be taken so that Indians would not remain tied to an aus- to be a daily work schedule of six hours. Goods h a d to be shared. We find ref-
tere way of life but would be attracted by the promises of material wealth. erences to these regulations in Quiroga's Reglas y ordenanzas, as well as in
Building u p o n the Indian's virtues of humility, simplicity, and gentleness, other writings.
Quiroga h o p e d to lead t h e Indians to value material prosperity withou t for- All t h e people would work according to their strength a n d health, and t h e
saking moderation. This hope was tied to another, that of developing in Indi- distribution of goods would be according to the needs of each member : "So
ans the value of work. Quiroga claimed that, because Indians were content that the result from the daily six h o u r s ' labor has to be apportioned a m o n g all
with little, they were n o t industrious and did not like work. But they were the people; and each of t h e m will get, according to his needs, w h a t is neces-
not lazy; they only needed to be taught the value of work. Quiroga's goal was sary for h i m and his family to live comfortably, so that n o one in the Hospital
to motivate Indians to work diligently and to combine this with their disdain lacks anything." 7 7
for luxuries; effectively, Quiroga w a n t e d to create a Christian community for With the moderate work of the community, there would be abundance
75
Indians like those of the earliest times. even for those w h o could not work. And this work and abundance would be
a service and a celebration of God. In order that only those w h o lived in the
The hospitals and social security community could m a k e use of the land and that this land could n o t be sold to
Quiroga's hospital-towns m a d e h i m a celebrated figure. According to Mi- those w h o did n o t live within the community, Quiroga added rules for t h e
randa, Quiroga believed that use of garden plots. Garden plots could only be cultivated by those w h o h a d
duly received them. The aim of this system was to ensure that the inhabitants
[t]he institution of the hospital had the Virgin Mary's (Nana Wari Yurishu) cult as
its justification, and the whole community was organized around this cult; it was could live free of danger and vice (laziness, ignorance, etc.), while pursuing a
a brotherhood in which all participated; it was the most important source of so- life of integrity and wisdom in a communal spirit, a life according to Christian
cial aid, taking care of the ill, providing burial for the dead, shelter for the pil- doctrine.
grims, and help to the needy (orphans, widows, and poor people). The whole
With the Doctrina he had written and printed and which had received the
community constantly increased the hospital's funds thereby allowing for a cer-
pope's approval, Quiroga wished to teach his pupils the Gospels and the
tain splendor in the festivities. Moreover, this fund and the work of the members
of the brotherhood provided the community with economic resources; these in virtue of prudence. He took advantage of the natural virtues of Indians and
turn were in need of control which the ecclesiastic authorities provided."76 encouraged t h e m to abandon any vices they might have, such as laziness.
Quiroga writes, "[i]n taking away the evil, and keeping the good of your cus-
The hospital project was practical insofar as it had social goals, and it was toms, ways, and circumstances, like in all good p r u d e n t policy which should
liberating insofar as one of its major goals was to aid in the establishment of be given to people like you: you must attempt, according to the quality, m a n -
the self-sufficiency of Indians. Guiding this liberating, practical work was a ner, condition, mistakes, needs, and capacity of the people to w h o m it is
theoretical base expressed in the humanist and Utopian ideal. The hospitals given, to keep t h e m in good condition, without destroying their characters,
were conceived as part of something 'natural' or as a return to nature; that is or changing t h e m for something different, which could possibly be evil rather
I b a n good for them." 7 8
75. Quiroga, Information en derecho, p. 201. See also Nicolas Leon, Don Vasco de
Quiroga. Grandeza de su persona y su obra (Morelia, Mexico: Universidad Michoacana de
San Nicolas de Hidalgo, 1984), pp. 139if. 77. "Item lo que asi de las dichas seis horas del trabajo en comrm como dicho es, se
76. "Era el hospital una institution que tenia como justificative el culto a la Virgen hubiere, despues de asi habido, y cogido, se reparta entre vosotros todos, y cada uno de
Maria, Nana Wari Yurishi, y en torno a este culto se organizaba la comunidad, una vos en particular aeque congrua, comoda y honestamente, segiin que cada uno, segun
cofradia de la que formaba parte todos; se preocupaba de cuidar los aspectos asisten- sn calidad, y necesidad, manera, y condition lo haya menester para si, y para su familia,
ciales mas importantes, asi fuera la atencion a los enfermos, el entierro de los muertos, de manera, que ninguno padezca en el Hospital necesidad." Vasco de Quiroga, "Reglas
la acogida a los peregrinos o la ayude a los menesterosas; huerfanos, viudas y pobres. y ordenanzas para el gobierno de los hospitales de Santa Fe de Mexico y Michoacah,"
La comunidad toda incrementaba constantemente los fondos del hospital que daban In Vasco de Quiroga: educador de adultos, ed. Francisco Miranda and G. Briseno (Patzcuaro,
esplendor a la celebration de las fiestas y que contando con el trabajo de los confrades, Mlclto.iciii, Mexico: CRIil'AI./Colcgio de Michoacan, 1984), p. H5.
constimfan siempre im recurso importanlc en la ceononii'.i clc la coimmidad que cxigt'ii 78. "[Qjuitindoos lo malo, y dcxahdoos In bueno de vuestras cost timbres, manera y
vigilancia y control de las atiloridadcs cclcsiaslicas para qui' no se l,i apropiaran los am < licidii, como en toda biieim pollefa, que <lc niievn se haya de d.u a person.is seme-
blciosos." Miranda, "Vasco de Quiroga," p. 147. j.inlrs, que de ell.i y de prudemin Ileum l.inl.i necesidad, como vosotms lenels, se tlehe
44 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Humanists 45

Quiroga also offered advice to parents within this social organization. He As Zavala has shown,80 Quiroga's Reglas y ordenanzas were inspired by
wanted children to be taught to work in the fields as if it were a game, so that Thomas More's Utopia. Going further, though, the Reglas y ordenanzas antici-
they would learn to do such tasks with happiness and would work joyfully pate social welfare as we know it today. Quiroga worked for the integral de-
one or two hours a day. He also requested that children learn to have a com- velopment of the town, where safety would be assured. This physical safety
munal sense and to be just in distributing the harvest. He insisted that girls be as well as the just distribution of goods would help to prevent problems asso-
taught the tasks proper to women. He established a system whereby younger ciated with orphans, old age, widowhood, unemployment, and overpopula-
members of the community served elders, for this taught the children to re- tion. The well-being and perfection of the individual would be obtained only
spect their elders and eliminated the need for servants. within this welfare system. According to Quiroga:
Quiroga goes on to describe the working details of the community. Build-
The hospital-towns impart physical, mental, and spiritual well-being: physical
ing and restoration would be an integral part of the community. There would health during a designated stay in a sick-room; mental health by a system of di-
always be more sown than necessary to ensure that there was enough for the versions and games, good usage of free time, holidays and adequate rest each
community in case the following year reaped a bad harvest. Dress would be week; spiritual health would be achieved through rest and tranquility, medita-
the same for all the people. There would be holidays in which relaxation and tion and the contemplation of the natural surroundings. Maintenance of
health through this division of activities helps to balance differences due to
rest were celebrated. Elections would be democratic and focused on the
gender, age, physical capacities, and sensibilities. The result is dynamic health,
virtues of those elected as heads of family, principals, rulers, etc. Justice both for the individual, as his circumstances dictate, and for the group and its
would be enforced by the rector and the rulers, so that there would be no specific needs. Don Vasco thought about a complete system because he divided
need of judges. All would proceed with love (caridad) as the guiding principle. health into certain fields, those of anatomic, physiological, mental, social, and
Quiroga insisted on hygiene, paying attention to physical as well as mental economic health which were all superimposed and amalgamated to create
man as a bio-psycho-social unit.81
health. Concerning the hospital, he says, "[f]or the sick there is shelter (the
house), or the large infirmary: it is two times larger than the place for the
What has been referred to as Quiroga's 'socialism' or 'communism' is per-
healthy. Inside the shelter for the sick, there is a room for those with contagious
haps more accurately called a sense of community (comunitarismo) because it
illnesses, and opposite this there is another room for those with illnesses that
really consists of community work accompanied by a highly developed sense
are not contagious. Between the two there is a chapel covered on either side
of social consciousness: "Quiroga looked for the creation of a better society.
with a highly decorated altar; this is where the masses are given. The other two
We can say, employing modern terms that were not used in his time, that his
rooms at the head of this building are for the mayor and medical dispensor of
the sick, who also occupy offices in this infirmary."79 A doctor, surgeon, and
pharmacist would be assigned to care for the sick. However, in order to empha- capilla cubierta por los dos lados, en que haya un altar adornado completamente,
donde se diga misa, y la puedan oir los enfermos, y las otras salas de cabeza, y pies sean
size the benefits and joy of membership in the community, festivals were to be para el Mayordomo, y Despensero de los dichos enfermos, y para tener las oficinas
held in the main hall to celebrate the society. In his Reglasy ordenanzas, Quiroga necesarias a la enfermerfa." Ibid.
80. Zavala, Utopia de TomdsMoro.
established expulsion from the hospital as the gravest punishment. 81. "En los 'hospitales-pueblo' se imparte salud. Salud fisica en la estancia especial
destinada para ello; salud mental dentro del regimen organizado en el que se planean
diversiones yjuegos, ocupacion del tiempo libre, vacaciones, descanso semanal; salud
hacer, y conviene se haga, que es, y ha de ser conforme a la calidad, y manera, y (•spiritual a traves del reposo y la tranquilidad, la meditation, el estudio contemplativo
condition de la gente a quienes se de, y segun sus faltas, calidad, y necesidades, y ca- de la naturaleza, salud porque se minimizan o restringen en extremo el sufrimiento y el
pacidad, conservandoles siempre lo bueno, que tenga, y no destmyendolo, ni trocan- dcsajuste al considerar los factores edad, sexo, capacidad fisica, preferencias afectivas,
doselos por lo que no les cuadra, ni conviene (segun suerte, y manera de vivir, en- en el reparto de las tareas profesionales. Salud dinamica, individual, de acuerdo con las
tendimiento, estado, y condition) y les sea a ellos mas danoso, que provechoso." Ibid., liiviinslancias que rigen la existencia de cada quien, y comunal, acumulativa en el
p. 138. grupo. La totalidad de los campos organicos esta abarcada, concentrada con una finali-
79. "Para los enfermos hay una familia [i.e., a house], o enfermeria grandc dad: la de que los terrenes analomico, fisiologico, mental, social, economico, se super-
cuadrada: dos veces mayor que las otras de los sanos, y algo apartada de ellas, en quo pongan y ainalgaiiicii, y al fundirse rescatan al hombre como unidad biopsicosocial." F.
en el un cuarto haya una sala grande para los enfermos de males contagiosos, y olra Cardenas de la Pefla, Vasco de Quiroga, precursor de Secjuridad Social (Mexico: Instituto
enfrente de ella para los de enfermedades no contagiosa*, y en medio del patio una Mi-xic,mo del Scgiiro Social, l'K>K), p. 1 ?2.
46 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Humanists 47

goal was to create a welfare state. He understood the process and put it into the obligation of the Spaniards to impose their culture upon the Indians, even
practice. The primary material consisted of individuals who found dignity in if violence is necessary.
work. A just social and human context was necessary in order to create a fin- The author of this treatise knew that Cajetan, Vitoria, Soto, and Las Casas
ished work from this raw material."82 had each claimed that, according to both the law of nations and natural
Clearly, the humanitarian enterprise of Quiroga had its roots in Renais- law, the Indians could not be dispossessed of their goods, especially if the
sance Christian humanism. Through Thomas More's Utopia, Quiroga learned Spaniards wanted to convert them. Therefore, the war against the Indians
about the 'golden age' portrayed in Lucian's Saturnales, and he applied what was unjust, because their goods justifiably belonged to them and the
he learned of the European 'golden age' to the Indian societies in the New Spaniards had no right to take them away. However, the author of this
World. Influenced by these ideas, Quiroga maintains that "the work to be treatise opposed these writers and made another assumption: Any power
done in the civilization of the New World consisted not simply in the transfer and kingdom, even a civil power, comes from the Church, and, therefore,
of old customs but also in the elevation of them from their natural simplicity Christ has the sovereign right to endow absolute power on the pope, his
to ideal levels of humanism and primitive Christianism. The instrument for representative on earth. As this power was transferred from the pope to
realizing such a task would be More's Utopia, whose laws were the most ade- the Spanish kings, the Spanish kings could justify their ownership of the
quate for the accomplishment of this enthusiastic project for the improvment Indies. Opposing Cayetano, who said that the Indians were not subject to
of man."83 the power of the Church and, therefore, could not be offered by the Papacy
to the Spanish kings, the author of the De debellandis treatise responded by
The question of the war of conquest against the Indians stating that only God and His Church had the right of power and, therefore,
There is one more aspect to consider in this account of Quiroga's ideas. In the pope was completely within his rights to offer the Indies to the Spanish
spite of his strong humanstic ideals, Quiroga supported the Spanish conquest. kings.
In his work, De debellandis indis,"4 a philosophic-theologic-legal treatise, we Furthermore, the author continues, there existed not only the right to at-
find his arguments in support of the legality of the war made by the Spaniards tack the Indians but also, under certain circumstances, even the duty to make
against the Indians. The ideas expressed in it differ radically from those ex- war against them. Because the Indians did not recognise the authority of the
pressed in Quiroga's other works; so much so that scholars such as Silvio Church, modern civilization, or the Gospels, the Spaniards had a duty to de-
Zavala do not think that Quiroga is the author of this work.85 Translated from clare war against them for purposes of reformation. There are two types of in-
the Latin, the title of the contested work reads: "On the war that should be fidels: those who recognize the power of the Church and hence should not be
brought against the Indians." The conclusion reached in the work is that it is attacked, and those who do not recognize such a power and thus are inca-
pable of having principalities and must be brought, even through violent
82. "Quiroga buscaba la construction de una sociedad mejor y valdria la pena, uti- means, to recognize the power of the Church.
lizando los terminos modernos que el no conocio, decir que su meta era conseguir la
seguridad social. Comprendia el proceso y lo puso en practica. La materia prima eran That such a document coufd be the work of Quiroga seems to be highly
los individuos que habfa que habituar a su propia dignidad por el trabajo, pero nece- questionable. After all, Quiroga, like Las Casas, had fought hard to defend the
sitaba el contexto social justo y humano para sacar de esa cera blanda la mejor ima-
gen." Francisco Miranda, "Vasco de Quiroga: precursor de la Seguridad Social," in Vasco
lights of Indians against the cruelty of the Spanish.86 His obedience to certain
de Quiroga: educador de adultos, ed. Miranda and Briseflo, p, 66. laws and practices led him to make war against the Indians but only in order to
83. "[L]a tarea de la civilizacion en el Nuevo Mundo ha de consistir no en la trans- put them in a position to understand and benefit from European civilization
ferencia de la vieja cultura a los pueblos descubiertos, sino en elevar estos, desde su
simplicidad natural, a las metas ideales del humanismo y del cristianismo primitive El
instrumento sera la Utopia de Moro, cuyas leyes son las mas adecuadas para encauzar '185-515; B. Biermann, "Don Vasco de Quiroga y su tratado de debellandis indis," Historia
esta obra entusiasta de mejoramiento del hombre" "Reglas y ordenanzas," n.p. Mcxkana 18 / 72 (1969): 6 i 5-22; Silvio Zavala, "En torno del tratado de debellandis indis
84. Vasco de Quiroga, De debellandis indis, ed. Rene Acuna (Mexico: UNAM, 1988). de Vasco de Quiroga," Historia Mexicana, 18 / 72 (1969): 623-26. Because the issue of
85. In his introduction of De debellandis indis, Rene Acuna gives the reasons lli.il Ihc work's authenticity has not yet been resolved, instead of speaking of Don Vasco as
urge him to present this treatise as the original of Don Vasco. Bui others express serious llie aulhor of lliis work, we refer simply to 'the author'.
doubts about this. Por that reason, one should see the work of Silvio Zavala, Tin bllSCI 86. Quiroga, InfomuuhUi en Ikreclio, passim; F. Man in Hernandez, "Don Vasco de
del tratado de debellandis indis de Vasco de Quiroga," Historia Mexiama 1 7 / 6 8 (1968): Quiroga, protector de ins indloi/" Salmantictnsis vi (1987): 61-85.
48 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Humanists 49

and the Gospels.87 Quiroga was essentially a defender of the Indians; his This tendency to combine the elements from both Plato's and Aristotle's
thought can be understood as a humanitarian and humanist philosophy thought is particularly evident in Hernandez's work on physics and ethics.
blended with his Christian ideals.
Natural philosophy

Francisco H e r n a n d e z Hernandez was an accomplished natural scientist who carried out biologi-
cal and medical research, and thus his interest in the works of Aristotle was
Francisco Hernandez, physician to Philip II, was born in Spain in 1518 and focused upon those aspects which dealt with physics and natural philosophy.
came to Mexico in 1570. He was commissioned by the king to complete some His work on Aristotle proceded by summarizing and discussing the problems
studies of the flowers and plants in New Spain. In the seven years he spent posed by Aristotelian texts.
exploring, aided by his son, he faced many obstacles and suffered many pri- Hernandez first worked on Aristotle's Physics. He also discussed nature,
vations. Hernandez died in Spain, and his contributions to science went un- concentrating on nature in motion, or corporeal nature, and established its
recognized. principles: matter, shape, and privation. He explained in some detail the
In addition to his studies of nature, however, Hernandez wrote philosoph- functions of the following Aristotelian principles: When a thing changes,
ical works that reveal a strong humanist tendency. His philosophical works in- matter is the support of the change, and what really changes is the shape,
clude (1) Compendia de philosophia moral segun Aristoteks en las Ethicas que escrivio that is, the matter changes its shape into a different shape, which the body
a Nicomaco, (2) Libro primero de los phisicos que tracta de los principios de ciencia nat- was lacking before. This is why privation and shape are somehow opposed in
ural, (3) Quaestiones stoicorum liber unus, (4) Probkmatum stoicurum liber unus, the process of transition from the privation of a shape to its possession. The
(5) Problemata seu erotemata philosophica, secundum mentem peripateticorum, et receptacle in this process is matter. Such a process is movement or change
earum principis Aristotelis, and (6) Problemata morqlia exmente Aritotelis.m At least (not only local but of any other kind). Hernandez then discussed the four
four of these works (Libro primero de los phisicos, Probkmatum stoicurum liber causes of movement and of being: the final, efficient, formal, and material
,11 unus, Problemata seu erotemata philosophica, and Problemata moralia) appear to causes. The final cause is the change's end or fate; the efficient cause is the
19:11
have been written in New Spain. The titles of the first two suggest they are agent of the production or change; the formal cause is the way in which the
commentaries on Aristotle, but in fact they are notes upon Aristotle's works, matter is transformed; and the material cause is the matter itself. He consid-
sometimes as brief as summaries and in no way comprehensive. Perhaps they ered the order of the causes and the movement they provoke with their in-
are best considered as representative of the interests Hernandez had in certain flux. He also dealt with another Aristotelian theme: that of chance as op-
aspects of Aristotle's philosophy rather than as attempts at a systematic treat- posed to necessity. And, in relation to movement, he spoke about the place in
ment of his thought. This is also true of the Problemata moralia ex mente Ari- which it happens, discovering time and the void. In the same way that Aris-
totelis, an independent work in which Hernandez combines elements of the totle had been led by his study of the series of movements, the movers, and
philosophy of Plato and Aristotle which was typical of the humanist and Re- movement to the postulation of a Prime Mover, Hernandez, too, is led to a
naissance style of the time. Platonic elements are present in his neoplatonic Prime Mover whom he calls God.
essay on love, which Hernandez regarded as Stoic (recall that the Stoics, too, In his Aristotelian book, Del cielo y del mundo, Hernandez dealt with the
were interested in the connections between the thought of Plato and Aristotle). world's unity and with the finitude of the sky. He claimed that there can be
nothing outside of this realm because the sky is not a composite of the four
87. Marcel Bataillon, "Vasco de Quiroga et Bartolome de las Casas," Revista de Histo- sublunar elements, but a single, quintessential element. He considered its
ria de America 33 (1952): 83-95; G. Vargas Uribe, "La influencia de la Utopia de Moro en
los hospitales lundados por Don Vasco de Quiroga," Boletin de la Coordination de la Inves- perfection and perpetual movement and studied celestial orbs and their
tigation Cientifica de la UniversidadMichoacana 10 (1986): 16-23. movements, the sun, the moon, and the stars, referring to the earth as the
88. G. Somolinos d'Ardois's introductory biography and bibliography to Francisco
Hernandez, Obras Completas (Mexico: UNAM, 1960), and E. C. Frost, "Los interest's center of the universe.
filosoficos de Francisco Hernandez," in Francisco Hernandez, Obras Completas, vol. 6 Hernandez's Aristotelian book, De la generation y la corruption, dealt with
(Mexico: UNAM, 1984), p. 205.
oilier pcripalhelie llicmcs, such as llie four elements (earth, water, air, and
50 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Humanists 51

fire) with their opposing qualities, their transmutations, the mixtures pro- nounce the arrival of earthquakes, droughts, winds, floods, death, plagues,
voked by them, their increase or growth in all living things, and their death or wars, the fall of kings and catastrophes for princes?"90Hernandez tries to give a
decomposition. scientific answer to this question, explaining how comets were formed from
Following Aristotle in De meteoris, Hernandez wrote a work "about what exhalations: When comets descend to the depths of the earth, they provoke
happens above," in which he dealt with cosmic vapours, comets, the galaxy, earthquakes, dry the air and make it windy, contaminate the environment
and the winds. In this book, he included an analysis of earthquakes and other and produce plagues, excite people and move them to war and revolution.
acts of nature such as thunder, lightning, hailstones, snow, mist, frost, rain, This type of reasoning was considered scientific during Hernandez's time.
springs, mountains, the sea, rainbows, metals, and stones. Concerning the soul, in addition to what is dealt with in the Aristotelian com-
To complete his examination of physics, Hernandez includes a discussion pendium of the problems of the soul, some questions are raised about percep-
of the soul. According to him, the soul allows living things to have movement. tion and knowledge; these are rather rudimentary and chimerical observa-
There are three types of soul: vegetative, sensible, and rational. Hernandez tions. But we also find more substantial observations on vital spirits, for
studied the vegetative soul, its nutrition, growth, and generation. He noted example.91 Here Hernandez makes reference to the physicians who dealt the-
the uses and senses of the sensible soul: sight, sound, smell, taste, and touch. oretically with what Descartes would later call 'animal spirits'. Hernandez
He then addressed the Aristotelian theme of corruption of the sense when the adds something about the physiological place of evaluative thought and
sensed object is excessive. He provided a detailed discussion of visibly per- memory, and he ends with some questions regarding the intellect and will.
ceived, sensible objects, and he connected these objects to the common, sensi-
ble objects in general, which are the data that the external senses structure Moral philosophy
and order through the common or internal sense. Hernandez next gives an In his Compendio de philosophia moral segun Aristotles en las ethicas que escrivio
account of Aristotelian psychology: the reflexive or evaluative imagination, a Nicomaco, Hernandez closely follows the order of the Aristotelian Ethics. He
and memory. He also considered the faculties of motion; that is, the appetitive begins with a treatment of man's purpose, the search for the good life. This
and affective. His final object of study in this work is the rational soul. Here he search is carried out in many ways. There is, however, only one authentic
gives an analysis of the intellect, in both its active and passive functions, and Good and only this can make men truly happy. This is the common or politi-
treats some problems related to human understanding and will. cal good. This common good unites the goods of both body and soul, which
In his work on natural philosophy, Problemas o erotemasfilosoficos,Hernan- are ordered in the living of a virtuous life and classified into intellectual and
dez discusses what he had treated in earlier works, this time by means of a moral virtues. Departing from Aristotle, Hernandez, in his appendix, states
questionnaire, although he introduces some substantial changes. For exam- that God is more perfect than the political good. Thus, Christain faith super-
ple, in his discussion of the answer to the question: Why is it said that matter sedes Aristotelian philosophy.
contains all potential forms?, he claims that it is because matter has the ca- Virtues are good habits, that is habits that dispose one to do good acts (in
pacity to receive all (substantial) forms; without this capacity, matter would contrast, vices are bad habits). The good habit "perfects and honors man, and
not be able to contain all forms and nature shows us that matter does indeed man's actions; we have already said virtue is to be found in the middle be-
contain all forms.8' He considers various types of movement: straight, curved, tween two extremes, because this is the essence of art, which is far more un-
and reflexive, as well as the movements of space, the void, and time. He also certain than virtue, but it is always difficult to find the middle."92 With this
explains the reason why certain things had infinite or eternal movements statement, Hernandez accurately interprets Aristotle's doctrine.
and others did not. In his book about the sky and the world, he discusses
some interesting issues concerning geocentrism. In his work on generation 90. "iPor que los cometas presagian terremotos, sequias, vientos, inundaciones,
muerte, pestes, guerras, cafdas de reinos y calamidades para los pn'ndpes?" Ibid., p. 284.
and corruption, he discusses mixed and composite bodies. 91. Ibid., p. 303b.
In his book on meteors, we find a curious question: "Why do comets an- 92. A good liahil "perfecciona y honra al hombre, y a la accion del hombre; ya
li.ivcmos dicho qui- la virlnd oslii on el medio, porquc lambicn es eslo proplo de las
linos, que son inuilio ma's Inclcrtas que la viand, y rs sienipre cosa imiy dificullosa bai-
89. Hernandez, Obras Completas, vol. 6, p. 272. lor el medio." Ihid., p, * I ''I1
52 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Humanists 53

Next comes a study of voluntary action. Free acts are necessary for moral- these. Consequently, the mature and accomplished man develops good habits
ity to be possible at all. Following Aristotle, Hernandez distinguishes volun- that are virtues—both moral and intellectual virtues—and avoids the vices
tary from involuntary actions. Involuntary actions have no ethical dimension that pervert the natural impulses of passion. It has been said that this ideal is
(acting from force, fear, ignorance, etc.). The application of the will is some- absurd and unattainable because the perfectly equilibriated man, contem-
thing we choose, something dependent upon our deliberation. From this plated by the Greeks and Christains, does not exist. This criticism rests on a
process of deliberation, voluntary acts emerge; they can be virtuous or lack- misunderstanding of Aristotle's doctrine whereby virtue is understood to be a
ing in virtue. type of geometric equilibrium rather than the result of deliberation in con-
Having discussed voluntary action in general, Hernandez moves on to par- crete circumstances. Philosophers who supported Aristotle's doctrine of
ticular virtues. He begins with moral virtues: temperance, justice, and pru- virtue were well aware that virtue is an ideal that is always a paradigmatic
dence. Fortitude is tested in difficult times and is demonstrated by an ability tendency, to be achieved only with great difficulty, perhaps never, but
to face suffering with courage. There are many types of fortitude and many nonetheless an essential guide for human action. The virtuous man is a man
adverse circumstances in which we can test this virtue. "Fortitude is the of reason; he is authentically human.
power to sustain dangers, rather than back away from t h e m ; . . . to resist fear, Next, Hernandez discusses justice. Following Aristotle, he distinguishes
in resisting fear we bear our superiors and face our equals or inferiors; resist- justice from injustice; an unjust person is "he who works against laws, he
ing a fear is more difficult than bearing one that one does not like."93 Temper- who is too greedy with the goods of wealth, and he who is not interested in
ance moderates pleasure. One should not take more goods than is necessary, eliminating evil."94 Hernandez understood justice within a social context as
and one should limit the goods desired to those that are present and not those participation in and solidarity with the common good. He divides justice into
that are absent. legitimate (or legal), distributive, and conmutative justice. The first, legiti-
From among the virtues dealt with by Aristotle, Hernandez held generos- mate justice, concerns the order of the individual insofar as it contributes to
ity to be the most important, because it helps to moderate the distribution of the order of society; the second, distributive justice, refers to the order of soci-
wealth, keeping a balance between prodigality and avarice. Magnificence ety with individuals; and the last, commutative justice, speaks about common
adds splendor and excellence to generosity. Modesty is the mean between order among individuals. These categories also relate to money, necessity, and
ambition and lack of ambition. Gentleness (or good temper) tempers irascibil- provision. Hernandez refers to the natural right every citizen has to his own
ity and the fury of lost honor, which Hernandez says was typical of the Span- rational essence. He connects these themes to a discussion of right and equity
ish at this time. Hernandez classifies friendliness as the ability to converse and that aim to procure the common good, thereby making justice a real and con-
deal with people, seriousness as the middle ground between irony and osten- crete thing in society.
tation, and ready-wit as the mean between buffoonery and boorishness. Fi- Hernandez concludes his treatment of virtue with a discussion of intellec-
nally, Hernandez speaks of shame, which is not a virtue but which helps to tual virtues. While other virtues concern action, intellectual virtue is directed
curb passions and avoid vice. to reflection. Reflection is divided into five categories: art, prudence, under-
The Aristotelian idea of the virtuous man is a beautiful one which the me- standing, science, and wisdom. Art is the habit concerned with what can be
dieval Scholastics integrated into Christianity. Using this idea as his model, created; prudence deals with things that cannot be made but can be done or
Hernandez presents an ideal of a human being who is not blindly taken by his realized, like moral conduct; understanding is concerned with the origin of
passions but is led in action by his virtues which organize the passions or nat- I hings that cannot be shown; science is the "the demonstrative habit, which is
ural desires that are inherent in man. Passion is not denied, for it is, in itself, born from things that are not more noteworthy than their conclusion,"95 and
not bad but good; only its extremes are to be avoided, for these are vices.
Vices arise from excess or lack of prudence or moderation; virtue opposes 94. An unjust person is "el que obra contra las leyes, el que es demasiadamente
cobdicioso de los bienes defortuna,y el que no quiere ser participe de los males." Ibid.,
p. 329a.
93. Fortitude is the ability to "softener los peligros que no acometerlos,. .. resistlr el 95. Science is "hibitO demostratlvo, que nace de las cosas que no son mas notorias
ternor, [por ella] sufrimos al superior y acomclcmos al igual o inferior, clc I.is cuale) que In conclusion." Ibid., p. 336a.
eosas es rn.is cliIfci 1 la primora, ilen siiirir dolor que no gozo." Ibid., p. I.'.,'.a.
54 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o S i x t e e n t h Century: H u m a n i s t s 55

the category of reflection, which is wisdom, contains the knowledge that is He also mentions natural law and legality. Concerning wisdom, h e says that
greater t h a n any of the other categories, because it comes from the very origin only he is wise w h o has reached complete knowledge of w h a t can be k n o w n ,
of things and imparts knowledge about the highest causes (i.e., metaphysics). because knowledge involves both intellect and science.
In addition, curiosity is the virtue to ask, give advice, and consult; therefore, it
is closely related to prudence. Shrewdness is also attached to prudence be- Stoic ideal: harmony between Plato and Aristotle
cause it is fast a n d certain j u d g m e nt that belongs to law. The Greeks had a In the preface to Libro unico acerca de las cuestiones estokas (addressed to King
n a m e for a virtue that they called 'gnome', or things pertaining to equality. 96 Phillip II), Hernandez explains that this is his attempt to conciliate Peripa-
Virtues accompany one another and prudence is favorable in all of them, but thetic and Stoic doctrines. The primary t h e m e he uses to achieve this is the
it is wisdom that is truly the crown and o r n a m e n t of virtue. t h e m e of love; he indicates that, as far as h e knew, n o one had ever devoted
In his book, Problemas morales segiin la doctrina de Aristoteles, Hernandez enough attention to this t h e m e .
dealt with Aristotelian ethics by m e a n s of a questionnaire. He asked w h a t He asks about the origin of the world a n d deals with t h e Aristotelian a n d
happiness is and w h y it is to be found in intellectual virtue. Another question Platonic doctrines, favoring Aristotle, w h o spoke of a world created by God ab
in this questionaire is: W h y are there intellectual and moral virtues? He re- aeterno, not temporally. The latter would imply that the world would have
peats these questions often but also introduces n e w ones. He asks, "Why is been created after eternity, suggesting a time before time. 100 Hernandez t h e n
virtue in the middle, which determines prudence, but not controlled by the asks if love and desire are opposed to the will, 101 and his answer is negative
thing itself?" 97 T h e answer is that virtue is a chosen habit and moderation is a because the will is ruled by reason and there are m a n y things we desire that
function of reasoning proper. Hernandez t h e n asks, "Why don't w e call are in conformity with reason such as virtue and wisdom. Another interest-
strong those w h o die in order to avoid a terrible grief? Because they were not ing question that Hernandez poses in this miscellaneous series of questions is
moved by virtue b u t rather by bad intentions (sino Ios movio el medio de u n w h e t h e r desire can have as its object something which does not exist. 102 His
mal)." 9 8 Another topical question that Hernandez raised is: answer is that the object must exist because w e cannot love w h a t w e do not
know, and we do not k n o w w h a t does n o t exist in some way. Hernandez fur-
Why does distributive justice consist of the proportion of things that are distrib-
uted and the number of people they are distributed to? Because there can ther asks w h e t h e r contemplative life excludes the practical life; for example,
never really be equality between two people, and justice must be exercised if it involves giving up the life of material riches. The Stoics maintained that
among many. In this way, the amount one person surpasses another, the same wealth was to be despised, but the Peripathetics did not hold this, claiming in-
as one thing surpasses another, the distribution will be fair according to geo-
stead that wealth actually enhances the theoretical life, making it comfortable.
metric proportion, but it will not take care of civil dissension. But there has to
be proportion in both the measure of distribution and distribution itself. Such
proportion occurs in two ways: the separate one, which has four periods, and apenas si pueded haber igualdad entre dos personas, y la justicia debe ejercitarse tanto
the continuous one, which has three. The first one is that of distributive justice supera una cosa a la otra, sera recta la distribution que se haga guardando la propor-
because if we observe that one thing is to another as one person is to another, tion geometrica, descuidada la cual sugiran dimensiones civiles. Mas no solo ha de
then we will also see that such is the measure or proportion of a thing to a per- haber proportion en la media de lo que se distribuye, sino tambien en lo mismo que se
distribuye. Tal proportion es de dos especies, la separada, que tiene cuatro terminos, y
son, as of the other thing to the other person. We will also prove the accuracy, la continua, que tiene tres. La primera es propia de la justicia distributiva, pues si
if there is the same proportion between each of the persons and between each vemos que en una cosa es a otra como una persona es a otra, podremos tambien adver-
of the things, rather than between both things and both people. 99 lir conjuntamente que tal es la medida o proportion de una cosa a una persona, como
la de otra cosa a otra persona. Podra asimismo comprobarse la exactittud, si hay la
misma proportion entre cada una de las personas y cada una de las cosas que entre
96. Ibid., p. 338b. .imbas cosas y ambas personas." Ibid., pp. 352b-353a.
97. "t[P]or que se sitiia la virtud en el medio, que determina nuestra prudencia y 100. This theory is wrongly attributed by some scholars to Aristotle. It was also de-
no fijado por la cosa misma?" Ibid., p. 343b. fended by Aquinas who said that we could accept the creation of the world by faith, be-
98. "i[P]or que no llamamos fuertes a los que por evitarse una pena sc dieron cause the creation in time was more probable. Hernandez mentions the miraculous In-
muerte? Porque no los movio la virtud, sino el medio de un mal." Ibid., p. 346b. tervention of God; see Thomas Aquinas, "De aeternitate mundi contra murmurantes,"
99. "iPor que la justicia distributiva que guarda este medio ConslSte en la propor- Opusatla (Taurini: Marielli, 1950).
tion entre las cosas que se dlstrtbuyen y las pcrsonas a quienes se disiiibiiyni.' I'orque 101. Hernandez, Ohms Complclas, p. 567b. 102. Ibid., p, 369a.
56 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico
Sixteenth Century: Humanists 57

Hernandez combines both doctrines, saying that one may wish for (or even
say that, as in the microcosm where man is the axis between the corporal
procure) wealth but only as a means to other ends; one should not be bound
parts, understanding is the axis between the faculties of the soul; and just as
to it. Having discussed these practical issues, Hernandez next considers love in the macrocosm, the sun is among corporal beings what divine understand-
and desire for pleasurable things and finds that continence plays an impor- ing is between spiritual things."105
tant role in the moderation of these desires. He also deals with the question of
Love has an origin: the loved thing is its efficient, final, and formal cause,
love for noble things or superior goods, which is the most perfect love, be-
while its material cause is the lover; that is why the loved thing is usually
cause it reaches its climax in divine love. Following his Christian philosophy,
more perfect than the lover. Hernandez asks who the first loved one was. In
Hernandez claims that, insofar as it is possible to understand God at all, the
order to give content to this sort of tautology, he adds that, according to Plato,
more one knows God, the more one loves Him.103
the first loved one is God's intrinsic love, a love in which the lover and the
This love of God is accompanied by desire that elevates it and makes it beloved are the same. Extrinsic love, or God's love for the world that He has
complete; it is the climax of happiness. Hernandez expresses this in the fol- created, came afterwards. Hernandez ends with a question concerning the
lowing way: "From this we can infer that happiness lies in superior goods, origin of created love: Whether it was born in the inferior world of generation
and in the acts and habits of the intellectual soul, which are the supreme ones and corruption, in the celestial world of perfect movement, or in the spiritual
and the goal of all other human habits; we can say that man is man above all world of pure intellectual vision. He defends the claim that love began in the
the other living beings."104 Concerning the relation between God and man, created world, more particularly in the angelic world, and from there it was
Hernandez asks whether happiness consists in the knowledge of God or in transported to the inferior world. "It is not easy to say how love was trans-
the love of God. Here, the answer is that the love of God creates happiness. ported to the celestial and inferior worlds. As we mentioned before, some
Although one cannot love what one does not know, and God is remote from claim that it was derived from the first intelligence and then moved through
the limited knowledge of man, it is necessary to love Him, and this love in- the other more imperfect ones and finally to all inferior ones; others say that
creases with our knowledge, as limited as it is, of God. it was transported to all intelligences simultaneously just as an image can be
The most complete love and knowledge of God can only be obtained in reflected simultaneously in innumberable mirrors."106
the next life. Yet, because some had reached an intense relationship with God
As he had done in his Aristotelian works, in this Stoic work Hernandez
in this life, Hernandez asks whether perhaps ecstasy or rapture is a more pro-
adds a book entitled Libro unko acerca de los problemas estoicos about problems
found affection than dreaming. Dreams are distinguished from visions of ec-
arising from the doctrine he had exposed. He begins with some questions re-
stasy by the naturalness of the former and the intensity of the latter.
lated to love, and, as was customary in Renaissance and humanist treatments
All beings, even inanimate ones, and more especially, sensible beings and
of this topic, he uses Greek symbolism and mythology. He relates love to
superior beings, share what we call love. According to Hernandez, inanimate
beauty. Here he again tries to combine the ideas of Plato and Aristotle, as the
beings possess a type of innate love, due to the attractions that exist in nature; Stoics had tried to do. He claims that beauty depends more on shape than
sensible beings possess sensible desire, and superior beings possess rational matter; in other words, beings composed of matter and form are beautiful
love. The most perfect beings love the least perfect beings and vice versa, but when form dominates matter, for in this case, proportion is achieved. Imma-
the most perfect love of all is that between most perfect beings; God, the most terial beings are beautiful only with respect to form.107 For this reason, spiri-
perfect being, loves all things. i ual beings are more beautiful. He asks why some souls capture beauty more
All these considerations reveal Hernandez to be a Platonist or Christian-
ized neo-Platonist rather than a Stoic. Hernandez even deals with a favorite 105. "Diremos finalmenete que, asi como en el microcosmos que es el hombre el
theme of neoplatonic humanists, that of man as a microcosm: "We will finally eje es entre las partes corporales lo que el entendimiento entre las facultades del alma,
asi en el macrocosmos es el sol, entre las cosas corpdreas, lo que es el entendimiento di-
vino entre las espirituales." Ibid., p. 388b.
103. Ibid., p. 375b. 106. "Como se haya commiiiiicado el amor al mundo celeste y al inferior, no es facil
104. "De donde se infiere que la felicidad estriba en los biencs superiores, y en Ins dccirlo. Afirman algunos que, como antes indicamos, ilerivo de la primera Intdlgenda
actos y habitos del alma intelectiva, que son los supremos y el Jin de los ilein.ls li.ibiios ,i oiras in.is Imperfecta!, y por ultimo a loil.is las iiili'iioics; olros ilicen que a la vez y de
humanos, y merced a los cuales el liombrc es liombre y csl.i por cm nn.i <lr los dcin.is una sola vez se conumlco ,i lodas las iiiielifjciiiias, como si algo visible se iellej,ise, sl-
seres animados." Ibid., p. ?76b. Miiill.iiiiMiiiciilc, en etpeJOl liiiiiiini'i,ililcs." Ibid., p. I'' lb.
my. [bid., p. 198b,
58 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Humanists 59

than others, and he attributes this to the influence of matter or the body, sance philosophy, such as the attempt to combine Plato and Aristotle. This
which helps some and hinders others. tendency was shared by the Stoics in classical times, and Hernandez recov-
In his Platonic discussion of love and beauty, Hernandez introduces an in- ered it in his neostoicism. The influence of the ancients, for example, Aristo-
teresting problem that demonstrates a deep appreciation of Platonism in spite tle and Plinius, is present in all of these philosophers as well, and it is present
of his general preference for Aristotelian doctrines. The problem is that of try- in them in a direct way; that is to say, without intermediaries.
ing to reconcile Plato with the Bible: Juan de Zumarraga's reference to Erasmus in the Doctrina breve and his ap-
If the ideas and understanding are divine, then why does Plato think that di- preciation of the Spanish humanist, Constantino Ponce, as expressed in the
vine knowledge is different from the ideas and that God is different from both Doctrina cristiana, reveal a direct humanist influence. Zumarraga shared with
understanding and the ideas; something which is prior to these? Why does Erasmus and Ponce the ideal of returning to the origins of the Church, a time
beauty seem to be prior to the beautiful thing and wisdom prior to the wise during which people lived the message of the Gospels with simplicity and
man? It might be because in reality they are the same, but it does not seem cor- honesty.
rect to say that wisdom is wise or beauty is beautiful, but that their origin is so.
A unique supra-being rather than a non-being is posited because it is the most The source of Don Vasco de Quiroga's humanism was Thomas More's
ineffable and incomprehensible being. For, although we seem to have some Utopia. In his Information en derecho, Quiroga describes Indians in an age full of
knowledge of divine beauty, we have none of the beautiful per se. And this happiness that he parallels to the 'Golden age' (cf. Lucian's Saturnales). He
seems to be in agreement with the Holy Scriptures, where we can read in Gen- wanted to maintain this state of innocent happiness for the Indians. To this
esis: "In wisdom God created heaven and earth," and other similar expressions end, he planned towns, hospital-towns inspired by More, that would protect
seem to confirm that wisdom is somehow different from God, who created it ab
the Indians from the Spanish. Qurioga carefully laid out his plans for these
aeterno and created all things from it.108
hospital-towns in the Reglasy ordenanzas he left for these institutions.
The attempt to combine Aristotelian and Platonic doctrines reveals Hernan- The great Bartolome de las Casas can be called a humanist because he real-
dez's debt to the Stoic tradition and Renaissance humanism. ized humanist ideals in his fight for the Indians, although his defense of
human dignity has certain scholastic roots. In his struggle for the freedom of
the Indians and in his belief that monarchy has no divine origin but originates
General Evaluation of Humanism in the people, we can observe the influence of both Medieval Scholastic and
Renaissance doctrines.
Having completed an analysis of these four thinkers, we can reach some
conclusions regarding humanism in the philosophy of New Spain. First, these
authors are not humanists in the strict sense of this term; rather, they are
thinkers with scholastic training who were also receptive to Renaissance hu-
manist ideas.
In the work of Hernandez, we can observe some typical traits of Renais-

108. "i?ox que supone Platon el entendimiento divino distinto de sus ideas, y a
Dios distinto de uno y otras y anterior a ellos, si son las ideas el mismo entendimiento
divino, y el entendimiento divino el mismo Dios, y, por otra parte, parece anterior la
belleza a la cosa bella y el sabio a la sabiduna? Bs acaso porque, aunque en realidad
sean lo mismo, no parece propio decir que es sabia la sabiduna o bella la belleza, sino
aquello de donde la belleza o la sabiduria emanan. Da asi por supuesto un unico no entt
sino supraente, por ser lo mas inefable e incomprensible. Pues aunque parezcamol
tener algun conocimiento de la belleza divina, ninguno tenemos de lo bello per se. Y
aun parece tal manera de hablar mas de acuerdo con las Sagradas Escrituras, donde se
lee en el Genesis, I: 'En sabiduria creo Dios el cielo y la tierra,' y olras exprcsioni's se-
mejantes que parecen confirmar que la sabiduria es en ClertO modo distinto de Dios,
quien la produjo ab aelerno y creo en ell.i loci.is las cosas." Ibid., p. <!(> lab.

^^^Hl^^^^^^^l
Sixteenth Century: Scholastics 61

excelled in this task. They also had to attend to the education of their own
priests. Thus, it was within this context that philosophy was taught at the
time.
Along with schools for children, the Franciscans set up other educational
institutions for the training of Franciscan priests. Studying was also under-
taken in several convents such as those of San Francisco and San Diego. In
addition to Friar Juan de Zumarraga, who became famous at the time, other
Franciscans also excelled in philosophy. For example, we know that Friar
Miguel de Gornales, born in Mallorca in 1527, came to Mexico in 1555 at the
age of twenty-eight to offer an arts course at a convent of his order. Similarly,
we know that Friar Marcos Camara, after reaching New Spain at a very

3 I p The Sixteenth Century young age, became a Franciscan in 1564 and was a lecturer of philosophy
(and perhaps of theology as well).1 Finally, we have the Tratado de logica
(1597) by Friar Pedro de Espinosa, who taught at the end of the sixteenth
The Scholastic Philosophers
century.2
Together with logic and grammar, Scholastics introduced rhetoric into the
area of philosophy known today as linguistics (sermocinalis). To help with the
education of Franciscan priests, Friar Diego Valades wrote a treatise intended
to provide them with the rhetorical tools to convert the Indians to Christian-
Among Mexican Scholastics of the sixteenth century, one finds sev- ity. The treatise contains several philosophical elements from the Lullian the-
/ \ eral authors of importance, such as Friar Alonso de la Vera Cruz ory of rhetoric.
JL J L . O.S.A., Friar Tomas de/Mercado O.P., and Father Antonio Rubio
S.J. Other minor figures are also of interest. We have grouped Scholastics ac-
Diego Valades
cording to religious orders (with the exception of those belonging to the secu-
lar clergy). It is important to follow this procedure because one can thus per- Valades was probably born in Tlaxcala in 1534. His mother was Indian
ceive the different Schools encompassed by the Scholasticism of the period. and his father a conquistador, thus he was a mestizo. Given his origin, he could
The Thomist School was composed of Dominicans, Augustinians, and mem- interact with the Indians, whom he came to know and love deeply. At a very
bers of the secular clergy; the Scotist School flourished among Franciscans; young age he came under the tutelage of Friar Pedro de Gante, for whom he
and among Jesuits there prevailed a divergent Thomism initiated by Pedro da later worked as a secretary. He entered the Franciscan Order around 1551
Fonseca (1528-1599) and explored by Francisco Suarez (1548-1617). and was ordained in approximately 1555, when he was about twenty-one or
twenty-two years of age. He almost always worked with Indians: first as an
instructor at the School in Santa Cruz de Tlaltelolco and then as a preacher in
Franciscans Nahuatl. Later, he was the guardian of the Convent in Tlaxcala, and he
The Franciscans were the first priests to reach New Spain. They arrived in
1523, but during the sixteenth century, they could not devote much time to 1. Sec Gallegos Rocafull, El pensamiento mexkano, pp. 220 and 224.
philosophy due to their evangelizing and pedagogical work. One musl nol 2. Sec Walter Redmond, Bibliography of the Philosophy in the Iberian Colonies ofAmerica
(The Hague: Martinus NijholT, 1972), p. 38, no. 280. The author states that it is found
forget that, in addition to teaching the Catechism, they were also in charge of in the library Of the Ulllversldad de San Luis Potosf. See also L. Gomez Canedo, Los
the instruction of Indians. Friar Pedro de Gante, Friar Bernardino de Sa- archives de la hisloria tic America, I'criodo colonial espanol (Mexico: lnsliluto Panamericano
de Geograffa e fflstoria, 1961), p. 343.
hagun, and Friar Toribio de Benavente (called 'Motolim'a' by the Indians)
62 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Scholastics 63

preached the Gospel to the Tarascan Indians around 1560. He also preached Dominicans
the Gospel to the Otomies in 1569 and lived in the Convents of Tepeji del Rio
and Tula. Finally, he preached to the Chichimecans of Queretaro, Zacatecas, The Dominicans, or preaching priests, reached New Spain in 1526. In ad-
and Durango. dition to their work as missionaries, they attached great importance to intel-
In 1571, while he was the procurator of his province in the Franciscan lectual work because the structure and constitution of their Order required
Curia of Rome, he finished the Rhetorica Christiana. This work was the result it. Friar Bartolome de las Casas, whose work was described in our discussion
of many years of study and was published in Peruse in 1579. We have no of humanist philosophers, was one of many prominent Dominicans. As early
record of the place or the date of Friar Diego's death, but it must have oc- as 1540, the study of philosophy was established in the Dominican province
curred in Italy during the 1580s. of Santiago. We find reference to this in records of the provincial chapters,
The aim of Valades's Rhetorica Christiana was to prepare priests to educate where there is mention made of the establishment of a Chair for summulae
and evangelize Indians, and therefore it contains much theology and numer- (these were compendiums of logic) at the Convent of Santo Domingo in
ous references to the Holy Scriptures. Nonetheless, it also includes notable Mexico City. The text used for instruction was written by Pedro Hispano and
chapters on philosophy. For example, the first of its six sections consists of a accompanied by the commentary of the Dominican Domingo de Soto. The
discussion of the definition and the qualities of the orator, his relationship to first edition of the commentary dated from 1529. The first professor of arts,
the liberal arts, and authoritative of argumentation. The second section is or philosophy, was Friar Andres de Moguer. He was educated at the cele-
more philosophical. In it, Valades defines and divides rhetoric, explaining its brated Convent of San Esteban de Salamanca. It is said that Friar Andres de
purpose (chaps. 1-6). He specifies the purposes of rhetoric, saying that he will Moguer left numerous manuscripts, but they have been lost.4
talk about them all (chaps. 7-19). He does so with a marked Lullian tone, for Friar Bartolome de Ledesma, an outstanding theologian who excelled in
Lull's influence on Franciscan philosophy was strong. Valades also explains philosophy, was appointed lecturer of philosophy in 1552. He too had stud-
the main elements of rhetoric: invention, disposition, elocution, memory, and ied in San Esteban de Salamanca. In Mexico, at both the Convent of Santo
argumentation (chaps. 19-29). In the third section, the most outstanding Domingo and the Real Pontificia Universidad de Mexico, he taught the vig-
chapters are on pronunciation (chap. 16) and on the division of the affections orous Thomism he had learned in Salamanca. From 1560 to 1570 he lec-
and how these should be stirred (chap. 21). Section 4 has several chapters tured in the arts. He was also a censor appointed by the Inquisition and later
that deal with philosophical issues. Chapters 1 and 2 are about the genres of became Bishop of Oaxaca. He published a theological work, a Summa of
oratory; chapter 3 deals with the demonstrative genre of discourse; chapters Sacraments, which reflects his knowledge of philosophy.5 For example, he dis-
13 and 14 are concerned with the deliberative genre; chapter 17 discusses the cusses the concept of sign in his exposition of the notion of sacrament and the
judicial genre; and chapters 18-20 concern the laudatory genre. In the fifth idea of substance in his treatment of the Eucharist and trahsubstantiation.
section, the author expounds the following elements of invention or con- Similarly, in his treatise on baptism, Ledesma, following Vitoria, condemns
struction of discourse: exordium, narration, egression and digression, parti- ihe use of force during evangelization except when preaching is resisted.
tion, confirmation, confutation, and conclusion. Moreover, he goes back to
the art of the orator and the stirring of the affections. In the sixth section, he pana. Su obra (Mexico: Ed. Jus, 1982); and Fray Diego Valades, evangelizador, humanista de
touches upon the tropes or figures of discourse and the different kinds of ar- la Nueva Espana. El hombre y su epoca (Mexico: Ed. Jus, 1963). These works have been
gumentation, pointing out which function as topics of rhetoric or argumenta- compiled in Diego Valades, O.F.M., evangelizador humanista de la Nueva Espana. El hombre,
su epoca y su obra (Mexico, Universidad IberOamericana, 1988). See also I. Osorio, Flo-
tive foundations (i.e., supports) of oratory.3 Valades offers a philosophy of resta de gramdtica, poetica y retorica en Nueva Espana (Mexico: UNAM, 1980), pp. 134 ff.
rhetoric according to which the art of oratory is part of the general theory of and Diego Valades, Retorica Cristiana, ed. Tarscicio Herrera, et al„ a bilingual edition.
(Mexico: Fondo de Cultura Economica, 1989).
argumentation: it is not merely a matter of stirring the passions but of appeal- 4. See Maurido Beuchot, Fildsofos dominicos novohispanos (entre la universidad y sus
ing to reason (argumentation) and to emotion (persuasion) as well. colegios) (Mexico: UNAM, 1987).
">, Bartolome dc Ledesma, De septum novae legis sacramentis summartum (Mexico: An-
lonlo lispinosa, 1566; Pamplona, 1 581; Salamanca: Malfas Guast, 1585). See Mamiei<>
3. See B. J. Palomera, Pray Diego Valadfo, evangelizador, liuiiiniiislti de lit Nuevti lis IU-III hoi, "ll.iriolomr de Ledesma y su Siiina de stimulation," lisliidios de hisloria novohis-
pana II (1991): 253-65.
64 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Scholastics 65

Friar Pedro de Pravia was a contemporary of Ledesma. He had also been a theological and economic work on commercial transactions and contracts
student at the Convent of San Esteban and was later a lecturer at the School reflects his lectures, discussions, and moral advice.7
of Santo Tomas de Avila. After reaching New Spain, he became a professor at On his way back from Spain to Santiago, Mexico, he was struck by a fatal
the convent in the capital and at the university. De Pravia's propensity for illness. He died in 1575 and was buried in the ocean off the coast of Veracruz,
controversy and argument became apparent in the lectures he delivered at in San Juan de Ulua. In a document about the visits that the members of the
the convent in 1553 and when he taught at the university, around 1558. Like Inquisition paid to ships in order to check the books they carried, there is ref-
Ledesma, de Pravia was strongly influenced by Cayetano, especially in the erence to the visit to San Juan de Ulua in August of 1575 and to the ship in
courses on philosophy that he offered both at the convent and the university which Mercado was traveling when he died. It laconically states: "Ship.—
and in his treatise on the Eucharist where he explains transubstantiation.6 San Juan, property of Juan Antonio Corzo; grand master: Rodrigo Lechon,
Because Friar Tomas de Mercado was the most reputed figure among the scribe: Bme. Hernandez. Books: Historia Pontiftcial, Paulo Jovio, Orlando, Horas,
Mexican Dominican philosophers of the sixteenth century, we will discuss and others, as well as four trunks belonging to a friar called Tomas de Mer-
his views in greater detail. cado who died at sea."8

The 'summulae' or formal logic


Tomas de Mercado
Mercado's interpretation of Pedro Hispano's Tractatus or Summulae logicales
Tomas de Mercado, a leader among sixteenth century Dominican philoso- follows the school of St. Thomas Aquinas. With little innovation, he here ac-
phers, was born in Seville, Spain and probably arrived in Mexico as a mer- cepts the line of Thomist commentators such as Juan Versor and Domingo de
chant. There he entered the Order of Preachers in about 1552. Assigned to Soto, belonging to what was known as Minor Logic (logica minor or parva log-
the Convent of Santo Domingo in the capital, he studied philosophy and icalia). Adopting Soto's perspective, Mercado's intention is to discuss subjects
theology at the Convent's School, where he was ordained in 1558. He was pertaining to formal logic, setting aside ontological or psychological matters
advanced in years and probably had some education when he entered the for the Major Logic (or magna) and the Opuscle. This prepared the way for the
Order, because he was ordained shortly after and was immediately destined division drawn by Juan de Santo Tomas in the seventeenth century between
for teaching, which was uncommon. 'formal logic' and 'material logic'. In pointing out that the summulae should
Upon being ordained, Mercado was appointed lecturer of arts in the Con- only discuss formal logic, Mercado anticipated the understanding we have of
vent of Santo Domingo, holding that professorship until 1562. For some logic today.
time he was the curate of the same convent in Mexico, but he was later Mercado deals with the logical form of reasoning or argumentation,
transferred to Spain. In Spain he studied in Salamanca and Seville. In Seville closely examining terms and sentences or propositions. Terms are ordered
he also taught philosophy, moral theology, and law, and acted as an advisor according to the proposition and the proposition is ordered according to the
to merchants. During his stay in Spain, Tomas de Mercado published the
works that, as suggested by several indications found in them, were for the 7. See Tomas de Mercado, Suma de tratos y contratos (Salamanca: Matias Guast,
most part the result of his teaching experience in Mexico. The commentary 1569; Seville: Fernando Diaz, 1571 and 1578; Italian version, Brescia: Pietro Maria
Marchetti, 1591; incomplete modern version with an introductory study by R. Sierra
to Pedro Hispano's Tractatus or Summulae of logic, the translation and com- Uravo, Madrid: Editora National, 1975; complete modern version with an introduc-
mentaries to a section of Aristotle's Organon (namely the Categories and the tion by N. Sanchez Albornoz, 2 vols. (Madrid: Clasicos del Pensamiento Economico
Espanol, Instituto de Estudios Fiscales, 1977); Commentarii luddissimi in textum Petri His-
Posterior Analytics, apart from Porphyry's Isagoge), and an Opuscle on selected pani. . . cum argumentorum selectissimorum opusculo . . . (Seville: Fernando Diaz, 1571;
logical arguments were the result of his experience as a lecturer in arts. His translation and introduction by Mauricio Beuchot, Mexico: UNAM, 1985); In logicam
magnam Aristotelis commentarii, cum nova translatione textus ab eodemauctore (Seville: Fer-
nando Diaz, 1571). The commentary on Porphyry's Isagoge, or book of Predicables, has
6. See Mauricio Beuchot, "Lectores conventuales en la Provincia de Santiago de been translated with commentary by Adoli'o Diaz Avila, and the Commentary on Aris-
Mexico (siglo XVI),' Archive Dominkano (Salamanca, Spain) 7 (1987). A bilingual edi- totle's Categories, or book Of Predicaments, has been translated with commentary by
tion with an introductory study of the treatise by Pravia on lite Eucharist is being Mauricio Beuchot.
prepared by Clara Ines Ramirez and Mauricio Beuchot and will be published by 8. I1. Hernandez del Castillo, ed., Ubivs y libreros en ehiqloXVI, 2d ed. (Mexico: FCE-
UNAM. AGN, 1982), p. 510.
66 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Scholastics 67

argument. Therefore, he presents an analysis of the theory of formally valid confusing, he sets these aside so as not to encumber the work but rather to
argumentation that takes into account the arrangement of the elements. The facilitate its comprehension.10
definitions, divisions, and properties of such elements are studied, and the The Summulae are structured as follows: the Prologue presents Mercado's
rales of formation and transformation of the elements that validate infer- conception of the nature of logic and announces the division of the work into
ences, consequences, or argumentations follow. The Opuscle touches upon five books. The first book deals with signs, language, and terms. The second
problems that are not appropriate for beginners because of their difficulty; takes up sentences, modes of knowing, propositions, and the properties of
such problems are set aside for more advanced students. terms. In the third book, Mercado discusses the relations between categorical
The book opens with Jacobo Donio's Epigram, which comes after the title assertive propositions and includes a treatise on modal propositions. The
page and the Privilegio real.' In this epigram, Donio praises Mercado, com- fourth book concerns the hypothetical and exponibile propositions. The fifth
paring him to Hercules, for having avoided all the useless matters and exces- book is devoted to syllogisms. It is surprising that the Opuscle does not refer to
sive technicisms typical of decadent Scholasticism, especially among nomi- all the books of the Summulae; it is an appendix of considerable length, but it
nalists, of the time. These technicisms had burdened the manuals and only deals with matters that are related to the contents of books 1 and 2.11
courses on logic to such an extent that they scared students away from the In the first book on signs, language, and terms, Mercado includes a chap-
study of philosophy, instead of attracting them to it. Donio exaggerates many ler devoted to supposition. In this section he provides us with one of the
of these useless matters and excessive technicisms; in fact, many of these clearest explanations of that property of terms. He also offers a classification
matters are now valued highly by contemporary historians of logic and cor- of supposition that contains the most essential ones and provides very intelli-
respond to some subtle problems discussed in recent discussions of logic. It is, gible criteria with which to distinguish them.12 In the fourth book, which is
however, true that in Mercado's time the books on logic were burdened with also remarkable, Mercado offers a very faithful and precise Aristotelian un-
superfluous elements and that technical problems made the study of logic an derstanding of propositions or sentences. From the general theory of propo-
arduous task. Today logical and mathematical symbols facilitate the discus- sitions and its classes, he selects two main divisions: the categorical and the
sion of these problems. hypothetical (or the simple and the compound). He sets the categorical aside
After the Epigram comes the dedication to Cristobal de Rojas y Sandoval. .ind focuses on the hypothetical. Mercado studies the most basic types of hy-
Today this kind of dedication seems excessive and pompous, but during Mer- polheticals: the conjunctive or copulative, the disjunctive, and the condi-
cado's time it was commonplace and not understood as false praise but lional (together with negation). With precision he provides us with truth-
rather simply as acknowledgments expressed to a well-known person. Fol- lables, which were known since the times of the Megarians and Stoics, and
lowing the dedication is the Proemio to the reader in which Mercado explains highlights some of the main rules of inference pertinent to every logical con-
his intention to purge formal logic by removing the complications to which it nective.13 Based on this he constructs a solid propositional logic.
had heretofore been subjected. The prefatory matters end with an Encomia In his explanation of syllogisms, Mercado discusses quantification logic,
(eulogy) by Jacobo Donio. Icrms, and predicates. The exposition is didactic and provides a very useful
This volume contains two works. Apart from the Summulae, there is an procedure for the determination of the valid and useful syllogistic modes for
Opuscle of arguments that appears as an appendix. Here, Mercado discusses each figure of the syllogism. In the same way, his treatment of the principles
many objections against the subjects he addresses. These subjects pertain to .ind fundamentals of syllogistic argumentation tallies perfectly with the ex-
what would later be called "the philosophy of logic." Naturally, Mercado re- position of his derivation.
solves many other difficulties and objections throughout, but, in keeping
with his intention to exclude the complications that made other logic texts 10. The arguments compiled in this Opuscule correspond only to the issues dealt
wilh in the lirst two books of the five that make up the Summulae.
I 1. Sec Redmond and Beuchot, La logica mexicana.
9. See Mauricio Beuchot, "La logica formal en las Sumulas (1571) de Tomas dc\Mcr- 12. Sec Mamicio Hcnchol, "La semantica en la logica de Tomas de Mercado," Critica
cado," Cuadernos Salamantinos de Filosofia (Salamanca, Spain), 10 (1983): pp. 141-56; 12, a. 42 (1982): 49-63.
and "Introduccion" to Tomas de Mercado, in Comenlarios hwidkimm alttxto de Pedro His 1 V Sec Maurld0 Beuchot "La 16gica propOSldonal en Tomas de Mercado," Didnoia
pano (Mexico: UNAM, 1.986), pp. 5-26. HI (1984): 21 I l'».
68 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Scholastics 69

Ricardo, and other pioneers in this field.15 In this celebrated Suma, Mercado
'Dialectics' or material logic first deals with natural law as the basis of positive economic justice. He goes
In the commentary on the Logica magna or Logica mayor concerned with on to relate natural law and positive law or authority to the subject with
the Aristotelian writings that were not dealt with in the Summulae, Mercado which he is concerned: commercial relations (he devotes several chapters to
presents his view of the foundations of logic itself and of science in general. these topics in the context of the Indies). Immediately thereafter comes the
The commentary is based upon Mercado's translation of the Greek into pragmatics of wheat (from Felipe II). He subsequently deals with exchanges
Latin. In the preface, he briefly deals with the nature of logic, its function and bank transactions, devoting the following book to loans and usury, con-
and importance. He goes on to comment on Porphyry's Isagoge, the obliga- cluding with a treatise on restitution.
tory and habitual introduction to Aristotle's Categories with which Aris- According to Mercado, the philosophical backbone of economics is consti-
totelian logic books actually begin, and, at this point, he examines the differ- tuted by reason and justice. Thus, ethics becomes the mediator between eco-
ent predicables. He immediately turns to the predicaments or categories nomics and philosophy. Mercado's goal was to unite theory and praxis as
themselves, pointing out that he is doing so in a logical way and without much as possible. Man desires knowledge, knowledge about that with which
touching upon metaphysics. Because Mercado had dealt with De interpreta- he interacts, and this is transaction. But to carry out transactions, one must
tione in the Summulae—that is, with matters that for us belong to the philoso- distinguish the just from the unjust. Since reason guides human life, transac-
phy of language—and with the Analytica priora in his discussion of the propo- tion must conform to reason. Life is good when it is rational, and it is rational
sition and of syllogism, here his focus is the Analytica posteriora. It consists of a when just. Mercado's anthropology rests on the belief that human reason
Treatise on Demonstration; that is, of a discussion concerning what consti- conforms itself to natural law when it authentically follows human nature
tutes science. This Treatise is very useful because it identifies the limits of (which is human reason in search of justice). Effectively, man makes use "pri-
demonstration as well as its strengths; Mercado distinguishes the conditional marily of reason or natural law, from which the latter (i.e., the practical) more
(hypothetical) from what is properly scientific (apodictic) and explains the closely derives; it is the measure and proper rule of all human rules."16 Free-
conditions required for knowledge to be considered scientific in an Aris- dom is based upon reason and must respect the needs of human beings, needs
totelian sense. that compel individuals to form society. Mercado bases his grounding of both
Mercado examines and explains the conditions that Aristotle assigned to the rational order of justice and commercial laws on his sharp observations of
principles such as self-evidence, immediacy, and antecedence or priority with commerce, buying and selling, cash flows, etc. He concludes that merchants
respect to conclusions. Every science is based upon certain primary principles have three purposes: the first, to be useful to their nation; the second, to help
that must be known beforehand. Mercado analyzes and clarifies the different the poor; and the third, to promote the advantage of their own families.17
types of logical priority, as well as the different ways in which a scientific Although Tomas de Mercado was not an original thinker, he encouraged
proposition is better known and immediate. These topics have been reexam- the study of logic, and he applied his philosophical and theological knowledge
ined in recent philosophy of science, especially in the formal sciences.14 lo economics. Thus he is a deservedly esteemed figure of Mexican cultural life.

Social and economic philosophy


Other figures
Tomas de Mercado achieved substantial fame with his Suma de Tratos y
Contratos, considered a classic work in the area of the ethics of economics and Another remarkable Dominican philosopher was Friar Cristobal de Or-
even in the theory of economics itself, because it discusses problems and lega who was appointed lecturer of the arts to the Convent of Santo
concepts that were to be developed later by Hutcheson, Adam Smith, David
is. See J. Iniguez, "Tomas de Mercado y la Suma de Tratos y Contratos," Justicia y Paz.
14. See Mauricio Beuchot, "La logica material o dialectica (1571) de Tomas de Mer- Revista de Derechos Humanos, 2 (1987): n. 2. See also Mauricio Beuchot and J. Iniguez, El
cado," Palabra 1, rm. 2-3 (1986): 76-88; and "Los principios de la cicniia en Toni.is de iviisiimieiito Jihsttjico de Tomas de Mercado. L6gicay economla (Mexico: UNAM, 1989).
Mercado," Quipu. Revista Latinoamericana de Historia de las Cieneias y la Teciwloylit M\ u>. Mercado, Suma dt tratosy contratos, n. 27.
(1986): 103-111. 17. Ililil., nn 115-16.
70 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico
Sixteenth Century: Scholastics 71

Domingo in 1578.18 The Order conferred on him the degree of Master in Sa-
Alonso de la Vera Cruz
cred Theology. He also taught at the University, where he became a teacher
of theology in 1591. He became Rector of the University on 10 November Friar Alonso was one of the founders of the philosophical and intellectual
1602 and died in 1604. life of New Spain. In many respects he may be considered the founder and
In 1583 Friar Fernando Bazan was appointed professor of arts at the Uni- 'patriarch' of philosophy in Mexico. He was born in Caspuenas, Spain,
versity where he also taught two seminars on theology (one as substitute to around 1504. He studied grammar and rhetoric at the Universidad de Alcala
the Chair of Prime and the other as Tenure of Vespers) in which he proved his de Henares and went on to study arts and theology at the Universidad de
competence in philosophy as well as in theology. The depth of his philosoph- Salamanca where he received the degree of Master in Theology. He studied
ical thought is also evident in his theological writings. Father Bazan left hand- under highly acclaimed masters, such as the Dominicans Francisco de Vitoria
written commentaries to Aquinas's Summa Theologiae (I-II and III) which, ac- and Domingo de Soto, who introduced him to Aquinas's philosophy. In time
cording to the chronicler Davila Padilla, were much appreciated: "And he also became a professor of arts in Salamanca.
although many things on this matter have appeared during our time, his will He was ordained a secular priest and was already a young professor with a
be much appreciated because, with brevity and acuteness, he has seen what brilliant future when something unforeseen changed the course of his life. In
is most difficult in Theology and what is most pure in Metaphysics."19 spite of great academic and material promise, he decided to join a group of Au-
Friar Luis Lopez, from the Convent of Santo Domingo in Oaxaca, wrote gustinians who were embarking to Mexico to spread the Gospel. They invited
Instructorium negotiantium sive tractatus de contractihus et negotiationibus, a work Vera Cruz to teach theology and act as their teacher in New Spain. Thus, in
pertaining to the ethics of economics, a field that had been cultivated by 1536 he abandoned the prospects of a brilliant career and moved to New Spain
Friar Tomas de Mercado. This piece of Friar Lopez's work was intended for where, upon arrival at the port of Veracruz, he became an Augustinian priest.
merchants. In spite of differing points of view, this work, together with those Friar Alonso de la Vera Cruz taught arts and theology in schools which he
of Vitoria and Soto, makes up a veritable school of social and economic helped to establish: Tiripetio in 1540, Tacambaro in 1545, and soon after Ato-
morality brought to America by Bartolome de las Casas and Tomas de Mer- tonilco. He was the first to teach seminars, open libraries, and publish works
cado. Its members applied the doctrines of this school to the events and prob- on philosophy in America. Not surprisingly, Oswaldo Robles calls him "the
lems that arose in America.20 Venerable Father of Mexican Intelligence."21 and Rafael Salazar to some ex-
tent considers him the representative of 'criollo philosophy'.22 In 1553 he be-
came a professor at the newly-founded Universidad de Mexico, where he
Augustinians taught the Sacred Scriptures and Scholastic theology. His philosophical works,
The Augustinians reached New Spain in 1533. In addition to their work 1 he first to be published in the New World, appeared in Mexico in 15 54 and in
as missionaries, the intellectual work they performed in their convents and 1557. After many years devoted to encouraging philosophical and theological
schools was also of importance. They had schools in the Purepechan and studies, he died in New Spain in 1584.2'
Tarascan regions as well as in other areas such as the capital, where they es-
tablished the celebrated School of the Convent of San Agustin. Friar Alonso Philosophical work
de la Vera Cruz played a very important role in these Augustinian educa- Friar Alonso wrote what may rightfully be called the first coursebook for
tional projects. philosophy of the New World. It encompasses minor logic, major logic, and

18. See A. Franco, Segunda parte de la Historia de la Provincia de Santiago de Mexico, 21. Robles, Pilosofos mexicano, p. 11.
(Mexico: Museo National, 1900), pp. 180 ff. 22. See Rafael Salazar, "El ser absoluto en la filosofia de Fray Alonso de la Vera
19. A. Davila Padilla, Historia de la fundacion y discurso de la Provincia de Santiago de Cruz," Libro Anual del ISEE 1 (1971): 199-221; and "La persona humana como testigo
Mexico, de la Orden de Predicadores (Mexico: Editorial Academica Literaria, 1955), p. 572. del ser en la filosofia de Fray Alonso de la Vera Cruz," Libro Anual del ISEE, 2 (1973):
20. See Mauricio Beuchot, Lafilosoflasocial en los pensadores novohispanos (Mexico: 257-74.
IMDOSOC, 1989). 2 >. See I' Ccre/o de Dicno, Alonso de Veracruzy el dtrecho degcnlcs (Mexico: f'orriia,
I9H5).
72 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n C o l o n i a l M e x i c o Sixteenth Century: Scholastics 73

physics in the Aristotelian sense. To this one might add his philosophical- words. The theory of supposition served to determine t h e intension and ex-
juridical work. The section on logic and physics contains three m a in works: tension of terms in order to control their quantification and to ensure the
Recognitio summularum, Dialectica resolutio, and Physica speculation which is his validity of inferences. Friar Alonso's logical acuteness m a y be seen in his
strictly philosophical work. 25 He explored other areas as well and left m a n u - discussion of t h e supposition of terms with special quantifiers in analyzable
26
scripts that are n o w greatly appreciated. We will discuss some of his philo- propositions (which were k n o w n as exponibiles or resolubiles).
sophical and juridical works o n the Conquest because they constitute valu- In predicate logic, Vera Cruz employs n e w quantification signs used by
able practical applications of his highly speculative thought. 2 7 We t u r n first to nominalist logicians. Many of the authors after him neither used nor ade-
his logical physical, and juridical thought in that order. quately understood these signs. These quantifiers were innovations in formal
Logic occupies a very important position in Friar Alonso's thought. The logic that the excellent medieval and post-medieval nominalist logicians had
first two works cited above are devoted to this subject. The Recognitio summu- developed. Vera Cruz's quantification logic also includes numerou s extensions
larum is so called because it is a revision or abbreviation of the Summulae o n of the quantification of predicates, k n o w n today as multiple quantification.
logic. It deals with logic, and, although it includes introductory parts, it con- Following the Stoics, Vera Cruz's prepositional logic also contains trea-
tains topics similar to those taught today in courses on mathematical logic tises o n hypothetical propositions for which h e provides truth-functional ta-
(but without the symbolism). 28 bles. And his treatment of argumentation, unlike most, is not limited to syl-
In his minor logic, Vera Cruz tries to revise and abbreviate the Summulae, logisms. The core of his treatment of argumentation is the general doctrine
leaving out all that was useless and out of place in relation to formal logic. In of inference or consequentia that includes m a n y areas such as modal logic. In
t h e treatise on terms and their logical properties, h e explains the mai n as- the area of modal logic, for example, Vera Cruz makes distinctions in order to
pects of the theory of supposition. His explanation of this classic doctrine is work with modal propositions de re without either confusing or reducing
competently executed. Supposition was the logical-semantic component t h e m to de dicto modals. This is widely studied by contemporary logicians. He
with which medieval philosophers established the kind of meaning or refer- also made advances in the logic of relations. 25 In general Vera Cruz's work
ence that a term had in the proposition. For example, in " h u m a n has t wo demonstrates that h e had a strong grasp of the developments of logic during
syllables," the term ' h u m a n ' has material supposition; that is, it supposes for his time.
itself as a term, therewith indicating a reference to the word. In the proposi- In major logic or dialectics, Vera Cruz carries out an analysis (resolutio) of
tion "man is a species," ' m a n ' has simple formal supposition, having as a ref- the principles that pertain to logic and to science in general. Thus the title of
erence point a c o m m o n concept or c o m m o n n a t u r e. This is not to be con- his work: Dialectica resolutio. The semiotic, epistemological, and even meta-
fused with "man has reason," w h e r e ' m a n ' has personal supposition with physical problems of formal logic were studied by dialectics or major logic;
reason presupposed for t h e individual and not for essences, concepts, or this is w h y it was later called 'material logic'. Vera Cruz deals with the nature
of logic, the entity of reason that is its object, as well as with predicables and
24. The editions are the following: Recognitio summularum Reverendi Patris lllefonsi a categories. This work also contains an extensive study of universals, the
Vera Cruce (Mexico: Ioannes Paulus Brissensis, 1554; 1562 [Salamanca]; 1569; 1573;
1579 [hypothetical]); Dialectica Resolutio cum textu Aristotelis edita per Reverendum Patrem principles of knowledge, and the fundamentals of science.
Alphonsum a Vera Cruce.... (Mexico: Ioannes Paulus Brissensis, 1554; 1562 [Salamanca]; Dialectics usually included some treatises relative to Porphyry's Isagoge,
1569; and 1573); Physica Speculatio, Aedita per R.P.P. Alphonsum a Vera Cruce. . . . Accessit
compendium Spherae Campani ad complementum tractatus de coelo. . . . (Mexico: Ioannes Aristotle's Categories, in some cases, the De interpretatione, and, above all, the
Paulus Brissensis, 1557; 1562 [Salamanca]; 1569; and 1573). The Spanish editions do Posterior Analytics. The Posterior Analytics and, on occasion, the De interpreta-
not include the Compendium.
25. See Redmond, Bibliography of Philosophy, p. 105. tione were discussed in the Summulae, and the Topics and Elenchi were reserved
26. See A. Bolafio e Isla, Contribution al estudio bibliogrdfico de Pray Alonso de la Vera
Cruz (Mexico: Robredo-Pornia, 1947). 29. Walter Redmond states the following: "It is known that before De Morgan,
27. See Gallegos Rocafull, El pensamiento mexicano, pp. 276 ff; and "La filosoli'a en I'rcge, and Peirce there was no general theory of the relations in the history of logic.
Mexico en los siglos XVI y XVII," in Estudios de historia de lafilosoflaen Mexico 3d ed. Fray Alonso de la Vera Cruz and Scholastic colleagues of the XVIth century constantly
(Mexico: UNAM, 1980), p. 134. .iii.ilyv.od the logical relations, both syntactical (prepositional and predicative) and se-
28. As with the other Scholastics, his formal logic can be rcconstriu led will) mod- iii,nnic, ,ind Ihey also made use of an onlological theory of relations," Kelaciones y
ern symbolism; see Redmond and Beuchot, La Idgicti mcxhinid. pp. 17 It. inutilities tvmpltjM en In Willed mexiciiiiti del sigh XVI (forthcoming),
74 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Scholastics 75

for the appendices. Alonso de la Vera Cruz's work was no exception to this After a discussion of predicability, Vera Cruz deals with predication, espe-
trend. His Dialectica or Logica contained treatments of the Isagoge, the Cate- cially with categories; that is, with the supreme genres of predicates or
gories, and the Posterior Analytics. modes of knowing. His treatise begins with a brief section on the modes of
The first treatise of Vera Cruz's dialectics is on predicability, which corre- predication, called ante-predicaments. Following a consideration of the main
sponds to the Isagoge. This is followed by a treatise on predication, or the modes of predication—that is, univocity, equivocity, analogy, and denomina-
main types of predicates, namely the categories, a subject that corresponded tion—he goes on to the most general predicates. These are the categories
to the Categories. Finally, he discusses the theory of scientific demonstration enumerated by Aristotle: a substance and nine accidents; namely, quantity,
that corresponds to the Posterior Analytics. quality, relation, action, passion, place, time, position, and habit. The treatise
In the dialectics, Vera Cruz studies the logical universal. The universal is a concludes with a section on post-predicaments, which are the relations that
concept and constitutes the instrument of reasoning, the nucleus of thought. the categories have to each other; for example, anteriority, simultaneity, op-
Therefore, although this seems to be an abstract subject, for Scholastics like position, etc."
Vera Cruz it was a useful and necessary one. Now, the universal is an entity When presenting the table of categories, Vera Cruz does not shy away
of reason that is the object of dialectics or logic. Because the entities of rea- from a question that comes up immediately: What basis does the table of cat-
son are products of the operations of the mind, and the first operation pro- egories have in reality (if and when it has one); is it arbitrary, and if so, how
duces the universal, Vera Cruz studies the universal as the starting-point of arbitrary? These questions concern whether the table of categories is natural,
logic. He concludes that the universal has the ontological status of a mental artificial, or both. Strangely enough, there have been more than just a few
entity (i.e., reason), a concept of the mind that is expressed both by the term philosophers who claim that their table of categories is, if not the only valid
and its sign.30 He divides the universal into five types that were known as one, the one that best conforms to reality. Vera Cruz asks whether such a
the quinque voces and were present in Porphyry's Isagoge, studying the man- claim is possible; that is, whether one can speak of a table of categories that
ner in which the universal is known and produced in the intellect by means conforms with more precision to reality. Within this context he discusses the
of abstraction and intellective comparison. However, he argues that if the problem of objectivity and subjectivity. Is man's perception of the categories
nature and function of the universal in thought is not understood, it is im- of reality tainted by subjectivity? Is it relative to culture, language, and the
possible to comprehend logic because the modi sciendi or modes of knowing, conceptual scheme he has received? Or can it achieve objectivity? Why
which constitute the objective of logic, would not be understood. These should one table of categories be accepted instead of another? What are the
modes are three: (1) definition, (2) division or proposition, and (3) argu- decisive criteria for its acceptance? Would these criteria take the form of a
mentation. These modes of knowledge, due to their reliance on our under- formal argument, whether transcendental or of a different sort? The Platon-
standing of the universal, demonstrate the importance of the universal for ists declare that reality is categorized by nature and that this categorization
knowledge. occurs a priori. The nominalists believe that all possible categorizations are
Of subjects treated in dialectics, the predicables stand out. Predicables are merely arbitrary. In response, Vera Cruz urges us to adopt a middle course ac-
names given to the elements that can function as subjects or predicates in cording to which, following the Platonists, it is possible to accept a categorical
sentences or propositions. The discussion of predicables centered around order given in nature. However, following the nominalists, this order is not
whether they were extralinguistic or linguistic; that is, whether the subjects perceived a priori but a posteriori; it is an arbitrary and cultural construction.
or predicates were things or words without any relation to things. Vera Cruz In the treatise on science, Vera Cruz speaks of science as knowledge
shows that there is need for a middle term. The words play the role of sub- ih rough demonstration. He classifies demonstration, following Aristotle into
jects and predicates, but they definitely do so because they refer to things, to demonstration of fact, or quia and explicative demonstration of cause or
realities.
31. See Mauricio Beuchot, "La dialectica comofilosofiade la logica en Alonso de la
30. See Mauricio Beuchot, "EI problems de los universales en Domingo tie Solo y Vera Cruz," in Pemamiento y realidad en Pray Alonso de la Vera Cruz, ed. Redmond and
en Alonso de la Vera Cruz," Revista de Pilosofla 17 (1984): 249-73; reprinted in Kol Beuchot; reprinted in Dos homtrtajes, Alonso de la Vera Cruz yPrancixcoXavierClavigero, ed.
niond and Beuchot, Pemamientoy realidad en I'rny Alonso de la Van C,ni7. M.miino liciidioi and u. Navarro (Mexico: U'NAM) (forthcoming).
76 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Scholastics 77

propter quid. The latter is the most demanding and is satisfactorily and ade- of the Indians whose passion equals that of Las Casas, although Vera Cruz's
quately applicable only to mathematics. He establishes conditions or criteria search for justice was not as exceptional as that of the Bishop of Chiapas. Sev-
for the explicative demonstration or cause, that is, the characteristics of its eral things illustrate the generosity of the scholastic juridical doctrine found in
premises and conclusions, especially the epistemic characteristics of axioms the De dominio infidelium. Like his teacher, Vitoria and the theologians of Sala-
and theorems as well as of rigorous inferential concatenation. This enables manca, Friar Alonso believes that sovereignty can only be granted by the peo-
him to create a hierarchical table of sciences. ple and that a ruler becomes a dictator either by the manner in which he
Finally, Vera Cruz's treatises, Topicos and Sofismas are also exceptional.32 came to power (tyrannus ab origine or a titulo) or the way he governs or rules
All this work was carried out for the sake of his teaching because Vera Cruz (tyrannus a regimine). When either the way in which he came to power or the
was conscientiously preparing himself to offer all that was within his grasp to use of his power is unjust, then the ruler deserves to be overthrown. Vera
those who, in Mexico, were new to philosophy. In his courses on philosophy, Cruz denies that there are humans who are, by nature, destined to serfdom.
he wanted to offer all that was being offered at the universities in Europe, Accordingly, the dominion of the king and his encomenderos over the Indians
His work culminates in his Physica speculatio, which deals with cosmology depends upon popular will and not upon a dictate of nature. Indians cannot
and astronomy. In particular, Vera Cruz considers the nature of physics, cor- be dispossessed of their land; Indigenous peoples, despite their infidelity or
poreal being, movement and its classes, and space and time. He also com- paganism, cannot lose their right to own land.
ments on De caelo, De meteoris, De generatione et corruptione, and De anima. De Friar Alonso also follows Vitoria in the demand that Indians be taught
anima studies living beings, especially man. This work concerns not only the Christian doctrine, whether or not they are legitimately welcomed by the
senses and the sensitive aspects of human beings but also the intellect, rea- encomenderos. At the same time, he claims that Indians are legitimate owners
son, and the life of the spirit. Therefore, the problem of the immortality of of land. Wyclif claimed that Indians could have no dominion over anything
the soul is raised, a problem closely related to what was, in Vera Cruz's time, because of original sin. The Thomist School opposed this, claiming that Indi-
the celebrated problem of the agent intellect.33 ans were legitimate owners of their land and, therefore, that any land taken
With respect to legal philosophy, we must consider the De decimis (on from them had been taken unjustly. Friar Alonso does not acknowledge the
tithes), the De dominio infidelium, and the Speculum coniungiorum. The last of universal power of the emperor defended by Miguel de Ulzurrum, nor
these is a sampler of practical philosophy that describes Friar Alonso's ideal Ostiensis from Ostia's claim regarding the the universal power of the pope.
of the human couple; that is, it applies ethics or morals to marriage and the He concludes that Indians are legitimate rulers of their land and neither the
family. This work contains remarkable sections devoted to the issues of con- emperor nor the pope can justifiably seize those lands. Nevertheless, Vera
sent, marital separation, and the difficulties inherent in marriages between Cruz does allow for the possibility of the pope's commissioning the emperor
Indians. The last was an important issue because missionaries had to deal as lord of the entire globe for spiritual purposes and of giving this emperor
with problems such as polygamy. part of the world for the sake of evangelization. Here Friar Alonso actually
Antonio Gomez Robledo34 places Friar Alonso's work on the philosophical resorts to the ominous doctrine of the indirect temporal power of the
and legal docrines concerning the political situation of the New World into Church.
the same category with Vitoria's. Moreover, Vera Cruz emerges as a champion This conclusion is open to question. Indeed, although Vitoria himself de-
fended the right to preach the Gospel, in Mexico it was done with violence,
32. See Mauricio Beuchot, "Introduccion" to the bilingual edition of the Elenchi and and this invalidated such preaching. The need to preach the Gospel did not
the Topics by Fray Alonso (Mexico: UNAM, 1987); reprinted in Pensamiento y realidad en
Fray Alonso de la Vera Cruz, ed. Redmond and Beuchot. confer the right to conquer infidels. In the opinion of Vitoria and Vera Cruz,
33. See Mauricio Beuchot, "La antropologia filosofica de Alonso de la Vera Cruz," in the Conquest had no legitimacy. In fact, even if the pope and the emperor
Homenaje a Fray Alonso de la Vera Cruz en el IV centenarlo de su muerte (1584-1984), ed.
Mauricio Beuchot and others (Mexico: Instituto de Investigaciones Juridicas, UNAM, h.ul jurisdiction over lands, it did not follow that they owned these lands.
1986), pp. 11-24, and in Pensamiento y realidad, ed. Redmond and Beuchot. Besides, the indies were not colonies but were, as established by the Laws of
34. See Antonio Gomez Robledo, El magisteriofilosdficoy jurfdico de Alonso de la Vera
Cruz (Mexico: Porrua, 1984); see also E. J. Burrus, The Writings of Alonso de la Vera Cruz,
the Indies, realms or provinces and were entitled to the rights accompanying
5 vols. (Rome and St. Louis, Mo.: n.p., 1968). such status.
78 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Scholastics 79

Like Vitoria, Friar Alonso discusses the illegitimate and legitimate actions, of planting a philosophical seed in the newly discovered lands. Although he
as well as reasons for acting during the Conquest. The illegitimate reasons transferred Scholastic thought to New Spain, he did not merely copy it; he
that Vera Cruz mentions are the following: (1) disbelief of Indians, (2) de hire changed and purified many doctrines and, above all, modified teaching
possession of the New World by the ancient Roman empire, (3) injuries in- methods, divesting them of the technicalities with which later Scholastics
flicted upon the Spaniards by Indians, (4) Indian opposition to evangeliza- had burdened them. He was the first to open schools and libraries, and he
tion, (5) contra naturam sins committed by Indians, (6) mental retardedness has thus gained the name of initiator and father of Mexican thought.
and feeble-mindedness of Indians, and (7) the Conquest as God's mandate. There is another aspect to Vera Cruz's contribution worthy of mention
Those who resorted to these reasons could not legitimize the Conquest. here. Friar Alonso was the first to train students of his time in philosophy;
However, Vera Cruz invokes the following reasons that, from his point of this group of students included Spaniards, criollps, and Indians. In his com-
view, do legitimize the Conquest of Indians, although they do not legitimize mentary on a work by Antonio Gomez Robledo,36 Silvio Zavala observes, "It
the manner in which this was accomplished: (1) natives were under the is a privilege for great university masters to have disciples who deserve them.
obligation of receiving the faith and the emperor could compel them to fulfil This is the case of Friar Alonso de la Vera Cruz with respect to his master Vi-
it; (2) fulfillment of this obligation could also be enforced by the Roman toria, not only because he inherited the knowledge of the new Scholasticism,
pope; (3) giving a Christian prince to the converts; (4) tyrannical rule of bar- but also because he maintained a propensity to observe the events of the
barian princes; (5) anthropophagy and human sacrifices practiced by Indi- world critically. Vitoria had witnessed the Conquest from the considerable
ans; (6) alliances between the Spaniards and other Indigenous peoples, distance of a celebrated university of the Old World. Vera Cruz came into his
above all the Tlaxcaltecs; (7) free and voluntary vote of Indians; and (8) ius own as a thinker at a nascent Mexican university, only three decades after
communicationis et commercii, as well as other derivative rights. Cortes conquered Tenochtitlan, with students who were the immediate de-
scendants of the conquistadores and of the first settlers of New Spain."37 An
Evaluation example of Vera Cruz's efficiency as a teacher is to be found in his outstand-
Alonso de la Vera Cruz follows Aristotelian and Thomist doctrines but ing disciple, Antonio Huirzimengari Mendoza y Calzonzin, son of the last in-
demonstrates an extensive knowledge of the new humanist theories of his digenous lord of the Tarascans.
time. Despite his didactic intentions, he develops some philosophical innova-
tions and becomes a clear exponent of intellectual renewal.35 In fact, apart Other figures
from his knowledge of the Aristotelian and Thomist tradition, one may also
note the influence of the 'neoterici', a name that designates both the nominal- Another remarkable philosopher who belonged to the Order of Saint Au-
ists and Renaissance humanists. Just as he was a disciple of Vitoria in Sala- gustine was Friar Jose de Hinojosa, a Spaniard who was a professor at the
manca and a devoted follower of Soto, in his work we may also perceive his Real y Pontificia Universidad de Mexico until he returned to his native
intention of assimilating new doctrines derived from humanist philosophers country.38 He started teaching at this Mexican university in 1561 and was
and not just a desire to imitate their style. the first to be appointed through a competitive process. He won the Chair of
Above all, Friar Alonso is a missionary of knowledge. The other mission- Arts, which was given to him officially on April 19, 1561.39 In his lectures,
aries worked eagerly to spread the Gospel throughout the New World, but he used a well-established text of the Dominican Domingo de Soto,40 but
teachers like Friar Alonso were also devoted to the promotion of philosophi- eventually he prepared his own coursebook, Summa philosophiae scholasticae
cal and theological studies. Moreover, although originality was not their pri-
36. Seen. 31.
mary objective, several of these men made remarkable contributions and 37. Silvio Zavala, "Fray Alonso de la Vera Cruz en la vision de Antonio Gomez Rob-
opened new paths in philosophy. Vera Cruz's work has the particular merit ledo," Di&logOS (El Colegio de Mexico), n. 113 (1983), 22.
?«. See Samuel Ramos, Historia de lafilosofia en Mexico, vol. 2 (Mexico: UNAM, 1985),
j). I 14,
35. For some of bis innovations, see Maurkio Beuchot and li. Gonzalez Ruiz, "L.a v>. See C, H. de la 1'l.rz.i y .Lien, Crinica de la Real y Pontiflcia Universidad de Mi'xico,
falacia de peticion de principio en Fray Alonso de la Vera Cruz," Nova TtllUS I (1985): vol. I (Mexico: Miipicut.i IlniviMsil.iti.i, 1931), p. 28.
221-33. '10. Iliid.. p. 60.
80 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Scholastics 81

patris Dominici de Soto, Ordinis Praedkatorum, in usum Academiae Mexicanae acco- 1578. He taught Summulae, dialectics and physics (or natural philosophy). In
modata. This work was, however, never published and has been lost. In 1566 1587 he resigned, probably resentful because he had not been promoted to a
Hinojosa was promoted to the Chair of Theology, which he held until he re- more important and prestigious position. Although he took several competi-
turned to Spain, where he was given a Chair at the Universidad de Osuna.41 tive examinations for the seminars on theology, he failed to gain another
We also have a philosophical work by Friar Francisco Coronel (born in teaching position. Within the Augustinian Order, Contreras was a professor
Torija, Spain), entitled Quaestiones aliquot eruditissimae in libros De anima Pri- at the School of San Agustin,44 Rector of San Pablo, Prior of the Augustinian
mae Partis Divi Thomae, written between 1589 and 1591.42 Influenced most Convent in Mexico, and Definitor and Provincial of the Order (1596).45
strongly by Aquinas, Coronel's work deals with the soul and examines the When he died in 1613, Contreras left a manuscript entitled Lectiones philoso-
definition offered by Aristotle, who considers it the first act of an organism. phiae studentium captui accommodatae*6
Coronel distinguishes the soul from the body and explains how it can subsist Two Augustinians shared the surname of Zapata. There is a reference to
after the death of the body. He then goes on to discuss the intellective soul Juan Zapata y Alarcon at a university cloister on 10 November 158947 and as
and to analyze its character as a form united to matter, which is the body. He the president of a viva.a The title of his thesis is Has totius dialecticae generales
studies the means of this union and concludes that the soul is found assertiones defendet. . . in Mexicano S. P. N. Augustini, coventu F. Bernardus Romero
throughout the entire body and in each of its parts. artium liheralium studiosus sub praesidio et tuttissimo auxilio, literatissimi Patris
Focusing upon the soul, Coronel examines whether the soul can be iden- Joannis Zapata Alarcon, eorundem Artium Lectoris meritissimi. Die 20 mensis au-
tified with its faculties, and he decides it cannot. The soul is susbsistent and gusti post meridiem. Ex offlcina Melchioris Ocharte anno 1597. A coursebook is at-
has, rather than is, its faculties. Coronel adds that these faculties of the soul tributed to him, but we do not have it.49
are divided according to the objects toward which their acts tend. He thus De iustitia distributiva, published in 1609 in Valladolid, Spain, is also attrib-
dwells upon the faculties of the soul, in its vegetative, sensible, and intellec- uted to Juan Zapata y Alarcon,50 but it is probably the work of Juan Zapata y
tual parts. In this discussion of the sensible part, he examines both internal Sandoval, another Augustinian. It is entitled Fratris Ioannis Qapata y Sandoval,
and external senses. When considering the intellectual part of the soul, he augustiniani. ... De iustitia distributiva et acceptione personarum ei opposita discep-
raises the issue of whether our intellect can know a singular object. He ex- tatio. Pro Noui Indiarum Orbis rerum Moderatoribus, Summisque et regalibus Con-
plains knowledge of singular objects as something to which the intellect has siliariis elaborata. . . . Anno 1606, Vallisoleti, excudebdt Christoforus Lasso Vaca.31
no direct access (only the senses can know individuals directly); this knowl- Reference has also been made to a work in three volumes produced at the
edge is a reflexive act of the intellect. Finally, he discusses the soul in its rela- end of the sixteenth or the beginning of the seventeenth century by Friar
tion to rational understanding; that is, the discursive intellect and not only Diego Villarrubia, entitled Philosophia scholastico-Christiana.32
the apprehensive (or 'intuitive') one. He concludes the work with a discus-
sion of the kind of knowledge that the separated soul may acquire.
Jesuits
We also have a handwritten commentary by Friar Juan Amorillo, Com-
mentaria in primam divi Thomae a quaestione 12 ad 14. Amorillo's commentary The first Jesuits who came to Mexico arrived in 1572. In Europe, the Soci-
concerns the knowledge that man may have of God in order to form some ety of Jesus was known for its didactic undertakings. These clergymen were
concept of Him in accordance with the diverse names that may be given to
Him, and the issue of the knowledge that God has of things.43 44. See Gallegos Rocafull, El pensamiento mexicano, p. 221.
Friar Juan Contreras was born in Mexico, where he studied and gradu- 45. Ibid., p. 296.
46. See E. Valverde Tellez, Bibliografiafilosoficamexkana, vol. 1 (Zamora, Mexico: El
ated from the University. After having explained Soto's Summulae for the (lolegio de Michoacan, 1989; fascimile edition of the 2d ed. of 1913), p. 20.
competitive examination, Contreras was appointed to the Chair of Arts in 47. See Plaza y Jaen, Crdnka de la Realy Pontificia Universidad de Mexico, vol. 2, p. 184.
48. See Valverde Tellez, Bibliografi'afilosoficamexicana, vol. 1, pp. 15-16.
49. Ibid., p. 16.
41. See Gallegos Rocafull, El pensamiento mexicano, pp. 294-95. '>(). Sec Gallegos Roc.ifull, HI pensamiento mexicano, p. 295.
42. See J. Yhmoff Cabrera, Cataloao de obras manuscritas en latin de la liiblioleca Na- 51, The balm-Spanish bilingual edition of this work was published by UNAM,
tional de Mexico (Mexico: UNAM, 1975), p. 192. edited by Arluro Ramirez Trcjo and M.nuicio Hcuehol.
43. [bid, 52. See V.ilvcide telle/, HiblloiiraflafllOStSflMtMXtCCUta, vol. 1, p. 23,
82 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Scholastics 83

cloistered, so they generally operated outside the universi-t T ty. In IJ74 Poihcr accepted that the University asked permission from the Society of Jesus to
Pedro Sanchez founded the School of San Pedro and Seaiin IMliln, lIlC flrsi honor him with the title of Doctor of Theology; the title was conferred in
major Jesuit school of New Spain." Father Pedro Lopez d e HParr.i Wll llic flisl 1582. He continued teaching at the Jesuit School and on occasion acted as
philosophy professor at the School of San Pedro and San F* aablo.*1 I 111 P were Dean of the School of Theology at the University. Considered a wise and
other minor schools or 'students quarters' in existence a s * well, 1U| li II San saintly man, he died on 12 May 1626.
Miguel, San Bernardo, and San Gregorio, a school for y o u n i g g Indian! Around Among Hortigosa's purely theological works, there are several related to
1583 these schools merged to form the great School of Sara.. I Ildefonitl philosophy. Some center around what would now be known as philosophy
of religion. In several sections of his treatise, De natura theologiae, de Dei essen-
P e d r o d e Hortigosa tia et de perfectionibus, Hortigosa discusses the problems of God's existence and
divine attributes. He also devotes a section of this book to the knowledge
Father Pedro de Hortigosa (also known as Ortigosa) vwwas mors Involved that man may have of God. On the other hand, in De fide, spe et charitate
with theology than philosophy, yet, through his t e a c h i n g , lie did Irllnitc (1590), Hortigosa questions the notion of a 'just war', an issue that falls
to the philosophical education of Mexican philosophers. I lie dliu dl lUiwi'd within political or social philosophy. With respect to this issue he states the
various philosophical matters in his theological works. following: "(1) War is not always illicit, it can be honest if carried out under
Hortigosa was born in Villa de Ocana, Toledo, in 154t-7\7. Ik illldjjll liu the proper conditions. (2) Three conditions are required if war is to be licit;
manities at the local Jesuit School, later attending the UnAjwvmld.nl dl Hi all namely, public authority, just cause, and honorable intention. (3) When one
where he studied and then graduated with a bachelor of a n t s dt'KH I lllhw of these is lacking, war is illicit."58 He also wrote a Tractatus de usu auri et ar-
quently, at eighteen years of age, he joined the Society c»f!l Jcmi III 111 genti apud Novohispanos pertaining to economic philosophy.59
vows in 1571. He continued his studies at the Colegio JlvM.ixInin di Maid
where he eventually succeeded his own professor, F a t h e r A A/III, In I III ' lldll
Antonio Rubio
of Theology. Thus, he acquired the same rank as Alonso EDiir/d II
Toledo, and he received the praise of Francisco Suarez.56 Antonio Rubio was born in Villa de Rueda, close to Medina del Campo, in
Hortigosa traveled to Mexico in 1576 to lecture in t h e o H o c r II llli Ijlllegkl 1548. He later went to Alcala and, after taking three courses on philosophy
Maximo de San Pedro. There was, however, no theology B|iinn i ll at the Universidad Complutense, entered the Society of Jesus in 1569 at the
that the students he had were students of philosophy - who liiid IIUilM age of twenty-one. OnCe a member of the Society, he studied one year of
briefly with Pedro Lopez de Parra. Alegre recounts that 3Hloiil| Ill philosophy and four years of theology at the Colegio de Alcala de Henares.
that if he wanted students of theology, he would have t«oo lldlll ll I There he studied under Francisco de Toledo and became acquainted with the
self." Hortigosa took on this task, continuing the courser- in plillii U|lll) (I teachings of Toledo's teacher, Domingo de Soto.60
ready begun under Lopez de Parra, yet he did it with the iarri I e n I li Ml ill |Hl'|iAl Rubio was sent to Mexico in 1576 to teach philosophy and theology at
ing good philosophers so they could later attend his lectur-«e"iiMi llirill the Colegio de San Pedro y San Pablo where he succeeded Hortigosa to the
also become good theologians. He taught arts for only cz>nnr s I lIlHl Chair of Arts. He taught philosophy for four years, beginning in October
turned to theology, which he taught for the next forty y e a i i h H> 1577, and around 1580, he began to teach theology and continued until

53. See C. Diaz y de Ovando, El colegio maximo de San Pedro y St^nw f'tft 58. Gallegos Rocafull, El pensamiento mexicano, p. 207.
ico: UNAM, 1985), pp. 14 ff. 59. According to Oswaldo Robles, the handwritten manuscripts of the first two
54. See David Mayagoitia, Ambientefilosdfico de la Nueva Espana„ - i (MMll works are in the Library of the Universidad de Mexico, and the third manuscript is lo-
p. 166. aned in the Secretan'a of the Iglesia Catedral Metropolitana de Mexico, Filosofos mexi-
55. Ibid., p. 141. canos, pp. 70-71.
56. See Robles, Filosofos mexicanos, pp. 67-70. 60. For I he biography of Rubio, see Alegre, Historia de la Provincia; see also Walter
57. See F. X. Alegre, Historia de la Provincia de la Companta de . Mctuli i Redmond, "I.a l.ogka Mexic.in.i de Antonio Rubio: Una nota historica," Dianoia, 28
ed. B. J. Burrur and P. Zubillaga, rev. ed. (Rome: Instilli« mini III (1982); reprinted in Redmond and llcucltol, La loqica mcxicana en el siglo de on,
1956-1960). pp, 24 I li.
84 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Scholastics 85

1592. Owing to Rubio's growing prestige, in 1593 the Jesuit province re-
quested the General of the Order to grant him a doctorate and permission to Theories
publish a coursebook for philosophy or a commentary on Aquinas. Actually, Owing to the influence of humanism, the tradition of Summulae had lan-
Rubio's coursebook is a commentary on Aristotle modeled on Aquinas's own guished, and Aristotle's texts were given more attention. As a result, Rubio's
commentary. The Universidad de Mexico granted him the degrees of Master work consists of commentaries on Aristotle that are organized systematically
(1594) and Doctor of philosophy (1595) and theology. as a coursebook. This is particularly evident in Rubio's logic. This commen-
In 1600 he went to Rome as the Procurator of the Order's Mexican tary on Aristotelian logic deals with Porphyry's Isagoge and Aristotle's Cate-
province. He was also sent to Europe to publish the philosophical work he gories, De interpretatione, Prior and Posterior Analytics, Topics, and Elenchi. It cov-
had written during the twenty-five years he had spent in Mexico. In 1601 ers the entire Organon."
the Spanish Crown granted him permission to publish a book of logic, and in Rubio is inclined toward a moderate Scholasticism, without the faults of
1602 he went to Spain. The following year, in 1603, his coursebook for phi- the decadent variety of this movement. Following a humanistic tendency to-
losophy was approved by an exacting committee and became a compulsory ward pedagogy, he was led to simplify the materials with which he dealt. He
text at the Universidad de Alcala. His commentaries on logic were also pub- begins With the usual introductory themes on logic itself. Dialectics is neces-
lished and became standard textbooks. In 1605, reacting to the news that not sary for all the non-rudimentary levels of science and proves useful, if not es-
all university instructors were using Rubio's textbook in their courses, the sential, at least at the beginning. Dialectics is itself a science because it
king wrote a letter restating the policy that obligated all instructors to use demonstrates conclusions based upon evident principles. It is also an art be-
Rubio's textbook. Responding to a request from the university teachers, cause it includes rules of procedure and of application that are to be followed
Rubio wrote briefer commentaries on Aristotle's logic so that the subject in practice. Dialectics is speculative and practical and its object of study is rea-
matter could be taught in less time thereby adhering to the conventions son or thought.
adopted by the Universidad Complutense. These shorter commentaries were Rubio's discussion of universals in the context of Porphyry's Isagoge is
published in 1606 under the title Logica mexicana. Rubio continued working worth mentioning. He rejects nominalism and Platonism, adopting an Aris-
on his coursebook for philosophy and wrote sections on physics and psychol- totelian and Thomistic middle course. Only individual entities exist in reality.
ogy; however, the project was interrupted by his death in 1615. Universals exist only in the mind but are abstracted by the mind from things
that exist in reality. So, universal natures exist in things in a material, or fun-
Works damental manner, whereas in the mind they exist in a formal or proper
Rubio intended to include logic, physics, and metaphysics in his course- manner only. Thus, against the Nominalists, Rubio maintains that universals
book, but some sections on natural philosophy and meteors, and the entire liave a material, foundational, or fundamental reality in things, but they
section on metaphysics, were never written. Among his works are the fol- only have a formal reality in the mind and not in things. Against the Platon-
lowing: the extensive commentaries on Aristotle's Dialectics, the shorter com- ists, he denies that universals have reality outside of things. The universal
mentaries or Logica mexicana, the commentary on the Physics, the De caelo et exists in the many, e.g., in man or in humanity. A consequence of universal-
mundo, the De ortu and the De anima.61 All these works underwent several ity is predication; the universal is predicable of many. There are five modes of
printings, a fact that attests to the high regard in which they were held.62
1
eta, 1610; Lyons, 1611; Alcala, 1613; Cologne, 1616; Lyons, 1618; 1620; Alcala, 1620;
61. For Rubio's bibliography see Redmond, Bibliography ofPhilosophy, pp. 84-85, nn. Brescia, 1626; Cologne, 1629; Lyons, 1640); Commentarii in libros Aristotelis de caelo et
626-32. See also I. Osorio Romero, Antonio Rubio en lafilosofianovohispana (Mexico: mundo (Madrid, 1615; Lyons, 1616; Cologne, 1617; Lyons, 1620; 1625; Cologne, 1626;
UNAM, 1988), pp. 75-83. Brescia, 1626); Commentarii in libros Aristotelis de ortu et interitu (Madrid, 1609; Lyons,
62. Commentarii in universam Aristotelis Dialecticam (Alcala, 1603; Cologne, 1610; 1614; Madrid, 1615; Cologne, 1619; Lyons, 1620; Alcala, 1620; Lyons, 1625; Brescia,
1613); Logica mexicana . . . hoc est Commentarii breviores et maxime perspicui in universam 1626); Commentarii in libros Aristotelis Stagiritae philosophorum principis de anima (Alcala,
Aristotelis Dialecticam (Cologne, 1605; Valencia, 1606; 1607; Cracow, 1608; Cologne, 161 I; Lyons, 1613; Cologne, 1613; Madrid, 1616; Lyons, 1620; Brescia, 1626).
1609; Alcala, 1610; Lyons, 1611; 1613; Alcala, 1613; Paris, 1615; Cologne, 1615; Va- 63. For this discussion, we will use the edition oi Rubio's coursebook published in
lencia, 1615; Lyons, 1617; 1620; Cologne, 1634; London, 1641); Commentarii in otto li Lyons, Sumptilms Antonii I'llli'hotll. 1620.
bros Aristotelis de Physico audali.... (Madrid, 1605; Valencia, 1606; Cologne, I MO; V.ilen-
86 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Scholastics 87

predication, which are called predicables; all other modes of predication are discusses its division into modes and figures. In the Posterior Analytics, the dis-
reducible to them. Predicables are entities of reason that only exist 'objec- cussion of scientific or demonstrative syllogisms reveals that the structure of
tively' (objective), namely, as objects of thought.64 science is based on apodictic (necessary, universal, and evident) principles.65
Rubio explains the five predicables separately and goes on to the predica- All this is discussed in connection to the gnoseological problems involved in
ments or Aristotelian categories. Aristotle had placed the ante-predicaments human faith, certainty, and the criteria of truth. The Topics briefly discusses
before them. These are special modes of predication: denomination, univo- inferential rules of discussion and the probable or contingent syllogism.66 The
cation, and equivocation. The last is divided into two: the causal and the sys- Elenchi, in dealing with sophisms and false syllogisms, establishes what is ex-
tematic or analogous, which is why Rubio deals with analogy in this context. cluded from logic and thereby serves as a good tool for the teaching of proper
He studies the nature of analogy and its division; the type of abstraction in- argumentation.
volved in analogies in relation to the analogized; the analogy between God Rubio goes on to treat Aristotle's ideas on philosophy and nature. He be-
and creatures; and the analogy present among creatures themselves; namely, gins with a preamble on the division of philosophy into physical or natural
between substance and accidents and between accidents themselves. He dis- and metaphysical or supranatural philosophy. In a short history of philoso-
cusses every one of the ten Aristotelian categories and concludes the section phy, he deals with the epistemological status of physics: its nature as a sci-
with a discussion of the post-predicaments. These are relations among vari- ence and its object. This discipline is speculative; it is a unified science, not a
ous categories. The post-predicaments are opposition, priority (or anterior- disperse one. Its objects are entities subject to motion. Rubio adopts the Aris-
ity), simultaneity, transference, and the modes of having. totelian division of natural or physical philosophy. Each division studies the
Rubio proceeds to comment on the De interpretatione which contains the moveable entity from a different perspective. In the Physica, Aristotle exam-
main elements of the Aristotelian philosophy of language. He discusses the ines the principles/beginnings and causes of natural things; in the De caelo et
elements of the proposition which are the noun and the verb. He conceives mundo, he studies local movement and the elements of astronomy; the prin-
the proposition as a sentence that is true or false and affirms or denies some- ciples of movement or substantial changes of generation and corruption are
thing about something else. Rubio adds a classification of propositions into dealt with in the De ortu et interitu, whereas De meteoris deals with generation
categorical and hypothetical, and he deals with the relations between propo- and corruption of some imperfect composites; De anima focuses on the prin-
sitions, such as opposition, equipollence, etc. ciple of vital movement; and the Historia animalium, together with a lost trea-
For Rubio, the Categories is concerned with the first operation of the mind; tise on plants, discuss the movement of the body that has either a sensible or
that is, the apprehension of simple elements. The second operation, namely vegetative soul. Rubio did not comment on the books concerned with mete-
the composition of elements within the proposition, is the subject matter of ors and animals.
the De interpretatione. Finally, the remaining books of the Organon concern the At the time it was assumed that one had to proceed from the most famil-
third operation of the mind, which is reasoning, and thus the syllogism is dis- iar to the least known, and thus Rubio asks at the beginning of his discussion
cussed in them. of the Physica whether it is convenient to begin the book with effects and
According to Rubio, the Prior Analytics describes the syllogism in general, I lien go on to causes. His response is that the causes and principles with
and the other books on logic focus on particular species of syllogisms. The Pos- which one must begin are those that demonstrate the properties of physical
terior Analytics considers scientific, demonstrative, and necessary syllogisms; things easily grasped by means of their operations. He dwells on other mat-
the Topics focuses on the probable or contingent syllogism; and the Elenchi ters concerning method as well.
concentrates on the false and sophistic syllogisms. The Prior Analytics studies Rubio also discusses the principles of natural corporeal beings. He briefly
the nature and division of the syllogism. Moreover, the book formulates the
rules to convert imperfect modes into perfect ones (of the first figure) and 65. Sec Waller Redmond, "Logica y ciencia en la Logica mexicana de Rubio," Quipu.
lievlsta latinoamericana de historia de las ciencias y la tecnologta (January-April, 1984), in
Redmond and Beuchot, i.a Idgica mexicana en elsiglo deoro, n. l, pp. 273 ff.
64. See Mauricio Beuchot, El problema de los universale (Mexico: UN AM, 1982), 66. See Mauricio Heuehol, "l.os lopicos dialogicos en la IJyicii mexicana de Anlonio
passim. Kuliio," I'liilosoi'hica (Valparaiso, Chile), forthcoming,
88 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico
Sixteenth Century: Scholastics 89

deals with the modes and limits of things (i.e., their limits or the incipit and
that the faculties are distinguished in terms of their objects. He studies the
the destinit of each). Rubio discusses Aristotle's definition according to which
facuities of the vegetative, sensible, and rational soul, especially, understand-
principles are not made from other things but compose other things. Then he
ing. He concludes with a discussion of the soul separated from the body.
moves on to discuss the contrariety that is found between principles. Contra-
Following Aristotle's order, Rubio next studies generation, corruption, al-
riety is important because it allows change and movement that takes place
teration, increase and decrease, the combination of simple elements to form
where there is matter, form, and the privation of form. He considers typically
composites, and the primary qualities of simple elements. He discusses the
Scholastic issues: whether matter is one and the same for all physical and
subject and terms of generation (a quo and ad quern) as well as substantial
natural things, and whether it is merely potentiality or has some act by
generation and alteration. Corruption is established to be a power of sublu-
virtue of which it can subsist independently from form and its properties.
nary bodies, their relation to generation; that is, how a body is broken down
Concerning form, Rubio investigates whether it derives from the potentiality into its raw material. Rubio studies the degrees and subject of alteration, by
of matter, whether it can subsist without matter (for example, in the case of explaining how nutrition influences the growth of living beings. He goes on
the human soul), whether there is a multiplicity or unity of forms in the sub- to a discussion of rarefaction and condensation, action and reaction, and the
stantial composite, etc. He also questions whether privation is only an entity mixtures or combinations that appear in composite entities. Rubio also dis-
of reason or whether some kind of reality corresponds to it. cusses the primary qualities of elements and explores whether they are sub-
Rubio also discusses nature and causes. He examines Aristotle's remarks stantial or accidental forms and how they exist in the elements. He continues
on existence, essence, and the division of causes (the four Aristotelian with the problem of the reciprocai generation of elements and the tempera-
causes: material, formal, efficient, and final cause), as well as first and second ments of composite bodies. Rubio concludes with the problem of whether
types of causality. To this he adds something on the exemplary cause, which one thing can be reproduced with the same numerical identity (and he adds
he considers to be related to the formal cause. He also studies chance and interesting remarks that anticipate present advances in biology such as
fate. Following the Scholastic and Aristotelian order of exposition, he moves clones).
to the infinite (whether it is actual or potential and whether it can be known
Finally Rubio comes to the books on the heavens and the universe. He
by man), place and time, the vacuum and the continuum, the relation be-
touches upon the elements that compose the cosmos; namely, the four phys-
tween the mover and moved, the phenomenon of motion in its entirety, du-
ical essences, which are water, air, fire, and earth, as well as the fifth essence,
ration, the beginning of everything, and the Prime Mover. Rubio ends this
heaven. Here he discusses the nature of the universe, its divisions and prop-
section with a discussion of straight movement, reflection, and violent
erties; the definition, movements, and properties of celestial bodies, as well as
movement.
the elements and their relations. Anticipating Leibniz and his universal opti-
He opens his discussion of the soul by asking whether the study of the
mism, Rubio states that the nature of the universe is the perfection that is
soul is compatible with physics. He then gives an account of how the study of
characteristic of the creature; heavenly beings are even more perfect than
physics is divided and what it is for. He studies the nature or definition of the
sublunar beings, and celestial bodies are incorruptible and incapable of being
soul and its classes: vegetative, sensible, and rational or spiritual. The pri-
generated. Philosophical argument cannot prove that there is only this uni-
mary issue concerning the relations of the soul is how these relations consti-
verse and not many others. Through faith, however, we can conclude that it
tute one soul in a human body. Rubio concludes that this is so because what
is more convenient to believe that there is only this one. On the other hand,
is most perfect can comprise and realize the most imperfect and its corre-
and contrary to the beliefs of the ancients, ceiestial bodies are not animated.
sponding functions. Next he considers animation; that is, whether the soul
Therefore, living things are more perfect than celestial ones. Rubio accepts
has a particular site in the body or whether it informs the entire body and
I hat the stars influence earthly things such as minerals, animals, and even
how it can do this. Rubio then discusses the difficulties surrounding the issue
humans; however, he rejects the idea that future events can be known by
of the faculties of the soul: (1) Are the faculties distinct from the soul? (2)
menus of the stars because he holds that angels, not the stars, are responsible
How the faculties can be distinguished from the soul? (3) How can the facul-
lor ihe movements of celestial bodies. Rubio closes wilh a section on the four
ties be distinguished from each other? Rubio's response to the l.isi question is
elements mentioned earlier .mil says ih.u earth is Ihe center of the universe.
90 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Sixteenth Century: Scholastics 91

In accordance with traditional ideas on cosmology and despite the fact that and Aliqua notatu digna super Commentaria P.D.F. Toleti in libros Aristotelis De gen-

several scientists of the time already had stated that it moved from west to eratione et corruptione.

east, he maintains that the earth is static because of its gravity and inclination. Arias is more original in other works where he not only adds issues and
Although Rubio never completed the metaphysics he had envisioned, his scholia to ancient and medieval authors (Aristotle, Euclid, Juan de Sacro-
coursebook for philosophy is extensive. In spite of the contemporary rele- broso) but also personal observations and analyses. For example, he dis-
vance of his work in logic and ontology, it is fair to say that his cosmology cusses the calendar, the construction of clocks, and meteorological and astro-
and physics are outdated, burdened by a tradition that resisted the advances nomical phenomena in the manuscript, In libros Aristotelis De coelo scolia
of experimental science. quaedam et praedpuae de sphera mundi partim ex veterum astronomorum partim ex
recentiorem doctrina et observatione collectus per doctissimum P. Antonio Arias, Soci-
etatis Jesu. He also left an interesting treatise, De lingua originali, written while
Antonio Arias he taught the Bible. Arias was a remarkable linguist and philologist. In his
This philosopher was born in Valladolid, Spain, in 1565 and died in Mex- works on biblical exegesis, he uses the official Latin text (Versio Vulgata) and
ico on 10 July 1603." He entered the Society of Jesus on 16 October 1581, also considers the Hebrew, Aramaic (which was called 'Chaldean' during
and he was among the first and most eminent Jesuits who traveled to New Arias's time), Greek (the Versio Septuagintae), and other Latin texts. Motivated
Spain. He taught at the Colegio de San Pedro y San Pablo where he was well- by this erudition, he engaged in the search for the original human language.
respected. He also occupied several positions in the Mexican province of the His work is a prelude to later works on the philosophy of language.
Society of Jesus, among others as Secretary and Procurator of the Congrega-
tion of the Annunciation. Although he died at the age of thirty-nine, he left
behind a considerable number of writings.
At the Colegio de San Pedro y San Pablo, Arias taught philosophy and
theology. Within the field of philosophy, he devoted himself especially to
cosmology or natural philosophy, leaving several remarkable philosophical
works on these matters.68
His known philosophical works consist primarily of class notes in which
he shows little originality, closely following the Spanish Jesuit Francisco de
Toledo;6' on occasion he merely summarizes Toledo. At other times he com-
ments and defends Toledo's doctrines, resorting to the authority of Aristotle,
Aquinas, Pedro de Fonseca, and Domingo de Soto. Only on rare occasions
does he offer important doctrines of his own. His work on philosophy in-
cludes: Illustris explanatio Commentariorum P.D. Francisci Toleti, S.J. in octo libros
Aristotelis De physica Auscultatione per Reverendum Admodum Patrem Antonium
Arias, ejusdum Societatis et Philosophiae in celebri Mexicanrum Accidentia professorem

67. See Mauricio Beuchot, "Arias, Antonio, S.J..," in Encidopedia de la Iglesia Catdlicu
en Mexico, ed. J. R. Alvarez, vol. 1 (Mexico: Encidopedia de Mexico, 1982), pp. 330-31;
Alegre, Historia de la Provincia, vol. 1. See also A. Perez de Rivas, Cronica y historia de la
Provincia de la Compania de Jesus de Mexico en Nueva Espana (Mexico: n.p., 1896).
68. See J. E. Uriarte and M. Lecina, Biblioteca de escritores de la Compania de JtsAs
pertenecientes a la antigua asistencia de Espana desde sus origenes hasta el ana de 177 i (M. 111 ii 11
n.p., 1925-1930).
69. See GaEegoS Rocafull, El pensamiento mexicano, pp. 287-89.
Seventeenth Century 93

believed in their intellectual mission and strove for t h e well-being of t h e


whole of society.
Nonetheless, a general feeling of stagnation prevailed. Figures such as
Friar J u a n de Zapata y Sandoval, Don Carlos de Sigiienza y Gongora, and
Sister J u a n a Ines de la Cruz became active in the fight against this decay. Oc-
tavio Paz complains about the lack of philosophical and theological depth
during this period, both in Spain and in Mexico:

The doctrine had been established and the important thing was to put it into
practice. The Church became immobilized in Europe and was always on its
guard. Scholasticism defends itself badly, like the heavy Spanish ships which
were prey to the lighter Dutch and English ones. The decadence of European
i|f§ The Seventeenth Century Catholicism coincides with its Hispanic American zenith: it spreads through
new lands the moment it stops being creative. It offers a preformed philosophy
and a petrified faith, and therefore the originality of the new believers has no
possibility of expressing itself. Their participation is passive. The fervor and
depth of Mexican religious feeling contrast with the relative poverty of its
product. We do not possess great religious poetry, or an original philosophy,
and we do not have even one important mystic or reformer. 2

I
t is extremely difficult to provide a well-balanced interpretation of sev-
enteenth-century Mexico. On t h e one hand, t h e seventeenth century New Spain was certainly dependent o n t h e latest research from Europe, b u t
can be seen as a period of peace and contentment, a period of economic this does n o t m e a n that there was n o original work being carried out in New
prosperity and of political stability; it even appears to be a century in which Spain, especially in the areas of Scholastic philosophy, the newly introduced
knowledge was not only passed on but also developed in n e w directions. On modern philosophy (Bacon, Descartes, etc.), and hermetic philosophy.
t h e other hand, w e also k n o w that t h e lower classes were unjustly oppressed Fernando Benttez characterizes the complex situation of seventeenth-
and that there existed a marked degree of absolutism. The level of culture century Mexico in the following way:
was comparable to Spain's, but the fruits of culture were only available to
New Spain was not the prosperous, peaceful country the historians who love
Spaniards and criollos w h o supported the clergy. the viceregal period would like us to imagine. It was a huge colony and its pros-
The Mexican clergy of t h e seventeenth c e n t u r y found itself in a far m o r e perity was monopolized by the high clergy, the landowners, the merchants,
comfortable situation t h a n that of the brave missionaries from the previous and the miners: it was a far cry from a just, ordered, and calm realm. There
were two bloody uprisings in Mexico City, one in 1624 and another in 1692.
century. The task of t h e clergy was n o longer to w i n souls for t h e true faith
Hundreds of rebels had their heads cut off. The Inquisition organized its cruel
b u t rather to maintai n b o t h t h e learning and order a m o n g t h e multitude of
indigenous peoples w h o h a d b e e n taught t h e Christian doctrine in a very
2. "La doctrina estaba hecha y se trataba sobre todo de vivirla. La iglesia se inmovi-
superficial way. As a result, t h e clergy grew, w i t h m a n y people embracing llzaba en Europa, a la defensiva. La escolastica se defiende mal, como las pesadas naves
this w a y of life n o t because they felt a true vocation for it but because they ii'spanolas, presa de las mas ligeras de holandeses e ingleses. La decadencia del catoli-
vismo europeo coincide con su apogeo hisparioamericano; se extiende en tierras
were attracted by t h e t h e splendid life one could lead in a convent.
nuevas en el momento en el que ha dejado de ser creador. Ofrece una filosoffa hecha y
Spaniards a n d criollos, even half-breeds a n d Indians, could be found in Una fe petrificada, de modo que la originalidad de los nuevos creyentes no encuentra
these convents. 1 Nevertheless, even during this period, w h e n rules rapidly ocaslon de inanifestarse. Su adhesion es pasiva. El fervor y la profundidad de la reli-
Cinsiil.ul inexicana contrastan con la relativa pobreza de sus creaciones. No poseemos
became lax and decadent attitudes flourished, there were priests w h o truly una gran poesi'a religiosa, como no tenemos una filosoffa original, ni contamos con un
solo nifslico o reformador de importancia." Octavio Paz, "Un mundo en otro," in El
1. See I. A. Leonard, La epoca barroca en el Mexico colonial (Mexico: I'Cli, 197-1), ptrtgrinotnsu patrta, Mexico, in La abrade Octavio Paz, vol. l (lelmpressloii, Mexico: FCE,
pp. 74-75. 1989), pp. 111-12.

•>.'
94 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o S e v e n t e e n t h Century 95

autos de fe, the indigenous population rebelled in the north, the Isthmus of los and Indians came to occupy important public positions as well. Friar J u a n
Tehuantepec, and Yucatan, and if there were long periods of peace, this peace
de Zapata y Sandoval, an Augustinian, soon became well k n o w n because of
was the result of imprisonment, exile, the garrotte, the gallows, inquisitional
his excellent treatise o n distributive justice. Don Carlos de Sigtienza y Gon-
burnings, and interiorized repression. 3
gora was a criollo whose studies on the Indigenous culture became one of the
Yet during this period, w h e n injustices were so often committed by the pow- foundations of Mexican nationalism.
erful members of society, there were some members of the intellectual clergy If w e bear in mind these examples of intellectual capacity and achieve-
w h o raised their voices against such injustices. This is the case, for example, ment, it becomes clear why, at the beginning of the century, Bernardo de Bal-
of Bishop Palafox y Mendoza, w h o wrote a defense of the indigenous popu- buena commented favorably upon culture in Mexico. Addressing a potential
lation. 4 Above all, he defended t h e m against the alcaldes mayores and corregi- visitor to Mexico City, he writes of the University:
dores w h o had taken t h e place of the encomienda in tormenting the Indians. In
Si quisiera recreation, si gusto tierno
this connection, w e may also m e n t i o n Friar Miguel Aguayo, a Franciscan; de entendimiento, ciencia y letras graves,
Father Francisco Coello, a Jesuit; and Friar Alonso Norefia, a Dominican trato divino, don del cielo eterno;
w h o had been associated with Friar Bartolome de las Casas. They voiced si en espiritu heroico a las suaves
their disagreement with those w h o were opposed to the liberation of the In- musas se apliCa, y con estilo agudo
de sus tesoros Ies ganziia las Haves;
dians. Yet, in spite of some rather conservative policies concerning the rights
si desea vivir y no ser mudo,
of the Indians, certain macehuales, or poor indigenous people, held important
tratar con sabios que es tratar con gentes,
positions during the seventeenth century: "This was the case of Don Nicolas fuera del campo torpe y pueblo rudo;
del Puerto, an Indian, a university lecturer of rhetoric and t h e n of canon law, aqui hallara mas hombres eminentes
Canon of Mexico and Bishop of Oaxaca. He was called the Cicero of the en toda ciencia y todas facultades,
courts of Mexico and the Mexican Solomon. We find another example of que arenas lleva el Gange en sus corrientes;
monstruos en perfection de habilidades,
this in the case of the Indian Jesuit J u a n Esteban w h o was born in Tepot-
y en las letras humanas y divinas
zotlan. It is said that he was so industrious, almost instinctively so, w h e n
eternos rastreadores de verdades.
teaching others to read and write and became so famous for this that chil- Precianse las escuelas salmantinas,
dren were sent from Spain to learn with him." 5 During this period other criol- las de Alcala, Lovaina y las de Atenas
de sus letras y ciencias peregrinas;
3. "La Nueva Espafia no era un pais prospero y pacffico como afirman los escritores precianse de tener las aulas Uenas
amantes del virreinato. Era una enorme colonia cuya prosperidad monopolizabaii el de mas borlas, que bien sera posible,
alto clero, los latifundistas, los comerciantes y los mineros, y de ningun modo un reino mas no en letras mejores ni tan buenas;
justo, ordenado y tranquilo. Dos motines sangrientos estallaron en la ciudad de Mexico
en 1624 y en 1692. Centenares de negros rebeldes fueron degollados. La inquisition que cuanto llega a ser inteligible,
organizo sus crueles autos de fe, los indios se rebelaron en el norte, en el istmo de cuanto un entendimiento humano encierra,
Tehuantepec y en Yucatan, y si hubo largos periodos de paz, esta paz la impusieron la y con su luz se puede hacer visible,
carcel, el destierro, el garrote, la horca, las hogueras inquisitoriales y la represion interi- los gallardos ingenios desta tierra
orizada." F. Benitez, Los demonios en el convento. Sexo y religion en la Nueva Espafia (Mexico:
Era, 1985), p. 13. 10 alcanzan, sutilizan y perciben
4. See J. de Palafox y Mendoza, De la naturaleza del indio, in Obras del llustisimo, Exce- en duke paz, o en amable guerra. 6
lentisimo y Venerable Siervo de Dios Don Juan de Palafox y Mendoza, vol. 10 (Madrid: D.
Gabriel Ramirez, 1762), pp. 444-93. 11 you want recreation, the tender flavor
5. "[E]se fue el caso de don Nicolas del Puerto, indio, catedratico de retorica, y of understanding, science and grave letters,
luego de canones en la universidad, candnigo de Mexico y obispo de Oaxaca, que file and a divine treatise, the gift of eternal heaven;
llamado el Ciceron de los estrados de Mexico y el Salomon mexicano, y en otro orden,
il you apply yourself with heroic spirit to the soft muses,
el del jesuita indio Juan Esteban, natural de Tepotzotlan, quien 'tuvo tal tadustria, casi
instinto, de ensenar a leer y a escribir y tuvo en ello tanto credito, que desde Espafia le and catch the keys io their treasures with a line style;
trafan nihos para que lograsen sis ensenanza." GallegOS Rocafull, Blpensamicnto mexi-
cano, p. 51. (.. It. ile ll.illiuen.i, (imndiTil mexiciiiid, .M i-il, (Mexico: UNAM, 1934), pp. 59-61.
96 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o
S e v e n t e e n t h Century 97

if you desire to live and not be silent, el Serafm, en quien esta el retrato
and to deal with wise men, that is, gentlemen, del nudo celestial de Dios hecho hombre;
away from the sleepy countryside and boorish people— con los que de su misma regla y trato
here you will find men who are eminent siguen descalzos de virtud la senda,
in every science and all the faculties, y al mundo dan de pie ventero ingrato.
more of them than the grains of sand Del famoso Augustino la gran prenda,
carried in the streams of the Ganges; en santidad y letras rico erario,
monsters in perfection of skills del libre mundo concertada rienda;
and in divine and human letters la Compania y santo relicario
eternal searchers of truths. del nombre de Jesus, su gran concierto
Salamantine schools pride themselves, de profesos, colegio y seminario,
t un
•mi'
those of Alcala, Louvain, and of Athens
regarding their peregrine letters and sciences;
adonde al cielo vivo, al mundo muerto,
esta el unico fruto que pariste
• lih!
they pride themselves on having classrooms full de tu sangre y virtud precioso injerto;
E of more hoods, which might very well be the case, angel en todo, porque en todo fuiste
but not in better or nearly as good letters su madre, y alma y cuerpo le criaste
than what gets to be intelligible, con la doctrina y leche que le diste.

it
inasmuch as a human understanding involves, La estrecha regla, donde en fino engaste
and with light becomes visible resplandece la gloria del Carmelo,
the gallant minds or this land sin que el brocado entre el sayal se gaste;
reach it, made subtle and perceive del pio Mercedario el santo celo
in sweet peace, or in kind war. en rescatar, conforme a su institute,
los cuerpos y las almas para el cielo;
Balbuena's descriptions are exaggerated. Nevertheless, it is evident that a
y del monje antiqufsimo de luto
rich intellectual atmosphere existed in Mexico. This despite the fact that both que en el monte Casino por su mano
• l«lkll

the theory and the practice of justice were n o longer w h a t they h a d been rompio de Apolo el simulacro bruto;
during the previous century. Overall, w h e n compared to the sixteenth cen- de la fria Nursia alumno soberano,
ill!
tury, the seventeenth century is less impressive. It is also interesting to note hasta en el nombre singular bendito,
Ill'
nueva grandeza al suelo mexicano. 7
II! that the great majority of the testimonies that were supposedly written dur-
in. ing this century have disappeared. These testimonies were produced at the From the Spanish torch that, once lit,
university as well as at the colleges of the religious orders. These colleges illuminated the world and reformed the earth,
were k n o w n for their dedication to both science and virtue. Here we have also born from Guzman's lineage,
Guzman, that holy trumpet at whose war cry
Balbuena's florid description:
the intellect trembles, and the land rejoices and sees
De la espanola antorcha que encendida more stars than the eighth heaven encloses.
x
alumbra el mundo y reformo la tierra, Admire his temple, house, and riches,
tambien del tronco de Guzman nacida, as well as the pulpit that gave his order its name,
el clarin santo, a cuyo son de guerra and instantly inspires learning and virtue.
tiembla el intelecto, el suelo goza y mira and to which humility was made renown
mas luces que el octavo cielo encierra. by the Seraphim, in whom the portrait is found
Su templo, casa y su riqueza admira, of the celestial knot of God made man;
y el piilpito que dio a su regla el nombre with those who of that same rule and agreement of his
y a soplos, letras y virtud inspira; follow barefoot Ihe path of virtue,
y a la que de humildad puso renombre
7. 11)1(1., |)|). I l l) 12.
98 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Seventeenth Century 99

and to the world they give standing up an ungrateful innkeeper. Fortunately, not all documents from this period were mishandled in this
From the famous Augustine the great pledge, way; the Biblioteca Nacional has possession of a commentary on the Senten-
a rich treasury in holiness and learning, cias written by Friar Pedro de Leyva. He tries to stress the importance of the
the harmonious rein of the free world;
doctrine of Duns Scotus, the principal doctor of his Order. His text begins
the Company and holy relic
of the name of Jesus, his great symphony with the following words: "Incipiunt proemiales quaestiones super prologum
of professed followers, schools, and seminaries, Primi Sententiarum a nostro clarissimo necnon sapientissimo Patre Fratre
where to the heaven alive, to the world dead Petro de Leiva, nuper et acutissime (quia scotice) enucleatae in hoc Sanctae
there is only fruit you gave birth Barbarae. . . . Angelopolitano coenobio, Die Januarii 17a. Anno Dni 1620."
from your blood and virtue, beautiful blend; This commentary was written in the Convent of Puebla in 1620.
angel in everything, because in all you were
his mother, and soul, and body you raised for him There also exists documentation on the journey that the famous Friar
with the doctrine and milk that you gave him Buenaventura Salinas made across Mexico. Friar Buenaventura was born in
The narrow ruler, where the fine mounting Lima and had held numerous positions in the Order. One such position took
shines the glory of Carmelo, him to Mexico in 1646. He was a great defender of the criollos and wrote an
without the brocade between the sackcloth wearing out; Apologia por los criollos. Another work, Cursus philosophiae, was to be published
of the pious Mercedary the holy concern
in Rome, but it was never printed and all traces of it have disappeared. Sali-
to rescue, in accordance with its institution,
the bodies and the souls for heaven; nas died in Cuernavaca in 1653.
and of the very ancient monk in mourning Another Curso on Scotistic philosophy was written by Friar Francisco Cruz,
who at Mount Casino by his hand who at the beginning of the century had crossed over from the province of
broke from Apollo the brutish rehearsal; San Jose to that of San Diego. In this second province he taught philosophy;
of the cold Nursia sovereign student,
the Curso is a compilation of his lectures (the manuscript has been lost). At the
until the blessed singular name
new greatness to the Mexican soul. lime of his death in 1655, Friar Francisco was a censor for the Inquisition.
In 1658, a Scotus Chair was created at the University for the Franciscans.
Our study of the philosophy of New Spain during the seventeenth cen- Athough it was a Chair of Theology, it greatly influenced the growth of Scotis-
tury will concentrate on the philosophical positions of the most important I ic philosophy. The philosophy produced by those who held this Chair is rig-
religious orders and the most prominent members of the secular clergy. The orous and sophisticated, and could even be termed 'subtle', an epithet that
philosophical position of Sister Juana fries de la Cruz will also be considered. had also been applied to Scotus. Use of this epithet was widespread; it even
appears in this humorous matinal song from the Cathedral of Mexico (1654):

Franciscans A los cojos, los difuntos


hechos justillos se siguen,
In the seventeenth century, Franciscan philosophers became more promi- mas palidos que el temor
nent than in the previous century because they were no longer entirely ab- y mas que la noche tristes.
sorbed by the evangelization activities that had been entrusted to them. At Reparando de la vida
comas, apices y tildes,
the beginning of the century, Friar Jose de Gabalda, born in Valencia, finished
ya Valerios por lo flaco,
his studies in Mexico. He taught in Guatemala, where he left a manuscript, ya Escotos por lo sutiles,
Comentario a las "Sentencias" (a commentary on the work of Pedro Lombardo). con prolundas reverencias
According to Beristain, after Gabalda died, his work was sold as wrapping .i Pedro can tan los Kyries,
paper, due to an oversight on the part of Convent authorities.8
i'il. (Mexico: I'uonlo Cultural, 1947), p. M\, n. \2M; and Gallegos Rocafull, El pen-
\,titticiilo iiifxictiiio, p. 117.
8. Sec J. M Ucrislnin do Sou/a, Diblioteca llispmio Ameriainu Sfplcnirioiial, vol. 2, it'd
100 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o S e v e n t e e n t h Century 101

y han dado en querer hacer catorce cuestiones propuestas por los RR. PP. velemitas. He was a specialist in canon
de Requiem a los maitines. 9 law, philosophy, and theology. 12

To the crippled, the deceased


crammed facts follow,
Dominicans
more pale than fear
and more sad than nights.
The Dominicans were active both in teaching and writing at their colleges
Caring about life
commas, iotas, and tildes, and at the University (the St. Thomas Chair was founded in 1617).
already Valerios because they are so thin,
already Escotos because they are so subtle,
Antonio de Hinojosa
with deep reverence
to Pedro they sing the Kyries,
The first major philosophical figure a m o n g the Dominicans of t h e m sev-
and they now desire to make
Requiem to the matinal. enteenth century was Friar Antonio de Hinojosa. Hinojosa entered the Order
in 1590 and taught arts and theology in the Convent of Santo Domingo. In
Don Emeterio Valverde Tellez mentions a work by Friar J u a n de Almanza 1603 he became a lecturer of philosophy there. In that same year he was a
called Disputationes una cum sectionibus in universam Aristotelis philosophiam, octo candidate for the presentatura, and his order suggested he teach theology.
libros comprehensam, anno 1660. Valverde says that this text was found in the Hinojosa also studied at the Universidad de Mexico, and in 1606 he re-
Franciscan Convent in Queretaro. 1 0 He also mentions another philosophical ceived the degree of Master or Doctor in Theology. Afterwards h e was ap-
work written by Friar Martin de Aguirre, whic h has since been lost, a Ldgica. pointed Prior of the Convent Of Coyoacan w h e r e the historian Antonio de
On the first page this passage was found: "Incipiunt trienales scholasticae Remesal visited him. Remesal describes the Convent in this way: "I observed
controversiae u t i n a m feliciter super universam, naturalem, rationalem et that it was closer to a university cloister t h a n to a Convent of friars." 13 This he
supernaturalem philosophiam iuxta m e n t e m subtilissimi praeceptoris, N. attributed to the great a m o u n t of studying that w e n t on, and the austere way
Joannis Duns Scoti. . . per Fratrem M a r t i n u m ab Aguirre liberalium artium of life of its inhabitants. So great was Hinojosa's intellectual and moral
lectorem elaboratae . . . in hoc divi Bernardini vulgo de Xochimilco coenobio stature that, four years after receiving his degree, o n 10 November 1610, he
a n n o Domini 1687 mense februario die vigesimo quinto hora n o n a ante was listed (with Friar Luis Vallejo) as candidate for the rectorship of the Uni-
meridiem." versity. However, due to obscure legal motives hinted at by the outgoing rec-
This manuscript (1687) contained two works on logic; the Summulae and tor and ratified by the Real Audiencia, a decison was reached that prohibited
the Dialectica magna, copied by Friar Bias de Carmona y de San Jose. Accord- clergymen from becoming rectors. 14
ing to Valverde, it was found in the Museo del Padre Chaparro in Temascal- Hinojosa published a book in Madrid in 1627 called Directorium decissionum
cingo, but Gallegos Rocafull disputes this claim. 11 regularium circa ambiguitates constitutionum on the rights of people w h o were
Finally, we come to Friar Andres Borda (or Bordas), a Mexican w h o be- members ,of religious orders. In it he makes reference to another book ready
came well k n o w n at the university, successfully holding the Scotus Chair for for print: Clypeus thomistarum ex quaestionibus metaphysicis et theologicis affabre
twenty years. His philosophical manuscripts, De qualitate qualificabilium propo- compactumP Hinojosa's interest in metaphysics is evident from the title of this
sitionum and Commentaria in Scoti quodlibeta, have been lost. His only pub- work.
lished work (1708) was Solution de la Realy Pontificia Universidad de Mexico a las
12.Ibid.
9. Nocturno III/III, in Poetas novohispanos, segundo siglo (1621-1721), Parte primera, ed. 13. "|N|ote que mas parecia claustro de universidad que Convento de frailes." A. de
Mendez Plancarte (Mexico: UNAM, 1944), p. 82. Remesal, Historia de la provincia de San Vicente de Chiapa y Guatemala de la esclarecida Orden
10. See Valverde Tellez, Criticafilosdftca("Mexico: Sues, de Fco. Din/, do I .ci'in, 1904), p. 51. ile nuestrogloriow Padre Santo Domingo de Guzman (Madrid, 1619).
11. See Valverde Tellez, Bibliografiafilosdficamexicana, pp. 21-24; Galli'icos Rocafull, 14. See Mauricio Mcucliol and A. Mclcon, Los dominkos en la Realy Pontificia Univer-
sidad de Mexico, (Mexico: Oudrioos Doniiiiicuios, 1984) p. 18, n, 10.
El pemamiento mexicano, p. 318.
I'>. lU'tisliiiu iiiciuioiis ilils, anil so docs .1, (iarcfa Iia/halcela HihliOfirnJJit mexicana
102 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Seventeenth Century 103

Francisco Naranjo and intelligence." Naranjo's name appears in 1663 in the Adas of the provin-
cial chapter houses of the Order, on a list of the dead. It is, however, clear
Another important Dominican was Friar Francisco Naranjo, a man fa- that he had died earlier, probably in 1655.
mous for his outstanding memory and intelligence. He was a criollo born in Another well-known Dominican of the times was Friar Jose Calderon. He
Mexico City. In his youth he had been posted in the Castle of San Juan de was born in Antequera de Oaxaca and received a scholarship to attend the
Ultra. He entered the Dominican Order in 1604. He studied in Mexico at the College of Santa Maria de Todos los Santos. He received his doctoral degree
Convent of Santo Domingo, and he taught at different convents belonging to in theology at the university and was then ordained and entered the Do-
the Order and then at the University. He began teaching at Santo Domingo minican Order. He was a lecturer at various convents and also a Prior.
in 1616, lecturing on arts. He was promoted to Lecturer of Theology, first in Valverde mentions his work, Compendium philosophiae Thomisticae in usum
the Convent of Puebla in 1620 and then in the Convent of Mexico in 1624, Fratrum Praedicatorum S. Hippolyti de Oaxaca, which was a summary of Domingo
where he taught for several years. de Soto's coursebook for philosophy and was used in the colleges of that
In 1631 he tried for a Chair but failed to obtain it. He tried again in 1636, province for a long time. Valverde thinks it was printed,18 but it has been lost.
but once again he failed. It was only in 1638 that he was named to the St. Thus, most of the works on philosophy by Dominican friars in the seven-
Thomas Chair, which he held until 1653. For many years, people remem- teenth century which we have mentioned have been lost. The only docu-
bered that in his two unsuccessful attempts for the Chair he had impressively ment we have to give us a general idea of the development of Thomist phi-
recited several texts from memory, including Aquinas's Summa as well as a losophy during this period is Naranjo's Teologia. Information about the rest
series of other works by Aquinas and others. The written record of these ex- must be gathered from second-hand accounts.
traordinary events still exists.16 Naranjo's teaching career was cut short when
he was named Bishop of San Juan de Puerto Rico. Before this, however, he
Augustinians
had held two other positions within the Order as Regente de Estudios and Cen-
sor for the Inquisition. Like the Dominicans, the Augustinians devoted a great amount of their
According to Beristain, when Naranjo was named bishop, he burned his time to teaching during the colonial period. During the seventeenth century,
scholastic manuscripts saying, "This is no longer necessary, all a bishop needs this devotion to pedagogy remained strong, yet the hours spent teaching
is the Book of Christ." Yet, according to other sources, there was a folio vol- decreased.
ume in the Convent of Santo Domingo which Naranjo wrote, the Teologia en
lengua castellana. This manuscript was removed from the Convent by mem-
Diego Basalenque
bers who considered such subject matter inappropriate for the cloister. Al-
though the manuscript was lost for a long time, it has recently resurfaced, Among the Augustinians of the seventeenth century, Friar Diego Basa-
thereby affording us a firsthand appreciation of Naranjo's vast knowledge lenque occupies a central position. He not only wrote a series of historical
texts, but he also produced a number of philosophical studies at the beginning
del siglo XVI (Mexico: FCE, 1954), n. 146, p. 426. Beristain says that Hinojosa had pre- of the century. He was born in Salamanca, Spain, in 1577 and came to Mex-
pared a Clypeus thomistarum before the author of Clypeus Theologlae Thomisticae was born. ico to study, ultimately settling in the state of Michoacan.19 Here he taught
Beristain probably meant Juan Bautista Gonet (1616-1681), a French Dominican who
wrote five volumes of Clypeus theologiae thomisticae (Cologne, 1671). He does not take arts and then theology. He wrote on logic and physics and also prepared a
into account that long before Hinojosa, the Hungarian Dominican, Petrus Niger
(1434-1483), had written a Clypeus thomistarum contra modernos et scotistas, published in 17. The author of this book found it in the Biblioteca Nacional de Mexico, and it
Venice in 1481, and a Clypeus thomistarum adversus omnes doctrinae doctoris angelici obtrec- will be published by the UNAM.
tatores, published in Venice in 1504. 18. See Valverde Telle/., Apuntaciones historicas, p. 425.
16. See G. R. G. Conway, Friar Francisco Naranjo and the Old University of Mexico 19. lie wrote a history of Michoacan. See D. Basalenque, Historia de la provincia de
(Mexico: Gante Press, 1939); A. Zahar Vergnra, "Frai Francisco Naranjo," Anuario de San Nicola's de lolentino de Michoacan, del Orden de N. P. San Agustin, Aho de 1673, ed. J.
Filosofia del Seminario de Invest ic/aciones Filosdficas de la Facullad de Filosofla y l.elras de la Bravo Ug&Tte (Mexico: I'omia, 1963).
UNAM, 1 (1943): 47-90.
104 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Seventeenth Century 105

coursebook for philosophy. His work on logic is the Summa summularum et terms, then discussing enunciations before moving on to consequences or
totius diakctkae Aristotelis per Fr. Didacum Basalenque Salmanticensem Ordinis syllogisms. He explores the nature and division of the terms; their single
Eremitarum S. P. nostri Augustini Anno Domini 1602 mensis julii. It is a com- property, that is, signification; and the properties these acquire within a
pendium on dialectic that focuses on studies of Aristotle's De interpretatione proposition, that is, supposition. He examines the different parts of an enun-
and Posterior Analytics. Valverde Tellez and Gallegos Rocafull say that this ciation, particularly the noun and the verb; he analyzes the statement in re-
work can be found in the library of the Augustinian Convent of Morelia,20 lation to quantity (universal, particular, etc.), quality (affirmative or nega-
but it is found in fact in the Augustinian Archives of the City of Mexico.21 tive), and opposition, equipollence and conversion. He also studies modal,
Basalenque also wrote the following work on natural philosophy: Commen- expositive, and hypothetical propositions. He works on the different modes
taria in octo libros Physicae, De coelo et mundo et Metheoris. Per Fr. Didacum Basalen- of knowledge such as definition, division or classification, and argumenta-
quem Ordinis Eremitarum S. P. nostri Augustini. Anno Domini 1603. Die 22 mensis tion, concentrating on syllogistic argumentation.
mail. This manuscript contains Physica, De coelo et mundo, and De metheoris. It In major or dialectical logic, Rueda analyzes the primary issue of the sub-
was kept in the Augustinian Convent of Morelia, and is now in Mexico City. ject of logic. He treats the predicables and studies the universal and its five
Basalenque's coursebook for philosophy is entitled Philosophia ad usum categories: genera, species, differences, properties, and accidents. After this
scholae. Apparently, it was kept first in Charo and later in Morelia, eventually he deals with the predicaments or categories. He begins with the antipredica-
being brought to Mexico City. De contractibus is a work on moral economy to ments, which consist of the modes of predication, that is, univocity, equivoc-
which Valverde Tellez makes reference,22 but which has been lost.23 ity, analogy, and denomination. In his discussion of predicaments, he dis-
cusses quantity, quality, and relations, and he concludes with the so-called
Juan de Rueda postpredicaments, the relations established between predicaments, for ex-
ample, anteriority, simultaneity, posteriority, etc. Regarding the second oper-
Juan de Rueda was Mexican. He lectured on theology at the Colegio de ation, enunciation or proposition, he only discusses its most important prop-
San Pablo in Mexico. Then he competed successfully for the Chair of Rhet- erty, that is, its capacity to be true or false, adding some considerations on the
oric at the University, preparing a Commentarium in orationem Ciceronis pro truth of contingent future propositions. Regarding the third operation, that
Marcello. In 1689 he obtained the Chair of Arts and held this position for is, inference or argumentation, he discusses its different properties or rules
eight years. He died in 1697, leaving the manuscript of a coursebook for phi- and then concentrates on the principal class of argumentation, that is, scien-
losophy, Cursus philosophicus. This manuscript contains the following sec- tific or demonstrative argumentation. He studies its conditions and structure
tions: Summulae, Logica sive dialectica, Physica sive philosophia naturalis; Disputa- and compares it with faith, opinion, and other forms of thought.
tiones in duos libros Aristotelis De coelo et mundo, Disputationes in libros Aristotelis The section on physics begins with a discussion of its object of study and
De anima sive Tractatus de anima, Disputationes metaphysicae, Quaestiunculae in its scientific qualities. Rueda follows the Aristotelian process of exposition. In
tres praecipuos Aristotelis libros De metheoris. This coursebook was written be- the first book he discusses the principles of physical bodies: matter, form, and
tween 1675 and 1677 and can be found in the Biblioteca Nacional of Mexico. privation.. Regarding matter, he speculates on its existence, essence, classes,
Rueda's teachings are highly abbreviated; he includes only the most basic and relations to forms. He adds something on privation and analyzes sub-
notions of logic and deals with them in the traditional order, beginning with stantial union, asking how substantial union takes place in substantial com-
position and how many types of unions exist in it. In the second book, he
20. See Valverde Tellez, Biblografiafilosoficamexicana, p. 26; Gallegos Rocafull, El passes from principles to causes, claiming that causes are a kind of principle
pensatniento mexicarw, pp. 315-16.
21. We wish to thank Father Roberto Jaramillo for letting us study these works. related to being and not just to knowing. He establishes a difference between
One can also consult his book, Los augustinos en Michoacdn, 1602-1652. La difkil formacidn the natural and the violent, and he locates causality between these two cate-
de una provincia (Mexico, 1991).
22. See Valverde Tellez, Biblografia filosdfka mexicana, pp. 27-28. gories, describing it in general terms and relating causes to their effects. He
23. See Redmond, Bibliography of the Philosophy in the Iberian Colonies of America. then proceeds to discuss each of the four Aristotelian causes: final, efficient,
p. 17, n. 128.
formal, ,IIHI nnilciial. lie compares natural or second causes wiili llie first or
106 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Seventeenth Century 107

Supreme Cause and explores the problem of physical predetermination of In closing, we mention one other important Augustinian, Friar Diego de
the former by the latter. He comments on books 3 and 5 of Aristotle's Physics, Villarrubia. He was born in Puebla and taught theology at Valladolid (today
discussing action and passion, the two aspects of movement. He then ana- Morelia). He also taught in Mexico, where he wrote Philosophia scholastico-
lyzes the different classes of movement and discusses various ideas concern- christiana. This manuscript has been preserved in the monastery of Charo.25
ing infinity. Book 4 explores the nature of place, the void, and time. Rueda
concludes with a discussion of two problems, one from book 7 of Aristotle's
Mercedarians
Physics, namely, the problem of action at a distance, and another from book
8, that is, whether or not a creature can be eternal. As one can see, he adds During the seventeenth century, the most important Mercedarian in phi-
new topics (such as infinity and the possibility of creatures being eternal) to losophy was Friar Pedro de Celis. He was born in 1587 in Mexico, entered the
standard Aristotelian and Scholastic discussions. Order of La Merced in 1604, and was then sent to Spain to finish his studies.
Rueda also comments upon those books of Aristotle that discuss the heav- After studying in Alcala and Salamanca, he received a doctoral degree. In
ens, the world, generation and corruption, and something on meteors. These 1613 the Universidad de Mexico recognized this degree. In Spain he studied
were important issues in the seventeenth century. Rueda's "Commentary on the doctrines of the Jesuit Gabriel Vazquez. Vazquez had tried to reconcile
Aristotle's De anima " begins by defining what the soul is and describing its di- Plato with Aristotle, and due to his Augustinian background, he had become
vision into three parts: vegetative, sensible, and rational. He also discusses known as the 'Spanish Augustine'. In Mexico, Celis taught Vazquez's doc-
how the soul informs the body according to its parts. He then analyzes the trine. In 1615 he published two works of his own, Tractatus theologicus in Pri-
sensible part of the soul. This analysis involves an enumeration of the senses, mam partem Divi Thomae, in which he discusses philosophical matters, and
particularly the external senses, and especially sight. An account of the ratio- Laurea Mexicana, sive quaestiones disputatae.26 In 1616 he was awarded the Chair
nal part of the soul is also provided, in which the focus is on understanding of Vespers of Theology, a position he did not hold long because in 1617, at the
and reason. He follows Aristotle very closely, dividing understanding into ac- age of 30, he died.
tive and passive (or possible) parts. He explains the process of cognition and Friar Diego Rodriguez's accomplishments also deserve mention. He
its result, which is the 'mental verb', a concept or judgment. His "Commen- taught mathematics at the Universidad de Mexico and was one of de
tary" concludes with a discussion of the will, habits, and the divided soul. Sigtienza y Gongora's professors. He contributed more to physics than to phi-
Rueda devotes three disputations to metaphysics. The first concerns pos- losophy. Friar Francisco Hernandez was another important Mercedarian re-
sible entities, or the possibility of an entity, understood as the first step to- puted to be a good philosopher. He was born in Mexico and held various po-
wards studying the relation between essence and existence. The second dis- sitions such as Secretary to the Inspector and Vicar General of the Order of
putation explores the transcendental properties of unity, truth, and goodness La Merced. In 1643 he won the Chair of Arts for four years, a position that
which all entities must possess and the way in which these properties mani- was renewed for another four years and then in 1653 granted to him for life.
fest themselves. The third disputation is incomplete but was intended to give He also taught theology at the University lecturing from the text, Relectio the-
an account of predicamental entities, that is, substance and accident. ologica, which he published in 1661. He died the following year.
Rueda's scholarship, "shows that the level of philosophical studies in
Mexico was at the same level as studies in Europe."24 Friar Juan de Rueda is
attentive and receptive to the best Scholastic thought produced during his
Jesuits
time. However, he can be faulted for his negligence of the modern ideas that
Diego de Santisteban, a member of the Society of Jesus at the beginning
were becoming available in the seventeenth century. This was a common of the seventeenth century, left a series of philosophical texts; they are part
weakness among this group of thinkers. Nevertheless, they did develop phi-
losophy in Mexico. 25. Ibid., p. 317.
26. Redmond, Bibliography of the Philosophy in the Iberian Colonies of America, p. 27,
mi. 190-91,
24. Gallegos Rocafull, Elpensamiento mexicano, p, 335.
108 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Seventeenth Century 109

of a commentary he wrote on the Summa theologiae of St. Thomas Aquinas. volumes on natural philosophy which are kept in the Biblioteca Nacional of
The title of this w o r k is Expositio in Primam Secundae Divi Thomae a quaestione Mexico and which contain commentaries on some of Aristotle's works on
18 ad 21 et a 109 ad 114. It was probably written between 1607 and 1609. The physics. The titles of Guerrero's manuscripts are: Commentarii in universam
most philosophical sections of Santisteban's theological commentary are Aristotelis philosophiam, una cum dubiis et quaestionibus generationis et corruptio-
those that discuss human acts (points 18 ff.) and laws (points 90 ff.). nis, vol. 2, Mexico, 1622 and Commentarii in universam A[risto]telis doctrinam De
Another Jesuit of this period was Father Juan de Ledesma who was born anima triplici libra contentam, una cum dubiis et quaestionibus De coelo et mundo et
in Mexico in 1578 and died there in 1637. He held the Chair of Theology at De metheoris, vol. 3. Volume 1 has been lost.29
the Colegio de San Pedro y San Pablo. His major contribution to philosophy is Guerrero's commentary on the Physica, which, following the custom of
found in a manuscript dated 1619; this is a commentary on Aquinas's Summa, his time, he calls philosophia (naturalis), comprises the greater part of vol-
in which truth and falsehood are discussed from a philosophical perspective. ume 2. After a preface on the object of this discipline, in book 1 he discusses
Father Andres de Valencia occupied the Chair of Theology after Ledesma. the principles of natural entities: matter, form, and privation and how matter
He was born in Guanajuato around 1578. He entered the Society of Jesus in and form are joined. In book 2, he discusses natural and artificial entities
1596, and taught theology at the Colegio de San Pedro y San Pablo. There is subject to motion, as well as natural causes. The subjects of book 3 are move-
conclusive evidence that he wrote a philosophical work in three volumes, ment and infinity. In book 4, place, the void, and time are discussed. In book
Patris Andreae de Valentia Societatis Jesu liberalium artium sapientissimi magistri, 5, Guerrero deals with successive movement. In book 6, he writes about
earumque indefese admodum dignissimi professoris Commentaria quatuor quibus continuity and extension as they relate to movement. Book 7 is an explo-
universa Aristotelis Stagirae Logicae comprehenditur, una cum Dialecticis Institution- ration of all that is involved in knowledge of the Supreme Cause. The final
ibus in principio additis quas Summulas nuncupamus. Anno 1609, which suggests book, book 8, is a treatment of the Supreme Cause as the Primum Mobile, the
he also taught philosophy. According to Valverde Tellez, these manuscripts first movement and the first mover. There is also an appendix on violent and
are kept in the Biblioteca Publica of Guadalajara, but Gallegos Rocafull has reflexive movement.
reported that he was not able to locate them there.27 Aristotelian physics was still of great importance during this period, and
Later in the century, Father Francisco Aguilera, who was born in Mexico Guerrero's commentary on De ortu et interitu or De generatione et corruptione
in 1622 and died there in 1666, explored a series of philosophical issues in falls within this tradition. In book 1, he discusses generation, corruption, in-
his treatise on the principles of morality, that is, the ethical principles of crease, alteration, and mixture. In book 2, he discusses the principles of the
human conduct. This treatise is entitled the Tractatus de bonitate et malitia hu- generation of elements, their causes, relationships, and the compounds that
manorum actuum. In it, Aguilera discusses morality in general, as well as good result from them.
and evil from the moral perspective of man's internal acts (those related to In his Commentary on De anima, after a preface on the place Aristotelian
his intelligence or will). physics occupies in the field of philosophy, in book 1 Guerrero provides a
summary of it. In book 2, he discusses the nature of the soul. He develops a
Alonso Guerrero definition of it and discusses its faculties, as well as the relationship that ex-
ists between these faculties and mental substance. In book 3, after having
Father Alonso (Alfonso or Idelfonso) Guerrero was born in Mexico in briefly discussed external senses, he explores the object, modes of procedure,
1576. He is said to have been both very virtuous and knowledgable, and he and nature of the internal senses (common sense, imagination, vis cogitativa,
was very well known during his time. He entered the Society in 1610 and and sensitive memory). Then he gives an account of the intellect, in both its
devoted his life to prayer and teaching at the Colegio de San Pedro y San active and passive roles. Next he discusses memory, and finally we get his
Pablo until his death in 1639.28 He is known primarily for two hand-written I realise on the will. An examination of the problems created by the separa-
tlon of the soul from the body is found in an appendix.
27. Gallegos Rocafull, Elpensamiento mexkano, p. 319.
28. See Alegre, Bistoria de la Provincia de la Compania de Jesus de Nuevti lispaiia. 2'). Sec Yliiiiufl' C.ibivr.i. Ciildlocio de ohms manuscritas, pp. 174-76.
HO History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Seventeenth Century 111

In treatise 1 of Commentary on De coelo et mundo, Guerrero discusses the identity and distinction; the fourth is concerned with objective precision or
universe in general. Here he questions whether one or more than one world distinctions. In the choice of these topics, one can already detect a Suarecian
exists, and which world would be the most perfect (thus anticipating Leib- concern, in turn inherited from Scotism, with subtle distinctions. The third
niz) . In treatise 2, he discusses the nature of the heavens, asking whether book is a discussion of universals. In the first disputation, Alcazar examines
they are composed of a simple, perfect element or of matter and form. He their nature; and in the second he explores universals in as much as they are
also discusses the following issues: how the heavens differ from the sublunar produced by the intellect. The fourth book contains a discussion of the pred-
world; whether or not the heavens are soluble, that is, corruptible; and icables or modes of predication. The first disputation discusses each particu-
whether they are circular in shape. In treatise 3, the characteristics of celes- lar category: gender, species, difference, property, and predicable accident;
tial movements are studied, that is, whether they proceed in order, whether the second disputation searches for what these five predicables have in com-
they move intelligently, whether they influence inferior beings, and whether mon. Book 5 approaches the issue of the predicaments, or supreme predicate
astrologers can extract predictive knowledge from them. modes (based on the supreme modes of being). In the first disputation, the
The Commentary on De metheoris is devoted to the study of comets, vapors, antepredicaments are discussed, that is, the ways in which a predicate can
fog, clouds, rain, snow, hail, and rainbows, lightning, thunder, and finally modify a subject: by univocation, analogy, or denomination. In the second
winds, the sea and tides, springs, rivers, and earthquakes. This study follows disputation, the predicaments themselves are examined, that is, substance
Aristotle's doctrine closely. and the nine accidents: quantity, quality, relation, action, passion, time,
It is clear that Guerrero's remarks have a didactic intention and that they place, situation or position, and habit. Relation is not analyzed extensively
are the result of his teaching experience. These commentaries are a good ex- here, for there is a detailed treatment of it in the third disputation.
ample of the high standards in teaching that the first Mexican professors The second volume of this Cursus is devoted to natural physics or philoso-
strove to achieve.30 phy. It is called Disputationes in octo Physicorum libros Aristotelis Stagiritae
(1668). It contains a treatment of the traditional themes related to the mo-
bile or natural entity. Nevertheless, the eighth book is unique because it con-
Diego Marin de Alcazar
tains a disputation on the beginning of the world and another on the move-
Of the Jesuits who worked in New Spain during this period, Diego Marin ment of projectiles.31 One of the two surviving copies of the second volume
de Alcazar was the most eminent. He was born in Caravaca, Spain, and died of this Cursus contains matters related to De ortu et interitu and De anima.
in Tepotzotlan in 1708, where he had been teaching. His most important The third volume, Disputationes in universam philosophiam scholasticam, quam
philosophical work is Triennalis philosophiae cursus, a textbook for a three- metaphysicam scientiam universalissimam vacant (1669) is much more interesting
year course on philosophy: two copies, both incomplete, survive, and are because it contains writings on metaphysics. The very word "Disputationes"
found in the Biblioteca Nacional. This work is divided into three volumes; relates this metaphysics to the work of Suarez, but it is the content itself
the first dates from 1667 and is both a compendium and dialectic of logic. In which shows Diego Marin to be a Suarecian. The work consists of a preface
the Summulae, he concentrates on (1) the essence and the properties of sim- and five books. Book 1 concerns the essence and attributes of entities as such;
ple truth or terms, (2) the essence and properties of compound truth or it explores its subject in six disputations. The first deals with real identity and
propositions, and (3) the essence and properties of mediate truth or inferen- distinction; the second with formal identity and distinction among the predi-
tial discourse. The section on dialectics contains five books. The first disputa- cates of the entity, that is, precision; the third discusses objective precision; the
tion of the first book explores the essence and properties of dialectics; the fourth treats the distinction between essence regarded as existence and pos-
second is concerned with the object of logic. The second book discusses dis- sibility. Here we find another Suarecian element in the work of Alcazar, for
tinctions between things. The first disputation discusses entities of reason; he rejects the formal distinction, so dear to the Thomists, between essence
the second deals with real identity and distinction; the third discusses formal and existence in creatures. The fifth disputation explores the connection

30. See Gallegos Rocafull, Elpensamiento mexicano, pp. 289-93. 11.11. .'.Otv .'.Mr.
112 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Seventeenth Century 113

between essence and possible entity, and the sixth discusses subsistent en- Tractatus in duos Aristotelis libros De corpore generabili et corruptibili. Tractatus in
tity or substance. The second book discusses opposites in two disputations. tres Aristotelis libros De corpore animato. Appendics in Aristotelis libros de Meta-
The first concentrates on entities of reason, and the second discusses the physica, Coelo, Metheoris et Parvis naturalibus. Per Sapientissimum Patrem Au-
lack of being. The third book is devoted to transcendental properties and to gustinum de Sierra. Societatis Jesu, in Angelopolitano ejusdem Societatis Collegio
univocal predication. The adoption of Scotistic univocalism rather than dignissimum phylosophiaeprofessorem (1688). The influence of Suarezis strong
Thomistic analogy in relation to the predication of entity is another charac- here as by this time his philosophy had become the official philosophy of
teristic of Suarecianism. In the first disputation of this book, Alcazar asks the Society of Jesus.
whether or not an entity formally transcends the differences of particular Father Fernando Valtierra (1640-C.1708) wrote a section on philosophy
entities. He answers in the affirmative, for in all cases the being of particu- within a theological manuscript; it relates to human acts. This text forms
lar entities is predicated univocally, that is, all differences of whatever type part of a series of works written between 1687 and 1688 in Mexico. Father
are entities of some sort. The second disputation is devoted to a study of Matfas Blanco (Durango, 1660-Mexico, 1734) wrote a treatise on free will,
the univocal aspects of entities. Book 4 is about incorporeal or spiritual en- De libertate areata sub divina scientia, voluntate et omnipotentia, in which he de-
tities. The first disputation of this book analyzes the nature and properties fends the Jesuit theory of a middle knowledge against both the Thomist the-
of this type of entity; the second disputation explores its potencies or facul- ory of physical premonition and the Scotist theory of accompanying decree.
ties; and the third discusses memory, intellect, and intellection. The fifth The date and place of publication are unknown. Father Antonio Peralta
book explores the operations of the intellect in a more concrete fashion: (Zumpango, 1668-Patzcuaro, 1736) wrote, among other things, a disserta-
the first disputation is devoted to apprehension and judgment; the second tion, De ente supernaturali (date and place of publication unknown). In this
disputation to the truth and falsity which can exist in the acts of the intel- work he explores the possibility, the existence, and the properties of super-
lect; the third disputation to the opposition between truth and falsity; and natural entities. Father Diego Caballero, a Mexican lecturer on philosophy
the fourth disputation to the study of the third operation of the mind or in the Jesuit College of Guadalajara, left behind a Controversiae scholasticae in
reason. octo libros Physicorum Aristotelis which is preserved in the Colegio Mayor de
In his theological treatises, Marin de Alcazar also addresses philosophical Santa Maria de Todos los Santos, in Mexico. Finally, a treatment of some
problems. One example of this is his discussion of the conditional knowledge philosophical issues can be found in Father Manuel Arteaga's theological
that God has of future contingents and His influence on human acts, will, work, De scientia Dei et de divinis ideis. Arteaga was Mexican and taught at the
and liberty.32 Found within one of Marin de Alcazar's manuscripts there are Colegio de San Pedro y San Pablo. Father Martin Carlos Tamallo Granillo's
two theological works by other authors. One of them is by Father Morejon Disputationes physicae in octo libros Aristotelis de physico audita, sive de naturali
and is entitled An sit possibilis substantia supernaturalis, and the other is Father auscultatione is another example of a theological work which deals with
Moria's Tractatus de iustitia et iure.i3 philosophical issues. It was written in Mexico City during the years 1684-
1685."
Other Jesuits
Seciilar Clergy
Father Antonio Nunez (1618-1695) also discussed philosophical issues
within a theological context. He wrote a treatise on the science of God which Among the secular clergy, the first important philosopher during this
is dated Mexico, 1668.34 Father Agustin Sierra, a professor in Puebla, wrote an century is Canon Marcos Portu. He was born in Puebla but studied in Mex-
important book on philosophy. Its title is really a description of its contents: ico at the Colegio de Todos los Santos. According to Beristain, he specialized
in indigenous languages and philosophy. In 1639 he wrote Comentarios a
32. See Yhmoff, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, nn. 333, 334, 339, and 340.
33. Ibid., p. 263, n. 380.
34. Ibid., p. 234, n. 331, and p. 260. (S. [bid., p. 34S, n. 512.
114 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o S e v e n t e e n t h Century 115

Aristoteks, and in 1643 he w o n the Chair of Arts at the University. In 1647 O matter, you who have informed yourself with life,
the University appointed h i m representative to t h e royal court and sent h i m in how many metaphors have you lived?
to Spain for a short period. By 1650, he was back in Mexico and involved in You have seen yourself as a scented snowflake on a gardenia,
and you have endured in the pale ash.
the tasks of the Chair of Arts. Later, he became a canon at the Metropolitan
Cathedral of Mexico, and in 1653 was appointed Chair of Vespers of Theol- After such horror you have undressed,
ogy. Then the University and the Cathedral commissioned h i m once again to and then dressed yourself as king of violets.
travel to Spain; he died in Madrid. In so many dead forms, you have not died
you have made being-close-to-death something eternal.
Another important figure of this period, Don Luis de Sandoval Zapata,
was not only a notable philosopher but also an excellent poet. He was born What? You never awaken the light of thought,
in Mexico at t h e beginning of the seventeenth century. He studied at t h e but you do not die
Colegio de San Ildefonso from 1634, developing interests in philosophy and with the invisible rush of the winged hours, you murderer?
theology. He was probably a m e m b e r of the secular clergy. Are you not wise, having been close to so many dead?
His philosophy displays particular Stoic elements which are evident in his Having been widow to so much life,
prose and poetry. In 1645, he published Panegmco a la paciencia.i6 In the pro- are you indestructible nature?
logue he mentions that among the works he was about to publish were El
This p o e m reveals a familiarity with Aristotelian-Scholastic philosophy. In
Epicteto cristiano, with Stoic undertones, Quaestiones selectae, and Examen veritatis.
another p o e m w e observe Zapata's appreciation of good reasoning and argu-
Notwithstanding his Stoicism, his training, as was the case with most
ment, something shared by most scholastics:
thinkers during this period, was Aristotelian and scholastic. These influences
are present in his poetry, as, for example, in a p o e m dedicated to matter: En lazos silogisticos prendiste
las mas desesperadas rebeldfas. . . .38
Materia que de vida te informaste,
,;en cuantas metaforas viviste? You have caught rebelliousness most desperate
Ampo oloroso en el jazmin te viste, In syllogistic knots.
y en la ceniza palida duraste.
Zapata's Christianized Stoicism is evident in some poems that deal with the
Despues que tanto horror te desnudaste,
ephemeral character of life. An example is found in a sonnet dedicated to a
rey de las flores purpura vestiste.
day of Corpus Christi in Mexico:
En tantas muertas formas, no moriste:
tu ser junto a la muerte eternizaste. Hurto a la selva Mexico pensiles
^Que discursiva luz nunca despiertes, que en la pared ecliptica tuvieron
y no mueras al impetu invisible doseles, primaveras se Uovieron,
de las aladas horas, homicida? se descolgaron icaros abriles.

lQu€, no eres sabia junto a tantas muertes? Miucha invention en liquidos marfiles,
^Que eres, naturaleza incorruptible en el campo de dosel arroyo fueron,
habiendo estado viuda a tanta vida?37 y cantando las flores, que murieron,
sonaron muchos cisnes anafiles.
36. This is the original title, though some wish to change the 'a' (to) into 'de' La luz agota su festivo modo,
(about). Thus Carlos Gonzalez Pefia says, "Publico ademas, Sandoval, en 1645—y bar-
runtando quiza la mucha que se necesitaba para Ieerla—un Panegmco de la paciencia" mayo a la aurora. |Oh lastima a la fiesta!
Historiadelaliteraturamexicana, 14th ed. (Mexico: Porrua, 1981), p. 82. This edition was La primavera marchito su risa.
prepared by J. PascualBuxo in L. de Sandoval Zapata, Obras (Mexico: FCB, 1986).
37. Mendez Plancarte, ed., Poetas novohispamos segundo sigh (1621-1721), p. 103. See
also Sandoval Zapata, Obras, p. 83. SK. Sonnet to FnnciBCO Corchero Girreno, in Sandoval Z.ip.ii.i, Obras, p. 117.
116 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Seventeenth Century 117

Todos cansados y apagado todo, after he was caught sneaking out of the convent on a midnight escapade.
fue funebre reliquia de la fiesta Nevertheless, he never felt resentful toward the Jesuits, whom he considered
el arrepentimiento y la ceniza.39
his teachers, and he always treated them with great respect.
From the wilderness Mexico stole gardens In fact, he continued to prepare himself for the priesthood after his dis-
that at the equinox became canopies, missal, this time with the secular clergy in mind. He began studying theology
when springs rained down at the Real y Pontificia Universidad de Mexico. He displayed the marks of a ge-
and Icarus-like Aprils descended.
nius with many talents, combining great ability for the physical sciences with
Much was found in the white waters gifts for the humane sciences such as philosophy, history, poetry, and theology.
that, in the canopied field, formed a stream; At the University, he tried for and won the Chair of Astrology and Mathe-
many swans, like trumpets, made music, matics in 1672, and the following year he was ordained. Besides some lunarios
singing of flowers that died.
in which he uses judiciary astrology, he also published Glorias de Queretaro, in
The light lost its festive mode which he praises a temple dedicated to the Virgin of Guadalupe, and the
In May at dawn. Alas for the feast! Teatro de virtudes politicas que constituyen a un principe, in which h e writes about
The smile of Spring faded away. several ancient Mexican princes, thus revealing his interest in local history.
When everyone was tired and everything worn out, Both books appeared in 1680. The following year a brightly-colored comet
regret and ashes appeared in Mexico and was considered an evil omen. Responding to this
were funereal relics of the feast. widespread superstition, Siguenza published his Maniflesto filosdfico contra los
cometas, despojados del imperio que tenian sobre los timidos, in which he argues
Both the distance from the mundane and the search for long-lasting spiritual
against the belief that comets herald tragedies and catastrophes. Martin de la
delights reflect the influence of Stoicism.
Torre, a Flemish citizen who resided in Campeche, answered him in another
Another cleric who wrote about philosophical issues in his theological
piece of writing called Maniflesto cristiano en favor de los cometas, mantenidos en su
works was Don Alonso de Talavera, author of Tractatus de essentia Dei (1675).
natural signification, and Siguenza in turn responded to that with the now lost
This work is registered in the public library of Guadalajara.40 Finally, we
Belerofonte matemdtico contra la quimera astroldgica de Don Martin de la Torre. Fa-
must mention and describe in some detail the contributions Don Carlos de
ther Eusebio Kino (or Kuhn), a Jesuit from the Tyrol who was well known in
Siguenza y Gongora. He was well known in the fields of science and history,
European universities, intervened in the polemic. He disagreed with Siguenza
but we will focus on the philosophical dimensions of his work.
on the physical nature of comets and argued that they foreshadow future
evils. Sigtienza's answer is contained in Libra astronomica y philosophica which
Carlos de Siguenza y Gongora is a well-documented treatise containing the most modern theories of his
time, and one in which the most recent authors such as Descartes, Gassendi,
Carlos de Siguenza y Gongora was born in Mexico City in 1645. He en-
Galileo, and Kepler^are mentioned. Siguenza was said to have won the argu-
tered the Society of Jesus while still an adolescent and took his simple vows
ment. The Libra was written in 1681, but it was not published until 1690.
on August 15, 1662, in the famous Colegio de Tepotzotlan. Two years later
Siguenza was chaplain of the famous Hospital del Amor de Dios (today
he published a long poem devoted to the Virgin of Guadalupe entitled Pri-
Hospital de Jesus). During this period, he published a poem in praise of the
mavera Indiana.11 He took his vocation as a Jesuit very seriously and therefore
Virgin entitled Triumpho parthenico (1683), and the following year he also pub-
felt frustrated and guilty when he was asked to leave the Society in 1667
lished Parayso occidental. Another of his works, Piedad heroica de D. Fernando
39. J. Pascual Buxo, ed., Muertey desengano en la poesia novohispana (sighs XVI y XVII)
(Mexico: UNAM, 1975), p. 134.
40. See Catdhgo de libros que existen en la Biblioteca Publico del Estado, vol. 2 (Guadala- biography, we have followed I. A. Leonard, Don Carlos de Siguenza y G6ngora, un sabio
jara, Mexico: S. Banda, 1874), p. 382, n. 21. Quoted by Redmond, Bibliography of the mexkanoo del sigh XVII (Mexico: VCM, 1984). For a bibliography, see I. A. Leonard, En-
Philosophy in the Iberian Colonies of America, p. 95, n. 706. siiyii bibliogrtifico de don Carlos de Sigilcinui y Cdngora (Mexico: Sccrctaria ile Rel.iclones
41. There were two ollu-r editions of lliis work, in 1668 iind 1681. I'or Sigiien/.a's i ixterlorei, 1929).
118 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Seventeenth Century 119

Cortes, Marques del Valle (1689) also deals with moral philosophy and follows riod of transition, who looked both to the past and present, well-aware of
the same line of thought as Teatro de virtudespoliticas. His novel, Infortunios que the major philosophical trends of his time. This is particularly evident in his
Alonso Ramirez natural de la Ciudad de S. Juan de Pverto Rico padecio assi en poder philosophy of science and his philosophy of history.44 In both of these areas
de ingleses piratas que lo apresaron en las Islas Philipinas como navegando por si solo we come across examples of Sigiienza's independence from Scholasticism
y sin derrota, hasta varar en la costa de lucatan: Consiguiendo por este medio dar and his connections with modernity. Like Descartes before him, he belongs
vuelta al mundo (1690), is another notable piece of writing, and has been con- to a tradition, yet he takes this tradition into new directions.45
sidered the first of its sort in Mexico- In 1690, apart from publishing Libra As- In his philosophy of science, the influence of modernity is evident in his
tronomica y Philosophica, Sigiienza also published two other historical works: criticism of traditional doctrines, such as the astronomical concepts of Father
Relation de lo svcedido a la Armada de Barlovento and Trofeo de lajusticia espanola Kino and his followers. This critical attitude is a primary characteristic of
en el castigo de la alevosia francesa. modern philosophy and is operative in the work of Descartes, Galileo, and
In 1692 there was an uprising in the capital of New Spain in which the Gassendi among others, all of whom Sigiienza quotes in his discussion.46 The
consistorial wing of the Cabildo caught fire. Sigiienza risked his life to save the critique of the tradition is consistent with Sigiienza's insistence that one
books that were kept in this section of the building. That same year he wrote should not appeal to authority in order to settle disputes, but rather to reason.
Admiral Andres de Pez a letter describing what had happened during the Authorities are fallible; indeed, their judgments are mere opinions, prone to
riots. And in October he asked for permission to leave the Chair of Astrology error as are all opinions. Even judgments of the wise should never be ac-
and Mathematics. In 1693, he joined the expedition led by Admiral Pez to cepted as unquestionable truths. Universal consensus regarding the opinion
study the Bay of Panzacola, and afterward he presented Viceroy Conde de of a so-called authority is not valid; all judgments must be examined critically.
Galve with an account of the expedition. He also published Mercurio volante The value of critique is that it opens a space for the testing of claims by
con la noticia de la recuperacidn de las provincias del Nuevo Mexico, in which he de- means of experimentation and logical argumentation. One of the criteria
scribes the way in which Diego de Vargas recovered these territories. Sigiienza uses to criticize the work of others is the formal validity of their ar-
In 1697 he met the Italian traveler, Giovanni Francesco Gemelli Careri, guments. This, of course, presupposes a certain knowledge of the rules and
who wrote about this meeting in his book of travels.42 That Christmas laws of logic. Sigiienza respected formal logic and the theory of argumenta-
Sigiienza was granted permission to resign from his Chair at the University. tion. He specialized in both the natural sciences and mathematics and his
The year 1700 was full of important events for Sigiienza and marks the work reflects his knowledge and appreciation of the scientific method. Si-
end of his career: his Oriental planeta evangelico. Epopeya sacro-panegyrica al giienza was methodical in his scientific activities, basing his work on disci-
apostol grande de las Indias S. Francisco Xavier, an epic work devoted to the Je- plined and exact observation and on rigorous calculations. Moreover, he al-
suit missionary St. Francis Xavier, was sent to the printers; on August 9, he ways strove for precision and dismissed prejudices. He believed that the
made his will; he was allowed to reenter the Society of Jesus, something he application of empirical observation requires adequate instruments, and in
had tried to do on numerous occasions throughout his life;43 he died as a Je- astronomy this depends on mathematical calculations.47
suit and so could be buried in the Capilla de la Purisima of the Colegio de San Thus scientific truth is reached by means of a method based not on author-
Pedro y San Pablo. ity but on experience (aided by instruments) and also on logical mathematical

Philosophical positions 44. See L. Benitez, La idea de historia en Carlos de Sigiienza y Gongora (Mexico: UNAM,
1982).
Though Sigiienza y Gongora's philosophical training is substantially scho- 45. See Jose Gaos, Presentation to Libra astronomica yfilosofica,by Carlos de
lastic, he also shows unexpected modern leanings. He was a thinker in a pe- Sigiienza y Gongora, 2d ed. (Mexico: UNAM, 1984), pp. XV ff., and E. Trabulse, Ciencia
y religidn en el sigh XVII (Mexico: El Colegio de Mexico, 1974), p. 62.
46. See F. Lopez Camara, "El cartesianismo en Sor Juana y Sigiienza y Gongora,"
42. Compare Careri's Giro del Mondo and Viaje de la Nueva Bspana (Mexico: UNAM, Filosofla VLetras, 39 (1950): 107-31, and R. Moreno, "Lafilosofiamoderna en la Nueva
1983). He talks about his interview with Sigiienza on pp. 118-19. Esparto," in Estudios de historia de la filosofla en Mexico, 2d ed. (Mexico: UNAM, 1973),
43. See E. J. Burrus, "Sigiienza y Gongora's Efforts for Readmisslon Into the Jesull pp. 121-67.
Order," Hispanic American Historical Review, 33 (1953): 387-91. •17. See Trabulse, Cienciay rcligifin en elsiqb XVII.
120 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o
S e v e n t e e n t h Century 121

demonstration. It should be possible to apply the principles of physics to the tude toward astronomy and in his poetry. He considers the movements of
study of all natural things, because they are governed by causality, and physi- the heavenly bodies a form of h a r m o n y created by the divinity and reminis-
cal laws do nothing but express the dynamics of that universal causality. In cent of Galileo's neo-Pythagorean ideas 54 which affirmed that this h a r m o -
the branch of physics where the empirical predominates, there is less truth nious language of God was to be found in mathematics. This is expressed in
t h a n in mathematics, which is governed by reason alone. Therefore, there are one of Sigtienza's poems:
degrees of truth. Siguenza seems to have considered metaphysics to be a type
Tti, del Cielo Armoma
of pure speculation and does not consider it subject to empirical evidence. 48
nunca dormida, siempre vigilante,
Astronomy is a science located between physics and mathematics. Insofar que en facistol de olfmpico diamante
as it draws o n experience, it is not purely speculative and thus is related to metrica entonces duke melodia:
physics and t h e principle of causality. But astronomy is also a science of exact pues debes a los Cielos
calculations and therefore closely related to mathematics. The supposition generosos desvelos,
that in n a t u r e there exists a causal and determined type of behavior, that is, dispende ahora, con cadencias bellas,
consonancias de luz, voces de estrellas. . . .
the supposition of a principle of universal causality that can be applied to
physics and astronomy, m e a n s that astronomy follows an inductive method; . . . Metricas armonias
49 los Quertibicos Coros alternaban,
this implies a causal determinism in nature. Siguenza holds a different view
y en las Iiras mentales que tocaban
regarding astrology. Although it was a field he k n e w well and for which he dulces daban al alma melodfas,
had composed a n u m b e r of lunarios, he is quite critical of it. His criticism siendo el tierno concento
stems from its defective methodology, which does not allow it to be consid- envidia del movimiento
ered a science, and gives it, at the very most, the status of an art that yields de imperceptibles numeros giros
de esos rodantes imisicos Zafiros. . . . "
neither empirical evidence nor mathematical certitude. 50 He argues that his
experience as a teacher of astrology provided h i m with insight into its weak- O Harmony of Heaven
nesses, thereby allowing h i m to deem it u n w o r t h y of being referred to as a never asleep, always awake,
scientific discipline. 51 Astronomy can only be considered a science if it has a you who, in the choir-bench made of Olympic diamond,
solid foundation and promises to m a k e authentic progress. Siguenza consid- then sweet metrical melody:
then you owe to the heavens
ers that m o d e r n astronomy and physics should do away with Aristotelian
noble night-watches,
qualitative physics, which centered a r o u nd properties, virtues, and qualities now, with beautiful cadences, give forth
difficult to handle, and should strive to become a m o re quantitative sci- consonants of light, voices of stars. . . .
ence. 52 This would allow for the possibility of scientific progress. Progress can
. . . The Choirs of Cherubim
take place w h e n , within the limits of our knowledge, ideas, hypotheses, and exchanged metrical harmonies,
laws are gradually discovered which explain to us, each time with greater and played on lyres of the mind
clarity and precision, the p h e n o m e n a of t h e world. Astronomy was able lo from which they gave the soul sweet melodies,
offer such explanations, for example, to explain comets. Astrology, in contrast, being the tender concert
envies the moment
ends up in a cul-de-sac. 53 Sigiienza's scientific beliefs emerge in both his atti-
of the uncountable cycles
of those revolving musical sapphires. . . .
48. See Benftez, La idea de historia en Carlos de Siguenza y Gdngora, p. 61 and Siguenza
y Gongora, Libra astronomica yfilosofica,p. 5, n. 6.
49. Ibid., p. 33, n. 57. 54. On Neopythagoreanism in Galileo Galilei, see Mauricio Beuchot and J. Iriiguez,
50. Ibid., p. 160, n. 334. "Ciencia empirica contra ciencia l:e6rica: un falso dilema (Aristoteles y Galileo)," Quipu.
51. See Trabulse, Ciencia y religion en el sigh XVII. Revista Latinoamerkana de Historia de las C.knciasyla Tecnolgfa, 3/2 (1986): 213-32.
52. See Siguenza y Gongora, Libra astrondmicay filosdfiea, pp. 174-75, n. 372. 55. Carlos de Siguenza y Gongora, "Oriental plancla evangelieo," in Poetas novohis-
53. Ibid., p. 60, n. 116. puuos, sci/i/ndo sitflo (I(>2I-I72I), parte si'ilitiulti, ril. A. Menilez I'laiicailc (Mexico:
UIMAM, I'"I5), pp. 10 and I 1.
122 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o
S e v e n t e e n t h Century 123

The baroque conceptual elements of his poetry remind us that Sigiienza consists in that two or three witnesses will agree to it. M y praise of the bay
was a relative of Luis de Gongora y Argote. Sigiienza was a thinker with has also been shared (according to the prosecutor) not by two or three peo-
m a n y talents w h o could handle mathematics and poetry, at times even com- ple but by the one h u n d r e d and twenty w h o accompanied m e indefinitely.
bining t h e m . Therefore, if I say the same thing they do, I can in n o way be lying." 58
Sigiienza's gift for science is present in his 'philosophy of history'. Here Sigiienza would seem to follow Cicero's dictum, "Historia magistra vitae,"
his critical attitude toward sources and testimonies is notable, and, although for he believes that history mirrors h u m a n passions and virtues. The events
this is arguable, it would seem that h e believed that in relation to history and characters that figure in history Can teach h u m a n s m a n y important
there existed the possibility of making certain scientific predictions or of es- lessons. This is w h y historical discourse is highly pedagogical and not simply
tablishing certain nomological statements (although in very few cases), by a series of memoirs. Great deeds and actions, notable for their degree of pru-
means of which one would be able to predict the course of events. 56 He sug- dence or wisdom, transmit important values to those w h o hear about them .
gests that written history be based on reliable documents, which implies Historical discourse has a strong moral dimension for it must not only be true
spending m a n y hours in archives (such as the one in the cabildo which he 'scientifically' but must also possess moral truth or goodness. Historical good-
rescued from the flames or the one for prehispanic history which he ness teaches us about God's intervention and about the p a t h of virtuous be-
founded). According to him, one must establish a difference b e t w e e n w h a t is havior that leads to Him. This is w h y Sigiienza thinks that history belongs
true and w h a t is doubtful, and insist u p o n a critical attitude and a search for within a providencial context. God guides history, and history leads to God:
m a x i m u m objectivity w h e n studying a document. God is its end. Sigiienza is very clear about this: "The other time I talked o n
Regarding this last point, there is an interesting passage that appears at this subject, I said that the heart of those w h o rule are in the hands of God so
the very beginning of Sigiienza's description of the 1692 uprising: that he may bend t h e m mor e easily toward w h a t pleases Him; and let this be

He who looks at an object with a green glass between the object and his eyes proved so in the present case, this person affirms that people will judge as
will necessarily see a green object; this is due to the fact that the species that the causality w h a t is nothing but the disposition of the Almighty, as it was u n-
object sends to the glass which is in between will be dyed green. The eyeglasses doubtedly His justice that moved the heart of this highly religious prince and
I wear are transparent and clear because I live far removed from any type of gave him the order and also governed the h a n d of he w h o subscribed." 59
pretensions. I lack nothing, for I have nothing (as Abdolomino said to Alexan-
One final characteristic of Sigiienza's personality and work merits m e n -
der the Great), hence it would be very wrong of me to claim that things are not
like this. So, having made sure that there is nothing which will color that tion: his nationalism and solidarity with t h e criollos.w Sigiienza was not only
which I have observed with care and will here talk about, I do solemnly concerned with Indigenous issues, but h e also possessed a criollo conscious-
promise myself that even those who censure everything will agree that my
words are inspired by the truth. 57
haymedios que me tinan las especies de lo que cuidadosament he visto y aqui dire,
desde luego me prometo, aun de los que nada se pagan y lo censuran todo, el que dara
Sigiienza's great desire for objectivity is evident in this passage. He was con- asenso amis palabras por muy veridicas."
scious of his o w n subjectivity and of his wish to remove as m a n y traces of it 58. Carlos de Sigiienza y Gongora, "Carta contra Arriola," in F. Perez de Salazar, Bi-
ografia de Carlos de ^Sigiienza y Gongora de varies documento ineditos (Mexico: Antigua Im-
as possible from his work. Revealing himself to be a serious historiographer, prenta Murguia, 1928), p. 152. "La entidad de la verdad de una cosa consiste segun el
he writes, "According to the Holy Scriptures, t h e entity of truth of a thing Sagrado Evangelio en que dos o tres testigos concuerden en sU asencion: los mismos bi-
enes y elogios que digo de la Bahia diecn (segun el sefior fiscal) no dos o tres personas
sino los que me acompanaron indefinidamente que fueron ciento veinte. Luego di-
56. Compare Benftez, La idea de historia en Carlos de Sigiienzay Gongora with J. Graue, ciendo yo lo mismo que ellas de ninguna manera miento."
La explication histdrica (Mexico: UNAM, 1975). 59. Carlos de Sigiienza y Gongora, "Trofeo de la justicia espafiola," in Obras historicas
57. Carlos de Sigiienza y Gongora, "Alboroto y motin de Mexico del 8 de junio de (Mexico: Porrua, 1944), pp. 137-38. "Dije cuando otra vez discurrf este asunto hallarse
1692," in Relationes historicas, 3d ed. (Mexico: UNAM, 1972), p. 99. "El que mini mi en la mano de Dios el corazon de los que gobiernan para inclinarlos facilmente a lo que
objeto, interpuesto entre el y los ojos un vidrio verde, de necesidad, por Iciiiisc las el lucre de su agrado; y que asf se verificase en el suceso de ahora, nos lo asegura este que
pedes que el objeto envia en el color del vidrio que esta intermedin, lo vera verde. I.os otro juzgara casualidad no siendo sino disposition del Altfsimo, pues rue su justicia sin
anteojos que yo uso son muy diafanos, porque, vivicndo aparladisinio de pretcn iluilri Li que movid el coia/cin de este rcligiosisiino prfneipe y lc diclo el orden y clla
siones y no faltandome nada, porque nada tengo, (como dijo Ahdolomino a Alejandro inisina la que >.il que suscrilua lc gobtmd It iii.uio."
Magno), seria en mi muy culpable el que .isi no fuera; eon que, .urrlansn el que nn 60. Benftez, i.«lint it hlttcrts m Carlos it Stftiinza yQingon, pp. 119 ft
124 H i s t o ry of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o S e v e n t e e n t h Century 125

ness. His nationalism was based u p o n this hard-to-define consciousness, a Would gladly be subject to your flourishing Triumph,
which, in its judiciousness, inspires the Partenico with honor;
consciousness that contrasted strongly with the customary servile attitude
toward Spain. A part of Sigiienza's criollo consciousness a m o u n t s to a n for your Triumph (which I am exploring)
awareness of t h e fact that h e was from New Spain. He even gives t h e impres- outdoes Arabia, the Tajo, the Ganges, the Hymmetus
sion of seeing and thinking about Mexico as a n e w nation, a nation that in fragrance, sweetness, pearls, and gold.

wanted to be considered a criollo nation and that would express itself


through a criollo culture. He conceives this nation as complex and hybrid. It Religious Women
posseses certain aspects inherited from Europe (Spain) and others from its
Indigenous roots, thereby acquiring a series of u n i q u e characteristics that During the period u n d e r consideration, the achievements of some
range from the religious (the Indigenous or mestiza Virgin of Guadalupe) to w o m e n were considerable. Because Sister J u a n a Inez de la Cruz's achieve-
the political (conceiving or planning a n e w nation). ments were particularly extraordinary, w e shall devote a section to her life
A p o e m written by Father Br. D. Francisco de Ayerra Santa Maria ( 1 6 3 0 - arid work.
1708) indicates the high esteem in which Sigiienza was held:

<^Por que el Himento aplaude sus panales Sister J u a n a I n e s d e la Cruz


y el Ganges de su aljofar los candores;
por que la Arabia eleva sus olores J u a n a Ramirez de Asbaje, or Sister J u a n a Ines de la Cruz, was born in
y arenas de oro el Tajo en sus raudales, 1651 in a farmhouse in San Miguel Nepantla, jurisdiction of Amecameca, and

si de tu heroica pluma los caudales, she died in Mexico in 1695. She entered the Order of the Jeronimas in 1669.
si de tu dulce estilo los primores, In the convent of San Jeronimo, she was a dedicated student and made great
sudando aromas y vertiendo flores, progress in several disciplines. In Primer sueno, she describes her attraction to
perlas son, son auriferos cristales? philosophy as part of her desire to understand the h u m a n being:
A tu florido Triunfo, que discreto
. . . el Hombre, digo, en fin, mayor portento
el Partenico alienta con decoro,
que discurre el humano entendimiento;
lo que antes fue blason, este sujeto;
compendio que absoluto
pues que vence tu Triunfo (a lo que exploro) parece al Angel, a la planta, al bruto;
a Arabia, al Tajo, al Ganges, al Himeto, cuya altiva bajeza
en fragancia, dulzuras, perlas y oro. 61 toda participo Naturaleza. 62

Why does the Hymmetus applaud its honeycombs, . . . Man, I say in short, the greatest wonder
and the Ganges the beauty of its pearls; that human understanding encounters;
why does Arabia praise its spices, - an absolute summation
and the Tajo the golden sand in its currents— resembling arigel, plant, and brute;
one whose lofty lowness
since what flows from your heroic pen,
participates in the whole of Nature.
and the beauties of your sweet style,
aromatic and flowering, In these lines we find Sister Juana's image of m a n as a microcosm, revealing
are pearls and golden crystals?
the confluence of Neoplatonic, Medieval, Renaissance (hermetic), and mod-
The Partenico, which was previously glorified ern influences on her thought. We will use this symbol of the microcosm as

61. Francisco de Ayerra Santa Maria, "Soneto a Sigiienza y G6ngora" (in the prr
liminary section to Triumpho Parthenico), in Poetas novoliispoiios, soimiilo */<//<' (/<>.'/ / / . ' / ) 02. Sisli'i' Juan.i Ines dr l,i Cm/, "HI sueno," in Obras completas, vol. 1, Lirica per-
ed. Mendez Plancarte, pp. 24-25. soti.ll, I'd. A. Memlez I'Lincnrto (Mexico: I'Cli, 1976), pp. H5 II., vv. 690-95.
126 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Seventeenth Century 127

our point of departure to discuss her concepts. The amount of knowledge


Sister Juana possessed was amazing. In her time, women received a limited Sister Juana and philosophy: a brief defense of women
education or were entirely prohibited from receiving a formal education. Philosophy was one of the many disciplines Sister Juana cultivated. We
Nevertheless, Sister Juana's knowledge of philosophy was extensive. The re- know that she wrote a work on logic which has been lost.68 It is interesting to
search of various scholars has established that she must have been familiar speculate on what led her to write a work of this sort when she herself tells us
with Neoplatonism,63 Scholasticism,64 Hermeticism,65 as well as with various that her study of philosophy was to a certain extent unsystematic and to a
modern thinkers.66 In this study, we will limit ourselves to an investigation of large extent self-directed. It must have been her, great love for philosophy,
the influence of Scholasticism upon her thought avoiding, however, the ex- particularly Scholastic philosophy, that inspired her to write such a text. Her
tremes of which Octavio Paz accused Mendez Plancarte when the latter tried work on logic was written in Latin. This is significant because in her time most
to show that Sister Juana was a NeoThomist. We will begin with an explo- women did not learn Latin. Indeed, it was commonly held that Latin could
ration of the presence of Scholasticism in her poetry.67 not edify women and could even hurt them (mujer que sabe latin, tiene malfin).
Sister Juana's work on logic, a systematic philosophical text written by a
The microcosm and Scholastic philosophy woman in Latin, was a rarity of its time. In order to balance the emphasis that
The idea of a microcosm as a symbol of man, the idea of man as a small other scholars have placed on the Neoplatonic, Hermetic, and modern ele-
world, a synthesis of everything, developed from the Greeks and is still rele- ments of her thought, we will focus instead on the Scholastic influence.
vant today. This idea flourished during the period of Medieval Scholasticism Sister Juana had to face a great number of difficulties in order to study at
and Renaissance Neoplatonism, and it was through the Medieval Scholastic all. Her superiors forbade her to study, claiming that such activity did not
tradition that this concept of man as microcosm reached Sister Juana. Her allow her to concentrate on the duties expected of her or that it might dam-
acquaintance with Hermetism intensified this image. age her health. Yet she could not avoid looking at all that was going on
According to Scholastic philosophical anthropology or the philosophy of around her with philosophical eyes, and she reports having learned some-
man, the central structuring idea is the image of a microcosm; this was a thing even from the most simple experiences. In her Respuesta to Sister
mystic idea present in religious and theological meditations. The role of Filotea, Sister Juana writes of the discoveries made while she cooked, adding
philosophical anthropology in Sister Juana's thought can be understood as with irony: "[I do not wish] to tire you with these uninteresting bits of infor-
the result of the influence of Scholastic philosophy; it underlies her theory of mation, which I only mention to give you a more complete account of my
knowledge and her search for wisdom or metaphysics. Before we explore natural disposition and which I also think will amuse you; but senora, what
this, however, we must first discuss some central aspects of the philosophy can we women know except kitchen philosophy? Lupercio Leonardo was
she studied. right when he said 'one can very well philosophize and prepare supper.' And
many times I say when I see these things: 'If Aristotle had cooked, he would
63. See J. Pascual Buxo, "Elsueno de sor Juana. Alegoria y modelo del mundo," in have written more.'"69 These are thoughts that reveal an ability to reflect
Sdbado, suplemento de Unomasuno, 15 August 1981; J. Pascual Buxo, SorJuana Ines de la upon even the most common experiences and introduce a fresh perspective
Cruz en el conocimiento de su "Sueno" (Mexico: UNAM, 1984), pp. 51 ff. This latter work
emphasizes Aristotle's influence on the poetry of Sor Juana. See also Octavio Paz, Sor to philosophy. \
Juana Ines de la Cruz o las trampas de la fe (Mexico: FCE, 1982).
64. See A. Mendez Plancarte's notes on "El sueno" and O. Castro Lopez, SorJuanay
el "Pritnero Sueno" (Xalapa, Mexico: Universidad Veracruzana, 1982). 68. See Redmond, p. 136, where he discusses a compendium by Sister Juana on
65. Paz, Sor Juana Ines de la Cruz o las trampas de lafe and E. Trabulse, El circulo roto logic (Summulae), which has been lost.
(Mexico: FCE-SEP, 1983). 69. Sister Juana Ines de la Cruz, Repuesta a sor Filotea de la Cruz, published as an ap-
66. Lopez Camara, "El cartesianismo en sor Juana y Sigiienza y Gongora," In pendix in R. Salazar Mallen, Apuntes para una biografia de sor Juana Ines de la Cruz, 2d ed.
Filosofia y Letras, 39 (1950): 107-31. See also Moreno, "La filosofia moderna en Li (Mexico: UNAM, 1978), p. 98. "[No quiero] cansaros con tales frialdades, que solo re-
Nueva Esparia," in Estudios de historia de lafilosofiaen Mexico, pp. 121-67, and BemaM li'ero por daros entera noticia de mi natural y creo que os causara risa; pero senora,
Navarro, "La presencia de descartes," in Cultura mexicana moderna en el sigh XV1I1, 2d nl. (.que podemos saber las mujeres sino filosofias de cocina? Bien dijo Lupercio Leonardo:
(Mexico: UNAM, 1983), p. 94. que bien se puede filosvfar y aderezar la cena. Y yo suelo decir viendo estas cosillas: Si
67. Also sec Beuchot, "La lilsoffa escolaslica en la poesia do sor Juana," in EstudtM Arisldlclcs liuhiciti guisado, muclio mas Imbiera cscrito"
de historia y defilsofia en el Mi'xico colonial, pp. 177-90.
128 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Seventeenth Century 129

It is clear that Sister Juana's philosophy was not restricted to reflection judge. This last is an unmistakably Scholastic term72 that is also called 'cogita-
upon her household duties; she went far beyond these. The ideas she dis- tive'; its task is to perceive the representations (intentiones, a term that pre-
cusses, the authors she mentions, and even the importance she gives to cer- sent day phenomenology has revived) that are not received by the senses.73
tain aspects of philosophy clearly demonstrate the degree of understanding She compares the imagination74 to an artist:
she possessed of the philosophical panorama and its priorities. This is present . . . asf ella, sosegada, iba copiando
in her response to Sister Filotea, when she criticizes the lack of logical rigor las imagenes todas de las cosas,
in the work of certain preachers, particularly visible in their deplorable bibli- y el pincel invisible iba formando
cal exegesis: "All of this begs for more study than some would think neces- de mentales, sin luz, siempre vistosas
colores, las figuras
sary, especially by those who wish to interpret the Scriptures simply as gram-
no solo ya de todas las criaturas
marians, or in the best case are ready to do so just by using four terms from sublunares, mas aun tambien de aquellas
the compendiums and insist upon Mulieres in Eccksia taceant, without know- que intelectuales claras son Estrellas. . . .
ing how to interpret this."70
. . . thus, she calmly copied
So high was the value she gave to logic that she considered it to be indis-
the images of all things,
pensable for the study of theology. And theology was the field she valued and the invisible brush formed,
above all others. She writes, "I continued to direct my studies in the direction out of the unlit but ever-vivid colors of the mind,
of the summit of Holy Theology; and thought it necessary, in order to reach the shapes
this summit, to use the sciences and human arts as stepping stones. After all, not only of all sublunar creatures,
how could anyone be able to understand the Queen of the Sciences, if one but also of those
that are bright intellectual stars. . . .
were not familiar with its servant? How would I know about the general and
particular methods with which the Holy Scriptures were written if I did not Sister Juana also mentions the heavenly sphere and the internal orbits in
know logic?"71 She proceeds to list the other disciplines that formed part of which the celestial bodies revolve. The presence of Scholastic theories fig-
philosophy. Keep in mind that at the time, all sciences that were not theolog-' ures even more prominently when she describes knowledge as an inten-
ical were considered to be philosophical. tional species of the soul.75 For the Scholastics, the species was the mental
representation (be it sensible, imaginative, or conceptual) of the thing, and
Philosophy in Sister Juana's poetry it was given intentionally within the spirit (an intentionality which through
In certain passages of Primer sueno we can detect traces of Scholastic phi- Brentano was recovered by Husserl for present day philosophy). Sister
losophy. First and foremost is the presence of a philosophy of human beings Juana discusses the importance of the species for the intellectual operations
or a philosophical anthropology characteristic of Scholasticism. When Sister in the following passage:
Juana refers to human beings, she mentions those characteristics that
. . . como el entendimiento, aqui vencido
Scholasticism attributed to the cognitive faculties, speaking of the internal
no menos de la inmensa muchedumbre
senses such as the common sense, fantasy or imagination, and the faculty lo de tanta maquinbsa pesadumbre
(de diversas especies conglobado
70. Ibid., p. 109. These compendiums represented the formal logic and the seman- esferico compuesto),
tics of the period. The phrase "mulieres in Ecclesia taceant" ("let women in Church he que de las cualidades
silent") is taken from Paul, 1 Cor. 14.34. "Todo esto pide mas leccion de lo que piensan dc cada una, cedio. . . ,M
algunos, que, de meros gramaticos, o, cuando mucho, con cuatro terminos de Sumul.is,
quieren interpretar las Escrturas y se aferran del Mulieres in Ecclesia taceant, sin saber
como se ha de entender." 72. Sister Juana Ines de la Cruz, El Sueno, v. 258.
71. Ibid., p. 82. "Prosegui dirigiendo siempre los pasos de mi csuidio a la cuinlm- dc 73. Octavio Castro has interpreted this correctly by following the doctrine of
la Sagrada Teologica; pareciendome preciso, para llegar a clla, subir pot Ins eicalOMI Aquinas's Summa ThtolOgittt, I, q. 78, a. 4, c.
delas ciencias y artes humanas; porquc ^como entcndcra el csiilo dc la Kcin.i dc I.p. 7'I. Sister Juana Ines de l,i Cruz, HI Sueno, vv. 280 IT.
Ciencias quien aiin no sabe el de las ancillas? /.Como sin l.oglca s.ilirf.i yo los nn'Modo* 75. Ibid., v. 40 V 7(>. Ibid. vv. 4<,>)-Ti.
gcncralcs y particulates ion esla cscrila la Sagrada liscriluraV"
130 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o S e v e n t e e n t h Century 131

. . . as the understanding, being here defeated . . . una por una discurrir las cosas
no less by the huge crowd que vienen a cenirse
of such machine-like weight en las que artificiosas
(a spherical composite dos veces cinco son Categories. 79
made up of various species),
than by the qualities of each one, . . . to discourse, one by one, upon
gives up. the things that come to us,
for whom Categories, two times five of them,
She makes explicit reference to the species also in stressing that, in rela- have been contrived.
tion to all the knowledge she expected to acquire, she is conscious that the
Here the word contrived {artificiosas), which Sister J u a n a uses to character-
soul sometimes manages to achieve only a very confused species or concept:
ize the Aristotelian categories, is significant. It is, to a certain extent, an am-
. . . permitiendole apenas biguous term. Octavio Castro interprets it as clever"0 because that which is
de u n concepto confuso contrived, is m a d e , i.e., is a product of creation, of cleverness. But artificiosa
el informe embrion que, mal formado
can also m e a n 'arbitrary', even t h o u g h most Scholastics thought that the cat-
inordinado caos retrataba
egories mentioned above were the natural categories of things. Was Sister
de confusas especies que abrazaba. . . ,77
J u a n a paying tribute to Aristotle or was she casting a shadow of doubt over
. . . allowing him scarcely the apparently accepted natural character of his categorical scheme? Was she
the unformed embryo of a confused concept, supporting the Aristotelian-Scholastic doctrine? Or was she subtly under-
which, being badly formed,
mining it? The Cartesians disagreed with Aristotle's table of categories and
portrayed the disorderly chaos
of confused species that it included. . . . insisted that it could not be the only one and that it was not t h e most natural
one, declaring, furthermore, that it was both artificial and arbitrary. Sister
Metaphysics is also very m u c h present in Sister Juana's p o e t r y and it is J u a n a could have b e e n influenced by t h e Cartesians h e r e .
present from a cosmological perspective. This is evident in the passage w h e r e Sister J u a n a believed that metaphysics could help h u m a n beings ad-
she mentions the Aristotelian-Thomistic concept of God as closely related to vance in their search for knowledge. This is related to Sister Juana's central
a final cause in that all beings in the universe are d r a wn to Him: philosophical idea, which she termed 'metaphysical reduction'. This is w h a t
. . . y a la Causa Primera siempre aspira Aristotle and the Scholastics considered t h e m e t h o d of wisdom; that is, the
—centrico punto donde recta tira reduction or resolution (analysis) of all beings into the most universal cate-
la linea, si ya no circunferencia, gories. Metaphysics was both an understanding and a science, that is intel-
que contiene, infinita, toda esencia—.7S lection (or intuition) and discourse. But, whereas the most accepted belief
. . . and it always desires the First Cause was that intellection predominated over discourse, Sister J u a n a discovered
—the central point that perfect knowledge was not the result of intellective intuition, and thus
to which the line, now no longer a circumference, she w e n t on to search for it in discourse or in argumentative discourse, only
draws straight, to realize eventually that this does not offer complete knowledge either:
and which, being infinite, contains every essence—.
reduction metafisica que ensena
The same metaphysical concerns are revealed w h e n she speaks about I lie (los entes concibiendo generales
categories in which Aristotle wished to place all things: en solo unas mentales fantasias
donde de la materia se desdena

77. Ibid., vv. 547-51. 79. Ibid., vv. 579-82.


78. Ibid., vv. 408-11. 80. See Cislm, Soi .liiiiiuiy el "I'riinnv SutflO," p. 82.
132 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o S e v e n t e e n t h Century 133

el discurso abstraido) tion she includes prior to the p o e m itself, expresses h e r reservations con-
ciencia a formar de los universales,
cerning the accumulation of too m u c h scientific information, for she fears it
reparando, advertido,
is useless to knowledge and hazardous to life. Apparently, she wishes to dis-
con el arte el defecto
de no poder con un intuitivo cuss h e r lack of trust in man's capacity to embrace all things by means of
conocer acto todo lo criado, knowledge. Yet, w h a t stands out is h e r constant feeling of disappointment
sino que, haciendo escala, de u n concepto regarding absolute knowledge, a disappointment similar to the one she felt
en otro va ascendiendo grado a grado regarding complete love. Nevertheless, this p o e m is not a sceptical Pyrrhon-
y el de comprender orden relativo istic manifesto or a methodical piece of writing full of Cartesian doubts. Cer-
sigue, necesitado
tainly, there is a touch of scepticism expressed in the following lines:
del entendimiento
limitado vigor, que a sucesivo Todo el mundo es opiniones
discurso fia su aprovechamiento. . . .81 de pareceres tan vanos,
que lo que el uno dice que es negro,
metaphysical reduction, which science
el otro prueba que es bianco. . . .
(by conceiving beings in general
Los dos filosofos griegos
in just a few mental images
Men esta verdad probaron:
in which matter is disregarded
pues lo que en el uno risa,
by the abstract discourse)
causaba en el otro Uanto. . . .
teaches us to perform upon the universal concepts
Para todo se halla prueba
by attentive observation,
y razon en que fundarlo;
has, together with its skill,
y no hay razon para nada,
the defect of not being able to grasp,
de haber razon para tanto. 83
in an intuitive act of knowing, all of creation,
except by gradually ascending All the world is opinion
from one concept to another, step by step, of appearances so vain
and the act of grasping the relative order of things comes after, that that which one holds to be black,
depending on a limited power of understanding the other proves to be white.
that entrusts its improvement to the subsequent discourse. . . . Two Greek philosophers
proved this truth well:
At this point, after realizing that intelligence and reason can be defeated, Sis-
for that which caused laughter in one,
ter J u a n a abandons herself to theological knowledge based o n faith. It would caused sobs in the other.
seem that mysticism triumphed over reason. 82 For everything one finds proof
and reason to estabfish it;
Disappointment with knowledge and there is no reason,
to have reasons jor so much.
There is another p o e m by Sister J u a n a that contains an important philo-
sophical point, yet it has hardly been explored. It is a romance belonging to a
One might think that this is in itself proof that w e are in the presence of a
group of poems that Mendez Plancarte has called "Romances filosoficos y
sceptical quasi-Pyrrhonistic attitude or else in the presence of one of the ob-
amorosos (sin fecha conjeturable)," and it is the only one of the group that
servations (the proof that there was a lack of agreement among philosophers.)
really deserves to be called philosophical. Sister Juana, in the brief explana-
(hat led Descartes to uncover the foundations of philosophy. Fundamentally,
81. Sister Juana Ines de la Cruz, El Sueno, vv. 583-99. however, what these lines reveal is an attitude of healthy humility in the
82. Ibid., vv. 757 ff. See also P. Gomez Alonso, "Ensayo sobre la filosofia en sor
Juana Ines de la Cruz," Filosofiay Letrds 60-62 (1956): 59-74; and J. Gaos, "El sueno de 83. Sister Juana Ines de In Cruz, Ronnunvs, Romance n. 2, vv. 13-16, 25-28, and
un sueno," HistoriaMexicana 10 (1960): 54-71. 41-44.
134 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o S e v e n t e e n t h Century 135

face of w h a t w e do n o t yet know. This holds particularly for those mysteries este duro afan pesado,
a los hijos de los hombres
that we cannot handle by means of understanding or by reason, and so w e
dio Dios para ejercitarlos. . . .
must leave unsettled. Sister J u a n a takes refuge in a p r u d e n t type of knowl-
iOh, si como hay de saber,
edge and in moral judgments. 8 4 Matters of faith or of mystical experience hubiera algun seminario
were for her (as they were for Cusa and would be for Kant) legitimate, o escuela donde a ignorar
t h o u g h not cognitive, parts of our experience of the world. Does this imply se ensenaran los trabajos!86
that our knowledge is flawed or incomplete? In the following lines, Sister
Knowing is also a vice:
J u a n a reflects u p o n this question: for if you don't cut it short,
the less you know,
No es saber, saber hacer
the more harmful the havoc;
discursos sutiles, vanos;
and if the flight is not cut short,
que el saber consiste solo
if one is lured on by subtleties,
en elegir lo mas sano. . . .
then, by caring about what is exotic,
! Que feliz es la ignorancia
one forgets what is needful. . . .
del que, indoctamente sabio
This horrible exercise,
habla de lo que padece,
this hard and heavy task,
en lo que ignora, sagrado!85
God gave to the sons of men
Knowledge is not knowledge of how to make in order to train them. . . .
subtle, empty discourses; Oh, if only, just as they have them for knowing
for knowledge consists solely there were some seminary or school
in choosing what is most b e n e f i c i a l . . . . where one would be taught exercises
How happy is the ignorance for not knowing!
of the one who, being unleamedly wise,
speaks of what he suffers,
and is silent about what he does not know! The microcosm once again
A constant in the philosophical thoughts found in Sister Juana's poetry is
One must search for a useful type of knowledge, a more practical and moral
a feeling of disenchantment and distrust regarding the possibility of perfect
knowledge, a knowledge similar to the 'knowledge of salvation' Christianity finds
and complete knowledge. 8 7 This contrasts to the m e n t i o n she makes in her
in theology: biographical Respuesta a sor Filotea, that since childhood she had been intent
Tambien es" vicio el saber: on learning as m u c h as possible. It is interesting to think about w h a t m a d e
que si no se va atajando, her abandon this insatiable desire and take one of the most important steps
cuanto menos se conoce of her life. Her ideas and experiences related to the microcosm (a synthesis of
es mas nocivo el estrago;
all levels of being, both inferior and superior ones) exerted a fundamental
y si el vuelo no lo abaten,
influence on the way she finally fused all aspects of knowledge into the high-
en sutilezas cebado,
por cuidar de lo curioso est faculty, faith. The highest degree of being and knowledge governs all the
olvida lo necesario. . . . minor ones, and in this way faith, which for her signifies the most perfect
Este pesimo ejercicio, and important type of knowledge, contains and elevates all other modes of
knowledge. Within the realm of faith, which is w h e r e the mystical micro-
84. In fact, the work of this poet also contains an important moral dimension; see
C. M. Montross, Virtue or Vice: Sor Jauna's Use of Thomist Thought (Washington, D.C.;
Catholic University of America Press, 1981). 86. Ibid., vv. 89-96, 125-28, and 133-36.
85. Sister Juana Ines de la Cruz, Romances, Romance n. 2, vv. 69-72 and 81-84. 87. See R. Xirau, Oenioyjiyura Jesor.luaiM. M eel. (Buenos Aires: EUDEBA, 1970), p. 85 [f.
136 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o
S e v e n t e e n t h Century 137

cosm finds its culmination, Sister J u a n a discovers the possibility of quench- has had centuries in her nine lustrums,
ing h e r thirst for knowledge . This is so because she does n o t conceive of she now has nothing more to know, she now is ignorant of nothing
faith as something irrational b u t rather as something that originates in the
Die now, since it has been wisely settled
rational and t h e n proceeds o n to the mysterious and the mystical. In this
that, for her who knows everything in an hour,
process, faith does n o t lose its desire to defend the objects of its belief a long time among the living is more than enough.
t h r o u g h argumentation. Did Sister J u a n a fall into t h e traps of faith? Yes, she
did, b u t in a very positive way. Sister Juana found the answer to h e r expecta-
tions concerning knowledge in a mystical wisdom acquired through faith.
She expressed this in h e r poetry, making great use of t h e image of t h e
h u m a n being as a microcosm in which a quasi-angelic knowledge is com-
bined with the senses and with reason.
Doctor Don J u a n de Aviles expresses this in the following sonnet dedi-
cated to Sister Juana:

Si en la pequena clara luz de u n dia


vive la fresca Rosa edad entera,
la Rosa—cuando el dia muere—muera,
pues ya no ha de crecer su gallardia.

Si su debil fragante bizarria


no ha de ser mas—aunque su vida fuera
emula de la Delfica carrera—,
muera, que ocioso su vivir seria.

Pues si esta Rosa, que la Fama Uora,


en nueve lustros siglos ha tenido,
ya no ha de saber mas, ya nada ignora.
Muere ya, pues que docto acuerdo ha sido
que a quien todo lo sabe en una hora
le sobra mucho tiempo en lo vivido. 88

If, in the brief clear light of a single day


the fresh Rose lived her whole life,
the Rose—when the day died—would die,
since then her elegance will grow no greater.

If her weak fragrant splendor


is to be no more—although her life would be
a competitor on the Delphic race-course—,
she will die, since to live would be pointless.

For since this Rose, for w h o m Fame weeps,

88. Dr. D. Juan de Aviles, "Soneto ninebre a Sor Juana" {Famay Obras pdstumas del
Fenix de Mexico), in Poetas novohispanos, segundo sigh (1621-1721), parte segundo, ed. Mcn-
dez Plancarte, p. 88.
E i g h t e e n t h Century 139

The philosophy of New Spain during the first half of this century was con-
cerned with traditional Scholastic doctrines. The second half of the century,
however, was dominated by the conflict b e t w e e n traditional and m o d e r n
thought. This conflict ended with the retreat of traditionalism and the tri-
u m p h of modernity. Scholasticism remained influential, especially at t h e Uni-
versity, but only a modernized version that supported traditional doctrines,
e.g., opposition to tyranny, and combined these with progressive ideas that
led to m o v e m e n t s of social change that ultimately led to independence in the
early n i n e t e e n t h century. Clearly, the incorporation of m o d e r n elements
combined with the mor e traditional doctrines of Scholasticism to actualize
the emancipation of Mexico from Spain. 3
The Eighteenth Century Strenuous intellectual labor is well appreciated in philosophy. This appre-
ciation is expressed in t h e following verses of Cayetano de Cabrera y Quin-
tero, a period playwright:

Yo soy mirado a otra luz


del admirable edificio
del hombre, la mejor parte:
A lthough during the eighteenth century, Mexico experienced b o t h an
La antorcha que lo ilumino
/ \ economic and a cultural boom, immense socio-economic contrasts
la aguja que lo gobierno
JL M a m o n g different groups of the population remained quite visible; la estrella que lo dirijo
for example, betwee n the wealthy and those condemned to crass slavery. 1 y, en voluntarios naufragios,
The political relationships with t h e Spanish were such that t h e y led to a n in- el timon de su albedrio.
creasingly despotic-tributary system; this created dissatisfaction and ulti- Yo lo sabido comprendo,
yo lo ignorado investigo,
mately led to t h e revolutionary wars. Although t h e changes of t h e eighteenth
yo lo dividido aduno,
century were not as drastic as those of the nineteent h century, they were sig-
y lo adunado divido.
nificant. A major source of t h e changes that took place was t h e accession of Y, para no proceder
the Bourbons to the Spanish throne. The Bourbons were a family of French defendiendo en infinito,
ancestry and fought against t h e legacy of t h e Austrias that pervaded both the soy entendimiento, que es
Spanish government and its possessions. todo y mas de lo que he dicho.
Yo soy aquel que, embarcado
The period marked a n important shift in Mexican colonial philosophy. 2 It
en el velero navio
was at this time that the dispute between traditional Scholastic thought and de la gran Filosofia,
m o d e r n t h o u g h t began. Nonetheless, most philosophers of this period did not en tres anos he corrido
choose one over the other, rather they tried to integrate m o d e rn ideas into de todo su vasto oceano
t h e m o r e traditional Scholastic framework. There were, of course, excep- las sirtes y los bajios.
Ya encallando y zozobrando,
tions. The traditionalists were less tolerant of m o d e r n ideas; they resisted
surge el pielago enemigo
change, and this resistance gave rise to some animosity.
que cuantas olas abarca,
I.E. Semo, Historia del capitalism/} en Mexico. Los origenes: 1521-1762, 3d i-il. (Mexico: lanlos previcne peligros.
Era, 1975), pp. 252H.
2. A. V. Davis, El Siglo de Oro de la Nueva Espana (Sigh XVIll) (Mexico: Polls, 1 W5),
pp. 91 ff. l. Sioi'i/.cr, his mdvsI'sivliislii'ih

HH
140 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o E i g h t e e n t h Century 141

I am watching, by another light, demonstrated m o r e concern for m o d e r n philosophy. Most of the Franciscan
the amazing construction courses revealed t h e extent to which tradition, in particular, the Scotist
called man, the best part: school, had become firmly established. 5
The torch I shine for him Friar Jose Antonio de Aldalur, lecturer in philosophy at the Convent of
the compass with which I steer him
San Francisco in Queretaro, 6 wrote a complete philosophy course, admentem
the star by which I guide him
Scoti, which h e began to dictate in 1716 and finished in 1719. The quatrain
and the rudder of his free will
when he shipwrecks himself deliberately, that closes the last lesson of the first year is w o r t h quoting:
I understand what is known,
Estudia poco y siempre
I search for what is not known,
y seras como la espiga
I unite what is divided,
que no se vio crecer
and separate what is united.
y se ve crecida.
And, in order not to go on
defending myself ad infinitum, Study few things, but constantly
I am the understanding, which is and you will be like the blade of grass
everything 1 have said, and more. that nobody saw growing,
I am the one who, aboard Yet one sees it grown.
the sailing vessel
of great Philosophy, In addition to this philosophy course, Aldalur wrote a Tractatus perutilis defig-
has travelled all of its vast seas, uris rethoricis and a Tractatus de hominis ultimo fine, et de beatitudine, iuxta . . .
including the sandbanks and the shoals, mentem ... D, Scoti which he started in 1725 and finished in 1726.
for three years.
During the period betwee n 1716 and 1719 at the Colegio de San Bue-
Now, running us aground and capsizing us,
naventura, Friar Antonio Quinones wrote a Triennalis philosophicus cursus iuxta
there rises up the hostile ocean,
which has as many dangers prepared Joannis Duns Scoti menten.1 As was customary, it contains the summulae (a com-
as the waves it contains. p e n d i u m of the essential elements of logic) or minor logic, dialectic or major
logic, physics, metaphysics, and the De anima. Manuel Bnciso y Texada wrote
Cayetano refers here to the three years a student usually spent at the univer-
another Scotist coursebook, from which he lectured at the Convent of San
sity and colegios studying arts or philosophy. Most markedly in the 1750s, the
Francisco, in Totimihuacan, and which included the same treatises as
irrepressible wave of m o d e rn thought flooded t h e university and influenced
Quinones's as well as the De generatione et corruptione."
the teachings of m a n y colegios, especially Jesuit ones.
Cristoforo Grande, w h o taught at the Convent of Santiago in Queretaro,
gave a course from 1730-1731, Tractatus in ... librosPhyskorum, de Ortu etinter-
Franciscans ituyde Anima etMetaphysica ad mentem subtilis Scoti.9 Manuel Garcia de Rendon
practiced philosophy at the Colegio de San Buenaventura in Tlatelolco. In
During the eighteenth century, the Franciscans followed the Scotist school 1730 he lectured from ad mentem Scoti. Only the part of his lectures dealing
to a greater extent t h a n in previous centuries. The philosophy courses of the with logic remains, both the section on the essentials and o n dialectic. 10 And
period usually tried to discuss Aristotle from the perspective of Duns Scotus.
For the Franciscans at the end of the eighteenth century, philosophical reno-
5. P. Gonzalez Casanova, El misoneismoy la modernidad cristiana en el siglo XVIII (Mex-
vation with a focus on m o d e r n philosophers was not a major concern. Other ico: El Colegio de Mexico, 1.948).
orders, the Jesuits, the Oratorians, and, to a lesser degree, the Dominicans, 6. Beristain de Souza, Biblioteca Hispano Americana Septentrional, vol. 1, p. 110.
7. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 295, no. 424.
8. [bid., p. 158, no. 222.
4. C. de Cabrera y Quintero, Obra dramdtica. Teatro novohispano del sigh XVIII, ed. C. 9. Ibid., p. 173, no. 248.
Parodi (Mexico: UNAM, 1976), p. 217. 10. Iliid., p. 171, no. 241.
142 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o E i g h t e e n t h Century 143

Jose Torres of the Convent of San Francisco in Guadalajara wrote Naturae Angeles, in Ocholoposco, one can find, with his signature, his logic lessons
indagatrix Philosophia Aristoteliea via triennali lustratura curriculo Antesignano (dated 1742 and 1742-1743 respectively), as well as his volumes o n physics
Smo. acMariano D. Joanne Duns Scoto . . . in 1732." and metaphysics (from 1743 and 1744-45). They still bear t h e marks left
According to the official biographer of the Order, the teachings of the Fran- from a fire in the library of the Convent of San Diego. 21
ciscans followed the lines of the Scotist school. Aristotle was discussed but Emiliano Millan de Zerezeda taught at the Colegio de San Bernardino de
under the guidance of Scotus. Sometimes the Aristotelian text was only used Siena, in Xochimilco, w h e r e he left a coursebook from which h e lectured in
as a pretext to defend the Subtle Doctor against the schools of the other orders. 1743. He also lectured in Texcoco at the Convent of San Antonio in 1745 and
In 1733 at the Convent of San Francisco in Totimihuacan, Friar Felipe produced another coursebook. Both coursebooks are ad mentem Scoti.22 A sim-
Ortiz lectured on logic and Fray Joaquin Camacho Davila on physics, the De ilar coursebook (dated 1750-1753) Was written by M a n u e l del Camino at t h e
anima, and metaphysics. This w e k n o w from a compilation carried out by Convent of San Francisco in Puebla and the Colegio de San Buenaventura in
Friar Pedro Jose de Jesus Maria Aliri12 and another by Friar Francisco Perez, Tlatelolco. 23 At the Colegio de San Buenaventura, one can also find the minor
which makes reference to the courses taught from 1 7 3 2 - 1 7 3 6 . " Camacho and major logic lessons written by Jose Varela, lecturer from 1750-1751. 2 4
was born in Tenancingo, Mexico and taught at t h e Convent of San Cosme, There is also an arts course (1752) by Jose Villasenor that was preserved at
outside the capital. Twice h e was warde n of the convent as well as definitor of the library of the University of San Luis Potosi. 25
the recollets of the province of the Santo Evangelio. 14 At Jesuit colleges the modernization of philosophy began in the 1750s,
Anselmo Zespedes (or Cespedes) taught philosophy in Puebla at the Con- while the Franciscans remained devoted to the Scholastic teachings. Thus,
vent of San Francisco from 1735-1737. He wrote Philosophicus cursus follow- during this period, there were several coursebooks written that were strongly
ing Scotus. 15 Friar Francisco Camacho was lecturer in theology in the influenced by Scotist philosophy. An important coursebook was written by
province of the Santo Evangelio in Mexico. 16 His Philosophia Scotistica ad usum Luis Mariano de la Vega between 1752 and 1754. Vega was a lecturer at the
Imperialis Collegiide Tlatelolco was prepared for publication during the first half Convent of San Francisco in Totimihuacan. 2 6 Similar coursebooks were writ-
17
of the eighteenth century. Jose Rodriguez Malo taught at Totimihuacan at ten by Friar Agustin Jose Vidarte, reader at the Convent of San Gabriel in
the Convent of San Francisco from 1736-1738 and also left a Scotist course- Cholula (1765-1767) 2 7 and Friar Miguel de Sologuren, lecturer at t h e Con-
book for philosophy. 18
Jose Alderete, lecturer at the Colegio de San Bue- vent of San Francisco in Puebla (1762-1767). 2 8 In his Pisica, Sologuren
naventura in Tlatelolco, prepared a coursebook for philosophy as well, and he makes reference to the atomists (p. 62), whereas in De anima, he mentions
bequeathed his Trietericus Scotisticae philosophiae cursus, Hortus conclusus, dated the Cartesian notion that the soul 'helps' m a n (p. 97), and in the treatise De
1740, to the college library. 1 ' caelo etmundo, he refers to t h e three systems of the world—the Ptolemaic, the
Friar Pedro de Oronsoro, born in Huamantla, province of Tlaxcala, bishopric Copernican, a n d t h e Tichonian (i.e., that of Tycho Brahe). It is possible that
of Puebla, was the w a r d e n of t h e convents of Mexico and Puebla. Later he the copyist of Friar Miguel's coursebook wrote by mistake that the Coperni-
20
became definitor and provincial of the province of San Diego in New Spain. can system was the one that should be recognized because t h e others were
At the Convent of Santa Barbara and at the Convent of Santa Maria de los c o n d e m n e d by the Church; in fact, the Church questioned the theories of
Copernicus. 29
11. Valverde Tellez, Bibliografiafllosoficamexkana, p. 73.
12. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catalogo de obras manuscritas, p. 330, no. 13. 21. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catalogo de obras manuscritas, p. 311, no. 458.
13. Ibid., p. 270, no. 390. 22. Ibid., p. 251, no. 360.
14. Beristain de Souza, Biblioteca Hispano Americana Septentrional, vol. 2, p. 25, no. 594. 23. Ibid., p. 67, no. 73.
15. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catalogo de obras manuscritas, p. 84, no. 102. 24. Ibid., p. 410, no. 623.
16. Beristain de Souza, Biblioteca Hispano Americana Septentrional, vol. 2, p. 24, no. 593. 25. Gomez Canedo, Los archivos de la historia de America.
17. Valverde Tellez, Bibliografiafllosoficamexicana, p. 103. 26. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catalogo de obras manuscritas, p. 416, no. 631.
18. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catalogo de obras manuscritas, p. 311, no. 458. 27. Ibid., p. 417, no. 632.
19. Beristain de Souza, Biblioteca Hispano Americana Septentrional, vol. 1, p. 114, no. 28. Ibid., p. 337, no. 499.
132. 29. Hi'i'imbe Navarro, la iiilivdmrion de In filosi'Jh modema en Mexico (Mexico: 111
20. Ibid., vol. 4, p. 53, no. 2213. Colegio de Mexico, 1948), p, L44,
144 H i s t o ry of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o E i g h t e e n t h Century 145

Other important authors of philosophical coursebooks are Francisco Ace- W h e n h e became master of students, Mancilla was succeeded by Antonio
vedo, lecturer at the Convent of San Francisco in Totimihuacan w h e r e he Viar y Larrimbe at t h e Colegio de Porta Coeli. Larrimbe m a d e a valuable con-
taught a Scotist Curso from 1772 to 1774; Jose Manuel Chamorro, lecturer at tribution to Dominican philosophy, writing a philosophy coursebook which,
the Convent of Santa Barbara in Puebla whose coursebook, dictated in 1773, in 1761, gave rise to heated debates at the Provincial Chapter. The Mexican
deals with subjects of natural philosophy; 30 Joaquin Bernardo Balmaseda (or province proposed that Larrimbe's coursebook be used instead of the course-
Balmaceda) of t h e Colegio de San Buenaventura in Tlatelolco wrote a course- book that the Order wanted to impose which had been written at the end of
book from 1778-1781, which focused primarily on logic and, to a lesser de- the seventeenth century by Antonio Goudin, a Dominican from Limoges.
31 Larrimbe's coursebook was m u c h mor e conservative t h a n Goudin's, and the
gree, physics; and Friar Jose Roldan, lecturer of the Convent of San Diego,
Mexico City, concluded his coursebook in 1798. 32 fathers of the Mexican province preferred it.35
Vicente Aragon taught at t h e Colegio de San Luis in Puebla from
1 7 4 1 - 1 7 4 3 . He left a philosophy coursebook, curiously entitled Philosophiae
Dominicans rivulus.16 Beginning in 1749, Jose Ignacio Cuellar was a lecturer at t h e Cole-

During the eighteenth century, the Dominican order acted as the defender gio de Porta Coeli. In 1751 h e wrote a Cursus philosophicus iuxta Divi Thomae

of Thomist doctrines. During the first half of the century, the Dominicans did de Aquino doctrinam^ and in 1752 h e became master of students. M a n u e l

not even take the m o d e r n philosophers into account, and w h e n they did, in the Lopez de Aragon 3 8 taught at Porta Coeli from 1757-1759, and h e left an Ar-

second half of the century, it was only to oppose them. Thus, the Dominicans tium cursus iuxta Angelici praeceptoris doctrinam™ written a r o u n d 1758. The

studied the moderns in order to attack t h e m from the Thomist perspective. 33 only subject included in Friar Jose Jimenez de Villasefior's In universan Aris-

Friar Antonio Mancilla was a criollo born in 1709. He began to teach for totelis Dialecticam, iuxta Angelici Doctoris mentem, cursusm is dialectics or major

the Order in 1734, but his teaching career must have started earlier. In 1737 logic. The manuscript bears n o references to t h e date or t h e place in w h i c h it

he was already a priest at the Colegio de Porta Coeli in Mexico City, and he was written.

held the post of master of students. Beginning in 1734 h e was lecturing from In 1763 Cristobal Coriche was teaching in Puebla. Here he published, at

his coursebook in philosophy. Such positions would not have been granted to the Imprenta del Colegio Real de San Ignacio de la Puebla, his Oration vindica-

one w h o had had n o previous teaching experience. He was master of students tiva del honor de las letras y las ciencias." This is an apologetic dissertation in

from 1737-1741, and in 1741 he became a lecturer in theology, until 1749, favor of the different sciences and virtues, and against w h a t had been written

w h e n h e was appointed primary regent of studies. by Jean-Jacques Rousseau, w h o was h o n o r e d by the Academy of Dijon. In

In 1752 Mancilla was appointed Vicar of Ixtapalucan, and in 1756 he was this work, one can see that Coriche had studied m o d e r n philosophy seriously,

sent to the Convent of Oaxtepec. The 1760 chapter nominated h i m to become even if only to criticize it. He defends traditional Scholasticism. Although t h e

a presentee, and he acted as provincial procurador at the Convent of Santo reception of modern philosophy by the Society of Jesus (and some other or-

Domingo. In 1765, while he was working as vicar at San Miguel Tlacotalpan, ders such as that of the Oratorians) has been widely studied, the confrontation

the Provincial Chapter proposed him for the post of master in sacred theology,
which he obtained in 1769. He died shortly before December 1772. His thought Valverde Tellez, Critica filosdfica, p. 58. Valverde claims to have known of the existence
of eight reprints of the popular work. He also says that there may have been even more
is preserved in the coursebook Cursus Philosophicus iuxta firmiorem, celsioremque
reprints.
Angelici Doctoris D Thomae doctrinam elucubratus, dated at Porta Coeli in 1727." 1 35. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 41, no. 37.
36. Ibid., p. 99, no. 124.
37. Beuchot and Melcon, Los dominicos en la Real y Pontificia Universidad de Mexico,
30. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 119, no. 145. p. 46.
31. Ibid., p. 52, no. 50. 38. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 210, no. 309.
32. Ibid., p. 314, no. 461. 39. Ibid., p. 200, no. 283.
33. Beuchot, Filosofos dominicos novohispanos. 40. It can be found in the Reserved Section of the National Library of Mexico under
34. As a result of the imposition, there was a Mexican edition of Goudln'S work, fileR/710LAF.
Philosophia iuxta inconcussa tutissimaque D. Thomae dogmata, reprinted a! Angelopoli, 1767, 41. A. Sanchez Vazquez, Rousseau en Mexico (Mexico: Grijalbo, 1970), pp. 56-57.
Typis Regalis Coflegii D. Ignatii, 3 vols, in quarto, parchment bound. II Is mentioned l>y
146 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Eighteenth Century 147

between Scholasticism and modernity in the Order of Preachers in Mexico, In addition, Friar Simon Jose Cervante, who taught at the Colegio Maximo de
has been largely neglected. The teachers who belonged to this Order also San Pablo in Mexico in 1789, left a coursebook which has been preserved. In
studied the new philosophy. The very title of Coriche's work indicates that his coursebook, he deals with physics and metaphysics. We also have his trea-
the Dominicans, just a decade after the Jesuits had begun their work with the tise on law, which contains insightful comments about the philosophy of nat-
moderns, were acquainted with the work of modern philosophers.42 ural and positive law.49
In 1769, Jose Gallegos taught philosophy at the Convent of Santo
Domingo in Mexico City. He left an oratory that defends the reform of the
Carmelites
philosophical-theological studies set up by the General of the Order, Juan
Tomas de Boxadors. The title of this work is Apologia delMetodo de Estudios, im- Friar Juan de San Anastasio was born in Villarasa, Seville. He entered the
puestos por S. Rma. La dedica a N. Rmo. P. Fr. Juan Thomas de Boxadors, Maestro Carmelite order in 1759 and then lectured on rhetoric, philosophy, and theol-
General del Orden dePredicadores. It was published in Mexico by the Mexican ogy at the Colegio de San Alberto in Queretaro1 and at the Colegio de San
Library Press of the Lie. Don Joseph de Jauregui in 1774.43 Gallegos defends Angel in Chimalistac. His Retdrica para jovenes was the product of the lessons
the new method against its critics. Apparently, the reform consisted of setting he gave on rhetoric at San Alberto.50 He was a prior several times, eventually
up the Goudin course for the study of philosophy and using the texts of Saint becoming a provincial in 1784. He died early in the nineteenth century.51 Os-
Thomas and Melchor Cano's great methodological introduction for the study waldo Robles claims that "[t]he purpose of the work written by Fray Juan is
of theology. Gallegos himself read from Cano's work at the University. to offer a definition of the philosophical terms employed in scholastic discus-
sions and disputes, based mainly upon the texts both of Saint Thomas and of
Fray Francisco de Santo Tomas; it represents what we call nowadays a philo-
Augustinians sophical lexicon or dictionary, and which, like Signoriello's Lexicon Peripateticum,

Friar Ferrnin de Ylarregui stands out among the Augustinian philosophers helps us to be more precise in philosophical debates. It is an indispensable
of the eighteenth century. His logic treatise, which includes both the essen- tool to judge the propriety of the peripathetic-scholastic language."52 Friar
tials and dialectics, has been preserved. He used it when he taught in Mexico Juan's work indicates his view of the central role that clarity and respect for
semantic definition must play in any controversy as requirments for rigour
at the Colegio de San Pablo from 1717-1718.44 Another coursebook for phi-
in argumentation. Argumentation was, afterall, the principal philosophical
losophy was written by Friar Francisco Javier de Meza (or Mega) who used it
activity of the scholastics, and they took this activity seriously and carried it
when he taught at the Convent of San Agustin in Puebla in 1732.45 In 1751
out responsibly.
Manuel Murillo (or Morillo) left a summary of the Pilosofia written by Nicolas
Cardenas.46 Murillo was born in Mexico and taught at the province of the
Holy Name of Jesus where he presided over the 1754 Chapter. He was also 49. Beristain de Souza, Biblioteca Hispano Americana Septentrional, vol. I, p. 138.
no. 182.
Rector of the Colegio de San Pablo. He left a philosophical-theological com- / 50. This is put forward by Oswald Robles, against Beristain. See Oswald Robles,
mentary on the first part of Aquinas's Summa, as well as a treatise entitled De "Breve npta sobre Fray Juan de San Anastasio y su glorsario escolastico," in Anuario de
Pilosofia del Seminario de Investigachnes Pilosdficas de la Facultad de Pilosofia y Letra, vol. 1
scientia Dei.47 (Mexico: UNAM, 1943), p. 107, n. 1.
Friar Vicente Tenorio, too, left a coursebook for philosophy, dated 1750."" 51. When Robles writes "Fray Francisco de Santo Tomas," doesn't he rather mean
"Fray Juan de Santo Tomas"? "La obra escrita por Fray Juan tiene por objeto ofrecer,
I'undandose en los textos de Santo Tomas y de Fray Francisco de Santo Tomas, princi-
42. It is reproduced in Nicolas Leon, Bibliografia mexicana del sigh XV1U, vol. 1 (Mex- palmente, una definition de los terminos hlosoficos usados en las discusiones y dis-
ico: Imprenta Dias de Leon, 1902), pp. 263-74. putas escolasticas; representa lo que comunmente llamamos hoy dia un lexico o vocab-
43. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 427, no. 643. ulario filosofico, y que, a semejanza del Lexicon Peripateticum de Signoriello, es, ademas
44. Ibid., p. 240, no. 325. de un auxiliar que nos permite dar precision al debate filosofico, un instrumento in-
45. Ibid., p. 260, no. 374. dispensable para juzgar de la propiedad del lenguaje peripaterico-escolastico." Ibid.,
46. Beristain de Souza, Biblioteca Hispano Americana Septentrional, vol. 3, p. 306. p. 99,
47. Navarro, La introduccidn de lafilosofla moderna en Mexico, p. 295. 52. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catalogo de obras manuscritas, p. 330, no. 486.
48. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catalogo de obras manuscritas, p. 8i, nos. 99-100.
148 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Eighteenth Century 149

Mercedarians Father Gregorio Vazquez de Puga, who was born in Compostela in 1677
and died in Puebla in 1747, produced a philosophical coursebook for the Cole-
Friar Juan Antonio de Segura y Troncoso was an outstanding philosopher gio Maximo de San Pedro y San Pablo, in Mexico City, which he also taught in
among the Mercedarians. He left a work on logic, Libri tres Summularum et Puebla from 1715-1717. One volume, dated 1715-1717, contains materials
Tractatus in Logican Aristotelis germanam Doctoris Angelici doctrinam continens, on logic, physics, and metaphysics; another is entitled Disputationes in Logicam
published in 1707, in Mexico at the Convento Grande de la Merced.53 In this et Physicam and was published in Mexico at the Colegio de San Pedro y San
work he deals with dialectics and the essentials of logic according to the doc- Pablo in 1715; and a third one, Disputationes in Physicam, was published in
trine of Aquinas. Born in Mexico City, Segura y Troncoso taught at the Cole- 1716-1717.58 Another important Jesuit author is Father Francisco Javier Her-
gio de San Pedro Pascual, which he also directed. Beristain writes of de Se- ize who was born in Mexico in 1682. He wrote Summulae et Tractatus in univer-
gura y Troncoso: "He was a great scholastic, well-versed in reading the Holy sam Aristotelis Logican in 1716-1717 and Disputationes in octo Aristotelis libros de
Fathers of the Church, a renowned orator and poet; he founded a poetry Physico auditu, et Metaphysica in 1718-1719.59 All of these coursebooks were
academy in Mexico over which he presided."54 Segura y Troncoso wrote a written under a strong scholastic influence in which the work of Aquinas is
commentary on Horace's Ars Poetica and was himself the author of various studied under the guidance of Suarez, the "official" philosopher of the Society.
poems. One of his literary creations is entitled, "El Seneca de la Merced; Modern ideas had not yet arrived.
moralidad joco-seria entre Bpicuro y Momo" and, according to Beristain, can Following this scholastic tendency, Father Jose del Villar wrote a Curso de
be found at the library of the Mercedarian Order in Mexico City. artes in 1718,60 as did Father Jose Maldonado, who was born in Maravatio in
1692 and died in La Habana in 1746. Father Maldonado's coursebook
(1721-1724) includes a volume on logic, another on physics, and a third on
Jesuits
metaphysics, a subject he taught at the Colegio Maximo de San Pedro y San
The eighteenth century was a period of intense activity for the Colegios of Pablo. He had previously taught rhetoric in Puebla.61 Another thorough
the Society of Jesus. Then, in 1767, the Jesuits were abruptly expelled from coursebook was written by Jose Ignacio Sanchez. The section on logic was in-
the country by the Spanish Crown. The Jesuits had become the primary edu- cluded first in a volume issued in 1725 at the Colegio de San Ildefonso, Puebla,
cators of the Mexican youth and had a strong influence on the philosophical and then in another volume (1728-1729) which was used at the Colegio Max-
ideas of the time. They taught traditional philosophy and introduced modern imo de San Pedro y San Pablo, Mexico City; the volume on physics is from
ideas in Mexico. 1728, whereas the one on metaphysics is from 1725.62 The same solid and
Father Domingo de Toledo, who was born in San Sebastian, Guipiizcoa, well-developed scholastic teachings are found in Father Jose Francisco de
died in Mexico in 1706. In 1701, he wrote Disputationes de praecisionibus, Molina's coursebook, which was issued in 1726, though the place of its publi-
which was part of Disputationes de logica, a work written by various authors cation is unknown. 63 Manuel Alvarez's Disputationes in octo Aristotelis libris de
and used at the Colegio de San Francisco Javier in Queretaro.55 Cristobal Flo- Physico auditu, seu Auscultatione is devoted to physics and was read at the Cole-
res, who was born in 1679 and died in 1728 in Patzcuaro, also left a complete gio de San Ildefonso, Puebla in 1727.64 It reveals a definite Suarecian influence.
philosophical coursebook which he used to teach from 1711-1713.56 And Father Nicolas Prieto was born in Monterrey, Nuevo Leon in 1696. He en-
Jose de Maya wrote Disputationes on physics and metaphysics, which were tered the Society in Tepotzotlan in 1718. He then traveled to Mexico City,
taught from 1709-1711.57
58. Ibid., p. 180, no. 255. 59. Ibid., p. 420, no. 635.
60. Beristain de Souza, Biblioteca Hispano Americana Septentrional, vol. 3, p. 179; and
53. "Fue un gran escolastico, muy versado en la lectura de los Santos Padres, orador Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, pp. 221 fi, nos. 312-15.
y poeta muy acreditado, y establecio en Mexico una academia de poesia, de que era 61. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 321, no. 474.
presidente." Beristain de Souza, Biblioteca Hispano Americana Septentrional, vol. 4, p. 3 52. 62. Navarro, La introduccidn de lafilosofia moderna en Mexico, p. 290, no. 34.
no. 2885. 63. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 33, no. 15.
54. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 133, no. 169. 64. As reported by lirrisl.iin de Sou/a, lliblioleca Hispano Americana Septentrional,
55. Ibid., p. 167, no. 239. 56. Ibid., p. 245, no. 151. vol, 4, p. 165, no. 2466.
57. Ibid., pp. 413 fl„ nos. 627-29.
150 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o E i g h t e e n t h Century 151

w h e r e h e taught philosophy at the Colegio Maximo de San Pedro y San Pablo Several other philosophy coursebooks have survived, such as one by Fa-
in 1729. Of his Cursus Philosophicus,6i w e only have the logic, dated 1730. M He ther Jose Luis de la Santa Cruz from 1738, 73 and another by Father Pablo Rob-
lectured on theology in Guatemala where he became Rector of the Colegio de ledo. Robledo was born in Puebla in 1709, taught philosophy at the Colegio de
San Francisco de Borja. He also directed the Colegio de Merida, Yucatan San Ildefonso in Mexico City from 1740-1742, and theology in Guadalajara,
w h e r e h e died in 17 51. where he became Rector of the Colegio de San Juan. 7 4 In his work on physics,
Born in Torino in 1697, Father Jose Luis Falcumbelli also taught in San he attacks the atomist or corpuscular m o d e r n philosophers. 7 5
Pedro y San Pablo. In his 1730 Disputationes in octo Aristotelis libros de physico au- We also have a philosohy coursebook (1744) from Jose de Zamora, lec-
ditu seu de Naturali auscultatione," he refers to the m o d e r n philosophers but turer in the Colegio de San Pedro y San Pablo. In his physics he mentions the
only to attack them. For instance, w h e n dealing with matter, he alludes to ' m o d e r n French' philosophers and refers to the Cartesians and atomists. 76 Fa-
m o d e r n atomist theories saying, "According to c o m m on opinion, I argue that ther Matias Blanco, w h o was born in Durango (1660) and died in Mexico
even if many species of atoms are possible in the primary matter, all primary City (1734), taught at the Colegio de San Pedro y San Pablo and wrote a trea-
matter both of sublunary and of celestial bodies is in fact, however, only one tise o n h u m a n liberty which was published in Mexico by Hogal in 1746. 77
species of atom. . . . The primary matter of the celestial bodies would be of a Some undate d manuscripts of this work have survived. 78 Father J u a n
different primary matter t h a n that of sublunary bodies because celestial bod- Lorenzo Valdetaro, born in Atlixco, Puebla in 1718, taught rhetoric at the
ies would be incorruptible and because sublunary bodies corruptible; but as Colegio Maximo de Mexico in 1745 and philosophy in Guadalajara in 1748. 79
68
this is n o reason, then, etc." At Guadalajara's Colegio de Santo Tomas, he left a logic s u m m a r y as well as a
J u a n Francisco Lopez was also a teacher at San Pedro y San Pablo. In work o n logic entitled Bipartitum artis oratoriae breviarium et tractatus de sum-
1732 he left a coursebook o n logic and in 1743 one on metaphysics. He fol- mulis et Logica Maior, 1748. 80 During Valdetaro's time, rhetoric and logic were
lows the usual Scholastic approach. So does Jose de Utrera, w h o was b o r n in both considered types of argumentation and thus closely related disciplines at
Velez, Malaga. He was rector of t h e Colegios at Zacatecas y Tepotzotlan. 6 ' He the university.
also taught in Queretaro w h e r e in 1735 h e wrote a Cursus Philosophicus, a Father J u a n Jose Villar Villa Amill taught at the Colegio Maximo de San
work which was later copied in Puebla at the Colegio de San Ildefonso in Pedro y San Pablo, and in 1748 he wrote a coursebook which included logic
1738. 70 His coursebook shows some hints of m o d e r n inspiration, but it re- and physics. 81 In the section o n physics, he quotes Descartes and his disciples,
mains a Scholastic work. Nonetheless, in his role as provincial, Lopez sup- referring to the latter as "few a n d outdated." 8 2 He also attacks other m o d e r n
71
ported the modernization movement. Pedro Ignacio de Avilez also lectured philosophers. In contrast, another Jesuit, Father Mariano M. Jeronimo del
at the Colegio de San Pedro y San Pablo and wrote a philosophy coursebook Puerto, in two manuscripts dated 1749 and 1751, does not even take the
in 1738. 72 moderns into account in his work on logic. 83

65. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 291, no. 420. 73. Beristain de Souza, Biblioteca Hispano Americana Septentrional, vol. 4, p. 239,
66. Ibid., p. 165, no. 233. X HO.2660; and Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 308, nos. 450-52.
67. "Sostengo inmediatamente con la sentencia mas comiin que aunque sean posi- 74. P. Robledo, Physica, 1742, pp. 10-11 and 29.
bles muchas especies de dtomos en la materia prima, sin embargo, toda materia prima tanto 75. J. de Zamora, Philosophia naturalis in octo Aristotelis libros, 1744, pp. 33 and 42v.
de los cuerpos sublunares como de los celestes, es de hecho una sola especie de atomos.... La 76. Beristain de Souza, Biblioteca Hispano Americana Septentrional, vol. 1, p. 271,
materia prima de los cuerpos celestes seria de diversa especie que la materia prima de no. 466.
los cuerpos sublunares, porque los cuerpos celestes serian incorruptibles y porque los 77. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 57, nos. 60-61.
sublunares corruptibles, pero como esta no es ninguna raz6n, luego, etc." J. L. Falcum- 78. Beristain de Souza, Biblioteca Hispano Americana Septentrional, vol. 5, p. 79,
belli, Disputationes in octo Aristotelis Libros de phisico auditu seu de Naturali auscultatione, no. 3149.
1730, p. 24v. 79. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 407, no. 618.
68. Beristain de Souza, Biblioteca Hispano Americana Septentrional, vol. 5, p. 70, 80. Ibid., pp. 420-23, nos. 636-40.
no. 3126. 81. J. J. Villar Villa Amill, Disputationes in octo Physicorum Libros, 1748, p. 21.
69. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 402, no. 612. 82. Ibid., p. 295; Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 292, no. 422.
70. Navarro, La introduction de lafilosofia moderna en Mexico, pp. I 1 and 99. 8S. .1. I.. Manciro and M. L'ahrl, Vidas de mexicanos ilustres del sigh XVIII, trans. B.
71. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 50, nos. 48-49. Navarro, 3d cd. (Mexico: 1INAM, 1989); licrislain de Son/a, Hiblioleea llispano Aiucri
72. Redmond, Bibliography of the Philosophy, p. 89, nos. 662-63, nina Septentrional, vol. 4, p, I (8, no. .' 188.
152 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Eighteenth Century 153

Nicolas de Peza was born in Mexico City in 1712 and entered the Society opposed to the ideas and methods of modern philosophers. Beristain says of
of Jesus in 1730. He taught philosophy in Puebla and theology in Guadala- Vallarta y Palma that "[h]e was a remarkable humanist, a sharp Aristotelian
jara, and he died in Bologne in 1777.84 Between 1749 and 1751 at the Cole- philosopher, and unique in the precision, subtlety, and energy of his speeches
gio de San Ildefonso, Puebla, he wrote a coursebook that included sections and arguments in the scholastic arena where his syllogisms were formidable;
on logic and physics.85 Father Francisco Javier Alejo de Orrio also wrote on for this reason, it was commonly said in Mexico that 'he who could answer
logic and physics in a work entitled Novum Philosophiae Semen Scientias omnes Father Vallarta's arguments has gained enough to answer the devil's argu-
virtute complectens. He lectured from this work at the Colegio of the Society in ments at the Judgment Tribunal.'"90 In addition to his work on rhetoric, pub-
Zacatecas in 1750. In the same year, Father Jose Prudencio de la Piedra, who lished in Mexico City in 1753 and in Bologne in 1784, Vallarta y Palma wrote
was born in Patzcuaro in 1709 and died in 1790,86 left a philosophy course- "El sabio con aprobacion de Dios."91
book written for the teaching he did at the Colegio de Valladolid (now called Father Mariano Soldevilla wrote on physics and metaphysics at the Jesuit
Morelia). Colegio in Puebla in 1754. Soldevilla was born in Tuxtla in 1721 and died in
Evidence of the increasing attention paid to modern philosophy is pro- Barcelona in 1799.92 He had studied the moderns, yet he mentions them only
vided in of Father Jose Zepeda's Fisica (p. 55). This work and another on logic in order to attack them.93 His main targets were Maignan, Tosca, and other
were written in 1750 at the Society's Colegio in Guadalajara. Father Zepeda physicists who defended atomism.
mentions the atomist, or "so-called corpuscular modern philosophers," and Father Pedro Bolado, who was born in Mexico City in 1732 and died in
this in less than complimentary terms. Zepeda was born in Guatemala in 1720 Italy in 1792, wrote a coursebook in 1756, rewriting it from 1760-1762.94 In
and died in Havana in 1767. He taught Latin in Valladolid, Michoacan; his treatment of physics, he makes reference to Descartes, Torricelli, and the
rhetoric in Puebla; and philosophy in Guadalajara and Mexico City. He was modern atomists.95
also rector of the Colegios of San Ildefonso, both in Mexico City and in Puebla. During the 1750s, the philosophical renovation of the Jesuit Order begins;
He then worked as procurador in Madrid and Rome and as Rector of the Cole- its main exponents are Diego Jose Abad, Francisco Javier Alegre, and Fran-
gio de Guatemala, from which he was expelled.87 cisco Javier Clavigero. Maneiro, the biographer of this period, refers in this
Father Jose Bueno Bassori, who was born in Mexico City in 1716, wrote a context to Rafael Campoy, Salvador Davila, Agustm Castro, and Julian Par-
work on Scholastic logic in San Ildefonso, Puebla, in 1750-1751.88 And Fa- reno as thinkers who paved the way for the process of philosophical modern-
ther Jose Mariano de Vallarta y Palma, born in Puebla in 1719, taught philos- ization in the various Jesuit colegios, but from whom there are no surviving
ophy there in 1745 and then at the Colegio Maximo in Mexico City in 1749. philosophical writings.96 Fabri, another biographer of the Jesuits, identifies
He was prefect of studies at the Colegio de San Ildefonso, and he earned his Father Abad as the head of the movement.
doctorate at its University, occupying the Suarez Chair until 1767. He died in
1790 in Bologne.89 Vallarta y Palma's work on rhetoric and poetics was widely Diego Jose Abad
used; it is a rigorous philosophical work. Moreover, it is a traditionalist work,
Abad was born in Xiquilpan, Michoacan in 1727. He entered the Colegio
84. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catalogo de obras manuscritas, pp. 280-84, nos. 403-11. de San Ildefonso in Mexico City in 1738. In 1741 he joined the Society at the
85. Beristain de Souza, Biblioteca Hispano Americana Septentrional, vol. 4, p. 140, no.
2395.
86. Ibid., vol. 5, p. 195, no. 3536; Yhmoff Cabrera, Catalogo de obras manuscritas, 90. This work was published by Gonzalez Casanova, El misoneismo y la modemidad
pp. 431--32, nos. 647-48. cristiana en el siglo XVLIl, p. 136.
87. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catalogo de obras manuscritas, p. 64, no. 71. 91. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catalogo de obras manuscritas, pp. 336-37, nos. 495-97.
88. Beristain de Souza, Biblioteca Hispano Americana Septentrional, vol. 5, pp. 86-88, 92. Navarro, La introduction de lafllosofla moderna en Mexico, pp. 132 ff.
no. 3166. 93. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catalogo de obras manuscritas, pp. 60-63, nos. 65-67.
89. "Fue excelente humanista, filosofo aristotelico agudi'simo, y singular por la pre- 94. Navarro, La introduction de lafllosofla moderna en Mexico, pp. 136-37.
cision sutileza y energia de sus discursos y argumentos en la palestra escolaslica, donde 95. Maneiro and Fabri, Vidas de mexkanos ilustres del siglo XVIII, p, 20.
eran formidables sus silogismos; y por eso era vulgar dicho en Mexico 'que qiiien sabfa <>(>. A. Oclina, Diego .lose Alnul v sn ftimilin (Morelia, Miiiio.u.in: Fonapas and Gov-
responder a los argumentos del P. Vallarta, tenia murlio adelanlado p.ir.i responder .i ernment of the SI,lie of Mlciin.nvin, I9K0).
los que el dlablo podia ponerle en el Tribunal del .Initio'." Ibid., p. 87.
154 H i s t o ry of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o E i g h t e e n t h Century 155

seminary of Tepotzotlan. He studied philosophy in San Ildefonso, Puebla, that h e will deal with subjects c o m m o n to b o t h m o d e r n and Scholastic
w h e r e he m e t Campoy. In 1748, he moved to the Colegio Maximo de San philosophers and in which there is some agreement. He adopts an eclectic
Pedro y San Pablo in Mexico City to read theology. He t h e n taught grammar position.
in Zacatecas w h e r e he wrote the "Rasgo epico descriptivo de la fabrica y Abad refers particularly to Gassendi and the atomists, and he attempts to
grandeza del templo de la Compania de Jesus en Zacatecas." Later, Abad him- reconcile atomism with Aristotelian hilemorphism. He tries to do the same
self considered this work to be convoluted and conceptista. with Descartes, writing about the need to construct physics with the help of
He was ordained in 1751 and was called to teach philosophy at the Colegio experimentation and mathematics. However, as Father Honorato Fabri had
Maximo in 1754. According to Fabri, during the time that Abad was prefect of done before him, Abad defends the 'substantial and accidental' forms of the
the Colegio de San Ildefonso in Mexico City, he was (as Campoy had been be- Scholastics above those of the moderns. Abad quotes Fabri and states that
fore him) active in reforming the courses taught there. In 1764, Abad was ap- Fabri had developed a reformed and moderate Aristotelian system in which
pointed rector of the seminar of San Francisco Javier in Queretaro where he m o d e r n and ancient ideas were eclectically mixed:
taught theology. During this period, he devoted m u c h time to writing poetry
According to Fabri, primary matter is nothing more than the elementary parti-
and to his translation of Virgil. W h e n s u m m o n e d by the Provincial Father Ce-
cles or indivisible corpuscules of fire, water, air, and earth. He claims, in con-
ballos, Abad traveled to San Ildefonso in Mexico City, to study, together with trast to Gassendi and Descartes, that such corpuscles are heterogeneous and
other reformers, the viability of academic reform. different among themselves. He agrees, however, with Descartes that the cor-
W h e n all Jesuits were banished from Mexico in 1767, Abad relocated to puscles are simple in themselves and not yet compound, even when elements
are compound and not simple. . . . Regarding material form, Father Honorato
Ferrara, Italy. Abad's major literary work, De Deo Deoque Homine (or Heroic
demonstrates that it is not an absolute entity but a modal and relative being or
Poem), was printed in Venice and received m u c h praise from the public. It
a pure mode and a modification of elementary particles, a modification that
was reprinted, enlarged, and corrected in Ferrara in 1775. According to Fabri, consists in the combination, harmony, order, shape, and proportion of the ele-
in addition to scientific-mathematical, literary, and theological writings, Abad mentary particles which he calls substantial form, insofar as it transforms sub-
also left a philosophical work entitled Tratado del conodmiento de Dios. The best stance into act, that is, makes substance sensible and able to operate sensibly.
He argues that this is Aristotle's real thought and that Aristotle was best under-
example of his philosophical work, however, is his coursebook for philoso-
stood by the oldest Greek philosophers and by many of the Latins, among
phy. 97 Abad died in Bologne, in 1779. 98
whom he mentions Cayetano. Regarding the substantial absolute forms, as
Abad's work is the most profound of the innovative philosophical work of they are usually taught by the Peripatetics, he openly claims that these forms
the Jesuits. His Curso was influential; a thorough treatment of m o d e r n ideas. 99 were introduced in the School through the perverse and tendentious interpre-
This coursebook, which is n o longer entitled Cursus Philosophicus, but simply tation of the Arabs. . . .'01
Philosophia, can be found at the Colegio de San Pedro y San Pablo in Mexico
City. It was used to teach a course from 1754-1756 and includes discussions 101. "Segun el, la materia prima no es otra cosa que las particulas elementales o
100
corpusculos indivisibles del fuego, del agua, del aire y de la tierra, y afirma contra
of logic, physics, and metaphysics. Abad was the first Jesuit philosopher Gassend y contra Descartes que esos corpusculos son heterogeneos y diferentes entre si
w h o attempted to assimilate, rather t h a n merely attack, the ideas of m o d e r n /especfficamente; conviene, sin embargo, con aquellos al establecer que son simples en
si mismos y no compuestos todavia, aun cuando los elementos sean compuestos y no
philosophers. simples. . . . Mas en cuanto a la forma material, ensena el P. Honorato que no es una
In his discussion of logic, Abad considers Caramuel, Carleton, Descartes entidad absoluta, sino Un ser modal y relativo o modo puro y modification de las
particulas elementales, que consiste en la diversa combination, armonia, orden, figura
and the Cartesians. In physics, h e mentions the 'moderns' in general and says y proportion de aquellas y al que llama forma sustancial, en cuanto que constituye en
acto la substancia, esto es, la hace sensible y capaz de operar sensiblemente: que este es
97. Maneiro and Fabri, Vidas de mexicanos ilustres del sigh XVLII, p. 175. el autentico pensamiento de Aristoteles, lo defiende esforzadamente, y que asi en-
98. Redmond, Bibliography of the Philosophy, p. 1. lendieron a Aristoteles los mejores y mas antiguos interpretes griegos y muchos latinos,
99. Navarro, La introduction de lafilosofia moderna en Mexico, p. 150. entre los que enumera a Cayetano. Y respecto de las formas sustanciales absolutas,
100. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 21, nos. 1-3. The UNAM is como conuinmenlc las cnsefian los peripaleticos, afirma abierlamente que fueron m-
preparing an edition of his Metafisica and of some writings on naliiral philosophy. Irodncidas en la liscucln a Haves de la perversa y tendenciosa interpretation de los
The edition is being prepared by Conception Abcllan, Ginliana Ancidei, ami Maurtdo .iiiihes." Diego Jose Ahad, Philosophia Ntittmdis. Dispiilatioiii's in oclo lihros Physkorum
Beuchot. Aristotllis (1756), p. I I.
156 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o E i g h t e e n t h Century 157

However, following Suarez, Abad defends the traditional system of the sub- he taught philosophy. He t h e n lived in Merida, Yucatan w h e r e he taught
stantial forms. That is, he supports atomism in physics but not in metaphysics. canon law.
He observes that m a n y Aristotelian claims concerning h e a v e n were aban- In 1767, Father Alegre was s u m m o n e d to Mexico City in order to continue
doned by the Scholastics after the invention Of the telescope, which permit- Father Francisco Florencia's Historia of his Jesuit province. At this time, the Je-
ted m a n to see the spots of the sun. Our understanding of the vacuum, ac- suits were expelled from New Spain, and Alegre travelled to Bologne w h e r e
cording to Abad, was also modified after n e w evidence emerged in light of he wrote o n mathematics, poetry, and theology. His Institutionum Theologi-
experiments carried out by Torricelli, Othon de Gericke, and Robert Boyle. carum libri XVIII were published in Venice in 1789, one year after his death. 107
Abad also mentions Maignan and makes several references to Descartes in Alegre also wrote an Ars rhetorices ex Tullii praeceptis concinnata, printed in
subjects related to h u m a n philosophy and to changes in our understanding of Parma, and a Prolusion de syntaxi, written in 1750. los These works were proba-
various topics. Although he usually defended the Scholastic tradition, Abad bly written w h e n h e taught grammar and rhetoric at San Pedro y San Pablo.
was open to some ideas of m o d e r n philosophy. We also have two letters by Alegre addressed to Clavigero in which he de-
scribes his philosophy course and discusses the ways in which he would like
to organize it to include m o d e r n ideas. Alegre was older t h a n Clavigero but
Other figures
nonetheless a close and trusted friend. Alegre's brilliant eclectic background
During the same period, Father Ignacio Blanco (probably Ignacio Javier made h i m a competent adviser to Clavigero, and thus he became instrumental
Blanco w h o was born in Mexico City in 1726 and died in Bologne in 1792) in the reform of philosophical studies in Jesuit schools and in Mexico. 109
102
wrote on logic for his 1757-1758 course in Puebla. And betwee n 1758 and
1760, Father Raymund o Mariano Cerdan wrote a coursebook for the Colegio Francisco Javier Clavigero
de Santo Tomas in Guadalajara, 103 in which he makes reference to the atom-
ists, the Cartesians, and the Gassendists in order to attack them. 1 0 4 Father Father Clavigero was born September 9, 1732 in Veracruz. 110 His father ed-
J u a n Angel de Ochoa wrote a coursebook o n logic which h e used to teach in ucated h i m at h o m e until 1741 w h e n he entered the Jesuit Colegio de San
1759 at the Colegio de San Ildefonso in Puebla. Father Antonio Jose de Jugo Jeronimo in Puebla. He t h e n attended the Colegio de San Ignacio, also in
(born in Parral in 1733; died in Civitta Vechia in 1801) wrote a coursebook for Puebla.
a class on physics that he taught from 1765-1767. 1 0 5 In this work w e find a He decided to become a priest and joined the Jesuit Seminary o n Febru-
strong critique of the corpuscular or atomist philosophers such as Descartes, ary 13, 1744, and in 1749, at the age of eighteen, he professed in the Society
Gassendi, andTosca. 106 of Jesus. In 1750 he began his priestly studies, whic h according to the Jesuit

107. Beristain de Souza, Biblioteca Hispano Americana Septentrional, vol. 1, pp. 114—
Francisco Javier Alegre 16, no. 165. See also Mauricio Beuchot, "La ley natural como mndamento de la ley
positiva en Francisco Javier Alegre," Dieciocho. Hispanic Enlightenment, Aesthetics and Lit-
Francisco Javier Alegre was born in Veracruz in 1729. He studied philoso- Arary Theory 14 (1991): 124-29.
108. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 25, no. 363. The Prolusio de
p h y at the Colegio de San Ignacio in Puebla, and he entered the Society in syntax! has been edited by Osorio in his Floresta de gramdtica, reterica y poetica, p. 198.
1747. He taught grammar and rhetoric at the Colegio Maximo de San Pedro y 109. Navarro, La introduction de lafilosofia moderna enMexico, pp. 146 ff.
110. For information about the life and work of Francisco Javier Clavigero, we fol-
San Pablo in Mexico City as well as in Veracruz. He carried out his theological
low the biography written by Juan Luis Maneiro in his De vitis aliquot mexicanorum, alio-
studies in Mexico, but, because of poor health, h e was sent to Havana w h e r e rumque, qui sive virtute, sive litteris, Mexici imprimisfloruerunt(Bologne, 1792). There are
Ihree translations: one by Bernabe Navarro, J. L. Maneiro—M. Fabri, Vidas de mexicanos
102. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 57, no. 59. ilustrcs del sigh XVIII, 2d ed. (Mexico: UNAM, 1989); another by Jesus Gomez Fregoso,
103. Ibid., p. 80, no. 95. Clavigero. Ensayo de interpretation y aportaciones para su estudio (Guadalajara, Jalisco, Mex-
104. Navarro, La introduction de lafilosofia moderna en Mexico, p. 150. ico: Univcrsidad de Guadalajara, 1979); and a third one by Alberto Valonzuela Rodarte,
./. /.. Maneiro, Vidas de algunos mexicanos ilustrcs (Mexico: UNAM, 1988). We have also
105. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 206, no. 290.
taken relevant data front A Clinniica IVliUv,, I'rancisco Clavigeroy aires ensayos (Mexico:
106. Navarro, La introduction de la filosoffa moderna en Mexico, pp. 140-41.
Bdsde I.I Librerfa Parroqutal, 1985)
158 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Eighteenth Century 159

customs of the time included humanities, philosophy, and theology. In addi- tools for the revitalization of more traditional ideas. While these thinkers did
tion to strong training in classical and modern languages, Clavigero also make room for new ideas, there was a strong tendency to preserve more tra-
learned Nahuatl and Mixtec. Father Rafael Campoy introduced him to the ditional doctrines; this resulted in a form of eclecticism. Clavigero was an
Mexican codices bestowed to the Society by Sigiienza y Gongora and to which eclectic who tried to synthesize or reconcile Aristotelian-Scholastic thought
Clavigero had access at the Colegio de San Pedro y San Pablo in Mexico City. with modern ideas.
Clavigero then moved to the Colegio de San Ildefonso, Mexico City where As Maneiro observes, Clavigero tried to fit the ideas of modern thinkers,
he later became prefect. He also taught rhetoric at the Colegio de San Pedro y from Bacon and Descartes to Franklin, into the basic structure of traditional
San Pablo, even before being ordained. After ordination, he was appointed to philosophy.113 Thus, modern philosophical ideas, as well as the most recent
work at the Colegio de San Gregorio, located next to that of San Pedro y San scientific developments of his time, were incorporated into his work. Accord-
Pablo, where he taught Indians. From this position, he moved to the Colegio ing to Maneiro, "In his Fisica Particular, Clavigero presents some of Descartes's
de San Xavier, in Puebla. And in 1764 he was sent to Valladolid (today known theses, such as: the universe is indefinite or indeterminate (infinite?); the
as Morelia) where he taught philosophy at the colegio run by the Society empyreal sky is not the limit of the world (universe); the ashen light ('little
there. It is claimed that, as a teenager, Don Miguel Hidalgo may have at- light') of the moon comes from the rays of the sun reflected from the earth.
tended Clavigero's courses, but no supporting documents exist to substantiate He gives us his opinions concerning the shape of water particles, magnetism,
this claim. Certainly, however, there is evidence of Clavigero's influence on the soul of animals, the nature and functions of the heart, the union of soul
the work of Hidalgo. and body, and how this depends upon the pineal gland, external and internal
From 1766 to 1767, Clavigero taught philosophy in Guadalajara. In 1767 sensations, and their subjectivity, etc."114 In his work on physics, Clavigero
when the Jesuits were expelled from the country by Charles III of Spain, discusses the recent scientific developments of his time, questioning the effec-
Clavigero went to Bologne where he lived until his death in 1787. tiveness of their concrete applications.
Bibliographers make reference to various philosophical works written by Clavigero's attempt to reconcile Scholasticism with modern thought was
Clavigero. Some of the mentioned works have not survived, and so the refer- influenced by the methods and terminology of Scholasticism. This was effec-
ences to these works cannot be validated. Maneiro speaks about a Curso de tive because his audience was familiar with these methods and could be con-
fllosofla which was planned by Clavigero, however only the Fisica Particular vinced by them. His terminology was also strongly influenced by his Scholas-
survives. His Didlogo entre Paledfilo y Filaletes, which would be an opuscule tic training. This, too, proved to be an advantage as his readers were
against the argument of authority in physics, has not been preserved.111 His acquainted with this terminology.
Historia antigua de Mexico has been preserved and in it, he discusses strictly Nonetheless, although Clavigero tried to model his method on the Scholas-
philosophical topics as well as other themes related to philosophy, such as the tic's dedication to rigorous argumentation, too often he adoped the method of
history of the Indian world view and some considerations concerning philo- simply expounding the efficiency of modern scientific advances without
sophical anthropology and philosophy of history.112 providing any arguments in their favor. Furthermore, although he criticized
/arguments that rested upon some appeal to authority, he actually used such
The encounter between Scholastic philosophy and
113. Maneiro, De vitis aliquot mexicanorum, aliorumque, qui sive virtute, sive litteris, Mex-
modern philosophy
ici imprimis floruerunt, in translation by Fregoso, p. 41; Navarro, Cultura mexicana mod-
Most thinkers who were active in introducing modern philosophy in erna en el sigh XVIII, p. 100.
114. "En la Fisica Particular, Clavigero nos expone estas tesis de Descartes: que el
Mexico were only interested in modern ideas insofar as these could serve as imiverso es indellnido o indeterminado (ynfinito?); que el cielo empireo no es el
li'mile del mundo (universo); que la luz cenicienta ('lucesilla') de la luna proviene de
111. Gomez Fregoso, Clavigero. Ensayo de interpretation y aportaciones para su estudio, los rayos del sol reflejados desde la tierra; nos da sus opiniones sobre la figura de las
p. 45; Navarro, La introduction de lafilosofia moderna en Mexico, p. 176. partfculas del agua; sobre el magnetismo; sobre el alma de los animales; sobre la natu-
112. The manuscript of the Physica Particularis rests at the Public Library of the State ralcza y luncioncs del cora/on; sobre la union del alma con el cuerpo y su residencia
of Jalisco, in Guadalajara (Manuscript 209). Clavigero's Historia Antigua de Mexico hail a en la gUnduU pineal; sobre las sensaciones exlernas e internas y su subjelividad,
Spanish and an Italian version. The edition used here is the Spanish one, published by eicclera." Navarro, Cultimi mcxicana moderna en el siglo XVIII, p. 98.
Father Mariano Cuevas, 4lh ed. (Mexico: Editorial Pomia, 1')74).
160 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Eighteenth Century 161

arguments, claiming, for example, that certain aspects of modern physics Clavigero appealed to modern philosophy in order to support traditional
could be accepted based upon support in the Holy Scriptures. He also accepted Scholastic arguments. Zavala claims that Clavigero was aware that he was
some theories, not substantiated by sufficient evidence, over other theories continuing the struggle initiated by Las Casas in his defense of Indian rights:
that were based more strongly upon scientific experimentation. For example, "One can find in Clavigero an awareness of the possible affinity between the
he favored Tycho Brahe's system over those of Copernicus and Galileo.115 ideas of the eighteenth century and those Christian ideas of the sixteenth
It can be said that Clavigero's Physica Partkularis is a scientific rather than a century that were used to defend the capacities and liberty of the Indians."118
philosophical work because he merely describes and comments upon various Like Bartolome de las Casas, Clavigero made use of both scientific anthro-
scientific theories and their methodological foundations. His defense of the pology and philosophical anthropology (or the philosophy of man) in order
new physics is based on pragmatic considerations, for he based his assessment to demonstrate that Indians were not inferior to Europeans. He pointed out
on the results of experimentation rather than on theoretical speculation.116 the positive physical and cultural disposition of American Indians and argued
that they were endowed with the same kind of rationality as Eurpoeans. Any
Philosophical anthropology differences in the way this rationality manifested itself could be overcome
In examining Clavigero's eclecticism within the context of the anthropol- through education; these differences, he argued, were not due to any inher-
ogy and philosophy of history he developed in his Historia Antigua de Mexico, ent weaknesses of Indians. It followed, then, that Indians were entitled to the
we find various issues concerning philosophical anthropology. Like Las Casas, same rights as Europeans.
Clavigero was concerned with issues of justice, especially regarding the rights In order to defend his claims regarding the rights of Indians, Clavigero in-
of Indians. He, too, sought to defend the rights of the Indians against the Eu- sisted that their bodily composition, mental faculties, and cultural capacities
ropeans. are not, as de Pauw had claimed, degraded or inferior. The mental faculties of
In his Historia Antigua de Mexico, Clavigero engages in a debate with Cor- Indians (memory, understanding, will), are not less developed than those of
nelius de Pauw and William Robertson concerning the rationality of the Indi- Europeans; indeed, Clavigero claimed that Indians are superior both in their
ans. The issue of whether the Indians had a rational soul was no longer de- intellectual and their practical or moral virtues. Finally, the cultural capacities
bated, but the issue of their level of rationality and thus of the rights they of Indians are not inferior; their language, their laws, and their religion are
deserved was still an issue open to debate. Some claimed that the inherent clear indicators of the force of their intellect. Let us now look at Clavigero's
weaknesses of the Indian soul were such that the Indians would always be in argument.
need of European protection and domination. Clavigero's defense of the Indi- De Pauw claimed that the bodily composition of Indians was the result of
ans is one example of his attempt to reconcile some Scholastic theses, such as the corruption of the air and bad climate, and thus they were disfigured and
those of Vitoria and Las Casas (which had the purpose of defending the inferior to Europeans in this respect (and this was a clear indication of their
human rights of Indians based on the thesis that Indians too had essential dig- intellectual deficiencies). Clavigero argued that this is false, that Indians have
nity), with certain enlightened or modern principles; for example, the de- a normal bodily composition and de Pauw commits a serious mistake in tak-
mand for scientific evidence to settle issues. ing the European body to be the standard of normalcy. Clavigero also indi-
Silvio Zavala observes that, in this debate concerning the question of the cated that the numerous 'irregularities' and 'weaknesses' that could be ob-
nature of the Indian soul, Clavigero consistently spoke in favor of the Indians: served among Indians did not attest to their inferiority but were the result of
"The personal conviction of the Mexican Jesuit was in favor of the intellec- the miseries and inhumane work loads imposed upon them by Europeans.11'
tual abilities of the Indians and of the power of education over reputedly nat-
ural impediments."117 In his arguments in defense of the rights of Indians, luales de los indios de America y al poder de la education sobre los impedimentos que se
reputaban naturales." Zavala, La defensa de los derechos del hombre en America Latina, p. 52.
115. Ibid., p. 131. 118. "La conciencia de la posible afinidad de las ideas dieciochescas con las ideas
116. C. Ulloa Cardenas, "Cambio insensible: la filosoti'a dc Francisco Javier Clavl- crislianas del siglo XVI que defendieron la capacidad y libertad de los indios, se des-
jero," typescript (Universidad de Guadalajara), pp. 2-3. cubre en el propiO Clavigero." Ibid., p. 53.
117. "La conviction personal del jcsuila mcxicano cm i.ivoralile a las doles iiilclec- I I'}. Clavigero, llistorin Antigua tic Mexico, p. SO1;.
162 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Eighteenth Century 163

Concerning the mental faculties of Native Americans, de Pauw claimed inferior to those of Europeans, that they are capable of studying all the sci-
that they are weaker, citing their poor intellect and weak memory. He ences, even the more abstract ones, and that if they were properly educated, if
claimed that they are unable to remember what has happened the previous they were brought up from childhood in seminaries under the tutelage of good
day; incapable of ordering their thoughts; and even, due to their cold will, in- teachers, and if they were protected and encouraged with prizes and rewards,
capable of loving. Thus, de Pauw portrays the Indians as indolent and stupid. one would find among the Indians philosophers, mathematicians, and theolo-
These claims are outlandish and unsupported by any valid arguments, and gians who would be able to compete with the most famous of Europe."120
did not even merit a reply. But Clavigero did reply. In his response, Clavigero In light of this evidence for the strength of the Indian intellect, evidence
called upon his own childhood experiences with Indians. He refuted de Pauw which in itself contradicts de Pauw's primitive characterizations of Indians,
by offering experimental data and by appealing to the most reliable authori- Clavigero rejected as inadmissable the description of Indians as 'barbarians'.
ties on the subject. Clavigero knew Indians well and even spoke their lan- To further substantiate his defense of the Indians, Clavigero used a strategy
guage. He was thus able to provide a fuller, more accurate account of Indians similar to one used by Bartolome de las Casas two centuries earlier (in his de-
than had de Pauw. bate against Juan Gines de Sepulveda), arguing that the terms 'savage', 'bar-
Given his view of Indians, it is surprising that de Pauw voiced indignation barian', etc., cannot be used to describe the Indians. He writes, "Today we call
over the Spaniards' doubts concerning the rationality of Indians. He ridiculed barbarian and savage those men who, driven less by reason than by whim
such doubts, claiming that the Indians were accepted as human not by con- and natural desires, do not live in society, nor have laws for their own gov-
viction but as a result of Pope Paul ni's decree. To this Clavigero answered ernment, nor judges who can adjudicate their differences, nor superiors who
that the doubt concerning the rationality of Indians was motivated by Euro- watch over their conduct and exercise the necessary skills to meet the needs
pean avarice and by the evil and contemptuous attitudes of people like de and miseries of life; those who, finally, have no idea of the Divinity, or have
Pauw. The fact that Spaniards had to appeal to the Pope was only to guaran- not established the cult with which to honor it."121 Clavigero's argument is
tee, just as the missionaries and Bishop Garces had wanted to do, that natural sound because in his work on history he shows that the culture of the Indians
rights would be respected and obeyed by force of positive law. Further, Clav- was strong and autonomous, having a well-developed religion;122 governors
igero claimed that, under the influence of Las Casas, all of this had already and magistrates to provide laws and justice; and sciences and arts, even
been settled by the Catholic Monarchs and the Laws of the Indies, but had highly developed fine arts. Clavigero, therefore, found no valid reason to ex-
been overlooked for the sake of other interests. clude Indians from the category of civilized beings.
According to Clavigero, the attempts to educate Indians prove that Indians In his work, de Pauw said that Indians did not make use of currency or
are not inferior to Europeans. Missionaries had made much progress with In- iron and that they lacked the ability to write and to build ships and bridges.
dians and were convinced of their intellectual capabilities. The Indians had Furthermore, he claimed that the mathematical system of the Indians was
had their own cultures, and, in the case of the Aztecs, Mayas, Incas, and some
others, these cultures were not insignificant. Furthermore, from the very be- 120. "Despues de una experiencia tan grande y de un estudio tan prolijo, por el que
creo poder decidir con nienos peligro de errar, protesto a De Pauw y a toda Europa, que
ginning of the process of acculturation, Indians learned European grammar, las almas de los mexicanos en nada son inferiores a las de los europeos; que son capaces
rhetoric, philosophy, and medicine, in addition to having mastery of these de todas las_ciencias, aun las mas abstractas, y que si seriamente se cuidara de su edu-
disciplines from the perspective of their own culture. cation, si desde ninos se criasen en seminarios bajo buenos maestros y si se protegieran
y alentaran con premios, se verfan entre los americanos, filosofos, matematicos y teolo-
Clavigero taught Indians at the Colegio de San Gregorio in Mexico City and gos que pudieran competir con los mas famosos de Europa." Ibid., p. 518b.
at the Colegio of San Xavier in Puebla, for both Jesuit schools were devoted to 121. "Barbaras y salvajes llamamos hoy dia a los hombres que, conducidos mas por
capricho y deseos naturales que por la razon, ni viven congregados en sociedad, ni
the instruction of Indians. Precisely because he had first-hand knowledge of tienen leyes para su gobiemo, ni jueces que ajusten sus diferencias, ni superiores que
the intellectual abilities of Indians, Clavigero could say that "After experiences velen sobre su conducta, ni ejercitan las artes indispensables para remediar las necesi-
dades y miserias de la vida; los que, I'inalmente, no tienen idea de la Divinidad, o no
that brought me into close contact with Indians and enabled me to study them li.in cslahli'cidt> el nillo con que dcbcn honrailc." [bid., p. 525ab.
closely, I think that my observations stand in less danger of being wrong. 1 an- 122. Although il was lull of deficiencies, as ll was only natural because they did noi
have Kcvcl.ilion, Clavigero says.
swer to de Pauw and to all of Europe thai the souls of Mexicans are in no w.iy
164 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Eighteenth Century 165

weak. Clavigero answered these claims with his well-based observations: he Bartolome de las Casas two centuries earlier, Clavigero employed the results
indicated that Indians used cocoa seeds as money; that they used a picto- of his study to prevent the legitimation of slavery and the oppressive 'tute-
graphic type of writing, which, though different from European writing, was lage' of Europeans over Indians. Clavigero knew that if he proved that Indi-
sophisticated enough for them to express even the most abstract ideas; and ans were neither physically nor intellectually inferior to the Europeans then
that their mathematical systems were sophisticated and even included the their human dignity would not be questioned. If this could be demonstrated,
use of zero. Moreover, he pointed out that the Indians had amazing architec- then the so-called defects of the Indians would no longer be viewed in terms
tural abilities, excellent astronomical sciences, and, if they did not build ships, of their intrinsic weaknesses but as the reult of the exploitation and abuse of
it was only because they never were a people of navigators. Europeans. Clavigero's concern was to defend the rights of human beings.
Finally, however, Clavigero realized that it was useless to continue to re-
spond to de Pauw's false claims. He stopped his work on the defense of the In- The philosophy of history
dians and moved to the task of preparing a work on their language, religion, It is possible to find Clavigero's philosophy of history articulated in various
and laws. Thus, Clavigero's philosophical anthropology starts from the as- works. Ronan claims that Clavigero's philosophy of history is a characteristi-
sumption of the equality of all human beings, equality that leads to equity, cally Christian philosophy of history.124 In the historical works of Clavigero,
that in turn is linked to justice. It is the same position as that of Bartolome de Ronan finds the assertion that God intervenes in the actions of man and
las Casas: the project to ensure justice for all humans. Like Las Casas, Clav- throughout history. This divine intervention has four modalities: (1) it is the
igero based his arguments for human rights upon traditional doctrines. Like ultimate and most profound explanation of the course of history; (2) it guides
the thinkers of the Enlightenment, he was concerned with establishing the the lives of men in a metaphysical way, without reducing their liberty; (3) it
equality of rights for all human beings. He brought together traditional phi- takes history toward the fulfilment of certain divine ends—the plans of Prov-
losophy and modern philosophy in service of this ideal. And despite the fact idence; and (4) it permits the intervention of evil as something that intro-
that he became the victim of the violation of his rights when he was arbitrar- duces imperfection or limitation into human history. The intervention of evil
ily expelled from the country, he continued to defend human rights in Italy. occurs because, as a result of their subordination to God, evils come to pro-
Clavigero's philosophical-anthropological task in his Historia Antigua de duce goodness to man.
Mexico was the study of the cultural products of the Indians as effects and Although Clavigero did not achieve a philosophical synthesis, he did bring
signs of their creative and cognitive powers. His acquaintance with the an- together certain traditional and modern elements in order to defend the Indi-
cient and modern works of the Indians made possible the proper evaluation ans who were unjustly judged by some Europeans. These abusive, 'enlight-
of their intellectual and moral abilities and disposition and thereby made pos- ened' men based their findings upon the 'progressive' ideas of thinkers such
sible the disavowal of European claims that Indians were 'barbaric' or 'sav- as Buffon, de Pauw, Raynal, and Robertson. Clavigero used his scientific,
age.'123 Clavigero's work did not end here. Following the precedent set by philosophical, and historical knowledge to vindicate, even from his exile in
Italy, the dignity of his humiliated homeland.
123. When Clavigero speaks of the natives of California, who were so savage and
unrefined—as he himself notes in his narrations of the history of that place—he de-
fends their equality in relation to the rest of mankind. He writes, "En cuanto a la alma
no son distintos de los restarites hijos de Adan. Los que se han criado en las selvas Oratoxjans
tienen aquellos vicios e imperfecciones que en todos los pafses son consiguientes a la
vida salvaje; son rudos, muy limitados en sus conocimientos por falta de ideas, pere- The Congregation of the Oratory of San Felipe Neri was a new order
zosos por falta de estimulo, inconstantes, precipitados en sus resoluciones y muy incli-
nados a los juegos y diversiones pueriles por falta de freno; pero por otra parte carecen (founded in the sixteenth century) which became one of the most important
de ciertos vicios muy comunes entre otros barbaros y aiin en algunos pueblos cultOS, a
saber, no se embriagan, no hurtan, no rifien entre los pr6ximos sino contra los de OtTM
tribus enemigas; y no son obstinados ni tercos." (Regarding their soul Ibey are not (111- vices common among other barbarian countries, and even in some refined ones, that
ferent from the other sons of Adam. Those who have grown in the jungles have those is, they do not gel drunk, do not steal, do mil quarrel among themselves, only against
vices and imperfections that in all countries are linked to the savage life; they are null members of enemy tribes; and they are neither stubborn nor obstinate.) t'ramisni
mentary, very limited in their knowledge for lack of ideas, lazy for lack ol stimulus, In- Javier Clavigero, Historia it la AMi/iiui 0 Boja California (Mexico: Po , I''70), p. 52.
constant, hasty in their resolutions, and very much attracted lo childish games and ru 124 C. Ronan, Praneisce Javtn Clavtjiro Hfun wfluMadam Bnlifhttnmtnt, His lift
terlninmenls .is they lack restraint; hut on the ulhci hand, ihey do nut have certain iiiiil Works (Rot Insiliiiiuiu IIMiiili uni '.u, i, I.III. I, \u, I'i77)
166 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Eighteenth Century 167

intellectual forces in eighteenth-century Mexico. It had a colegio in San fonso in Mexico City. He then moved to the Colegio de San Miguel el Grande,
Miguel el Grande, where a good deal of the philosophical renewal in New where he became a priest at the Congregacion del Oratorio de San Felipe Neri
Spain originated. The instruction provided by the Oratorians vividly reflected on November 15,1764. In 1767, he traveled to Europe and worked as procu-
their interest in introducing new doctrines of modern philosophy. The Orato- rator of his congregation in Spain and Italy. He used these journeys to study
rians pursued this project of modernization with an intensity that paralleled the works of modern philosophers.
the efforts of the Jesuits. In Pisa, Gamarra obtained a doctorate in canon law and was accepted as
The Oratorians of New Spain may have been influenced by the priests of member of several scientific associations, including the Bologne Academy. He
the Society of Jesus whose way of teaching became an inspiration for other was even distinguished by Pope Clement XIII as private apostolic protono-
orders. Or they may have been influenced by the Oratorians of Europe, who tary. He returned to Mexico around 1770 and was ordained the same year. He
were devoted educators. One thing is certain: the Congregation of the Ora- then devoted himself to teaching philosophy and to spreading modern Euro-
tory was well represented in Mexico, and Father Jose Antonio Fernandez was pean ideas in New Spain. He was careful, however, to remain within the lim-
one such representative. In 1772, he wrote a discourse on the "Historia de la its of Catholic orthodoxy. He even became censor and commissioner of the
filosofia de Aristoteles, inutilidad de ella para la sagrada teologia y ventajas y Inquisition in 1778.
utilidades de la filosofiamoderna eclectica"125 in SanMiguel el Grande. As the Gamarra taught philosophy at the Colegio de San Miguel where he was in
last words of the title suggest, the work tried to reconcile traditional and mod- charge of the Oratory. When, during Bucareli's period as Viceroy, he became
ern philosophy. In this work, Fernandez made use of a popular and wide- Rector and Prefect there, Gamarra reformed the curriculum and modernized
spread version of modern philosophy known as eclecticism. This philosophy the teaching methods. The colegio was so highly esteemed that in 1740 it had
was a branch of modern philosophy which synthesized modern ideas with already been granted a concession allowing its pupils to obtain degrees from
more traditional doctrines giving rise to a new sort of Christian philosophy. the Universidad Real y Pontificia de Mexico. Gamarra maintained close links
with the university, which unanimously approved his book as the official phi-
losophy coursebook. However, the university was also the cause of some
J u a n B e n i t o Diaz d e G a m a r r a y Davalos
hardships. Eventually, he became embroiled in controversies generated by
A good example of such an 'eclectic' philosopher is Juan Benito Diaz de his modern ideas. He found opponents both at his university as well as at
Gamarra y Davalos who was strongly influenced by the Portuguese philoso- other institutions. Gamarra died when he was not yet forty, on November 1,
pher Luis Antonio Verney.126 Like the Jesuits who preceded him in the 1783.
process of modernization of Mexican philosophy, Gamarra had encountered
a number of difficulties in his efforts to develop and communicate effectively Works
the modern ideas imported from Europe. However, once these obstacles had In the few examples of Gamarra's Academias Filosdficas (Mexico, 1774) that
been overcome, he wrote a coursebook which was highly acclaimed even in have been preserved,128 Gamarra emerges as a thinker who encouraged
Europe. It was eventually adopted as a textbook by universities in Spain. pupils to discuss the theories of the new physics, the new explanations of
This was a rare honor for a text written by a philosopher from the New electricity, the new optics, and the soul of irrational animals.
World. Gamarra's major contribution to philosophy is the Elementa Recentioris
Juan Benito Dfas de Gamarra y Davalos was born in Zamora, Michoacan, Philosophiae (Mexico, 1774),129 in which he develops and elaborates his topics
on March 21, 1745.127 He studied the humanities at the Colegio de San Ilde-
cion de Mexico, ed. C. Herrejon Peredo (Zamora, Michoacan: El Colegio de Michoacan,
125. Redmond, Bibliography of the Philosophy, p. 40, no. 293. 1984), pp. 339-58.
126. M. del C. Rovira, Bclecticos Portugueses del sigh XVIIIy algunas de sus influencias in 128. Compiled in Juan Benito Diaz de Gamarra, Tratados, ed. J. Gaos (Mexico:
America (Mexico: UNAM, 1979, reprint), p. 183 If. UNAM, 1974),
127. F. Fuentes Galindo, "Don Benito Dias de Gamarra y Davalos," in lliiiiiuiiidiides, 129. Juan Benito Dial de Gamarra, Sltmtntosdi Filosofia Modtma, Intra tad trans,
vol. 1, no. 1 (Mexico: 1943); Bernabe Navarro, "Diaz de Gamana, icprcseiilrtnlc plcnn by Bernabi Navarro (Mexico: UNAM, 1963), The Emulation ol Blmunta RutntiorU
del proccsn de modernidad en el Mexico colonial," in lliiiiitinismo y liencln fit hi forma I'liihsophiiitby Ueriiahc1 Navarro li Incomplete,
168 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Eighteenth Century 169

with a modern outlook, similar to Christian Wolff's. The work includes a His- professed aim was primarily didactic, and as such, he was less concerned with
toria de lafilosofia (which is the first history of philosophy written in the New detailed and original research than with good organization and explanatory
World), a Ldgica, a Metafisica (containing the Wolffian divisions into Ontology, accuracy. He is considered an eclectic because he appeared to be caught be-
Psychology, and Natural Theology, an Etica, a Geometria (this section was not tween Scholasticism and modern philosophy, taking elements of both in order
written by Gamarra but by the mathematician Augustm de Rotea) and a Fisica to create a 'perpetual philosophy'. His eclecticism is critical of both scholastic
(which contained a section on Cosmology). and modern philosophers, even while showing a marked preference for the
Gamarra's Errores del entendimiento humano (Puebla, 1781) is also part of latter. While Gamarra's critical attitude makes him anti-dogmatic, his inten-
his philosophical corpus. This was published under the pseudonym of Juan tion was to purify Scholasticism and to select the best modern doctrines. Be-
Felipe de Bendiaga, an anagram of Gamarra's complete name.130 More than a cause eclecticism is in itself selective and because any selection implies an ap-
philosophical work, this is the work of a philosopher who has a strong peda- peal to some criteria, Gamarra supported theses from both scholastics and
gogical focus and a clear goal to popularize philosophy. The title indicates the moderns and pragmatically based his selections upon the utility they would
rationalism and 'enlightenment' of the author, who argues that moral and so- serve in his goal to create a perpetual philosophy, that is, a philosohy which
cial mistakes are the result of misunderstandings. Gamarra fights against the would enable us to detect valid truths independently of any particuiar school
anti-scientific prejudices of the time, and he deals with concrete questions. or tendency.
For instance, he suggests some health and hygiene reforms adjusted to na- This eclecticism explains why Gamarra cannot be considered either a pure
ture; he attacks the system of education, indicating the need to foster the sci- Scholastic or a strictly modern philosopher. His aim was to supersede the nar-
ences and to distinguish clearly philosophy from the sciences; he proposes so- row confines of any one school of thought or trend. On some occasions, he re-
cial changes in keeping with his ideas of progress and the specific needs of tains the traditional and rejects the modern; on others, more often, he adopts
New Spain. Despite the fact that Gamarra never opposed the government of the modern and excludes the traditional. His eagerness to modernize scholas-
the Viceroy and did not view his activities as revolutionary in spirit, his Er- tic philosophy is reflected in his interest for more recent philosophical devel-
rores del entendimiento humano has led some scholars to view Gamarra as a pre- opments. He does not always balance these two tendencies well, at times re-
cursor of the wars of independence. vealing an exaggerated modernism, at times an extreme traditionalism.
Other major contributions by Gamarra to the philosophy of New Spain in- Three central concerns characterize the various aspects of his philosophi-
clude a satirical work entitled Memorial Ajustado (Mexico, 1790),I31 the De ve- cal activity: a pedagogical philosophy, reflected in his Mdximas de educacion; a
tusta studiorum ratione in philosophicis.disciplinis reformata (manuscript), as well refined display of argumentation, logically regulated in the Academias or in
as the Mdximas de educacion en la piedad cristiana y en la politica para instruction de the public debates; and the intended philosophical synthesis, never fully
los alumnos del Colegio de San Francisco de Sales del Oratorio de esta villa de San achieved, between Scholasticism and modern philosophy in the Elementos de
Miguel."2 Gamarra also left some writings which deal with religious subjects. filosofia moderna.

Gamarra's philosophy Philosophy of education and logical argumentation


Gamarra has usually been rather imprecisely characterized as an eclec- Whereas in Mdximas de educacidn, Gamarra presents his pedagogical philos-
133
tic. Though he seemed to be aware that he lacked originality and depth, his ophy, in Academias, he summarizes the public events in which his disciples
displayed the doctrines he taught them and which would later appear in his
130. In Gamarra, Tratados. Elementos de Filosofia Moderna.
131. Ibid.
132. Juan Benito Diaz de Gamarra, Mdximas de educacidn, Academias defilosofiav About his Mdximas, Gamarra says that they are "founded on reason and ex-
Academias de Geometria, intro. by C. Herrejon Peredo (Zamora, Michoacan: El Colegio dl perience." 154 These maxims amount to an appeal to virtue. Virtue is appealed
Michoacan, 1983). The text had been left in manuscript form and was recently edited
in facsimile by C. Herrejon Peredo.
133. See V. Junco de Meyer, Gamarra o el eclecticism*} en Mexico (Mexico: londo dl I 34. "... luiuladas en l.i ivi/on y en la cxpci iiiu i.i." (iiimarra, Mtixinnts de eduCttcUn,
Cultura Economics, 1973). p. 16.
170 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o E i g h t e e n t h Century 171

to because a virtuous life is a life in which the perfection of m a n is realized philosophy. In fact, Gamarra even claims that the objective of "[t]hose Stu-
and in perfection w e find happiness: "Let virtue be the m a in object of your dents of philosophy, w h o will in time carry out these Academic Functions,
desires—he tells his pupils—because it is our main duty and the only princi- must prepare themselves by studying geometry, if their philosophy is to be
ple of our happiness." 135 Virtue, however, can only be achieved with effort worthy of such n a m e . Such preparation is provided with m u c h success by the
and practice. And the exercise of virtue is a good way to achieve good ends, Royal Studies of Madrid." 145
says Gamarra, who, as a good moralist, wants to prevent equivocal causality The importance and necessity of geometry for the study of philosophy is
in ethical h u m a n action. 136 discussed by J u a n Jose Mazorra, Gamarra's pupil. Mazorra's speech makes
Virtue brings with it all goods. It offers perfect friendship, as "good friend- reference to the Lecciones matemdtkas written by the Mexican J. I. Bartolache
ship is founded u p o n virtue." 137 Prudence is characterized by Gamarra as that (1769). Concerning mathematics, Mazorra writes that "his Metodo knows
virtue which is central to all other virtues, enabling us to deal moderately h o w to record insensibly in the soul the order of ideas and the accuracy in dis-
with others. 138 An academic debate carried out prudently is one which is not course, which makes a m a n truly wise and just appraiser of things. The excel-
led by pride b u t by the impartial search for truth. 139
Prudence also helps pre- lence of this m e t h o d consists in its accurate and rigorous way of finding and
vent idleness and helps one enjoy work without losing the desire for healthy teaching the hidden truths, beginning by the easiest and mounting by degrees
diversions and leisure. 140 towards the most difficult and obscure." 146 The importance of mathematics
Gamarra also praises the virtue of truthfulness as congruent with the for philosophy is not a m o d e r n insight but was recognized by Thales,
search for t r u t h he emphasized to his pupils. 141
Truthfulness should manifest Pythagoras, Anaxagoras, Democritus, Aristotle, and Plato, w h o did not admit
itself in debates and intelligible, well-grounded arguments. 1 4 2 Such debates to the Academy anyone w h o did not k n o w geometry.
should receive m u c h attention from philosphers because in these exercises
the tools of logic find their application and m u c h can be learned from these Attempt to synthesize scholastic and modern philosophies

displays. These debates b e t w e e n theologians and philosophers, moderated by We have already said that Gamarra's philosophy is eclectic, part scholastic,
other teachers, occurred often as they were quite popular. 143 part modern. His major work, the Elementos, is more strongly scholastic. His
The Academias filosoficas (1772) and the Academias de geometria (1782) are discussion of t h e following topics is influenced most strongly by the scholastic
good examples of such exercises. The former emphasize the significance of tradition: ethics; natural theology; psychology, especially the issues of the spir-
studying the history of philosophy, and they deal equally with Aquinas, ituality and immortality of the soul; certain topics of logic, namely, his treat-
Newton, and Jacquier. 144
We are w a r n e d that t h e senses betray us, and we m e n t of predicabies, propositions and their properties, both intrinsic (matter
are s h o w n h o w w e can prevent this betrayal. In these works, Gamarra antic- and form, quantity and quality) and extrinsic (oppositions and equivalences),
ipates his o w n writings o n the errors of understanding (works which, as we and the syllogism; and his treatment of ontology, with the ensuing discussion
have argued, lacked philosophical depth but had important pedagogical of entities and their divisions, transcendentai properties and principles.
aims). He provides a metaphysical analysis of t h e immortality of t h e soul and Nonetheless, his inspiration, method, and m a n y of his topics can be called
the interplay of mental and corporal powers. On the other hand, it is possible modern. His work carries the traces of certain m o d e r n philosophers, and he
to see the significance of Academias de geometria as a more complete study of was interested in modernizing scholastic philosophy. His numerous references

135. "Sea pues la virtud el principal objecto de vuestros deseos—dice a sus ahun- 145. "Los Cursantes Filosofos, que han de sustentar estas Funciones Academicas
nos—p0r que ella es nuestra principal obligation, y unico principio de nuestra lellii- abrirse el paso con el estudio geometrico, a una Filosofi'a digna de tal nombre, y qual se
dad." Ibid., p. 19. cnsena hoy con tanto fruto en los Reales Estudios de Madrid." Ibid., p. 121.
136. Ibid., p. 29. 146. "Su Metodo sabe gravar insensiblemente en el alma aquel orden en las ideas,
137. "[L]abuena amistad esta fundada en la virtud." Ibid., p. 32. y aqiiclla exactitud en el discurso, que hace a un hombre verdaderamente sabio, y
138. Ibid., p. 39. 139. Ibid., p. 44. justo apreciador de las cosas. La excelencia de este metodo consiste en un exactisimo y
140. Ibid., p. 47. 141. Ibid., p. 49. rigorosfsimo orden de hallar, y cnscnar las verdades incognitas, comenzando por lo
142. Ibid., p. 65. 143. Ibid., p. 77, mas I'acil, y suhicndo despues como por grados hasl.i lo mas diflcultoso y oscuro."
144. Ibid., pp. 96-97. Ibid., p. 125.
172 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Eighteenth Century 173

to major modern thinkers attests to his wide knowledge of modern philoso- Scholastic convictions. Despite his acknowledgment of the validity of Locke's
phy. But this modern influence is most clear in his assimilation and adapta- thesis regarding substance, he does not support the modern view of accidents
tion of new theories with more traditional ones. Gamarra's method is innova- and substance. Gamarra's theories are the result of a transition between
tive; he breaks with the custom of commenting upon works and instead gives scholastic and modern thought. On the relationship between the body and
a systematic exposition of the main problems generated by each subject mat- the soul, for example, Gamarra accepts, on the one hand, the doctrine ac-
ter. Although he does not make explicit reference to Descartes, Gamarra's cording to which the soul endows the body with form, and, on the other, the
method follows the rules of Descartes's Discours de la Methode very closely.147 Cartesian doctrine of the soul/body dualism. We find something similar in his
His application of modern methodology can be observed in the substitution of view of the relation between ideas and senses; Gamarra considers the ideas to
many of the theoretical speculations usually used by scholastics, by experi- be the result of sense data but also supports the thesis that they are innate.
ments taken from recent scientific theory, such as experiments in optics, These tensions are present in his view of truth as well; he questions the
physiology, etc. Although his methods are not completely modern, he also in- scholastic doctrine that our criteria for truth provide absolute certainty and
troduces some innovations in teaching. Several subject matters had not been yet is inclined to seek these criteria in the rules of logic.150
thematically studied before his time; e.g., the history of philosophy, ethics, It is important to note that Gamarra exerted a profound influence upon the
ontology, psychology, and natural theology (where he follows Wolff, al- main centers of study in New Spain. Gamarra is a philosopher whose work pro-
though he deals with what the latter calls 'cosmology', under the traditional vides a clear example of the merging of Scholasticism with modern thought.
heading of 'physics'). Prior to Gamarra's work, none of these had been
treated in a unified and distinct way.148 The object of Gamarra's research is, as
Secular Clergy
we shall see, modern as well.
Although he holds a traditional view of philosophy, namely that philoso- Among the secular clergy who worked on philosophy during the eigh-
phy is knowledge of truth, goodness, and beauty under the light which na- teenth century, Father Carlos Celedonio Velazquez de Cardenas y Leon de-
ture bestows on reason, Gamarra introduces many modern theories to this serves mention. In 1731, at the Seminary of San Pablo y de la Punsima Con-
traditional Scholastic conception. He emphasizes the theory of the modes of ception in Mexico City, he wrote a Cursus Philosophicus which follows
being, a theory that underlies modern scientific physics. Following Descartes, Aquinas's doctrine closely.151 Apparently, this clergyman was the uncle of the
Gamarra attacks the substantial forms of the Aristotelians and rejects their celebrated Mexican scientist Don Joaquin Velazquez de Leon.152 Another
table of categories, substituting it with a modern one that divides substance member of the clergy who wrote a work in physics in 1738, Juan Ignacio de la
into corporal and spiritual. He establishes five classes or modes of being: mea- Rocha also taught at the Tridentine Seminary of San Pablo y de la Pun'sima
sure, rest, movement, position, and shape. He even rejects the Aristotelian Conception.153 He was born in Santa Maria (Andalucia, Spain) and was taken
notion of substance, accepting instead Locke's notion of substance as some- to Mexico as a small child. He taught philosophy at the Tridentine seminar and
thing obscure and mysterious. He adopts the Cartesian notion of idea and the at the University, from which he ultimately retired. He was the first rector of
corresponding notion of clear and distinct ideas, and their further division the Colegio de San Ildefonso after the expulsion of the Jesuits. Beginning in
into innate, adventitious, and factitious ideas. Gamarra provides an empirical 1772, he was bishop of Michoacan, and he died ten years later in Valladolid
explanation of sensation and sensible objects or sense data as well as of imag- (today known as Morelia).154 He opposed the modernist innovations carried
ination. He supports Descartes's view of the soul; he does not, however, ad- out by the Oratorians, especially those proposed by Gamarra. One other secular
here to the view that the soul is located in the body.149
150. Ibid., pp. 57 ff.
Gamarra's enthusiasm for modern philosophy is checked at points by Ins
151. Valverde Tellez, Bibliografia filosofica mexicana, p. 77.
152. R. Moreno de los Arcos, Joaquin Velazquez de Leon y sus trabajos cientificos sobre el
147. See Gamarra, Elementos de filosofia modern a, pp. 80-81. On pane 81, he quiilr, ValledeMixico, 1773-1775 (Mexico: UNAM, 1977), p. 22.
Descartes, between brackets. 153. Valverde Tellez, Bibliografla filosofica mexicana, p. 78.
148. Ibid., pp. 1103-104. 154. Herisiain tti' Souza, Hiblioleca llis/mno Americana Septentrional, vol. 4, p. 242,
149. Ibid., pp. 154 ff. no. 2670.
174 H i s t o ry of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o E i g h t e e n t h Century 175

clergyman of note is Father Antonio Mariano Aragones w h o wrote a logic, ophy of t h e E n l i g h t e n m e n t as well as a representative of m o d e r n science. 160
155
dated 1738, but the work's place of publication remains unknown. Having some connection to Alzate were other scientists such as Joaquin
Father Agustin Jose del Rio y Loza, born in Guadalajara, taught at the Tri- Velazquez de Leon (1732-1786), 1 6 1 Antonio de L e o n y Gama (1735-1802), 1 6 2
dentine Seminary of that city. He obtained his doctorate there and was rector and Jose Ignacio Bartolache. In his 1769 Lecclones matemdticas, Bartolache put
of the coleglos of San Gregorio and of Guadalupe and expert adviser of t h e IV forward a n e w mathematical methodology that was applicable to all natural
Mexican Provincial Council. His Tesis de filosofia were published in 1762. 156 sciences. These lessons dealt with Arnauld (lesson 1, n o . 2), Descartes and
Two of his works are quite remarkable: a "Dictamen singular sobre que n o Malebranche (no. 5), and Wolff (nos. 7 and 10). In the first lesson, Bartolache
correspondia al Concilio Provincial entrometerse en pedir al Papa la secular- deals thoroughly with logic, applied as methodology, whereas in lesson 2, h e
ization perpetua de los Jesuitas," and a book entitled La mayor alma del adds m a n y questions from gnoseological psychology or from the theory of
mundo, Aurello Agustlna (that is, Saint Augustine), printed in Mexico City in knowledge. He follows Leibniz closely, as he himself states in n o . 4 3 . He also
1786. 157 suggests that all natural science should be treated with a mathematical
A n u m b e r of scientific thinkers were closely related to this philosophical method, of the mathesis universalis or logical calculus applied not only to for-
m o v e m e n t and were especially influential in its modernization. Father Jose mal but natural knowledge, a perspective which places h i m in the steps of
Antonio Alzate was born in Ozumba, in 1737. He studied philosophy and the- Descartes, Leibniz, Wolff, and Newton (whom he mentions in n o . 66). 163
ology at the university, receiving a degree of Bachelor of Arts in 1753 and of Jose Mariano Mocino Suarez de Figueroa, w h o directed two presentations
theology in 1756. On March 12, 1768, he began the publication of the Dlarlo of theses or dissertations, was also closely linked to the scientific group, al-
Llterario de Mexico, which only appeared for two months (eight numbers) but though he concentrated more on philosophy. One presentation dealt with
which was influential in the renewal of Mexican thought. Number 2, dated logic and was defended by Jose Joaquin Varela at the Colegio de Santa Cruz; it
March 18, reviews some theological-philosophical claims made by Jose de shows the clear influence of Mocino himself, as can be seen from its title:
Soria, O.F.M., presided over by Antonio Vicente Arias, O.F.M., and defended at Josepht Martant Moztnnl Suarezil de Figueroa Instttutiones Loglcas quae, Ipso prae-
the Convent of Santiago in Queretaro in January, 1768. Father Soria's claims side, Josephus Joachtmus Varela Xlmenes Bohorques ad Sanctae Crucis aedem Acade-
concerned primarily the issue of physics and its relation to creation and a de- miae discustoni subjicit, Puebla, D. Pedro de la Rosa, Typographer, 1781. I M The
fense of Gassendi's m o d e r n and atomist ideas (although Father Soria refutes other thesis was on metaphysics and was defended by Luis Mantecon e Ibanez
Newton's notions about light), and in this context Galileo, Buffon, Kepler, in the same place and during the same year and published by the same print-
Huygens, Du Hamel, Fontenelle, and John Wilkins are mentioned. 1 5 8 ing press. Finally, one should also mention J u a n Nepomuceno Sanchez y
Alzate's w o r k o n geography, meteorology, a n d a s t r o n o m y gained him. Gonzalez, w h o wrote some Adsertiones ex Phystca Generall, published in Mexico
m e m b e r s h i p t o t h e Science Academ y of Paris in 1771. In 1773, h e was ac- City at t h e printing press r u n by Mariano Zuniga y Ontiveros, in 1796. 165 The
cepted as a regular m e m b e r at t h e "Real Sociedad Vascongada de Amigos
del Pais." He c o n t i n u e d to w o r k for n e w s p a p e r s a n d w r o t e several scien- 160. See Rafael Moreno, "Alzate y la filosofia de la Ilustracion," Filosofiay Letras XIX,
tific works until his death in 1799. 159 Alzate was an advocate of t h e philos- no. 37 (January-March 1950): pp. 107-29; and "J. A. Alzate y la filosofia de la Ilus-
tracion," Memorias y Revista de la Academia National de Ciencias 57, nos. 1-2, (1952): pp.
55-84.
155. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catdlogo de obras manuscritas, p. 40, no. 34. 161. See Moreno de los Arcos, Joaquin Velazquez de Leon.
156. Valverde Tellez, Bibliografia filosofica niexicana, p. 100. 162. See E. Trabulse, "Antonio de Leon y Gama, astronomo y novohispano," Hu-
157. Beristain de Souza, Biblioteca Hispano Americana Septentrional, vol. 4, p. 235, no. manidades (Universidad Iberoamericana) 3 (1975): p. 201 ff.
2646. 163. See R. Moreno de los Arcos's edition of the mathematical lessons, "Las Lec-
158. Jose Antonio Alzate y Ramirez, Obras, I-Periodicos, ed. R. Moreno de los Alios clones Matemdticas del Doctor Bartolache," Humanidades (Universidad Ibero Americana)
(Mexico: UNAM, 1980), pp. 8-13. 2 (1974): p. 221 if. See also the editions by R. Moreno de los Arcos, J. I. Bartolacje, Mer-
159. R. Moreno de los Arcos, "tntroduccion" to Jose Anolonio Alzate, Memorias y curio Volante (Mexico: UNAM, 1979) and J. I. Bartolache, periodismo ilustrado (Mexico:
ensayos, ed. R. Moreno de los Arcos (Mexico, UNAM, 1985). See also J. Hernandei UNAM, 1983).
Luna, "J. A. Alzate, hombre de la Ilustracion," in Memorias del Primer Coloquio Mexicano 164. Valverde Tellez, Bibliografia filosofica mexicana, p. 102.
de Historia de la Ciencia, vol. 2 (Mexico: Sociedad Mcxieana de llislori.i de la Ciciul.i y hi 165. See Gorizakv. Casanova, El niisonci'smo y la modernidad cristiana. See also Red-
Tecnologfa, 1964), pp. 201-206. mond, Bibliography of the Philosophy, p. 89, no. 660.
176 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico

Logicae et Metaphysicae assertiones written by Jose Maria Miranda y Estrada were


published at the same press in 1797.166 And in 1798 some Philosophicae asser-
tiones et quaestiones were defended by Jose Maria Castro y Gonzalez at the Tri-
dentine Seminary of San Jose, under the direction of Manuel Cervino de los
Rios; they were published the same year.167 There is another treatise that be-
longs to the eighteenth century but about which there is no additional infor-
mation: De logica facultate sive de philosophia rationali.'6"

166. Redmond, Bibliography of the Philosophy, p. 60, no. 454.


167. Valverde Tellez, Bibliografiafilosoficamexicana, p. 102.
168. Yhmoff Cabrera, Catalogo de obras manuscritas, p. 267, no. 385.

^ The Nineteenth Century

C
olonial philosophy came to an end in the nineteenth century. With
the wars of independence which began in 1810 and ended in 1821,
the period of New Spain's viceroyalty was over, and the formation of
what would become the Mexican Republic began. The Jesuits, exiled since
1667, were not present during these wars, but before their expulsion, their
ideas had exerted a profound influence upon those who eventually forged the
movement of national independence. The Jesuits carried on their work for
New Spain from Italy. Meanwhile, in New Spain, priests from other orders re-
mained active, trying to integrate modern thought with traditional scholastic
doctrines, and merging as well philosophy and the modern sciences. During
this critical historical period, clergy and laymen were united in a single philo-
sophical task, namely, to think about the foundations that would rationally le-
gitimize the emancipation of the colony from the Spanish metropolis. With
the wars of independence, the colonial period of Mexican history came to an
end and with it the very philosophy that had made this end possible. The
'colonial' philosophy which helped to pave the way towards the new age of
independence thus gave rise to Mexican philosophy.

Franciscans
Even though the political and social unrest during this period limited the
iTiiiH'ist'ans' inli'lli'ilual pai'liiipalioii in New Spain, I hi're is one important

177
178 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Nineteenth Century 179

figure who contributed during the early part of the century. Father Calvo Tapachula, Chiapas, around 1766 or 1768. He studied at the seminar in Ciu-
Duran, who belonged to the Order of the Lower Friars, wrote Elementos de dad Real, Chiapas, and became a Dominican priest in the City of Guatemala
ftlosofia (1802) in which he deals with issues of law. This work remains in the in 1782. For this reason, both Guatemala and Chiapas claim him as a native
Library of the University of San Luis Potosi.1 son. He studied philosophy and theology at the University of San Carlos,
where he showed interest both for modern and Thomist authors. In 1793, he
was appointed lecturer of philosophy and theology at the Convent of Santo
Dominicans Domingo in Guatemala. In 1800 he taught rhetoric at the University of
A prominent philosopher of the Order of the Preachers was Friar Ser- Guatemala, writing some Prelecciones a los libros de elocuencia for this purpose.
vando Teresa de Mier.2 Born in 1763, in Monterrey, at the Nuevo Reino de From 1803-1809, he negotiated in Spain for the establishment of the inde-
Leon, New Spain, he received his early education. He then traveled to Mexico pendence of the Dominican Province in San Jose de Chiapas from Guate-
City, where he entered the Dominican Order. He was ordained in 1780 at the mala; this proposal was accepted in 1810. He was an active participant in the
Convento Real de Santo Domingo. Following his ordination, he moved to the proceedings that took place to establish the pacific independence of Chiapas
Colegio de Porta Coeli in order to study philosophy and theology. In 1792, and in its integration into Mexico in 1821. He also made important contribu-
after obtaining his degree, Mier became lecturer and then teacher at the Con- tions to education in Mexico; he founded a primary school in Ciudad Real.
vent of Santo Domingo, Mexico City. His teaching career was interrupted as a This school was the concrete result of his ideas on education. His philosophy
result of a sermon he delivered in 1794 on the Virgin of Guadalupe which of education was influenced by the doctrines of Aquinas and emphasized the
government officials viewed as an act of political aggression. As a result, Mier potential or virtual abilities of the pupil and the best process by which these
was persecuted and ultimately exiled. This made him sympathetic to the rev- potentialities could be realized. In his Metodo fdcil de ensenar a leer y escribir,
olutionary movement, and he became directly involved in it. Cordova developed an original phonetic method for the teaching of reading;
Teresa de Mier may be considered justifiably a philosopher (even within this was a specific application of his theory of education and demonstrated his
the confines of the Thomist doctrine) for two reasons. First, after his studies of great inventiveness. Apart from establishing schools, Friar Matias also
philosophy and theology at the Colegio de Porta Coeli, and up to the time he founded newspapers and wrote a famous anthropological-moral fable in
received his doctorate in theology, he acted as reader in philosophy at the verse entitled "La tentativa del leon y el exito de su empresa."4
Convent of Santo Domingo and subsequently at the university. His writings
reflect the influence of both his training in and his teaching of philosophy. Jesuits
Second, as a remarkable writer and orator, he served the cause of indepen-
dence by trying to provide a good theoretical explanation (using certain During nineteenth century, the intellectual work of the members of the
Thomist doctrines) for the events that shaped the new political dimensions of Society of Jesus was produced in exile, in the Pontifical States of Italy. Thus,
the country. For instance, he used the Thomist and medieval theory of legiti- the treatise Sobre lo bello en general written by Father Pedro Jose Marquez
mate insurrection for overthrowing a tyrant. In this way, he applied his philo- (1741-1820) was published in Madrid in 1801.5
sophical theory to the concrete political plans he proposed. His philosophy Another important Jesuit philosopher was Father Andres de Guevara y
became a type of social philosophy. Basoasabal who was born in Guanajuato in 1748. He studied in Mexico City
Friar Matias de Cordova was another Dominican of note.3 He was born in at the Colegio de San Ildefonso, which was run by Jesuits. He entered the

1. Redmond, Bibliography of Philosophy, p. 23, no. 166. 4. Matias de Cordova, La tentativa del leon y el exito de su empresa. Pdbula (Chiapas:
2. See Mauricio Beuchot, "Fray Servando Teresa de Mier y el derecho a la insurgen- Coleccion Ceiba, Fonapas, 1979), pp. 31-43.
ciaenelcaso de Mexico," Justiciay Paz, Revista de Derechos Humanos II, no. 3 (May 1987)1 5. See Redmond, Bibliography of Philosophy, p. 57, no. 432. See also A. Ibargiien-
pp. 82-88. jjoilia, "Pedro JoscTVlarqucz (1741-1820), primer estudlOSO de la estetica en Mexico,"
3. See Mauricio Beuchot, "Fray Matias de Cordova, filosofo, liberlador y maestro," Revista de Filosofla (Universldad Ibero Americana, Mexico) 24 (1991): pp. 41-46; and
Justicia y Paz, Revista de Derechos Humanos III, nos, 3-4, (Oct. 1988): pp. 81 88. Justino Irrii.iiidez, "Pedro .lose M,iic|iir/ en el in undo y en l,i cii'lii',1," Aitmirio de l!s
lelhn (\>H,Z): p p . 'i I 1 ).
180 History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico Nineteenth Century 181

colegio in 1766 and studied there until 1767, when he joined to the Society of 16. Continuation of Copernican's dream; Baron de Leibniz's thoughts
Jesus. The deportation of the Jesuits took place when he was a novitiate in 17. Ideas of doctor Carlos Bonnet, put forward in his Paligenesia filosofica
Tepozotlan. After his expulsion, he went to Italy where he produced most of 18. M. Lambert's world system, summarized by M. Merian
his intellectual work. He died in 1801, in Piacenza, Italy, where he was 19. Continuation of Lambert's system
teaching. 20. Second part: universal system
Guevara left two major works. The four-volume Institudones Elementales de 21. Continuation of the second part
Filosofla;6 and the Pasatiempos de cosmologia, which he dedicated to the City of 22. Harmony of the universe
Guanajuato.7 We also have a compendium of his philosophical works.8 He 23. Continuation of the same subject
showed his love for Mexico in his Institudones Elementales de Filosofla, referring 24. The third proposed point is briefly dealt with; conclusion of part one.
to himself as 'Guanaxuatensi Presbytero'; the book is dedicated to the Colegio
The contents of Guevara's work and his references to various modern au-
de San Ildefonso.
thors reveal the influence of the Enlightenment in Mexico. Guevara was fa-
Guevara's Pasatiempos de cosmologia are important, and we will give a brief
miliar with the most recent philosophical doctrines of the Modern Age, and
summary of their contents. Apart from the dedication and the introductory
he presented these doctrines objectively instead of judging them by the crite-
letter, they consist of 24 chapters or pasatiempos:
ria of the scholastics. He thus displayed the kind of freedom of thought and of
1. General idea of the universe judgment that belongs to someone who does not need to follow any specific
2. Age of the World, or of human kind authority and who may leave aside any kind of suspicion, reserve, or scruple
3. Shape and size of the universe regarding modern scientists and philosophers.
4. Limits, unity, season in which the universe was created We even observe how, in his Pasatiempos, Guevara criticizes modern
5. Various aspects of the universe as seen from earth; brief explanation philosophers, no longer from the point of view of Scholastic philosophy (at
of the sphere least in this specific work), but from the perspective of the Enlightenment.
6-8. World systems Moreover, if he criticizes scientists, he does so following the precepts of sci-
9. Copernican system ence, that is, according to what he believes is more certain where experience
10. Continuation of the Copernican system and analytical reason are concerned. Thus, he criticizes Descartes and Leibniz
11. Dialogue between a Ptolemaic, a Copernican, a lawyer, and a priest from the point of view of other modern philosophers who may be more ac-
explaining and clarifying notions pertaining to the Copernican system ceptable to him, and he refutes various world systems following Kepler's and
12. Continuation of the cosmic-systems dialogue between the priest, the Newton's positions. Although Guevara respects Leibniz's doctrine, he is de-
Copernican, and the Ptolemaic tached enough to reject some of his theses.
13. Center of the universe; continuation of the cosmic-systems dialogue One can say that more than being committed to any particular philosoph-
14. Dream of the Copernican ical authority, scholastic or modern, Guevara's sole commitment was to his
15. Continuation of the Copernican's dream; system of the Count of Buffon religious faith, which he viewed as perfectly compatible with modern science
and philosophy. To demonstrate the lack of contradiction between faith and
6. Andres de Guevara y Basoazabal, Institutionum Elementarium Philosophiae ad usum
studiosae juventutis (Venice: Apud Foresti et Betinelli, 1819, and Madrid: ex thy- science was certainly one of his aims in studying cosmology. Guevara's refu-
pographia Regia, 1833). tation of thinkers such as Spinoza was based upon his religious convictions,
7. Andres de Guevara y Basoasabal, Pasatiempos de cosmologia, ed. J. I. Palencia (Gua- yet he attempted to base his arguments against Spinoza upon scientific expe-
najuato, Mexico: Universidad de Guanajuato, 1982).
8. Andres de Guevara y BsLsaasiba\,Definitiones et epitome doctrinae, quae in Institution- rience and rational argumentation.
ibus elementariis Philosophiae a D. Andrea de Guevara editis continentur (Madrid: ex Ty- Although Guevara makes reference to its pragmatic aspects, his concep-
pographia Leonis Amarija, 1826). See also, Mauricio Beuchot, "Tradition and Moder- tion of science remains speculative and does not emphasize the significance of
nity in a Spanish Compendium of the Cursus Philosophicus of Andres de Guevara y
Basoazabal," Dieciocho. Hispanic Enlightenment, Aesthetics and Literary Theory I ) (I'WO): the practical application of science In the form ol ted logy in .my cate, (or
pp. 165-70.
182 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o N i n e t e e n t h Century 183

him the best practical consequence of science is the encouragement of free- Joaquin Menendez Valdez and became a substitute in the chair of scholas-
dom of knowledge, that is, the promotion of liberality and leisure for m a n to tics. 11 His background and training in t h e moderns was at least as strong as his
be able to devote more time to 'pure' science. However, as far as the scientific scholastic background. It is believed that h e may have k n o w n Clavigero, be-
aspects of his o w n work are concerned, Guevara was sometimes outdated. fore the latter was expelled with other Jesuits. 12 He was also very well versed
In addition to his scientific training, which reached an acceptable level in m o d e r n philosophy, particularly French enlightenment philosophy." This
given the times, one must consider Guevara's humanist formation. Cicero, influence is evident in his dissertation on m e t h o d in theology in which he
Virgil, Ovid, Horace, Lucretius, Salustius, and other classical writers are gen- proposes a modernist renewal of Scholasticism. 14 This fusion of classical and
erously cited in his work. m o d e r n ideas became the theoretical basis for the m o v e m e n t of indepen-
To conclude, Guevara's position was eclectic and at times even syncretic. dence. Although Hidalgo was executed by the Royalists in 1811, the move-
He fused the ideas of physicists, mathematicians, and m e n of letters, accord- m e n t h e had initiated continued to flourish both militarily and intellectually.
ing to his own convenience and in absolute freedom. He also took account of There was some resistance to the independence m o v e m e nt by intellectuals
some famous Jesuits, such as Boscovich and Hervas, and as well as some of such as Father Manuel de Burgos, w h o wrote a Defensa del Trono y del Altar con-
his fellow exiles, such as Landivar, Alegre, Clavigero, Abad, Maneiro, and tra losfilosofos liberates deldia, published in 1839. 15 Most intellectuals, however,
others. Guevara emerges as one of those eclectic thinkers who, as a result of supported the movement. Manuel Maria Gorrifio y Arduengo (1767-1831)
his free and a u t o n o m o us spirit, opened a path, even from exile, toward the was an ardent supporter of the independence movement. 1 6 Some of his
m o v e m e n t of independence in Mexico. 9 k n o w n works are De el hombre (finished o n October 11, 1791), Elhombre Inm
quilo o reflexionespara conservar la pazdel espiritu (1800?), Filosofiade la fe catdlica
(1811), and Reflexiones sobre la incredulidad (1814). The year of Gorrino's birth,
Secular Clergy
1767, was the year of the expulsion of the Jesuits (who for the most pari si11>
The parish priest of Dolores, Father Don Miguel Hidalgo y Costilla, father ported efforts to modernize scholastic philosophy). Gorrifio was influenced by
of Mexican independence, occupies a foremost place during this period. He the Jesuits and supported the independence movement. At time of his death
was born in Corralejo, Guanajuato, in 1753. In 1765, two years before the ex- in 1831, Gorrifio had become one of the pillars that sustained the gates of the
pulsion of the Jesuits, he studied humanities at the Jesuit Colegio de San n e w liberalism which ultimately triumphed in Mexico.
Francisco Javier, in Valladolid (today k n o w n as Morelia). The colegio closed
w h e n the Jesuits left, and Hidalgo moved to the Colegio de San Nicolas 11. See J. Bonavit, Fragmentos de la historia del colegio primitivo y national de San NlcolAs
de Hidalgo (Morelia: Tipografia de la Escuela Industrial Militar, "Porfirio Diaz", l')lII),
Obispo, in the same city. In 1770, he graduated with a degree of Bachelor of pp. 244-45.
Arts from the Real y Pontificia Universidad de Mexico, and in 1773 as Bache- 12. Macias, Hidalgo, Reformadory maestro, pp. 19-20.
13. See J. Hernandez Luna, Imdgenes historicas de Hidalgo (Morelia: Universidad Mi
lor in Theology from the same university, w h e r e he was given credit for his choacana de San Nicolas de Hidalgo, 1981), p. 133 If.
studies at the Colegio de San Nicolas. 14. Miguel Hidalgo y Costilla, "Disertacion sobre el verdadero mclodo de csliiili.n
teologia escolastica," in A. Rivera y Sanroman, Eljoven teologo Miguel Hidalgo v Costilla,
Hidalgo then taught philosophy and theology at the Colegio de San
Anales de su viday de su Revolution de Independencia (Morelia: Universidad Mlchoacana tie
Nicolas. Here he became the object of envious attacks and eventually, in San Nicolas de Hidalgo, 1987), pp. 15-38. A remarkable study on this dissertation is (I.
Mendez Plancarte's, "Hidalgo, reformador intelectual," in Hidalgo reformador inkieclnal v
1792, lost both the rectorship and both of his chairs. He t h e n worked as a
libertador de los esdavos (Morelia: Universidad Michoacana de San Nicolas de Hidalgo,
parish priest in Colima, San Felipe, and, finally, in Dolores, the cradle of the 1982), pp. 13-50.
independence movement. 1 0 15. See Redmond, Bibliography of Philosophy, p. 21, no. 151.
16. Concerning the life and though of Gorrifio, see R. Cardiel Reyes, Del model nisino
Hidalgo had solid scholastic training. He studied Aquinas with his tcachei al liheralismo. I.a Jilosoffa de Manuel Maria Gorrifio, Jrd ed, (Mexico: UN AM, 1989).

9. See the "Introduction" by J. I. Palencia in Guevara y liasoasabal, l'asalienwos tic


cosmologia.
10. See P. G. Macias, Hidalgo, Reformadorv maestro (Mexico: UNAM, 1959), p. IV II
Bibliography

Abad, Diego Jose. Philosophia Naturalis. Disputationes in octo libros Physicorum Aris-
totelis. 1756. Manuscript.
Abellan, Jose Luis. Filosofia espanola en America (1936-1966). Madrid: Bdiciones
Guadarrama, 1967.
. Historia critica del pensamiento espahol. 7 vols. Madrid: Espasa-Calpe,
1979-91.
Alegre, R X. Historia de la Provincia de la Compania de Jesus de Nueva Espana. Edited
by E. J. Burrur and P. Zubillaga. Rev. ed. Rome: Institutum Historicum S-X,
1956-1960.
Alejos Grau, C. J. "Zumarraga, Erasmo y la observancia franciscana." Carthaginen-
sia,6 (1990): 288.
Almoina, J. "EI erasmismo en Zumarraga." Filosofia y Letras 29 (January-March
1948): 93-126.
Alzate y Ramirez, Jose Antonio. Memorias y ensayos. Edited by R. Moreno de los
Arcos. Mexico: UNAM, 1985.
. Obras, I- Periddicos. Edited by R. Moreno de los Arcos. Mexico: UNAM,
1980.
Aquinas, Saint Thomas. Opuscula. Taurini: Marietti, 1950.
Ashwoth, E. J. Language and Logic in the Post-Medieval Period. Dordrecht-Boston:
Reidel, 1974.
Balbuena, B. de. Grandezamexicana. 2d ed. Mexico: UNAM, 1954.
Basalenque, D. Historia de la provincia de San Nicolas de Tolentino de Michoacan, del
Orden de N. P. San Agustin, Ano de 1673. Edited by J. Bravo Ugarte. Mexico: Por-
rua, 1963.
Bataillon, Marcel. Estudios sobre Bartolomi de Las Casas. Barcelona: Peninsula, 1976.
. "Vasco de Quiroga et Bartolome de las Casas." Revista de Historia de America
33 (1952): 83-^5.
Benftez, F. Los demonios en el comsnto. SlXO y religidn en la Nueva Espana. Mexico:
lira, 19K5.

IH1
186 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o Bibliography 187

Benitez, L. La idea de historia en Carlos de Siguenza y Gongora. Mexico: UNAM, 1982. . "El problema de los universales en Domingo de Soto y en Alonso de la
Beristain de Souza, J. M. Biblioteca Hispano Americana Septentrional. 3d ed. Mexico: Vera Cruz." Revista de Filosofia 17 (1984): 249-73.
Fuente Cultural, 1947. . "La semantica en la logica de Tomas de Mercado." Critica 12, n. 42 (1982):
Beuchot, Mauricio. "La actualidad de la antropologia filosofica de Fray Bartolome 49-63.
deLas Casas." Cuadernos de Realidades Sociales nn. 27-28 (1986): 255-65. . "Los topicos dialogicos en la Logica mexicana de Antonio Rubio." Philosoph-
. "La antropologia filosofica de Alonso de la Vera Cruz." In Homenaje a Fray ica (Valparaiso, Chile) Forthcoming.
Alonso de la Vera Cruz en el IV centenario de su muerte (1584-1984). Edited by . "Tradition and Modernity in a Spanish Compendium of the Cursus Philo-
Mauricio Beuchot, et al. Mexico: Instituto de Investigaciones Jurfdicas, UNAM, sophicus of Andres de Guevara y Basoazabal." Dieciocho. Hispanic Enlightenment,
1986. Aesthetics and Literary Theory 13 (1990): pp. 165-70.
. "Argumentation, retorica y conversion en Bartolome de Las Casas." Beuchot, Mauricio, and E. Gonzalez Ruiz. "La falacia de petition de principio en
Cuadernos para la historia de la evangelizacion en America Latina 4 (1989): 123-28. Fray Alonso de la Vera Cruz." Nova Tellus 3 (1985): 221-33.
"Arias, Antonio, S.J." In Enciclopedia de la Iglesia Catdlica en Mexico. Edited Beuchot, Mauricio, and J. Iniguez. "Ciencia empirica contra ciencia teorica: un
by J. R. Alvarez. Vol. 1. Mexico: Enciclopedia de Mexico, 1982. falso dilema (Aristoteles y Galileo)." Quipu. Revista Latinoamericana de Historia de
. "Bartolome de Ledesma y su Suma de sacramentos." Estudios de historia novo- las Cienciasy la Teenolgia, 3/2 (1986): 213-32.
hispana 11 (1991): 253-65. . El pensamiento filosdfico de Tomas de Mercado. Logica y economia. Mexico:
. "La dialectics como filosofia de la logica en Alonso de la Vera Cruz." In UNAM, 1989.
Pensamiento y realidad en Fray Alonso de la Vera Cruz. Edited by Walter Redmond Beuchot, Mauricio, and A. Melcon. Los dominicos en la Real y Pontificia Universidad
and Mauricio Beuchot. Reprinted in Dos homenajes. Alonso de la Vera Cruzy Fran- de Mexico. Mexico: Cuadernos Dominicanos, 1984.
cisco Xavier Clavigero. Edited by Mauricio Beuchot and B. Navarro (Mexico: Beuchot, Mauricio, and B. Navarro, eds. Dos homenajes. Alonso de la Vera Cruz y
UNAM). Forthcoming. Francisco Xavier Clavigero. Mexico: UNAM. Forthcoming.
. "Escepticismo en la edad media: El caso de Nicolas de Autrecourt," Revista Beuchot, Mauricio, and others, eds. Homenaje a Fray Alonso de la Vera Cruz en el IV
Latinoamericana de Filosofia 15, 3(1989): 307-19. centenario de su muerte (1584-1984). Mexico: Instituto de Investigaciones Jurfdi-
. Estudios de historia y de filsofia en el Mexico colonial. Mexico: UNAM, 1991. cas, UNAM, 1986.
. Filosofos dominicos novohispanos (entre la universidad y sus colegios). Mexico: Biermann, B. "Don Vasco de Quiroga y su tratado de debellandis indis." Historia
UNAM, 1987. Mexicana 18 / 72 (1969): 615-22.
. La filosofia social en los pensadores novohispanos. Mexico: IMDOSOC, 1989. Bolano e Isla, A. Contribucidn al estudio bibliogrdfico de Fray Alonso de la Vera Cruz.
—. "Fray Matias de Cordova, filosofo, libertador y maestro." Justiciay Paz, Re- Mexico: Robredo-Pornia, 1947.
vista de Derechos Humanos HI, nn. 3-4, (Oct. 1988): pp. 83-88. Bonaventure. Collationes in Hexaemeron 19. In Opera omnia, vol. 5. Ad Claras
. "Fray Servando Teresa de Mier y el derecho a la insurgencia en el caso de Aquas: Collegium S. Bonaventurae, 1882-1902.
Mexico." Justicia y Paz, Revista de Derechos Humanos II, n. 3 (May 1987):pp. 82-88. Bonavit, J. Fragmentos de la historia del colegio primitivo y nacional de San Nicolas dt
. "Fundamentos filosoficos de la justicia: Vitoria y Las Casas." CIDAL Hidalgo. Morelia: Tipografia de la Escuela Industrial Militar, "Porfirio l)i,i/",
(Republica Dominicana) afio 5, n. 11 (1985). 1910.
. "Introduction" to Tomas de Mercado. In Comentarios lucidisimos al texto de Burrus, E. J. "Siguenza y Gongora's Efforts for Readmission into the Jesull
Pedro Hispano. Mexico: UNAM, 1986. Order." Hispanic American Historical Review, 33 (1953): 387-91.
. "Lectores conventuales en la Provincia de Santiago de Mexico (siglo . The Writings ofAlonso de la Vera Cruz. 5 vols. Rome and St. Louis Mo.: u.p„
XVI)." Archivo Dominicano (Salamanca, Spain) 7 (1987). 1968.
. "La ley natural como fundamento de la ley positiva en Francisco Javier Cabrera y Quintero, C. de. Obra dramdtica. Teatro novohispano del siglo XVIII. Edited
Alegre." Dieciocko. Hispanic Enlightenment, Aesthetics and Literary Theory 14 by C. Parodi. Mexico: UNAM, 1976.
(1991): 124-29. Cardenas de la Pefia, F. Vasco de Quiroga, precursor de Seguridad Social. Mexico: lnsti-
. "La logica formal en las Sumulas (1571) de Tomas de Mercado." Cuadernos tuto Mexicano del Seguro Social, 1968.
Salamantinos de Filosofia (Salamanca, Spain), 10 (1983): pp. 141-56. Cardiel Reyes, R. Del modernismo alliberalismo. La filosofia de Manuel Maria Corrino.
. "La logica material o dialectica (1571) de Tomas de Mercado." Palabra 1, 3rd ed. Mexico: UNAM, 1989.
nn. 2-3 (1986): 76-88. Careri, Giovanni Francesco Gemelli. Giro del Mondo and Viaje de la Nueva Espafia,
. "La logica proposicional en Tomas de Mercado." Didnoia 30 (1984): Mexico: UNAM, 1983.
211-19. Carreno, A. M. Misioneros de Mexico. Mexico: Jus, 1961.
. "El primer planteamiento teologico-juridico sobre la conqulsta (li* Carro, V. D. Los poslulados teoldgico-juridicos de Hariolomi' de las Casas. Sus acicrlos, sus
America: JohnMair o Major." Ciencia Tomista 103 (1976): 213-30. olvidosy sus fallas, ante los mucstros Francisco de Vitoria y nomingo de Solo. Seville:
. "Los principios de la ciencia en Tomas de Mercado." Quipu. Revista tali Escueln de Hsludlos Illspano.iiiiericaiios/CSIC, I9M>.
noamericana de Historia de las Ciencias y la Tecnologia 3 /1 (1986): 103 I I I . Casas, Bartolome' de Us. Apologitica historia sumaria, Edited by li. ()'(!
. Elproblema de los universales. Mexico: UNAM, 1982. vols. Mexico: UNAM, [967
188 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n C o l o n i a l M e x i c o Bibliography 189

. Apologia. Edited by A. Losada. Madrid: National, 1975. Falcumbelli, J. L. Disputationes in octo Aristotelis Libros de phisico auditu seu de Naturali
. Del unico modo de atraer a todos los pueblos a la verdadera religion. Edited by A. auscultatione. 1730, Manuscript.
Millares Carlo. Mexico: FCE, 1942. Fernandez, Justine "Pedro Jose Marquez en el recuerdo y en la critica." Anuario
. De regia potestate o Derecho de autodeterminacion. Edited by L. Perefia. deEstetica (1962): pp. 5-19.
Madrid: CSIC, 1969. Fernandez, Luis Gil. Estudios de humanismo y tradition cldsica. Madrid: Editorial
. Historia de las Indias. Edited by A. Millares Carlo. Mexico: FCE, 1951. Complutense, 1984.
. In Defense of the Indians: The defense of the most reverend Lord, Don Fray Bar- La filosofia en America: Trabajos presentados en el IX Congreso Interamericano de
tolome de las Casas, of the Order of Preachers, Late Bishop of Chiapas, against the Perse- Filosofia. 2 vols. Caracas: Sociedad Venezolana de Filosofia, 1979.
cutors and Slanderers of the Peoples of the New World discovered across the seas. Trans- Franco, A. Segunda parte de la Historia de la Provincia de Santiago de Mexico. Mexico:
lated and edited by Stafford Poole. Forward by Martin E. Marty. DeKalb, 111.: Museo Nacional, 1900.
Northern Illinois University Press, 1992. Frondizi, Risieri. "Hay una filosofia iberoamericana?" Realidad 3 (1948), 158-70.
. Obras escogidas. Edited by J. Perez de Tudela Bueso and E. Lopez Oto. 5 Reprinted in Filosofia e identidad cultural en America latina, edited by Jorge J. E.
vols. Madrid: BAE, 1956. Gracia and Ivan Jaksi<j. Caracas: Monte Avila, 1988.
. Tratados. Edited by Lewis Hanke, J. Tudela, and A. Millares Carlo. 2 vols. — . iQue son los valores? Introduction a la Axiologia. Mexico: Fondo de la Cultura
Mexico: FCE, 1965. Economica, 1958. What Is Value? An Introduction to Axiology. Translated by
Castro Lopez, Octavio. Sor Juana y el "Primero Sueho ". Xalapa, Mexico: Universidad Solomon Lipp. La Salle, 111.: Open Court, 1963.
Veracruzana, 1982. Frost, E. C. "Los intereses filosoficos de Francisco Hernandez." In Obras Completas,
Catdlogo de libros que existen en la Biblioteca Publica del Estado. Vol. 2. Guadalajara, by Francisco Hernandez. Vol. 6. Mexico: UNAM, 1984.
Mexico: Tip. by S. Banda, 1874. Fuentes Galindo, F. "Don Benito Dias de Gamarra y Davalos." In Humanidades.
Cayetano, T. de Vio Cardinal. In Summam Theologicam Divi Thomae. Romae. Vol. 1, no. 1. Mexico, 1943.
Cerezo de Diego, P. Alonso de Veracruzy el derecho degentes. Mexico: Porrua, 1985. Furlong, Guillermo. Nacimiento y desarrollo de la filosofia en el Rio de La Plata,
Chamberlin, E. R. The Bad Popes. New York: Dorset Press, 1969. 1536-1810. Buenos Aires: Guillermo Kraft, 1952.
Chauvet, F. de J. Fray Juan de Zumdrraga. Mexico: n.p., 1948. Fuster, J. Rebeldesy heterodoxos. Barcelona: Edicions Ariel, 1972.
"Chicanos, not Hispanics," Third World Forum (14 March 1990). Gallegos Rocafull, Jose Maria. "La filosofia en Mexico en los siglos XVI y XVII." In
Churruca Pelaez, A. Francisco Clavigero y otros ensayos. Mexico: Eds de la Librena Estudios de historia de la filosofia en Mexico. 3d ed. Mexico: UNAM, 1980.
Parroquial, 1985. . El pensamiento mexicano en los siglos XVIy XVII. 2d ed. Mexico: Universidad
Clavigero, Francisco Javier. Historia de la Antigua o Baja California. Mexico: Porrua, Nacional Autonoma de Mexico, 1974.
1970. Gaos, Jose. Historia del pensamiento de lengua espahola en la edad contemporanea
. Historia Antigua de Mexico. Edited by Mariano Cuevas. 4th ed. Mexico: Edi- (1744-1944). Mexico: Seneca, 1945.
torial Porrua, 1974. . Sobre Ortegay Gasset. Mexico: Imprenta Universitaria, 1952.
Conway, G. R. G. Friar Francisco Naranjo and the Old University of Mexico. Mexico: . "EI suefio de un suefio." HistoriaMexicana 10 (1960): 54-71.
Gante Press, 1939. Garcia Icazbalceta, J. Bibliografia mexicana del siglo XVI. Mexico: FCE, 1954.
Copleston, Frederick. A History of Philosophy. New York: Image Books, 1950. . Fray Juan de Zumdrraga, primer obispo y arzobispo de Mexico. Buenos Aires:
Cordova, Matias de. La tentativa del leon y el exito de su empresa. Fdbula. Chiapas: Espasa-Calpe, 1952.
Coleccion Ceiba, Fonapas, 1979. Garcia Villoslada, R. La Universidad de Paris durante los estudios de Francisco de Vitoria,
Davila Padilla, A. Historia de la fundacion y discurso de la Provincia de Santiago de Mex- O.P. (1507-1522). Rome: Universitas Gregoriana, 1938.
ico, de la Orden de Predicadores. Mexico: Editorial Academica Literaria, 1955. Giacon, Carlo. La seconda scolastica. 2 vols. Milan: Fratelli Bocca, 1946.
Davis, A. V. El Sigh de Oro de la Nueva Espana (Siglo XVIII). Mexico: Polis, 1945. Gilson, Etienne. History of Christian Philosophy in the Middle Ages. New York: Ran-
Defourneaux, M. Inquisition y censura de libros en la Espaha del siglo XVIII. Madrid: dom House, 1954.
Taurus, 1973. Gomez Alonso, P. "Ensayo sobre la filosofia en sor Juana Ines de la Cruz." Filosofia
Diaz y de Ovando, C. El colegio mdximo de San Pedro y San Pablo. 2d ed. Mexico: yLetras 60-62 (1956): 59-74.
UNAM, 1985. Gomez Canedo, L. Los archivos de la historia de America, Periodo colonial espahol.
Diaz de Gamarra, Juan Benito. Elementos de Filosofia Moderna. Introduced and Mexico: Instituto Panamericano de Geografia e Historia, 1961.
translated by Bernabe. Navarro. Mexico: UNAM, 1963. Gomez Fregoso, Jesus. Clavigero. Ensayo de interpretation y aportaciones para su estu-
. Mdximas de education, Academias defilosofiay Academias de Geometria. Introduc- dio. Guadalajara, Jalisco, Mexico: Universidad de Guadalajara, 1979.
tion by C. Herrejon Peredo. Zamora, Michoacan: El Colegio de Michoacan, 1983. Gomez Robledo, Antonio. El magisteriofilosdfico-juridicode Alonso de la Veracruz.
. Tratados. Edited by J. Gaos. Mexico: UNAM, 1974. Mexico: Porrua, 1984.
Duns Scotus, John. Philosophical Writings. Edited by Allan Wollcr. London: Nelson, Gonzalez, David. "What's the Problem with 'Hispanic,'" The New York Times, 15
1963. November 1992.
Espindola, Walter Hannisch. En torno a la filosofia en Chile 1594-1810. Santiago! Gonzalez Casanova, I' HI mhonefsmo v hi nunkriudai ciisliiiihi en el siglo .Will. Mex-
Universidad Calolica de Chile, 196 l. ico: I'.l Colegio de Mexico, [948
190 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o Bibliography 191

Gonzalez Pena, Carlos. Historia de la literatura mexicana. 14th ed. Mexico: Porrua, . "J. A. Alzate, hombre de la Ilustracion." In Memorias del Primer Coloquio
1981. Mexicano de Historia de la Ciencia. Vol. 2. Mexico: Sociedad Mexicana de Historia
Gracia, Jorge J. E., ed. America Latina: Historia y destine 2 vols. Mexico: Universi- de la Ciencia y la Tecnologia, 1964.
dad Nacional Autonoma de Mexico, 1992. Hernandez, R. "Francisco de Vitoria y Bartolome de Las Casas, primeros
. Latin American Philosophy in the Twentieth Century. Buffalo, N.Y.: teorizantes de los derechos humanos," Archivo Dominicano 4 (1983): 199-266.
Prometheus Books, 1986. Herrejon Peredo, C. "Fuentes patristicas, juridicas y escolasticas del pensamiento
. "The Origins of Hispanic Philosophy." Review of Metaphysics 46 (1993): quiroguiano." In Textos politicos en la Nueva Espaha. Mexico: UNAM, 1984.
475-502. Herrejon Peredo, C , ed. Humanismo y ciencia en la formation de Mexico. Zamora, Mi-
Gracia, Jorge J. E., and Ivan Jaksig, eds. Filosofia e identidad cultural en America choacan: El Colegio de Michoacan, 1984.
latina. Caracas: Monte Avila, 1988. Hidalgo y Costilla, Miguel. "Disertacion sobre el verdadero metodo de estudiar
Gracia, Jorge J. E. et al., eds. Philosophical Analysis in Latin America. Dordrecht: Rei- teologia escolastica." In A. Rivera y Sanroman, Eljoven tedlogo Miguel Hidalgo y
del, 1984. Costilla. Anales de su vida y de su Revolution de Independencia. Morelia: Universidad
Graue, J. La explication histdrica. Mexico: UNAM, 1975. Michoacana de San Nicolas de Hidalgo, 1987.
Greenleaf, R. E. Zumdrraga y la inquisition mexicana, 1536-1543. Mexico: FCE, Ibargiiengoitia, A. "Pedro Jose Marquez (1741-1820), primer estudioso de la es-
1988. tetica en Mexico." Revista de Filosofia (Universidad Ibero Americana, Mexico) 24
Grice-Hutchinson, M. The School of Salamanca: Readings in Spanish Monetary Theory, (1991): pp. 41-16.
1544-1605. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1952. Ideas en torno de Latinoamerica, 2 vols. Mexico: Universidad Nacional Autonoma de
Guevara y Basoasabal, Andres de. Definitiones et epitome doctrinae, quae in Institution- Mexico, 1986.
ibus elementariis Philosophiae a D. Andrea de Guevara editis continentur. Madrid: ex Ines de la Cruz, Sister Juana. Obras completas. Vol. 1. Edited by A. Mendez Plan-
Typographia Leonis Amarija, 1826. carte. Mexico: FCE, 1976.
. Institutionum Elementarium Philosophiae ad usum studiosae juventutis. Venice: Ifiiguez, J. "Tomas de Mercado y la Suma de Tratosy Contratos." Justitiay Paz. Revista
Apud Foresti et Betinelli, 1819, and Madrid: ex thypographia Regia, 1833. de Derechos Humanos, 2 (1987): n. 2.
. Pasatiempos de cosmologia. Edited by J. I. Palencia. Guanajuato, Mexico: Iriarte, J. "La proyeccion sobre Europa de una gran metaiisica, o Suarez en la
Universidad de Guanajuato, 1982. filosofia en los dias del Barroco," Razdn y Fe, mimero extraordinario (1948):
Guy, Alain. Histoire de la philosophic espagnole. 12th ed. Toulouse: Universite de 236.
Toulouse-Le Mirail, 1985. Jaramillo, Roberto. Los augustinos en Michoacan, 1602-1652. La dificil formation de
. Panorama de la philosophic Ibero-Americaine du XVIe siecle a nos jours. unaprovincia. Mexico: n.p., 1991.
Geneva: Patino, 1989. Jones, W. T. A History of Western Philosophy. New York: Harcourt, Brace, & World,
Hanke, Lewis. All Mankind Is One: A Study on the Disputation between Bartolome de las 1952.
Casas and Juan Gines de Sepulveda in 1550 on the Intellectual and Religious Capacity of Juan de Aviles, Dr. D. "Soneto funebre a Sor Juana" (Fama y Obras postumas del
the American Indians. DeKalb, 111.: Northern Illinois University Press, 1974. Fenix de Mexico). In Poetas novohispanos, segundo siglo (1621-1721), parte segundo,
. Aristotle and the American Indians: A Study in Race Prejudice in the Modern ed. A. Mendez Plancarte. Mexico: UNAM, 1944.
World. Bloomington, Ind.: Indiana University Press, 1970. El prejuitio racial en el Junco de Meyer, V. Gamarra o el eclecticismo en Mexico. Mexico: Fondo de Cultura
Nuevo Mundo. Mexico: SEP, 1974. Economica, 1973.
. Bartolome de las Casas: An Interpretation of His Life and Writings. The Hague: Kretzman, Norman, et al., eds. The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy.
M. Nijhoff, 1951. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982.
. Estudios sobre Fray Bartolome de Las Casas y sobre la lucha por la justitia en la Kristeller, Paul Oskar. Renaissance Thought and Its Sources. New York: Columbia
conquista espahola de America. Caracas: Universidad Central de Venezuela, 1968. University Press, 1979.
. The Spanish Struggle for Justice in the Conquest of America. Philadelphia: Uni- . Renaissance Thought: The Classic, Scholastic, and Humanistic Strains. New York:
versity of Pennsylvania Press, 1949. Harper and Brothers, 1961.
. Uno es todo elgenero humano. Estudio acerca de la querella que sobre la capaci- Ledesma, Bartolome de. De septem novae legis sacramentis summarium. Mexico: An-
dad intelectualy religiosa de los indigenas americanos sotuvieron en 1550 Bartolome de tonio Espinosa, 1566; Pamplona, 1581; Salamanca: Matias Guast, 1585.
Las Casasy Juan Gines de Sepulveda. Chiapas, Mexico: Gobierno Institucional del Leon, Nicolas. Bibliografia mexicana del siglo XVIII. Vol. 1. Mexico: Imprenta Dias de
Estado, 1974. Leon, 1902.
Hernandez, Francisco. Obras Completas. 6 vols. Mexico: UNAM, 1960-1984. . Don Vasco de Quiroga. Grandeza de su persona y su obra. Morelia, Mexico:
Hernandez del Castillo, F. ed., Librosy libreros en elsiglo XVI. 2d ed. Mexico: FCE • Universidad Michoacana de San Nicolas de Hidalgo, 1984.
AGN, 1982. Leonard, I. A. Don Carlos de Sigiienza y Gongora, un sabio mexicanoo del siglo XVII.
Hernandez Luna, J. Dos ideas sobre la filosofia en la Nueva Espafia (Rivera vs. de la Mexico: FCE, 1984.
Rosa). Mexico: UNAM, 1959. . Ensayo bibliogrtifico de don Carlos de Sigiienza y Gongora. Mexico: Secretarfa
. Imdgenes histdricas de Hidalgo. Morelia: Universidad Mlchoacana de S.in de Reladones Exterlores, 1929.
Nicolas de Hidalgo, 1981. . iiitpoca barroca in il Mixta colonial, Mexico: PCB,I'''/•!.
192 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o Bibliography 193

Lobato, A. "Dignidad del hombre y derechos humanos en Fray Bartolome de las . Joaquin Veldzquez de Leon y sus trabajos cientificos sobre el Valle de Mexico,
Casas y en la doctrina actual de la iglesia." Communio 18 (1985): 59-81. 1773-1775. Mexico: UNAM, 1977.
Lombardo Toledano, Vicente. Las corrientes filosoficas en la vida de Mexico. 2d ed. . "Las Lecciones Matemdticas del Doctor Bartolache." Humanidades (Universi-
Mexico: Universidad Obrera de Mexico, 1963. dad Ibero Americana) 2 (1974): p. 221 ff.
Lopez Camara, R "El cartesianismo en Sor Juana y Sigiienza y Gongora." Filosofia Munoz Delgado, V. "La logica en Salamanca durante la primera mitad del siglo
yhetras, 39 (1950): 107-31. XVI," Salmanticensis 14 (1967): 171-207.
Macias, P. G. Hidalgo, Reformadory maestro. Mexico: UNAM, 1959. . "La obra logica de los espafioles en Paris (1500-1525)," Estudios 26
Maneiro, Juan Luis. De vitis aliquot mexicanorum, aliorumque, qui sive virtute, sive lit- (1970): 209-80.
teris, Mexici imprimis floruerunt. Bologne: 1792. "Logica hispano-portuguesa hasta 1600 (notas bibliografico-doctrinales),"
Maneiro, Juan Luis, and M. Fabri. Vidas de mexicanos ilustres del siglo XVIII. Trans- Repertorio de historia de las ciencias eclesidsticas en Espana 4 (1972): 9-122.
lated by B. Navarro. 3d ed. Mexico: UNAM, 1989. -. "Nominalismo, logica y humanismo." In El erasmismo en Espana, edited by
Martin Hernandez, F. "Don Vasco de Quiroga, protector de los indios." Salmanti- M. Revuelta Sanudo and C. Moron Arroyo. Santander: Sociedad Menendez
censis 34 (1987): 61-85. Pelayo, 1986.
Martinez Gomez, L. "Evaluation de Francisco Suarez Filosofo." Cuadernos Salman- Navarro, Bernabe. Cultura mexicana moderna en el siglo XVIII. 2d ed. Mexico:
tinos de Filosofia 7 (1980): 5-25. UNAM, 1983.
Mayagoitia, David. Ambiente filosofico de la Nueva Espana. Mexico: Jus, 1945. .—. La introduction de la filosofia moderna en Mexico. Mexico: El Colegio de Mex-
Mendez Plancarte, Gabriel. "Hidalgo, reformador intelectual." In Hidalgo refor- ico, 1948.
mador intelectual y libertador de los esclavos. Morelia: Universidad Michoacana de . J. L. Maneiro—M. Fabri, Vidas de mexicanos ilustres del siglo XVIII. 2d ed.
San Nicolas de Hidalgo, 1982. Mexico: UNAM, 1989.
. Humanismo mexicano del siglo XVI. Mexico: Universidad Nacional Nicol, Eduardo. "Meditacion del propio ser: La hispanidad." In Filosofia e identidad
Autonoma de Mexico, 1946. cultural en America latina, edited by Jorge J. E. Gracia and Ivan Jaksic. Caracas:
Mendez Plancarte, A. Poetas novohispanos, segundo siglo (1621-1721). Mexico: Monte Avila, 1988.
UNAM, 1944. . Elproblema de la filosofia hispdnica. Madrid: Editorial Tecnos, 1961.
Mercado, Tomas de. Commentarii lucidissimi in textum Petri Hispani... cum argumen- Norena, Carlos. Studies in Spanish Renaissance Thought. The Hague: Nijhoff, 1975.
torum selectissimorum opusculo. . . . Seville: Fernando Diaz, 1571. Translation and Ochoa, A. Diego Jose Abady sufamilia. Morelia, Michoacan: Fonapas and Govern-
introduction by M. Beuchot. Mexico: UNAM, 1985. ment of the State of Michoacan, 1980.
. In logicam magnam Aristotelis commentarii, cum nova translatione textus ab Osorio, I. Floresta de gramdtica, poetica y retorica en Nueva Espana. Mexico: UNAM,
eodem auctore. Seville: Fernando Diaz, 1571. 1980.
. Suma de tratos y contratos. Salamanca: Matias Guast, 1569. Seville: Fer- Osorio Romero, I. Antonio Rubio en la filosofia novohispana. Mexico: UNAM, 1988.
nando Diaz, 1571 and 1578. Italian version, Brescia: Pietro Maria Marchetti, Palafox y Mendoza, J. de. Obras del Ilustisimo, Excelentisimo y Venerable Siervo deDios
1591. Incomplete modern version with an introductory study by R. Sierra Don Juan de Palafoxy Mendoza. Vol. 10. Madrid: D. Gabriel Ramirez, 1762.
Bravo. Madrid: Editora Nacional, 1975. Complete modern version with an in- Palomera, E. J. Fray Diego Valades, evangelizador, humanista de la Nueva Espana. El
troduction by N. Sanchez Albornoz. 2 vols. Madrid: Clasicos del Pensamiento hombreysu epoca. Mexico: Ed. Jus, 1963. Compiled in Diego Valades, O.F.M., evan-
Economico Espanol, Instituto de Estudios Fiscales, 1977. gelizador humanista de la Nueva Espana. El hombre, su epoca y su obra. Mexico, Uni-
Michalski, K. La philosophic au XlVe siecle. Six etudes. Frankfurt: Minerva, 1969. versidad Iberoamericana, 1988.
Miranda, Francisco. "Vasco de Quiroga, artifice humanista de Michoacan." In Hu- . Fray Diego Valades, evangelizador, humanista de la Nueva Espana. Su obra.
manismo y ciencia en la formation de Mexico. Edited by C. Herrejon Peredo. Mexico: Ed. Jus, 1982. Compiled in Diego Valades, O.F.M., evangelizador humanista
Zamora, Mexico: El Colegio de Michoacan, 1984. de la Nueva Espana. El hombre, su epoca y su obra. Mexico, Universidad Iberoamer-
Miranda, Francisco, and G. Briseno, eds. Vasco de Quiroga: educador de adultos. icana, 1988.
Patzcuaro, Michoacan, Mexico: CREFAL / Colegio de Michoacan, 1984. Pascual Buxo, J, ed. Muerte y desengaho en la poesia novohispana (sighs XVI y XVII).
Montross, C. M. Virtue or Vice: Sor Jauna's Use of Thomist Thought. Washington, D.C.: Mexico: UNAM, 1975.
Catholic University of America Press, 1981. . "Elsueno de sor Juana. Alegoria y modelo del mundo." In Sdbado, suple-
Moreno, Rafael. "Alzate y la filosofia de la Ilustracion." Filosofia y Letras XIX, mento de Unomasuno, 15 August 1981.
no. 37 (January-March 1950): pp. 107-29. . Sor Juana Ines de la Cruz en el conocimiento de su "Sueho". Mexico: UNAM,
. "La filosofia moderna en la Nueva Espana." In Estudios de historia de la 1984.
filosofia en Mexico. 2d ed. Mexico: UNAM, 1973. Paz, Octavio. El peregrino en su patria, Mexico. In La obra de Octavio Paz. Vol. 1. Reim-
. "J. A. Alzate y la filosofia de la Ilustracion." Memoriasy Revista de la Acade- pression, Mexico: FCE, 1989.
mia Nacional de Ciencias 57, nn. 1-2, (1952): pp. 55-84. . Sor Juana or the Traps of Faith. Translated by Margaret Sayers Peden. Cam-
Moreno de los Arcos, R. J. /. Bartolacje, Mercurio Volatile. Mexico: UNAM, 1979. bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1988. Sor Juana Inh de la Cruz o las tram-
. J. I. Barlolache, periodismo iluslrado. Mexico: UNAM, 198 !. pas de Id ft: Mexico: I'Cli, 1982.
194 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o Bibliography 195

Perena Vicente, Luciano. La carta de los derechos humanos segun Bartolome de Las . Pensamiento y realidad en Fray Alonso de la Vera Cruz. Mexico: Universidad
Casas. Guatemala: Convento de Santo Domingo, 1978. Autonoma de Mexico, 1987.
. The Rights and Obligations of Indians and Spaniards in the New World. Sala- Remesal, A. de. Historia de la provincia de San Vicente de Chiapa y Guatemala de la es-
manca: Universidad Pontificia de Salamanca and Catholic University of Amer- clarecida Orden de nuestro glorioso Padre Santo Domingo de Guzman. Madrid: n.p.,
ica Press, 1992. 1619.
Perez de Rivas, A. Cronica y historia de la Provincia de la Compahia de Jesus de Mexico en Revuelta Sariudo, M., and C. Moron Arroyo, eds. El erasmismo en Espafia. San-
Nueva Espafia. Mexico: n.p., 1896. tander: Sociedad Menendez Pelayo, 1986.
Perez de Salazar, F. Biografia de Carlos de Siguenza y Gdngora de varios documento in- Reyes, Alfonso. Capitulos de literatura espahola. 1st ser. Mexico: La Casa de Espafia
editos. Mexico: Antigua Imprenta Murguia, 1928. en Mexico, 1939.
Perez Fernandez, I. Cronologia documentada de los viajes, estancias y actuaciones de Fray Rivera, Agustin. Lafilosofia en la Nueva Espaha: Disertacion sobre el atraso de la Nueva
Bartolome de Las Casas. Puerto Rico: Universidad Central de Bayamon, 1985. Espaha en las ciencias filosoficas. Lagos: Lopez Arce, 1885.
. Fray Bartolome de Las Casas. Caleruega: OPE, 1984. . Treinta sofismas y un buen argumento del Sr. Dr. D. Agustin de la Rosa. Lagos:
. Inventario documentado de los escritos de Fray Bartolome de Las Casas. Puerto Lopez Arce, 1887.
Rico: Universidad Central de Bayamon, 1981. Robledo, P. Physica. n.p., 1742.
Pinta Llorente, de la M. La Inquisition espahola y los problemas de la cultura y de la in- Robles, Oswald. "Breve nota sobre Fray Juan de San Anastasio y su glorsario es-
tolerancia. Madrid: Ediciones Cultura Hispanica, 1953-1958. colastico." In Anuarh de Filosofia del Seminario de Investigachnes Filosoficas de la
Plaza y Jaen, C B . d e la. Cronica de la Realy Pontificia Universidad de Mexico. 2 vols. Facultad de Filosofia y Letra. Vol. 1. Mexico: UNAM, 1943.
Mexico: Imprenta Universitaria, 1931. . Filosofos mexicanos del sigh XVI. Mexico: Porrua, 1950.
Popkin, Richard. The History of Scepticism from Erasmus to Descartes. Assen: Van Gor- Rocafull, Gallegos. El pensamiento mexicano en los sighs XVIy XVII. Mexico: UNAM,
cum, 1964. 1974.
Osorio Romero, I. Antonio Rubio en lafilosofia novohispana. Mexico: UNAM, 1988. Romero, Francisco. Theory of Man. Translated by William Cooper. Berkeley: Uni-
Queralto Moreno, R. J. El pensamiento filosofico-politico de Bartolome de Las Casas. versity of California Press, 1964. Teoria del hombre. Buenas Aires: Editoral
Seville: Escuela de Estudios Hispano-Americanos, 1976. Losafa, 1952.
Quesada, Vicente G. La vida intelectual en la America espahola durante los sighs XVI, Ronan, C. Francisco Javier Clavigero. Figure of the Mexican Enlightenment: His Life and
XVII, y XVIII. Buenos Aires: Arnoldo Moen y Hermano, 1910. Works. Roma: Institutum Historicum Societatis Iesu, 1977.
Quiroga, Vasco de. De debellandis indis. Edited by Rene Acuna. Mexico: UNAM, Rosa, Agustin de la. La instruction en Mexico durante su dependencia de Espaha.
1988. Guadalajara: n.p., 1888. Reprint, Guadalajara: Instituto Tecnologico de Guada-
. Information en derecho . . . sobre algunas provisiones del real Consejo de Indias. lajara, 1952.
Edited by C. Herrejon Peredo. Mexico: SEP, 1985. Rovira, M. del C. Eclectieos Portugueses del sigh XVIII y algunas de sus influencias en
. "Reglas y ordenanzas para el gobierno de los hospitales de Santa Fe de America. Mexico: UNAM, 1979. Reprint.
Mexico y Michoacan." In Vasco de Quiroga: educador de adultos. Edited by Fran- Ruiz Maldonado, E. "El Cardenal Cisneros, Bartolome de las Casas y la reforma de
cisco Miranda and G. Briseno. Patzcuaro, Michoacan, Mexico: CREFAL / Cole- Indias." laLibro AnualdelISEE, vol. 4, pt. 2 (1974-1975).
gio de Michoacan, 1984. . "La justicia en la obra de fray Bartolome de las Casas." In Libro Anual del
Ramos, Samuel. Hacia un nuevo humanismo: Programa de una antropologia filosofica. ISEE, vol. 4, pt. 2 (1974-1975).
Mexico: Fondo de Cultura Economica, 1962. Originally published in 1940. . "Proselitismo cristiano, libertad religiosa y justicia en la obra de Bar-
. Historia de la filosofia en Mexico, vol. 2, Obras completas. Mexico: UNAM, tolome de las Casas." Christus 469 (1974): 32-45.
1985. Salazar, Rafael. "La persona humana como testigo del ser en la filosofia de Fray
Redmond, Walter. Bibliography of the Philosophy in the Iberian Colonies of America. Alonso de la Vera Cruz." Libro Anual del ISEE, 2 (1973): 257-74.
The . "El ser absoluto en la filosofia de Fray Alonso de la Vera Cruz." Libro
Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1972. Anual del ISEE 1 (1971): 199-221.
. "Logica y ciencia en la Logica mexicana de Rubio." Quipu. Revista lati- Salazar Bondy, Augusto. zExiste una filosofia de nuestra America? Mexico: Siglo XXI,
noamericana de historia de las ciencias y la tecnologia. January-April, 1984. In La 1968.
logica mexicana en elsiglo de oro, edited by Walter Redmond and Mauricio Beu- . "The Meaning and Problem of Hispanic American Thought." In Latin
chot. Mexico: Universidad Nacional Autonoma de Mexico, 1985. American Philosophy in the Twentieth Century, edited by Jorge J. E. Gracia, Buffalo,
. "La Logica Mexicana de Antonio Rubio: Una nota historica." Didnoia 28 N.Y.: Prometheus Books, 1986.
(1982). . Sentido y problema del pensamiento hispano-amerkano. Translated by Arthur
. Relacionesy unidades complejas en la logica mexicana del sigh XVI. Forthcom- Berdtson. Lawrence: University of Kansas Center for Latin American Studies,
ing. Occasional papers ii. 16, 1969.
Redmond, Walter, and Mauricio Beuchot. La logica mexicana en el sig/o de oro. Mex- Salazar Mallen, R, Aptmlcs para una biografla dt sor Juana lues de la Cruz. 2d ed.
ico: Universidad Nacional Autonoma de Mexico, 1985. Mexico; UNAM, 1978,
196 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o Bibliography 197

Sanchez Vazquez, A. Rousseau en Mexico. Mexico: Grijalbo, 1970. . Critica filosofica. Mexico: Sues, de Fco. Diaz de Leon, 1904.
Sandoval Zapata, L. de. Obras. Edited by J. Pascual Buxo. Mexico: FCE, 1986. —• . Biblhgrafia filosofica mexicana. Vol. 1. Zamora, Mexico: El Colegio de Mi-
Schmidt, Peter L. "Suetons 'Pratum' seitWessner (1917)." In The Classical Tradition choacan, 1989. Fascimile edition of the 2d ed. of 1913.
and the Americas, edited by W. Haase, et al. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1994. . Critica filosofica, o Bibliografia de la filosofia en Mexico. Mexico: Herrero
Schmitt, Charles B., et al., eds. The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy. Hnos., 1904.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988. Vargas Uribe, G. "La influencia de la Utopia de Moro en los hospitales fundados
Schutte, Of elia. Cultural Identity and Social Liberation in Latin American Thought. Al- por Don Vasco de Quiroga." Boletin de la Coordination de la InvestigaciSn Cientifica
bany, N.Y.: SUNY Press, 1993. dela UniversidadMichoacana 10 (1986): 16-23.
Scorraille, Raoul. Francois Sudrez de la Compagnie de Jesus. 2 vols. Paris: P. Lethiell- Vasconcelos, Jose. Historia del pensamiento filosdfico. Mexico: Ediciones de la Uni-
eux, 1912. versidad Nacional de Mexico, 1937.
Semo, E. Historia del capitalismo en Mexico. Los origenes: 1521-1762. 3d ed. Mexico: Vera Cruz, Alonso de la. Dialectica Resolutio cum textu Aristotelis edita per Reverendum
Era, 1975. Patrem Alphonsum a Vera Cruce. . . . Mexico: Ioannes Paulus Brissensis, 1554;
Shorris, Earl. "Latino Si. Hispanic, No," The New York Times, 28 October 1992. 1562 (Salamanca); 1569; and 1573.
. Latinos: A Biography of the People. New York: W. W. Norton, 1992. . Physica Speculatio, Aedita per R.P.F. Alphonsum a Vera Cruce. . . . Accessit com-
Sierra Bravo, R. El pensamiento social y econdmico de la escoldstka desde sus origenes al pendium Spherae Campani ad complementum tractatus de coelo. . . . Mexico: Ioannes
comienzo del catolicismo social. 2 vols. Madrid: Consejo Superior de Investiga- Paulus Brissensis, 1557; 1562 (Salamanca); 1569; and 1573.
ciones Cientificas, 1975. . Recognitio summularum Reverendi Patris Illefonsi a Vera Cruce. . . . Mexico:
Sigiienza y Gongora, Carlos de. Libra astrondmica y filosofica. 2d ed. Mexico: Ioannes Paulus Brissensis, 1554; 1562 (Salamanca); 1569; 1573; 1579 (hypo-
UNAM, 1984. thetical).
. Obras historicas. Mexico: Porrua, 1944. Villanueva, E. "Philosophical Analysis in Mexico." In Philosophical Analysis in Latin
. Relaciones historicas. 3d ed. Mexico: UNAM, 1972. America, edited by Jorge J. E. Gracia, et al. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1984.
Solana, Marcial. Historia de lafilosofia espahola: Epoca del Renacimiento (sigh XVI). 3 Villar Villa Amill, J. J. Disputationes in octo Physicorum Libros. 1748. Manuscript.
vols. Madrid: Real Academia de Ciencias Exactas, Fisicas y Naturales, 1941. Villasenor, R. "Luciano, Moro y el utopismo de Vasco de Quiroga." Cuadernos
Someda, H. "Bartolome de Las Casas como historiador." Studium 23 (1983): Americanos 4 (1942) 155-75.
137-45. Warren, F. B. Vasco de Quiroga y sus hospitales-pueblo de Santa Fe. Morelia, Mexico:
Somolinos d'Ardois, G. Introductory biography and bibliography to Obras Comple- Universidad Michoacana, 1977.
tas, by Francisco Hernandez. Mexico: UNAM, 1960. Windelband, Wilhelm. A History of Philosophy. 2 vols. New York: Harper and
Stoetzer, O. Carlos. Las raices escoldsticas de la emancipation de la America espanola. Brothers, 1958.
Madrid: Centra de Estudios Constitucionales, 1982. Wittgenstein, Ludwig J. J. Philosophical Investigations. New York: Macmillan, 1953.
Trabulse, E. "Antonio de Leon y Gama, astronomo y novohispano." Humanidades Xirau, R. Genioyfigura de sor Juana. 2d ed. Buenos Aires: EUDEBA, 1970.
(Universidad Iberoamericana) 3 (1975): p. 201 fi. Yhmoff Cabrera, J. Catdlogo de obras manuscritas en latin de la Biblioteca Nacional de
. Cienciay religion en el sigh XVII. Mexico: El Colegio de Mexico, 1974. Mexico. Mexico: UNAM, 1975.
— . Elcircuh roto. Mexico: FCE-SEP, 1983. Zahar Vergara, A. "Frai Francisco Naranjo." Anuario de Filosofia del Seminarh de Inves-
Trentman, John. "Scholasticism in the Seventeenth Century." In The Cambridge tigaciones Filosdficas de la Facultad de Filosofiay Letras de la UNAM, 1 (1943): 47-90.
History of Later Medieval Philosophy, edited by N. Kretzman, et al. Cambridge: Zamora, J. de. Philosophia naturalis in octo Aristotelis libros. 1744. Manuscript.
Cambridge University Press, 1982. Zapata y Sandoval, Juan de. De iustitia distributiva. Vallisoleti: Cristoph. Lasso Vaca,
Trejo, Pedro de. Cancionero General. Mexico: UNAM, 1981. 1609.
Ulloa Cardenas, C. "Cambio insensible: la filosofia de Francisco Javier Clavijero." Zavala, Silvio. La defensa de los derechos del hombre en America Latina (sighs XVI-
Typescript. Universidad de Guadalajara. XVIII). Mexico: UNAM-UNESCO, 1982.
Uriarte, J. E., and M. Lecina. Biblioteca de escritores de la Compahia de JesUl . "En busca del tratado de debellandis indis de Vasco de Quiroga." Historia
pertenecientes a la antigua asistencia de Espana desde sus origenes hasta el ano de I'/'/1 Mexicana 17 / 68 (1968): 485-515.
Madrid: n.p„ 1925-1930. . "En torno del tratado de debellandis indis de Vasco de Quiroga." Historia
Vafades, Diego. Retdrica Cristiana. Edited by Tarscicio Herrera, et al. Mexico: FondO Mexicana, 18 / 72 (1969): 623-26.
de Cultura Economica, 1989. . "Fray Alonso de la Vera Cruz en la vision de Antonio Gomez Robledo."
Valdez, R. Estudio sotiopedagdgico de laobra educativa de don Vasco de Quiroga. Mexico: Didhgos. No. 13. El Colegio de Mexico, 1983.
n.p.,T975. . Recuerdo de Vasco de Quiroga. 2d ed. Mexico: Porrua, 1987.
Valenzuela Rodarte, Alberto. J. L. Maneiro, Vidas de algunos mexicanos ilustres, Mev . La Utopia de Tomds Mora en la Nueva Espana. Mexico: Robredo, 1935.
ico: UNAM, 1988. Zea, Leopoldo, "En torno a nun lilosoli'.i .liiiericana." In Filosofia e idenlidad cultural
Valverde Tellez, E. Apuntaciones histdricas sobre In filosoffa en Mexico. Mexico: I In en America latina, edited by Jorge J. li. (ii.ici.i .nut Iv.iti J.iksic. CH.H.IS: Monte
rero Hnos., 1896. Avil.i, I9KH.
198 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o

. La filosofia en Mexico. Vol. 1. Mexico: Libro-Mex Eds., 1955.


Zumarraga, Juan de. Doctrina breve muy provechosa de las cosas que perteneeen a lafe
catholica y a nra. cristiandad, en estilo llano pa. comu(n) intelige(n)cia. Mexico: n.p.,
1543.
. Doctrina cristiana mas cierta y verdadera para gentes sin erudition y letras. Mex-
ico: n.p., 1546.
. Reg la cristiana breve. Edited by J. Almoina. Mexico: Jus, 1951.
"Segundo parecer sobre la esclavitud." In Textospoliticos en la Nueva Espaha,
edited by C. Herrejon Peredo. Mexico: UNAM, 1984.

Index

Abad, Diego Jose, 153-56 Astrology, 120


Alarcon, Ruiz de, 15 astronomy, 117, 120
Albingensians, xxiii atomism, 150-56
Alcazar, Diego Marin de, 110-12 Augustinians, 3, 5, xxiv, xxvi, 7 0 - 8 1 ,
Aldalur, Friar Jose Antonio de, 141 103-7, 146-47
Aldereta, Jose, 142 authority, 34-35
Alegre, Francisco Javier, 156-57 Avilez, Pedro [gnaclo de, I 50
Alvarez, Manuel, 149
Alzate, Father Jose Antonio, 174 Bacon, Francis, 159
Amill, Father Juan Jose Villar Villa, 151 Balbuena, Bernardo de, 95-96
Amorillo, Friar Juan, 80 barbarianism, 28-32
analogy, 86 Baroque period, viii
anthropology, 28-30, 126, 128, 160-65 Basalenque, Friar Diego, 103-4
Aquinas, St. Thomas, xxvi, 9, 36, 108 Bassori, Father Jose Bueno, 152
Aragon, Manuel Lopez de, 145 Bazan, Friar Fernando, 70
Aragon, Vincente, 145 beauty, 57
Aragones, Father Antonio Mariano, Benevente, Friar Toribio de, 60
174 Beristain, 5
Arias, Antonio, 90-91 Bible, 58
architecture and philosophy, 4 Blanco, Father Matfas, 113, 151
Aristotle: xxvi, 3; catagories, 86, 131; Blanco, Father Ignacio, 156
ethics, 51, 54; human rights, 28; Borda, Friar Andres, 100
logic, 67-68, 73-75; love, 57; nat- Bourbon, family, 138
ural philosophy, 49-50, 87-89; Brattle, William, 13
physics, 55, 87-89, 105-6, 109, Briceno, Alfonso, xiii
120; psychology, 50; science, 76; Buffon, ix
slavery, 26-28, 30—31; universals, Burrus, 6
85-86; virtue, 32,52-54; voluntary
actions, 52 Cabrera y Q i i i n l c r o , C i y e l a n o de, I i'>
A r i c i g . i , Pniher Manuel, I I \ CabtUero, i.11111• i Diego, 11 I

!<<'»
200 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n C o l o n i a l M e x i c o Index 201

Calderon, Friar Jose, 103 de Pauw, iv, 161-64 Gamarra, Diaz de, 4, 5 individuation, x
Camacho, Friar Francisco, 142 decadence of clergy, 92 Gante, Friar Pedro de, 60, 61-62 infinite, 88
Camara, Friar Marcos, 61 democracy, 34 Garces, Friar Julian, 21 Inquisition, xxiv, 6, 25
Cardenas y Leon, Carlos de, 173 demonstration, 75-76 Gasset, Jose Ortega, xiii, xv, n. intentionality, 129
Careri, Giovanni Francesco Gemelli, Descartes, Rene, xxix, 151, 155, 159 generation and corruption, 89, 106 international relations, Spain and
118 desegregation, early, 37-38 Generation of 1898, xv, n. 12, n. 14 Indes, 69
Carmelites, 147 dialectics, 68, 74, 110 generousity, 52 Isabella of Castile, xi
Cartesian influence, 131, 133-34, 143, dictatorship as government, 36 God, 56, 123, 130 Islamic philosophy, xi, xx, xxiv, xxviii,
151-55, 159 dignity of man, 20-21 Gonzalez, Nepomuceno Sanchez y, 175 39
Casas, Friar Bartolome de la, 21, 2 6 - divine right, 47 good, 30, 35, 51 Isidore of Seville, xxvii
36, 38, 63, 160-61 Dominicans, xxvi, xxvii, 3, 5, 63-70, Gornales, Friar Miguel de, 61
Caso, Antonio, 5 101-3, 144-46, 178-79 Gorrifio y Arduengo, Manuel Maria, Jesuits, vii, ix, 3, 7, 12, 81-92, 107-
Cassiodorus, xxvii Donio, Jacobo, 66 183 13, 148-56
categories, 68, 74-75, 86, 105 dreams, 56 Goudin, Antonio, 145 Jewish philosophy, xi, xx, 11
Catelan philosophy, xi Duran, Father Calvo, 178 Grande, Cristoforo, 141 Jews, 39
causes, 88, 105, Aristotelian, 49 Granillo, Father Martin Carlos jurisdiction, 34, 39
Celis, Friar Pedro de, 107 economics, 6, 138 Tamallo, 113 justice, x, 32, 35-36, 160
Cerdan, Father Raymundo Mariano, education of Indians, 61, 169-71 greek philosophy, 20-21, 126 Jugo, Father Antonio Jose de, 156
156 el Porfiriato, vii Guerrero, Father Alonso, 108-10
certainty, 87 elements, 49-50, 89 Guevara y Basoasabal, Father Andres Kino, Father Eusebio, 117
Cervante, Friar Simon Jose, 147 empirical sciences, 8 de, 179-81 Kircher, Atannsio, ix
chance, 88 enlightenment, 9 knowledge: of God, 56; theory of, 74,
children, rearing of, 44 Encisco y Texada, Manuel, 141 happiness, 51, 54, 56 86, 105, 129-37, 170-71
Christianity: academics and, 8; freedom emancipation of Mexico, 139 Hapsburgs, 6
and, 36, 39; humanism and, xxii- Erasmus of Rotterdam, 21-22 Hartmann, Nicolai, xiii-xiv land, ownership of, 77
xxiv; man's dignity and, 21; New Espinosa, Friar Pedro de, 61 heavens, 89, 106 language, philosophy of, x, xxx, 68, 91
World, xxi; philosophy, xxii-xxv, 6; Esteban, Juan, 94 Hegel, 7 Latin American philosophy, xi; renais-
slavery and, 23; virtue and, 52 ethics, x, 51 Herize, Father Francisco Javier, 149 sance of, xii
Church, temporal power, 77 evangelization of Indians, 43, 60-62, hermetism, ix law: 53, 76, 77; human rights and, 3 2 -
civilization, development, 32 77-78, 98 Hernandez, Dr. Francisco, ix, 21, 48-58 34; justice and, 35; of nations, 47;
Clavigero, Francisco Javier, ix, 157-65 Hidalgo y Costilla, Father Don Miguel, philosophy, 6, 7, 33
cloning, 89 Fabri, Father Honorato, 155 182 Ledesma, Father Juan de, 108
comets, 51 faith, 87, 181 Hinojosa, Friar Jose de, 79, 101 Ledesma, Friar Bartolome de, 63
Contreras, Friar Juan, 80 Falcumbelli, Father Jose Luis, 150 Hispano, Pedro, 63, 65 Leibniz, 89,181
Copernicus, 143, 160 fate, 88 Hispanic, definition of term, xv-xx, Leon, Don Joaquin Velazquez de, 173
Cordova, Friar Matias de, 178-79 Ferdinand of Aragon, xi xxv, xxvi Leyva, Friar Pedro de, 99
Coronel, Friar Francisco, 80 Figueroa, Jose Mariano Mocino history, vii, xvi, xvii, xxvii, 122-23, 165 liberalism, 16
Coriche, Cristobal, 145 Suarezde, 175 Hortigosa, Pedro de, 82 liberation, philosophy of, 39
cosmology, 89-90, 121, 130, 159, Flores, Cristobal, 148 hospitals, 37-39, 42-46 logic: x, xxx, 65-68, 72, 104-5, 127-
180-81 fortitude, 52 human rights, 32-36 28, 148, 149, 151-52
Council of Trent, xxiv Franciscans, vii, xxvi, 3, 60-62, 9 8 - humanism, ix, xii, xix, xxii-xxvi, 15, Lombardo, Pedro, 98
counter reformation, xiii-xxv, xxviii 101, 140-44, 177-78 21,46, 85, 153 Lopez, Juan Francisco, 150
creation, 55 freewill, 29, 34-35, 113, 151 hygiene, 44 Lopez, Friar Luis, 70
criollos, viii, 8-10, 15 Frondizi, Risieri, xv, n. 14 love, 56-57
Cruz, Friar Francisco, 99 imagination, 129 Loza, Father Agustin Jose del Rio y,
Cruz, Sister Juana Ines de la, 125-37 Gabalda, Friar Jose de, 98 \ Indians: branding of, 24; liberation of, 174
Cuellar, Jose Ignacio, 145 Galilei, Galileo, 121, 160 39, 42, 94; rationality of, 161-65;
culture, Mexican, 92, 95-96, 124 Gallegos, Jose1, 146 rights of, 26, 28, 94-95, 160-61; Mair, John, 28
(iam.irrn y Onvalos, Juan licnilo Di,i/ superstitions, 117; Utopian, 41; val- Maldonado, I'allicr Jose, 149
Davila, Fray Joaquin Camacho, 142 de, 166-73 ues of, 42 Miilo, lose Rodriguez, 142
202 History of P h i l o s o p h y i n Colonial M e x i c o Index 203

man, nature of, 126, 128 ontology, xxx Raynal, ix slavery, 23-24, 26, 28, 29, 32-33, 39,
Mancilla, Friar Antonio, 144 Oquendo, Mateo Rosas de, 19-20 reformation, xix, xxi, xxii, xxiii-xxiv 40, 165
Marquez, Father Pedro Jose, 179-80 Oratorians, x religious, rights of, 101 sociability, 29, 34
marriage, 76 Oronsoro, Friar Pedro de, 142 religious centers, 3 social philosophy, 8, 68-69
Marxism, 15 Orrio, Father Francisco Javier Alejo religion, natural to man, 29-30 socialism, 15, 43, 45
Maya, Jose de, 148 de, 152 Rendon, Manuel Garcia de, 141 society, good of, 35, 36
Mayagoitia, David, 10-12, 17 Ortega, Friar Cristobal de, xix, 69 rhetoric, 61-62, 151, 152 Soldevilla, Father Mariano, 153
medieval philosophy, xi, xix Ortiz, Friar Felipe, 142 rights, 34 Sologuren, Friar Miguel de, 143 (SP)
mental illness, 44-45 Rivera, Agustin, 2, 13 Soto, Domingo de, 63
Mercedarians, 107, 148 paganism, xxiii Rosa, Agustin de la, 2 soul: faculties of, 159; immortal, 170;
Mercado, Friar Tomas de, 6, 64-69 perfection, 34 Robledo, Father Pablo, 151 nature of, 80, 88-89, 106, 128;
metaphysics, x, 111-12, 131, 149 peripathetic philosophy, 49-50 Robledo, Antonio Gomez, 76 types of, 50-51
mathematics, 119-20, 171 Pez, Admiral Andres de, 118 Robles, Oswaldo, 12-14 Suarez, Francisco, xvii, xxvii, 3, 5,
method, in science, 87, 120 Peza, Nicolas de, 152 Rocafull, Jose Maria Gallegos, 14 111, 113; influence of, 149
Mexican Provincial Council, 38 Peralta, Father Antonio, 113 Rodriguez, Friar Diego, 107 syllogism, 67
Meza, Friar Francisco Javier de, 146 phenomenology, 129 roman philosophy, xi, xx, xxiii stoicism, ix, xiii, 3, 55-58, I I 5 Id,
microcosm, symbol, 126, 135-37 Philip II, 6 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 145 140-43
Mier, Friar Servando Teresa de, 178 physics, 76, 87, 105-7, 109, 111, 149, Rubio, Antonio, xvii, 83-90
mind, operations of, 86 150, 150-52, 180 Rueda, Friar Juan de, 104-6 Talavera, Don Alonso de, I 16
missions: vii-viii Piedra, Father Jose de la, 152 Tellez, Bmeterio Valverde, 2-4
modern philosophy: 4; influence in place, 88 Salinas, Friar Buenaventura, 99 Tenorio, Friar Vicente, 146
Mexico, 8, 118, 139, 145, 148-50, Platonism, 57-58, 75, 85 Sanchez, Jose Ignacio, 149 Thomism, xiii, ), 5, 60, 65, i \i, [48
154, 158ff, 166; scholasticism and, Ponce, Constantino, 21, 22, 25 Sandoval Zapata, Don Luis de, 114-15 49
5-7, 10-11 Portugal, philosophy of, xi Sahagun, Friar Bernardino de, 60 time, 88
Moguer, Friar Andres de, 63 Porphyry, 68, 73 San Anastasio, Friar Juan de, 147 Toledo, Father Domingo de, 148
Molina, Father Jose Francisco de, 5, Portu, Canon Marcos, 113 Santa Cruze, Father Jose Luis de la, Torre, Ma rl in de la, 117
149 positive law, 69, 162 151 Torres, Jose, 141
monarchy, 34 positivism, vii Santiago, 63 Trejo, Pedro de, 21
Montaigne, xxiv Pravia, Friar Pedro de, 64 Santisteban, Friar Diego de, 107-8 truth, 30, 87, 120, 122-23, 170
Montufar, Bishop, 25 preaching gospel, right to, 39-40 Santo Tomas, Juan de, 65 TychoBrahe, 143, 160
moral philosophy, 51-55 predication, 68, 74, 85-86 Segura y Tronceso, Friar Juan Antonio tyranny, 36, 77, 178
More, Thomas, 20-21, 27, 41, 45, 46 Prieto, Nicolas, 149 de, 148
motion, 88 prime mover, 49 semiotics, xxx universal, x, 74, 85, 105, 111
Murillo, Manuel, 146 principle, 88 Sepulveda, Juan Gines de, 26, 30-32 universe, nature of, 89
mysticism, 132-37 property, 33-34 science, 75-76, 119; method of, 87, Utrera, Jose de, 150
providence of history, 123 120; modern, 159 Utopia, 20, 21, 26, 41, 45
Naranjo, Francisco, 102-3 prudence, 32 Scheler, Max, xiii-xiv
nationalism, 124 psychology, 50 scholastism: anthropology, 126, 128; vacuum, 88
natural law, 23, 27, 32, 34, 47, 69, 162 Puerto, Don Nicolas del, 94 baroque and humanistic, ix; church Valades, Friar Diego de, viii, 61-62
natural religion, 30 Puerto, Father Marino Jeronimo del, and, 15, 16; Iberian, xxvi; influence Valdetaro, Father Juan Lorenzo, 151
natural science, 119-20 151 in Mexico, 2-4, 13-18, 61, 118, Valencia, Father Andres de, 108
nature, 49, 87 Puga, Father Gregorio Vazquez de, 149 138-39, 143, 145, 149-50, 159ff; Vallarta y Palma, Father Jose Mariano
Neri, San Felipe, 165 Pythagoreanism, 121 method, 159; problems of, 6-11, 17; de, 152-53
New World, exploration, xix, xxii truth and, 7, 11 Valtierra, Father Fernando, 113
neo-Platonism, ix Quevedo, Bishop Juan de, 28 scotists^xiii, 3, 99-100, 112 Varela, Jose, 143
novels, 118 Quinonos, Friar Antonio, 141 Scotus, Duns, xxvi Vasconcelos, Jose, 4 - 5
Nunez, Father Antonio, 112 Quiroga, Vasco de, 21, 36-48 Sierra, Father Agustin, 112 Vazquez, Friar Gabriel, 107
Sigiienza y G6ngora, Don Carlos de, Vega, Luis Mariano de la, 143
objectivity, 122 Ramos, Samuel, v, 5-10, 16, 17 viii, 15, I 16-25 Vera Cruz, Alonso de la, xiii, u. 7, 6,
Ochoa, Father Juan Angel de, 1 56 rational animal, 29 skepticism, xxi, xxii, xxiv, I H - 3 4 It, 15, 18, 71-79
204 H i s t o r y of P h i l o s o p h y i n C o l o n i a l M e x i c o

Versor, Juan, 65 will, 29, 50, 52


Viary Larrimbe, Antonio, 145 women religious, 125-37
Vidarte, Friar Agustin Jose, 143 work, 42, 44
Villar, Father Jose del, 149
Villarrubia, Friar Diego de, 107 y Mendoza, Bishop Palafox, 94
Villasenor, Jose, 143 Ylarregui, Friar Fermin de, 146
Vincent of Beauvais, xxvii
Virgin Mary, 42 Zapata y Sandoval, Juan de, viii, ix, 7
virtue, 51-54, 170 Zavala, Silvio, 160
visions, 56 Zea, Leopoldo, xv, n. 14, 16-17
Vitoria, Francisco de, xiv Zepeda, Father Jose, 152
Zerezeda, Emiliano Millan de, 143
war, 23, 39-40, 46-48 Zespedes, Anselmo, 142
wealth, 55-56 Zumarraga, Friar Juan de, 21-26
welfare, social, 45

The History ofPhilosophy in Colonial Mexico was composed in H.5/I l Meridicn Kniii.in
by Generic Compositors, Stamford, New York; primed on 60-pomul (il.illcllci
SuppJe Opaque Recycled Natural and bound by Thomson-Shore, Inc., Drain.
Mitliij-',.in; and designed and produced by Kdi'hcrgll Hook Design, I'lllsbnin, North
Carolina.
Maurido Beuchot, O.P.

mm

History of
Philosophy
in Colonial
Mexico
Translated by Elizabeth Millan
Foreword by Jorge J. E. Gracia

The Catholic University of America Press


Washington, i>.<:.
Contents

Prologue vii
Originally published as Historia de lafilosofia en el Mexico Colonial by Foreword: The Origins of Hispanic Philosophy xi
Editorial herder, Provenza 388, 08025 Barcelona, Spain. Copyright
© 1996. This translation published by permission. Introduction: Understanding the History of Philosophy in
Colonial Mexico 1
Copyright © 1998
The Catholic University of America Press 2 The Sixteenth Century: The Humanist Philosophers 19
All rights reserved
Printed in the United States of America 3 The Sixteenth Century: The Scholastic Philosophers 60
Franciscans / 60 Dominicans / 63
The paper used in this publication meets the minimum A U0ustin ians I 70 Jesuits 181
requirements of American National Standards for Information
Science—Permanence of Paper for Printed Library materials, ANSI 4 The Seventeenth Century 92
Z39.48-1984. "Franciscans 198 Dominicans 1101
A ugustinians 1103 Mercedarians /107
Jesuits 1107 Secular Clergy 1113
Religious Women 1125
LIBRARY OF CONGRESS CATALOGING-IN-PUBLICATION DATA
Beuchot, Mauricio. "> The Eighteenth Century 138
[Historia de la filosofia en el Mexico colonial. English] Franciscans 1140 Dominicans 1144
The history of philosophy in colonial Mexico / Mauricio Beuchot; Augustinians 1146 Carmelites 1147
translated by Elizabeth Millan; foreword by Jorge J. E. Gracia. Mercedarians 1148 Jesuits 1148
p. cm. Oratorians 1165 Secular Clergy 1173
Includes bibliographical references and index.
1. Philosophy—Mexico—History. 2. Philosophy, Mexican. << The Nineteenth Century 177
3. Mexico—Intellectual life. I. Title. I'lmtiisiiiits 1177 Dominicans 1178
BI016.B4913 1998 Jesuits 117<> Secular Clergy 1182
199'.72—dc21
98-9210
ISBN 0-8132-0906-4 (alk. paper) Hll.lloKr.iphy 185
Index i""

You might also like