You are on page 1of 15

Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology © 2010 American Psychological Association

2010, Vol. 30, No. 2, 94 –108 1068-8471/10/$12.00 DOI: 10.1037/a0020290

Improving Moral Judgments: Philosophical Considerations


Annemarie Kalis
Utrecht University

In contemporary moral psychology, an often-heard claim is that knowing how we make


moral judgments can help us make better moral judgments. Discussions about moral
development and improvement are often framed in terms of the question of which mental
processes have a better chance of leading to good moral judgments. However, few studies
elaborate on the question of what makes a moral judgment a good moral judgment. This
article examines what is needed to answer questions of moral improvement and develop-
ment. It distinguishes 3 types of claims that are at stake: descriptive claims, metaethical
claims, and normative claims. To find out what makes certain moral judgments better than
others, one needs to have insight in the psychological processes and capacities underlying
moral judgment formation. However, one also needs to address the question of what makes
a moral judgment justified, and this in turn requires a view on the nature of moral goodness
and on the question of what makes a judgment moral at all. The author discusses possible
ways in which philosophical theories in the areas of metaethics and normative ethics can
contribute to the answering of such questions. Also, she provides concrete suggestions for
doing interdisciplinary research that is able to address those questions in moral psychology
that have both normative and descriptive aspects.

Keywords: moral judgments, moral psychology, normativity, normative ethics, metaethics

In recent years, the neuroscientific and psy- Thagard, 2007). However, to determine what
chological study of moral behavior and moral role processes such as rational reflection and
decision making has been rapidly expanding emotions can play in improving one’s moral
(Greene & Haidt, 2002; Sinnott-Armstrong, judgments, one first needs to answer the ques-
2008; Wallace, 2005). Central questions in this tion of what makes certain moral judgments
field are the following: What brain processes are better than others. In other words, the question
involved in moral decisions and behavior of how to improve moral judgments should be
(Casebeer, 2003; Greene & Haidt, 2002)? What preceded by another question: What would “im-
is the role of rational deliberation in moral judg- provement” consist of? The claim that a moral
ment formation (Fine, 2006; Horgan & Tim- judgment is a good moral judgment can mean
mons, 2007; Pizarro & Bloom, 2003), and what different things. To name a few examples, it can
is the role of emotions (Jones, 2006; Nichols, mean that the content of the judgment somehow
2008; Prinz, 2006)? Several authors have em- reflects a moral truth, or it can mean that the
phasized that knowledge about how people judgment is good in that it has been reached by
make moral judgments can also tell us how to means of a sound method. In this article, I argue
make better moral judgments, that psychologi- that recent work in moral psychology is in need
cal insights can contribute to the improvement of more explicit “criteria of quality,” and that
of human moral skills (Fine, 2006; Haidt, 2001; some influential distinctions from philosophical
ethics could contribute to the development of
such criteria.

Annemarie Kalis, Ethics Institute, Department of Philos-


ophy, Utrecht University. The Issue of Improvement in Moral
I thank Robert Heeger, Ineke Bolt, Maartje Schermer, and Psychology
Micha Werner for their valuable comments on a draft of this
article.
Correspondence concerning this article should be ad-
The Debate About Moral Development
dressed to Annemarie Kalis, Ethics Institute, Utrecht Uni-
versity, Heidelberglaan 8, 3584 CS Utrecht, The Nether- The idea that some moral judgments are better
lands. E-mail: A.Kalis@uu.nl than others plays an important role in psycholog-
94
IMPROVING MORAL JUDGMENTS 95

ical research; it has a long tradition in the work on ample is Kohlberg, who explicitly based his
moral development and moral education. Central model of moral development on a Kantian ap-
issues in this debate, which blossomed in the proach to morality (Kohlberg, 1981). He argued
1960s partly in response to the work of Lawrence for what he labeled methodological nonrelativism
Kohlberg (Kohlberg, 1958), are questions such as (Kohlberg, 1971), a method that was based on
how people develop moral skills, and what social John Rawls’s version of Kantianism (Kohlberg,
and educational structures contribute to (or ham- 1981; Rawls, 1971). This approach constituted
per) the development of such skills. Within this Kohlberg’s theoretical basis for his claim that
extensive field of research, different traditions can higher stages of moral reasoning are better than
be distinguished. The behaviorist tradition, repre- earlier stages. Given its Kantian philosophical
sented by authors such as Durkheim (1961) and foundation, his model has been criticized for being
Bandura (Bandura & McDonald, 1963), is based vulnerable to the same objections that can be
on the assumption that all moral skills must be made against Kantianism in general (Rest et al.,
learned from the social environment, that human 1999). On the other hand, psychologists working
beings do not possess any inborn moral abilities. in behaviorist and psychoanalytic traditions have
Developing such skills thus requires certain forms been criticized for basing their psychological hy-
of social learning. A completely different picture potheses on unreflected common opinions about
has been brought forward by the psychoanalytic what we take to be morally right and morally
tradition: Psychoanalysts argue that moral devel- wrong (Kohlberg, 1971; Turiel, 2008).
opment consists of finding a good balance be- Whereas the normative basis of psychologi-
tween one’s instinctual (mainly sexual) impulses cal research on moral development was at least
and the requirements of society (Emden, Johnson, an explicit topic of discussion in earlier tradi-
& Easterbrooks, 1990; Freud, 1930/1961; Meiss- tions, most recent literature on the psychology
ner, 2003). In this tradition, developing one’s and neuroscience of moral judgment formation
moral skills involves active suppression of inborn does not seem to make use of the insights
tendencies. On the other hand, authors such as gained in these discussions (Turiel, 2008). One
Piaget (1965) and Kohlberg (1958) emphasize interesting question is why this would be so.
that human beings are different from other ani- One influential point of criticism raised against
mals because they possess reasoning skills, and Kohlberg’s work was that it was based solely on
that moral development consists precisely of a the notion of justice and ignored other possible
development of these cognitive skills. Whereas normative grounds for good moral decision
Piaget focused on moral development in young making (Gilligan, 1982). This problem of one-
children, Kohlberg developed a stage model of sidedness in the theoretical position adopted by
moral development covering development into Kohlberg might have led psychologists to re-
adulthood. He distinguished six stages of moral frain from taking a philosophical stance in gen-
reasoning ranging from a moral orientation that is eral. Also, regardless of a growing interest in
based merely on notions of obedience and punish- interdisciplinary research, current scientific
ment (Stage 1) to moral reasoning based on uni- practice is still largely focused on specialization
versal and abstract principles (Stage 6). Kohl- and not on combining insights from different
berg’s work has been criticized for different academic fields. However, as I argue below,
reasons (for an overview, see Rest, Narvaez, many contemporary psychologists working in
Bebeau, & Thoma, 1999). As a result of these moral psychology implicitly do venture beyond
debates, several adaptations of Kohlberg’s stage the domain of empirical investigation: The sub-
model have been developed (Gilligan, 1982; ject matter they are concerned with requires
Turiel, 1983). them to make certain assumptions regarding the
In trying to get a grip on the complicated issue question of what makes some moral judgments
of moral development, researchers in all these better than others.
psychological traditions have made claims about
what makes certain moral judgments better than Contemporary Moral Psychology
others, claims about what “moral maturity” con-
sists of. Some authors have paid extensive atten- Jonathan Haidt has gained widespread atten-
tion to the normative assumptions underlying their tion with his work on the role of intuitive pro-
psychological hypotheses. The most notable ex- cesses in moral judgment formation (Haidt,
96 KALIS

2001; Haidt & Bjorklund, 2008). Briefly sum- ments are morally objectionable, for instance,
marized, Haidt claims that most moral judg- because they are stereotypic. Here, an interest-
ments are caused by instant feelings of approval ing distinction is introduced between automatic
and disapproval. When people think that it is moral judgments (called by Fine “automatic,
morally wrong to have sex with one’s sibling, stereotypic moral judgments”) and higher level
for example, this moral judgment is the result of moral judgments that make us want to suppress
primitive emotional responses such as disgust. our automatic moral judgments (Fine calls these
Rational deliberation hardly plays a causal role “consciously held nonprejudiced beliefs”). Fine
in the generation of moral judgments: Most of does not elaborate on this distinction, but the
the time, it is used merely to provide post hoc idea is clearly that the second are better moral
rationalizations (Haidt, 2001). Haidt’s claims judgments than the first. For example, she refers
have given rise to a lively debate (Fine, 2006; to stereotypic judgments as being inaccurate.
Horgan & Timmons, 2007; Kennett & Fine, Also, she argues that we can improve the qual-
2009; Levy, 2006; Pizarro & Bloom, 2003; ity of our moral judgments by explicit reasoning
Saltzstein & Kasachkoff, 2004). Some have ob- and critical reflection. Just as in Haidt’s article,
jected that Haidt presents an exaggeratedly Fine thus appeals to a notion of “good moral
bleak picture of human moral capacities, that he judgment” without making explicit what she
claims that our presumed moral capacities are means by it. She employs concepts such as the
largely illusory (Fine, 2006). Against such ob- absence of prejudice and egalitarianism, but she
jections, Haidt has argued that his model “does does not elaborate on these notions.
state that moral reasoning is less trustworthy A third author making this kind of implicit
than many people think. . . . But the alternative normative claim is Joshua Greene (2003).
to reason is not chaos, but intuition. Intuitive Greene provides a subtle and philosophically
and automatic processes are much smarter than sophisticated analysis of the normative implica-
many people think” (Haidt & Bjorklund, 2008, tions of empirical work on moral judgment for-
p. 216). To emphasize this point, Haidt has mation. In an introduction, he states, “There is a
presented possible ways to use insights in psy- growing consensus that moral judgments are
chological processes to improve our skills in based largely on intuition. . . . Are all moral
making good moral judgments. He argues that intuitions equally worthy of our allegiance, or
methods such as creating the right moral envi- are some more reliable than others?” (Greene,
ronment and stimulating reasoning processes 2003, p. 847). In raising the normative question
and discussion with others would lead to the about which moral intuitions are “worthy of our
questioning and possible adaptation of one’s allegiance,” Greene appeals to a notion of qual-
intuitions (Haidt, 2001). In his view, moral de- ity: Apparently, moral judgments based on cer-
velopment benefits most from a combination of tain intuitions are better than others. However,
implicit learning and explicit discussion. Thus, Greene does not elaborate on the question of
whereas Haidt emphasizes the importance of what makes some moral judgments better than
intuitions in describing how people actually others.
make moral judgments, he assigns a role to both A final example can be found in Thagard
intuitive and reasoning processes in contribut- (2007), who is concerned with decisions that
ing to improvement. However, he does not de- involve a conflict of interest: cases where peo-
fend any view on the question of what “im- ple make decisions in favor of their own inter-
provement” would consist of. ests while neglecting a responsibility they have
Another example is found in the work of to look after the interests of others. Thagard
Cordelia Fine (2006), who criticizes Haidt’s argues that insights in the neuropsychological
claim that “reason is the slave of the passions,” processes underlying such decisions may “re-
to use the Humean phrase. Against this claim, duce the prevalence of immoral decisions de-
she argues that people certainly have the possi- riving from conflicts of interests” (Thagard,
bility to overrule their intuitive processes by 2007, p. 378). He acknowledges that the claim
cognitive control (see also Kennett & Fine, that such decisions are immoral needs to be
2009). Furthermore, she shows that people can defended in its own right, but as he takes the
successfully suppress their automatic moral claim to be easy to defend, he does not elaborate
judgments when they believe that these judg- on this issue further: “There is . . . no doubt that
IMPROVING MORAL JUDGMENTS 97

acting under the influence of a conflict of inter- be based on reflection, it is actually caused by
est is often morally wrong” (Thagard, 2007, p. other things. For instance, her upbringing might
377). have provided her with a strong gut feeling that
So, whereas several authors refer to moral material wealth should be distributed evenly.
judgments as having a certain quality (as some Of course, any answer to the question of how
being better than others), these authors hardly to improve our moral skills will consist partly of
discuss the question of what such quality con- descriptive claims. After all, suggestions for
sists of. In the remainder of this article, I argue improvement should be based on what we know
that providing an answer to this question in- about the psychological and maybe also neural
volves making not only descriptive claims processes involved in moral judgment forma-
about moral judgments (the traditional domain tion. But thinking about improvement also re-
of moral psychology), but that it also involves quires thinking about the content of those moral
making two other types of claims about moral- judgments, and this leads us into the realm of
ity: normative claims and metaethical claims. normative ethics and metaethics.
The next section introduces these three types of The distinction between normative claims
claims. As I try to show, philosophical ethics and metaethical claims is a common one in
could provide valuable contributions to the field ethics (Couture & Nielsen, 1995; Garner &
of moral psychology by providing theoretical Rosen, 1967). Normative claims are claims
frameworks for both normative and metaethical about which things are morally wrong and mor-
claims. ally right. Examples of normative claims are
“acting under the influence of a conflict of in-
Three Types of Claims About Morality terest is morally wrong” or “it is morally wrong
for companies to award lavish bonuses to their
The core of the debate on moral psychology CEOs.” Normative ethics is the subdiscipline
consists of descriptive claims: claims about how within ethics that provides justificatory frame-
we come to make moral judgments (Casebeer, works for normative claims: examples of such
2003; Greene, 2003; Greene & Haidt, 2002; frameworks are Kantian deontology and utili-
Haidt, 2001; Koenigs et al., 2007; Moll & de tarianism. Normative claims thus form the con-
Oliveira-Souza, 2007; Prinz, 2006). This dis- tent of everyday moral judgments. On the other
cussion employs a very specific definition of hand, metaethical claims are claims about the
moral judgments. Moral judgments are defined scope of the moral domain and the nature of
as claims or statements with moral content moral judgments in general. Metaethics is un-
made by human beings in everyday situations. derstood as a subdiscipline of ethics specifically
Prinz (2006), for example, states that his aim is concerned with clarifying the meaning and
to give an analysis of our ordinary moral con- metaphysical status of moral judgments; it pro-
cepts: “It’s a question about what goes on in our vides “metareflection” on the concepts and
heads when we use moral terms like ‘good’ and claims made in normative ethics (Garner &
‘bad’ or ‘right’ and wrong’” (Prinz, 2006, p. Rosen, 1967; Sinnott-Armstrong & Timmons,
40). These authors are thus concerned with the 1996). Important questions in metaethics are,
question, If someone says, “It is wrong to do What do terms like right, wrong, and good
A,” how has this statement come about? Let us mean? What makes a judgment a moral judg-
imagine that someone named Laura makes the ment? Do moral judgments refer to universal
moral claim, “It is morally wrong for companies truths, to social conventions, or to something
to award lavish bonuses to their CEOs.” The else? Examples of metaethical claims are
descriptive question is, How did Laura’s judg- “moral judgments are judgments about social
ment come about? Is it the result of reflection or norms” and “moral judgments are either true or
of automatic, emotional processes? This is a false.” Whereas the domain of metaethics cov-
question on a descriptive level. It is a question ers various issues, what all metaethical theories
that can be answered by psychological theories have in common is that they reflect on the status
and data, and this is precisely what the data of or nature of moral judgments in general.
Haidt and other moral psychologists are about. The roles of psychology, metaethics, and nor-
Haidt’s answer, for instance, would be that al- mative ethics in research on moral judgments
though Laura’s moral statement might seem to are clarified in Figure 1. Moral judgments can
98 KALIS

Metaethics
concerned with the scope of morality and
the status and nature of moral judgments

Normative ethics
Moral judgments
concerned with justificatory
principles for moral judgments

Psychology
concerned with the psychological and
neural processes involved in moral
judgment formation

Figure 1. The roles of psychology, metaethics, and normative ethics in research on moral
judgments.

be justified by means of normative theories. statements such as “I think that killing is mor-
Whereas psychological theories investigate the ally wrong,” according to Prinz, they do not
underlying processes involved in the formation really hold that killing is morally wrong: They
of such judgments, meaethical theories provide do not make genuine moral judgments (for other
a “metareflection” on the status and nature of recent work on moral impairment associated
moral judgments in general. with psychopathy, see Blair, 2007; Glenn,
As shown in the previous section, recent Raine, & Schug, 2009). To answer the question
studies in moral psychology frequently make a of whether psychopaths make real moral judg-
combination of descriptive, normative, and me- ments, one needs to have factual knowledge
taethical claims about morality. However, only about psychopaths’ moral capacities, but one
rarely are the normative and metaethical claims also needs to know what it means to make a real
justified or embedded within a theoretical moral judgment. This is no longer a descriptive
framework. The next section discusses ways in question but a metaethical one. Different me-
which recent work in moral psychology could taethical theories present different views on
benefit from philosophical insights on these what characterizes “real” moral judgments. This
topics. implies, for example, that different metaethical
positions defend different positions on the ques-
The Role of Metaethics in Moral tion of whether psychopaths make “real” moral
Psychology judgments (Kennett & Fine, 2008; for a differ-
ent view, see Roskies, 2003).
As said, moral psychology is concerned with The question of what makes moral statements
actual moral statements that human beings “real” moral judgments has received growing
make in their everyday lives. However, things attention in the field of moral psychology
get confused when authors start to argue that (Jones, 2006; Joyce, 2006). This can, for exam-
sometimes people are not making real moral ple, be observed in Haidt and Bjorklund (2008).
judgments. Several authors claim this about In that article, the authors discuss an empirical
psychopaths; an example can be found in Prinz study on hypnotically induced disgust. In that
(2006). Although psychopaths can make moral study, they used hypnosis techniques that made
IMPROVING MORAL JUDGMENTS 99

participants experience a pang of disgust every companies because she takes these decisions to
time they heard the word often. As a result, be unfair or because she takes these decisions to
some of those participants rated a completely be harmful for certain people. It is not necessary
benevolent action (the story describes a student that people are consciously aware of such rea-
making efforts to stimulate constructive debate sons for their emotional reactions, but somehow
between professors and students) as morally such reasons must play a role. In Jones’s terms,
objectionable, if and only if the description of real moral judgments are reasons-responsive.
the action contained the term often. Haidt and She explains this by commenting on the hypno-
Bjorklund (2008) conclude from these data that sis induction experiments. Let’s say that after
moral judgments are caused by gut feelings. the experiment, the participants were debriefed:
However, what they actually say is that moral They were told that their moral reactions were
statements are caused by gut feelings, and that manipulated by hypnotic suggestion. Jones asks
these moral statements can be considered gen- us to imagine a participant, call him Harry, who
uine moral judgments. However, they do not would not change his moral statements after
give arguments for the second claim. Many being debriefed. Even though he now knows
authors in the field of moral psychology not that these statements were manipulated by hyp-
only defend a certain explanation of the origins nosis, Harry would keep saying that it is mor-
of our moral statements, but they also take ally wrong to stimulate constructive debate
position with regard to the question of which between professors and students. Would we
statements reflect genuine moral judgments. consider Harry’s statement to be a real moral
That is, they explicitly defend a certain view on judgment? Jones argues that sentimentalists like
what a real moral judgment is: a metaethical Prinz would need to maintain this. After all,
view. The metaethical position that many moral Harry’s statement is an expression of a tendency
psychologists seem to embrace is sentimental- to respond with certain emotions. But this is
ism (Joyce, 2006; Nichols, 2008; Prinz, 2006). strongly counterintuitive, according to Jones.
According to sentimentalism, to judge that She argues that we do not consider Harry’s
something is morally wrong means to have a statement to be a real moral judgment because it
sentiment, or an emotional disposition, of dis- is not reasons-responsive. Because of the de-
approbation toward it (Nichols, 2008; Prinz, briefing, Harry now knows that he does not have
2006). Prinz (2006) for instance defines a moral reasons for responding to the case with the
judgment as a tendency to respond to a state of moral emotions he feels. If Harry’s statement
affairs with certain emotions. To say that I hold was a real moral judgment, he would have re-
the moral judgment that it is wrong to kill just tracted his statement after finding out that he did
means that I am predisposed to respond with not have any reasons for making it. In other
emotions like anger to instances of killing. words, Jones claims that our moral statements
So, if we apply this to Laura’s statement that are only real moral judgments insofar as we
“it is morally wrong for companies to award believe them to be justified.
lavish bonuses to their CEOs,” we would say This implies that different metaethical ap-
that she is making a real moral judgment if she proaches lead to different interpretations of psy-
has a disposition to respond to certain decisions chological data. So, how could metaethical the-
made by companies regarding bonuses with ories contribute to psychological research on
emotions like anger and indignation. In a com- moral judgments? As said, one of the questions
ment on Prinz, the philosopher Jones (2006) has that metaethics is concerned with is the question
objected that such a sentimentalist position is of the delineation of the moral domain: What
problematic, and has developed an alternative makes a certain judgment a moral judgment?
metaethical view. Jones argues, by means of a Philosophical work on this point (such as Gert,
metaethical analysis, that for Laura’s statement to 2005; Harman, 1977; Joyce, 2001) could help in
be a real moral judgment, Laura must believe her clarifying whether one sees moral judgments as
moral statement to be justified. She must have being in any sense different from emotional
reasons for her emotional response of anger and judgments or social judgments. For instance,
indignation. For example, if Laura’s statement is several researchers working in the tradition of
a real moral judgment, she will be inclined to evolutionary biology and psychology (De Waal,
respond with indignation to certain decisions of 2009; Moll et al., 2006) tend to identify moral
100 KALIS

judgments with judgments that express a proso- the scope of moral justification. Crudely said, if
cial attitude. Although this is not necessarily one finds that citizens of the southern states of
problematic, it is clearly only one of the possi- the United States have certain moral views that
ble interpretations of the essence of morality. oppose views held in the northern states (Nis-
Also, as shown, metaethical theories could bett & Cohen, 1996), the practical implications
prove fruitful in debates about the status of of such results highly depend on whether one
judgments made by people suffering from psy- thinks that only one of those opposing views
chopathy or autism. can be right. Some argue that this is an incorrect
As a second type of contribution, metaethical way to phrase the problem (Doris & Plakias,
theories offer a spectrum of definitions of good- 2008): They argue that if normative disagree-
ness, which researchers could use in clarifying ment turns out to be intractable, this empirical
and specifying their notions of quality and im- fact might itself threaten the idea that moral
provement. I outline some general steps such a judgments are either wrong or right. However, it
process of clarification could take. First, one only does insofar as one holds that if moral
should ask oneself, When referring to the qual- judgments are either wrong or right, it must be
ity of moral judgments, am I referring to their possible for most human beings to find out
moral quality or to other ways in which a judg- which ones are wrong and which ones are right.
ment can be good? After all, moral judgments And this, again, is not an empirical claim but a
can be good or bad in nonmoral ways as well: claim about the nature of morality.
They can promote certain nonmoral values. To Such reflections on the meaning and nature of
give an example, a moral judgment can be good morality and moral judgments can thus help in
in that it is accepted as valid within a certain determining one’s theoretical starting points
political, social, or cultural community. Also, it and in clarifying what practical conclusions one
can be good in the sense that it follows the laws could draw on the basis of one’s empirical re-
of logical inference. This is not the same as sults. The different steps in such a reflective
saying that the judgment is good in that it is process are summarized in Figure 2.
morally justified. However, the delineation be- As explained above, metaethical theorizing
tween moral and nonmoral criteria of quality is should be seen as conceptual clarification of the
not always easy to make. Insofar as one holds meaning and status of concepts such as morality
that criteria for moral justification can be de- and the good. Such general reflections form the
rived from principles of logic (as some norma- background for specific normative claims,
tive theories do; see Illies, 2003), making a bad which are attempts to answer the questions of
moral judgment is essentially the same as mak- which judgments or actions are morally justi-
ing an illogical judgment. This brings us to the fied, and what makes them morally justified.
second step: If one is concerned with the moral Such normative claims thus give more concrete
justification of judgments, what does one take content to notions of the moral good and moral
moral justification to mean? justification, and show how these notions could
One important difference here is between be applied to concrete actions and judgments. In
people who believe that moral justification is a the next section, I outline how contemporary
concept that is necessarily universal in scope, work in moral psychology involves making nor-
and those who hold that it is not. The question mative assumptions, and how normative theo-
is, Is it possible that, for example, the practice ries could contribute to the clarification of such
of awarding large corporate bonuses is morally assumptions.
justified in one society but not in another? And
thus, is it possible that a judgment condemning The Role of Normative Theories in Moral
such a practice is morally better in one society Psychology
than in another? The scope of moral justification
is a large issue in metaethical debate, and the As said, normative ethics is the discipline that
position one takes on this issue is highly rele- is concerned with the question of what makes
vant for work in moral psychology. After all, behavior morally right or morally wrong. For
how one interprets psychological data on cul- instance, one could ask why it would be morally
tural and social variations in moral judgments wrong if companies award lavish bonuses to
depends on (among other things) one’s view on their CEOs. Different normative theories pro-
IMPROVING MORAL JUDGMENTS 101

good

= justified by = justified by non-


moral criteria moral criteria

social criteria
universal moral non-universal
criteria moral criteria
political criteria

economic
criteria

(...)

Figure 2. Overview of basic reflective steps for answering the question, What makes a
moral judgment a good judgment?

vide different answers to this question. The dif- by calculating its expected utility compared
ferent normative theories are all concrete mod- with other possible decisions. Moreover, what
els for moral justification; they thus belong in is characteristic about utilitarianism is that it
the left half of Figure 2. Models of nonmoral derives its moral principle from a value that is in
justification are not part of the domain of moral itself not moral, namely the “neutral” value of
philosophy, but are instead found in fields such utility.
as political philosophy, sociology, and econom- This latter point is what distinguishes utili-
ics. The major normative theories found in con- tarian theories from deontological ones. There
temporary moral philosophy are utilitarianism, are different kinds of deontological theories, but
deontology, and virtue ethics. I briefly introduce what they share is that they claim that their
each approach and show how each theory justificatory principles are based on values that
should be placed within the structure outlined in are themselves moral values. For example,
Figure 2. Rawls’s (1971) version of Kantian deontology
Utilitarian theories state that those acts are was based on the value of justice, which he
morally right (even morally prescribed) that argued to be a universal moral value. Most
maximize utility (Brandt, 1979; Singer, 1993). deontological theories offer justificatory princi-
In such an account, certain decisions made by ples that are universal in scope, but this is not
companies regarding bonuses might be morally necessarily so. After all, it is possible to defend
objectionable because these decisions would re- that moral judgments can be justified by refer-
sult in less overall utility than some other pos- ring to moral values that are not universal val-
sible decisions. Most important, this requires an ues; such a view would still count as a deonto-
account of what utility consists of: Is it pleasure, logical theory.
happiness, welfare, or something else? Differ- A completely different way of developing
ent versions of utilitarianism constitute differ- justificatory norms for moral judgments is to
ent answers to this question. With regard to the ask, What moral judgments would a good or
distinctions made in Figure 2, it is important to virtuous person embrace? Such an approach
note that utilitarianism as a theory is universal shifts the focus from assessing specific moral
in its scope: It states that every moral decision claims to a moral assessment of persons as a
made by every possible entity might be assessed whole. This is the starting point of virtue ethics,
102 KALIS

which has its background in Aristotelian philos- Bjorklund’s (2008) claim about this moral judg-
ophy (Anscombe, 1958; Slote, 2001). Virtue ment is that “every human being instantly rec-
ethicists have developed elaborate accounts of ognizes it as being true” (p. 214). How would
human flourishing, a term they use to refer to this normative view be a basis for a theory of
optimal development of human beings. This good moral judgment? What seems to follow
also covers optimal moral development: The from Haidt and Bjorklund’s normative position
idea that well-being, flourishing, and moral is this: A good moral judgment is a moral judg-
quality all come together is characteristic of ment that is held on the basis of one or more of
virtue ethics. Different views exist regarding the these moral truths (that is, held for reasons of
question of what kind of physical, psychologi- sensitivity to harm, reciprocity, hierarchy, pu-
cal, and social capacities are required for a rity, or in-group– out-group boundaries). But in
human being to flourish and thus to become a fact, this is not what Haidt and Bjorklund claim.
good person. Some virtue theories are universal They acknowledge that there is a lot of dis-
in scope: Such theories claim that there are agreement about the moral values of hierarchy,
certain characteristics and capacities that uni- purity, and in-group– out-group boundaries:
versally contribute to human flourishing. Other “American liberals in particular seem quite un-
virtue approaches are narrower in scope and comfortable with the outputs of those modules,
state that what contributes to flourishing might because they often lead to jingoistic patriotism
depend on the cultural and social context of the (ingroup), legitimization of inequality (hierar-
person. chy) and rules or practices that treat certain
Do the authors I have been discussing in the ethnic groups as contagious (purity, as in the
first half of this article embrace a specific nor- segregation laws of the American South)” (p.
mative theory? Haidt and Bjorklund (2008) 209). Whereas purity, hierarchy, and in-group–
elaborate somewhat on the normative back- out-group boundaries constitute moral truths, it
ground of Haidt’s moral psychology. They ar- is not the case that every moral judgment that
gue that there exist “anthropocentric moral reflects these truths is itself a moral truth. If it is
truths”: moral claims that are true with respect not merely its foundation in one of the core
to all human beings. These moral truths are moral values, what makes a moral judgment
moral values that are widely shared all over the justified? At some point, Haidt and Bjorklund
world. They are partly innate and partly shaped seem to claim that for a moral judgment to be a
by one’s culture and social environment during justified judgment, it must be widely shared.
development. This shows that they start from They state that “A well-formed moral system is
the assumption that moral justification is uni- one that is endorsed by the great majority of its
versal in scope. The five core moral values as members, even those who appear, from the out-
they formulate them are side, to be its victims” (p. 216). By being a little
charitable, we can interpret the notion of a moral
1. Sensitivity to harm: Sensitivity to signs of system as a set of moral judgments. By combin-
pain and suffering in others; ing this claim with their claim about the five
core moral values, we could formulate the view
2. Reciprocity: Emotional responses related that justified moral judgments are those that
to playing tit-for-tat; have their foundation in one or more of the core
moral values and are endorsed by the great
3. Hierarchy: Concerns about navigating sta-
majority of its members, even those who appear
tus hierarchies;
to be its victims. However, we still cannot con-
4. Purity: Concerns about cleanness, related sider this to be a satisfactory notion of “good
to the emotion of disgust; and moral judgment.” Haidt and Bjorklund have not
dealt with the obvious objection against such a
5. Boundaries between in-group and out- view: If the majority of the Jews had embraced
group: Emotions related to loyalty and the moral judgment that it was morally right to
special concerns for one’s own group. annihilate them for reasons of purity and in-
group– out-group boundaries, would that have
To give one example, “Motherhood requires made the judgment justified? Haidt and Bjork-
loving and caring for one’s children.” Haidt and lund do have a (possibly justified) optimistic
IMPROVING MORAL JUDGMENTS 103

view of the shared moral intuitions that the criterion is that a justified moral judgment oc-
evolutionary process has predisposed us to: curs under conditions of reflection. Unfortu-
Most of those moral intuitions are aimed at nately, he does not really elaborate on the role
social cooperation and survival of the species. of reflection. And third, he claims that a justified
However, the mere fact that most of our widely moral judgment is free from emotional influ-
shared moral intuitions contribute to social co- ences that the person deems unrelated to the
operation and survival does not make them jus- matter at hand. This is an interesting normative
tified moral judgments. Stereotypic judgments, claim; however, it immediately raises the ques-
for example, might also contribute to social tion, How do we distinguish relevant emotional
cooperation and survival, but we nevertheless dispositions from unrelated emotional influ-
do not consider such judgments to be justified. ences? An answer requires a theory that identi-
Haidt and Bjorklund (2008) thus have some fies certain elements as relevant to the matter at
kind of normative theory: They have identified hand: a theory that identifies good reasons for
five core moral values, and thus have given an having an emotional disposition. This is what
account of the things that we consider morally normative theories do. For example, one could
right and morally wrong. However, they cannot back up Prinz’s view of moral judgment with a
show how one can derive justified moral judg- utilitarian normative theory. The normative
ments from this theory. As a result, they do not starting point would be that those actions are
have a satisfactory answer to the question of morally right that maximize utility. A corre-
what constitutes a good moral judgment. sponding view of justification would be that a
Prinz (2006) takes a different approach to this moral judgment is justified if it uses knowledge
issue: His goal is to analyze our common use of relevant for maximizing utility and if it is free of
moral terms such as right and wrong. At the end emotions that have nothing to do with maximiz-
of his article, he briefly discusses normative ing utility. Prinz formulates some criteria for
theories: He states that normative theories “can- normative justification, but because he does not
not be defended as plausible analyses of ordi- make his normative starting points explicit,
nary moral concepts. . . . They are best under- these criteria remain empty boxes.
stood as proposals for replacing ordinary moral So, how could normative theories contrib-
concepts, not as analyses of them” (p. 40). This ute to the development and interpretation of
seems to me a correct but rather mundane ob- research in moral psychology? A first possi-
servation; every normative theorist will agree bility is to start with a descriptive question
that normative theory is normative, and not de- on, for example, moral reasoning, develop-
scriptive, in nature. In any case, Prinz’s state- ment, or judgment formation, and examine
ment makes clear that he is not interested in this the normative concepts used while developing
normative enterprise, but in the analysis of our this question into an empirical paradigm. For
ordinary moral concepts. Prinz himself does not example, one could ask the descriptive ques-
seem to start from a specific normative theory. tion of whether and when everyday moral
Nevertheless, he makes certain general claims reasoning involves making utility calcula-
about the justification of moral claims. For ex- tions: calculations of the expected rewards
ample, he argues that my moral judgments are and costs of one’s options. Whereas this is a
justified insofar as I hold them “under condi- purely descriptive question, psychological
tions of full factual knowledge and reflection, theories of decision making employ certain
and freedom from emotional biases that I my- standards of adequacy (derived from econom-
self would deem as unrelated to the matter at ics) that might not be identical to moral
hand” (Prinz, p. 35). Let’s analyze these criteria standards of adequacy (Tobler, Kalis, &
in more detail. To begin with the first, they must Kalenscher, 2008). It, therefore, would be
occur under conditions of full factual knowl- worthwhile to combine such an empirical
edge. Prinz elaborates on this by explaining project with a normative analysis, examining
how moral judgments can be in error because when it is morally desirable to decide on the
they result from a lack of knowledge. Let’s say basis of utility calculations and when it is not.
that it turns out that Laura is completely wrong In such a way, a descriptive study might not
about current bonus policies. That would make only lead to factual knowledge on strategies
her moral judgment unjustified. Prinz’s second of moral decision making, but can also con-
104 KALIS

tribute to a normative assessment of such the conclusion that everyone doing research
strategies. Another way to develop studies in in moral psychology should commit oneself
moral psychology is to begin with a certain to one of the existing normative theories,
normative position and to examine empirical which would lead to different “philosophical
hypotheses that can be generated on the basis schools” in moral psychology. One could ar-
of this position. A possible area where such gue that Kohlberg himself developed one
research would be fruitful is the field of virtue such school, by explicitly grounding his re-
ethics. As already mentioned, one of the search in a Kantian tradition. However, this
claims made by virtue theories is that moral precisely constituted one of the major objec-
assessment should take place on the level of tions that were brought up against his work.
the person, and that to become a virtuous His explicit moral foundations led others to
person, one should develop certain capacities. conclude that his empirical work seemed
One of the capacities frequently mentioned is valid only for those who believe that Kant
practical wisdom (or the Greek term phrone- was right about morality, and narrowing
sis). The idea is that to make good moral down of the validity of one’s research is
decisions, one needs to be sensitive to con- surely not appealing to psychologists. An-
text: One needs to see what are “evaluatively other problem is that the plurality of moral
relevant” features of particular situations. approaches available and the lack of consen-
Also, being a good person requires flexibility: sus might give the impression that one theory
One needs to be able to adapt to changes in is ultimately as good as another, that one
the situation. These philosophical theories on could just choose the moral theory that best
practical wisdom could form a theoretical ba- fits one’s data. So, how to deal with this plu-
sis for an interesting line of interdisciplinary rality of normative approaches? In my view, the
research. Moral psychology could try to de- main point is that making choices in the norma-
velop more concrete and specific notions of
tive domain is something that cannot be avoided
practical wisdom, contributing to the identi-
in doing moral psychology. In addressing major
fication of the kinds of capacities and psycho-
questions on moral development and moral im-
logical mechanisms involved in making vir-
provement, one must use some philosophical
tuous moral decisions. Existing psychological
work on the notion of wisdom could be useful anchor points, some way to think about good-
in this respect (Schwartz & Sharpe, 2006; ness and justification. The choice might not be
Sternberg & Jordan, 2005). Again, such work between being normatively neutral or being
would only make sense if combined with an committed to normative starting points, but
assessment of the normative validity of a vir- between being implicit or explicit in one’s
tue– ethical approach. normative commitments. The intertwinement
The possibilities presented above raise an between descriptive and normative issues is
important issue, which also played a role in something that is found not only in the field of
the discussion of Kohlberg’s work on moral moral psychology; it is actually widespread in
psychology. It is clear that there are different psychology in general. Areas such as positive
competing approaches to moral philosophy: psychology and health psychology rely on
Some philosophers defend a deontological normative assumptions as well. This seems
theory of morality, there are those who call inevitable because to investigate topics such
themselves utilitarians, some take a virtue– as happiness or health, one needs to take a
theoretical approach (and, of course, there are stance on what health or happiness is, and this
also moral philosophers defending an ap- immediately leads one into the normative
proach that does not belong to either of these realm. Although this is not necessarily unde-
three major schools). But how should the field sirable, it requires an explication and justifi-
of moral psychology deal with this existing cation of the assumptions made. Still, such a
plurality in moral theories? Philosophers are message might evoke substantial resistance in
keen to emphasize that normative theories are psychologists: Empirical psychologists are
mutually exclusive: Those that defend utili- generally not interested in spreading moral
tarianism cannot hold that deontological the- opinions; they are interested in generating
ories are correct as well. This might lead to factual knowledge about psychological pro-
IMPROVING MORAL JUDGMENTS 105

cesses. In the next section, I develop possible They are not trained to address normative issues
strategies to deal with these tensions. in a systematic way. This is what moral philos-
ophers are trained to do—they, on the other
Addressing Normative Issues in Moral hand, know very little about doing experiments.
Psychology: Some Suggestions The question of whether or not this is a desir-
able state of affairs is beyond the scope of this
The main point of the analysis so far has been article; what is at stake here is the question of
that many questions in moral psychology have how moral psychology should move forward
normative aspects, and this means that research- given this state of affairs. One relatively
ers cannot avoid making normative choices in straightforward answer is that to address both
the way they set up and interpret their empirical factual and normative aspects of moral psychol-
studies. I have argued that the best way for ogy, research in this field should be developed
researchers in moral psychology to deal with by multidisciplinary research teams. This means
this intertwinement is to be much more explicit that psychologists and moral philosophers
about the normative starting points and inter- should develop, execute, and report on research
pretations they use. My proposal is that the projects together. Within these teams, it would
main thing researchers need to do is make clear be the psychologists’ role to focus on the factual
which part of their work is about facts and aspects, to contribute relevant descriptive ques-
which part involves the making of certain state- tions and sound empirical methods for answer-
ments about values. This does not necessarily ing them. It would be the philosophers’ respon-
lead to the problems associated with a Kohlber- sibility to generate relevant normative questions
gian approach to moral psychology. Most of the and to assess the explicit and implicit normative
objections against Kohlberg’s work were either claims made in the research process, both in the
empirical objections or objections to the kind of generation of questions and in the discussion of
normative assumptions he defended: He used a the empirical results. Whereas such a structure
theory that was much more narrow and restric- involves a clear division of labor on the basis of
tive than most contemporary normative theo- training and experience, the work of each dis-
ries. However, I expect that most researchers cipline can be done only in close collaboration
working in moral psychology would still go with the other discipline. Currently, this is not
along with his general starting point that the standard practice: Although there is a growing
normative and descriptive dimensions of moral body of work relating results in moral psychol-
psychological work should be clearly separated. ogy to philosophical work in normative ethics
In other words, it is possible to adopt this aspect and metaethics (Sinnott-Armstrong, 2008), psy-
of Kohlberg’s approach to moral psychology chologists and philosophers most of the time
without having to accept any of his normative or still work independently of each other. The
empirical conclusions. main disadvantage of trying to disentangle de-
An important point here is that such separa- scriptive and normative aspects of moral psy-
tion makes the factual aspect of moral psycho- chology only afterward is twofold. First, inter-
logical work stronger as well. By clearly show- esting philosophical choices are often already
ing which part of the study is concerned with made in the process of formulating empirical
empirical description and which part is con- hypotheses. For example, Haidt’s hypothesis
cerned with normative interpretation, one pre- was that moral reasoning is in most cases
cisely avoids the objection that one’s data are merely post hoc rationalization. He presents this
valid only within a certain normative frame- hypothesis as a “debunking” of our common-
work. In contrast, by failing to disentangle one’s sense way of thinking about reasons. However,
empirical data from normative interpretations, there exist different views on what our com-
one makes one’s descriptive conclusions much mon-sense way of thinking about reasons is.
more vulnerable to objections (Fine, 2006; One widespread account is in fact that reasons
Roeser, 2010). function not as causal but as rationalizing ex-
But how should this be done in practice? planations (Wedgwood, 2007). From such a
Those working in experimental psychology are philosophical starting point, Haidt’s hypothesis
trained to develop and analyze scientific exper- would not be debunking but actually confirming
iments that lead to reliable and valid results. our common sense of what moral reasoning
106 KALIS

does. Because the formulation of empirical hy- Bandura, A., & MacDonald, F. (1963). The influence
potheses is frequently colored by certain theo- of social reinforcement and the behavior of models
retical assumptions about the concepts used, it in shaping children’s moral judgment. Journal of
appears more fruitful to engage in interdiscipli- Abnormal and Social Psychology, 69, 1–9.
nary discussion from the beginning of the re- Blair, R. J. R. (2007). The amygdala and ventrome-
dial prefrontal cortex in morality and psychopathy.
search process. The second disadvantage of post
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11, 387–392.
hoc interdisciplinary integration follows from Brandt, R. (1979). A theory of the good and the right.
the fact that the opposite is true as well: The New York: Oxford University Press.
formulation of normative and metaethical theo- Casebeer, W. D. (2003). Moral cognition and its
ries frequently depends on the making of certain constituents. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 4,
psychological assumptions about mental pro- 841– 846.
cesses and capacities. An example was already Couture, J., & Nielsen, K. (Eds.). (1995). On the
provided for virtue theories and their use of the relevance of metaethics: New essays in metaethics.
notion of practical wisdom. In developing their Calgary: University of Calgary Press.
accounts of morality and the good, philosophers De Waal, F. (2009). The age of empathy: Nature’s
could thus benefit greatly from interacting with lessons for a kinder society. New York: Harmony
psychologists at an early stage in the research Books.
process. Doris, J., & Plakias, A. (2008). How to argue about
The observation that the relevance of inter- disagreement: Evaluative diversity and moral real-
ism. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psy-
disciplinary cooperation goes both ways raises
chology, Vol. 2: The cognitive science of morality
the question, What is the right order in which (pp. 303–332). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
research in moral psychology should proceed? Durkheim, E. (1961). Moral education: A study in the
Does one need to start by formulating a clear theory and application of the sociology of educa-
normative position and developing empirical tion. New York: Free Press.
paradigms on the basis of this position, or Emden, R., Johnson, W. F., & Easterbrooks, M. A.
should one first get the facts straight and then (1990). The do’s and don’ts of early moral devel-
develop a normative position that is in accor- opment: Psychoanalytic tradition and current re-
dance with these facts? Neither option appears search. In J. Kagan & S. Lamb (Eds.), The emer-
attractive. Instead, one could see the process of gence of morality in young children (pp. 245–276).
doing research in moral psychology as a reiter- Chicago: Chicago University Press.
ative process, during which the normative and Fine, C. (2006). Is the emotional dog wagging its
descriptive claims brought forward remain open rational tail, or chasing it? Philosophical Explora-
tions, 9, 83–98.
to reassessment. This means that insofar as
Freud, S. (1961). Civilization and its discontents. In
one’s normative claims depend on psychologi- J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.), The standard edition of
cal or social facts, new knowledge on these the complete psychological works of Sigmund
facts might change such claims. Also, insofar as Freud. New York: Norton. (Original work pub-
one’s descriptive claims depend on a certain lished 1930)
normative or metaethical view, new arguments Garner, R. T., & Rosen, B. (1967). Moral philoso-
concerning that view would affect one’s de- phy: A systematic introduction to normative ethics
scriptive claims as well. By engaging in such and meta-ethics. New York: Macmillan.
critical evaluations within research teams in- Gert, B. (2005). Morality: Its nature and justification
stead of between research teams, one greatly (Rev. ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.
increases the chance that the process will result Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice. Cambridge,
in research that is both normatively and empir- MA: Harvard University Press.
ically better justified. Such a practice of “inten- Glenn, A. L., Raine, A., & Schug, R. A. (2009). The
neural correlates of moral decision-making in psy-
sive interdisciplinarity” seems preferable over
chopathy. Molecular Psychiatry, 14, 5– 6.
what now and then looks more like a practice of Greene, J. D. (2003). From neural “is” to moral
“mutual debunking.” “ought”: What are the moral implications of neu-
roscientific moral psychology? Nature Reviews
References Neuroscience, 4, 847– 850.
Greene, J. D., & Haidt, J. (2002). How (and where)
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1958). Modern moral philoso- does moral judgment work? Trends in Cognitive
phy. Philosophy, 33, 1–19. Sciences, 6, 517–523.
IMPROVING MORAL JUDGMENTS 107

Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational Moll, J., & de Oliveira-Souza, R. (2007). Moral
tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judg- judgments, emotions and the utilitarian brain.
ment. Psychological Review, 108, 814 – 834. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11, 319 –321.
Haidt, J., & Bjorklund, F. (2008). Social intuitionists Moll, J., Krueger, F., Zahn, R., Pardini, M., de Oliveira-
answer six questions about moral psychology. In Souza, R., & Grafman, J. (2006). Human fronto-
W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology, mesolimbic networks guide decisions about charita-
Vol. 2: The cognitive science of morality (pp. 181– ble donation. Proceedings of the National Academy
218). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. of Sciences, USA, 103, 15623–15628.
Harman, G. (1977). The nature of morality. New Nichols, S. (2008). Sentimentalism naturalized. In
York: Oxford University Press. W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology,
Horgan, T., & Timmons, M. (2007). Morphological Vol. 2: The cognitive science of morality (pp. 255–
rationalism and the psychology of moral judgment. 274). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 10, 279 –295. Nisbett, R. E., & Cohen, D. (1996). Culture of honor:
Illies, C. (2003). The grounds of ethical judgment. The psychology of violence in the South. Boulder,
New transcendental arguments in moral philoso- CO: Westview Press.
phy. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. Piaget, J. (1965). The moral judgment of the child
Jones, K. (2006). Metaethics and emotion research: A (M. Gabain, Trans.). New York: Free Press. (Orig-
response to Prinz. Philosophical Explorations, 9, inal work published 1932)
45–53. Pizarro, D. A., & Bloom, P. (2003). The intelligence
Joyce, R. (2001). The myth of morality. Cambridge, of moral intuitions: Comment on Haidt (2001).
England: Cambridge University Press. Psychological Review, 110, 193–196.
Joyce, R. (2006). Metaethics and the empirical sci- Prinz, J. (2006). The emotional basis of moral judg-
ences. Philosophical Explorations, 9, 133–148. ments. Philosophical Explorations, 9, 29 – 43.
Kennett, J., & Fine, C. (2008). Internalism and the Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge,
evidence from psychopaths and “acquired psycho- MA: Harvard University Press.
paths.” In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psy-
Rest, J., Narvaez, D., Bebeau, M. J., & Thoma, S. J.
chology, Vol. 3: The neuroscience of morality (pp.
(1999). Postconventional moral thinking: A neo-
173–190). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kohlbergian approach. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Kennett, J., & Fine, C. (2009). Will the real moral
Roeser, S. (2010). Intuitions, emotions and gut feel-
judgment please stand up? The implications of
ings in decisions about risks: Towards a different
social intuitionist models of cognition for meta-
interpretation of “neuroethics.” Journal of Risk
ethics and moral psychology. Ethical Theory and
Moral Practice, 12, 77–96. Research, 13, 175–190.
Koenigs, M., Young, L., Adolphs, R., Tranel, D., Roskies, A. (2003). Are ethical judgments intrinsi-
Cushman, F., Hauser, M., & Damasio, A. (2007, cally motivational? Lessons from “acquired psy-
April 19). Damage to the prefrontal cortex in- chopathy.” Philosophical Psychology, 16, 51– 66.
creases utilitarian moral judgements. Nature, 446, Saltzstein, H. D., & Kasachkoff, T. (2004). Haidt’s
908 –911. moral intuitionist theory: A psychological and
Kohlberg, L. (1958). The development of modes of philosophical critique. Review of General Psychol-
moral thinking and choice in the years 10–16. ogy, 8, 273–282.
Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Schwartz, B., & Sharpe, K. E. (2006). Practical wis-
Chicago. dom: Aristotle meets positive psychology. Journal
Kohlberg, L. (1971). From is to ought: How to com- of Happiness Studies, 7, 377–395.
mit the naturalistic fallacy and get away with it in Singer, P. (1993). Practical ethics (2nd ed.). Cam-
the study of moral development. In T. Mischel bridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
(Ed.), Cognitive development and epistemology Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (Ed.). (2008). Moral psychol-
(pp. 151–236). New York: Academic Press. ogy (three volumes). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kohlberg, L. (1981). Justice as reversibility: The Sinnott-Armstrong, W., & Timmons, M. (Eds.).
claim to moral adequacy of a highest stage of (1996). Moral knowledge? New readings in moral
moral judgment. In Essays on moral development, epistemology. Oxford, England: Oxford University
Vol. 1: The philosophy of moral development. Press.
Moral stages and the idea of justice (pp. 190 – Slote, M. (2001). Morals from motives. Oxford,
226). San Francisco: Harper & Row. England: Oxford University Press.
Levy, N. (2006). The wisdom of the pack. Philosoph- Sternberg, R. J., & Jordan, J. (Eds.). (2005). Hand-
ical Explorations, 9, 99 –103. book of wisdom: Psychological perspectives. Cam-
Meissner, W. W. (2003). The ethical dimension of bridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
psychoanalysis: A dialogue. New York: SUNY Thagard, P. (2007). The moral psychology of con-
Press. flicts of interests: Insights from affective neuro-
108 KALIS

science. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 24, 367– Wallace, R. J. (2005). Moral psychology. In H. Jack-
380. son & M. Smith (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of
Tobler, P. N., Kalis, A., & Kalenscher, T. (2008). contemporary philosophy (pp. 86 –113). Oxford,
The role of moral utility in decisionmaking: An England: Oxford University Press.
interdisciplinary framework. Cognitive, Affective, Wedgwood, R. (2007). Normativism defended. In
& Behavioral Neuroscience, 8, 390 – 401. B. P. McLaughlin & J. Cohen (Eds.), Contempo-
Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social knowl- rary debates in philosophy of mind (pp. 85–101).
edge: Morality and convention. Cambridge, En- Oxford, England: Blackwell.
gland: Cambridge University Press.
Turiel, E. (2008). The development of children’s
orientations toward moral, social, and personal or- Received March 20, 2009
ders: More than a sequence in development. Hu- Revision received May 4, 2010
man Development, 51, 21–39. Accepted May 4, 2010 䡲

You might also like