You are on page 1of 28

675175

2016
ASRXXX10.1177/0003122416675175American Sociological ReviewLizardo

American Sociological Review

Improving Cultural Analysis: 2017, Vol. 82(1) 88­–115


© American Sociological
Association 2016
Considering Personal Culture DOI: 10.1177/0003122416675175
journals.sagepub.com/home/asr

in its Declarative and


Nondeclarative Modes

Omar Lizardoa

Abstract
While influential across a wide variety of subfields, cultural analysis in sociology continues
to be hampered by coarse-grained conceptualizations of the different modes in which culture
becomes personal, as well as the process via which persons acquire and use different forms
of culture. In this article, I argue that persons acquire and use culture in two analytically
and empirically distinct forms, which I label declarative and nondeclarative. The mode of
cultural acquisition depends on the dynamics of exposure and encoding, and modulates the
process of cultural accessibility, activation, and use. Cultural knowledge about one domain
may be redundantly represented in both declarative and nondeclarative forms, each linked
via analytically separable pathways to corresponding public cultural forms and ultimately to
substantive outcomes. I outline how the new theoretical vocabulary, theoretical model, and
analytic distinctions that I propose can be used to resolve contradictions and improve our
understanding of outstanding substantive issues in empirically oriented subfields that have
recently incorporated cultural processes as a core explanatory resource.

The past two and a half decades have seen a are acquired and used by persons. Instead,
virtual explosion of interest in culture among one-size-fits-all proposals, deploying the
sociologists, first as a delimited topic of anal- term “culture” as a generic (and thus ambigu-
ysis (“the sociology of culture”) and more ous) category of analysis, seem to be the rule
recently as a general resource for explanation rather than the exception (Alexander 2003;
(“cultural sociology”). In this sense, cultural Swidler 2001a). Second, even when incipient
sociologists can proclaim with confidence analytic distinctions are made (Sewell 1992;
that their work stands “at the crossroads of Swidler 2001b), we find partial, insufficiently
the discipline” (Jacobs and Spillman 2005), developed, and sometimes empirically inade-
helping to inform the research of scholars in quate conceptualizations of how different
virtually every substantive area of sociology kinds of cultural elements relate to one
(DiMaggio 1997; Patterson 2014; Sewell another (Patterson 2014). One of the primary
2005). Yet, despite its widespread influence,
cultural analysis in sociology is limited, and
thus prevented from fulfilling its putative a
University of Notre Dame
discipline-unifying role, in at least two impor-
tant respects.1 Corresponding Author:
Omar Lizardo, Department of Sociology,
First, sociologists generally have an University of Notre Dame, 810 Flanner Hall,
impoverished understanding of how analyti- Notre Dame, IN, 46556
cally and empirically distinct forms of culture E-mail: olizardo@nd.edu
Lizardo 89

goals of this article is to provide a coherent defense and exegesis of previous work that
analytic and empirical basis for the distinc- emphasizes the tacit bases of action (e.g.,
tion between different forms of culture and to Bourdieu 1990). Instead, my goals are more
provide the first steps toward a model of how modest but not necessarily less programmatic.
the distinct modalities of culture interrelate to My aim is to provide a flexible (but princi-
produce the empirical phenomena of interest pled) conceptual vocabulary that cultural ana-
to sociologists. lysts may draw upon regardless of underlying
A roadblock to reaching this goal is that, persuasion or commitment to any specific
under the most influential approaches, the program. The conceptual toolbox should then
implicit, or nondeclarative aspects of culture be used to qualify, sharpen, and extend the
(phenomenologically opaque and not open to quality of theorizing focused on cultural pro-
linguistic articulation) are usually conceptual- cesses across diverse empirical settings.2
ized as being inherently intertwined with, or Naturally, the distinctions I propose are
as being of secondary analytic importance in not completely neutral as to how the concepts
relation to, its explicit or declarative facets of “culture” and “action” are conceptualized,
(phenomenologically transparent and elicited and while the argument attempts to be ecune-
as linguistic reports). That is, knowledge mical it is not neutral as to conceptualization.
“how” is not properly differentiated from My own thinking on these issues has been
knowledge “that” (Ryle 2002:25–26). In the most strongly influenced by the line of work
modal case, linguistically articulated forms of known as “practice theory,” which is most
culture are presumed to be of more inherent clearly articulated in the work of Pierre
substantive interest than “how” knowledge, Bourdieu (1990) and Ann Swidler (2001b).
or at least of being capable of serving as a While acknowledging these influences, the
relatively unproblematic point of access to approach I propose is neither a reproduction
the latter (Jerolmack and Khan 2014). nor a retranslation of Bourdieusian or Swidle-
My argument in what follows is that a seri- rian insights into a different set of theoretical
ous consideration of the distinction between terms. In the case of Bourdieu, one problem
declarative and nondeclarative culture (at the with even attempting such a recasting is that
personal level), and both from the way culture is he saw the project of cultural explanation in
manifest in public (extra-personal) form (Strauss social science, available to him mainly in the
and Quinn 1997), is a requirement for effective form of mid-twentieth structuralist and sym-
cultural analysis on analytic and empirical bolic anthropology, as a dead end (Bourdieu
grounds. I will show that having an adequate 1973). This stance led him to develop a
conceptualization of both the analytically rele- counter-project in which the concept of cul-
vant differences between cultural elements as ture entered only as a topic to be accounted
well as the multifaceted relations that these ele- for but never as an analytic resource for
ments enter into, helps resolve a host of empiri- explanation (Lizardo 2011). This required the
cal issues that would otherwise remain shrouded development of a somewhat idiosyncratic,
in ambiguity, confusion, and paradox. and in many ways unwieldy, theoretical
Having stated my positive goals, allow me vocabulary—one that has never been coher-
to clarify what I do not intend to do here. First, ently incorporated into Anglophone cultural
my aim is not to formulate another grand analysis (e.g., Alexander 2003; Sewell 1992;
approach to cultural analysis, in the vein of Swidler 2001b). Furthermore, Bourdieu’s
classical normativist functionalism (e.g., Par- ambivalence in relation to the culture concept
sons 1951) or “the strong program” (e.g., essentially meant he made little effort to pro-
Alexander 2003). Nor is it my goal to displace vide an empirically defensible account of
influential contemporary approaches to the how persons acquire and use culture in con-
culture/action linkage (e.g., Swidler 2001a; text, outside of some suggestive, but ulti-
Vaisey 2009), or to provide a full-fledged mately elliptical, allusions.
90 American Sociological Review 82(1)

In contrast to this stance, the approach source of material. This has two additional
developed here remains fully committed to a analytic and substantive advantages. First,
robust notion of culture as an analytic resource this is an area where a consideration of cul-
for explanation (Sewell 2005). Accordingly, I tural processes, after a long period of self-
attempt to integrate the practice-theoretical imposed banishment (Patterson 2014), have
insight that a lot of what functions as culture re-emerged with a renewed vigor, but where
remains in the tacit dimension, never rising to the ultimate substantive implications of this
the level of discourse, with the empirical fact cultural turn remain to be fully demonstrated
that a lot of what gets referred to as “culture” (Lamont, Beljean, and Clair 2014). Second,
presents itself to the analyst in the form of culture and inequality studies is an area where
explicit talk and discourse (e.g., Swidler empirical researchers are forced to deal with
2001a). To that end, I draw on recent interdis- fundamental issues in cultural theory that,
ciplinary work on the enculturation process to while superficially presenting themselves as
provide a principled account of how we may purely empirical debates, can be directly
be able to pull off this feat, an account that traced to analytic choices affecting how cul-
should be usable by social scientists commit- ture is (or is not) brought in as an explanatory
ted to the project of cultural explanation. This factor in the first place. The synthetic benefits
reformulation has several analytic advantages that can accrue from moving to the frame-
over previous synthetic attempts, whether of work I propose are thus most evident here.
Bourdieusian provenance or not, including We will see how substantive issues that
the fact that it does not require either the would otherwise be accounted for using
adoption of an idiosyncratic terminology incompatible or globally incoherent theoreti-
(opting instead for terms with wide currency cal vocabularies, or segregated into seem-
in social science) or all-out commitment to a ingly competing forms of cultural explanation,
delimited theoretical system or program. can be brought under a coherent conceptual
To showcase the substantive payoff of the umbrella. I also show how the analytic vocab-
approach I propose, I take contemporary stud- ulary I develop provides a way to avoid hav-
ies of the role of culture in the reproduction of ing to engage in strained acts of intellectual
inequality as paradigmatic test cases for con- gerrymandering, in which cultural explana-
ceptual clarification. I do this with full knowl- tions are deployed for a selective range of
edge that this is precisely the area that may be cases and arbitrarily foreclosed for others
thought of as having been settled by practice- (Skrentny 2008), or in which equally arbitrary
inspired models, such as that developed in the distinctions between culture and not-culture
early work of Bourdieu and Passeron (1990) (e.g., structure) have to be brought in through
and the cottage industry of work that grew the backdoor (Hays 1994). Both of these
around the concept of cultural capital follow- issues continue to serve as obstacles to effec-
ing this intervention. My intent here is neither tive cultural analysis in the field.
to replicate nor displace the insights generated
by these lines of work, nor to develop a
generic model linking culture, institutions, A Theory of
and the reproduction of power. Instead, my Enculturation
aim is to show that we can do better cultural With these preliminary considerations out of
theory and provide more compelling, convinc- the way, I begin by providing a theoretically
ing, and generative modes of cultural explana- informed account of the enculturation process
tion when the right set of distinctions is made that connects analytically distinct ways in
and we focus on the right kind of processes. which persons internalize culture to processes
To that end, I chose primarily empirically of cultural activation and use.
driven efforts in the study of culture and ine- The theory of enculturation that I propose
quality in the United States as my main is grounded in approaches to the study of
Lizardo 91

culture in action with a strong basis in the analytically distinct forms. On the one hand,
interdisciplinary study of human cognition or persons may acquire explicit, symbolically
“cognitive social science” (e.g., DiMaggio mediated culture via a relatively small num-
1997; Patterson 2014; Strauss and Quinn ber of exposures, with the limiting case being
1997; Vaisey 2009). The analytic advantage one-shot, long-term storage in “flashbulb”
of a cognitively grounded conception of the memories (Whitehouse 1996). Memory for
enculturation process comes from its capacity this type of culture is consolidated via fast-
to link distinct pathways and mechanisms of binding neural mechanisms (given the rela-
cultural exposure and transmission to correla- tively low number of exposures necessary for
tively distinct ways culture comes to be stored acquisition) in a declarative memory system
in long-term memory (Smith and DeCoster (Smith and DeCoster 2000). Encoded in this
2000). form, culture may also be accessed and
Following cognitively motivated theories deployed in the same explicit, symbolically
of cultural meaning, I conceive of encultura- mediated format (Kolers and Smythe 1979). I
tion as a process of internalization of experi- refer to this type of culture as declarative cul-
ential patterns encountered in the world via a ture (Patterson 2014:10).
developmental learning process (Tomasello The primary symbolic medium via which
1999). Internalization, in turn, can be thought persons are exposed to declarative culture is
of as the modification (e.g., strengthening or spoken or written language (Tomasello 1999),
weakening of links) of neural pathways con- although other public non-linguistic symbolic
stitutive of memory consolidation processes systems (e.g., audio-visual codes, iconic sym-
(Changeux 1997), entailing the encoding and bols, ritual performance) may also serve as a
storage of cultural knowledge in functionally conduit for the transmission and internaliza-
and physiologically distinct memory systems tion of declarative culture. Most forms of
(Whitehouse 1996). When subject to an inter- declarative culture therefore consist of “know-
nalization process, culture becomes a (rela- thats” stored in a semantic memory system
tively) enduring part of a person’s knowledge (Martin and Chao 2001), with declarative
repertoire (Lizardo and Strand 2010). know-thats constituting (lay or folk) knowl-
A key insight of recent work on memory edge in the phenomenological sense (Berger
systems is that different forms of knowledge and Luckmann 1966). Semantic knowledge is
are differentially encoded such that they are usually impersonal and thus mainly stated as
dissociable. That is, even when it comes to propositions about the world, at varying
the same domain, knowledge encoded in one degrees of abstraction, without explicit refer-
form may be lost but other forms may be ence to individual experience (e.g., “in the
retained. Even when both forms are present, United States, doing well in school leads to
one knowledge structure may be activated better jobs”). For instance, when political sci-
without implying the necessary activation of entists query persons as to whether they know
the other form. The mode of cultural encod- who their congressional representative is
ing is connected to cognitive process, because (Zaller 1992), they are trying to access declar-
the way that culture is accessed, retrieved, ative culture in the political domain stored in
and ultimately used is systematically influ- semantic memory (i.e., political knowledge).
enced by the format in which it is encoded in In the same way, when sociologists ask per-
the first place. sons to report what national or world events
are especially significant (Schuman and Scott
1989), they are trying to access mnemonic
Declarative and Nondeclarative
knowledge stored in autobiographically sig-
Pathways of Cultural Acquisition
nificant semantic forms.
Declarative culture. A key premise of the As is the case of the “collected memories”
model to be proposed is that, in its personal reported by large segments of the population,
state, culture may take two empirically and declarative culture is distinctive in that it is
92 American Sociological Review 82(1)

capable of retaining a high degree of fine- learning” pathway in the form of implicit,
grained detail in relation to the original encod- durable, cognitive-emotive associations, bod-
ing experience. Declarative culture is also ily comportments, and perceptual and motor
“intentional”: it is about (points to) entities, skills built from repeated long-term exposure
persons, events, objects, happenings, and to consistent patterns of experience (Bourdieu
experiences in the world (Searle 1983). The 1990; Cohen and Leung 2009; Wacquant
term “world” should be understood in the phe- 2004). This culture retains very little of the
nomenological sense to include, in addition to detail of each of the exposure episodes, keep-
the commonsense world of the here-and-now, ing only the experiential structure that is com-
imaginary, presumed, possible, theoretical, mon across each episode. The resulting
previously experienced, counterfactual, or knowledge produced by the slow encultura-
temporally and spatially distal “worlds” tion process is not structured according to
(Schutz 1967). In addition to being inten- semantic or logical links among explicit sym-
tional, declarative culture has the potential to bolic elements. Instead, this variant of the
be phenomenologically transparent, in the enculturation process leaves behind recurrent
sense of being open to inspection via reflec- linkages based on patterns of physical and
tive cognitive acts (Heiskala 2011). Persons perceptual similarity and spatial and temporal
not only “know” declarative culture, but upon contiguity (Strauss and Quinn 1997). Ulti-
reflection, may also “know that they know it.” mately, this culture is stored for later use in a
Declarative culture is normally accessed, nondeclarative memory system; accordingly,
and thus put to use, in a deliberate (slow), I refer to this type of culture as nondeclarative
linear fashion (as in the construction of life culture (Patterson 2014:11).
narratives or motivational justifications), and The acquisition and internalization of non-
in the case of declarative culture used for such declarative culture differs from declarative
tasks as reasoning, evaluation, judgment, and culture in both the mode of exposure and the
categorization. In these cases, persons are mode of encoding. This means that the latter
aware of applying explicit criteria or rules differs from the former in how it is put to use.
(Sloman 1996). This may involve chaining First, in terms of the mode exposure, persons
together a series of cultural chunks to produce can acquire nondeclarative culture only via
a judgment (e.g., working out the reasoning slow learning (habituation and enskillment)
steps that lead to a given conclusion). Exam- processes after a (relatively) large number of
ples of such judgments are evaluating an repeated encodings; this is different from
action as proper or improper using explicit declarative culture, which may be acquired
ethical rules or deciding that a given token via fast memory binding even after a single
belongs to a certain type using overt assign- experience (Smith and DeCoster 2000). Sec-
ment criteria (Margolis 1987:73). Persons ond, nondeclarative culture may be internal-
also use declarative culture when producing ized (and later elicited), without explicit
justifications for their public stances and symbolic mediation, directly via experiential
commitments, spinning out vocabularies of correlations or manipulation of the body
motive (Mills 1940) and generating post hoc (Cohen and Leung 2009). This differs from
justificatory rationalizations for their actions declarative culture, which requires some form
(Vaisey 2009). Declarative culture is also of symbolically (e.g., linguistically) mediated
elicited when persons report their normative interaction to be internalized (Strauss and
commitments and aspirations or when they Quinn 1997).3 Third, nondeclarative culture
deliberate about different courses of action is not stored in a format that is akin to exter-
and future projects (Mische 2009). nal symbols (Kolers and Smythe 1979).
Instead, nondeclarative culture is stored in the
Nondeclarative culture. On the other form of a complex multimodal and multidi-
hand, persons may acquire culture via a “slow mensional network of associations between a
Lizardo 93

large number of subsymbolic elements, each outside the action contexts under which it was
of which has a close link to experience initially acquired. Because nondeclarative
(Strauss and Quinn 1997). culture has an underlying associationist basis,
The underlying neural imagery is that of it is usually deployed online in a fast (effort-
Hebbian learning: when two neurons (or neu- less) mode; this is in contrast to declarative
ronal systems) fire together they wire together, culture, which usually requires relatively high
and the more often they fire together the levels of attention, motivation, and cognitive
stronger the link becomes and the slower it capacity (e.g., activation and temporary reten-
decays over time. The underlying cognitive tion in a short-term memory store) to be
imagery is that of connectionist models and deployed (Strack and Deutsch 2004).
knowledge accessibility via “spreading acti-
vation” and “soft constraint satisfaction” in a
Public Culture, Declarative Culture,
network of cognitive associations (Kunda and
and Nondeclarative Culture
Thagard 1996). Finally, nondeclarative cul-
ture has the potential to be accessed and In this section, I link the analytic distinction
deployed, ultimately affecting action, cogni- between declarative and nondeclarative cul-
tion, emotion, and judgment via fast (non- ture with the higher-order distinction between
reflective, intention-independent) pathways culture made manifest at the level of the indi-
(Strack and Deutsch 2004). vidual, namely personal culture, and culture
Skill acquisition is the prototypical exam- externalized in the form of public symbols,
ple of nondeclarative enculturation (see Wac- discourses, and institutions, that is, public
quant 2004), although the same mechanism is culture (Patterson 2014; Strauss and Quinn
behind the acquisition of the “implicit associa- 1997).4 This is meant to combat the often-
tions” and “implicit attitudes” that have noted tendency to use the term “culture” in
become the bread and butter of social and unqualified, undifferentiated, generic, and
cognitive psychology for the past two decades ultimately analytically unproductive ways,
(Shepherd 2011). In the same way, the extrac- thus obscuring the relation between different
tion of an implicit categorical schema from a cultural elements.
large number of exposures to category mem- The resulting cross-classification is shown
bers, allowing persons to classify via “family in Figure 1, a diagram modeled after similar
resemblance” rather than the application of branching depictions in the literature on mem-
explicit rules, is made possible through nonde- ory systems (e.g., Squire 2004). The first
clarative structures acquired via slow inter- branch splits the public and personal facets of
nalization processes (Rosch and Mervis 1975). culture. At the second level, the rightmost
Once acquired, nondeclarative culture sub- branch splits the declarative and nondeclara-
sists as a resource to be applied to action situ- tive forms of culture at the personal level. We
ations that bear a structured similarity to could imagine further splits along the declara-
those in which the relevant associations were tive and nondeclarative leaves (and further
formed. Persons thus deploy nondeclarative splits in types of public culture, such as sym-
culture “online” and in real time, as a result of bolic versus material), but I stop at two levels
perceiving an environmental prompt or open- for the sake of simplicity, economy of presen-
ing that requires a response (e.g., categorizing tation, and relevance to the present argument.5
a person by gender and race when encounter- The classification outlined in Figure 1
ing them for the first time). This is in contrast clarifies something that is usually not explic-
to declarative culture, which, due to its encod- itly articulated in existing formulations. As
ing as (relatively) context-free representa- Figure 2 shows, any attempt at cultural analy-
tions, can also be used for “offline” processes sis must consider, either implicitly or explic-
of reasoning, planning, imagining, anticipat- itly, at least three sets of relations between
ing, remembering, justifying, and narrating cultural elements. Recent theoretical efforts
94 American Sociological Review 82(1)

Figure 1. Branching Diagram Depicting the Distinction between Declarative Culture,


Nondeclarative Culture, and Public Culture

Figure 2. “Cultural Triangle” Depicting Three Sets of Relations among Cultural Elements

have been characterized by a tendency to which analysts are not even clear on what
privilege only one set of dyadic considera- they actually disagree on, and are speaking
tions at a time. While there is nothing wrong past one another as each emphasizes their
in principle with a strong argument for the preferred set of relations without articulating
substantive primacy of any one set of rela- this clearly (see, e.g., Swidler 2008; Vaisey
tions depicted, these arguments have to be 2008).
made in the context of a careful consideration For instance, proposals such as Vaisey’s
of the full set of relations as a whole. Mini- (2009) dual process model are primarily con-
mizing or excluding one set of relations from cerned with the (a) relation of declarative and
explanatory primacy is an argument that has nondeclarative cultural elements at the per-
to be made explicitly, taking into considera- sonal level. This type of account (strategi-
tion both analytic warrant and empirical ade- cally) deemphasizes the public/personal
quacy. Otherwise, we end up in a situation in interface (Swidler 2008). The most explicitly
Lizardo 95

Table 1. Relation between Public, Declarative, and Nondeclarative Forms of Culture in


Classical and Contemporary Cultural Theory

Declarative Nondeclarative Public


Declarative Normativist Functionalism Strong Program
   
Nondeclarative Dual Process Strong Practice Theory
   
Public Toolkit Theory Semiotic Practice Theory  

Note: Perspectives in gray shaded cells presuppose a strong coupling between row and column
categories; unshaded cells presuppose a weak coupling.

elaborated aspect of Swidler’s (2001a) sometimes making an ambiguous nod toward


“toolkit” approach, on the other hand, is con- both sides. Three sets of relations between
cerned with the (b) relation between the cultural elements, each with a bipolar struc-
declarative commitments reported by her ture, results in six analytic possibilities. These
informants and public codes and institutions. are depicted in Table 1. The table cross-clas-
Her analysis, however, only partially theo- sifies each of the three forms of culture
rizes (although it strongly nods toward) the against one another, ignoring the reflexive
nondeclarative/public linkage, especially in (diagonal) cells. Shaded cells (upper triangle)
pointing to the role of “cultured competences” depict approaches that are concerned with
and skills in relation to external cultural scaf- theorizing strong coupling; unshaded cells
folds (Lizardo and Strand 2010). Finally, (lower triangle) list approaches primarily
most forms of practice theory, from Bourdieu concerned with theorizing weak coupling.6
(1990), to Sewell (2005), to Biernacki (1995), The table makes clear that extant theoretical
to the “cultured competences” aspects of perspectives in cultural analysis are con-
Swidler’s toolkit model, concern themselves cerned with either the interface between per-
with the (c) relation between hard to articu- sonal culture (in either its declarative or
late commitments (in the form of cultural nondeclarative forms) and public culture, or
practices) and public culture, whether this the within-person relation between different
latter element is conceived as “fields” (in forms of culture. In addition, theorists may be
Bourdieu), “semiotic structures” (in Sewell), concerned with theorizing either decoupling
systems of accounting and production (in or coupling phenomena across these different
Biernacki), or “codes, contexts, and institu- forms of culture.
tions” (in Swidler). As noted at the outset, Accordingly, Vaisey’s (2009) dual process
however, these variants of practice theory model is best thought of as emphasizing the
falter when it comes to offering a coherent weak coupling between the two different
formulation of how declarative commitments forms of personal culture. One part of
link to action within fields independently of Swidler’s (2001a, 2001b) most recent articu-
nondeclarative practices, and in specifying lation of the toolkit perspective deals with the
the within-person dynamics governing the weak coupling between declarative commit-
relation between declarative and nondeclara- ments at the personal level and institutions at
tive knowledge (on this last score, see the public level.7 Practice theory shows up in
Leschziner and Green 2013). two guises, depending on whether the analyst
Further complexities (and misunderstand- emphasizes weak or strong coupling between
ings) emerge because any one of the three sets nondeclarative and public culture (Patterson
of relations may be characterized as a form of 2014).8 Some forms of “semiotic practice
weak or strong coupling, with different ana- theory,” evident in the work of analysts such
lysts emphasizing one side of this polarity or as Biernacki (1995), emphasize the weak
96 American Sociological Review 82(1)

coupling between unarticulated techniques characterized by the much maligned proposal


embedded in material practices and explicitly of a strong coupling (almost fusion) between
institutionalized systems of commensura- declarative commitments (e.g., values) and
tion.9 To the extent that Swidler’s appeal to nondeclarative culture (e.g., need disposi-
“cultured capacities” and “strategies of tions) at the personal level (Swidler 2001b).11
action” can be read as a nod toward nonde- The fact that we can locate most schools or
clarative culture, the toolkit approach can also proposals in contemporary cultural analysis
be considered a theory concerned with the today within a space defined by such a decep-
weak coupling relation between nondeclara- tively simple set of distinctions speaks to the
tive culture and public cultural codes; as a face validity of the proposed classification. In
form of semiotic practice theory, this weak essence, the proposed set of distinctions
coupling approach has been endorsed by makes analytically clear what previous ana-
Sewell (2005). lysts have rendered in obtuse, incomplete,
In Bourdieu (1990) and related work, ren- and confusing ways. Of course, with parsi-
dered under the label “strong practice theory,” mony comes some level of analytic aggrega-
the emphasis is on the strong coupling (e.g., tion. Note that this organizing portrayal of
ontological complicity) between nondeclara- current strands of cultural analysis as revolv-
tive skills and cognitive structures at the per- ing around three sets of relations is premised
sonal level and the public contours of fields on the simplifying assumption of a single
and institutions at the public level (Lizardo unitary analytic category referred to as “pub-
and Strand 2010). The “strong program” of lic culture.” While this is sufficient for our
cultural analysis (e.g., Alexander 2003) analytic purposes, it is important to point out
emphasizes the (obviously) strong coupling that it is insufficient for any compelling
between declarative discursive commitments attempt to apply the scheme to concrete
at the personal level and public cultural codes. empirical cases, since most analysts (implic-
This strategy is also followed by most forms itly or explicitly) distinguish between differ-
of “culturalist” analysis in cognitive sociol- ent facets of public culture (e.g., Eliasoph and
ogy (Brekhus 2007). Eliasoph and Lichter- Lichterman 2003; Swidler 2001a). However,
man (2003) respond to various empirical it is also important to keep in mind that any
inadequacies in such strong programs by pro- conceptual disaggregation of public culture
posing their own weak coupling account into more than one facet (as suggested by
between public culture and declarative dis- Sewell [2005] or Patterson [2014]) would
course (a form of semiotic practice theory). In increase the analytic burden to a considera-
their formulation, the semantics of public tion of a larger set of relations between cul-
codes may fail to match the declarative impli- tural elements and runs the risk of introducing
cations drawn by persons in context, because unjustifiable levels of analytic complexity.
this link is mediated via the (interactive) For instance, if an analyst were to distin-
deployment of a form of nondeclarative cul- guish between facets of public culture that
ture that they refer to as “group style.” themselves happen to be objectifications of
Sewell’s (2005) version of semiotic practice personal culture in its declarative mode (e.g.,
theory, like Swidler’s, can be considered a textual materials, codified rules) and those
more ambiguous argument, as he offers a that come closer to objectifications of nonde-
contingency theory in which, depending on clarative skills and competences (e.g., mate-
circumstances, we may observe either strong rial culture, artifacts, implicit rules), then the
or weak coupling between nondeclarative analyst would be forced to consider six rela-
cultural practices and public semiotic struc- tions among cultural elements. Some rela-
tures.10 Finally, the normativist-functionalist tions cut across the public/personal divide
theory of action (Parsons 1951), against while remaining in the same mode (e.g., the
which the original version of the toolkit argu- relation between declarative culture at the
ment was initially forged (Swidler 1986), is personal level and the implicit component of
Lizardo 97

public culture and institutions), some require basic proposal is that rather than being the
a consideration of cross-mode relations result of a tug of war between cognitive and
among elements at the same level (e.g., emotive systems, weak coupling (dissocia-
implicit and explicit facets of public culture; tion) between declarative and nondeclarative
as in Geertz 1973), and another set requires a commitments at the personal level emerges as
consideration of relations between elements a natural outcome of the dual enculturation
that cut across both location and mode bound- pathways detailed earlier. To make this insight
aries (e.g., the relation between nondeclara- productive, I introduce a novel theoretical
tive competences at the personal level and the vocabulary useful for understanding these
explicit facet of institutions). processes. In this way, my argument can be
read as a reformulated case for the weak
within-person coupling of declarative and
The Relationship between Declarative
nondeclarative culture, in which both facets
and Nondeclarative Culture
of personal culture are conceived as equally
Having clarified how extant approaches in worthy of the labels “cultural” and “cogni-
cultural analysis fit into the set of analytic tive” without implying any strong hiatus
distinctions that I propose, in this section, I between these two statuses. The wager is that
provide a reconstruction of the theoretically after having secured an understanding of the
crucial (a) relation depicted in Figure 2. Most origins and consequences of weak coupling
cultural analysts have devoted sustained between the declarative and nondeclarative
attention to the relationship between personal dimensions of personal culture (relation (a) in
culture (in either its declarative or nonde- Figure 2), we will be in a better position to
clarative forms) and how it relates to public theorize how both relate to public systems of
culture (the (b) and (c) relations). However, cultural symbols, codes, and institutions (rela-
contemporary cultural theory continues to tions (b) and (c)).
suffer from a lack of clear theorizing of the
within-person relationship between declara-
Correspondence, Redundancy,
tive and nondeclarative culture (Strauss and
and Dissociation
Quinn 1997), with Vaisey’s (2009) dual pro-
cess proposal having done a lot to bring atten- The correspondence principle. A mis-
tion to this issue. The key problem here is that leading premise in contemporary cultural
Vaisey’s memorable formulation of this link- theory has been to presume there is a single
age, built around the “warring systems” per- way in which persons encode knowledge in
spective proposed in Haidt’s (2012:46) long-term memory: namely, in quasi-linguistic
Platonic imagery of the struggle between the format.12 This linguistic fallacy is misleading
nondeclarative “elephant” and the declarative to the extent that it prompts analysts to elide
“rider,” may have led to more confusion than the nondeclarative/declarative distinction and
enlightenment. The key analytic issue here is fail to consider their interrelation. It is also
the unwarranted presumption that the process methodologically harmful to the extent that it
via which nondeclarative culture is put to use fosters the practice of analyzing textual
is characterized by involuntary “hot” or responses, or even creative readings of non-
“emotive” cognition, whereas the process of verbal cues provided by co-presence (e.g.,
declarative cultural use is characterized by Pugh 2013), as giving unproblematic access
“cold” cognition under voluntary control. to nondeclarative culture-in-use (Jerolmack
In what follows, I develop a model of the and Khan 2014).
relationship between declarative and nonde- I propose that we substitute the single-
clarative culture that goes beyond the limita- encoding premise with the principle of corre-
tions of the warring systems formulation and spondence between the mode of exposure and
separates issues of cultural acquisition from the mode of encoding, such that culture
issues of cultural process and cultural use. My becomes personal in a format that matches how
98 American Sociological Review 82(1)

it is encountered in the world without having to course, once a person becomes an expert, she
be transduced into a common code (Ignatow may draw on the declarative representation of
2007). This implies that cultural knowledge the skill for purposes of teaching or serving as
encountered in explicit forms and internalized a role model for a novice (Holland 1992). The
via fast-binding pathways after a small number two forms are potentially dissociable, in the
of exposures will be encoded as declarative sense that the declarative representation can
culture, whereas cultural knowledge encoun- be lost, replaced, modified, or elaborated,
tered in experiential, multimodal forms inter- without necessarily interfering with the non-
nalized as embodied skills and implicit representational competence.
associations via slow-learning pathways will be The redundant nature of personal culture
encoded as nondeclarative culture. carries important implications for how we
conceptualize the connection between culture
Redundant encoding and dissocia- and action. As outlined earlier, different expe-
tion. The fact that encultured persons tend to riential histories at the personal level result in
have access to cultural knowledge about the distinct modes of encoding of cultural knowl-
same domain in declarative and nondeclarative edge. The mode of encoding determines the
formats follows from the correspondence prin- type of settings in which personal knowledge
ciple. Rather than restricting themselves to will be activated. The context of activation
mapping cultural knowledge about a given modulates the way that knowledge is
domain in single-purpose formats, persons accessed, which in turn constrains how this
appear to follow the principle of redundant cultural knowledge may be used. In this way,
encoding (Karmiloff-Smith 1995). This fol- the mode of exposure has an indirect effect
lows naturally from the existence of multiple (via encoding) on the way that cultural knowl-
pathways to enculturation at the personal level, edge is actually implicated in the structuring
resulting in distinct, or dissociable, modes of of everyday action.
familiarity with any given domain. Dissocia- For instance, persons may have a very nar-
bility implies a weak coupling between the row exposure to a domain of experience
different forms of personal culture. because this exposure is primarily textual or
The notions of redundant encoding and linguistic, relying on fast-binding memory
dissociation are not obscure or mysterious. In mechanisms requiring only a small number of
fact, most cultural analysts are at least implic- exposures. This personal culture will thus be
itly familiar with the phenomenon of redun- encoded in explicit form mediated by public
dant encoding and dissociation in the case of symbols. This (largely semantic) knowledge
skill acquisition (Wacquant 2004). The basic then becomes available to persons in a form
observation is that novices rely on explicit that matches the one in which it was origi-
rules and strategies when they are beginning nally presented (as declarative discourse) but
to acquire a skill (a declarative form of cul- not in other forms (as skillful practice). Per-
tural knowledge), but they are able to dis- sons usually evince semantic knowledge of a
pense with this form of representation once given domain by the production of offline
the skill has become embodied and can be declarations related to that domain, which can
deployed automatically (Dreyfus 2004). Of be characterized as its form of expertise (Col-
primary importance is the observation that lins and Evans 2008). Most importantly, this
rule-based declarative knowledge about the is also how declarative culture becomes avail-
skill does not disappear when the nondeclara- able for analysts when they elicit it in a
tive competence is perfected. Instead, both default setting that mirrors its conditions of
exist as redundant personal representations of acquisition and use (Eliasoph and Lichterman
cultural knowledge in that domain, but only 2003:743). The capacity to produce these
one of them (the nondeclarative encoding) is declarations does not imply that persons also
central for the production of skilled action. Of have the nondeclarative knowledge useful for
Lizardo 99

the production of online performances neces- redescribed” into declarative formats, and
sary to navigate that same domain. social scientists can use methods that facili-
This implies that, depending on the exist- tate this redescription (McDonnell 2014).
ence of overlapping histories of familiarity However, this labor of redescription not only
with a domain, knowledge may be encoded in requires motivation, inclination, effort, and
formats that allow for the retrieval and use of opportunity (all facilitated by external condi-
declarative knowledge, or in ways that are tions), it also entails a partial removal of the
keyed to the elicitation of nondeclarative cul- features of nondeclarative culture that render
ture and thus resist this sort of redescription it close to action. In this sense, redescription
into discursive form. More commonly, per- should not be mistaken for the one-to-one
sonal culture will be encoded in overlapping translation of nondeclarative culture into
formats. This is especially likely in institu- declarative forms, nor for a pristine mirroring
tional domains within which individuals have or mapping of one form of culture via the
had sufficiently rich experiential history. These other.
distinct modalities of personal culture may be In this way, the mechanisms of redundancy
layered by order of acquisition if the person is and structured dissociation at the personal
exposed to distinct ways of encoding knowl- level open up two distinct (ideal-typical) ways
edge about a given domain over time. That is, in which declarative and nondeclarative cul-
the existence of a given form of encoding does ture may relate to the world of public culture.
not determine whether some other form will One possibility is that persons may behavio-
also be present or absent. Only the specific his- rally master, via the slow-learning pathway, a
tory of enculturation in a given domain deter- set of nondeclarative cultured capacities keyed
mines the form of encoding of personal culture. to action that allows them to skillfully navi-
Persons may not only know more than they can gate, reproduce, and even modify, via the
tell (Polanyi 1966); they may also be able to same acquired patterns, objectified cultural
tell more than they know how (Jerolmack and realms (relation (c) in Figure 1). However,
Khan 2014; Swidler 2001a). when there is routine access and use of this
nondeclarative cultural knowledge, individu-
als may not possess the skills, motivation, or
Implications
habitual inclination to produce declarative
To summarize, a key substantive implication (meta) knowledge about this mastery. Here we
of the theoretical proposal I outlined is that find a substantial store of nondeclarative cul-
the two main forms in which personal culture ture without the accompanying declarative
presents itself to the analyst at the personal knowledge about it; cultural know-how is not
level—culture as declarative know-that and available for redescription as explicit verbal
culture as nondeclarative know-how—are statements and which does not relate to the
partially (and in many cases completely) dis- world of public culture via the usual referen-
sociable. Persons can display declarative abil- tial relations. This is culture that persons know
ities to produce knowledge about (public) how to use, but which lacks reflective phe-
culture that they do not know how to use nomenological transparency (Heiskala 2011);
(Collins and Evans 2008; Swidler 2001a), or that is, persons are unable to report that they
they may possess implicit cultural skills with know how to use this culture (a fact that might
no publicly accessible declarative counterpart be obvious to an outside observer). This type
(Bourdieu 1990; Polanyi 1966). of non-verbalizable culture may come to
This does not imply that there is an acquire objective phenomenological validity
unbridgeable phenomenological or practical as simply “the way that things are.” Geertz
hiatus between the two modalities of personal (1975) and Swidler refer to this as “common
culture. Instead, as cognitive scientist Annette sense,” and Bourdieu (1990) calls it “doxa”:
Karmiloff-Smith (1995) notes, nondeclara- nondeclarative knowledge so taken for granted
tive culture could be “representationally that it never rises to conscious awareness, and
100 American Sociological Review 82(1)

when it does, it is in the form of (practically If semiotic practice theorists are right, and
useless and generally self-contradictory) tau- such heterogeneity, contestation, and multi-
tologies or pithy (seemingly self-evident) ver- plicity at the level of semiotic codes is the
bal formulae. rule rather than the exception (Sewell 2005),
We can also envision a different (and ana- then weak coupling at the personal level is
lytically crucial) relationship between public overdetermined both by routine dynamics of
and personal culture: the case in which per- cultural acquisition and by vicissitudes of
sons are able to produce declarative “knowl- linkage across the personal/public interface
edge that” without a corresponding set of under high variability regimes.
nondeclarative capacities allowing them to Finally, it is a basic premise of contempo-
produce skillful performances in context rary cultural theory to deny that culture can be
(Collins and Evans 2008). Because of experi- systematic at the personal level (Swidler
ential and ontogenetic limits on the develop- 2001a). While this may be an eminently rea-
ment of nondeclarative culture (e.g., the sonable proposal (DiMaggio 1997), analysts
repeated exposure constraint), this state of seldom propose a principled account for why
affairs is in fact the norm when it comes to the this is the modal case. The theory of corre-
majority of personal knowledge about public spondence between exposure and encoding
culture (relation (b) in Figure 1). Here, we does this in a principled way. Rather than
encounter a situation in which culture that is being organized into corresponding within-
external to persons, and which persons may person systems whereby the presence of one
be quite capable of reporting knowing about, modality of personal culture implies the pres-
is not really implicated in their everyday ence of another modality, personal culture is
activities, exhibiting what an outside observer linked to experience and has no inherent sys-
may note as a loose coupling in relation to tematic ordering, although the environment
action (Swidler 2001a). Persons may have may be organized (e.g., via public institution-
developed the declarative capacity to produce alization processes) to elicit such ordering
talk about this culture and to orient them- (Martin 2010). Talk of institutional domains
selves to the objective existence of this cul- (e.g., art, politics, religion) as “cultural sys-
ture (e.g., they know that it exists, they orient tems” (e.g., Geertz 1973) is misleading to the
their strategies of action around this knowl- extent that the systematic nature of a cultural
edge, and they even might know that other domain is seen as inherent in the nature of
persons can use this culture proficiently), but public symbols as such and separated from
this knowledge is not stored or encoded for the relevant experiential contexts and from a
themselves as “how” knowledge. concrete history of acquisition. Accordingly,
The payoff of theorizing the mechanisms a systematic experiential history may produce
governing the relationship between different systematic traces at the personal level, but an
forms of culture at the personal level becomes unsystematic, haphazard one will not lead to
evident once we consider the possibility that such traces.
whether we find strong or weak coupling
between these elements may depend on how
both interface with public culture. For Shedding Light on
instance, Harding (2007) shows that the exist- Substantive Issues
ence of a multiplicity of possibly conflicting Given the relatively abstract nature of the
behavioral codes at the level of public culture foregoing discussion, in what follows I pro-
facilitates dissociation at the personal level vide a concrete exemplification of the ana-
between declarative commitments and nonde- lytic gains that can come from deploying the
clarative cultural practices. This is an instance theoretical vocabulary developed here to
in which dissociation emerges as a byproduct make sense of some outstanding empirical
of heterogeneity at the level of public culture. and substantive problems in the fields of
Lizardo 101

racial stratification and education, and culture the educational stratification literature: in
and inequality studies. These are subfields spite of having comparable aspirations and
that borrow cultural theory to shed light on subjective assessments of their academic
their own empirical problems (Carter 2005; competence, substantial gaps exist in achieve-
Lamont and Small 2008; Lareau 2011; Liu ment and the likelihood of making educa-
and Xie 2016; Skrentny 2008; Small, Hard- tional transitions for black and Hispanic
ing, and Lamont 2010). We will see that vari- youths in comparison to white youths in the
ous explanatory puzzles emerge here due to United States. Conversely, in spite of having
borrowing precisely the sort of cultural theory relatively modest aspirations and self-assessments
that deploys one-size-fits-all conceptions of of competence, Asian American youth (on
cultural acquisition and use. These puzzles average) outperform white youth (Kao 2000;
dissolve, and substantive insight is achieved, Kao and Tienda 1998).
once we consistently apply the distinctions The gap between declarative commitments
formulated and theorized in the preceding and on-the-ground performance for minority
sections. youth is puzzling on two theoretical fronts.
First, the classic line of research foundational
for the “Wisconsin model” of educational
Ethnoracial Inequality in Educational
attainment developed during the 1960s and
Outcomes
1970s found aspirations to be a consistent
The achievement-aspiration “paradox.” predictor of future behavioral outcomes. This
Attempts to incorporate culture into our under- linkage is now so tenuous that education
standing of ethnoracial inequality in educa- researchers today doubt whether survey items
tional outcomes in the United States have tapping aspirations are capable of capturing
suffered analytically due to a penchant to use the relevant behavioral factors in the contem-
the term “culture” almost exclusively to refer porary context (Kao and Thompson 2003).
to declarative discourses, relegating (with Second, the line of anthropological work on
some notable exceptions) nondeclarative com- “oppositional culture” elaborated by Ogbu
petences to the status of an extra-cultural fac- and collaborators from the late 1970s to the
tor. This is in spite of the fact that these carry late 1990s (Fordham and Ogbu 1986; Ogbu
the bulk of the explanatory weight at the end 1978, 1987; Ogbu and Simons 1998) seemed
of the day (e.g., Ainsworth-Darnell and to propose a straightforward mechanism link-
Downey 1998; Harris and Robinson 2007; ing group-based differences in outcomes to
Hsin and Xie 2014). This has led to the prolif- group-based differences in (mostly declara-
eration of explanatory “paradoxes” (Downey tive) cultural commitments.
2008; Farkas, Lleras, and Maczuga 2002; Kao
and Thompson 2003), rising skepticism that “Oppositional culture” theory. Accord-
culture “matters” for understanding large- ing to the oppositional culture account, mem-
scale group differences in educational out- bers of certain ethnoracial minorities (e.g.,
comes (Harris 2006; Tyson, Darity, and historically enslaved “involuntary migrants”),
Castellino 2005), and selective usages of “cul- would come to develop a set of adaptive cul-
tural” explanations for an arbitrary range of tural patterns that alienate them from the
cases (Hsin and Xie 2014; Liu and Xie 2016; achievement-oriented values of the dominant
Zhou and Lee 2014). In spite of this, a consid- (in the case of the United States) white cul-
eration of the vicissitudes of cultural explana- ture. The most important elements of this
tion in the educational stratification literature cultural pattern consist of skepticism and
holds several important lessons that all cul- cynicism toward educational institutions, and
tural analysts would be wise to heed. adaptive expectations and aspirations for suc-
The basic empirical mystery has now cess that fall below those of the more advan-
acquired the status of a canonical finding in taged majority group (Ogbu 2003). Black
102 American Sociological Review 82(1)

youth in the United States, according to this consistent evidence can be found that high-
account, do not link achievement- performing black students face a “burden of
oriented behaviors with success in school and acting white” by being ostracized, teased, or
beyond, as they see the game rigged against dismissed by their same-race peers (Ainsworth-
them regardless of the effort they put in. Darnell and Downey 1998; Downey 2008;
Alienated from dominant institutions, black Tyson et al. 2005).
youth develop a set of counter-normative atti-
tudes that end up depressing their academic “Asian values” theory. Another conse-
performance in relation to their white coun- quence of lack of theorizing the independent
terparts. To make matters worse, black youth roles of declarative, nondeclarative, and pub-
who do take up the achievement-oriented lic cultural elements (and their relations) is
values and aspirations of the white majority that in addition to paradox, we may also end
culture are predicted to be brought back in up with a situation in which cultural explana-
line via a peer-enforced social control mecha- tions emphasizing the link between declara-
nism linking these behaviors with lack of tive commitments, action, and performance
loyalty to the ethnoracial in-group. In other are deployed in blatantly selective ways. At
words, high-achieving minorities have the the same time that cultural models emphasiz-
“burden of acting white.” ing declarative elements are increasingly
Although initially developed using intui- shunned for their failure to shed light on
tive interpretations of ethnographic data white/black (and sometimes white/Hispanic)
(Fordham and Ogbu 1986), oppositional cul- differences in school performance, they are
ture theory makes explicit predictions regard- all the rage in studies dealing with the rela-
ing the link between declarative commitments, tively higher performance of Asian American
public culture, and action. In fact, almost all students in relation to white students (e.g.,
of the cultural mechanisms postulated in the Liu and Xie 2016).13
oppositional culture account rely on declara- Accordingly, we find a growing cottage
tive cultural elements, such as beliefs, atti- industry of studies purporting to explain the
tudes, and explicitly formulated folk theories superior performance of Asian students by
as to the functioning and linkage of dominant pointing to a whole slew of cultural factors.
institutions (Harris 2006). In this account, According to this line of work, Asians outper-
“sayings,” in the form of explicit declarations form whites because Asian students “prior-
of oppositional culture values and beliefs, itize self-reliance and achievement,” or are
inexorably lead to “doings,” in the form of more likely to “believe in education,” or are
counter-productive academic behaviors. more liable to feel “a greater obligation to
Researchers have tried to determine their immigrant parents,” or are more likely to
whether the culture-behavior-outcome links report belief “in the value of education for
postulated in the oppositional culture account future socioeconomic mobility,” “have stricter
can be verified using large-scale, population- work ethics,” and so on (Kao and Thompson
level data (Ainsworth-Darnell and Downey 2003:433; see also Hsin and Xie 2014). An
1998; Carter 2005; Tyson et al. 2005). This arbitrary grab bag of differences at the level
work not only generally fails to verify the of declarative culture (linked by purely
empirical linkage between declarative culture semantic relations) is put back on the explan-
and on-the-ground outcomes laid out by oppo- atory pedestal, even when the same type of
sitional culture theorists (e.g., Harris 2006), culture-mediated mechanism is rejected when
but it has instead uncovered a paradox: black it comes to accounting for the underper-
youth seem to have equal or even higher com- formance of African American and Hispanic
mitments to pro-school goals, and they seem students. This is clearly not theoretically
to make a stronger connection between suc- defensible, but it is the inevitable conse-
cess in school and status attainment in adult- quence of the incoherent way in which cul-
hood than do white students. In addition, no ture is conceptualized in this field.
Lizardo 103

However, as with oppositional culture the- understanding of culture deployed by the ana-
ory, the “cultural explanations” trotted out to lyst. In the particular case of oppositional
attempt to account for the Asian/white perfor- culture and Asian values theories, rather than
mance gap do not fare well when confronted being instances of well-conceptualized
with attempts at systematic empirical evalua- approaches that just had the hard-luck to run
tion. For instance, one proposal is that Asian against the facts, their failure has to do with
students outdo white students because of their analytic weakness as cultural theories.
strong cultural beliefs that link effort and Essentially, if you live exclusively by the
achievement, beliefs rooted in a cultural tradi- declarative sword then you die by the declara-
tion of Confucianism that emphasizes people’s tive sword. Insofar as action (and outcomes)
perfectibility via education and self-cultivation is tied to cultured competences, and these
(Jiménez and Horowitz 2013). This explana- competences are generally nondeclarative,
tion, however, runs against the recalcitrant fact then attempting to explain performance dif-
that Asian students outperform white students ferences by linking them to differences in
whether they trace their ethnic ancestry to geo- declarative commitments is like trying to get
graphic regions plausibly construed as charac- water from a rock. The very same lack of
terized by a Confucian heritage (East and variance (oppositional, Confucian, or other-
Southeast Asians) or not (South Asians and wise) in declarative commitments commen-
Filipinos) (Hsin and Xie 2014). surate with the performance differences
alluded to earlier will doom this sort of cul-
tural explanation from the start.
A Reformulation
Beyond paradox. The empirical difficulties Overcoming the strong coupling bias.
encountered by cultural explanations of ethno- The approach proposed here can help disci-
racial inequalities in school performance, pline researchers against the bias of expecting
rather than resulting in head-scratching para- strong coupling between personal and public
dox, contain important lessons for cultural culture or between either of these and differ-
analysis. In the case of the achievement-aspira- ent facets of public culture, when the likely
tion paradox among minority youth, it is clear empirical pattern is a more complex tapestry
that if the analyst departs from a (biased) of weak and strong coupling across different
conception of personal culture as exclusively cultural elements (to be established in each
composed of declarative attitudes and aspira- case). For instance, rather than strong cou-
tions, then said analyst would have a strong pling between declarative and nondeclarative
case for concluding that culture does not mat- culture, and between both of these and public
ter (Tyson et al. 2005). This further implies cultural codes, researchers attempting to test
that something that is not culture—namely, Ogbu’s explanation for achievement gaps
structure (Hays 1994)—should carry the bulk among minority youth found a pattern of
of the explanatory weight. In fact, this is pre- structured dissociation between declarative
cisely the conclusion reached by some post- commitments and nondeclarative compe-
functionalist critical and conflict theorists in tences—and between the first of these ele-
education research. This situation resembles, ments and achievement outcomes on the
for similar analytic reasons, that faced by ground (Farkas et al. 2002).
scholars who would like to bring a more theo- In this way, what appears paradoxical in
retically robust understanding of cultural pro- standard accounts can be made sense of by
cesses into the study of poverty (e.g., Lamont consistently distinguishing between cultural
and Small 2008). elements and specifying their interrelations.
However, this conclusion emerges not From this perspective, the achievement-
from the superior empirical adequacy of aspiration paradox emerges as the natural
structural models, but from the shortsighted result of institutionalization of achievement
104 American Sociological Review 82(1)

discourse at the level of public codes; this facet of public culture should be justified
public/personal coupling (relation (b) in Fig- independently.
ure 2) is manifest as a homogenizing discur- For instance, the fact that we can observe
sive constraint (resulting in a pattern of no seemingly oppositional behaviors decoupled
variance) and chronic accessibility and use of from performance (e.g., high academic per-
institutionalized vocabularies of motive con- formers who rebel against the culture of
stitutive of the American cultural code of schools) should not be surprising (Carter
achievement and success (Downey 2008; 2005): oppositional behaviors and academic
Harris 2006). Because nondeclarative compe- performance are outcomes that pertain to two
tences relevant for school success have an different ways in which personal culture may
independent causal etiology, the discursive interface with the public culture of schools.
homogenization process has the potential to Accordingly, it is quite possible (and in fact to
generate, in some cases, a structured dissocia- be expected) for persons to grind against
tion evident as a contrast between the chronic some aspects of an institution while matching
accessibility, and thus easy elicitation, of others. For instance, when the institutional-
declarative commitments to success and hard ized culture of schools is hostile to students’
work and the lack of availability of the forms lifestyle-based nondeclarative competences
of nondeclarative culture relevant for meeting (e.g., those related to speech, dress, cultural
the expectations of schooling institutions tastes, and interactive styles), both white
(relation (c) in Figure 2). working-class (Lareau 2011) and minority
youth of middle- and working-class prove-
Better specification of linkages nance (Carter 2005) display oppositional and
between cultural elements. Establishing nonconformist behaviors and attitudes. Yet
the distinct causal etiologies of both declara- this oppositional pattern may be empirically
tive discourses and nondeclarative compe- independent of performance as long as the
tences and their links to public culture can relevant nondeclarative academic skills are
help researchers provide more convincing available to the same youth (Harris and Rob-
and empirically adequate accounts of how inson 2007).
culture is implicated in important substantive In the same way, and despite its intuitive
outcomes. This will also allow analysts to appeal, the hypothesis that highly institution-
theorize which absent linkages are actually alized commitments to achievement and suc-
surprising (or paradoxical), which ones we cess are strongly coupled (in an oppositional
should expect as a matter of course, and relationship) to personal declarations of eth-
which ones should be regularly absent. Fur- noracial solidarity among black and Hispanic
thermore, due to the fact that, within persons, youth is false (Carter 2005). Contra Ogbu,
different facets of personal culture can arise there is no analytic reason to expect this oppo-
via independent enculturation pathways, link- sitional link, since these deal with two very
ages of different cultural elements (e.g., of distinct forms of the declarative/public rela-
declarative attitudes and nondeclarative dis- tion. One is tied to chronically accessible
positions) should not be taken as given; declarations of ethnoracial pride typical of
instead, they should always have the status of black and other racialized ethnic minorities in
empirical hypotheses. In this respect, the United States; the other is tied to equally
researchers should be wary of connecting long-standing and universal (across ethnora-
global characterizations of personal culture cial groups) commitments to American ideals
(e.g., summary typologies of attitudinal, dis- of success and achievement. Because these
positional, or behavioral clusters, such as emerge as distinct forms of strong coupling
“oppositional,” “street,” and “decent”), with (and thus declarative homogenization) at the
aspects of public culture and institutions. interface of declarative commitments and
Instead, each linkage between a given ele- institutionalized public codes (Swidler 2001a),
ment of personal culture and a corresponding there is no theoretically defensible reason to
Lizardo 105

expect that they should be negatively corre- nondeclarative competences and the public
lated within persons. Nor is there good reason demands of the institution. This implies that
to expect that declarative commitments to nondeclarative culture may, in some impor-
ethnoracial solidarity should have any relation tant cases, have an indirect effect on declara-
(positive or negative) to nondeclarative prac- tive (non)commitments when it repeatedly
tices productive of achievement and success fails to fit existing public codes, with declara-
in school (Carter 2005). tive non-commitment emerging as a result of
Accordingly, the issue is not that disadvan- this failure to fit (Harris and Robinson 2007;
taged youth possess adaptively rational but Stephens, Markus, and Phillips 2014).14
globally deviant forms of cultural knowledge
as to what it takes to be successful, or that they Overcoming the declarative culture
do not share the same attainment goals and bias. The approach proposed here can also
values as their more advantaged peers. Instead, help discipline researchers against the perva-
the key issue has to do with the mode of sive bias of reserving the (generic) term “cul-
encoding of the kind of cultural knowledge ture” (at either the individual or group level)
that is linked to outcomes. For advantaged only for declarative commitments, while
youth, cultural knowledge required for school ignoring that nondeclarative competences,
success is redundantly encoded in both declar- skills, habits, and nonverbal styles are also
ative and (most crucially) nondeclarative for- deserving of the label, and in some settings
mats. For disadvantaged youth, in contrast, the may be the more relevant cultural mechanism
link between school completion and the attain- to explain a given outcome. In race and edu-
ment of future goals is mainly encoded in cation research, the causal relevance of non-
semantic memory as “know that” knowledge, declarative culture applies to cases of
easily acquired via a small number of expo- under- and over-performance in relation to the
sures and just as easily elicited in the inter- (empirically arbitrary) white norm (Ainsworth-
view situation (see Carter 2005). Because Darnell and Downey 1998; Harris and Robin-
acquisition of nondeclarative knowledge must son 2007; Hsin and Xie 2014).
go through the multiple exposure bottleneck, For instance, Hsin and Xie (2014) find that
it is more demanding in terms of time and a series of nondeclarative cultured compe-
parental resources and thus more tightly linked tences—glossed under the antiseptic terms
to patterns of material advantage and disad- “noncognitive skills,” “self-control,” and
vantage (Lareau 2011; Weininger, Lareau, and “motivation”—are the primary mechanisms
Conley 2015; Zhou and Lee 2014). accounting for the academic advantage over
From these considerations, we can derive white students for all student groups sub-
the often-noted implication that, when it sumed under the Asian label regardless of
comes to situations that require nondeclara- ethno-geographic origin (e.g., East Asian,
tive know-how, especially in the context of South Asian, Filipino). In the same way, oppo-
navigating the established routines of educa- sitional culture researchers find that rather
tional institutions, skill-based background than devaluation and self-destructive opposi-
differences between and within groups should tion on the part of minority youth in relation to
emerge with a vengeance (Carter 2005; Lar- white youth, what exists is a nondeclarative
eau 2011). For disadvantaged minorities, this enculturation gap, especially when it comes to
process is sufficient to generate the often- development of the “cultural skills, habits, and
noted within-person dissociation between styles that are rewarded by teachers” (Downey
declarative “belief” in education and practical 2008:299). Statistically adjusting for differ-
“achievement” (Carter 2005:24). In other ences in previously accumulated (middle
cases, some forms of declarative opposition school) academic skills accounts for the bulk
to dominant values may emerge due to a of the differences in schooling performance
structured mismatch between existing between black and white high-schoolers, even
106 American Sociological Review 82(1)

after adjusting for what have been referred to distinct, class-differentiated “images of the
as oppositional behaviors (Harris and Robin- world.” These images were thought to be
son 2007). These factors, however, are usually accessible via the declarative reports pro-
not classified as cultural in the current litera- vided by informants in response to survey
ture, which reserves this label for the usual items or interview questions. Secondarily,
triad of aspirations, attitudes, and beliefs analysts aimed to provide process-based
allegedly characteristic of cultural groups (Liu explanations of the genesis of these class-
and Xie 2016).15 based orientations in the routine work and
domestic experiences of persons in class-
Beyond groupism. Finally, the approach differentiated societies. Finally, scholars pre-
outlined here has the advantage of allowing sumed that these orientations were passed
the analyst to move beyond the “groupism” down intergenerationally from parents to
sometimes afflicting cultural analysis in cul- children, thus contributing to a status repro-
ture and stratification research (Brubaker duction process (Kohn 1977). More recently,
2002; Zhou and Lee 2014). This tendency is incorporation of theories of practice into our
sometimes magnified by the declarative bias understanding of the genesis of class cultures
and its attendant focus on the discursive com- has enriched this picture by partially sensitiz-
mitments allegedly distinctive of minority ing analysts to the role of nondeclarative
groups composed of taxonomic (usually eth- pathways of enculturation in the creation of
noracial) categories (Liu and Xie 2016; Ogbu structured linkages between class and life
2003). When we hone in on the right set of chances (Lareau 2011).
cultural elements, we are better able to theo- However, as with the literature on race-
rize within- and between-group differences in based educational inequalities considered ear-
orientations and performance (Lareau 2011; lier, conceptual confusion haunts the more
Hsin and Xie 2014). recent incorporation of habit and practice
The example of the rocky careers of oppo- theories into the study of the role of cultural
sitional culture and Asian values theories processes in class-based inequality. This
should not only make analysts wary of focus- ambiguity leads to the emergence of empiri-
ing on the wrong kind of cultural elements, cal patterns that analysts are forced to con-
but it should also sensitize us to always try to ceptualize as paradoxical, absent a more
provide explanatory stories featuring similar precise formulation. The problem comes
kinds of cultural processes to explain within down once again to the deployment of an
and between “group gap” outcomes regard- impoverished theoretical understanding inca-
less of the direction (i.e., positive or negative) pable of distinguishing different modes of
of such outcomes. Maintaining a consistent internalization of personal culture, as well as
distinction between declarative and nonde- the relative absence of an explicit theory of
clarative culture, on the other hand, allows us enculturation capable of dealing coherently
to theorize both disadvantage and advantage with multiple pathways of cultural acquisition
(Carter 2005; Hsin and Xie 2014) by pointing and related dissociation phenomena.
to a unified set of cultural processes and When it comes to theorizing the genesis
mechanisms. and dynamics of class cultures, an emphasis
on structured dissociation and dual encultura-
tion pathways sensitizes the analyst against
Autonomy, Obedience, and Class
the default expectation that there should be
Cultures
strong couplings between sayings and doings
Traditionally, cultural analysts interested in (of either parents or children) within classes.
the origins of class cultures followed Weber Instead, this approach naturally predicts that
in thinking that the primary empirical goal structured disjunctures should exist between
was one of documenting the existence of the public semantics of the declarative
Lizardo 107

culture(s) espoused and transmitted in explicit amount of leisure time spent in structured
form in class-differentiated settings (e.g., (rule-governed) activities under tight adult
self-direction versus conformity; cosmopoli- supervision and control (Weininger and Lar-
tanism and meritocracy) and the pragmatic eau 2009). This type of enculturation occurred
goals of the nondeclarative practices (e.g., via both explicitly symbolized interaction
skillful adaptation to institutionalized adult (e.g., the issuing of verbal directives) and,
authority; performance of ease and natural- most significantly, via the enmeshing of chil-
ness in status attainment) transmitted by both dren in organizational structures endowed
parents and peers via nondeclarative path- with nondeclarative routines centered on the
ways. This is especially the case when it inculcation of habits attuned to the spatial and
comes to the forms of cultural competence temporal rules of the institution, sometimes
that prepare newcomers to navigate dominant involving the direct manipulation of the body,
institutions. a clear index of nondeclarative enculturation
Weininger and Lareau (2009) set out to (Cohen and Leung 2009). When it came to
test Kohn’s (1977) proposal that middle-class children’s leisure, working-class parents, on
parents emphasize a (declarative) orientation the other hand, followed a practical rule of
toward autonomy, self-direction, and freedom autonomy, in which children spent the major-
from control in relation to established author- ity of their time in unstructured self- or peer-
ities and conventions, whereas working-class directed activities with very little in the way of
parents emphasize an orientation toward con- intergenerational interaction. Children from
formity, obedience, and adaptation to extant working-class families had little to no expo-
rule structures. Not surprisingly, their sure to practical enculturation dedicated to
research, triangulating between interview- managing or navigating institutional environ-
based data useful for tapping into explicit ments controlled by adults in authority posi-
declarations and observational data attuned to tions outside the household.
nondeclarative practices, uncovers a paradox: In many ways, working-class children
the Kohn prediction seems to obtain only experience more practical and bodily auton-
when it comes to adult self-reports of parent- omy from adult demands than do their more
ing style and socialization goals or in terms of discursively self-directed middle-class coun-
the declarative utterances verbalized explic- terparts. For Weininger and Lareau (2009:
itly by parents in their interactions with chil- 693), this finding implies that class-based
dren. In these cases, middle-class parents did patterns of enculturation involve “paradoxical
seem to emphasize a language of autonomy pathways” not considered in the Kohn tradi-
and independence (e.g., negotiation with chil- tion. In our terms, however, this state of
dren over rules, emphasizing choice behav- affairs is not paradoxical, because it is quite
ior) and working-class parents did seem to possible to enculture individuals in seemingly
emphasize a discourse of obedience (e.g., contradictory ways as long as this is done via
issuing directives without qualification, justi- distinct enculturation channels (e.g., primar-
fying decisions by reference to positional ily declarative versus nondeclarative). This
authority), especially when it came to inter- type of paradox (or structured dissociation in
generational interactions within households. our terms) is relevant for stratification out-
However, when it came to enculturation comes, because it helps account for the subse-
processes linking children to institutional quent advantage that middle-class children
realms outside the household, middle-class have in navigating and succeeding in middle-
parents spent countless hours attempting to class institutions, in which they are expected
shape the behavioral dispositions of their chil- to negotiate their way through an environ-
dren in a direction of conformity and adapta- ment populated by authority figures in charge
tion to institutional environments populated of dispensing material and symbolic rewards
by adults in authority, and they maximized the (Lareau 2011).
108 American Sociological Review 82(1)

Omnivorousness, Ease, and the value of all forms of cultural expression, they
Culture of Privilege continue to engage ever-expanding sets of
cultural objects in inherently class-marked
A paradox besetting the sociological study of ways.
elite cultures is the rise of what Ollivier These forms of class-differentiated cultural
(2008) once provocatively referred to as engagement are able to survive in spite of
“conspicuous openness to diversity” and what elites lacking a coherent declarative discourse
most analysts, following Peterson and Kern marking them, or even themselves as a group,
(1996), refer to as “omnivorousness.” This is as particularly distinct (Khan 2011). Contem-
the tendency, on the part of contemporary porary elites thus express, in the aesthetic
cultural elites, to claim a multicultural open- domain, the same sort of structured dissocia-
ness to a wide variety of forms of aesthetic tion between declarative and nondeclarative
experience and engagement with a seemingly culture that Vaisey (2009) sees as characteriz-
broad cross-section of types of cultural goods. ing the moral domain of contemporary youth.
Across now countless studies using survey In spite of this hiatus between discourse and
and interview methods to capture the stated competence, there has clearly been a conser-
preferences and associated vocabularies of vation of nondeclarative habits of cultural
motive of elites, researchers find that high- engagement, such that the ways in which
status culture today seems to be characterized elites engage cultural goods is an extension of
by broad-ranging preferences and stated aestheticist practices first developed in the
refusals to express dislikes or rejections of traditional fine arts (Lizardo and Skiles 2012).
specific genres, forms, or objects across a This implies that class-linked forms of
wide range of aesthetic domains (Lizardo and aesthetic appreciation and judgment continue
Skiles 2012). The general phenomenon of to be reliably fostered and transmitted in elite
omnivorousness is thus now a seemingly households, and concomitantly predicted by
intractable issue for any theoretical account the usual markers of privilege and advantage,
that conceives of elites’ nondeclarative cul- without explicit exclusionary reference to
ture as having to follow in lockstep with their other forms of engagement or without the
stated declarative discourses, preferences, concomitant transmission of an elaborate
and motivations. declarative ideology privileging these forms
In contrast to this story, cultural analysts of engagement as superior. As with the case
have observed that in spite of the discursive of the dual transmission of paradoxical class
homogenization around the institutional lan- cultures (Weininger and Lareau 2009), in
guage of multiculturalism, tolerance, respect which the semantics of explicit declarations
for diversity, and non-comparability across do not necessarily match the pragmatic goals
forms of participation, elites continue to of nondeclarative culture, this is a plausible
engage aesthetic objects in ways that seem equilibrium. This also implies that the all too
both class-coded and linked to class-specific common analytic equation of elite declarative
experiences (Khan 2011). When suitably discourses as standing for the culture of elites
prodded, the same elites betray an implicit would result in the unwarranted conclusion
preference for complexity, formal innovation, that class cultures do not make a difference
and a purposive authorial intention in cultural for lifestyle practices (Atkinson 2011). The
works, even when engaging objects and expe- solution to this impasse is that elite culture
riences where these are not to be expected (like other forms of culture imputed to taxo-
(Holt 1998). In this case, while the declara- nomic groups) is an amalgam of both declara-
tive culture of contemporary elites is defi- tive discourses and nondeclarative practices,
nitely attuned to highly institutionalized which are more likely to display strong dis-
discourses regarding the value of inclusion, sociations between semantics and pragmatics
cross-cultural understanding, and the inherent than to exhibit strong coherence and unity.
Lizardo 109

This last claim is supported in studies of acquired, following the correspondence prin-
the contemporary “culture of privilege” ciple, via a mode of exposure bound to pro-
among elites in the United States (Khan 2011; duce the right sort of encoding (know-how)
Khan and Jerolmack 2013). This work has the rather than as declarative culture. This pro-
advantage of getting a closer look at cultural duces structured heterogeneity among privi-
transmission and encoding processes and thus leged youth keyed to an implicit ranking as to
at the experiential origins of weak couplings who can display the nondeclaratively privi-
between declarative and nondeclarative cul- leged forms of ease with the most proficiency.
tural elements. This research reveals system- People who do this, however, are precisely
atic links between the mode of encoding of those who become cultural omnivores capa-
cultural knowledge and subsequent dynamics ble of engaging all forms of experience, but
of cultural use, as well as weak couplings especially potentially aesthetic experience,
between the different cultural elements so with aplomb, assurance, and a sense that the
internalized. Not surprisingly, these take the world is unproblematically open to them
form of structured dissociations between (Khan 2011).
declarative “sayings” and nondeclarative
“doings” and are produced by the discursive
homogenization of declarative commitment Discussion and
mechanisms at the personal/public interface, Concluding Remarks
which we observed in the case of oppositional Roughly eight years ago, in the pages of this
culture theory. journal, Gross (2009:374) noted that:
The most salient manifestation of this phe-
nomenon, and the one Khan (2011) sees as The growth of cultural sociology in recent
constitutive of modern forms of privilege, is years owes little to a pragmatist theory of
that instanced in the declarative endorsement action or mechanisms, but the theory I pro-
of highly institutionalized public codes pro- pose implies a substantially broadened dis-
moting openness, cosmopolitanism, and meri- ciplinary role for cultural sociology, in part
tocracy, along with pervasive rhetorics because it suggests that, where meanings
connecting “earned rewards” with “hard vary among actors, cultural interpretation
work.” This declarative/public coupling is may generate more explanatory specifica-
accompanied by an unstated, socializing tions of mechanisms.
“group style” that marginalizes people who
actually attempt to practice what they preach, This article began by noting, like Gross, the
and which decouples this declarative discourse growing discipline-wide relevance of cultural
from practice (Khan and Jerolmack 2013). In analysis; however, I argued that without the
this case, the nondeclarative oppositional cul- requisite analytic specification of its central
ture (in relation to institutionalized codes) of concept, cultural analysis will not be able to
ease and naturalness enforced by elite peers live up to its discipline-unifying potential, nor
happens to be the actual culture of privilege will it be capable of doing the work of speci-
that garners social rewards in this context. At fying the generative mechanisms responsible
the level of public culture, the meritocratic for the phenomena of interest to social scien-
code produces homogenization of declarative tists at large. This analytic specification must
commitments and a simultaneous decoupling be tied to a flexible, empirically grounded
between declarations and practices that actu- account of the way persons acquire culture in
ally privilege those most adept at demonstrat- the first place. Such a theory of enculturation
ing effortless ease rather than nose-to-grindstone would provide a way to make the necessary
effort (Khan and Jerolmack 2013). distinctions while allowing the analyst to
Because ease is a kind of bodily profi- make sense of the relevant empirical
ciency (Cohen and Leung 2009), it must be phenomena.
110 American Sociological Review 82(1)

As we have seen, without sound theoreti- In this sense, the theory of enculturation I
cal footing, this can very quickly become a outlined is more compatible with pluralist con-
daunting task. As a rule, analysts face a rather ceptions of personal culture focused on the
complex landscape of empirical facts that can interplay among different cultural elements, at
be made sense of only by linking them to a the intra- and extra-personal levels, and
coherent analytic account of the nature and deployed in different modalities of action,
dynamics of the enculturation process. Absent whether in a controlled, intentional manner or in
such a framework, we have seen various automatic, habitual ways (e.g., Eliasoph and
examples of how failure to make the distinc- Lichterman 2003; Gross 2009; Swidler 2001a,
tion between declarative and nondeclarative 2001b; Vaisey 2009). However, as we saw ear-
forms of cultural knowledge can lead to para- lier, most pluralist accounts in contemporary
doxes, puzzles, and the misclassification of cultural sociology fail to make the required
relevant cultural processes as non-cultural. analytic distinctions. This work stands to benefit
These conundrums emerge not because of a from a more concerted effort to clarify the par-
dearth of empirical work or available data, ticular linkages between the elements that serve
but due to the failure to apply the most effec- as their focus (as well as the links that they
tive theoretical framework to the interpreta- deem secondary). Fruitful dialogue between dif-
tion of these data. ferent theoretical paradigms can thus be fur-
The analytic elaboration that I proposed is thered by adopting a theoretically consistent
meant as a necessary first step in achieving vocabulary of the sort I developed here.
these goals. The approach I laid out, while not At the level of meta-methodology, the
necessarily tied to any particular action the- model of enculturation I outlined is thoroughly
ory, is clearly influenced by formulations consistent with Gross’s (2009) call to specify
belonging to the broad family of “habit/prac- the dynamic role of “social mechanisms” at
tice theories” (e.g., pragmatism or Bourdieu- multiple temporal scales and levels of aggrega-
inspired approaches). These forerunners stand tion. As such, a key line of future work is to
out for having emphasized the importance of begin to theorize how dynamic enculturation,
habitual, nondeclarative competences in cul- cultural activation, and cultural use processes
tural analysis. It should be obvious that mod- link with dispositional, relational, and institu-
els of action that minimize or ignore tional/environmental mechanisms across set-
nondeclarative culture altogether, such as tings to generate important phenomena of both
rational-action, desire-belief-opportunity theoretical and practical interest.
models, or notions of agency that define the I focused on issues of culture and inequal-
term in question-begging terms as always ity as the core domains where the approach
implying voluntary (e.g., conscious and outlined could be used to further theorizing
effortful) action, are not consistent with the and aid in conceptual clarification, but it is
proposal outlined here. Such conceptions important to underscore that the framework
would perforce result in an artificially provided here is in no way logically tied to
restricted conception of personal culture as the role of cultural processes in the reproduc-
composed exclusively of explicitly espoused tion of power, privilege, and difference
beliefs, values, and other declarations used in (although this happens to be an area of broad
intentional ways. However, a sole focus on disciplinary interest). Instead, maintaining a
habits and habituation will not do either, consistent distinction between declarative and
because, as we have seen, the theoretical nondeclarative culture at the personal level,
action lies precisely at the intersection of and distinguishing both from (possibly disag-
declarative and nondeclarative culture and the gregated aspects of ) public culture, is impor-
link of both of these with institutionalized tant in all arenas in which cultural processes
public culture (Leschziner and Green 2013; figure prominently, including contemporary
Lizardo and Strand 2010). studies of racial and ethnic classification,
Lizardo 111

organizational analysis, studies of culture of This is more or less how some people use the
term “cultural sociology” (e.g., Alexander 2003);
markets, and social science history among
I avoid this term because it has become identified
others. In all these areas of inquiry, proper with a particular, and in many ways idiosyncratic,
specification and understanding of the role of approach to cultural analysis.
cultural processes require the analyst to note  2. On the importance of theorizing as a generative
and weigh the role of those understandings, activity—as opposed to the consumption of theory
as finished work—see Swedberg (2012).
habits, and skills that can be discursively
 3. This does not mean there cannot be a higher-order
articulated from those that remain below the association between nondeclarative embodiments and
surface but are evident in action, as both declarative knowledge. Recent research shows that
interlink with public culture in complex but declarative culture (e.g., attitudes, ideologies) can be
decipherable ways. cued and recalled when persons are forced to adopt a
(compatible) comportment (Cohen and Leung 2009).
 4. Strauss and Quinn (1997:8–9) sometimes opt for
Editors’ Note the less wieldy terminology of “intrapersonal cul-
This article was conditionally accepted by the previous ture” (or “culture-in-persons”) and “extrapersonal
ASR editors (Larry W. Isaac and Holly J. McCammon) culture.” Eliasoph and Lichterman (2003), for their
on September 16th, 2015, while they were still handling part, use the Durkheimian term “collective repre-
previously granted invitations to revise and resubmit as sentations” to refer to the public cultural domain
part of the editorial transition. To prevent any conflict (but later disaggregate this into “languages,”
of interest, Isaac served as the lead editor on subsequent “vocabularies,” and “codes”). To simplify matters,
revisions of the manuscript until its official acceptance on here I stick to the personal/public distinction, with
June 27th of 2016. the understanding that I refer roughly to the same
partition as these other authors.
  5. For a more elaborate, but less analytically wieldy,
Acknowledgments disaggregation along similar lines, see Patterson
(2014).
Early versions of this paper were presented at the spring
 6. I see “decoupling” as the limiting case of weak
of 2013 University of Notre Dame’s Culture Workshop
coupling and “fusion” as the limiting case of strong
and at the fall of 2013 Yale University’s Workshop in
coupling. The obsolete Parsonian (1951) notion of
Cultural Sociology. I would like to thank Terry McDon-
“interpenetration” between personality and cultural
nell, Kari Christoffersen, Brandon Vaidyanathan, Daniel
systems constituted an awkward attempt to theorize
Escher, Phillip Smith, Ilana Silber, Emily Erickson,
the cultural coupling issue. Parsons’s formulation
Andrew Cohen, Alison Gerber, Joe Klett, Tim Malac-
failed because it could not be told apart form a
arne, Xiaohong Xu, Fred Wherry, and Jeff Alexander for
fusion argument (Swidler 2001b).
their incisive questions, challenges, and suggestions.
  7. Swidler (2001a) also deals with coupling between
Special thanks go to Robert Fishman who read early ver-
these two elements, but she theorizes this as a devi-
sions of the manuscript and provided invaluable feed-
ation from the modal pattern that requires special
back. Finally, I’d like to acknowledge the graduate
explanation.
student participants in the spring of 2015 edition of my
  8. This difference is clear in a recent debate between
“Cognition, Culture, and Society” graduate seminar,
Swidler (2008) and Vaisey (2008); both theorists
especially Dustin Stoltz, Marshall Taylor, and Justin Van
reveal that rather than disagreeing on fundamental
Ness, whose questions, reflections, and insight helped
analytic issues, they are actually interested in fun-
clarify the theoretical ideas presented here at a pivotal
damentally different empirical phenomena.
moment in the development of the manuscript. Finally, I
  9. Biernacki’s (1995) work has been enthusiastically
would like to thank Larry Isaac and the anonymous ASR
endorsed by Swidler (2001b), suggesting they do
readers for pushing me, sometimes kicking and scream-
share the same approach to theorizing the weak
ing, to expand and clarify the core theoretical contribu-
coupling between nondeclarative practices and pub-
tion. This process made the paper an order of magnitude
lic culture.
better than it otherwise would have been. All remaining
10. This is an argumentative turn Alexander (2004) also
errors and omissions, of the intended and unintended
made when he directed his attention toward ritual,
variety, remain my sole responsibility.
performance, and other elements of culture-in-use.
11. A more accurate characterization of Parsons’s
(1951) middle period functionalism would empha-
Notes
size the triple strong coupling between declarative
  1. I use the generic term “cultural analysis” to refer to culture (value commitments), nondeclarative cul-
any attempt by a sociologist to use cultural theory ture (unconscious need dispositions), and institu-
to tackle substantive issues regardless of subfield. tionalized patterns (public culture).
112 American Sociological Review 82(1)

12. See Ignatow (2007) for a review of the cognitive Brekhus, Wayne. 2007. “The Rutgers School: A
science evidence against this presumption. Zerubavelian Culturalist Cognitive Sociology.” Euro-
13. Resorting to cultural factors in this case seems pean Journal of Social Theory 10(3):448–64.
prima facie desirable due to the fact that appeal to Brubaker, Rogers. 2002. “Ethnicity without Groups.”
structural factors (namely, parents’ socioeconomic European Journal of Sociology 43(2):163–89.
status) provides limited leverage in accounting for Carter, Prudence L. 2005. Keepin’ It Real: School Success
the Asian/white gap (Hsin and Xie 2014; Liu and beyond Black and White. New York: Oxford Univer-
Xie 2016). sity Press.
14. For an application of this same principle to a dif- Changeux, Jean-Pierre. 1997. Neuronal Man: The Biol-
ferent case—that of the creation of an oppositional ogy of Mind. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
culture of disinvestment in traditional achievement Press.
values on the part of recent cohorts of the college Cohen, Dov, and Angela K. Y. Leung. 2009. “The Hard
educated under conditions of credential inflation— Embodiment of Culture.” European Journal of Social
see Vaisey (2006). Psychology 39(7):1278–89.
15. Nondeclarative factors subsumed under “effort” Collins, Harry, and Robert Evans. 2008. Rethinking
and “noncognitive skills” are indeed correlated Expertise. Chicago: University Of Chicago Press.
with declarative culture, such as explicit beliefs DiMaggio, Paul. 1997. “Culture and Cognition.” Annual
that effort is linked to achievement across all Review of Sociology 23:263–87.
Asian groups (Hsin and Xie 2014). However, the Downey, Douglas B. 2008. “A Funny Thing Happened
correlation between nondeclarative skills and On the Way to Confirming Oppositional Culture The-
immigration status is about twice as strong as the ory.” Pp. 298–311 in Minority Status, Oppositional
declarative/nondeclarative correlation, suggesting Culture, and Schooling, edited by J. Ogbu. New York:
that self-selection based on nondeclarative cultural Routledge.
knowledge is more tightly linked to the underlying Dreyfus, Stuart E. 2004. “The Five-Stage Model of Adult
mechanism generating differences in educational Skill Acquisition.” Bulletin of Science, Technology &
outcomes (Hsin and Xie 2014), and that for most Society 24(3):177–81.
Asians there is a structured decoupling between Eliasoph, Nina, and Paul Lichterman. 2003. “Culture
the nondeclarative skills responsible for success in in Interaction.” American Journal of Sociology
school and explicit assent to the values measured 108(4):735–94.
using standard self-placement methods. Farkas, George, Christy Lleras, and Steve Maczuga.
2002. “Does Oppositional Culture Exist in Minority
and Poverty Peer Groups?” American Sociological
References Review 67(1):148–55.
Ainsworth-Darnell, James W., and Douglas B. Downey. Fordham, Signithia, and John U. Ogbu. 1986. “Black Stu-
1998. “Assessing the Oppositional Culture Expla- dents’ School Success: Coping with the ‘Burden of
nation for Racial/Ethnic Differences in School “Acting White.” ’” The Urban Review 18(3):176–206.
Performance.” American Sociological Review Geertz, Clifford. 1973. The Interpretation of Cultures:
63(4):536–53. Selected Essays. New York: Basic books.
Alexander, Jeffrey C. 2003. The Meanings of Social Life: A Geertz, Clifford. 1975. “Common Sense as a Cultural
Cultural Sociology. New York: Oxford University Press. System.” Antioch Review 33(1):5–26.
Alexander, Jeffrey C. 2004. “Cultural Pragmatics: Social Gross, Neil. 2009. “A Pragmatist Theory of Social Mech-
Performance between Ritual and Strategy.” Socio- anisms.” American Sociological Review 74(3):358–
logical Theory 22(4):527–73. 79.
Atkinson, Will. 2011. “The Context and Genesis of Musi- Haidt, Jonathan. 2012. The Righteous Mind. New York:
cal Tastes: Omnivorousness Debunked, Bourdieu Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group.
Buttressed.” Poetics 39(3):169–86. Harding, David J. 2007. “Cultural Context, Sexual
Berger, Peter L., and Thomas Luckmann. 1966. The Behavior, and Romantic Relationships in Disad-
Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the Soci- vantaged Neighborhoods.” American Sociological
ology of Knowledge. New York: Doubleday. Review 72(3):341–64.
Biernacki, Richard. 1995. The Fabrication of Labor: Harris, Angel L. 2006. “I (Don’t) Hate School: Revisiting
Germany and Britain, 1640–1914. Berkeley: Univer- Oppositional Culture Theory of Blacks’ Resistance to
sity of California Press. Schooling.” Social Forces 85(2):797–834.
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1973. “The Three Forms of Theoretical Harris, Angel L., and Keith Robinson. 2007. “School-
Knowledge.” Social Science Information 12(1):53–80. ing Behaviors or Prior Skills? A Cautionary Tale of
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1990. The Logic of Practice. Stanford, Omitted Variable Bias within Oppositional Culture
CA: Stanford University Press. Theory.” Sociology of Education 80(2):139–57.
Bourdieu, Pierre, and Jean Claude Passeron. 1990. Repro- Hays, Sharon. 1994. “Structure and Agency and the
duction in Education, Society and Culture. London, Sticky Problem of Culture.” Sociological Theory
UK: Sage Publications. 12(1):57–72.
Lizardo 113

Heiskala, Risto. 2011. “The Meaning of Meaning in Lamont, Michèle, Stefan Beljean, and Matthew Clair.
Sociology: The Achievements and Shortcomings of 2014. “What Is Missing? Cultural Processes and
Alfred Schutz’s Phenomenological Sociology.” Jour- Causal Pathways to Inequality.” Socio-Economic
nal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 41(3):231–46. Review 12(3):573–608.
Holland, Dorothy. 1992. “How Cultural Systems Become Lamont, Michèle, and Mario Luis Small. 2008. “How Cul-
Desire: A Case Study of American Romance.” Pp. ture Matters: Enriching Our Understanding of Poverty.”
61–89 in Human Motives and Cultural Models, edited Pp. 76–102 in The Colors of Poverty: Why Racial and
by R. G. D’Andrade and C. Strauss. Cambridge, UK: Ethnic Disparities Persist, edited by A. C. Lin and D. R.
Cambridge University Press. Harris. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.
Holt, Douglas B. 1998. “Does Cultural Capital Struc- Lareau, Annette. 2011. Unequal Childhoods: Class,
ture American Consumption?” Journal of Consumer Race, and Family Life. Berkeley: University of Cali-
Research 25(1):1–25. fornia Press.
Hsin, Amy, and Yu Xie. 2014. “Explaining Asian Ameri- Leschziner, Vanina, and Adam Isaiah Green. 2013.
cans’ Academic Advantage over Whites.” Proceed- “Thinking about Food and Sex: Deliberate Cogni-
ings of the National Academy of Sciences of the tion in the Routine Practices of a Field.” Sociological
United States of America 111(23):8416–21. Theory 31(2):116–44.
Ignatow, Gabriel. 2007. “Theories of Embodied Knowl- Liu, Airan, and Yu Xie. 2016. “Why Do Asian Ameri-
edge: New Directions for Cultural and Cognitive cans Academically Outperform Whites? The Cultural
Sociology?” Journal for the Theory of Social Behav- Explanation Revisited.” Social Science Research
iour 37(2):115–35. 58:210–26.
Jacobs, Mark D., and Lyn Spillman. 2005. “Cultural Lizardo, Omar. 2011. “Pierre Bourdieu as a Post-Cultural
Sociology at the Crossroads of the Discipline.” Poet- Theorist.” Cultural Sociology 5(1):25–44.
ics 33(1):1–14. Lizardo, Omar, and Sara Skiles. 2012. “Reconceptual-
Jerolmack, Colin, and Shamus Khan. 2014. “Talk Is izing and Theorizing ‘Omnivorousness’: Genetic
Cheap: Ethnography and the Attitudinal Fallacy.” and Relational Mechanisms.” Sociological Theory
Sociological Methods & Research 43(2):178–209. 30(4):263–82.
Jiménez, Tomás R., and Adam L. Horowitz. 2013. “When Lizardo, Omar, and Michael Strand. 2010. “Skills, Tool-
White Is Just Alright: How Immigrants Redefine kits, Contexts and Institutions: Clarifying the Rela-
Achievement and Reconfigure the Ethnoracial Hier- tionship between Different Approaches to Cognition
archy.” American Sociological Review 78(5):849–71. in Cultural Sociology.” Poetics 38(2):205–228.
Kao, Grace. 2000. “Group Images and Possible Selves Martin, John Levi. 2010. “Life’s a Beach but You’re an
among Adolescents: Linking Stereotypes to Expec- Ant, and Other Unwelcome News for the Sociology
tations by Race and Ethnicity.” Sociological Forum of Culture.” Poetics 38(2):229–44.
15(3):407–430. Margolis, Howard. 1987. Patterns, Thinking, and Cogni-
Kao, Grace, and Jennifer S. Thompson. 2003. “Racial tion: A Theory of Judgment. Chicago: University of
and Ethnic Stratification in Educational Achieve- Chicago Press.
ment and Attainment.” Annual Review of Sociology Martin, Alex, and Linda L. Chao. 2001. “Semantic Mem-
29(1):417–42. ory and the Brain: Structure and Processes.” Current
Kao, Grace, and Marta Tienda. 1998. “Educational Aspi- Opinion in Neurobiology 11(2):194–201.
rations of Minority Youth.” American Journal of Edu- McDonnell, Terence E. 2014. “Drawing Out Culture:
cation 106(3):349–84. Productive Methods to Measure Cognition and Reso-
Karmiloff-Smith, Annette. 1995. Beyond Modularity: A nance.” Theory and Society 43(3–4):247–74.
Developmental Perspective on Cognitive Science. Mills, C. Wright. 1940. “Situated Actions and Vocabu-
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. laries of Motive.” American Sociological Review
Khan, Shamus R. 2011. Privilege: The Making of an 5(6):904–913.
Adolescent Elite at St. Paul’s School. Princeton, NJ: Mische, Ann. 2009. “Projects and Possibilities:
Princeton University Press. Researching Futures in Action.” Sociological Forum
Khan, Shamus R., and Colin Jerolmack. 2013. “Say- 24(3):694–704.
ing Meritocracy and Doing Privilege.” Sociological Ogbu, John U. 1978. Minority Education and Caste: The
Quarterly 54(1):9–19. American System in Cross-Cultural Perspective. New
Kohn, Melvin L. 1977. Class and Conformity: A Study in York: Academic Press.
Values. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Ogbu, John U. 1987. “Variability in Minority School Per-
Kunda, Ziva, and Paul Thagard. 1996. “Forming Impres- formance: A Problem in Search of an Explanation.”
sions from Stereotypes, Traits, and Behaviors: A Par- Anthropology & Education Quarterly 18(4):312–34.
allel-Constraint-Satisfaction Theory.” Psychological Ogbu, John U. 2003. Black American Students in an
Review 103(2):284–308. Affluent Suburb: A Study of Academic Disengage-
Kolers, Paul A., and William E. Smythe. 1979. “Images, ment. New York: Routledge.
Symbols, and Skills.” Canadian Journal of Psychol- Ogbu, John U., and Herbert D. Simons. 1998. “Voluntary
ogy 33(3):158–84. and Involuntary Minorities: A Cultural-Ecological
114 American Sociological Review 82(1)

Theory of School Performance with Some Implica- Squire, Larry R. 2004. “Memory Systems of the Brain:
tions for Education.” Anthropology & Education A Brief History and Current Perspective.” Neurobiol-
Quarterly 29(2):155–88. ogy of Learning and Memory 82(3):171–77.
Ollivier, Michèle. 2008. “Modes of Openness to Cultural Strack, Fritz, and Roland Deutsch. 2004. “Reflective and
Diversity: Humanist, Populist, Practical, and Indiffer- Impulsive Determinants of Social Behavior.” Person-
ent.” Poetics 36(2–3):120–47. ality and Social Psychology Review 8(3):220–47.
Parsons, Talcott. 1951. The Social System. Glencoe, IL: Stephens, Nicole M., Hazel Rose Markus, and L. Taylor
The Free Press. Phillips. 2014. “Social Class Culture Cycles: How
Patterson, Orlando. 2014. “Making Sense of Culture.” Three Gateway Contexts Shape Selves and Fuel
Annual Review of Sociology 40(1):1–30. Inequality.” Annual Review of Psychology 65:611–
Peterson, Richard A., and Roger M. Kern. 1996. “Chang- 34.
ing Highbrow Taste: From Snob to Omnivore.” Strauss, Claudia, and Naomi Quinn. 1997. A Cognitive
American Sociological Review 61(5):900–907. Theory of Cultural Meaning. Cambridge, UK: Cam-
Polanyi, Michael. 1966. The Tacit Dimension. Chicago: bridge University Press.
University of Chicago Press. Swedberg, Richard. 2012. “Theorizing in Sociology and
Pugh, Alison J. 2013. “What Good Are Interviews for Social Science: Turning to the Context of Discovery.”
Thinking about Culture? Demystifying Interpretive Theory and Society 41(1):1–40.
Analysis.” American Journal of Cultural Sociology Swidler, Ann. 1986. “Culture in Action: Symbols
1(1):42–68. and Strategies.” American Sociological Review
Rosch, Eleanor, and Carolyn B. Mervis. 1975. “Family 51(2):273–86.
Resemblances: Studies in the Internal Structure of Swidler, Ann. 2001a. Talk of Love: How Culture Matters.
Categories.” Cognitive Psychology 7(4):573–605. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Ryle, Gilbert. 2002. The Concept of Mind. Chicago: The Swidler, Ann. 2001b. “What Anchors Cultural Practices.”
University of Chicago Press. Pp. 74–92 in The Practice Turn in Contemporary
Schuman, Howard, and Jacqueline Scott. 1989. “Genera- Theory, edited by K. K. Cetina, T. R. Schatzki, and
tions and Collective Memories.” American Sociologi- E. von Savigny. London, UK: Routledge.
cal Review 54(3):359–81. Swidler, Ann. 2008. “Comment on Stephen Vaisey’s
Schutz, Alfred. 1967. The Phenomenology of the Social ‘Socrates, Skinner, and Aristotle: Three Ways of
World. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press. Thinking about Culture in Action.’” Sociological
Searle, John R. 1983. Intentionality: An Essay in the Phi- Forum 23(3):614–18.
losophy of Mind. New York: Cambridge University Tomasello, Michael. 1999. “The Human Adaptation for
Press. Culture.” Annual Review of Anthropology 28(1):509–
Sewell, William H. 1992. “A Theory of Structure: Dual- 29.
ity, Agency, and Transformation.” American Journal Tyson, Karolyn, William Darity, and Domini R. Castel-
of Sociology 98(1):1–29. lino. 2005. “It’s Not ‘a Black Thing’: Understanding
Sewell, William H. 2005. “The Concept(s) of Culture.” the Burden of Acting White and Other Dilemmas of
Pp. 76–95 in Practicing History: New Directions in High Achievement.” American Sociological Review
Historical Writing after the Linguistic Turn, edited by 70(4):582–605.
G. M. Spiegel. New York: Routledge. Vaisey, Stephen. 2006. “Education and Its Discontents:
Shepherd, Hana. 2011. “The Cultural Context of Cog- Overqualification in America, 1972–2002.” Social
nition: What the Implicit Association Test Tells Us Forces 85(2):835–64.
About How Culture Works.” Sociological Forum Vaisey, Stephen. 2008. “Socrates, Skinner, and Aristotle:
26(1):121–43. Three Ways of Thinking about Culture in Action.”
Skrentny, John D. 2008. “Culture and Race/Ethnic- Sociological Forum 23(3):603–613.
ity: Bolder, Deeper, and Broader.” Annals of the Vaisey, Stephen. 2009. “Motivation and Justification: A
American Academy of Political and Social Science Dual-Process Model of Culture in Action.” American
619(1):59–77. Journal of Sociology 114(6):1675–1715.
Sloman, Steven A. 1996. “The Empirical Case for Two Wacquant, Loïc J. D. 2004. Body & Soul: Notebooks of
Systems of Reasoning.” Psychological Bulletin an Apprentice Boxer. New York: Oxford University
119(1):3–22. Press.
Small, Mario Luis, David J. Harding, and Michèle Weininger, Elliot B., and Annette Lareau. 2009. “Para-
Lamont. 2010. “Reconsidering Poverty and Culture.” doxical Pathways: An Ethnographic Extension of
Annals of the American Academy of Political and Kohn’s Findings on Class and Childrearing.” Jour-
Social Sciences 629(1):1–22. nal of Marriage and Family Counseling 71(3):680–
Smith, Eliot R., and Jamie DeCoster. 2000. “Dual-Pro- 95.
cess Models in Social and Cognitive Psychology: Weininger, Elliot B., Annette Lareau, and Dalton Conley.
Conceptual Integration and Links to Underlying 2015. “What Money Doesn’t Buy: Class Resources
Memory Systems.” Personality and Social Psychol- and Children’s Participation in Organized Extracur-
ogy Review 4(2):108–131. ricular Activities.” Social Forces 94 (2):479–503.
Lizardo 115

Whitehouse, Harvey. 1996. “Rites of Terror: Emotion, Omar Lizardo is Professor of Sociology at the Univer-
Metaphor and Memory in Melanesian Initiation sity of Notre Dame. His research deals with various top-
Cults.” Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute ics in sociology, social psychology, cultural sociology,
2(4):703–715. network theory, and cognitive science. He was the recipi-
Zaller, John. 1992. The Nature and Origins of Mass Pub- ent of the 2013 Lewis Coser Award for Theoretical
lic Opinion. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Agenda Setting from the American Sociological Associa-
Press. tion Section on Theory. Previous work published in ASR
Zhou, Min, and Jennifer Lee. 2014. “Assessing What has been recognized (with Robert Fishman) with the
Is Cultural about Asian Americans’ Academic 2014 Charles Tilly best article award from the ASA sec-
Advantage.” Proceedings of the National Acad- tion on Comparative Historical Sociology, and the 2008
emy of Sciences of the United States of America Clifford Geertz prize for Best Article from the ASA Sec-
111(23):8321–22. tion on Culture.

You might also like