You are on page 1of 4

Phenomenology,

Meaning, and
Metaphor
Mads Gram Henriksen and
Josef Parnas

Keywords: schizophrenia, psychosis, auditory verbal AVHs. We are inclined to believe that AVHs are
hallucinations, pathogenesis, and etiology etiologically and pathogenetically heterogeneous
phenomena (Ey 1973).
By contrast, the alternative account offered by

T
he first commentary that we discuss is Thomas and Longden concerns only the etiology
the quite critical one by Thomas and Long- of AVHs (or ‘voices’ as they prefer). What they
den (2015). The pertinent question is if the offer is a strong environmental hypothesis of the
authors’ criticism hits the mark or if it is simply causation of AVHs, conceptualizing ‘voices’ as dis-
off the mark? We will let the reader decide. In the sociative mental phenomena resulting from “psy-
following, we address some of the most important chological distress and social adversity” (Thomas
problems in their commentary. and Longden 2015, 189). In other words, they
First, Thomas and Longden seem to conflate the propose that if you hear ‘voices,’ then it is because
concept of pathogenesis (referring to the develop- something unbearable or traumatic has happened
ment of a disorder or a symptom) with that of to you in your past. We understand this account
etiology (referring to the cause[s] of the disorder or as a standard type of psychological reductionism,
a symptom). We have presented a phenomenologi- although far less sophisticated than in contem-
cal account of the pathogenesis of some auditory porary psychoanalysis (a psychoanalytic account
verbal hallucinations (AVHs) in schizophrenia also offers some structural considerations, e.g.,
(Henriksen et al. 2015)—an account based on by referring to ‘psychological organization’). Ad-
empirical data derived from in-depth interviews ditionally, it seems that Thomas and Longden are
with numerous patients with schizophrenia (from strongly influenced by the ideas prevalent in voice
which the prototypical vignettes were drawn) and hearing networks. Thus, they readily reject both
on theoretical–philosophical reflections. In short, the very concepts of schizophrenia and of AVHs,
we describe the temporal and structural vicis- making their criticism even more impenetrable.
situdes in a process in which thoughts may come They claim a universally valid etiological account
to be experienced as alien voices, and we draw of ‘voices,’ whereas we presented a pathogenetic
attention to certain alterations of the forms of account of some AVHs in schizophrenia.
self-awareness that seem to allow AVHs to mani- Second, Thomas and Longden refer to the
fest themselves in schizophrenia. We make abso- ‘robust association’ between trauma (especially
lutely no claims regarding the possible etiology of during childhood) and AVHs (and partly schizo-

© 2016 by The Johns Hopkins University Press


194  ■  PPP / Vol. 22, No. 3 / September 2015

phrenia) to empirically support their account. way of finding unity and meaningful coherences is
We fully agree that childhood trauma may be a of course different from that proposed by Thomas
risk factor for AVHs and schizophrenia; however, and Longden, which seems to prescribe the mean-
it must be noted that this evidence stems from ing of psychotic experiences by a universal law-like
retrospective studies using retrospective reports. necessity: something unbearable happened to you
Moreover, inference of causality from such studies once and this is why you hear alien voices today.
is methodologically risky—association does not Finally, we need, however briefly, to address a
equal causation. A simple observation may help: rather odd claim by Thomas and Longden, namely
although some patients with schizophrenia, who that our account is in “conflict with the spirit of
experience AVHs, have been exposed to child- the work of Merleau-Ponty and Heidegger” (p.
hood adversity, trauma, or neglect, other patients 187). This vague reference to a “spirit” is unfor-
with schizophrenia, presenting similar symptoms, tunately a quite generalizing and formless claim.
have not been exposed to anything of that kind. Seemingly, it has something to do with the way
Moreover, there are also other well-known risk we analyzed the patients’ experiences, which, ac-
factors, which Thomas and Longden fail to men- cording to Thomas and Longden, is divorced from
tion, including a family history of schizophrenia the contexts of the patients’ life histories, which,
(the strongest factor), prenatal exposure, perinatal on their account, is the only source of meaning.
complications, urban birth or residence, migrant We do not accept their monopoly on the meaning
status, and adolescent cannabis use (e.g., Clarke of psychotic experiences or their reductive, etio-
et al. 2012; Gejman et al. 2011). In our view, the logical account of AVHs. Moreover, Thomas and
authors’ exclusive focus on trauma as the sole Longden find it significant that we make no refer-
cause of AVHs is far too simplistic and overlooks ence to Heidegger’s notion of being-in-the-world.
the variety of formative factors in the vulnerability However, they have overlooked that we have, in
to schizophrenia. fact, elsewhere explicitly discussed Heidegger’s
The third problem concerns two interrelated notion of being-in-the-world and shown how it
issues, namely the notion of meaning and the use can be fruitfully applied to grasp basic subjective
of phenomenology. According to Thomas and experiences in schizophrenia (Henriksen et al.
Longden (2015), our account is confronted with 2010). Somewhat ironically, the ‘faithful’ read-
a serious problem—as they put it, “[The] problem ings of Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty, offered
with using phenomenology this way is that it dis- by Thomas and Longden, are to some extent at
regards the possible meanings of the experiences odds with the ideas presented in these works.
of psychosis” (p. 188). We beg to differ. We have For example, Heidegger (2007) did not ‘set out a
elsewhere argued at length that applying such a general ontology,’ but struggled to uncover time as
phenomenological approach may enable us to un- the meaning of Being (Sinn von Sein). When they
derstand psychotic symptoms in schizophrenia that argue that Heidegger’s determination of Dasein
traditionally have been considered incomprehen- as history “opens up the possibility of thinking
sible or bizarre (e.g., Henriksen 2013; Henriksen about human lives in narrative terms … as having
and Parnas 2014; Parnas and Henriksen 2013). In a beginning, a middle and an end” (Thomas and
this context, understanding means a pathogenetic Longden 2015, 188), they apparently fail to realize
or developmental reconstruction of the psychotic that Heidegger’s determination is ontological, not
phenomena that enables the patient’s experiences ontic in nature (Heidegger 2007).
to appear less enigmatic, and we suggest that The second commentary by Allison-Bolger
this can be achieved by eliciting the generative (2015) is quite interesting, touching on many cen-
disorder that prefigures and constrains the range tral questions, not only relevant to our account,
of symptoms that may emerge. Such reconstruc- but broadly to the disciplines of psychiatry, psy-
tion, rather than hindering, may in fact facilitate chology, and anthropology, namely, how should
a more individual and biographically coherent we interpret the statements of our patients? She
self-understanding on the part of the patient. This argues that it “is an established opinion in psy-
Henriksen and Parnas / Phenomenology, Meaning, and Metaphor  ■ 195

chopathology that patients mean what they say audible thoughts (item 1.7) is present, it is not
literally” (p. 183), and that we endorse this posi- enough that the patient simply affirms the inter-
tion, when we, in her phrasing, claim, “that we viewer’s question; the patient must herself come up
should not understand their complaints as ‘merely with concrete examples of such experiences, and
metaphorical’” (p. 183). According to Allison- only upon further questioning, clarifying, through
Bolger, our account rests on this assumption. She active dialogue, what she means with her examples
accentuates her point, claiming that we say that the and the nature of these experiences, the interviewer
patient’s statements “should not be understood as may score the relevant item as present if it fulfills
metaphors” (p. 183, our italics), and she describes the item definition (Nordgaard et al. 2013).
our interpretation of the patients’ remarks as a
‘literal reading.’ On her account, we therefore risk Acknowledgements
misunderstanding what the patient intended to say.
There are several ways of responding to these Funding: M.G.H. is funded by the Carlsberg
comments. First, her argument seems to be a straw Foundation (#2012010195).
man. We also deplore a prevalent tendency among
References
psychiatrists not to pay sufficient attention to the
issues of expression and meaning. At no point Allison-Bolger, V. Y. 2015. Finding out what the speaker
is saying before explaining why he says it. Philoso-
do we claim that patients’ statements should be
phy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 22, no. 3 :183–6.
understood literally and not metaphorically. When Blondel, C. 1914. La Conscience morbide. Essai de
we suggest that the complaint of ‘living in the head’ psychopathologie générale. Paris: Alcan.
should not be understood ‘merely metaphorically,’ Clarke, M. C., I. Kelleher, M. Clancy, and M. Can-
our phrase does certainly not rule out the possibil- non. 2012. Predicting risk and the emergence of
ity of also understanding it metaphorically and, schizophrenia. Psychiatric Clinics of North America
more generally, that metaphor always conveys 35:585–612.
Ey, E. 1973. Traité des hallucinations. Paris: Masson.
certain lived aspects of the pre-linguistic experi-
Gejman, P. V., A, R. Sanders, and K. S. Kendler. 2011.
ence. Therefore, we do imply that this particular Genetics of schizophrenia: New findings and chal-
complaint might by meant in a more literal sense lenges. Annual Review of Genomics and Human
than most of us would be inclined to expect and Genetics 12:121–44.
that this is something to be aware of when encoun- Heidegger, M. 2007. Being and time. Oxford: Blackwell.
tering this complaint. In brief, Allison-Bolger’s Henriksen, M. G. 2013. On incomprehensibility in
arguments for attributing to us an exclusively schizophrenia. Phenomenology and the Cognitive
Sciences 12:105–29.
‘literal’ approach are not textually justified and
Henriksen, M. G., and J. Parnas. 2014. Self-disorders
she seems to be attacking a straw man. and schizophrenia: A phenomenological reappraisal
Second, we agree with Allison-Bolger that “we of poor insight and noncompliance. Schizophrenia
don’t only speak either literally or metaphorically” Bulletin 40:542–7.
(p. 184), and with her idea that we should always Henriksen, M. G., A. Raballo, and J. Parnas. 2015.
try to understand what a patient means with a The pathogenesis of auditory verbal hallucinations
given statement before explaining it or, alterna- in schizophrenia: A clinical phenomenological ac-
tively, identifying it as a certain type of complaint count. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 22,
no. 3:165–81.
(e.g., delusions or hallucinations). A metaphor
Henriksen, M. G., B. Skodlar, L. A. Sass, and J. Parnas.
is of course not just a metaphor and the role of 2010. Autism and perplexity: A qualitative and
metaphor in language, understanding, and, not theoretical study of basic subjective experiences in
least, psychopathology has always been a vener- schizophrenia. Psychopathology 43:357–68.
able topic for psychiatric phenomenology (Blondel Nordgaard J, L. A. Sass, and J. Parnas. 2013. The
1914). In fact, this consideration is a quintessential psychiatric interview: Validity, structure, and subjec-
aspect of the EASE interview (Parnas et al. 2005). tivity. European Archives of Psychiatry and Clinical
Neuroscience 263:353–64.
To examine if, say, loss of thought ipseity (item
Parnas, J., and M. G. Henriksen. 2013. Subjectivity and
1.2), spatialization of experience (item 1.8) or schizophrenia: Another look at incomprehensibil-
196  ■  PPP / Vol. 22, No. 3 / September 2015

ity and treatment nonadherence. Psychopathology Thomas, P., and E. Longden. 2015. Phenomenology in a
46:320–9. different key: Narrative, meaning and madness. Phi-
Parnas, J., P. T. Møller, J. Kircher, L. Thalbitzer, P. losophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 22, no. 3:187–92.
Jansson, D. Handest, and D. Zahavi. 2005. EASE:
Examination of anomalous self-experience. Psycho-
pathology 38:236–58.

You might also like