You are on page 1of 11

On Reading Collingwood's Principles of Art

Author(s): John Grant


Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 46, No. 2 (Winter, 1987), pp.
239-248
Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/431862
Accessed: 11-01-2020 04:22 UTC

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

The American Society for Aesthetics, Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

This content downloaded from 31.48.230.118 on Sat, 11 Jan 2020 04:22:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
JOHN GRANT

On Reading Collingwood's Principles


of Art

PERHAPS NO WORK of English aesthetics in this definition may be, it is most certainly not a
century has been more disputed than Colling- definition that is stated in Book I. I wish now to
wood's Principles of Art. 1 On one extreme it is examine this and other related assumptions.
insisted that Collingwood's chief and leading
doctrine is that the work of art is something I.
exclusively mental in nature, something whose
physical and publicly accessible embodiment is It is well known that Collingwood begins his
aesthetically extraneous. On the other extreme, famous work with the question, "What is art?"
while it is granted that Collingwood believed (PA, 1). In his Autobiography Collingwood
the work of art to be something "mental," it is calls the question-form a "vague portmanteau-
denied that he believed it to be something phrase covering a multitude of questions but not
"exclusively" mental. Art, for Collingwood, it precisely expressing any of them."3 But in the
is held, is something which is "unintelligible" Principles the question is immediately divided
apart from physical and publicly accessible into two "stages." The purpose of the first
behavior. stage, says Collingwood, is to "review the
The sharp divergence of opinion suggests improper senses of the word 'art' . . . so that at
what is true, i.e., that the text of the Principles, the end of it we can say not only 'that and that
while enviable for its precocity, is rife with and that are not art,' but also 'that is not art
chaos and confusion. Yet regrettably it may also because it is pseudo-art of kind A' and 'that,
be thought to suggest what is false, that the because it is pseudo-art of kind B.'" The
controversy about what Collingwood meant is purpose of the second stage is to address "the
insoluble. Collingwood's thesis is obscured by problem of definition." "Definition," Colling-
frequent changes of mind, to be sure. But as I wood particularly notes, "must come second,
shall endeavor very shortly to show, the and not first, because no one can even try to
changes are not in every case indiscriminate and define a term until he has satisfied himself that
unwitting. We read in Book I that the work of his own personal usage of it harmonizes with
art is something "(as we commonly say) 'ex- the common usage." "Definition," he goes on
isting in his [the artist's] head' and there only" to say, "means defining one thing in terms of
(PA, 37); and in what has become the usual way something else . . . " "constructing . . . a
of reading the Principles, the trick has been to 'theory' of something . . . " and "having a
square this assertion with Collingwood's evi- clear idea of the thing" and "its relations to
dent approbation in Books II and III for the other things as well" (PA, 1-2).
doctrine that the work of art is in some sense a The avowed purpose of this strategy is first to
"bodily" and "publicly accessible" thing or settle on the sense or senses in which the word
activity. But this way of reading the Principles, "art" is to be used and second, having done
I wish to insist, is entirely wrong. Whatever this, to investigate the nature of the activity to
Collingwood's "definition" or "theory" of which "art" so defined refers. It is not imme-
art, and however plausible or implausible that diately clear how "proper" and "improper"
JOHN GRANT is a graduate of the Department of usages are to be distinguished or what sort of
History and Philosophy of the Ontario Institute for investigation into the nature of art Collingwood
Studies in Education. envisages. But for the present let us notice a

? 1987 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

This content downloaded from 31.48.230.118 on Sat, 11 Jan 2020 04:22:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
240 G R A N T

distinction that we are likely to overlook. An Collingwood promises that his account of usage
attempt to state the meaning of a word, whether will tell us not merely in what senses the word
by description, stipulation, or some other "art" is and ought to be used, but also in what
method, is ordinarily called a "definition." By senses it ought not to be used and, most
"definition" in other words we commonly important, why. Contrary to Donagan, an ac-
mean the definition of words, and what count of "proper usage" for Collingwood con-
Collingwood describes as settling on a proper sists not merely of a brief lexical or historical
usage of the word "art" we are inclined to thinkdescription of various usages, but of something
a "definition" of "art." But particular atten- else as well: a critical examination of the theory
tion must be drawn to the fact that Collingwood or theories of art that underlie these usages.
himself uses the word "definition" in a differ- Now if Collingwood's account of usage is, in
ent sense, not as a statement of the meaning of its nature, something that cannot be brief, then
a word but as an investigation into the nature of it seems unlikely that it can be contained in the
the thing (activity, process, concept, word, brief space of Collingwood's introduction to the
etc.) to which a word may refer. Wherever Principles. Indeed, Donagan shows himself
ambiguity threatens, let us call definition inaware
this of this. "Despite his historical narrative
sense "real definition," a definition whose of how the aesthetic usage of the word 'art'
purpose it is to state in one way or another-by emerged, he [Collingwood] did not explain how
a whole range of methods that philosophers do he discriminated that usage from its fellows."6
not always distinguish (analysis, synthesis, di- Donagan then devotes considerable space to
vision, classification, etc.)4-the nature of a supplying what he takes to be the missing
thing. The quite different activity of defining explanation, an explanation which, evidently,
words we may call "verbal definition." he thinks implicit in what for him is
I shall have reason, very shortly, to modify Collingwood's "definition" of art in Book I.7
and to make more precise this tentative descrip- But here arises my second objection; for the
tion of the two stages into which Collingwood assumption that Collingwood's account of us-
divides his answer to "What is art?" But setting age is confined to the introduction prior to Book
aside for the moment this task, let us consider a I and that his "definition" of art begins in Book
much simpler matter: the precise locations in I seems to me entirely dubious. No feature of
the text of the Principles of what I have defined the Principles has more entirely escaped notice
in a preliminary way as Collingwood's than the one to which I am about to draw
"'verbal" and "real" definitions of art. Alan attention. The argument of Book I, I submit, is
Donagan's answer, which I take to be the not Collingwood's attempt to construct a "defi-
generally accepted one (certainly it is the only nition" or "theory" of art, as virtually all
explicit one), is that Collingwood's verbal defi- Collingwood's readers have supposed, but
nition, or account of "proper usage," consists nothing more nor less than the promised ac-
of a brief history of the word "art" up to the count of "proper usage" itself. The poihiis
present usage "in the modem European critical \na'e frequetny-throfghout Book I, but for
tradition" and comes in the introduction prior reasons of space I shall cite only one instance of
to Book I. What Collingwood calls his "defi- it.
nition" of art (and what I have called, tenta-
tively, a "real" definition) is then presumed to [Wie are still dealing with what are called questions of
begin at the outset of Book I. fact, or what in the first chapter were called questions
This reading seems to me open to two objec- of usage, not questions of theory. We shall not be trying
tions, the second of which is fatal. First, the to build up an argument which the reader is asked to
examine and criticize, and accept if he finds no fatal
brevity of Collingwood's verbal definition, as
flaw in it.... We shall be trying as best we can to
Donagan construes it, is incompatible with remind ourselves of facts well known to us all: such
Collingwood's declared purpose. Admittedly, facts as this, that on occasions of a certain kind we
an account of usage or verbal definition need actually do use the word art or some kindred word to
designate certain kinds of things . . . (PA, 105).8
not be a lengthy affair. It may consist for
example of an arbitrary assignment of meaning
or of a brief report of established usage. But The work of constructing a "definition" or

This content downloaded from 31.48.230.118 on Sat, 11 Jan 2020 04:22:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
On Reading Collingwood's Principles of Art 241

"theory" of art, in turn, comes not in Book I of we must appreciate that it is an essential feature of the
the Principles but in Books II and III. Croce-Collingwood thesis that not only can the artist
make works of art to himself, but that he may be in the
situation in which he can only make works of art to
The empirical and descriptive work of Book I left us
himself. 12
with the conclusion that art proper, as distinct from
amusement or magic, was (i) expressive (ii) imagina-
tive. Both these terms, however, awaited definition: we
might know how to apply them (that being a question of
And-here is perhaps the most distinctive characteristic
usage, or the ability to speak not so much English as the
of the Croce-Collingwood theory-when the part pro-
common tongue of European peoples), but we did not
cess is completed in the artist's mind; when the final
know to what theory concerning the thing so designated
artistic intuition is present to his consciousness, the
this application might commit us. It was to fill this gap
process of expression is also complete: for the intuition
in our knowledge that we went on to the analytical work
is the expression. 1
of Book II (PA, 273; italics mine).

Citing as conclusive evidence Collingwood's For evidence of what Wollheim and Hospers are
contention in Book I that the work of art is saying it is only necessary to turn to Book I
something made "in the mind, and there only," itself where, in spite of admitting, for example,
many writers, perhaps the majority, have de- the existence of "colours there in painting,"
fended what may be called the "Croce- Collingwood insists that all such "sensuous
Collingwood" interpretation of the Principles.9
parts" do not exist "objectively" in the work of
But others, attempting to reconcile Books IIart,andwhich is to say independently of a perceiv-
III with Book I, have insisted, on the contrary, ing subject, but are always "imagined" or, as
that Collingwood specifically denies that art has
he is wont to say, "solely in the artist's head"
no "bodily" and "publicly accessible" exis- (PA, 109, 113, 129, 151). Therefore, it may
tence. "Assimilating Collingwood's views to confidently be asserted, let us simply assume
those of Croce," writes one commentator, that Book I is a "definition" of art. Indeed, let
"runs the risk of seriously misreading The us assume that it is a "definition" in precisely
Principles of Art (and very likely Colling- the sense that Collingwood himself defines the
wood's major works as well)."'0 But if what Iword "definition" in his Essay on Philosophi-
have said is true, all such quibbles and disputescal Method, that is to say, as a "real definition"
may be seen to rest, at least in part, on a as opposed to analysis of a word, term, or
premise that is demonstrably unwarranted; for if
expression. 14
Book I is not a definition of art in the first place,
How should I reply to this way of reading
it is obviously false to suppose that everythingCollingwood? Should I abandon my thesis that
said in the later books needs to be shown to be there is nonetheless a good reason for thinking
compatible with Book 1. Book I an account of usage as opposed to a
"definition"? Certainly not. The distinction
II. between Collingwood's account of usage in
Book I and his definition of art in Books II and
The traditional reading of Collingwood's III, I suggest, may be cogently and faithfully
Principles may, however, be resurrected on reconstructed as a distinction between two spe-
another point. It will not have escaped the cies of verbal definition: one essentially restric-
reader's notice that even if, as I have argued, tive and based on established critical usages,
what Collingwood calls his "definition" or the other essentially nonrestrictive and based on
"theory" of art does not come until Books II established philosophical usage. Turning first to
and III, Collingwood's actual strategy is quite Collingwood's account of usage in Book I, the
different. For a theory is propounded in Book I,notoriously indefinite and confusing meaning of
surely. An aesthetic doctrine-we may call it "art," Collingwood tells us, is not to be legis-
the "mental-only" doctrine-is implied more lated according to a "private" rule, but is to be
or less directly in Collingwood's analysis of adopted by an analysis of conceptions underly-
what he calls "proper usage."" It is thus that ing the word in established critical usage. We
the following commentators, for example, havemust, as Collingwood expresses it, settle on a
written: meaning that both "fits onto common usages'

This content downloaded from 31.48.230.118 on Sat, 11 Jan 2020 04:22:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
242 G R A N T

and, at the same time, "clarifies" and "sys- Collingwood, "and both ways of thinking tend
tematizes" ideas we already possess. Note, to subsume the philosophy of art under the
especially, that "clarification" and "systemi- philosophy of craft..." Old usages "cling to
zation" mean, in this instance, arriving at a our minds like drowning men, and so jostle the
stipulation the application and logical conse- present meaning that we can only distinguish it
quences of which are at least clear (even if from them by the most careful analysis" (PA,
queried in Collingwood's later account) and 19, 7).
which does not transgress the usage of art critics More important for present purposes, the
and other knowledgeable persons (PA, 1-7). foregoing brings clearly to light the distinction
Proceeding in this way Collingwood ousts Collingwood means to draw between his ac-
from the entangled set of usages of which the count of usage in Book I and his definition of art
established critical usage of "art" consists what in Books II and III. In contrast to the argument
he calls the "distorting" idea that a work of art of Book I, the argument of Book II is,
is something susceptible to an exhaustive analy- precisely, unrestricted by the established usage
sis per genus et differentiam and adopts pre- of critics and the like. The verbal and concep-
cisely the opposite idea, i.e., that art is some- tual territory in which Book II operates,
thing whose individuality defeats analysis in Collingwood tells us, is bounded only by estab-
this sense. And all this is done, again, without lished philosophical usage and conceptions.
at any point stepping outside of what is in
Collingwood's view the realm of established
critical usage. The argument of Book I may In Book II, therefore, I shall make a fresh start. I
thus, to this extent, be likened to a disjunctive shall try to work out a theory of imagination and of its
place in the structure of experience as a whole, by
syllogism based on-or "restricted" to-vari-
developing what has already been said about it by
ous established usages of the word art. The well-known philosophers. In doing this I shall make no
syllogism begins with the disjunctive premise use whatever of anything contained in Book I (PA,
"we mean by 'art' in established critical usage 152-53).

one of two things-'craft' or 'expression.' "


The craft alternative is then eliminated, leaving
only one other established usage, that according Indeed, in "developing what has already been
to which art is ""expression."15 said," Collingwood frequently has cause to go
Now if this description of Book I is roughly quite beyond the realm of established philo-
true, then Donagan's explanation of what sophical usage to stipulate entirely new mean-
makes critical usage the "proper" usage for ings for old words and even to invent entirely
Collingwood cannot be correct. To be sure, new words. Thus the word "imagination" is
Collingwood begins by assuming the existence wrenched from its established range of mean-
of an established critical usage, as Donagan ings in philosophy to denote an "act of atten-
tion"
insists. 16 But it is certainly false to say that he in which the momentary flux of immedi-
assumes such usage to be "'aesthetically ate and undifferentiated sensation, "charged
proper," leaving the way open, as it were, to with emotion" is fixed long enough to form, for
construct (in Book I) what Donagan calls a example, an idea of this particular grief, this
"definition of the word 'art' " when it is used particular warmth, this particular pain, and so
"aesthetically." Collingwood's approach is ex- on (PA, 203). Similarly, the word "language"
is completely redefined to denote the "bodily
actly the opposite: it is assumed, precisely, that
critics are not exempt from the ambiguities andexpression of emotion" that accompanies all
false implications that plague the common us- such acts of attention or "imagination" (PA,
age of "art." Only once various kinds of "art 235ff). Last but not least, the term "psychical
falsely so called" are "cleared away," Col- expression" is freshly minted to denote the
lingwood tells us, can the proper usage of "involuntary" and '"wholly unconscious"
the word art be brought to light. "We [critics bodily acts, the "distortions of the face" ex-
and the like] are apt nowadays to think about pressing "pain," "slackening of the muscles
most problems including those of art, in and cold pallor of the skin" expressing "fear,"
terms of economics or psychology," writes and so on, that are said to accompany the

This content downloaded from 31.48.230.118 on Sat, 11 Jan 2020 04:22:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
On Reading Collingwood's Principles of Art 243

sentient being's immediate experience of sen- Collingwood's analysis of established usage in


suous flux (PA, 229). Book I, ultimately they serve merely to confirm
Fortunately, I am under no obligation to and to perfect tendencies of thought already
unravel the intricacies of this elaborate home- implicit in that analysis. The trump is the
spun terminology. My purpose is merely to following passage from Book llI.
show that there is an obvious and legitimate
distinction between Collingwood's account of 1A] work of art in the proper sense of that phrase is not
proper usage" and his "definition." The an artifact, not a bodily or perceptible thing fabricated
former, I suggest, aims at narrowing or "re- by the artist, but something existing solely in the
artist's head. . . . No reader, I hope, has been
stricting" an established and already relatively
inattentive enough to imagine that . this doctrine has
specialized critical usage; the latter, at refining been forgotten or denied (PA, 305).
and even at altering established philosophical
usage to the end of constructing a philosophical This passage obviously lends considerable
theory of art. There is no deadly rivalry between weight to the view that it is Collingwood's
these "theories"; indeed, neither counts as purpose to defend without possibility of appeal
Collingwood's definitive position. Book I iden- the "mental only" theory of art throughout the
tifies what is the established usage of "art," at Principles. Against this, what have I to say in
least, what is that part of it for which no defense of my interpretation?
demonstrable falsehoods can be found; Book II I should begin by noticing, quite apart from
analyzes the word from a philosophical per- this passage, that I am not alone in the view that
spective (PA, 109); Book III is then, as Collingwood changes his mind in Book III. "In
Collingwood puts it, the "union" of these Book (PA,
III Collingwood quietly relinquished the
153). That is to say, it is an account of what, sense inof 'imaginary' in which an imaginary
light of philosophical analysis, the established object exists only in the head." writes
usage of "art" ought to look like. 17 Thus Book l But I should want to go further than
Donagan.
III, we may say, is a new, improved "theory" Donagan here. I should want to say, first, by
of art: not a "philosophical" theory exactly, reference to Book II, not merely that the mental
but an attempt to provide, in light of philosoph- only line is "relinquished," but also that it is
ical analysis, a new conceptual underpinning replaced by almost the contrary position. Art is
for the work of artists, performers, and audi- "language," argues Collingwood in Books II
ences in England "here and now" (PA, vi, vii). and III, and "language' he particularly stresses
Essentially, then, established usages and con- is something which is "bodily" in nature.
ceptions undergo revision twice: first in Book I
in which demonstrable falsehoods (vestiges of [Lianguage is simply bodily expression of emotion,
craft theory) are removed; second in Book III in dominated by thought in its primitive form as con-
sciousness.
which the philosophical implications of Book II
are brought to bear. And it is the result of these Every kind of language is in this way a specialized form
revisions that counts as Collingwood's defini- of bodily gesture, and in this sense it may be said that
tive theory. It is perhaps, more than anything dance is the mother of all languages.
else, I suggest, in failing to appreciate this fact IElvery kind or order of language (speech, gesture, and
that readers have fallen prey to the imprecision so forth) was an offshoot from an original language of
and ambiguity in Collingwood's use of the total bodily gesture. . . . each one of us, whenever he
expresses himself, is doing so with his whole body. and
words "definition" and "theory" and have
is thus actually talking in this 'original' language of
mistaken his account of usage in Book I for his total bodily gesture (PA, 235, 243-44. 246).
"definition" or "theory" of art.
And I should want to say, second, in reference
Ill. to Book III, that far from being "quiet," the
change is explicitly avowed in the following
The misconception to which I have called explicit criticism of Book 1.
attention, however, is by no means fatal to
traditional assumptions. For it will be insisted
On the theory of art propounded in this book, the
that even if Books II and III are independent of audience seems at first sight to become inessential. It

This content downloaded from 31.48.230.118 on Sat, 11 Jan 2020 04:22:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
244 G R A N T

[the audience] seems to disappear altogether from the Collingwood changes his mind to be sure. But
province of art as such.... If the implications of the
what of the puzzling passage I cited at the
expressive theory had been completely grasped in the
case of the artist, there would have been no need to fall
outset? The fact of the matter is that it is
back on the technical theory in discussing his relation precisely having asserted the "indivisibility" of
with his audience (PA, 300, 302). the imaginative and the bodily experience that
Collingwood goes on to insist that the mental-
In Book I the process by which emotions are only doctrine from Book I has "not been
clarified and expressed is said to be an entirely forgotten or denied." Thus we should say not
internal affair: "a work of art may be com- that Collingwood changes his mind in a manner
pletely created when it has been created as a that is conscious and deliberate but, quite the
thing whose only existence is in the artist's opposite, that he changes it in a manner that
mind...." "The actual making of the tune is renders his theory inconsistent. Richard
something that goes on in the head, and no- Wollheim writes:
where else.." (PA, 130, 134). Its physical
and publicly accessible counterpart is thus con- In book I of the Principles of Art Collingwood asserts
that the work of art is something imaginary: it exists in,
ceived of as something which is not the work of
and only in, the artist's head or mind. In book III he
art, but merely something that conveys the denies that the relation of the audience is non-existent
work of art to the outside world by standing for or inessential. Collingwood goes on to say that these
it: "what is written or printed on the music two views--one an assertion, the other a denial-
which jointly constitute his aesthetic, are not inconsis-
paper is not the tune," we are told. "It is only
tent: though superficially they might seem so.20
something which when studied intelligently will
enable others (or himself, when he has forgot- But let us read further. The important ques-
ten it) to construct the tune for themselves in tion, Collingwood goes on to say, is whether
their own heads" (PA, 135). And since it is not the "solely" mental-only work may yet be
necessary to the existence of a work of art that "somehow necessarily connected" with the
it be made public, the artist has an audience bodily work (PA, 305). And in the pages that
"only in so far as people hear him expressing follow, Collingwood reviews his definition of
himself, and understand what they hear him art (Book II) and is drawn ineluctably to the
saying" (PA, 118). conclusion that there is indeed a "connection"
But all this changes in Book II and ipso facto and, what is more, that it is a connection in light
in Collingwood's translation of the results of of which the mental-only doctrine cannot be
Book II into the more ordinary nomenclature of sustained.
artists, performers, and audiences in Book III.
The making of a work of art, says Collingwood, The work of artistic creation is not a work performed in
is a bodily activity from its inception. Art is any exclusive or complete fashion in the mind of the
language and language "'simply bodily expres- person whom we call the artist. That idea is a delusion
bred of individualistic psychology together with a false
sion of emotion," "a specialized form of
view of the relation not so much between body and
bodily gesture," and so on. There is no ques- mind as between experience at the psychical level and
tion of having to "externalize" it in order to experience at the level of thought (PA, 323-24 [italics
make it publicly accessible. "9 As Collingwood mine]).

expresses it, there is no need "to fall back upon


the technical theory" in order to explain how Thus, significantly, Collingwood's attempt to
works of art are made publicly accessible (PA, resurrect the mental-only doctrine proves abor-
302). And elsewhere: "There is no question of tive. But more needs to be said than this, surely,
'externalizing' an inward experience which is lest Collingwood's argument should appear
complete in itself and by itself. There are two only more perversely erratic and irremedably
experiences, an inward and imaginative one inconsistent than before. Why, having defended
called seeing and an outward or bodily one throughout Book II the view that art is some-
called painting, which in the painter's life are thing bodily in nature, should Collingwood
inseparable, and form one single and indivisible even contemplate the idea that it is something
experience . ." (PA, 304-5). "solely" in the head? And why, having con-
Of course this hardly settles matters. templated it, does he then abandon it?

This content downloaded from 31.48.230.118 on Sat, 11 Jan 2020 04:22:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
On Reading Collingwood's Principles of Art 245

The answer to the first question is this: that (PA, 323-24). The reference here is, of course,
Collingwood's description of art as something to the definition of art as "language" and, as
both "bodily" and "inward" or "imagina- such, as something intrinsically "sensuous" or
tive" in nature is equivocal, and equivocal in a "bodily." What is "sensuous" or "bodily" at
way that lends superficial plausibility to the the "psychical level"'--our immediate experi-
doctrine that the work of art exists "in the ence of the world-Collingwood reminds us in
head." The "bodily" work and its "imagina- Book III, is not "left behind," as it were, by
tive" counterpart, Collingwood insists, are the act of attention which makes us aware of it.
"indivisible" and yet, curiously, are "two Rather, the bodily component is retained at the
experiences," not one. The work of art, he higher "imaginative" level, but now in the
says, is something that "exists solely in the form of "language" or "art" (PA, 234-35,
head" and yet, at base, something that is 305-8). It is thus, I suggest, that we are urged to
"necessarily connected with" its bodily coun- think of the work of art not as an amalgam or
terpart. Collingwood seems to want to have it interaction of two separate worlds, the "men-
both ways. He wants to say (and this is espe- tal" work existing in the artist's head and its
cially clear in the second example) that the exemplification existing somewhere else in an
"bodily" work is a necessary condition for the entirely distinct physical mode, but as a rela-
occurrence of the mental work but is not the tionship holding between the "sensuous" and
mental work (or work of art proper) itself-an "imaginative" levels of experience, which in
interpretation which echoes the doctrine of respect to their "matter," as Collingwood ex-
Book L.21 But he also wants to say something presses it, are one and the same thing (PA,
quite different: that far from belonging to two 305-7, 323-24).22 We may say with Colling-
quite separate worlds, res cogitans and res wood and, what is more, in agreement with
extensa, the mental and bodily work are two Book I, that the work of art is "wholly and
aspects-the "psychical" and the "imagina- entirely imaginative," that it is something
tive"' -of one and the same thing-"experi- which is made "deliberately and responsibly"
ence" -a position that is consistent with and yet without a plan. But as Collingwood
Collingwood's definition of art in Book II. ultimately stresses, this does not entitle us to
Collingwood, I say, is not immediately say that it is something made "exclusively" in
aware of the difference between these two sorts the head.
of statements; and it is in this unfortunate We continue to feel of course that a distinc-
context that the opportunity presents itself to tion between the mental and the physical is in
suggest that there is yet a grain of truth in some sense warranted-indeed Collingwood
"common usage," a sense in which it is com- himself continues to suppose it-and it is by no
patible with the philosophical work of Book II. means clear on Collingwood's monistic account
Certainly there is such a sense. We should not of "experience" how this distinction is to be
identify the work of art with "fabrication" or made, if at all. But I do not think my thesis is
mere physical exemplification; nor should we dented. The contention that Collingwood con-
suppose that "imagination" is an activity in sciously and deliberately changes his mind
any sense directed towards an end which is about the mental-only doctrine of Book I is not,
known in advance, as in craft. These two things after all, incompatible with the fact that his new
remain quite true in Book Ill, but they do not theory is not precisely worked out. Nor is it
justify, obviously, the assertion that the work of inconsistent with the fact that he initially sees a
art is something "solely" mental in nature. partial or superficial consistency between the
But turning now to the second question, provisional doctrine of Book I and the more
ultimately Collingwood is aware of an incon- definitive doctrine of Books II and III. To be
sistency in his position. As he expresses it, the sure, Collingwood may be justly criticized for
idea that the work of art is something "solely" being vague and imprecise and, as a result, for
or "exclusively" mental implies "a false view providing grist for the mills of numerous irrec-
of the relation not so much between body and oncilable interpretations. But if my reading has
mind as between experience at the psychical warrant, in one important respect all these
level and experience at the level of thought" interpretations may be called into question. For

This content downloaded from 31.48.230.118 on Sat, 11 Jan 2020 04:22:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
246 G R A N T

it is clear that the dualistic tendency to see the allowed "to pass for the moment un-
mental and bodily aspects of the work of art as challenged," he writes; and the assertion that
completely different entities is consciously and "craft" is necessary, he says, is true, but
deliberately abandoned, and with it the doctrine "true" when "properly understood" (PA,
that the work of art or imagination is something 26-27). But the matter is soon cleared up.
done exclusively in the head. Collingwood goes on to argue against the
doctrine that craft or skill is necessary in the
IV. second sense, that is, as a means of achieving a
specific end, and for the proposition that it is
My account of Collingwood's argument may necessary in the first sense, that is to say, as an
be thought open to one final objection. I have "effort" or "directed process" which is con-
suggested that Collingwood rules out entirely scious and deliberate but unplanned. "What he
the place of technique in art. But the opposite [the artist] wants to say," Collingwood con-
view is widely held. As one commentator cludes, "is not present to him as an end towards
expresses it: "Collingwood always stressed that which means have to be devised; . . ." (PA, 29).
technique was necessary to art, where technique But further qualification needs to be made.
is understood as the control which enables an Properly speaking, we are told, "craft," "tech-
artist to create exactly what he wants. "23 nique,' "skill," and the like are words which
Donagan advocates a qualified version of the should not be used to refer to the "directed" but
view, saying that Collingwood believed craft to "unplanned" nature of art. The latter is "no
be "necessary" for the "best" art. 24 This doubt a thing worthy of our attention; but we are
interpretation, I wish briefly to show, is un- only frustrating our study of it in advance if we
doubtedly false. approach it in the determination to treat it as if
To be sure, Collingwood appears in his com- it were the conscious working-out of means to
mentary on the theory of "poetic" or "artistic" the achievement of a conscious purpose, or in
technique to concede that technique or skill is, other words technique" (PA, 29). "Technique"
at the very least, a necessary condition of the used in its proper sense must, in other words,
best art if not, indeed, a necessary condition of refer to something which is planned. We are
any work of art "whatever" (PA, 27-29). It compelled to conclude, therefore, that "tech-
should be clear on closer examination, how- nique" in its proper sense, or "the control
ever, that the matter is not quite as simple as which enables an artist to create exactly what he
this. When proponents of the theory of poetic wants," is not, for Collingwood, a necessary
technique say that craft or technique is neces- condition of art.
sary, what they are really saying, according to But there is yet a further point in need of
Collingwood, is two things. In one sense they clarification. '"[The description of the unwrit-
ten poem as an end to which his technique is a
are using the words "technique," "craft," and
means is false," writes Collingwood, except in
"skill" to mean a "directed process" or "an
those instances where "the work of art is also a
effort . . . directed upon a certain end," saying
work of craft" (PA, 28-29). Just as the joiner
that these things are necessary to art. But in
"knows the specifications of the table he is
another sense, which in Collingwood's view
about to make" so the artist, where he is also a
they do not clearly distinguish from the latter,
craftsman, we are told, knows the specifica-
they mean to say that "craft" is an activity in
tions of the work of art he is about to make (PA,
which specific plans are laid out in advance and
28-29). Collingwood seems to be admitting
precisely followed, and that craft in this sense is here the necessity of technique-at least in
necessary to art (PA, 28-29). those cases where, as he puts it, "the work of
Now when Collingwood writes that it is quite art is also a work of craft." But we should
true that craft or skill is a necessary condition of examine this position more closely. Col-
art, initially he does not say to which sense of lingwood sharply distinguishes between "mak-
the word craft he means to give his approval. ing" in the sense in which the craftsman makes,
And this perhaps has misled many readers. The which he calls "fabricating," and "making"
key word "skill" in this context must be which is unique to the production of works of

This content downloaded from 31.48.230.118 on Sat, 11 Jan 2020 04:22:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
On Reading Collingwood's Principles of Art 247

art. Making in the latter sense is not "fabricat- he has established the truth, adequacy, and
ing" but "creating," that is, making without relevance of its premises-Collingwood is later
foreknowledge of the outcome (PA, 128) or compelled to revise it. We read in Book 1, for
making which is ''conscious and voluntary" example, that '"the actual making of the tune is
but "non-technical." Now, to be sure, the artist (as we commonly say) something that goes on
who typically makes in the latter sense can also, in his Ithe artist's] head and there only." But all
if he is competent to do so, "make" in the quite this is revised in Book II, and it is not until
different sense in which the craftsman does. But Book III that we are given-again in the no-
an artist who chooses to specify exactly how a menclature of artists, audiences, and perform-
work of art is to be made must be presumed, iners-what Collingwood thinks a definitive and
Collingwood's view, already to have created it: practically applicable theory of art. There we
"the artist has no idea what the experience is read that the work of art is, precisely, not
which demands expression until he has ex- something that is "performed in any exclusive
pressed it" (PA, 129). Fabrication, or making or complete fashion in the mind of the person
in the sense in which the craftsman makes, whom we call the artist" (PA, 323, 324). It is to
therefore, is extraneous to "creating" and statements such as these, not to the argument of
should on no account be thought necessary to it. Book 1, that readers who wish to understand
No doubt things 'created" can also be, in a Collingwood's "definition" or "theory" of art
manner of speaking, things "fabricated," but must give their unaccustomed attention.
we must conclude that what makes such things Of course, above all else we should want to
the one, for Collingwood, is a separate matter know whether Collingwood is right, a question
from what makes them the other. "Expres- that I have not here sought to address. But if my
sion,'" as Collingwood puts it, "is an activity of argument has warrant, most of the criticisms
which there can be no technique" (PA, I I 1). offered by critics against Collingwood's theory
Collingwood is open to criticism, no doubt, miss the mark, being not criticisms of his
because we surely do use "craft," "tech- definitive position, but criticisms of the various
nique," and like terms quite legitimately to tentative positions that precede it. To that extent
refer to things which cannot be made according my reading may be viewed as urging that the
to exact specifications. This is obvious, for key question, whether Collingwood was right,
example, where the thing being made is a be examined afresh.
dugout canoe, an apple pie, or a leather shoe.
No one tree, apple, or piece of leather is R. G. Collingwood, The Principles of Art (Oxford,
1938). Page references to be cited in the body of the text:
identical to any other; so we can never know
(PA, 99), for example, means Collingwood, Principles, p.
precisely, that is, we can never specify exhaus- 99.
tively, what the end result of working with such 2 Perhaps the most recent instance of this debate is in
material will be. We are very often compelled to Richard Sclafani's, "Wollheim on Collingwood," Philoso-
revise our plans in midstream. But to return to phY 51 (1976), in which it is argued against Richard
Wollheim's interpretation of the Principles in Art and its
the point at issue, if we feel such criticisms apt,
Objects (New York, 1968) that Collingwood never meant to
it is only because Collingwood uses the word deny the public accessibility of the work of art. The debate
"technique" in a sense that obliges him pre- has taken many other forms, but these are too numerous to
cisely to deny that it is a necessary condition of mention here.
- R. G. Collingwood, An Autobiography (Oxford,
art.
1939), p. 122; see also An Essa yv on Metaphysics (Oxford,
1940), p. 26; and Benedetto Croce, Guide to Aesthetics
V. trans. Patrick Romanell (South Bend, 1965), pp. 3-4. The
question "What is art?" writes Croce in his Guide to
In his Essay on Philosophical Method, Aesthetics, "has always, in fact, a circumstantial mean-
Collingwood writes that philosophical thinking ing-referring as it does to the particular difficulties that
is a "dialectical process where the initial posi- come to life at a specific moment in the history of thought."
4 Admittedly, Collingwood is not always clear, as for
tion is modified again and again as difficulties
example when he speaks of "defining' the term art. What
in it come to light."25 Certainly, we can say he really means when he speaks of "defining' the term, as
this much about the Principles, that having in all instances where he uses the word "definition," is an
stated his position in a provisional way-before analysis of the thing to which it refers, not verbal definition.

This content downloaded from 31.48.230.118 on Sat, 11 Jan 2020 04:22:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
248 G R A N T

' Alan Donagan, The Later Philosophy of R. G. '7 In this regard, Francis Sparshott's observation that
Collingwood (Oxford, 1964), pp. 96-99. the Principles contains, in fact, three distinct theories of art
6 Ibid., p. 96. should come as no surprise. Francis Sparshott, The Theory
7 Ibid., pp. 96-99. of the Arts (Princeton University Press, 1982), pp. 629-30.
8 See also Collingwood, Principles, pp. 109, 125, 131, 18 Donagan, The Later Philosophy, p. 118.
136, 152. 19 Indeed, again contrary to the usual interpretation, I
9 The nomenclature seems to have originated with Johnthink there is a case to be made for the view that
Hospers, "Croce-Collingwood Theory of Art," Philosophy Collingwood abandons what is, essentially, an "idea theory
31 (1956). of meaning" for the rival theory that meaning is established
10 Richard Sclafani, "Wollheim on Collingwood," by or bound up with language and, in particular, with the
Philosophy 51 (1976): 359. See also Donagan, The Later role of an individual act of expression and clarification
Philosophy, pp. 94-113; Peter Charmichael, "Collingwood within a language. But that is another matter which there is
and Art Media," Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 2 not space here to address. See Collingwood, Principles, pp.
(Spring-Summer 1971): 37-42; Peter Jones, "A Critical 244 47, 250-53.
Outline of Collingwood's Philosophy of Art," in Critical 20 Richard Wollheim, "On An Alleged Inconsistency
Essays on the Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood, ed., In Collingwood's Aesthetic," Critical Essays, p. 69.
Richard Krausz, (Oxford, 1972), pp. 42-65; Donald S. 21 There is no reason in principle why the artist whose
Taylor, "R. G. Collingwood: Art, Craft, and History," aim it is to make a work, "entirely in the head," as it were,
Clio 2 (June 1973): 239-78. should not have recourse along the way, perhaps necessar-
" Collingwood is annoyingly equivocal on this point. ily, to pencil and paper, clay, canvas, paintbrush, and so
"We have finished at last with the technical theory of art," on.
he writes at the outset of his discussion of "art proper." Yet 22 I speculate that Collingwood's division of experi-
in the next paragraph we read: "we are still dealing with ence is based on the theory of "overlapping classes" which
questions of fact, or what in the first chapter were called he sets forth in his Philosophical Method. In accordance
questions of theory." Collingwood, Principles, p. 105. with the apparata criticus of that theory, Collingwood may
12 Wollheim, Art and Its Objects, p. 100. be construed as classifying expression as "sensuous,"
13 Hospers, "The Croce-Collingwood Theory of Art," "imaginative," "intellectual," according to the differentia
p. 293. "increasing degrees of freedom." Thus imaginative expres-
14 R. G. Collingwood, An Essay on Philosophical sion (language, or art), for example, Collingwood defines
Method (Oxford, 1933), p. 92. as "a manifestation of freedom, intermediate between the
15 Anyone can see that the argument construed in this less free activity of mere feeling and the more free activity
sense is valid; but whether it is cogent is quite another of what is generally called thought. . ." (Collingwood,
matter. It may be doubted. for example, whether common Principles, p. 208). See also Philosophical Method, pp.
usage consists essentially of only two strains; whether the 26-91.
conceptions implied by craft usage are, in fact, false; and 23 Peter Jones, "A Critical Outline of Collingwood's
whether the conceptions that underlie "proper usage" are Philosophy of Art," Critical Essays, p. 63.
true or plausible. 24 Donagan, The Later Philosophy, p. 112.
16 Donagan, The Later Philosophy, pp. 96-99. 25 Collingwood, Philosophical Method, p. 210.

This content downloaded from 31.48.230.118 on Sat, 11 Jan 2020 04:22:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like