You are on page 1of 10

Moreana, no.

3 1-32 (Nov 197 1): 29-46

VTVOLO

Upon a tyme, when tidyngw came too the citie of Cainthe that
~gRliflippefathertoAlexanderaumamedtheGr8at,~~g
thethemde with an armie mydl to lay h g e to the citie : The
Cainthianabeing forthwith stryken with w t e foam, beganno b d ,
and e a m d y to looke aboute them, and to falle to wake of all
handas. Some to akowre and tryxnm@up harnsis, sum, to m
stoma, mmr, to amendo and buylde hyghsr the w a l k , mms t o
rampiereand fortyfie the bulwarkes, and fortresms, some one thynge,
and some anothw for the defendinqe, and stmgthenynge af the citie.
Ths whiche M e labour, and to& of t h k when Diogsnes the
phylosopher sawe having no profitable busin- hersupon to aette
himself on worke (neither any mtln required his labour, and helpe as
expedient for the cornmen wealth in that needtie) immediatly
girded about him his phylawphicall cloke, and began to rolle, and
tumble up and downe hether and thethsr upon the hih syda, that
lieth adjoyninge to the citie, his mt barrel or tunne, wherein he
dwelled : for other d d y n g e place wold he have none. Thia seing
one of hia frendes, and not a litell muaynge therat, cams to hym :
And I praye the Diogones (quod he) prhie dosst thou thus, ar what
meanest thou hereby ? F m t h e I am tumblyng my t u b k to
(quod he) bycauae it whom no rsaaon that I only should be y d d ,
when, so many be working.
32 ROBERT COOGAN NVNC Vlvo w VOLO 33
Harpsfield merely asserts that Hythlodaeus enables More to compliment
Morton.' Stapleton, like Roper, makes no mention of Raphael ; but, in tell rude truths and discuss burning questions.' Bridgett's position was
his remarks on the Utopia it seems that he identifies Hythlodaeus' views taken in order t o rebut Seebohm who held that More was a radical
with those of ore.^ In the seventeenth century, Cresacre More relates visionary m youth who became intolerant and conservative during the
Hvthlodaeus t o More's ~ersonalitv: in literature and in life More often Reformation. Seebohm looks on Hythlodaeus as the mouthpiece through
'
"fayned matters cunningly t o have heard them of others, which he himself which More counsels Henry VIZI.2 Mackintosh distinguishes Raphael from
had invented, as in his preface t o his Utopia he artificially discourseth as More in regard t o communism. Because the debate a t Morton's court
though Raphael Hythlodius had told that whole storie unto him."3 amounts to a severe satire on Tudor England.which could provoke a
Hoddesdon does not even touch on the Utopia. Nor does Regi in his biogra- reprisal, Mackintosh considers Hythlodaeus chiefly as a protective masque.3
phy, but his appendix samples I d y ' s response to the Utopia in the i Perplexed by the ironies of the Utopia, he is evidently eager t o get back
Renaissance. Paulus Jovius (d.1552), Bishop of Nocera, holds that it
reveals delightfully a flourishing republic and a holy way of life ; St. R,obert
:; quickly to the safer ground of biography. Hutton reflects a similar
uneasiness. In regard t o the debate on service, the treatment of thieves.
B e h m i n e (d.162 I ) , a leader of the Counter-Reformation, states that j and even the communism, he feels that the views expressed by Hythlodaeus
because of the Utopia More deserves the title of p h i l o ~ o p h e rThere
.~ seems are substantially More's own. Although he states that the vicious condition
to be no significant treatment of Hythlodaeus in the eighteenth century. ! of Europe forces More to propose a voluntary, temporary, and primitive
From the nineteenth century t o the present, however, the Utopia , Christian communism, he knows that nowhere else does More offer
such a solution. Acknowledging defeat, he concludes : "It is a question
has attracted much notice ;for socialists and communists it is a far-sighted
vision of reform, for religious polemicists its author is to be damned or : impossible t o d e ~ i d e . " ~Later he says that More could not endorse
canonized. In the renew;d interest in Raphael, various interpretations communism, divorce, euthanasia, etc.5
.#
arise which still obtain. Although the lines are not always clear-cut, there lWJ2NTlETHCENTURYINTERPRETATIONS
are three major views - one identifies Hythlodaeus completely with More, i
Our century has witnessed one significant modification : some critics
a second sees him as a protective screen, the thud focuses on the
demand an outright repudiation of the independent philosopher and his
differences between More and Raphael.
In the nineteenth century, John Macdiarmid, who is quite puzzled : counsels. Those who still take Raphael as More's prolocutor do so for
by the discourse, describes Raphael simply as an adventurous navigator and I diverse reasons. Sidney Lee does not distinguish between Hythlodaeus and
More ; like Seebohm, he thinks that More turned his back on his youthful
an intelligent eye-witness. From his appendix on the Utopia, one can infer
j idealiim.6 Dudok emphasizes the very close relationship between More and
that he twins More and Hythlodaeus. He sees Raphael as part of a
propaedeutic strategy rather than as a philosopher who stimulates thought a Hythlodaeus in the dialogue." In passing he mentions that an interest-
ing comparison can be made between Raphael and h m u e l Gulliver -- he
by attacks on the establishment. In the dialogue, More uses Hythlodaeus f
then quickly dismissesthe matter by commentingon the difference between
to expose vices, to ridicule prejudices, and, thus, t o prepare the reader for
the benign More and the misanthropic Swift. This comparison comes t o
a better reception of the radical program in the discourse. Hythlodaeus
the fore again and partially accounts for this century's deflation of
should have the audience impatient to hear of the "wonderful islanders."5 r
Lupton and Bridgett both lean to the view that Raphael is More's
mouthpiece - especially in Book I. Lupton feels that persona-More posits
z Hythlodaeus. Dudok, however, will not allow the stature of the inimitable
Hythlodaeus to be diminished. In Raphael, he sees More's deep veneration
arguments of straw against communism. These are not t o be taken serious-
ly - the diseased condition of Europe forces More to prescribe desperate
1
1
of Plato. Quoting from Churton Collins' edition of the Utopia, he relates
Morton to Cephalus, the lawyer t o Thrasyrmchut, and Hythlodaeus t o
Socrates.8
remedies6 Bridgett divorces More from ~ y t h l o d a e u son war and com-
munism, but sees Raphael as a protective screen which enables More t o
I
1. TE. Bridptt, Life and Wrings of Blessed Thomas More (London, 1904),
---- pp. 10244. First edition was 1891.
1. Harpfield-Hitchock. Nicholas Hnrpsfield, me Life and Lkatlr of Sir Thorn 2. Frederic Seebohm, 7he Oxford Reformers (London, 1913). p. 389. First edition
More, ed. E. V. Hitchock (London, 1932), p. 105. war 1867.
2. Thomas Stapleton, 7he Life and nlu~m'ou~ &rtyrdom of Sir l%onrasMore, 3. James Mackintosh, me Life of Sir momas More (London, 1831), p. 54.
translated by P. E. Hallett, edited by E. E. Reynolds (London, 1966), pp. 28-31. 4. W i a m Holden Hutton, Sir W m s More (London, 1895), pp. 11624.
3. Cresacre More, 7he Life of Sir 7homas More (London. 1726). P. 28. 5. Ibid., pp. 138-39.
4. Domenico Regi, Delh Vita di T o m o Mom, 2 vols. (Milan, 1675). 11 pp. 246-48. 6. Sidney Lee,CreatEnglhhmen of the Sixteenth Century (New York, 1904). p. 34.
5. John Macdiannid. Lives of British Statesmen (London, 180% Appendix I, 7. Gerard Dudok, Sir Thomas More and His Utopia (Amsterdam, 1923), p. 11 1.
p. 5. 8. Ibid., pp. 93-94.
6. J. H. Lupton, 77re "Utopin" of Sir 771omrrs More, ed. J. H. Lupton (Oxford,
18')s).p. xxxvii.
34 ROBERT COOCAN NVNC wvo VT VOLO
For various reasons, Routh, Kautsky, Ames and Hexter identify
Hythlodaeus with More. For Miss Routh, who stresses the moral aspects LATEST VIEWS

of the work, he voices More's indictment of pride.1 Praising More as a Since the publication of the Yale Utopia, Sylvester, Berger, and
prophet of modern communism, Kautsky makes Raphael his mouthpiece. Johnson have carefully formulated an interpretation akin to this one.
What persona-More says is not important - what Hythloday says is More's Although space prohibits the lengthy analysis their position merits, a few
political confession of faith.2 Raphael protects More and enables him to major issues will be treated here. The three Yale men associate Greek with
express his anticlericaism and h& criti- of England's economy which Raphael's alienation. By changing the title from Nusquam to Utopia, and
exploits the poor.Ames, while taking into account the distinctions made by by giving Raphael a decided reference for Greek learning and culture, More
Campbelland Chambers between More and Hythlodaeus, CaMOt see how a emphasized the esoteric quality of the mariner's social program. Berger
satirist could disagree with a view, namely communism, that he develops makes this parenthetical remark about Hythlodaeus' detachment :
as a major issue.3The most forceful case for the identification is made by "More, like Alberti and other humanists, indicates this tendency by
Hurter in More's "Utopia" : The Biography of an Idea. In the discourse, remarking Hythlodaeus' preference for Greek over Latin".l Johnson
he says, ~ y t h l o d a e u sexpresses More's opinions, and in the dialogue he endorses this view, which was not documented in regard t o Alberti and
represents More's person.' Basing his position on the fact that More se- which cannot be substantiated in regard to More. He even makes the dabious
riously considered entry into Henry VIIl's service in 1516, Hexter holds judgment weightier by calling it-a convention : "As Berger remarks, a
that More's problem coincides exactly with Hythlodaeus'. Further on, this ~ r e o c c u ~ a t i o with
n Greek at the expense of Latin is a convention
assumption will be questioned ;and it will be suggested that More decided frequently used by Renaissance humanists t o express a contrast between
t o serve before he completed the dialope. In the Yale Utopia, Hexter philosophic isolation and a more pragmatic and immediate civil in-
retains his view which amounts t o a modem and tolerant exposition of volvement."2 Alberti's judgment must be taken in the context of the
Seebohm's position : when More wrote Utopia he was a visionary pos- advanced civilization of Quincento Italy - not More's backward England.
sessed by a moment of acute perception.
- - Thus, in 1515-1 516, Hythlodaeus' Speakingof More, Erasmus wonders what his wonderful, rich nature would
counseh were More's - even if these were not ore's ultimate
convictions (xiri).
not have accom~lishedif his talent had been trained in l t d v (3). .
. , One
of More's greatest achievements was his successful defense and cultivation
When one passes from the above position t o that of those who of Greek learning which, for England, fust became a practical reality in
differentiate between More and ~ ~ t h l o d a e &one, encounters this century's his circle. In 1501, while Hythlodaeus was accompanying Vespucci on his
fear of utopia and the deflation of Hythlodaeus. For Campbell, if More secondvoyasMore put aside his Latin books for Greek ones, and Erasmus
and Raphael are one in their protest against injustice, they differ consider- began an intensive study of Greek that lasted for three years. In 1504, the
ably in the means they advocate to reform it. Far from being More's year of the fust printed editions of the Iliad and Odyssey, Hythlodaeus
alter ego, that is, the social revolutionary More longed t o be, Hythlodaeus wrested permission from Vespucci t o remain behind in Brazil. In the
has too many characteristics foreign t o More's makeup : he is "impatient, year More completed the Utopia, Erasmus dedicated t o Leo X his Greek
presumptuous, inexperienced and unbalanced in judgment ; and that in edition of the New Testament, the appearance of which made Fisher
spite of (or was it rather because of ? ) his adventurous journey t o and Colet eager t o learn Greek. More's letters t o Dorp (October 1515)
Nowhere."S Traugott and Hejserman also feel that the journey t o Utopia and t o Oxford (March 1518) are two of the English Renaissance's most
was an affliction rather than a blessing. They liken Raphael t o Gulliver significant defenses of Greek learning. The letter t o Oxford echoes the
returned &om the land of the ~ o u ~ h n h n m s . ~ Utopia (5011-2) : "Nam in philosophia, exceptis duntaxat his, quae Cicero
reliquit et Seneca, nihil habent Latinorum scholae, nisi vel Graecum, vel
1. E.M.C. Routh, Sir %m More and His Friends ;1477-1535 (London 1934). quod e Graeca lingua traductum est."3 More, as well as ~ u d Cand Beatus
v. 71.
2. Karl Kautsky, i'7tom.v More and his Utopia (New York, 1959), pp. ,131-39. Rhenanus, who employ Greek in their commendatory letters t o the
3. Russel Ames, Citizen i'7tomos More and His Utopia (Rinceton, 1949), pp. 33-96. Utopia, would find-~;thlo&eus' attachment to reek praiseworthy -
4. J.H. Hexter, More's "Utopia" : i'7te Biogmphy of an I d a (Rinceton, 1952), the philosopher must go ad fontes.
p. 114.
5. W.E. Campbell,MoreS "Utopia"rmd His Socicrl Teaching (London, 1930), p. 48.
For a more recent interpretation of HytNodaeus as More's alter ego, r e P. Sawada, 1. Harry Berger, 'The Renaissance Imagination : Second World and Green World,"
"The Raise of Realpolitik ? H. Oncken and More's Utopia," Moremm, 15-16 (1967), The Centennial Review, 9 (1965), p. 63.
145-64. 2. Robbin S. Johnson,More's "Utopia" : Ideal and nlusion (New Haven, 1969),p.5.
6. See John Traugott, "A Voyage to Nowhere. with Thomas More and Jonathan 3. Thomas More, m e Correspondence of Sir Thomas More.ed. E . F . Rogen
Swift : Utopia and m e Voyage to the Hacyhnhnm,"Sewee Review, 69 (1961), (Princeton, 1947), p. 117, translated in St. i%oms More :Selected Letters, ed. E . F .
543-565. A. R. Heiserman, "Satire in the Utopia," P M L A, 78 (1963), 163-174. Rogers (Yale, 1961), p. 100. See also Surtz's comments on 5012.
36 ROBERT COOGAN NVNC VlVO VT VOLO 37

In their deflation of Raphael, Berger and Johnson make much of the h a prophet-philosopher is fictional... "Eutopia" ("the happy place") re-
Morton episode. They think that Morton "humors Hythlodaeus as he v& itself as a garden of illusory, empty pleasures, pleasures gained without
humors the lawyer, friv and parasite - a Chaucerian gallery eminently struggle or sacrifice."l Is Hythlodaeus really proposing a soft prim-
quaUed to bring on an attack. He amuses himself with them, is amused itivism ? The primitivi9m of Utopia is hard. In addition to the farm labor
by them, allows them to vent their vanities and theories at his table, and imposed on all, each of the five Utopian trades requires persistent and
dismisses them when it is time 'to heare his suetorsl."l Hythlodaeus may tedious application in order to transfrom the goods of nature into
be too idealistic, tbe contrast between him and Morton is wident ;yet human amenities, i.e., into the matter of pleasure. In this society dominated
if any of his counsels could be implemented, certainly those he gives t o by the mature and old, even the dehghts of the common dining hall - if
Morton are most practical. Some had worked for the Romans. In regard they are to be taken seriously - are tempered considerably for the youths
to the vexing problem of enclosure, Wolsey was to enact a law along who must either serve the diners or stand by in silence and who must eat
~ saying - "not even you" - Morton
the lines of Hythlodaeus' p r o p o ~ a l .By what is handed them from the table (143). Utopian scholars labor nearly
acknowledges that Hythlodaeus is unconventional ; by saying - "my dear three years to master Greek (181). Re-dawn lectures, games that inculcate
Raphael" - he renders him an affection not granted to others in the scene virtue, compulsory military training which includes swimming under arms,
(71-73). Morton admires Hythlodaeus' personality, but reserves the right resmctions on travel etc., all these regulations and the regimentation
to evaluate critically his advice. The text shows the statesman eager to make Utopia so different from a Platonic Garden of Adonis that only one
hear more from Raphael whereas, the gloss points out, he checked the student m my experience has ever responded in the affirmative to the
lawyer for talkativeness (.71). Since Morton intends to hear Raphael again question : "Would you, if possible, want to live in Utopia ? " Her
the next day, it seems clear that he is not amused by him (71). reason ? The streets are safe. The objection to Hythlodaeus on the gcound
In regard to the Morton episode, Sylvester, who does not express the that he and his island are a fiction has already been answered. More's choice
above position, convicts Hythlodaeus of a kind of blindness - Hythlodaeus of the imaginary and dramatic dialogue frees him from the dull abstractions
argues that Europeans would not accept his counsel; yet Morton approves of the philosopher and the factual restrictions of the historian. Findy, to
his plan for the treatment of criminals and is ready t o implement it with discredit Hythlodaeus, the detached philosopher, simply because More
due modification (81). This, by the way, seems to be the proper response himself chose the active life of service appears to be a non sequitur. In the
to Hythlodaeus. One hesitates to take issue with a person of Sylvester's concluding pages of this article, Hythlodaeus' isolation and detachment will
stature so steeped in More. One can only say that More, in h i desire to be viewed in a positive Lght.
praise Morton, puts himself in a difficult position. Not only does he A final point must be made in regard to Sylvester's a r t i ~ l e .He ~
contrast the practical Morton to the idealistic Hythlodaeus, but he also observes that in the debate Hythlodaeus draws farther and farther from the
places this opponent to Richard 111 as a foil to the tyrannical French and real world - fust, there is the historical reality of Morton's court ; next,
imaginary kings. If Morton closed his mind to Hythlodaeus' sound and the hypothetical court of the French king ; third, the totally imaginary
humane counsel, he would hardly be the type of leader admired by More. court. It is possible that the second and third episodes are more remote
Furthermore, ~ ~ t h l o d a e knows
us that the evils for which he had offered than the fust because Wolsey and Henry VIII passed laws similar to those
a cure to the Chancellor of Henry VII s d remain ;in Henry VIII's reign Hythlodaeus recommended to Morton. But Henry could also be accused
they are, if anything, more critical.3 of having the warlike spirit of the French king, and Cardinal Morton did
Another major objection can be raised against Berger and Johnson, endorse financial policies like those of the imaginary king's councillors?
who seem influenced less by More's milieu than by the modem psychology In these instances, distance not only lends protection, it also keeps
of a Norman Brown and by commentators on utopian literature like Morton's image untarnished.
Northrop Frye and Lewis Mumford. Berger and Johnson treat Raphael as The ultimate isolation, of course, is the island itself which enshrines
a fantasy-maker captivated by the pleasure-principle, one who proposes Hythhheus' "ideals and virtues, but i t also- and he himself is completely
illusion not ideals. Utopia is a "Platonic Garden of Adonis a place without unaware of this - hints at the defects in his thinking and at the m r a l
pain where everyone learns everything the short smooth way."4 Raphael flaws in his character. Utopia is made like all famous creations, in the image
offers "an emasculated, soft, an unreal paradise of unearned pleasures... and Iilieness of its creator. If we accept the country, we accept its f ~ u n d e r . " ~
Utopia (Nowhere) is negative, unreal, because her citizens are a fiction and
I. Johnson,pp.10-11.
1. Berger, p. 6 4 :Johnson, p. 57. 2. R.S. Sylvester, "SI HYTHLODAEO CREDIMUS : Vision and Revision in
2. See 6 Henry VIll (I 514) in WOT Royd PtoclmMtiom, ed. by P. Hugha and Thomu More's Utopi~."Sounding, 51 (1969). 272-89.
J. krkin, 3 vols.(New Haven, 1964), 1, 122-23. Note also Surtz's comments on 6617. ,
3. See Surtz's comments on 58/19.
3. See Surtz's comments on 60/10. 4. Sykeater, p. 286.
4. Berger, p. 68. i
38 ROBERT COOGAN NVNC WVO VT VOLO 39

,Here Sylvester sounds like Hythlodaeus. One of Raphael's faults is what reconciliation provides for the best state of the commonwealth ? A t
that he overwhelms by a rush of feeling and prevents dialogue by the what point has injustice become so rampant, that there is a need - i n
finality of his judgments. It seems that the reader should respond to Sylvester's words - for a "total demolition job" on society ?
Raphael as do persona-More, Morton, and Bud&. Bud6 believes in RICHARD AND RAPHAEL
~ G h l o d a e u sto &e extent that he wants the three divine principles of It will be useful now t o examine More's method of characterization
Utopian l e d a t i o n fixed in the minds of all mortals (11). and t o comment on certain dimensions of ~ ~ t h l o d a e u
ins order t o show
E. SURTZ'S VIA MEDIA how he stands for the Renaissance and how he would be admired by More.
In the Yale Utopia, Surtz presents a more moderate view than the For his greatest creations, Richard I11 and Hythlodaeus, he employed the
Yale triumvirate and places great stress on the dramatic aspects of the same method, namely, delineate immediately the broad outline of the
Utopia As a result, he says, "it is no more possible t o say that the words character, employ contrast, and emphasize a dominant trait, Richard
which More puts into his own mouth represent his genuine sentiments and Hythlodaeus both appear in a setting where dissension is evident : i n
than it is t o hold him accountable for words which he puts on Hythlodaeus' a death-bed oration King Edward IV pleads for national unity ; on a
lips" (cxxxvi). In The Praise of Wisdom, in The Raise of Pfeusum, and in commission t o Flanders More seeks t o solve weighty matters and t o gain
the Commentary t o the Yale Utopia, Surtz accumulates biographical and international harmony. ~ e s i d eEdward - "of visage louely, of bodye
historical considerations that delineate More's view on all the major issues myghtie, stronge and cleane made"1 - the noble king loved by his people,
in the Utopia and thus reveals how More stands in relation to Hythlodaeus. More places his youngest brother,
Sura's introduction t o the Yale Utopia makes a literary evaluation little of stature, ill fetured of limrnes, croke backed, his left shoulder
that emphasizes the advantage of dramatic objectivity ; i.e., there is "the much higher then his right, hard fauoured of visage... He was mali-
tension between the author's apparent lack of personal emotion and his cious, wrathfull, enuious, and from afore his birth, euer frowarde. (7)
-
very r e d feelinp;, which, however, he merelv, implies and the reader must
inf&" (cxxxvi): He describes H thlodaeus' twofold function as follows :
The picture of Richard which More draws with seven hundred words a t
the begining of the history has lasted for eenturies. More, who contemned
As a fascinating character wio holds readwa spellbound with ptnonal auguries and divination, cleverly uses the'fact that Richard could not be
anecdote and amazing travelogue, he draws all the parts together and delivered of his mother "vncutte" :
unifies the whole. As an individual who % somewhat eccentxic, Hee came into the worlde with the feete forwarde, as menne bee
visionary, and uncompromising, he strongly defends views contrary bane outwarde,and (as the fame runneth) also not vntothed, whither
to current opinion in order to make his readers inquire and think.This menne of hatred raporte aboue the trouthe, or elles that nature
radical humanist is one of More's greatest wiurnphs. (cxlii) chaunged her course in hys beghinge, whiche in the course of his
Thus, Surtz would not accept the total rejectmn of Hythlodaeus. He feels lyfe many thinges vnnaturallye committed (7).
that More prevents us from completely sympathizing or identifying with Hard upon this unique description of Richard's birth, More presents
Hythlodaeus in two ways. First, persona-More offers sound and enduring the dominant a a i t of his character, the dissimulation which is the main
arguments against compulsive communism and has the parting words guideline in the interpretation of the history. More speaks of Richard as
that object t o some Utopian institutions (245). Secondly, since More "not letting t o kisse whome hee thoughte t o kyll... Frende and foo was
makes Hythlodaeus overstate his case, Surtz thinks that the reader would muche what indifferent." (8) More's parting stroke in the brief initial
hesitate t o accept parts of his message. Although Hythlodaeus is intelligent portrait applies the mark of Cain t o Richard : "Somme wise menne also
and engaging, he is also melodramatic ; and, consequently, one cannot weene, that his drifte c o u e r t l ~c o n u a ~ d e lacked
, not in helping furth his
take his position as "fully normative."l This interpretation seems t o be brother of Clarence t o his death." (8)
the soundest. More's mariner solves no problems, rather he raises funda- More gains much by stressing the dissimulation of Richard at the
mental and often unanswerable questions.2 For example, does the active very beginning of the work. Richard's words and deeds can become
life surpass the contemplative ? Is public better than private ownership ? In powerfully ironic. For example, when racke en bury refuses t o murder
light of the conflicting rights of the individual, the family, and the state, the royal children, Richard says, "Ah whome shall a man trust ? " (83).
Richard swears that he will not dine until Hastings has died - Hasting,
1. For a confinnation of Surtz's interpretation and an interesting treatment of therefore, got a very short shrift, for the king must keep his word (49)
Hythlodaeus' sentence structures, eee the review of the Yak Utopia by Ch~i?nceH.
Miller, English Longuuge Notes, 3 (1966), 30349. 1 1. The Yale Edition of the Complete Worb of St. Thomas More, vol. 2, me
k
2. For two studies which approach the Utopia from different viewpoints and which e Histoy of King R i c W In, ed. by R.S. Sylvester (New Haven, 1963), p. 4. The
arrive at this interpretation,see David M. Bevington, "The Dialogue in Utopia : Two Sides r pages references in the next two paragraphs are to this edition.
to the Question," Sfudies m Philology, LVII1 (1961), 496-509. C. S. Lewis, English
Literamre in the Sixteenth Cenmry (Oxford, 1954). 167-171.
5-
I
40 ROBERT COOGAN NVNC VlVO VT V O M 41
Before sending the royal children to the Tower, from which "they never As Petrarch at the dawn of the Italian Renaissance proposed the ideal of
came abroad", Richard kisses them. (42) More forces the reader to the unattached man of letters, More too, in the morning of the Northern
participate in this "green world", to interpret every word and deed of the Renaissance, creates the freedom-loving Hythlodaeus. Both replace clerical
tyrant who makes illusion the order of reality for his kingdom. By so doing, and courtly ideals by the Ciceronian motto of the unattached philosopher -
More forces the reader t o see the need for a just king and for a just uiuo u t uolo.1 In the debates of the civic humanists, the pendulum gradually
world where things are what they appear to be. swung from Petrarch's excessive independence to Palmieri's praise of the
In the introduction to the Utopia, More is as eager to emphasize active life.2 Yet Pico and Erasmus, the humanists most admired by More,
Hythlodaeus' indepengence as he was to reveal Richard's dissimulation. both lived lives of almost Petrarchan detachment. It is not necessarv to
As in the History, More keeps adding depth and color t o the initial lines linger on Erasmus' love of the philosopher's independence since he is one
of the portrait which do not change. The moderate humanists - Tunstd, of history's exemplars of this way of life. In the Commentary to the Utopia,
Giles, and More - are comparable to Richard's brothers and King Edward Surtz points out that Erasmus uses the motto in De contemptu mundi. In
in that they provide the basic contrast with the hero. Tunstd and More the chapter immediately following the praise of the solitary life, Erasmus
strive to resolve a dispute between Henry VlII and the future Charles V. applies to the monastic life Cicero's definition of liberty - potestas v i m -
Because ofadisagreement, negotiations cease: and the thirtyeight-year-old di u t velis.3 Pico, that model lay Christian, loved liberty above d l
More, anxious to return to his family, has reservations about the advantages thin@ ; the central notion of the Oration on the Dignity of Man -- one
of service to the king. manifesto of the Renaissance - is that man is free to determine his destiny.
After the moderate humanists in service have been presented, More Pico, More says following the Vita Pici, loved liberty above all and refused
swiftly delineates Hythlodaeus and emphasizes his independence. The to serve in church or in court. Three years before his death, he gave away
twenty-nine-year-old Giles is so enthusiastic when he f m t speaks of his wealth in order t o gain greater peace through detachment. According
Hythlodaeus that he prevents More from returning a greeting (49) to Savonarola, the world had seen nothing like Pico for the last 800 years
The independent voyager, Giles says, is somewhat like the adventurer (EW, I, 9) Giles makes the same claim for Hythlodaeus (21). More's
Ulysses and most like the philosopher Plato. He is not at all like the early poetry on Fortune expresses a similar admiration of the philosopher's
ill-fated seaman Palinurus (49). He is autonomous enough t o have devoted detachment. It is the philosophers like Socrates, Byas, and Democritus
himself "unreservedly t o philosophy" (51). When he was young, he left whom Fortuna cannot defeat. Democritus was so eager t o study and to
his pammony to his brothers so that he might be free to travel. While be hee from the burdens of riches that he gave his patrimony to his
voyaging under Vespucci, he further demonstrated his desire for freedom countr men.4
when he wrested by force (extorsit) the permission to stay at the farthest TX; youthful More .hexished this ideal for himself. His letter t o Colet
point of the last voyage -- "and so he was left behind that he might have (October 1504), seems to echo Petrarch's own attitude toward the joys of
his way" (51).The departure from the farthest point stresses his love of rural solitude and toward the horrors of the city.s Writing t o John Holt,
liberty. Giles notes the two sayings ever on the lips of Hythlodaeus : "He the youth of twenty-three applies t o himself the unattached philosopher's
who has no grave is covered by the sky" and "From all places it is the motto :
same distance to heaven." (51) DbO gracia, satis valemu atque (quod pauci de se fateri possunt)
VlVO VT VOLO ita viuimua vt volumu.6
When More was in service, he was uneasy under its restraints ;when
Equally appropriate would be the motto, "uiuo ut uolo" (56). he res@ed the chancellorship, he relished the return of his freedom. From
Hythlodaeus' independence provokes the reader as much as Richard's these instances, it is evident that More regarded highly the independent
dissimulation dws. Because his allegiance is to justice, he can battle every philosopher's way of life.
person in Christendom - pope, abbot, theologian, logician, king, lord,
warrior, courtier, lawyer, and even the humanist who recommends service 1. Petrarch, De vita solitaria, ed. Antonio Al-ura (Naples, 1943), p. 47.
t o the kim. He reduces to absurditv so manv "normal" institutions - the 2. See Hans Baron, "Ciaro and the Roman Civic Spirit," Bttlletin of the John
English economic system, the chivilric and ;end codes, the papacy and Ryhndc Librw, XXIl (1938). 72-97.
religious orders, the prevailing systems of education and law -- that one 3. Erasmus, "De contemptu mundi," in Opem omnia.. studio et opem Jmnnis
must constantly ask : does a veil of deceit hide the decay beneath civi- M,10volr. (Leyden, 1703-06), V, 1252.
lization ? Is Christian Europe a "green world" ? 4. For a treatment of Byas and Democritus, see my article, "Petrarchand Thomas
More," No.21 (l969), Moream, pp. 20-21.
Although More did not choose for himself the way of life of the 5. De vitn solitaria, Bock 1, Tractate ii ;Correspondence, p. 7.
independent philosopher, it is evident that he had a high regard for it. 6. Comspmdence, p. 3. Selected Lerrers, p. 2 : 'Thanks be to God, I am feeling
-
quite weU ;and - something few peopb can say for themselves I am living my Efe just
as I desire."
42 ROBERT COOCAN NVNC WVO V T VOLO 43
Hythlodaeus' intense concern with religion is characteristic of the
In addition to placing Hythlodaeus in this distinguished group, More
Northern Renaissance. This concern appears in his concept of justice and,
numbered him among the followers of Plato. Besides comparing especially, in the ultimate source of his values - the Gospel. He never
Hythlodaeus' travels with the journeys of Plato, Giles adds that
commends European justice ; he often speaks of it ironically or sar-
Hythlodaeus' favorite author is Plato (87). At the conclusion of the dialogue
castically. For the sake of brevity, only representative passages will be
and in the exordium, Hythlodaeus has recourse to the authority of Plato. cited. English laws go beyond justice in their rigidity (61). Capital
He finds the institutions of Plato's ideal state superior to Europe's (101).
punishment for theft is vain as well as iniquitous (71). The imaginary
He endorses Plato's refusal t o make laws for any nation which will not
king's laws which impose fines for the transgression of motheaten edicts
legislate an equal sharfng of all goods (105).
By depicting Hythlodaeus as a philosopher and admirer of Plato, are likewise a masque of justice (93). Compared to the laws o f t h e
Polylerites, E n g l ~ ~justice
h deserves but contempt (81). Raphael's final
More reflects the Platonic interest of his own circle as well as the Platonic
verdict is that Europe's justice, like that of Thrasymachus, is a conspiracy
revival of the Florentine Academy. Petrarch is partially responsible for of the rich and the strong against the poor and the weak.
the origin of this revival, for he possessed precious manuscripts of some
of Plato's dialogues and he was one of the first modems to make Plato
a
Hythlodaeus gives clue to his -concept of justice when he demands
that a comparison be made between European justice and Utopian fairness
the foremost puosopher. (aequitac) (239). In Aristotle's Ethics, equity is justice beyond positive
Thus, it seems that More wants the reader t o admire his independent
law ( 1137b5-1137b30). As More 'wrote the Utopia, Wokey was making
philosopher. One does not reject him because of this idealism that detach-
m'jor innovations in the En&h judicial system which were based on the
ment nurtures. After all, there must be The Education of the Christim
principle of equity. Through the Court of Chancery, he would execute
Rince to balance Machiavelli's The Rince ; someone must set Utopia
justice in a way that would temper the rigors of common law. More
against England with its maneating sheep and heavily laden gallows-trees.
approved of Wolsey's policy in this respect and later became a judge in a
PETRARCAS CONTRIBrnON
court of equity, the Court of Requests. Ideally, courts of equity would pass
In order to look upon Hythlodaeus in the light of R e n h a n c e hu- judgment in cases where positive law through changing times or unique
manism, it will be useful to touch on Petrarch's contribution in this respect. circumstances ran counter either to right reason or to the law of God. For
Petrarch travelled extensively to discover such texts as the Pro Archia and these very reasons, H~thlodaeusobjects t o England's penal code. F i s t , it
the Latin translation of the Phaedo. He would edit, copy, and disseminate is unreasonable : it encourages rather than discourages murder. Equity has
them. In the classics, he found truths and exemplars of virtue t o com- no meaning (73-75). Surtz's comments on these harsh Manlian laws is
plement those in the Christian tradition. Because he felt that Plato was pertinent - Erasmus stated that those who steal salad should not die with
closer to Christianity and more conducive to virtue than Aristotle, he murderers and that the Manlian laws are opposed to equity and humanity
disparaged the scholastics, the dialecticians, and the Averroists, thus (341). Secondly, the penal code neither conforms to the stem Mosaic law
bringing about a major intellectual upheaval. nor to the law of mercy (73-75).
In some respects, Hythlodaeus represents this intellectual tradition If any thing, Hythlodaeus leans too strongly to the absolute sovereignty
as it appeared in the b h Renaissance. His travels - a necessary com- of divine law and tends, like Luther in 1515,2 to disparage human law.
plement to formal study - are used t o disseminate Christianity as well as Thus. on the eve of the Reformation, Hythlodaeus proposes equity as a
the New Learning. He provides the Utopians with a knowledge of Greek principle that contrasts to common~law- a development in
and a collection of Greek texts. His mentioning the problem caused by early sixteenth-century England - and he calls
faulty readings and his specific reference to the Adine text of Sophocles UTOPIA A N D WOLSEY.
reflect Christian humanism's interest in textual matters. Since his travels
cardinal Wolsey would certainly be pleased with Hythlodaeus'
were a search for wise institutions and since he commends the moral bent
counsels on enclosures and on equity - two issues prominent in the mind
in Utopian education, Hythlodaeus clearly endorses the voluntarism that
of England's new Lord Chancellor (Dec. 1515). Swiss mercenaries with
marks C h r i s t . humanism from Petrarch to More. Like Petrarch, he has
whom his emissary Pace was negotiating in 1516 did act like the Zapoletans.
no use for scholastic subtlety, especially as taught in the Small L0gicab.l
In Book I, the humorous recital of the spat between the toady and the 1. See Stuart E. Rall, "The Development of Equity in Tudor England," American
friar - who was a theologian - obviously satirizes a sterile scholasticism. Journal oflegul History, 8 (1964), 1-19.
2. See F. Edward Cranz, "An Essay on the Development of Luther's Thought on
1. For More's antipathy towards decadent scholasticism, see Edward Surtz, Justice, Law, and Society," tkrrvmd ?7teobgical Studies, 19 (1959). pp. 3@71.
me h i s e of Reasurn (Cambridge. 1957), p. 105.
44 ROBERT COOCAN NVNC V l v o VT VOLO 45
It is possible that More's political rise and the publication of the Utopia In his last reference to Christ. Hythlodaeus insists that the wisdom o f
ue not just a coincidence. Little has been made of More's letter (Jan, Christ urges men to adopt Utopian standards. This particular allusion
1517) telling a member of Court that he had thought of dedicating the should be viewed in conjunction with the others. Hythlodaeus f i t men-
Utopio t o Wolsey. There is no unanimity among biographers as to the date tions Christ at the climax of the debate. He next uses his name to endorse
of More's entry into royal service. He received Court payment which was the Utopians' cardinal institution, communism. Although each of these
made retroactive to 1516. When More was writing Book I in February of instances has a special pertinency, Hythlodaeus reserves his concluding
1516, he told Erasmus that he refused a pension. On February 17,1516, appeal to Christ for the most crucial moment in the intense peroration. I f
Ammonio w r g e t o Erasmus that on his return f o m Flanders More was one reads the book with Erasmus' comment in mind - More's Utopia
&st on line to wish good morning to the chancel1or.l Thus it seems that
More returned to E n g h d determined to serve. His letter t o 'Erasmus
'
discloses the causes of evil in the commonwealth - then, this final mention
of Christ stands at the very climax of More's masterpiece. The moment
(c. 20 Sept. 1516) makes it clear that he wanted his book to satisfy, after calling upon the authority of Christ for the final time, Hythlodaeus
not only humanists, but also ~oliticians,and whom more than the newly names the monster that is the ultimate source of evil in European com-
appointed Lord Chancellor ? The author would be a man well worth having monwealths :
in the Council ; he had thought deeply not only on domestic and foreign Nor does it occur to me to doubt that a man's regard f w his own
affairs but also on the councilor's role - its dangers, its need for accom- interests or the authority of Christ our Savior - who in I% d d o m
modation, its m o n e t q and humanitarian rewards. could not fail to know what was best and who in His goodness would
T o return now t o the Erasmian idealist, Hythlodaeus. By relying so not fail to counsel what He knew to be best - would long ago have
strongly on divine law, Hythlodaeus shows that in the second decade of brought the whole world to adopt the laws of the Utopian common-
the sixteenthcentury he is the man of the hour - the reformer. The sense wealth, had not one single monster, the chief and progenitor of all
of urgency which surrounds the exordium and the peroration gives his %
plagues, shivcn against it -- I mean Ride (243).
words a prophet's intensity. His three references to Christ reveal this To a Christendom where pride has triumphed, Hythlodaeus - speaker of
aspect of his character. As he concludes the debate on councilorship and nonsense - preaches foolishness.
proclaims the superiority of Utopian practices, Hythlodaeus states that
the message of Christ is an absolute standard which must not be accom- 1. Opua EpQtolmum Des. Erasmi Roterodami, ed. P.S. Allen et of., 12 wls.
modated to the perverse morals of men (101). This is the only place in (Oxford, 1906-58), 11, 483.
U t o p i ~where More speaks directly of dissimulation. My previous refer-
ences to Richard JW show what he thought of dissimulation at the time lona College, New Rochelle Robert COOGAN, C. F. C.
he composed Utopia. Sharing his creator's hatred of dissembling, Hythlo-
daeus refuses to adapt the message of Christ to Europe's unchristian
standards. Of all the points that he makes during the s e ~ i o inn the garden,
REVIEWS OF UTOPlA
this one is the strongest. The doctrines of Christ should be preached from
the housetops (101). Metaphor and irony enforce his argument. Metaphor H .W. Donner , Studia NeapkLealagica, XXVII. 1965.
through 3 s evokingthe Lesbian rule of soft lead. Irony as he lays bare the "Nobody h a s w r i t t e n of t h e UZoph w i t h more l e a r n i n g
absurdity of accommodating the Gospel's message by saying that it allows and i n s i g h t t h a n F a t h e r S u r t z . His e d i t i o n of t h e Yale
men to be "bad in greater comfort." (101) Sdeoted Wokhd must be warmly welcomed. F a m i l i a r i t y , howe-
When ~ ~ t h l o d a ereports
us the advent of Christianity among Utopians, v e r , i n t h e c a s e of More,so f a r from b r e e d i n g contempt, in-
he notes that they had been impressed by the communism of Christ's v a r i a b l y l e a d s t o enthusiasm, and t h e v e r y e x c e l l e n t
disciples. Since he sees Utopian communism as the most efficacious remedy I n t r o d u c t i o n . . . does n o t go f r e e from a s u s p i c i o n of over-
for European &it is very significant that he refers to Christ at this point enthusiasm. The a n a l y s i s of t h e l i t e r a r y form i s f u l l of
(219). The truest followers of Christ, he holds, still practice communism new o b s e r v a t i o n s and could h a r d l y b e b e t t e r e d ... In spite
(219). In a word, he relies so heavily on the law of Christ that he uses it of j e r k s and j o l t s t h e t r a n s l a t i o n i s v e r y r e a d a b l e , and
t h e wordiness i s , i n a s e n s e , n o t un-Morean."
t o recommend the most crucial and controversial issue in his program
of reform - communism. Erasmus and Colet lean to this view. *
1. See Surb's comments on 54/14.
2. Sa Surtz's comments on 8/25-26 and 21815-6
46
Chicago, March 26, 1971
Dear AbbC Marchadour,
4

It is indeed pleasing to learn that the Autumn 1971 issue of


Moream Quarterly will be a Festschrift in honor of Rev. Edward
L. Surtz, S. J.
It was my privilege and pleasure to take two graduate courses
at Loyola U n ~ ~ n i tofy Chicago from Father S u r e : English 443,
St. Thomas More and Utopian Literature, 1st sem. 195556 ;and En@
444. Spenser, 2nd sem. 195556. My dissertation on Spenser was orig-
inally suggested by two term papers written in the Spenser course
following specific assignments by Father Surtz : Report on Scholarship
of Tke Shephemdes Calender and Literary Analysis of Colin C h t s
Come Home Agmne.
Out of the papers grew the dissertation "An Interpretation of
Spenser's Colin C h t s Come Home Aguine" (1960), written under the
direction of Father S u m . Out of the dissertation grew two articles
and a book :
"Spenser's Colin Clout : The Poem and the Book," Popers of the
BibliogruphicalSociety ofAmerica, LVI (4th quarter, 1962), 397-413.
"The Figures of Rhetoric in Spenser's Colin d o u t , " kblications
of the Modem Language Association of America, LXXIX (June, 1964),
206-218. (Reprinted in Rhetorical ~ n d y s e sof Litermy Works, ed.
Edward P. J. Corbett ;New York : Oxford UnN. Press, 1968, pp.
147-185, and incorporated, with slight changes, as Chapter 2 of
the book.)
An Interpretation of Edmund Spenser's Colin Clout (Cork, Ireland :
Cork UnN. Press, 1969 ;Notre Dame, Indiana : UnN. of Notre Dame
Press, 1969).
Less directly associated with my work under Father Surtz but
springing from studies in rhetorical modes of the past and present,
begun when I was a student of his, is another article, "Teaching the Rhetor-
ical Approach to the Poem," in Rhetoric : Tkeories for ~pplication,e d
Robert M. GorreU. National Council of Teachers of English (Champaign,
IU., 1967),pp. 82-89.
May 1 add that 1 count it a particular blessing, ~rivilegeand pleasure
to have known Father S u m , f m t as a student and later as a friend and
to glow faintly in the reflected light which his brilliant critical work,
especially on St. Thomas More's Utopia, has cast !
Very sincerely yours,

Sam MEYER
(Chairman, Language Arts Department,
Morton College, Cicero, lllinois)

You might also like