You are on page 1of 15

NeuroQuantology | September 2012 | Volume 10 | Issue 3 | Page 374-388 374

Georgiev D., Mind efforts, quantum Zeno effect and decoherence

Article

Mind Efforts, Quantum Zeno Effect and


Environmental Decoherence

Danko Georgiev
ABSTRACT
In this article we present the mathematical formalism of Quantum Zeno Effect (QZE) and explain how the QZE arises from
suppression of coherent evolution due to external strong probing action. Then we prove that the model advocated by Henry
Stapp, in which mind efforts are able to exert QZE upon brain states, is not robust against environmental decoherence if the
mind is supposed not to violate the Born rule and to act only locally at the brain. The only way for Stapp to patch his proposal
would require postulation of mind efforts acting globally on the brain and the entangled environment, which would be
regression to a theory predicting paranormal Psi effects. Our arguments, taken together with the lack of scientifically valid
confirmation of paranormal Psi effects such as telekinesis, imply that Stapp’s model does not have the potential to assist
neuroscientists in resolving the mind-brain puzzle.

Key Words:Quantum Zeno Effect, mind, brain, Stapp’s interactive dualism, decoherence
NeuroQuantology 2012; 3: 374-388

1. Introduction1 Surprisingly, the quantum physicist


The mind-brain problem is undoubtedly one of Henry Stapp claimed that he has found a
the most fascinating in natural sciences and quantum mechanism that allows for the mind
there has been hope that one can get deeper to govern the evolution of the brain despite the
insight in it by bringing together neuroscience environmental decoherence (Stapp, 2000;
and quantum mechanics (QM) (cf. Tarlacı 2001; 2007). It was suggested that mind
2010a,b). The fruitfulness of the latter efforts could prolong certain brain states via
approach however critically depends on the Quantum Zeno Effect (QZE) so that the
possibility of the brain to sustain quantum statistical averaging over macroscopic time
coherence for biologically relevant timescales intervals of brain's actions does not “wash out
(cf. Tegmark, 2000) and the quantum mind of all effects that depart from what would arise
advocates have been actively searching for from a classic statistical analysis that
physical mechanisms able to prolong desired incorporates the uncertainty principle as
quantum coherent states so that they may have simply lack of knowledge” (Schwartz et al.,
functional consequences in the operating 2005; p.1320). Formally, in order for the mind
neuronal networks. action upon brain to exert a form of QZE,
Stapp introduced two novel postulates
(axioms) according to which the metaphysical
(phenomenal) mind is given the freedom to
Corresponding author: Danko Georgiev, MD, PhD
Address: Department of Psychiatry and Neurobiology, Graduate locally operate at the brain and is able to select
School of Medical Science, Kanazawa University, 13-1 Takara-machi, both the timing and the measurement basis in
Kanazawa, Ishikawa 920-8641, Japan. which the brain state is collapsed: “the
Phone: +81-90-2038-7074
dankomed@yahoo.com
freedom to choose which questions are put to
Received April 19, 2012. Revised July 12, 2012. nature, and when they are asked, allows mind
Accepted July 13, 2012. to influence the behavior of the brain” (Stapp,
eISSN 1303-5150
www.neuroquantology.com
NeuroQuantology | September 2012 | Volume 10 | Issue 3 | Page 374-388 375
Georgiev D., Mind efforts, quantum Zeno effect and decoherence

2001; p.1488). Because the metaphysical brain and the entangled with the brain
mind represents the subjective aspects of environment (Section 3). From this follows
experience (qualia) and possesses no extra that either the mind efforts acting locally at
degrees of freedom different from those the brain are ineffective and not robust against
already possessed by the physical brain, the environmental decoherence contrary to
mind does not have its own wavefunction or Stapp’s claims, or that mind efforts act
density matrix and does not obey the globally at the brain and the entangled
Schrödinger equation. Stapp’s model is not environment, which implies telekinetic effects
based and cannot be based only on the axioms of the mind upon entangled with the brain
of QM introduced by von Neumann because in physical apparatuses. Finally, we prove a
von Neumann’s formulation there are no such quantum mechanical theorem based on
things as minds, spirits, ghosts or souls, which concrete calculation of the von Neumann
do not possess their own wavefunctions or entropy S ( ˆ) of the brain density matrix ̂ ,
density matrices but can interact with other which shows that the QZE exerted by the mind
physical objects. Exactly because the mind in locally onto the brain in general cannot slow
Stapp’s model does not have its own down or reverse the effects of environmental
wavefunction or density matrix, it should not decoherence (Section 4). Our argument, taken
be able to interact with anything physical together with the lack of scientifically valid
according to von Neumann’s formulation. confirmation of paranormal Psi effects such as
However, Stapp postulates that the mind telekinesis, implies that Stapp’s model does
actions could be modeled with the use of not have the potential needed to resolve the
quantum operators operating upon the brain mind-brain puzzle.
states (brain density matrix), which
necessarily requires the inclusion of the two
novel axioms allowing metaphysical objects 2. Mathematics of the QZE
(such as minds) to interact with physical The QZE was derived originally for unstable
objects by choosing which questions to ask, (decaying) systems where sufficiently quick
and when to ask them. Importantly, Stapp did repeated measurements delay the decay of the
not postulate that the mind is able to choose system. In the continuous measurement limit
the outcome of the wavefunction collapse, the system never decays (Misra and
which would be a radical violation of the Born Sudarshan, 1977). Experimentally the QZE was
rule in the standard QM formalism: “the brain first observed by Itano et al. (1990), who
does practically everything, but mind, by suggested that the QZE occurs because every
means of the limited effect of consenting to the measurement causes the wavefunction to
rapid re-posing of the question already collapse to a pure eigenstate of the
constructed and briefly presented by brain, measurement basis. Yet, this viewpoint was
can influence brain activity by causing this harshly criticized by several authors
activity to stay focused on the presented (Ballentine, 1991; Block and Berman, 1991;
course of action” (Stapp, 2001; p.1489). The Home and Whitaker, 1992; 1997), which
latter clarification is necessary, because if correctly pointed out that the quantum
mind efforts are postulated to violate the Born coherent evolution (according to the
rule then they could override easily the effects Schrödinger equation) is disturbed by frequent
due to environmental decoherence providing detector entanglements that lead to qubit
us with unlimited power to perform Psi effects mixed states, therefore the QZE results from
at our will. suppression of the coherent evolution of the
qubit, and does not require at all wavefunction
In the following exposition we present collapse. Insofar as we are not concerned with
the basic mathematical principles that account the reversibility of the QZE setup in the
for the QZE in a simple two-level system and following discussion we will leave it to the
without loss of generality we explain the reader to choose an interpretation for the
mechanism that makes QZE possible (Section evolution of the measured system: either it can
2). Then we introduce a laboratory setup to be viewed as evolving into proper mixture of
illustrate the discussion and to show that states as a result of wavefunction collapses or
generally in case of environmental just evolving into improper mixture of states
decoherence the mind efforts cannot exert as a result of external entanglements. Here we
QZE upon brain without acting globally on the remind that according to the terminology
www.neuroquantology.com
NeuroQuantology | September 2012 | Volume 10 | Issue 3 | Page 374-388 376
Georgiev D., Mind efforts, quantum Zeno effect and decoherence

introduced by d’Espagnat (1999), a proper therefore for the survival probability we


mixture is an ensemble for which can be given obtain:
an ignorance interpretation. Such a system is 2
in one of several possible pure states for which  t 
(4) p  1  
we could only ascribe different non-zero z 
statistical probabilities. That is why such a
state is also referred to as a statistical mixture. where the Zeno time is given by:
In contrast, an improper mixture is Hˆ
represented by a density matrix for which (5)  z1 

cannot be given an ignorance interpretation.
For improper mixture the individual systems where
are quantum entangled and cannot be thought ˆ   | H
ˆ 2 |   | H
ˆ |  2
(6) H
to be in some definite state of which we are 0 0 0 0

ignorant; rather, the reduced density operator Now suppose we make n quick
is the only description that they can have T 2T 3T
(d’Espagnat, 1999; Timpson and Brown, measurements at times t  , , ,,T . The
n n n
2005). Stapp agrees that the realities created survival probability is:
by two different preparation procedures that
n
give the same density matrix of the universe   T 2 
are one and the same reality. Thus if certain (7) p  1    
proper or improper brain mixtures are   n z  
described by identical brain density matrices,
and one easily verifies that in the
they will be considered one and the same
continuous limit if n   we obtain p  1 .
reality and the mechanism through which the
mixtures are obtained (external entanglements Mathematically the QZE relies on the fact that
or wavefunction collapses) will be irrelevant for n  1 :
for our discussion. n
  T 2    T 2 
The following mathematical sketch of (8) 1      1    
  n z   
  z  
QZE is rigorous and independent on the
interpretation of QM chosen. Let us have a Thus essential feature of the QZE is that
two-level system (qubit) undergoing decay and if the qubit is sufficiently frequently measured
let the quantum state at t  0 be | 0  . At time t there is a very high probability for finding the
the state evolves according to the Schrödinger qubit in undecayed state (Figure 1), or in other
ˆ / )|  . The Hamiltonian
equation to exp(ıHt words, the evolution of the qubit is delayed.
0

Ĥ , which is an operator corresponding to the In the following discussion, we will


total energy of the system, is assumed to have suppose without loss of generality that the
no explicit time dependence (Peres, 1980; brain could be modeled as an evolving two-
Facchi and Pascazio, 1998). The survival (non- level quantum system, which has two basis
decay) probability is given by: states | Yes and |No that correspond to Yes
ˆ / )|  |2 and No answers to a binary question, and that
(1) p |  0 |exp(ıHt 0
the brain Zeno time allows in principle for
Expanding as a power series: QZE to be realized (see also Stapp, 2001).
n
Then we will explain why the QZE could be

(2) ˆ / )  
exp(ıHt
  ıHtˆ /   effective only if the two-level brain being
measured in a certain basis is not being
n 0 n!
measured by a third party also. The latter
and for sufficiently small t we can result implies that a putative QZE depending
approximate: upon mind efforts in Stapp's model could not
ˆ ˆ2 2 be effective in case of environmental
(3) ˆ / )  1  ıHt  1 H t
exp(ıHt decoherence of the brain.
 2 2

www.neuroquantology.com
NeuroQuantology | September 2012 | Volume 10 | Issue 3 | Page 374-388 377
Georgiev D., Mind efforts, quantum Zeno effect and decoherence

Figure 1. QZE efficiency measured by the non-decay probability p for different values of the Zeno time τz (from 0.1 to 1.0) of the
system as a function of the number of observations n performed by an external agent for a unit time interval T. The non-decay
probability p for a given number of observations n is higher if the Zeno time τz of the system is longer.

3. QZE and Environmental Decoherence evolves into horizontally polarized state:


As we have briefly outlined in the introduction
 0
Stapp’s model relies on two postulates: the (10) | 2    
phenomenal mind, which has no extra 1
physical degrees of freedom is able (1) to The evolution of the quantum state of
measure the physical brain in a freely chosen the photon from vertical linear polarization
basis and (2) to choose the timing of this into horizontal linear polarization in the two-
measurement, which is supposed to work dimensional complex Hilbert space  plays
through wavefunction collapse and creation of the role of “decay” (Figure 2A). The
proper mixture of brain states rather than ˆ  ˆ , where ˆ
mind-brain entanglement and creation of Hamiltonian of the system H 1 1

improper mixture of brain states. Before we is the first Pauli spin matrix, is formally
address the environmental decoherence effects equivalent to the one governing the evolution
upon brain states let us introduce an easy to of two-level atom undergoing coherent Rabi
grasp laboratory setup of QZE with polarized oscillations (cf. Gagen, 1993).
photon, a version of which has been actually Next, we insert perfect polarizing
performed by Kwiat et al. (1995, 1996). First, beamsplitters after each polarization rotator,
we need a source of coherent light (laser). which are oriented so that the plane of
Then we pass the beam through vertical incidence coincides with the vertical plane and
polarization filter, after which we place n the angle of incidence of the laser beam is
equally spaced polarization rotators that rotate equal to the Brewster’s angle of the material
the polarization in clockwise direction by an the beamsplitter is made of. Thus each
angle    / 2n . After passing through the n beamsplitter entangles the photon
polarization rotators the initially vertically polarization with the photon path (cf.
polarized photon with state: Walborn et al., 2002; 2003) and in effect non-
destructively measures photon polarization so
1
(9) | 1     that the vertically polarized component will be
0 transmitted through the beamsplitter, while
www.neuroquantology.com
NeuroQuantology | September 2012 | Volume 10 | Issue 3 | Page 374-388 378
Georgiev D., Mind efforts, quantum Zeno effect and decoherence

the horizontally polarized component will be The projection operator asking the
reflected. The vertically polarized transmitted question “Is the photon not in the state | 1  ?”
ray through all beamsplitters is detected by is given by:
detector D1 , while the reflected horizontally
 1 0   1 0   0 0
polarized rays are detected by detectors D2 (14) Iˆ  Pˆ1     
through Dn  1 (Figure 2B). Since the detectors 0 1  0 0 0 1 
are assumed to be located in distinguishable For the two-dimensional Hilbert space of
spatial locations they automatically get the photon, the projection operator Iˆ  Pˆ1 is
entangled with the photon polarizations as the same as the projection operator
they absorb the photon traveling along one of
Pˆ2 | 2  2 | asking the question “Is the photon
the distinguishable paths. Notice that because
the beamsplitter orientation defines the plane in the state | 2  ?”. The two operators P̂1 and
of incidence and effectively decides the
Iˆ  Pˆ1
are orthogonal because Pˆ1 ( Iˆ  Pˆ1 )  0 .
measurement basis of photon polarization,
hereafter we will refer to each beamsplitter as These two orthogonal operators also sum up to
the measuring device that entangles the the unit operator Pˆ1  ( Iˆ  Pˆ1 )  Iˆ and thus
photon polarization and the corresponding define a choice of a measurement basis.
detectors.
Before the first polarization beamsplitter
After the first polarizing beamsplitter the the density matrix of the photon is:
vertically polarized photon state | 1  will be
 cos2  ı cos sin  
transmitted towards detector D1 , while the (15) ˆ   
 ı cos sin  sin 2  
horizontally polarized photon state | 2  will
be reflected towards detector D2 . Thus after After the first polarization beamsplitter
the first polarizing beamsplitter the composite the density matrix of the photon evolves as:
detector-photon system will be in a quantum (16) ˆ  ˆ1  Pˆ1 ˆPˆ1  ( Iˆ  Pˆ1 )ˆ( Iˆ  Pˆ1 )
entangled state:
| 1   cos | 1  | D1  Substituting the matrices for ̂ , P̂1 and
(11)
 ı sin | 2  | D2  ( Iˆ  Pˆ1 ) ,
and performing the matrix
and the photon state will be an improper multiplication gives:
mixture described by reduced density matrix:  cos2  0 
(17) ˆ1   
2
 cos  0   0 sin 2  
(12) ˆ1   
 0 sin 2   which was already obtained considering
In order to make a connection with the photon-detector entanglements.
Stapp’s description of the QZE, which uses Because an advocate of the
density matrices and projection operators, we “consciousness causes collapse” interpretation
should say that the action of the first of QM could theoretically replace the detectors
polarizing beamsplitter is formally equivalent with the eyes of human observers so that the
to a measurement of the photon in the photon evolves into proper mixture, it is
| 1 ,| 2  basis. After the measurement, the obvious that the conclusions from the
photon will be either in the state | 1  , or in the proposed laboratory setup will not depend on
state | 2  . The choice of a measurement basis the interpretation of QM used. Indeed it is a
basic quantum mechanical theorem that
is equivalent to a choice of a family of proper or improper mixtures described by the
orthogonal projection operators that sum up same density matrix are experimentally
to the unit operator Î . The projection indistinguishable.
operator asking the question “Is the photon in
the state | 1  ?” is given by: With every next beam splitting the
photon will evolve into an improper mixture
 1 0 of being horizontally polarized and thus
(13) Pˆ1 | 1  1 |  
0 0 reflected and detected by corresponding
detector, or being reset to its original state of
www.neuroquantology.com
NeuroQuantology | September 2012 | Volume 10 | Issue 3 | Page 374-388 379
Georgiev D., Mind efforts, quantum Zeno effect and decoherence

vertical polarization and transmitted towards measurements due to entanglements and we


D1 . After passing through the nth polarizing have shown that mathematically there is no
beamsplitter the photon state will be in a need for one to make recourse to
mixture in which the passage through all measurements due to von Neumann’s
detectors without decaying will have collapses. If the measurement of the evolving
probability of cos2n  . And this is exactly the qubit is continuous then a coherent state can
QZE - the photon decay probability from one be produced by the entanglements.
has been decreased to 1  cos2 n  due to Mathematically the QZE is result of
insertion of the polarizing beamsplitters, suppressing the quantum coherent (also
which measure the photon polarization and known as Schrödinger or unitary) evolution of
entangle it with the corresponding detectors. the target system, because in general the
In the final state |  n  resulting from n evolution from a state |a to state |b requires
successive entanglements: passage via intermediate state | a | b , which
entails interference (coherence). Unitary
|  n   cos n  | 1  | D1  (Schrödinger) evolution from |a to |b
 ı sin | 2  | D2  requires all the phase relations contained in
(18)
 ı cos sin | 2  | D3   the intermediate state | a | b and since the
 ı cos n 1  sin | 2  | Dn 1  phase relations are destroyed by
measurements, it is not surprising that motion
one can sort out the component | 1  | D1  becomes impossible in quantum theory if
that is realized with probability cos2n  and is coherence is completely absent (cf. Joos,
responsible for the QZE. Of course there are 2006). Thus QZE in the laboratory setup is a
also n orthogonal possibilities | 2  |D2  , result from diagonalization of the reduced
| 2  | D3  ,  , | 2  | Dn  1  , which are realized density matrix of the photon and it is
irrelevant whether such a diagonalized matrix
respectively with probabilities sin 2  , is proper or improper mixture.
cos2  sin 2  ,  , cos    sin2  . The reduced
2 n 1
Mathematically, the QZE can be also
density matrix of the photon becomes: reformulated in terms of density matrices and
 cos2 n  0  operators. Unitary evolution according to the
(19) ˆn   2n  Schrödinger equation is given by:
 0 1  cos  
(21) ˆ0  ˆ(t )
In the continuous limit when n   , the
latter n orthogonal states are realized with where ̂0 is the initial density matrix of
probability zero, while the state responsible for the quantum system at t=0, and the density
the QZE is realized with probability of one (cf. matrix of the system at time t is:
Joos, 1984). Therefore despite the fact that
(22) ˆ / )ˆ exp(ıHt
ˆ(t )  exp(ıHt ˆ / )
entanglements produce mixed state of the 0

photon, in the continuous limit n   the If the quantum system is not subject to
probabilities of reflected orthogonal states external measurements, it will evolve unitarily
vanish, and the final result is a coherent and would be able to “decay”. However if the
photon state | 1  at detector D1 , in which the system is subject to an external measurement
quantum amplitude of one is not caused by (described by a family of orthogonal projection
abrupt localization of the photon wavefunction operators that sum up to unity), the density
due to the von Neumann’s collapse postulate, matrix of the system would evolve non-
but is a mathematical consequence of the unitarily as:
continuous observation of the photon state. In
the continuous limit n   the reduced (23) ˆ  ˆ '  Pˆ ˆPˆ  ( Iˆ  Pˆ )ˆ( Iˆ  Pˆ )
density matrix of the photon is a pure state: If these non-unitary evolution steps
 1 0 ˆ  ˆ' are sufficiently frequent, the system
(20) ˆ   
0 0 will not be able to evolve at all i.e. QZE will
occur. The non-unitary evolution can be
Up to this point we have constructed a achieved either through external detector
laboratory QZE that results solely from entanglements or through von Neumann
www.neuroquantology.com
NeuroQuantology | September 2012 | Volume 10 | Issue 3 | Page 374-388 380
Georgiev D., Mind efforts, quantum Zeno effect and decoherence

wavefunction collapses. In both cases the collapses is “different” from the QZE realized
mathematics is the same, therefore the experimentally (Itano et al., 1990; Kwiat et al.,
putative mechanism for achieving QZE is 1995; 1996), in view of the preceding
irrelevant if one wants to study the effects of discussion it is clear that whatever that
environmental decoherence. Although Henry “difference” is, it does not and cannot affect
Stapp repeatedly stressed that the QZE the mathematics that is used to describe the
achieved through von Neumann wavefunction QZE.

Figure 2. Laboratory QZE experiment with a polarized photon. (A) Quantum coherent evolution of photon polarization from
vertical to horizontal one. The vertically polarized photon state decays into horizontally polarized one due to the n=3
polarization rotators, each rotating the plane of polarization by angle    / 2n . (B) Quantum Zeno Effect realized via
interspersed beamsplitters, which lead to photon-detector entanglements and photon mixed states. The photon polarization
decay is frozen by the polarizing beamsplitters, which observe the photon polarization state as the photon evolves.

Nevertheless, in order not to Now what remains in order to incorporate the


misrepresent Stapp’s position we will now environmental decoherence in our setup is to
require the reader to imagine that all the introduce a set of measuring devises (in our
intermediate measurements have been case beamsplitters) controlled by a third party
performed by a metaphysical (phenomenal) called environment, which will be able to
mind that acts upon and collapses the choose the measurement basis independently
wavefunction of the target two-level system, of the mind choices. Thus, let us double the
which in the discussed setup is the photon and number of rotators and beamsplitters to 2n
not the brain. Though from physical and let all odd numbered beamsplitters be
perspective the phenomenal mind does not controlled by the environment and all even
have extra degrees of freedom to get entangled numbered beamsplitters be controlled by the
with the photon (or the brain respectively) we mind. Since the environmental decoherence
will assume that this is not a conceptual could happen in any basis, we decide to
problem for Stapp’s model and the mind is investigate the effect of the environment if the
guiding the brain evolution via process that is measurements (projections) by the odd
equivalent to controlling the beamsplitter numbered beamsplitters are performed in a
orientation in the laboratory setup, which complementary basis:
effectively decides the measurement basis.
www.neuroquantology.com
NeuroQuantology | September 2012 | Volume 10 | Issue 3 | Page 374-388 381
Georgiev D., Mind efforts, quantum Zeno effect and decoherence

1 measurement basis (that is random switching


|    | 1  | 2   of the projection operators). The proof is
2
(24) transparent: if the mind itself does not use
1
|    | 1  | 2   QZE strategy and starts random switching of
2
the measurement basis the QZE will break
compared to the measurement basis chosen by down; therefore the QZE will break down also
the mind. This corresponds to all in the case when the mind is operating
beamsplitters operated by the environment together with a non-cooperating environment
being oriented with their plane of incidence at (e.g. one that uses a complementary
 / 4 so that they transmit the state |   and measurement basis or one that switches
reflect the state |   . The projection operators randomly the measurement basis).
associated with this choice of a measurement
basis are: 4. QZE cannot Slow Decoherence
What remains to be addressed is the claimed
½ ½ 
(25) Pˆ |    |   proof by Stapp (2007), according to which the
½ ½  QZE exerted by mind efforts upon the brain
 ½ ½  would work despite the environmental
(26) Pˆ |    |   decoherence, or to be more precise, the QZE
 ½ ½  exerted by the mind upon the brain in general
The operators P̂ and P̂ are orthogonal can slow down the environmental
decoherence of the brain. First, we note that
and they sum up to unity: Pˆ  Pˆ  Iˆ , as can be Stapp investigates a particular case in which
directly checked. the brain is measured by the environment in
the very same measurement basis in which
It is now easy to calculate that the
the mind makes wavefunction collapses. But
relevant probabilities are:
such an argument is fallacious, and practically
2n 2n
    says that if the environmental decoherence
(27) p1  cos     cos     assists the mind QZE and happens to be in the
4  4 
same measurement basis with the one chosen
2 k 2 2k 2
n
    by the mind, then the environmental
(28) p2   cos    cos     decoherence will not destroy the attempted by
k 1 4  4 
the mind QZE upon brain states. Only in the
2k 2 k 2
n
    special case when environmental decoherence
(29) p   cos     cos     happens to be in the desired by the mind
k1  4   4 
measurement basis, mind efforts will be
In the continuous limit n   , we have assisted by such decoherence. This is not
p1  0 , which means that the photon does not surprising because the environmental
arrive at all at D1 . Instead the photon ends decoherence of a macroscopic body can be
with probability 1/3 in state | 2  and with formally understood as a form of QZE in which
interference terms between different possible
probability 2/3 in state |   . Of course one locations of the macroscopic object are
might modify the setup in alternative ways and suppressed e.g. Joos (1984) argued that
suppose for example that the mind can also macroscopic body decoheres in a position
measure the reflected |   photon basis due to interaction with the photons
wavefunction branches, or alternatively the forming the background thermal radiation.
environment can measure the reflected | 2  Obviously if the mind wanted to decohere the
branches. Straightforward calculations show macroscopic brain in position basis, then the
that in either modification the QZE breaks environmental thermal decoherence will assist
down. This is due to the third party the job. Moreover, if this were the only basis
measurement (done by the environment) in a the mind can choose, then it is not clear what
complementary measurement basis, which is the function of such metaphysical mind and
effectively puts the photon polarization back what kind of freedom it has, since its role
into superposition of the states | 1  and | 2  . would be redundant with the one performed
by the thermal radiation.
The result is not surprising and would follow if
the mind itself started random switching of the
www.neuroquantology.com
NeuroQuantology | September 2012 | Volume 10 | Issue 3 | Page 374-388 382
Georgiev D., Mind efforts, quantum Zeno effect and decoherence

If the environment exerts the very same Neumann entropy is maximal. In other words,
QZE intended by the mind it will assist the the von Neumann entropy S ( ˆ) quantifies the
mind efforts. But this does not suffice for a departure of the system from a pure state.
general proof of robustness against
environmental decoherence, because it is First important feature of the von
possible for the decoherence basis to be Neumann entropy S ( ˆ) is that it remains
complementary to the one intended by the unchanged under unitary (quantum coherent)
mind. Thus Stapp’s discussion either evolution of the density matrix according to
presupposes that the environment already the Schrödinger equation. In other words, the
uses a measurement basis intended by the change of the von Neumann entropy in time
mind or that the mind cannot choose other for unitary evolution is zero:
measurement basis but the one chosen by the dS ( ˆ)
environment. (32) 0
dt
In general, environmental decoherence If the system is in a pure state with zero
can happen in any basis, although position and
von Neumann entropy and evolves coherently,
energy basis might be preferred (Zeh, 1996; then it will also have zero entropy after any
2000; 2005; Tegmark and Wheeler, 2001; period of time t.
Zurek, 2003; Hornberger, 2009).
Nevertheless, for the construction of the our Second important feature of the von
argument it does not really matter if the Neumann entropy S ( ˆ) is that if the quantum
environmental decoherence can happen in any system of interest undergoes environmental
basis or only in a certain preferred basis. What decoherence, the change of the von Neumann
is important is that whatever the basis in entropy in time is positive:
which the environmental decoherence
dS ( ˆ)
happens, the mind could not possibly exert an (33) 0
effective QZE in a complementary basis to the dt
one chosen by the environment. This Only for a completely mixed state the
contradicts with Stapp’s main thesis that change of the von Neumann entropy in time
mind choices are simultaneously effective and would be zero, but this is because the state
absolutely free. already has reached the maximal possible von
For those readers who are already Neumann entropy, which means that all
familiar with the basics of quantum possible quantum states are equally probable.
information theory we will prove a basic Since we are interested into realization
theorem, which directly invalidates Stapp’s of QZE, it is obvious that a completely mixed
claim that QZE can slow down environmental state having maximal von Neumann entropy
decoherence (Stapp, 2007). In the proof of the cannot be a starting point for QZE. If all
theorem we will use the concept of von quantum states are equally probable, then
Neumann entropy S ( ˆ) of the brain density with or without any intervention at a later
matrix ̂ , which provides a precise period of time t all quantum states will be also
quantitative measure of the brain equally probable. From the mathematical
decoherence. The von Neumann entropy S ( ˆ) sketch in Section 2, we have seen that in order
for QZE to be realized, one should start either
of a quantum system described by a density
with a pure state or with a quantum system
matrix ̂ is given by:
that is with very high probability in a certain
(30) S ( ˆ)  Tr ˆ ln ˆ initial quantum state | 0  . Then by performing
suitable QZE measurements one can keep high
which is equivalent to:
the probability for the quantum system to be
(31) S ( ˆ)   i ln i in the state | 0  even at a later time t. Note
i
that the QZE is not equivalent with the claim
where i are the eigenvalues of the that the state of the system does not change in
density matrix ̂ . If the density matrix of the time. The state may change in time and the
brain is a pure state, then the von Neumann probability for the system to be in the state
entropy is zero. If the density matrix of the | 0  may actually decrease in time. The
brain is a completely mixed state then the von important feature is that at the end the
www.neuroquantology.com
NeuroQuantology | September 2012 | Volume 10 | Issue 3 | Page 374-388 383
Georgiev D., Mind efforts, quantum Zeno effect and decoherence

probability for the system to be in a certain We will prove that if S ( ˆ0 ) is the von
state | 0  remains high (although it may not Neumann entropy of the initial brain density
be 100%). This requirement is violated for a matrix ̂0 and S ( ˆt ) is the von Neumann
completely mixed state where the state of the entropy of the density matrix ˆt , the inequality
quantum system may not change in time, but
S ( ˆt )  S ( ˆ0 ) holds for every P̂ . We will prove
all quantum states are equally probable, and
therefore no QZE occurs. the latter statement through direct algebraic
calculation of the relevant von Neumann
After ruling out a completely mixed state entropies.
as being the initial brain state in Stapp’s QZE
model, we can say that that environmental Keeping in mind that matrix
decoherence will always increase the von multiplication is not commutative we can
Neumann entropy of the brain density matrix rewrite ˆt as:
in time:
(39) ˆt  Pˆ ˆ0 Pˆ  ( Iˆ  Pˆ )ˆ0 ( Iˆ  Pˆ )
dS ( ˆ )
(34) 0
dt (40) ˆt  Pˆ ˆ0 Pˆ  ( Iˆ  Pˆ )( ˆ0 Iˆ  ˆ0 Pˆ )
Stapp’s claim that in general the mind ˆt  Pˆ ˆ0 Pˆ  Iˆ( ˆ0 Iˆ  ˆ0 Pˆ )
action onto the brain density matrix can slow (41)
down the environmental decoherence implies  Pˆ( ˆ0 Iˆ  ˆ0 Pˆ )
that the mind action should be able to
ˆt  Pˆ ˆ0 Pˆ  Iˆˆ0 Iˆ  Iˆˆ0 Pˆ
decrease the von Neumann entropy of the (42)
brain density matrix in time:  Pˆ ˆ0 Iˆ  Pˆ ˆ0 Pˆ
dS ( ˆ ) (43) ˆt  ˆ0  2 Pˆ ˆ0 Pˆ  ˆ0 Pˆ  Pˆ ˆ0
(35) 0
dt
Then we express the initial density
Indeed, if the mind QZE action cannot matrix ̂0 in the basis in which it is diagonal
generally decrease the von Neumann entropy
as:
of the brain in time, then it would be either
ineffective or may actually speed up k 0 
environmental brain decoherence, which (44) ˆ0   
 0 1  k
always increases the von Neumann entropy in
time. where k and 1  k are the eigenvalues of
the density matrix ̂0 . We note that because
To show that Stapp’s claim for mind
efforts slowing down the environmental the density matrix is a Hermitian operator, it
decoherence is erroneous, we will prove as a always has an orthonormal eigenbasis in
theorem that the von Neumann entropy which the matrix is diagonal.
production by the mind efforts is always: Next, we consider the most general case
dS ( ˆ ) for which P̂ chosen by the mind projects onto
(36) 0 an arbitrary vector |  and we express this
dt
vector in the basis in which ̂0 is diagonal as:
According to Stapp (2007) in QZE due to
the external probing mind action the density a
matrix of the brain evolves as: (45) |    
b
(37) ˆ0  ˆt
where a and b are complex numbers.
where ̂0 is the initial brain density Then we use the fact that introducing an
matrix just before the mind action, ˆt is the arbitrary pure phase exp  ı  does not change
brain density matrix at time t given by: the physical interpretation of the vector and fix
a to be real (see also Susskind 2006, 2008,
(38) ˆt  Pˆ ˆ0 Pˆ  ( Iˆ  Pˆ )ˆ0 ( Iˆ  Pˆ ) 2012). From the definition of a real number we
and P̂ is an arbitrary projection have:
operator. (46) a*  a

www.neuroquantology.com
NeuroQuantology | September 2012 | Volume 10 | Issue 3 | Page 374-388 384
Georgiev D., Mind efforts, quantum Zeno effect and decoherence

where a* is the complex conjugate of a . 1  k  ½


(54)
Next, we use the fact that the state is 2  1  k  ½
normalized so that aa *  bb*  1 (again see
Susskind 2006, 2008, 2012). Simple algebraic and the von Neumann entropy is
work gives us: maximal for both density matrices:
S ( ˆt )  S ( ˆ0 ) . (In addition, such scenario is not
1  a2 suitable for QZE because the initial state
(47) b* 
b cannot be completely mixed).
Since it is required that b  0 in order for Case 3. k  ½ , a  0,1 . First, let us note
the above fraction to be defined, the case in that the bigger the absolute difference
which b  0 will be investigated separately. between the two eigenvalues of the density
Thus for the projection operator P̂ we matrix, the smaller the von Neumann entropy
obtain: of the density matrix is. Therefore in order to
determine which density matrix ˆt or ̂0 has
a bigger von Neumann entropy it suffices to
(48) Pˆ |  |   a*  b* 
b compare the absolute differences between the
eigenvalues of ̂0 and ˆt , respectively.
 2 a(1  a2 ) 
a
(49) Pˆ   b
 The absolute difference between the
 
 ab
 1  a 
2 eigenvalues of ̂0 is:

Next we substitute into eq. (43) the (55) |1  2k | 0


matrices P̂ given by eq. (49) and ̂0 given by The absolute difference between the
eq. (44) in order to obtain ̂t in matrix form: eigenvalues of ˆt is:

A B | 1  2 ||1  2k  2a2 (1  2k )|
(50) ˆt   
C D (56) |(1  2k )(1  2a2 )|
where |1  2k |.|1  2a2 | 0

A  a2 (2  4k )  k  a4 ( 2  4k ) For a  0,1 , we have 0 |1  2a2 | 1 , and it


B  (a  3a3  2a 5 )( 1  2k ) / b is evident that the von Neumann entropy of
(51) the density matrix ˆt is always higher than
C  a( 1  2a2 )b( 1  2k )
that of the density matrix ̂0 : S ( ˆt )  S ( ˆ0 ) .
D  1  a4 (2  4k )  k  a2 ( 2  4k )
Taking together Cases 1-3 implies that
Although ̂t looks complicated, it has
the von Neumann entropy production by the
simple eigenvalues: mind efforts is always non-negative:
1  k  a2 (1  2k ) dS ( ˆ)
(52) 2
(57) 0
2  1  k  a (1  2k ) dt

The von Neumann entropy of the matrix From the above theorem follows
̂t is given by: immediately that QZE cannot decrease the
entropy of the brain density matrix ˆ0 , even if
(53) S ( ˆt )  1 ln 1  2 ln 2
it projects n times with an arbitrarily chosen
It is easy to see by inspection that always operator P̂ or operators Pˆ1 , Pˆ2 ,, Pˆn , because
S ( ˆt )  S ( ˆ0 ) because:
for each projection Pˆi the inequality
Case 1. b  0 , a  1 or b  1 , a  0 . The S ( ˆi )  S ( ˆi 1 ) holds. Projecting n times with
projection operators P̂ and Iˆ  Pˆ project onto any operators Pˆi cannot decrease the von
the basis in which the density matrix ˆ0 is
Neumann entropy of the brain.
diagonal. Therefore S ( ˆt )  S ( ˆ0 ) .
Finally, we would like to add that even
Case 2. k  1  k  ½ . Then a2 (1  2k )  0 , though the von Neumann entropy production
from which follows that: by the mind efforts is always non-negative,
www.neuroquantology.com
NeuroQuantology | September 2012 | Volume 10 | Issue 3 | Page 374-388 385
Georgiev D., Mind efforts, quantum Zeno effect and decoherence

there are possible special scenarios for which reflected or transmitted photon will get
the environmental decoherence could be entangled. This ensures consistency between
slowed down, but these require special the brain perceiving a flash due to the
requirements on the coupling between the transmitted photon and the actual
brain and its environment. Of course, if there transmission of the photon. If the mind locally
are some special requirements in the way the operating on the brain is able to choose the
brain decoherence occurs then QZE could slow outcome of the collapse it can always choose to
down such a special form of environmental see the flash, and thus the photon will be
decoherence, but this is something very always transmitted at the beamsplitter. Such
different from Stapp’s original claim for an effect is not dependent on external
general validity of his model irrespective of the decoherence, because regardless of the
form in which the environmental decoherence probability of the quantum event observed, the
occurs. We could further clarify that the mind by selectively actualizing the event
mentioned special requirements on the brain- (probability becomes equal to one) will affect
environment coupling concern the the externally entangled agent and it will not
Hamiltonian describing the brain- obey Born rule too. Indeed several advocates
environment interaction, and therefore there of the “mind causes collapse” proposal have
is no easy “patch” of Stapp’s model by simply tried to detect experimentally such mind
switching the decoherence basis or performing paranormal Psi effects and came up with
another simple trick. Indeed, it is not a big publications according to which the mind
surprise that Stapp failed in creating a working affects by thought the output from random
mind-brain model, because he did not use in number quantum generators (Jahn and
the construction of his model even the Dunne, 1986; Goswami, 1989; 1990; 1997),
essential minimum of quantum information conscious observer affects the decay of a qubit
theory. The possibility for an effective QZE (in (Bierman, 2003) or can change the outcome of
case of non-negative von Neumann entropy distant processes such as water crystal
production by mind efforts) for a special case formation (Radin et al., 2006). All such
of suitably chosen Hamiltonian describing the positive (successful) Psi experiments were
brain-environment interaction is a completely found to contain either statistical flaws
novel claim presented in this work and (Alcock, 2003; Jeffers, 2003; Bösch et al.,
therefore should not be attributed to Stapp 2006) or when performed by independent
whose QZE construction violates the basics of researchers end up with negative results (Hall
quantum information theory. et al., 1977). Therefore we assume that
paranormal Psi influence upon brain
5. Mind Physics and Psi Effects environment such as telekinesis would be a
In the preceding discussion we have presented regression for Stapp’s model. That is why we
the theory of the QZE arising from standard have stressed earlier that Stapp does not use as
QM formalism. We have also assumed that the a postulate possible violation of the Born rule.
mind affects directly the brain (or the photon Next, we show that if mind efforts were
in the laboratory setup) by choosing the acting globally upon the composite system
measurement basis. Moreover, since such an brain-environment they could be effective in
influence has been postulated by Stapp’s exerting QZE upon brain states, but also would
theory it is not considered here as a exert QZE upon the environment. Indeed, the
paranormal Psi effect. However, any influence only way for the mind to be generally effective
that might lead to detectable effect upon the in controlling the brain in case of
interacting with the brain environment (such environmental decoherence would be if the
as laboratory apparatus) is referred to as a mind is allowed to perform global
paranormal Psi effect (telekinesis). measurement of the composite system
First, we briefly discuss the possible describing both the brain and its environment.
violation of the Born rule, in which one insists Suppose that in addition to the brain, modeled
that the mind can chose the outcome of the as a two-level quantum system with
wavefunction collapse. Due to interaction corresponding two-dimensional complex
between the physical brain and observed Hilbert space 1 spanned by the two
external quantum system e.g. a photon passing orthonormal basis states | Yes and |No , we
through a beamsplitter, the brain and the have also a very simple two-level environment
www.neuroquantology.com
NeuroQuantology | September 2012 | Volume 10 | Issue 3 | Page 374-388 386
Georgiev D., Mind efforts, quantum Zeno effect and decoherence

with corresponding two-dimensional complex however, is hardly a justification for the


Hilbert space 2 spanned by an orthonormal general claim that QZE exerted by mind efforts
basis | 1  , | 2  . The composite brain- is robust against environmental decoherence,
environment system should be described in and, if pursued further, it would face the main
four-dimensional complex Hilbert space problem that all quantum mind theories are
total  1  2 (cf. Griffiths, 2003; Susskind, supposed to answer – how the brain avoids
decoherence and why there should be any
2006; 2008; 2012), which now has four basis special conditions within or around the brain
vectors | Yes | 1  , | Yes | 2  , |No | 1  , that suppress environmental decoherence
|No | 2 . If the composite brain-environment rather than enhance it?
system is in a pure state with zero von
Neumann entropy (or if it is in a state that is 6. Discussion
close to a pure state) one can show that the To the best of our knowledge the central
mind could achieve QZE upon both the brain argument of the current work that mind
and the environment if it were allowed to efforts in Stapp’s model are not robust
perform global measurements in the space against environmental decoherence is novel,
total and provided that this composite system although concerns for possible paranormal
is not decohered by the rest of the Universe. mind effects in Stapp’s model have been
Indeed, it is a standard approach to exert QZE voiced before (cf. Donald, 2003). We have
upon the local environment (e.g. rigorously shown that Stapp’s model cannot
electromagnetic cavity) in order to delay the satisfy and have at the same time: (1) mind
decoherence of a target quantum system (e.g. that does not violate the Born rule and does
trapped ions) provided that the actions upon not actively choose the outcome of the
this local environment are not overridden by collapse, (2) mind that acts only locally at the
decoherence due to interaction with the rest of brain, (3) mind that exerts a form of QZE upon
the Universe (cf. Maniscalco et al., 2008). brain, which is robust against environmental
Such a global effect of mind efforts however decoherence, and (4) mind, which chooses the
would imply existence of paranormal Psi basis in which the QZE is exerted. One of these
influence of the mind upon the environment, four requirements should be relaxed if Stapp is
which we have already noted is an to be consistent, but none is satisfactory.
experimentally disproved option. It could be Relaxing conditions (1) or (2) leads to
added, that if one thinks of QZE performed on prediction of paranormal Psi effects exerted by
the composite system containing the brain and the mind upon the environment surrounding
its local environment then it would be required the physical brain, relaxing the condition (3)
for this composite system to be isolated so that implies that mind efforts are generally
it does not suffer decoherence from the rest of ineffective in the case of environmental
the Universe. However, because the latter decoherence, and relaxing condition (4)
requirement cannot be physically justified, one implies that the mind has no free will
would be further led to postulate that the mind whatsoever. In the latter case the mind action
actually operates upon the whole Universe, would be redundant with the action of the
because at present it is considered that only environment to decohere the brain (with the
the Universe as a whole does not suffer possible exception that the mind introduces
external decoherence. Such a possibility does irreversibility in the overall process making
not seem to be attractive scientific program to quantum erasure impossible). Moreover, in
be further pursued, although it might be such a case the mind will observe the QZE
enthusiastically cheered by those who believe caused by the environment rather than cause
in paranormal Psi effects (cf. Bem and the QZE.
Honorton, 1994; Grinberg-Zylberbaum et al.,
Stapp’s description of how the mind
1994; Thaheld, 2010; de Castro, 2011;
Erickson, 2011; Haas, 2011; Krippner and exerts QZE upon the brain manages to obscure
the necessity to associate state vectors (and
Fracasso, 2011; Persinger and St-Pierre, 2011;
Temkin, 2011; Wolf, 2011). density matrices) both to the mind and the
brain, and this problem remains “hidden” in
Finally, there is a possibility to require the operator terminology attributed to von
some special conditions for the brain- Neumann. In the current work we have
environment coupling. Such an option, purposefully stressed upon the fact that the
www.neuroquantology.com
NeuroQuantology | September 2012 | Volume 10 | Issue 3 | Page 374-388 387
Georgiev D., Mind efforts, quantum Zeno effect and decoherence

metaphysical mind has neither a state vector where 0  8.85  1012 F m -1 is the
nor a density matrix within Stapp’s model. vacuum permittivity, m  3.85  1026 kg is the
Although similarly to Stapp we have assumed
mass of the sodium ion, N  1.15  109 is the
that the actions of the phenomenal mind can
be described by quantum operators that number of sodium ions that enter into the
represent the measurement processes cortical pyramidal neuron per single action
performed by the mind, we made it clear that potential (Laughlin and Attwell, 2004),
this assumption requires introduction of new n  1.75  1026 m -3 is the total density of ions
postulates (axioms). Thus, we consider that (both positive and negative) in the brain
Stapp misleadingly claims that his model is corresponding to physiological osmolarity of
equivalent to von Neumann’s formulation of 290 mOsm, qe  1.6  1019 C is the elementary
QM. It is not! charge, k  1.38  1023 J K -1 is the Boltzmann
The central result of the current work is constant, and T  310 K is the temperature.
that the original exposition by Stapp (2007), After numerical substitution with the
Sec. 11.2, Figures 11.3-11.7 describing how the biologically relevant values we obtain
mind efforts can slow down environmental  dec  5.14  1024 s . Since in the mental
decoherence is erroneous and contradicts a representation of sensory information (or for
basic quantum mechanical theorem proven in generation of motor output) is involved not a
Section 4 according to which the von single neuron but millions of neurons in a
Neumann entropy production by the mind particular field of the cerebral cortex, from
efforts is always non-negative. This result, Tegmark’s estimate follows that the
taken together with our objections against the decoherence time of the brain cortical
feasibility of paranormal Psi effects, implies neuronal network due to ion-ion collisions
that Stapp’s model does not have the potential
 dec  5  1030 s is only few orders of magnitude
to assist neuroscientists in resolving the mind-
brain puzzle. above the Planck scale. This estimate
essentially fixes the dynamical timescale of
mind choices in Stapp’s model due to the
Appendix requirement  dyn   dec .
Tegmark’s Decoherence Formula
If the mind is supposed to be effective in
controlling the brain states it follows that the
mind dynamic timescale  dyn should be
comparable but not slower than the brain
decoherence timescale  dec . From neuroscience
Acknowledgments
it is well known that the input of sensory and The author would like to thank Professor Henry Stapp
the output of motor information from the for providing clarifications of his own model and
brain cortex happen to be at millisecond commenting on a previous version of this manuscript.
timescale via electrical firing of axons. The Any remaining unclarities or omissions in the text
decoherence timescale due to ion-ion remain the responsibility of the author.
collisions for a single firing neuron was
estimated by Tegmark (2000) to be:
2 3
 4 0  m  kT 
(58)  dec 
Nqe4 n

www.neuroquantology.com
NeuroQuantology | September 2012 | Volume 10 | Issue 3 | Page 374-388 388
Georgiev D., Mind efforts, quantum Zeno effect and decoherence

References Krippner S, Fracasso C. Dreams, telepathy, and various states of


Alcock J. Give the null hypothesis a chance: reasons to remain consciousness. NeuroQuantology 2011; 9: 1-4.
doubtful about the existence of Psi. Journal of Kwiat P, Weinfurter H, Herzog T, Zeilinger A, Kasevich MA.
Consciousness Studies 2003; 10: 29-50. Interaction-free measurement. Physical Review Letters
Ballentine LE. Comment on “Quantum Zeno effect”. Physical 1995; 74: 4763-4767.
Review A 1991; 43: 5165-5167. Kwiat P, Weinfurter H, Zeilinger A. Quantum seeing in the dark.
Bem DJ, Honorton C. Does Psi exist? Replicable evidence for an Scientific American 1996; 275: 72-78.
anomalous process of information transfer. Psychological Laughlin SB, Attwell D. Neural energy consumption and the
Bulletin 1994; 115: 4-18. representation of mental events. In: Brain Energetics and
Bierman DJ. Does consciousness collapse the wave-packet? Neuronal Activity, Shulman RG and Rothman DL (eds.), pp.
Mind and Matter 2003; 1: 45-57. 111-124, 2004.
Block E, Berman PR. Quantum Zeno effect and quantum Zeno Maniscalco S, Francica F, Zaffino RL, Lo Gullo N, Plastina F.
paradox in atomic physics. Physical Review A 1991; 44: Protecting entanglement via the quantum Zeno effect.
1466-1472. Physical Review Letters 2008; 100: 090503.
Bösch H, Steinkamp F, Boller E. Examining psychokinesis: the Misra B, Sudarshan G.The Zeno’s paradox in quantum
interaction of human intention with random number theory.Journal of Mathematical Physics 1977; 18: 756-763.
generators - a meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin 2006; Peres A. Zeno paradox in quantum theory. American Journal of
132: 497-523. Physics 1980; 48: 931-932.
d’Espagnat B. Conceptual Foundations Of Quantum Mechanics, Persinger MA, St-Pierre LS. The biophysics at death: three
2nd edition, Reading, Massachusetts, Perseus Books, 1999. hypotheses with potential application to paranormal
de Castro JFB. Reflections about parapsychology and the phenomena. NeuroQuantology 2011; 9: 36-40.
philosophy of science: has parapsychology progressed as a Radin D, Hayssen G, Emoto M, Kizu T. Double-blind test of the
science to the point where science can include Psi and effects of distant intention on water crystal formation.
transpersonal views in its hard core? NeuroQuantology Explore: The Journal of Science and Healing 2006; 2: 408-
2011; 9: 106-117. 411.
Donald MJ. On the work of Henry P. Stapp. 2003; ArXiv: quant- Schwartz JM, Stapp HP, Beauregard M. Quantum physics in
ph/0311158 neuroscience and psychology: a neurophysical model of
Erickson DL. Intuition, telepathy, and interspecies mind-brain interaction. Philosophical Transactions of the
communication: a multidisciplinary perspective. Royal Society B 2005; 360: 1309-1327.
NeuroQuantology 2011; 9: 145-152. Stapp HP. Decoherence, quantum Zeno effect, and the efficacy
Facchi P, Pascazio S. Temporal behavior and quantum Zeno of mental effort, 2000; ArXiv: quant-ph/0003065
time of an excited state of the hydrogen atom. Physics Stapp HP. Quantum theory and the role of mind in nature.
Letters A 1998; 241: 139-144. Foundations of Physics 2001; 31, 1465-1499.
Gagen MJ. Quantum measurement theory and the quantum Stapp HP. The Mindful Universe: Quantum Mechanics and the
Zeno effect. Dissertation, University of Queensland. 1993. Participating Observer, Berlin, Springer, 2007.
Griffiths RB. Consistent Quantum Theory, Cambridge Susskind L. Quantum Entanglements. Stanford Continuing
University Press, 2003. Studies course, Stanford University, 2006.
Grinberg-Zylberbaum J, Delaflor M, Attie L, Goswami A. The Susskind L. Quantum Mechanics. Stanford Continuing Studies
Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox in the brain: the course, Stanford University, 2008.
transferred potential. Physics Essays 1994; 7: 422-428. Susskind L. Quantum Mechanics. Stanford Continuing Studies
Goswami A. Idealistic interpretation of quantum mechanics. course, Stanford University, 2012.
Physics Essays 1989; 2: 385-400. Tarlacı S. Why we need quantum physics for cognitive
Goswami A. Consciousness in quantum physics and the mind- neuroscience. NeuroQuantology 2010a; 8: 66-76.
body problem. Journal of Mind and Behavior 1990; 11: 75- Tarlacı S. A historical view of the relation between quantum
96. mechanics and the brain: a neuroquantologic perspective.
Goswami A. Consciousness and biological order: toward a NeuroQuantology 2010b; 8: 120-136.
quantum theory of life and its evolution. Integrative Tegmark M. Importance of quantum decoherence in brain
Psychological and Behavioral Science 1997; 32: 86-100. processes. Physical Review E 2000; 61, 4194-4206.
Haas AS. The interpretation of telepathy like effects: a novel Tegmark M, Wheeler JA. 100 years of the quantum. Scientific
electromagnetic and synchronistic version of the American 2001; 284: 68-75.
psychoanalytic model. NeuroQuantology 2011; 9: 22-35. Temkin AY. Extrasensory perception as a natural, but not
Hall J, Kim C, McElroy B, Shimony A. Wave-packet reduction as supernatural phenomenon. NeuroQuantology 2011; 9: 157-
a medium of communication. Foundations of Physics 1977; 165.
7: 759-767. Thaheld FH. Quantum nonlocality: does nature also perform the
Home D, Whitaker M.A critical re-examination of the quantum trick via a biological route? NeuroQuantology 2010; 8: 164-
Zeno paradox. Journal of Physics A 1992; 25: 657-664. 167.
Home D, Whitaker M.A conceptual analysis of quantum Zeno Timpson CG, Brown HR. Proper and improper separability.
paradox, measurement, and experiment. Annals of Physics International Journal of Quantum Information 2005; 3:
1997; 258: 237-285. 679-690.
Hornberger K. Introduction to decoherence theory. Lecture Walborn SP, Cunha M, Padua S, Monken CH. Double-slit
Notes in Physics 2009; 768, 221-276. quantum eraser. Physical Review A 2002; 65: 033818.
Itano WM., Heinzen DJ, Bollinger JJ, Wineland DJ. Quantum Walborn SP, Cunha M, Padua S, Monken CH. Quantum erasure.
Zeno effect. Physical Review A 1990; 41: 2295-2300. American Scientist 2003; 91: 336-343.
Jahn RG, Dunne BJ. On the quantum mechanics of Wolf FA. Towards a quantum field theory of mind.
consciousness, with application to anomalous phenomena. NeuroQuantology 2011; 9: 442-458.
Foundations of Physics 1986; 16: 721-772. Zeh HD. What is achieved by decoherence? 1996; ArXiv: quant-
Jeffers S. Physics and claims for anomalous effects related to ph/9610014
consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 2003; 10: Zeh HD. The meaning of decoherence. Lecture Notes in Physics
135-152. 2000; 538: 19-42.
Joos E. Continuous measurement: watchdog effect versus Zeh HD. Roots and fruits of decoherence. 2005; ArXiv: quant-
golden rule. Physical Review D 1984; 29: 1626-1633. ph/0512078
Joos E. Decoherence unlimited: From Zeno to classical motion. Zurek WH. Decoherence, einselection, and the quantum origins
In: Time & Matter, Bigi II and Faessler M (eds.), World of the classical. Reviews of Modern Physics 2003; 75: 715-
Scientific Publishing Company, pp.103-116, 2006. 765.

www.neuroquantology.com

You might also like