You are on page 1of 14

How Virtue Fits

Within Business Ethics J. Thomas Whetstone

ABSTRACT. This paper proposes that managers add of such an ethics approach in contemporary organi-
an attention to virtues and vices of human character zations requires further empirical research to develop
as a full complement to moral reasoning according a greater understanding of the moral language actually
to a deontological focus on obligations to act and a used. Meeting this challenge will allow academics
teleological focus on consequences (a balanced tri- better to assist practicing managers lead moral devel-
partite approach). Even if the criticisms of virtue opment and moral reasoning efforts.
ethics cloud its use as a mononomic normative theory
of justification, they do not refute the substantial KEY WORDS: act-oriented theories, character,
benefits of applying a human character perspective – ethical manager, leadership, moral language, servant
when done so in conjunction with also-imperfect leadership, tripartite ethics, vice, virtue, virtue
act-oriented perspectives. An interactive tripartite ethics
approach is superior for meeting the complex require-
ments of an applied ethic. To illustrate how deficien-
cies of a “strong” virtue ethics formulation can be Introduction
overcome by a balanced tripartite approach, this paper
compares normative leadership paradigms (each based What is the appropriate role for an ethic of
on a combination of virtue, deontology, or conse- virtues in managers’ moral development and
quentialist perspectives) and the dangers inherent in moral reasoning? An ethic of virtues (and vices)
each. The preferred paradigm is servant leadership,
emphasizes the process of personal moral char-
grounded in a tripartite ethic. Effective application
acter development. Donaldson and Werhane
(1999) note that some philosophers are reluctant
J. Thomas Whetstone, Assistant Professor of Management, to accept fully the “human nature” approach,
Davis College of Business, Jacksonville University, believing that consequentialism and deontology
Jacksonville, Florida, teaches MBA and Executive MBA exhaust all possible modes of ethical reasoning.
courses in business ethics and undergraduate courses in On the other hand, virtue ethics proponents
management, organization theory, organizational often imply that the personal character perspec-
behavior, and business strategy. He worked for ten years tive is more fundamental than act-oriented
in corporate management in the energy industry. He also theories, favoring a “strong” view of virtue
is a Presbyterian minister and public speaker on man- ethics. In An Introduction to Business Ethics (1996),
agement ethics and history. His doctoral dissertation is Jackson argues that, of the three basic approaches,
“The Manager as a Moral Person: Exploring Paths to only a virtues-based approach is able to make
Excellence” (1995). Publications include: “Teaching sense of the importance of morality and thus good
Ethics to Managers: Contemporary Problems and a
practice. In A Primer of Modern Virtue Ethics
Traditional Solution” (1998) in C. J. Cowton and R.
S. Crisp, editors: Business Ethics: Perspectives on (1995, p. 1), Duncan states his objective of
the Practice of Theory (Oxford University Press, beginning a full-scale project to reconstruct
Oxford), and “Ethics and Leadership: Searching for a morality as a whole on the basis of an ethics of
Comfortable Fit” (1997) in G. Moore, editor: Business the virtues so as to present a credible alternative
Ethics: Principles and Practice (Business Education to the other great traditions in ethics.
Publishers, Sunderland, U.K.). Is one of these views preferable? No, according

Journal of Business Ethics 33: 101–114, 2001.


© 2001 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.
102 J. Thomas Whetstone

to Robert Louden (1984). He argues that virtue teristic of the kind of person one wants to be.
ethics must be included in any adequate justifi- One might refrain from cheating because this is
cation of morality, along with deontological and the right way to act, and because so acting will
teleological approaches, proposing that his fellow create a better world, and because one is an
philosophers honest person. It is not necessary to choose a
single theory and stick with it; it is sometimes
need to begin efforts to coordinate irreducible or even better to take what seems most plausible
strong notions of virtue along with irreducible or from several theories and seek insights from all
strong conceptions of the various act notions into theories (Bowie, 1982, p. 7). For proper balance,
our conceptual scheme of morality. This appeal for the theorist needs to add virtue ethics as a fully-
coordination will not satisfy those theorists who
equal complement to deontological theories that
continue to think in the single-element of
mononomic tradition (a tradition which contem-
focus on obligations and teleological ones that
porary virtue-based theorists have inherited from place greatest priority on the consequences of
their duty-based and goal-based ancestors), but I acts. This is an important thesis that philosophers
do believe it will result in a more realistic account need to debate with renewed vigor, but one
of our moral experience. The moral field is not needing much more space (books?) and philo-
unitary, and the values we employ in making moral sophical rigor than is attempted in this paper. As
judgments sometimes have fundamentally different Rosalind Hursthouse (1997, p. 237) admits,
sources. No single reductive method can offer a defending virtues theory against all possible
realistic means of prioritizing these different values. criticisms would be a lifelong task. This paper
There exists no scale by means of which disparate focuses on the application of theory by business
moral considerations can always be measured, managers and leaders in terms of moral devel-
added and balanced. The theoretician’s quest for
opment and moral reasoning.
conceptual economy and elegance has been won
at too great a price, for the resulting reductionist
But a rehearsal of Louden’s thesis establishes
definitions of the moral concepts are not true to the context for the main proposition of this
the facts of moral experience. It is important now paper, which focuses on the practical application
to see the ethics of virtue and the ethics of rules of ethics theory, its role in the moral develop-
as adding up, rather than as canceling each other ment and moral reasoning of managers, rather
out (Louden, 1984, p. 191). than on the formal philosophical justification of
normative ethics theories. The proposition of this
Mononomics has not ceased since the 1984 paper is that managers need to add virtue ethics,
publication of Louden’s appeal in the American or more precisely an attention to virtues and
Philosophical Quarterly, possibly because of vices of human character, as a fully-equal com-
presuppositional differences between virtue and plement to moral reasoning according to
act-oriented theories. But as Crisp (1998, p. 19) deontological or consequentialist teleological
observes, much of contemporary moral philos- formulations.
ophy, business ethics included, operates on a This paper supports this claim using a variety
mistaken scientific model. In business ethics it is of approaches. It begins by noting that principle-
not necessary to explain our actions, as scien- based ethics (PBE) alone often has proven inad-
tific models require, but to justify them. One can equate for practicing managers, who have thus
have more than one reason for doing something. not adopted it. Virtue ethics has recently
One can read a journal for pleasure as well as to reemerged among moral philosophers, but its fit
stay informed; one can attend a dinner to eat and in terms of practical application is debatable.
to socialize. But many philosophers have been Certainly a “strong” virtue ethic, where act-
tempted to think that one must pick one ethics oriented theories are subordinated, is an inade-
theory in order to justify a particular course of quate theory (see Boatright, 1995). This paper
action. Moral reasons can include both the duty proposes a complementary approach, using a
to act and the consequences expected from the tripartite ethics formulation (balancing character
act as well as the belief that so acting is charac- considerations with a deontological focus on
How Virtue Fits Within Business Ethics 103

obligations to act and a teleological focus on the standing of the moral language used by practicing
consequences of acts) as a more fitting guide for business managers.
applying normative ethics theories to decision
making and moral development. This balanced
formulation enhances the realization of the The modernist commitment to
benefits identified with the addition of a char- act-oriented theories
acter perspective.
Indeed, organizational field research finds that Table I summarizes three ethics theories: conse-
virtue and vice concepts are necessary to describe quentialist teleology, deontology, and virtue
what is meant by an excellent manager; his or ethics, highlighting the fundamental differences
her productivity and principled-behavior are not in their perspectives. According to principle-
sufficient. Whether the principles are objective based ethics (PBE), successful managers do not
and absolute or are developed via social- rely solely on either a consequentialist or a deon-
construction within a community, an applied tological theory but try to balance the influences
ethic requires normative standards or decision of each of these act-oriented theories, positing
principles in some form to be used to assess that people have a duty to bring about the best
behaviors as right or wrong or good or bad. consequences. The basic premise is that man-
Applying via negationis, this paper illustrates how agement and management ethics are primarily a
deficiencies of a “strong” virtue ethics formula- cognitive matter of rational decision making
tion can be overcome by a more balanced concerning particular ethical dilemmas. However,
tripartite approach, referring to several norma- some critics claim that North American
tive leadership paradigms (each based on a managers have not adopted PBE models, cer-
combination of virtue, deontology, or conse- tainly not for routine business applications,
quentialist teleology ethics perspectives) and the because such formulations are too abstract and
dangers inherent in each. The most balanced and use philosophical language foreign to the business
thus favored leadership paradigm is servant community (Stark, 1993; Monast, 1994). A prin-
leadership, grounded in a tripartite ethic. The ciple-based ethic by its nature does not focus
value of the complementary or balanced tripar- directly on the psychological influences on
tite approach is further illustrated using a motivation, does not always point to clearly
complex situation from American literature. Just preferable courses of action in the hard cases, and
as it begins with a challenge to continue philo- cannot resolve issues in which the recommen-
sophic debate of Louden’s appeal for abandoning dations of utilitarianism and deontology conflict
mononomic conceptions or ethics theory, this (Horvath, 1995). It is impersonal and abstract,
paper concludes with a challenge to empiricists and draws on an incomplete view of human
to develop a more current descriptive under- nature. Nevertheless, business people can use a

TABLE I
Three ethics perspectives

Consequentialist teleology Deontology Virtue

Primary focus: Consequences; Duties: Moral obligations Character development


Costs vs. Benefits – re the act – for the person
– of the act
A right action: Promotes the best Is in accordance with a Is one that a virtuous agent
consequences in which moral principle required is disposed to make in the
happiness is maximized by God, natural law, or circumstances in order to
rationality flourish or live well
104 J. Thomas Whetstone

principle-based ethic profitably to guide ethical character suggests the presence of virtues and the
behavior, if they do so while exercising wise absence of vices, manifest in the moral behav-
judgment and demonstrating certain character iors referred to by Foot (1978). Indeed, the
qualities in order to act appropriately, given the “how” of virtue is more understandable, and
situation and cultural context (Larmore, 1987). more meaningful, for ethics research and
teaching, than is the “what.”

The reemergence of virtue ethics


Benefits of a virtue perspective
Starting with Elizabeth Anscomb (1958), a
growing number of scholars have now moved Adding a virtue perspective as a complement to
toward a more personal ethic, one requiring act-oriented perspectives can expand the scope
serious attention to the human dimension and perspectives of ethical analysis and under-
(Niebuhr, 1963; MacIntyre, 1985; Des Jardins, standing. This is because an Aristotelian (as
1984; Williams, 1984; De George, 1987; Walton, opposed to Platonic) ethic of virtue:
1988; Mahoney, 1990; Nash, 1990; Goodpaster,
1. is personal;
1991; Sommers, 1991; Solomon, 1992; Collier,
2. focuses on the motivations of the actor and
1995; Hartman, 1998). This paper defines a
the sources of action, bringing a dynamic
virtue to be a qualitative characteristic, gener-
to ethical understanding;
ally considered part of a person’s character,
3. is contextual, highlighting the importance
something within the person, although neither
of understanding the environment as it
materially nor biologically identifiable. A virtue
affects both actor and his or her acts; and
is closer to an internal value, something of the
4. complements other disciplines addressing
spiritual essence of the person. Aristotle’s
human behavior.
approach is more psychological than philosoph-
ically abstract and analytical, being meant to These potential benefits, each of which are vital
discover how a good person is to act (Barnes, for moral development and moral reasoning by
1976, p. 17). What is a fully virtuous act, one managers and their management of complex
that is done as a virtuous person would do it? human organizations, are briefly discussed
According to Aristotle, it must satisfy three below.
conditions: (1) the virtuous person does the act 1. An ethics of virtue is personal. If ethics is to
knowingly, aware of the pertinent facts and the answer the Socratic question of how one should
practical wisdom needed to apply the act so as live, it needs to be sensitive to the nuances of
to fit its appropriate purpose; (2) the motive for human life, to what human nature is really like.
choosing the act must be simply because it is Consequentialist and deontological approaches
virtuous, not for personal advantage or other tend to be impersonal. Hawerwas (1974),
non-ideal motives; and (3) the act must be as a MacIntyre (1985), and Pincoffs (1987) offer
result of a steady state of character disposition, variations to virtue theory in order to add
not a one-off or impulsive act, but irrespective the personal perspective. Moral properties or
of particular times and persons. A virtuous act is qualities do not pertain to choices, but more
thus a rational act based on a wise, purposeful fundamentally to persons, in the interpersonal
assessment of the factual situation, chosen for a world of the moral community. Even if virtue
pure motive and consistent with a steady dis- ethics proponents tend to overstate the relative
position of the actor’s character. importance of their position, their arguments
Whatever the ontology of virtue, it is not a lend support to a complementary role for this
subject for scientific proof, although virtue and personal perspective.
vice apply to behavior of biological persons. 2. An ethic of virtue focuses on the motivations of
Virtues and vices dispose one to certain the actor and the sources of action, bringing a dynamic
behaviors in the material world. To have good to ethical understanding. The Aristotelian under-
How Virtue Fits Within Business Ethics 105

standing of human nature is that the supreme crises. When the discipline of ethics includes the
good is the well functioning of the human being evaluation and development of character, its
as a human; functioning well is nothing other subject matter begins to look less impersonal and
than activity in accordance with virtue the responsibilities of people look less intermit-
(excellence) (Broadie, 1991, p. 57). One mark tent (Kupperman, 1991, p. 12).
of a good life is harmony between one’s motives
and one’s reasons, values, and justifications.
Virtues are not static; they are corrective. They A “strong” virtue ethic
help guide, motivate, or correct moral delibera-
tion and behavior. By promoting and facilitating Some even claim that virtue ethics should be
methods of moral education, character develop- viewed as being more fundamental or superior
ment, and emotional well-being of the actor, an to act-oriented theories (Duncan, 1995; Jackson,
ethic of virtue can serve as a framework for 1996). Koehn (1995, pp. 536–538) says that
implementing positive change in behavior. taking virtue ethics seriously will probably mean
3. An ethic of virtue is contexual, highlighting the that one ultimately must choose one system over
importance of understanding the environment as it the other, because there are profound differences
affects both the actor and his or her acts. Virtues and in how the various ethical systems understand
vices are fully understood only by considering concepts of practical reasoning and the truly
the overall context of life and work. A virtue is good act, and their views may be mutually
not merely a principle. The practice of an ethic exclusive. Indeed, philosophers still tend to
of virtue requires that a person have perceptive approach business ethics from only one of the
insight concerning the context of each act. What three perspectives, even if they note the contri-
is most right to do depends on the situation, butions of all three (Bowie, 1999). But is a
including recognition of coercive pressures and reductive, even bifurcating, insistence to choose
intentions for acting. Act-oriented approaches between virtue and act theory the best approach
also require consideration of the situational for ethical practice? Gareth Morgan (1996) shows
context (O’Donovan, 1986, pp. 137–138), but a how using several different paradigms of organi-
virtue perspective enriches such analysis. zations can increase understanding of these social
4. An ethic of virtue, by requiring the actor to seek systems. Likewise, considering multiple perspec-
to understand himself or herself as a person, comple- tives, based on admittedly different, but well-
ments other disciplines addressing human behavior. As considered, assumptions and worldviews, can be
critical as culture and environment are, they helpful for understanding complex ethical issues.
constitute only part of the contextual problem. A virtue ethic does have theoretical problems.
The perspective of virtue, because it concerns the Virtue theory’s concept of eudaimonia is difficult
nature and normative behavior of humans, also and obscure. It is criticized for its cultural
points to questions of philosophy and theology relativism because different people and cultures
beyond the normally-accepted sphere of social can consider different character traits as virtues,
science. although Hursthouse (1997, p. 222) notes that
Having a good moral character suggests the act-oriented theories also have this problem.
presence of virtues or moral excellences and the Indeed, Velazquez (2000) argues against the
absence of vices. The dispositions of character validity of hypernorms for global ethics
termed virtues are beneficial to personal actors (Donaldson and Dunfee, 1999) because of the
and to the others affected by their acts. They help cultural imperialism of Western moral theory.
to meet holistic needs; some motivate, some Different virtues sometimes point to conflicting
guide, some correct moral deliberation and actions, but rule deontology sometimes suffers
behavior. The virtue ethics perspective attempts from the same problem. The deontological rule
to help the person as actor understand himself to preserve life can lead to contradictory
and develop the moral capacities to live and work instructions in some cases, such as that of justi-
well in all situations, both ordinary ones and fying abortion to save the mother’s life.
106 J. Thomas Whetstone

If business grows due to entrepreneurial ini- important question for practicing managers is not
tiative of individuals rather than merely through which theory is superior, but what positive
social evolution, an Aristotelian virtue ethic is benefits result for personal moral development
inadequate on a stand-alone basis. Boatright and moral reasoning. But how can a tripartite
(1995) suggests that Solomon’s (1992) approach be implemented in an organization?
Aristotelian approach needs to be supplemented
with a set of fundamental human rights grounded
in human nature. It does inadequately credit Adding virtue ethics as a full complement
what Nesteruk (1995) calls the creative benefits to the act theories
of constraints, including laws and rules (also note
Giddens, 1984). More generally, a virtue ethic A comprehensive tripartite theory combines a
needs more than a telos that organizes the set of focus on cognitive decision making of individual
virtues into a concept of the good; it also needs acts simultaneously with the deliberate process of
a deontological standard of right and wrong developing the moral character of actors. To be
behavior. Furthermore, to be practical, an ethic fully tripartite, the deontological principles are
applied to business needs to help the business objective, not socially-constructed ones that
manager solve specific problems in a real time sit- emerge from a culture of virtuous people. Such
uation and context. a theory needs to recognize the tension between
Even if they undermine ready acceptance of a adherence to universal objective standards and the
“strong virtue” theory, the serious criticisms of free will of people who must interpret and apply
virtue ethics as a normative theory do not those standards in each situation. Donaldson and
necessarily refute the above benefits of applying Dunfee’s (1999) concept of hypernorms, as used
a virtue ethics perspective – when done so in to constrain decisions made on the basis of social
conjunction with also-imperfect act-oriented contracts at the local level, is somewhat analo-
perspectives. Instead, they point to the need for gous to this formulation. A business manager,
an interactive tripartite approach. Table II lists properly exercising his or her role at the intuitive
criteria or guidelines for a comprehensive level of practice, exercises and hones virtues such
approach. Neither a virtue ethic nor a deonto- as courage, temperance, humility, trustworthiness,
logical ethic nor a consequentialist teleology can diligence, love, patience, and practical judgment
satisfy all the postulated criteria, but all are met in applying a principle-grounded ethic to work-
when as Louden (1987) suggests, the perspectives place decisions.
of virtue and the act-oriented theories are viewed An ethic of virtue highlights the need for each
as additive. Moral knowledge is the sort of person to seek a social identity and to seek the
knowledge that is to be applied with the most purpose for his or her life. People act ethically
delicate and sensitive judgment, something or unethically in the world as they face challenges
acquired from the experiences of life. The that change continuously over time. Because

TABLE II
Guidelines for applying ethics to business

An ethics theory as applied within an organization should:


1. Offer normative recommendations that are grounded empirically;
2. Be concerned with forming and developing values and thus with actually changing behaviors;
3. Recognize the importance of the persons who act as well as the acts themselves;
and
4. Consider the context, the environmental situation and cultural milieu, as they affect actors and acts.
How Virtue Fits Within Business Ethics 107

improvement and correction of mistakes is more using a complementary tripartite ethics formu-
realistic and ultimately more advantageous than lation.
seeking to optimize each decision and action, the
distinctive perspectives provided by a virtue ethic
are needed to complete a practical ethic. Without How virtue ethics fits with other theories
neglecting the need to analyze individual acts
one-by-one, a virtue perspective can provide a How can a manager, as a leader, incorporate a
learning process highlighting the continuous deliberate character or virtues perspective?
dynamic of action and development of the Tables III and IV are presented to facilitate
motivational dispositions of human persons to act engagement of this most practical issue, featuring
within the broad environmental and community some dangers arising from using normative and
context. The normative aim is to move toward thus ethical leadership paradigms that put greatest
the standard set by a concept of the good orga- focus on one, two, or three of the major ethics
nization. perspectives of Table I. Table III includes
The excellent manager overcomes pressures to leadership approaches that subordinate or neglect
compromise even newly acquired values, at times the character of the actor. The dangers associated
even opposing and then changing his or her with each are meant to represent extreme
habitual behavior. Field research in the Southeast outcomes, not necessarily the most likely ones.
U.S. found that those managers most admired by Whether or not a person must be moral to be a
peers and subordinates had successfully rejected leader (Bowie, 2000), these tables suggest that too
values ingrained in them as youths in the period narrow a perspective encourages pressures that
of racial segregation, adopting new habits of inhibit ethical practice. Each of the leadership
language and behavior toward other races paradigms in Table IV combine a human char-
(Whetstone, 1995). As organizations and their acter focus with either a deontological or a
activities increasingly become more global, the teleological orientation.
benefits of a virtue ethics perspective will
increase. Flatter and geographically dispersed
organizations especially need to rely upon the Consequentialist teleology
moral character of their managers.
Realistically, a truly virtuous manager is an Application of a teleological ethic, whether in
unrealizable ideal, but nevertheless represents a the form of utilitarianism or egoism, tends
set of virtuous character dispositions toward toward pragmatism in striving for the goals set
which a real – and necessarily imperfect – according to the mission or vision (Friedman,
manager can strive. This is an abstract as well as 1970; Drucker, 1974). At the extreme, any means
optimistic description, but one based on empir- can be rationalized if the intended end is judged
ical findings concerning what a specific set of to maximize the overall good. An example is
contemporary managers envision as their most Rost’s (1993, 1995) post-industrial leadership
admired managers. paradigm, a teleological descendant of participa-
In summary, a complete ethic is person- tive management approaches. The telos is the
centered and act-focused, dynamic as well as process of interrelationship defined in terms of
static, developmental and decision-focused, and non-coercive influence and mutuality. This
contextually adaptable. A Western conception of suggests that an act is okay, if people can agree
morality requires consideration of the motives of that it is okay. In addition to a measurement
the agent, the extent of his or her knowledge of problem, this paradigm’s pragmatic and social
the situation, and the conditions under which he constructionist orientation denies the meaning-
or she acted, as well as the rightness or wrong- fulness of universal deontic principles and values
ness of the act itself (Barnsley, 1972, p. 50). It and offers no role for personal virtues.
makes more sense for the practical aims of moral
development and moral reasoning if approached
108 J. Thomas Whetstone

TABLE III
Leadership risks
– Dangers of focusing too much on a particular act theory

Consequentialist teleology Deontology Virtue Principle-based ethic

Example: Postmodern leadership “Rules of the game” U-R-J Model


Dangers: Relativism; Legalism; N.A. Moral schizophrenia;
Pragmatic ends over means “Political correctness” Non use?

TABLE IV
Leadership risks
– Dangers of focusing too much on a particular combination of perspectives

Consequentialist Deontology Virtue Principle-based


teleology and virtue as primary ethic
and virtue and virtue

Example: Transformational Principle-centered “Strong” Servant


leadership leadership virtue ethic leadership
Dangers: Tyranny; Stoicism; Too Subjective; Ignorance of
Cultism Pietism; Irrational decisions virtue language;
Legalism Manipulation by
those served

Deontology Principles-based ethics (PBE)

At least at the extreme, a deontological ethic, one Combination ethics such as the DU Model or
that places its primary emphasis on behavior in Janus-faced ethic (Brady, 1985; 1990), and the
terms of obligations, rights, principles, rules or U-R-J Model (Cavanagh et al., 1981) have the
codes, in application can become legalistic, admirable aim of combining the benefits of
operating strictly by the “rules of the game” deontological and teleological perspectives.
(e.g., Carr, 1968). The rule of law becomes the However, at the intuitive level of business ethics,
law of rules. Historically, universalist ethics have their application can lead to moral schizophrenia
sometimes led to legalistic practices. This (Stocker, 1976; Kreeft, 1992) when the indicated
occurred in New Testament biblical times, in the actions conflict (MacIntyre, 1985). Even though
Middle Ages, and in the seventeenth century such conflicts may not be frequent (Green, 1994),
among the English and American Puritans, as they do occur, leading to moral dilemmas that
well as on contemporary university campuses in undermine the credibility of business ethics
the form of “political correctness.” A personal, theory in the eyes of business practitioners (Stark,
relational complement is needed to humanize the 1993).
abstract. But a principles-based ethic can be very useful
when applied in proper context by one using
virtuous judgment. On a prima facie basis,
adding a character perspective improves an
impersonal ethic. Horvath (1995) even claims
How Virtue Fits Within Business Ethics 109

that only a person of virtue can successfully dictators or cult leaders with followers who are
implement a principle-based ethic. The leader- willing to go to frightening excess. Napoleon
ship paradigms referenced in the cells of Table IV Bonaparte, Adolph Hitler, David Koresh of the
add a deliberate character orientation, with Waco incident, and Marshall Applewhite or Doe,
greater focus on the process of personal moral who led thirty-eight intelligent and skilled pro-
development. fessionals to commit suicide in California, each
exemplify the dark side of transformational lead-
ership.
Virtue and teleology

Virtue ethics involves reevaluation of the nature Virtue and deontology


of a telos (purpose or desired end) for life and
behavior in the business context (Solomon, Neglecting or even subordinating the individual
1992). Such a conception combines the teleo- or the community visionary perspective also can
logical focus on visionary ends with a focus on be dangerous. Corporations are well-advised to
character formation and motivation for achieving develop ethics codes, but the companies who rely
the vision. Although business people, in the daily most on written codes are not always the most
press of activity, may not often stop to reflect on ethical (Sorell and Hendry, 1994); they may just
their telos (Stewart, 1970; Mintzberg, 1971), they want a document declaring their integrity,
could benefit thereby (see Hartman, 1996, and without being willing to abide by it ( Jennings,
Werhane, 1999). To enable such reflection, 1999, p. 3). A code can beneficially impact the
Moberg and Calkins (1999) propose a disciplined ethical culture of the organization provided the
approach based on the five hundred years old moral standards obviously apply to everyone, not
Spiritual Exercises of Ignatius Loyola, one offering just the personnel at the operating level, and
renewal and growth in clear-headedness, provided the Board of Directors and CEO address
meaning, and wisdom to business leaders and the moral problems actually faced by employees
employees at every level. The intended outcome at the divisional and operating levels (Hosmer,
is for each exercitant to formulate a response – 1996, p. 150). The code needs to be democrat-
ideally a specific commitment he or she is ically derived and applied in a virtuous or good
prepared to make as a result of the process. community culture, such as Hartman’s (1996)
Duncan (1995) classifies the ethics of virtue good organization or Goodpaster’s (2000) ethical
as a non-rule-governed teleological theory, one culture.
beginning with a conception of the best kind of Stephen Covey’s (1991) principle-centered
life for a human. This view allows recognition of leadership paradigm combines a deontic focus on
moral rules, for example the use of casuistry, but objective principles for behavior with serious
is this sufficient for a comprehensive ethic? Some attention to development of one’s moral char-
leadership models suggest not, at least pointing acter qualities. Instead of the process focus of
to significant risks. For example, transformational transformational leadership, Covey stresses certain
leadership (Burns, 1978; Bass, 1985) incorporates universal principles – described by him as self-
a joint focus on virtue and teleology, being evident, self-validating laws of nature. Each
concerned with changing the behavior of people person is a product of her choices and, in turn,
by first changing their character. Transforma- character and conscience are what matter for her
tional leadership can be dangerous because it is choices. This leadership approach recalls the
deficient in constraints as to personal rights and world and life perspective of stoics such as
responsibilities (Keeley, 1995). The resulting Marcus Aurelius, employing traditional virtue
sense of “political correctness” can lead to language to describe objective and external prin-
tyranny as Madison and other American ciples, presuming that men and women become
founding fathers feared. At the extreme, virtuous through a knowledge that enables them
unchecked transformational leaders can become to live harmoniously within their environment.
110 J. Thomas Whetstone

But Viktor Frankl (1962) observes that man servant leader can be subject to manipulation;
does not behave morally for the sake of having he or she thus needs a strong vision, objective
a good conscience but for the sake of a cause to principles, and virtue to minimize this risk.
which he commits himself or for a person whom The advantage of a comprehensive tripartite
he loves or for the sake of his God. Those who approach is most apparent when one is faced
autonomously have a good conscience as their with the toughest dilemmas, those which may
motivation can become legalistic. Principle- require use of narrative to explore adequately
centered leadership tends to promote the existing (Nash, 2000; Freeman, 2000). Christiana and
system, focusing on “heal thyself ” techniques and Fred Sommers (1993) point to the classic
influencing one’s close circle of relationships dilemma posed in Melville’s novel Billy Budd: do
rather than on addressing the systemic factors of we punish people for the evil they do or for what
business (Nash, 1994, p. 30). This may be a they are? Does Billy Budd’s exceptionally pure
reason why many corporate managers teach and good character excuse or even mitigate his
Covey’s philosophy to their employees. A person act of accidentally killing an evil man? This is a
needs to be oriented critically toward a mean- clash between the military duty to execute a
ingful corporate or societal telos; otherwise one capital offender and the moral obligation to show
may well withdraw into stoicism or pietism or compassion to a virtuous man caught up in tragic
legalism. circumstances. In the novel, the virtuous man,
Billy Budd, is convicted and hanged without
opportunity for appeal. Does the deontological
Teleology and deontology and virtue – as morality prevail over virtue ethics in this case?
complements Or is Budd’s character enhanced with greater
honor than ever before? Both questions can be
For a more balanced ethic, all three ethics answered “yes.”
perspectives are needed. Servant leadership The reality of complex issues suggests a need
(Greenleaf, 1977; Spears, 1995) exemplifies the for developing a practical, user-friendly decision
tripartite ethics approach. A servant leader has model combining act-oriented approaches with
the character of a servant who seeks to lead attention to the virtues and vices of human
others toward a meaningful telos, but only character. Several that move in this direction have
according to highly principled means. The been proposed, including Hosmer’s (1994)
antithesis of institutional bureaucracy, servant multiple analysis that asks the decision-maker to
leadership is characterized by behavioral infor- consider ethical problems from the various per-
malities, offering empathetic support for ethical spectives of ten principles, including virtue;
behavior, and finding creative ways to do things Cavanaugh, Moberg, and Velasquez’s (1995)
better. For example, John Woolman was a servant utility-rights and duties-justice-caring model;
leader in the eighteenth century, successfully and DeGeorge’s (1999) “Steps of a General
investing over thirty years to persuade other Moral Analysis.” This is a positive trend that
American Quakers to abandon slavery. Aung Suu will help managers committed to enhancing
Kyi of Burma is a contemporary servant leader, moral development and moral reasoning, espe-
displaying an engaging sense of humor along cially as the following challenge is successfully
with a steely seriousness and deep commitment addressed.
(Horne, 1997) in spite of the persecutions of
house arrest, separation from family, and physical
danger. The servant leader formulation attempts The need for relearning the language of
to bring together the conceptual and intuitive virtues and vices
levels of ethics, offering a focus on developing
people fit to make the ethical choices and to Adding an attention to the virtues and vices of
implement them one-by-one – while continuing human character as a full complement to rea-
to improve over time. As Bowie (2000) notes, the soning according to deontological and conse-
How Virtue Fits Within Business Ethics 111

quentialist teleological formulations can offer “ethical” is not always well received. Managers
benefits in terms of moral development and as leaders can be bold in speaking in moral terms,
moral reasoning. However, the traditional and can more openly acknowledge the fact
language of virtue, going back to the ancient that people in organizations have valued moral
Greeks and medieval scholastics, may no longer orientations. The problem for contemporary
be adequate for contemporary business people. business leaders is not primarily the lack of
Deciding upon what values are most important articulation of moral concerns (Maclagan, 1998,
and what personal character qualities are needed p. 6), but that of understanding the language
by actors is thus essential at the intuitive level of people actually use. A message and challenge for
ethical practice. But MacIntyre (1985, p. 244) business ethicists is that more research is needed
observes that since the Enlightenment, there has on the subject of contemporary virtue and vice
been an inability even to agree upon a catalogue language as well as on developing further helpful
of virtues and, even more fundamentally, an ways of combining the application of virtue
inability to agree upon the relative importance and act-oriented perspectives by practicing
of virtue concepts within a moral scheme in managers.
which notions of rights and utility also have a
key place.
However, the perceived inadequacy of Conclusion
language presents a challenge rather than a
roadblock for scholars interested in business How does virtue ethics fit within business ethics?
ethics. Indeed, field observation and interviews Robert Louden’s thesis is that virtue ethics
of managers in their workplaces, food stores in theory should be included in any adequate
Mississippi, Tennessee, and Arkansas in 1993 and justification of morality. It fits very well if added
1994 (Whetstone, 1995), disputes the view that as a full complement to both deontological and
people in the workplace are “morally mute” consequentialist teleological act theories. This
(Bird and Waters, 1989). The food store paper does not claim to prove Louden’s thesis
managers interviewed use a moral language of according to formal philosophical argument, but
virtues and vices freely and articulately. However, focuses on the practical application of ethics
this language is not that of abstract deontolog- perspectives by business managers and leaders
ical or teleological philosophy or even the same seeking to promote moral development and
virtue and vice language, after translation, of moral reasoning. It proposes that business
classical Greece and medieval Europe. managers need to add virtue ethics, or more
What Bird and Waters (1989) found is that precisely an attention to virtues and vices of
contemporary managers, perhaps because they human character, as a fully-equal complement
are educated to be, or to pretend to be, morally to moral reasoning according to a deontological
neutral, treat almost as taboos the use of “right” focus on obligations to act and a teleological
and “wrong” and “good” and “bad” in assessing focus on the consequences of acts. There are
persons. Taboos of language are not necessarily beneficial reasons for doing so.
descriptive of reality, however. Ancient German Adding a virtue perspective as a complement
peoples did not have a word for “bear” because to act-oriented perspectives can expand to scope
of their fears and Victorians were enculturated to and perspectives of ethical analysis and under-
avoid sexual references, even substituting “limb” standing. This is because an Aristotelian virtue
for a piano’s “leg” (Dooling, 1999). But the perspective is personal; focuses on the motiva-
Germans killed bears and the Victorians tions of the actor and the sources of action,
reproduced. bringing a dynamic to ethical understanding; is
The implication is that business leaders can contextual, highlighting the importance of
indeed encourage “good conversation,” although understanding the environment as it affects both
as Trevino and Nelson (1995, p. 212) observe, actor and his or her acts; and complements other
explicit use of terms such as “moral” and disciplines addressing human behavior.
112 J. Thomas Whetstone

Even if the criticisms of virtue ethics success- can assist practicing managers lead moral
fully cloud its use as a mononomic or “strong” development and moral reasoning efforts.
normative theory of ethical justification, they do
not refute the above benefits of applying a virtue
ethics perspective – when done so in conjunc- References
tion with also-imperfect act-oriented perspec-
tives. Instead, they point to a need for an Anscomb, E.: 1958, ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’,
interactive tripartite approach in order to meet Philosophy 33, 1–19.
the complex requirements of an applied ethic in Aristotle: 1976, The Nicomachean Ethics, translated by
terms of human moral development and moral J. Thomson, revised with note and appendices by
reasoning concerning specific behavioral deci- H. Tredennick, introduction and bibliography by
sions. In practice, a complete ethic needs to be J. Barnes (Penguin, London).
person-centered and act-focused, dynamic as well Barnes, J.: 1976, Introduction to The Nicomachean Ethics
as static, developmental and decision-focused, (Penguin, London).
and contextually adaptable. Without neglecting Barnsley, J. H.: 1972, The Social Reality of Ethics
the need to analyze individual acts one-by-one, (Routledge & Kegan Paul, London).
a complementary virtue perspective can provide Bass, B. M.: 1985, Leadership and Performance Beyond
Expectations (Free Press, NY).
a learning process highlighting the continuous
Bird, F. and J. Waters: 1989, ‘The Moral Muteness
dynamic of action and development of the of Managers’, California Management Review 32(1),
motivational dispositions of human persons to act 73–88.
within the broad environmental and community Boatright, J. R.: 1995, ‘Aristotle Meets Wall Street:
context. The fully complementary formulation The Case for Virtue Ethics in Business’, Business
does not eliminate the risk of relativism some- Ethics Quarterly 5(2), 353–359.
times attributed to virtue ethics because it Bowie, N.: 1982, Business Ethics (Prentice-Hall,
involves subjective judgments informed by Englewood Cliffs, NJ).
community culture, but minimizes relativism by Bowie, N.: 1999, Business Ethics: A Kantian Perspective
relying on objective deontological principles (Blackwell, Oxford).
applied with phronesis. Bowie, N.: 2000, ‘Business Ethics, Philosophy, and
To illustrate how deficiencies of a “strong” the Next 25 Years’, Business Ethics Quarterly 10(1),
7–20.
virtue ethics formulation can be overcome by a
Broadie, S.: 1991, Ethics With Aristotle (Oxford
more balanced tripartite approach, this paper University Press, Oxford).
refers to several normative leadership paradigms Burns, J. M.: 1978, Leadership (Harper & Row, NY).
(each based on a combination of virtue, deon- Carr, A. Z.: 1968, ‘Is Business Bluffing Ethical?’,
tology, or consequentialist teleology ethics per- Harvard Business Review 46 ( January-February),
spectives) and the dangers inherent in each. The 143–153.
most balanced and thus favored leadership Cavanagh, G. F., D. J. Moberg and M. Velasquez:
paradigm is servant leadership, grounded in a 1981, ‘The Ethics of Organizational Politics’,
tripartite ethic. Academy of Management Review 6, 363–374.
Just as it begins with a challenge to continue Cavanagh, G. F., D. J. Moberg and M. Velasquez:
philosophic debate of Louden’s appeal for 1995, ‘Making Business Ethics Practical’, Business
abandoning mononomic conceptions of ethics Ethics Quarterly 5(3), 399–418.
Collier, J.: 1995, ‘The Virtuous Organization’,
theory, this paper concludes with a challenge to
Business Ethics: A European Review 4(3), 143–149.
empiricists to develop a more current descriptive Covey, S. R.: 1991, Principle-Centered Leadership
understanding of the moral language used in (Simon & Schuster, NY).
contemporary organizations. This, along with the Crisp, R.: 1998, ‘A Defence of Philosophical Business
continuing development of user-friendly decision Ethics’, in C. Cowton and R. Crisp (eds.), Business
models combining act-oriented approaches with Ethics: Perspectives on the Practice of Theory (Oxford
deliberate attention to human virtues and vices, University Press, Oxford), pp. 9–25.
How Virtue Fits Within Business Ethics 113

DeGeorge, R. T.: 1987, ‘The Status of Business Hartman, E. M.: 1998, ‘The Role of Character in
Ethics: Past and Future’, Journal of Business Ethics Business Ethics’, Business Ethics Quarterly 8(3),
6, 201–211. 547–559.
DeGeorge, R. T.: 1999, Business Ethics, 5th ed. Hauerwas, S.: 1974, Vision and Virtue (Notre Dame
(Prentice Hall, Upper Saddle River, NJ). Press, Notre Dame, IN).
DesJardins, J. R.: 1984, ‘Virtues and Business Ethics’, Horne, A.: 1997, ‘Battle in Burma’, The Wall Street
in M. Hoffman, J. M. Moore and A. Fredo (eds.), Journal (March 17), A18.
Corporate Governance and Institutionalizing Ethics Horvath, Charles M.: 1995, ‘Excellence v.
(D. C. Heath, Lexington, MA). Effectiveness: MacIntyre’s Critique of Business’,
Donaldson, T. and T. Dunfee: 1999, Ties That Bind: Business Ethics Quarterly 5(3), 499–532.
A Social Contracts Approach to Business Ethics Hosmer, L. T.: 1994, Moral Leadership in Business
(Harvard University Business School Press, Boston). (Irwin/McGraw-Hill, Boston, MA).
Donaldson, T. and P. Werhane: 1999, Ethical Issues in Hosmer, L. T.: 1996, The Ethics of Management, 3rd
Business: A Philosophical Approach, 6th edition, edition (Irwin, Chicago, IL).
(Prentice Hall, Upper Saddle River, NJ). Hursthouse, R.: 1997, ‘Virtue Theory and Abortion’,
Dooling, R.: 1999, ‘From Swearing By to Swearing in R. Crisp and M. Slote (eds.), Virtue Ethics
At’, The Wall Street Journal ( July 6), A14. (Oxford University Press, Oxford), pp. 217–238.
Drucker, P. F.: 1974, Management: Tasks, Respon- Jackson, J.: 1996, An Introduction to Business Ethics
sibilities, and Practices (Heinemann, London). (Blackwell, Oxford).
Duncan, S. M.: 1995, A Primer of Modern Virtue Ethics Jennings, M.: 1999, ‘The Evolution-and Devolution-
(University Press of America, Lanham, MD). of Journalistic Ethics’, Imprimis 28, 7.
Foot, P.: 1978, Virtues and Vices and Other Essays in Keeley, M.: 1995, ‘The Trouble with Trans-
Moral Philosophy (Basil Blackwell, Oxford). formational Leadership: Toward a Federalist Ethic
Frankl, V.: 1962, Man’s Search for Meaning: An for Organizations’, Business Ethics Quarterly 5(1),
Introduction to Logotherapy, translated by I. Lasch 67–96.
(Hodder & Stoughton, London). Koehn, D.: 1995, ‘A Role for Virtue Ethics in the
Freeman, R. E.: 2000, ‘Business Ethics at the Analysis of Business’, Business Ethics Quarterly 5(3),
Millennium’, Business Ethics Quarterly 10(1), 533–539.
169–180. Kreeft, P.: 1992, Back to Virtue (Ignatius, San
Friedman, M.: 1970, ‘The Social Responsibility of Francisco).
Business Is to Increase Its Profits’, New York Times Kupperman, J.: 1991, Character (Oxford University
Magazine (September 13) in Hoffman, W. M. and Press, NY).
J. M. Moore (eds.), 1990, Business Ethics: Readings Larmore, C. E.: 1987, Patterns of Moral Complexity
and Cases in Corporate Morality (McGraw-Hill, NY). (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge).
Giddens, A.: 1984, The Constitution of Society: Outline Louden, R. B.: 1984, ‘On Some Vices of Virtue
of the Theory of Structuration (Polity Press, Ethics’, in R. Crisp and M. Slote (eds.), 1997,
Cambridge). Virtue Ethics (Oxford University Press, Oxford).
Goodpaster, K. E.: 1991, ‘Ethical Imperatives and MacIntyre, A.: 1985, After Virtue: A Study in Moral
Corporate Leadership’, in R. E. Freeman (ed.), Theory, 2nd edition (Duckworth, London).
Business Ethics: The State of the Art (Oxford Maclagan, P.: 1998, Management and Morality (Sage,
University Press, NY). London).
Goodpaster, K. E.: 2000, ‘Conscience and Its Mahoney, J.: 1990, Teaching Business Ethics in the U.K.,
Counterfeits in Organizational Life: A New Europe and the U.S.A.: A Comparative Study
Interpretation of the Naturalistic Fallacy’, Business (Athlone Press, London).
Ethics Quarterly 10(1), 189–201. Mintzberg, H.: 1971, ‘Managerial Work: Analysis
Green, R. M.: 1994, The Ethical Manager: A New from Observation’, Management Science 17, 97–110.
Method for Business Ethics (Macmillan College Moberg, D. J. and M. Calkins: 1999, ‘Reflection in
Publishing Company, NY). Business Ethics: Insights from St. Ignatius’ Spiritual
Greenleaf, R. K.: 1977, Servant Leadership (Paulist Exercises’, presented August 7 at the 1999 Annual
Press, NY). Conference of the Society for Business Ethics,
Hartman, E. M.: 1996, Organizational Ethics and the Chicago, IL.
Good Life (Oxford University Press, NY). Monast, J. H.: 1994, ‘What Is (and Isn’t) the Matter
114 J. Thomas Whetstone

with “What’s the Matter. . . .” ’, Business Ethics Sorell, T. and J. Hendry: 1994, Business Ethics
Quarterly 4(4), 499–512. (Butterworth-Heinemann, Oxford).
Morgan, G.: 1996, Images of Organization, 2nd edition Spears, L. C. (ed.): 1995, Reflections on Leadership
(Sage, Thousand Oaks, CA). ( John Wiley & Sons, NY).
Nash, L. L.: 1990, Good Intentions Aside: A Manager’s Stark, A.: 1993, ‘What’s the Matter with Business
Guide to Resolving Ethical Problems (Harvard Ethics?’, Harvard Business Review 71(3), 38–48.
Business School Press, Cambridge, MA). Stewart, R.: 1970, Managers and Their Jobs (Pam Piper,
Nash, L. L.: 1994, Believers in Business (Thomas London).
Nelson, Nashville, TN). Stocker, M.: 1976, ‘The Schizophrenia of Modern
Nash, L. L.: 2000, ‘Intensive Care For Everyone’s Ethical Theories’, Journal of Philosophy 73,
Least Favorite Oxymoron: Narrative in Business 453–466.
Ethics’, Business Ethics Quarterly 10(1), 277–290. Trevino, L. K. and K. Nelson: 1995, Managing
Nesteruk, J.: 1995, ‘Law and the Virtues’, a review Business Ethics ( John Wiley, NY).
of Ethics and Excellence by R. C. Solomon, Business Velasquez, M.: 2000, ‘Globalization and the Failure
Ethics Quarterly 5(2), 361–369. of Ethics’, Business Ethics Quarterly 10(1), 343–352.
Niebuhr, H. R.: 1963, The Responsible Self (Harper & Walton, C.: 1988, The Moral Manager (Harper & Row,
Row, NY). NY).
O’Donovan, O.: 1986, Resurrection and Moral Order: Werhane, P. H.: 1999, Moral Imagination and
An Outline for Evangelical Ethics (Inter-Varsity: Management Decision Making (Oxford University
Leicester, U.K.). Press, NY).
Pincoffs, E.: 1986, Quandaries and Virtues: Against Whetstone, J. T.: 1995, ‘The Manager as a Moral
Reductionism in Ethics (University of Kansas Press, Person: Exploring Paths to Excellence’, unpub-
Lawrence, KS). lished D.Phil thesis, Oxford University.
Rost, J. C.: 1993, Leadership for the Twenty-first Century Williams, O. F.: 1984, ‘Who Cast the First Stone?’,
(Praeger, Westport, CT). Harvard Business Review 62 (September-October),
Rost, J. C.: 1995, ‘Leadership: A Discussion About 151–160.
Ethics’, Business Ethics Quarterly 5(1), 129–142.
Solomon, R. C.: 1992, Ethics and Excellence:
Cooperation and Integrity in Business (Oxford
University Press, NY). Davis College of Business,
Sommers, C. H.: 1991, ‘Teaching the Virtues’, Jacksonville University,
Imprimis 20 (November). 4484 Charter Point Boulevard,
Sommers, C. H. and F. Sommers: 1993, Virtue and Jacksonville, FL 32277,
Vice in Everyday Life (Harcourt Brace, Ft. Worth, U.S.A.
TX). E-mail: twhetst@ju.edu

You might also like