You are on page 1of 9

N U R SI N G T H E O R Y A N D C O N C E PT D E V E L O P M E N T O R A N A L Y SI S

Technology and humane nursing care: (ir)reconcilable


or invented difference?
Alan Barnard RN BA MA PhD MRCNA
Lecturer, School of Nursing, Queensland University of Technology, Australia

and Margarete Sandelowski RN PhD FAAN


Professor, School of Nursing, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, USA

Submitted for publication 23 June 2000


Accepted for publication 22 December 2000

Correspondence: BARNARD A. & SANDELOWSKI M. (2001) Journal of Advanced Nursing 34(3),


Alan Barnard, 367±375
School of Nursing, Technology and humane nursing care: (ir)reconcilable or invented difference?
Queensland University of Technology,
Aim(s) of the paper. This paper questions the validity of a boundary presumed to
Victoria Park Road,
exist between technology and humane care. It argues the need for reconciliation of
Kelvin Grove Campus,
Queensland 4059,
presumed tension(s) between technology and person focused care and the need to
Australia. reconsider our ways of understanding the relations between technology and nursing.
E-mail: a.barnard@qut.edu.au Background/rationale. Recent scholarship in the social sciences related to repro-
ductive and imaging technologies and emergency resuscitation are examined and
arguments are presented that question the appropriateness of a humanist view that
emphasizes technology on the nonhuman and nonnatural side of a human/
nonhuman, nature/arti®ce divide. It is argued that what determines experiences
such as dehumanization is not technology per se but how individual technologies are
used and operate in speci®c user contexts, the meanings that are attributed to them,
how individuals or cultural groups de®ne what is human, and the organizational,
human, political and economic technological system (technique) that creates
rationale and ef®cient order within nursing, health care and society.
Conclusion. The paper concludes by asking whether the commonplace appeal to
resolve tensions between humane care and technology has erroneously highlighted
technology as the reason for impersonal care, and encourages re-examination of the
relationship(s) between technology, humane care and nursing practice.

Keywords: technology, humane care, touch, technique, nursing practice, humanism,


theory

beings, with creating the alienation between self and body,


Introduction
and with separating nurses from their mission to care. Some
A commonplace in nursing (although not exclusive to it) is to nurses (Allan & Hall 1988, Green 1992, Mann 1992, Cooper
portray medical technology as a `culprit in contemporary 1993, Calne 1994) have linked dehumanization with clinical
health care' (Timmermans 1998a, p. 435). We nurses (and environments characterized by standardization, the too pal-
others) have variously charged medical technology with the pable and audible presence of machinery and equipment, and
dehumanization, depersonalization, and objecti®cation of by the treatment of patients as extensions of that machinery.
patients and of nursing care: that is, with depriving patients A thematic thread in the nursing literature critical of tech-
of their individuality, subjectivity, and dignity as human nology is that technology/scienti®c cure is paradigmatically

Ó 2001 Blackwell Science Ltd 367


A. Barnard and M. Sandelowski

opposed to touch/humane care and thus is at odds with the


Contested terrain
practice and even moral imperatives of nursing (Braun et al.
1984, Gadow 1984, Sandelowski 1988). In this literature, the In sharp contrast to the humanist depiction of technology on
organized and ef®cient world of technology prevails over the the nonhuman side of the human/nonhuman divide is the
particular and spontaneous world of people, and functions to postmodern challenge to all `troublesome dualisms' (Balsamo
undermine expressions of caring. Medical technology is here 1997, p. 133), including nature/culture, person/object, female/
juxtaposed with the nursing `culture of caring' (Fox et al. male, and human/nonhuman (both animal and machine).
1990). Indeed, the positioning of nursing/care against tech- Although it is common to categorize technology as nonhuman,
nology/cure has been a key device by which some have sought pacemakers and arti®cial joints implanted in living human
to establish the distinctive professional identity of nursing beings, genetic engineering, and arti®cial intelligence systems
and the `narrative and symbolic boundary' between nursing regularly confront us with the reality of and potentiality for
and medicine (May & Fleming 1997). living artifacts and vital machines (Channell 1991). These
Even those of us who espouse the existence of a harmony cyborg `emblem(s) of postmodern identity' (Balsamo 1997,
between technology and care (Ray 1987, Bosque 1995, p. 32) blur the line between animate and inanimate, and
Locsin 1995, Walters 1995, Ozbolt 1996, McConnell 1998) human and machine (Haraway 1991).
have assumed a rapprochement between two separate and Long conceived in Western medicine as if they were
potentially irreconcilable entities (Sandelowski 1997). For machines (Lupton 1994), human bodies have actually
many of us technology is still something nurses must work become `technological artifacts' (Oldenziel 1998, p. 181) as
with, work around, or work hard to make compatible with, new media/medical technologies have made these bodies
or supportive, nursing care. To this end, we have encouraged more `plastic', `bionic', `interchangeable', and `virtual'
each other to develop an ethical awareness, in order to (Williams 1997). Body parts (for example, kidneys, hearts,
2 temper the effects of technology (Ray 1987, McConnell gametes) are now used as `therapeutic tools' (Hogle 1996). In
1998), including the `dissonance' that it engenders (Purnell the case of organ transplantation, these `personalized' and
1998). `objecti®ed' body parts challenge existing notions of a uni®ed
Yet as we will propose in this article, recent scholarship in embodied self (Sharp 1995, p. 361). Corpses, experimental
the social sciences has called into question the tension animals, fetuses, and brain-dead-but-otherwise-alive organ
presumed to exist between humane care and technology: donors confound and contest humanistic notions of person
between a `paradigm of relation' and a `paradigm of control' vs. object, natural vs. arti®cial, and living vs. dead (Casper
(Hawthorne & Yurkovich 1995, p. 1090). Indeed, the tension 1994, Ohnuki-Tierney 1994, Pickstone 1994).
between `touch' and `technology' as `two paradigms of patient (Casper 1994, pp. 307±308) located the fetus `at the
care' (Gadow 1984), and the positioning of nursing between margins of humanity': in the `spaces between ááá (the) concep-
the `humanistic' and `technologic frameworks' (McConnell tual dualism' of human/nonhuman. Technological innova-
1998, p. 26), may re¯ect better a certain social construction of tions in diagnosis and treatment have contributed to the
humane care and technology, rather than any essential marginality of the fetus. No longer solely a divine or natural
difference between them. Recent scholarship suggests a more creation, the contemporary fetus is a technologically `carp-
complicated relationship, as what any technology is at any entered' entity (Ihde 1979, p. 118): a `synthesized' product
moment in time is increasingly understood to depend on the (Duden 1993, p. 8) and `engineered construct of modern
eye of the beholder, the hand of the user, and the technological society (Duden 1993, p. 4). Contested objects, such as the
systems that in¯uence integration and use. fetus, exemplify the disappearance of the last great divide:
In this paper, we argue that technology is not necessarily that is, they exemplify the effacement of what Mazlish (1967)
opposed to humanized care, but rather is often speci®cally referred to as the `fourth discontinuity' between human and
and deliberately enrolled in the service of that care. In machine. Indeed, biomedical technologies, in particular, are
addition, we suggest that the continued polarization of the contested sites and even the `fault line' where such entities
technology and humane care may comprise a discourse that as nature and culture, person and object, and human and
is more in the service of maintaining a distinctive professional nonhuman meet, mingle, and regularly transgress traditional
identity than of improving nursing care. The paper seeks to boundaries (Casper & Koenig 1996, p. 525).
highlight an alternative approach to understanding the With the recognition of the `traf®c' between entities once
relations between technology and nursing and to discuss thought of as having inviolable borders (Casper & Koenig
critically whether there is necessarily an irreconcilable tension 1996, p. 526), technologies, like people, are now conceived of
between technology and humane care. as having agency, biographies, lives, lifecourses, histories,

368 Ó 2001 Blackwell Science Ltd, Journal of Advanced Nursing, 34(3), 367±375
Nursing theory and concept development or analysis Technology and humane nursing care

language, idiosyncratic quirks, inclinations (Ihde 1979, of science, and a bid to a higher social status (Sandelowski
Wiener et al. 1979, Cowan 1983, Rothenberg 1993, Callon 2000).
1995, Orr 1996, Prout 1996, Timmermans 1998a), and
`known propensities for perverse or benign behaviour' (Orr
Technology in the service of personhood
1996, p. 89). In contemporary social studies of science and
technology, and especially evident in studies framed in actor- While technological determinists assume a pre®gured stable
network theory, both human and nonhuman actors act. cause of effects, humanists assume a pre®gured stable self.
Agency is no longer conceived as the sole privilege of human This essential self is at the heart of prevailing notions of
beings. agency, identity, and person-hood. Several recent ethnog-
The `ontological extension of human agency' (Timmer- raphies challenge both of these ideas, emphasizing the
mans 1998a, p. 427) to nonhumans is said to occur through changing meanings of technology and the changing identities
`delegation'', whereby devices `substitute for ± stand in for technologies invoke (Timmermans 1996). In these ethnog-
and hold the place of ± the actions of people' (Timmermans raphies, technologies are shown to foster person-hood and to
1998a, p. 428). For example, Prout (1996) used actor- further humane caring.
network theory to show how the metered dose inhaler can
be usefully seen as a means of delegating biomedical work. Agency through objecti®cation
The inhaler was given the clinician's work of controlling the Cussins (1996, 1998) challenged the humanist notion of a
dose of medication delivered to the patient, even as the stable self appropriated by technology and the humanist
inhaler itself was placed in the hands of patients. The argument that these selves required protection from techno-
autonomy of the patient was extended, but it was also limited logical `objecti®cation to ensure their agency and authenti-
as the inhaler regulated the dose the patient could receive. city' (1996, p. 575). She especially wanted to confront the
The device thus offered simultaneously more control that was longstanding humanist tradition of viewing objecti®cation as
personal to patients while maintaining traditional medical alienating and technology as `usurping selfhood's (1996,
control over them. p. 576), and a speci®cally feminist tradition of viewing
The actor-network view of humans and nonhumans as infertile women as `paradigmatic of the objecti®ed patient'
analytically (as opposed to morally) similar (Prout 1996, (1998, p. 167). Not wanting `to deny the subjugating and
p. 215), and its emphasis on acts, not actors, contrasts with disciplining effects of many technologies', Cussins instead
dualistic and deterministic accounts of technology as alien to sought to `question whether ... objecti®cation per se (was)
human beings and as stable causes of effects (Barnard 1996). antithetical to personhood's (1998, p. 167). Cussins found
As (Timmermans 1998a, pp. 435±436) argued, critics using infertility clinics `rich sites' for answers to this question: that
`technological deterministic arguments dislodge technological is, for an `examination of agency and the ontological
innovations from their performance contexts'. Such argu- commitments that go with it' (1998, p. 169).
ments preclude us from seeing how technologies, like people, Cussins concluded that the infertile women she observed
simultaneously act, but are also `acted upon' (Timmermans often asserted themselves through objecti®cation. As she
1998a, p. 436): that is, how the human and the technological interpreted their experiences with assisted reproductive tech-
mutually constitute each other (Prout 1996) and thus cannot niques, there was no one infertility patient, who exempli®ed
be understood as entities apart from each other. Indeed, the the saved or victimized patient objecti®ed by technology,
one is in the other, as opposed to the one (that is, the but rather there existed at different times various kinds
technological) existing exclusively as Other to the human of active participants pursuing agency by means of objecti-
3 (Gadow 1984). ®cation.
Moreover, technological deterministic arguments preclude Cussins used the term `ontological choreography' to refer to
us from seeing that what technologies are depends on the the multiplicity of selves evident in infertility work, whereby a
historical, social, and cultural (including gender) contexts in woman is at one time and in one place a generic patient, and at
which they act and are acted upon: how the `potential and other times and places a set of ovaries and follicles on an
power of a technological device to shape an interaction is not ultrasound screen, a vagina and cervix on speculum exam-
pregiven but is realized in practice' (Timmermans 1998b, ination, or a satis®ed or dissatis®ed consumer of medical
p. 148). A stethoscope is what it is physically. But even more services. By permitting and even requiring these ontological
importantly, the stethoscope is also what it becomes in a variations to multiply, reproductive technologies offered
speci®c user context; the stethoscope is, among other things, women new options for achieving a long-term desired self:
an instrument of diagnosis, an extension of the ear, a symbol that is, to be a mother. Indeed, as Cussins proposed, women

Ó 2001 Blackwell Science Ltd, Journal of Advanced Nursing, 34(3), 367±375 369
A. Barnard and M. Sandelowski

did not allow themselves to be treated passively like objects in body is broken that we may speak of an alienated corporeal
order to comply with medical protocols, but rather they existence.
complied actively to permit themselves to be treated like
objects in the interests of achieving a long-range desired self. Legitimation through visual objecti®cation
Women actively participated in several kinds of objecti®ca- A special case of objecti®cation, and a key feature of
tion, including `medical operationalization', by which a contemporary health care, is the increasing turn to an
woman is `rendered into multiple body parts', `naturaliza- image-based reality. Health care is now a `panoply of
tion', by which many of a woman's social roles are made ``screens''' (Williams 1997, p. 1047) by which the natural is
irrelevant while her body becomes an object of experimenta- purportedly made visible. Technological images (for
tion and manipulation, `bureaucratization', by which only her example, X-rays, sonograms, computerized tomography
status as a generic infertility patient is made relevant, and by and magnetic resonance pictures) have created the `inside
`epistemic disciplining', by which a woman becomes an body', a body conceived to be the body as it really is: that is,
informed consumer of infertility services (1998, pp. 187±189). not the outside body that clinicians routinely engaged prior to
Cussins (1998) proposed that not only did women's selves the 20th century and the `blind old days' of medicine (Simon
vary, but also their perceptions of their own objecti®cation as 1999, p. 141).
operating for or against their long-range self. A woman might In the ultimate exemplar of technological objecti®cation,
say that a procedure objecti®ed her after failing to get the patient is not the `corporeal' person in the bed or on the
pregnant by it, but evaluate the same procedure more examining table, but rather the `hyperreal' re-presentation of
positively when she achieved pregnancy. Yet, as Cussins that patient on screen in the form of a rhythm strip, black and
(1998) argued, these judgements were not simply re¯ections white picture, colourized image, or digital or other display
of changes in any one woman's perception according to (Williams 1997). Arguably, these images `stand in for
outcome, but rather of different `subject(s) of discourse' patients with more life than the ``real'' thing' (Simon 1999,
(1998, p. 191); for one of these subjects, treatment entailed p. 157). Indeed, both clinicians and patients themselves now
retaining properties of personhood while for the other, it did look to screens to ®nd out how well or close to death a
not. Moreover, the care of women was personalized by patient is (Robillard 1997). Clinicians now treat `bad strips',
objecti®cation, because objecti®cation allowed a failed proce- not sick patients (Cartwright 1998, p. 249).
dure to be separated from a failed body/self. That is, it Yet as Rhodes et al. (1999) discovered in their study of
allowed a woman and those caring for her to see a failure to patients with chronic back pain, `visual objecti®cation of
achieve conception, not as her failure (I/she cannot get the body' often sustained patients' subjectivity by helping
pregnant), but rather as an organ failure (my/her fallopian them to legitimate their suffering. By offering these
tubes block conception) or technical failure (the embryos did patients, who had nothing to show for their pain, visual
not implant). This `synedochal's (1998, p. 176) relationship, proof of its cause, visual technologies conferred on them
by which an isolated body part or function comes to stand for the `power of the visible' in a culture that increasingly
a particular patient and by which instruments `acquire de®nes the real as the seen. For patients suffering from
properties of personhood in virtue of which they ®x, bypass, ambiguous diseases like chronic back pain, these technolo-
or stand in for stages in a woman becoming pregnant' (1998, gical images become meaningful as `visual representation(s)
p. 192), allowed women's subjectivity to be maintained. Only of the truth of pain' (Rhodes et al. 1999, p. 1192).
in cases of `synedochal breakdown', where `rupture (1998, Moreover, these patients seemed to derive a vicarious
p. 190) occurred between the long-range self and these pleasure from the sensuous pleasure their physicians
variously objecti®ed selves did feelings of alienation or experienced while gazing at and analysing these images.
dehumanization emerge. For them, there was a `satisfying visualization of the
Accordingly, as Cussins' work illustrated, there is no correspondence between objective ®nding and subjective
necessary tension between technology and self, nor techno- pain' (Rhodes et al. 1999, p. 1201).
logically-engendered alienation between body and self. (Van In contrast, for patients for whom no such visual proof of
Manen 1998, p. 16) observed that an `objectifying view of a their pain existed, these technologies were meaningful as
patient's body is not in itself a dehumanizing activity'. As he undermining their claims to pain. These patients experienced
proposed: these technologies as alienating because they not only `dele-
gitimized' their pain, but also fragmented their selves.
The physical body is the form in which our lived body can show itself
Reinforcing the Cartesian split between body and mind,
as object. It is only when the relation between physical body and lived
visual technologies, in cases where no visual proof of pain

370 Ó 2001 Blackwell Science Ltd, Journal of Advanced Nursing, 34(3), 367±375
Nursing theory and concept development or analysis Technology and humane nursing care

existed, supported the notion that `what is not clearly body ... it is not technology per se that renders birthing and dying
(becomes) only mind' (p. 1201). unnatural and inhumane, but rather technologies contribute
to situations that make possible such events to be conceived
Technology as humanized nature and lived as either natural or unnatural, and humane or
In addition to sustaining subjectivity, technologies may also inhumane, as these terms are de®ned by a person or culture in
enhance nature. Central to critiques of the modern way of a speci®c moment in time. Whether birthing woman or dying
birth and death is the view of technology as at odds with an patient, individuals `choose and combine elements of their
idealized nature (Eakins 1986, Davis-Floyd 1992). In these preferred natural event from a range of potentially contra-
critiques, natural birth and natural death are romantically dictory sources (Seymour 1999, p. 693). `What is natural is
conceived as painless, digni®ed, satisfying, and even beau- man's (sic) arti®ce' (Fletcher 1988, p. 44). Human beings
tiful. Natural birth and death are seen to be events in the create technologies and thereby the nature that technologies
`lost' but recoverable past preceding their medicalization, the reveal, alter, and even (as in the case of a baby conceived by
key component, cause, and effect of which is technological in vitro fertilization) make possible.
intervention (Harvey 1997). Indeed, the technological inter-
vention at the heart of medicalization is seen to be `emblem- A technological but digni®ed death
atic of inhumane and unnatural death' and birth (Seymour Timmermans (1998b) illustrated this phenomenon well in his
1999, p. 692). ethnographic study of resuscitation technology. Timmermans
Yet there is nothing natural about either birth or death, as challenged the prevailing assumption, largely derived from
natural childbirth and dying, and the human bodies central to cases of chronic illness, that medicalized or technological
both, are highly social entities. Indeed, nature is itself a interventions undermine digni®ed death in all cases, specif-
cultural artifact, as people in different cultures have continu- ically, in cases of sudden death. He argued that even with all
ally (re)de®ned and (re)created nature (Lock 1996). In many its problems and excesses, resuscitation technology addressed
Western countries, dead is now `dead enough' (Franklin a distinctively western reluctance to accept death. By taking
1996, p. 684) legally and morally to extract and use body away some of the suddenness of sudden death, resuscitation
parts as `therapeutic tools' (Hogle 1996). Dead is not an technology gave relatives and friends time to come to terms
absolute category, but rather a `negotiable terrain' (Franklin with the death of their loved ones, allowed them a sense of
1996, p. 684). Moreover, a natural death, when de®ned as a control over the inevitability of death, and offered them the
painless death, is frequently achieved with pharmacological consolation that everything possible had been carried out to
and technological intervention. avert it. In the case of sudden infant death, resuscitation
Nature is also culture in the case of natural childbirth. efforts, which were often initiated even when there was no
Early 20th century American women and clinician advocates hope of reviving the infant, helped parents make sense of a
of the Twilight Sleep, by which women were heavily sedated senseless death. These bene®ts were emphasized in cases
during labour and delivery, promoted drugs as allowing a where relatives were allowed to witness or participate in the
natural birth to occur. Indeed, births without drugs were resuscitation effort (Timmermans 1997). As Timmermans
considered to be unnatural. In contrast, the key feature of the proposed, resuscitation technology served as a cultural ritual
mid-20th century American Natural Childbirth Movement facilitating the passage from life to death. By providing an
was its antitechnological stance: drugs and surgery were seen opportunity to prepare for impending death, the technology
to interfere with a natural birth (Sandelowski 1984). In other naturalized and `digni®ed death' (Timmermans 1998b).
studies, patients have often conceived of technology as
operating in the service of nature (Calnan & Williams
From difference to paradox: from technology
1994). For example, infertile couples have described assisted
to technique
conception as natural because nature allowed it to succeed,
because it simulated natural conception, because the preg- Although postmodern views of technology challenge its
nancy, birth, and child that followed it were themselves separation from the human and the natural, nurses are
natural processes and entities, and because it allowed them to among many groups who still adhere to a humanist view of
become natural parents. For these couples, natural equaled technology on the nonhuman and nonnatural side of the
normal, moral, and technological (Sandelowski 1993). human/nonhuman, nature/arti®ce divide. We still depict
Technology can thus be conceived in two contradictory ourselves as the bridge spanning the divide between tech-
ways: as humanizing and `humanized nature' (Pfaffenberger nology and humane health care. We have thereby claimed
1988), or as an entity or force opposed to nature. Moreover, professional ownership of the space between technology and

Ó 2001 Blackwell Science Ltd, Journal of Advanced Nursing, 34(3), 367±375 371
A. Barnard and M. Sandelowski

patient, and the responsibility for maintaining humane care that the human differences, feelings, and meanings we
in technological environments (e.g. Ray 1987, Gordon 1992, identify, categorize, and order can themselves become
4 Cooper 1993, Halm & Alpen 1993, Pelletier 1994). Dwelling technique by virtue of our identifying, categorizing, and
in this space, we see ourselves as the mediators between two ordering them. When we set about, for example, to invent
seemingly irreconcilable and disparate forces. protocols for quality care, for teaching caring nursing, or to
Our claims to ownership of the divide between technology achieve natural birth, we facilitate the development of
and patient imply not only our alignment with the human, technique. Although practices such as family presence
but also our belief that we can control technology. Moreover, during emergency resuscitation allow digni®ed deaths, their
our association with technological knowledge and skill has transformation into `best practices' can lead to poorer
been a source of increased prestige and power for nursing practice. Because of technique, there can be over emphasis
(Barnard & Gerber 1999). Indeed, we have conceived of on the maximization of ef®ciency, specialization of practice,
technology as the embodiment of both scienti®c progress and and development of conformity and sameness in product,
of professional development. Although we have questioned process, and thought.
the impact of technological innovations on nursing practice, Accordingly, it is technique, not technological objects
we have accepted technological tasks delegated to us and per se, that we must confront, as we have delegated to
turned to technology to advance our profession (Barnard technique the power of decision-making and have relied on
1999, Barnard & Cushing 2001, Walker 1970, Donahue technique for the development of professional status. We
1985, Gordon 1992, Castledine 1995). As one nurse nurses have expressed concern over the impact of technology,
observed: but we have embraced technique. Yet, it is technique that has
made contemporary nursing `technological', not objects,
I think the profession looks more professional and more glamorous
machines, automata or equipment. Technology has always
with the technology because there's a lot more of it now in the wards
been part of nursing. The use of technology now, although it
that nurses use ... People ... outside of the nursing profession, don't
is more advanced and sophisticated than technologies of the
know anything about it. They tend to put nurses up a little bit higher
past, is not a criterion for de®ning contemporary nursing
because they can work all these machines that buzz and they [nurses]
practice as technological (Barnard 2001).
know exactly what to press. They [patients] think they are going to
be blown up or something like that, and they panic. The nurse comes
along and she just saves the day and presses the right button (Barnard Conclusion: nursing, technology, and difference
1998, p. 161).
In conclusion, we have in this paper questioned the validity of
Yet the discourse of difference that nurses have engaged in a boundary traditionally presumed to exist between tech-
concerning technology does not resolve the paradox of nology and humane care. We have proposed a more compli-
technique that exists in the nursing/technology relationship. cated view of technology. We have argued that what
Technique refers to the formation of system comprised of determines whether a technology dehumanizes, depersonal-
human, organizational, political, and economic structures, izes, or objecti®es is not technology per se, but rather how
which are aimed toward the absolute ef®ciency of methods individual technologies operate in speci®c user contexts, the
and means in every ®eld of human endeavor. Several meanings attributed to them, how any one individual or
philosophers of technology have emphasized the importance cultural group de®nes what is human, and the potential of
of technique over technology (Ellul 1964, Winner 1977, technique to emphasize ef®ciency and rationale order. Like
Mitcham 1994, Feenberg 1999). For them, technique ± not technology, humane care is itself a socially-constructed
technology ± has increasingly structured collective behaviour entity. The power any technology exerts derives from how
and in¯uenced individual lives, cultures and professional it acts in any given situation and from its meaningfulness.
perspectives. Many aspects of nursing and health care are Technology is thus not simply or necessarily a paradigm of
structured in accordance with technical demands arizing care opposed to touch, but rather also an agent and object of
from relationships that develop because of technique, which touch. Technology can itself be a humanizing factor, even in
emphasize a primacy of means, ef®ciency, and rational the most technologically intense arenas of health care. The
order. Technique does not attend to such phenomena as `duality of technology' (Orlikowski 1992) ± as matter and
individual and cultural difference. The purpose of technique meaning ± lies not in its necessary opposition to humaniza-
is to reproduce itself; it is the centre of its own attention. tion, but rather in its recursiveness: in its existence as both
When we raise issues of individual and cultural differences, objective, material force and as a socially constructed and
we emphasize the opposite end of technique. The paradox is chameleon-like entity.

372 Ó 2001 Blackwell Science Ltd, Journal of Advanced Nursing, 34(3), 367±375
Nursing theory and concept development or analysis Technology and humane nursing care

The problem of technology for nurses may thus lie less in Accordingly, the question of whether to maintain or to
technology itself than in the choices we and our patients abandon the distinction between technology and humane
make about what is humane, natural, and digni®ed care. As care is not a simple one to answer, as it confronts us with the
we have proposed, we all choose and combine elements of core issues of professional position and power, and of the
our own preferred humane, digni®ed, or natural event from a politics of difference. We have to ask ourselves: What
range of potentially contradictory sources. A digni®ed death differences will we `choose' (Burbules & Rice 1991, p. 400)
might thus entail a `low'- or `high'-technology presence. The to maintain? Does maintaining a distinction between tech-
resolution of this problem is, in part, to ascertain and honor nology and humane care reinforce or undermine gender and
these varied choices. other stereotypes and prejudices concerning nursing? Such
Alternatively, the problem of technology for nurses may lie distinctions have often entailed essentializing both nursing
less in technology itself than in the discourse of difference and technology, or minimizing the differences or diversity
(Burbules & Rice 1991) surrounding technology. (Ellul 1990, within these categories and thereby reinforcing stereotyped
p. 130) argued that we often experience what is opposite to a notions of them (Sandelowski 1997). Indeed, the idea of
prevailing discourse. Professional discourses, paradoxically, difference has itself become essentialized; rather than reifying
often re¯ect opposing realities; that is, more talk of freedom it, difference is better conceived as in constant interaction
often means there is less freedom, more talk of respect, less with sameness. Whether two entities are viewed as different,
respect, and more talk of humane care, less humane care. or the same, is a matter of changing cultural evaluation
Accordingly, by emphasizing the difference between touch (Burbules & Rice 1991). Does difference contribute to or
and technology, we may be focusing on differences that either detract from the goals of equality or privilege (Barrett 1987)
do not exist, or do not matter, and thereby diverting for nursing? As (Barrett 1987, p. 35) observed, `sites of
ourselves away from differences that do. A question that difference are also sites of power'. Finally, we must ask
we must answer is whether the discourse of difference ourselves whether the appeal to difference settles any differ-
surrounding technology is preventing us from recognizing ences for us concerning nursing, technology, and the humane
the technique that can undermine humane care? care of our patients?
Another key question for nursing is `whose interests are
being furthered or protected' (Munro 1997, p. 4) by main-
References
taining the distinction between technology and humane care.
Indeed, this distinction exempli®es `difference-in-use' (p. 19) Allan J.D. & Hall B.A. (1988) Challenging the focus on technology: a
by which divisions are exploited to achieve certain ends. We critique of the medical model in a changing health care system.
Advances in Nursing Science 10, 22±34.
nurses have engaged historically in the `labour of division and
Balsamo A. (1997) Technologies of the Gendered Body: Reading
identity' (p. 5), seeking to de®ne nursing in part by claiming Cyborg Women. Duke University Press, Durham, NC.
difference from medicine and the things with which it is Barnard A. (1996) Technology and nursing: an anatomy of de®nition.
culturally associated: namely, technology. For nurses, as for International Journal of Nursing Studies 33, 433±441.
others seeking identity and power through difference, there is Barnard A. (1998) Understanding technology in contemporary
surgical nursing: a phenomenographic examination. Unpublished
`no vision without division' (p. 10); division allows nurses to
5 doctoral Thesis, University of New England, Armidale, Australia.
see (themselves) and to be seen. The appeal to difference
Barnard A. (1999) Nursing and the primacy of technological
(between technology and humane care) is itself a technology ± progress. International Journal of Nursing Studies 36, 435±442.
an `artifact' (p. 4) ± by which we have sought to make `visible' Barnard A. (2001) On the relationship between technique and
our contributions to health care (Gordon 1991, p. 93). dehumanisation. In Technology, Caring and Nursing (Locsin R.
But we nurses have yet to examine the `effects that ¯ow 6 eds), Greenwood, Westport, in press.
Barnard A. & Cushing A. (2001) Technology and historical inquiry
from the presence of difference' (Munro 1997, p. 19). That is,
in nursing. In Technology, Caring and Nursing (Locsin R. eds),
for example, whether and how the distinction between 7 Greenwood, Westport, in press.
technology and humane care serves our patients or nursing Barnard A. & Gerber R. (1999) Understanding technology in
in an era when divisions that once seemed `®xed and contemporary surgical nursing: a phenomenographic examination.
fundamental' now appear increasingly `precarious and arbi- Nursing Inquiry 6, 157±170.
Barrett M. (1987) The concept of `difference'. Feminist Review 26,
trary' (p. 3). Indeed, for nurses, who comprise a social group
29±41.
that has never established fully a separate and secure identity,
Bosque E.M. (1995) Symbiosis of nurse and machine through fuzzy
it is the abandonment of divisions ± not the divisions logic: Improved speci®city of a neonatal pulse oximeter alarm.
themselves ± that may seem precarious and arbitrary. Advances in Nursing Science 18, 67±75.

Ó 2001 Blackwell Science Ltd, Journal of Advanced Nursing, 34(3), 367±375 373
A. Barnard and M. Sandelowski

Braun J.L., Baines S.L., Olson N.G., Scruby L.S., Manteuffel C.A. & Fox R.C., Aiken L.H. & Messikomer C.M. (1990) The culture of
Cretilli P.K. (1984) The future of nursing: combining humanistic caring: AIDS and the nursing profession. Milbank Quarterly 68,
and technological values. Health Values: Achieving High Level 226±256.
Wellness 8, 12±15. Franklin S. (1996) An excellent prognosis. Medical Anthropology
Burbules N.C. & Rice S. (1991) Dialogue across differences: Quarterly 10, 683±690.
continuing the conversation. Harvard Educational Review 61, Gadow S. (1984) Touch and technology: two paradigms of patient
393±416. care. Journal of Religion and Health 23, 63±69.
Callon M. (1995) Four models for the dynamics of science. In Gordon L. (1991) On `difference'. Gender 10, 91±111.
Handbook of Science and Technology Studies (Jasanoff S. Markle Gordon S. (1992) The importance of being nurses. Technology
G.E. Petersen J.C. & Pinch T. eds), Sage, Thousand Oaks, CA, pp. Review 95, 42±51.
29±63. Green A. (1992) How nurses can ensure the sounds patients hear
Calnan M. & Williams S. (1994) Lay perceptions of modern have a positive rather than negative effect upon recovery and
medicine and medical practice. In Life and Death Under High quality of care. Intensive and Critical Care 8, 245±248.
Technology Medicine (Robinson I. eds), Manchester University Halm M.A. & Alpen M.A. (1993) The impact of technology on
Press, Manchester, pp. 211±234. patients and families. Nursing Clinics of North America 28,
Calne S. (1994) Dehumanisation in intensive care. Nursing Times 90, 443±457.
31±33. Haraway D.J. (1991) Simians, Cyborgs, and Women. The Reinven-
Cartwright E. (1998) The logic of heartbeats. Electronic fetal tion of Nature. Routledge. New York.
monitoring and biomedically constructed birth. In Cyborg Babies: Harvey J. (1997) The technological regulation of death. With
From Techno-Sex to Techno-Tots (Davis-Floyd R. & Dumit J. reference to the technological regulation of birth. Sociology 31,
eds), Routledge, New York, pp. 240±254. 719±735.
Casper M.J. (1994) At the margins of humanity. Fetal positions in Hawthorne D.L. (1995) Science, technology, caring and the profes-
science and medicine. Science, Technology and Human Values 19, sions: are they compatible? Journal of Advanced Nursing 21,
307±323. 8 1087±1091.
Casper M.J. & Koenig B.A. (1996) Recon®guring nature and culture: Hawthorne D.L. & Yurkovich N.J. (1995) Science, technology,
Intersections of medical anthropology and technoscience studies. caring and the professions: are they compatible? Journal of
Medical Anthropology Quarterly 10, 523±536. Advanced Nursing 21, 1087±1091.
Castledine G. (1995) Issues for nursing in 1995. British Journal of Hogle L.F. (1996) Transforming `body parts' into therapeutic tools: a
Nursing 4, 45. report from Germany. Medical Anthropology Quarterly 10,
Channell D.F. (1991) The Vital Machine: A Study of Technology and 675±682.
Organic Life. Oxford University Press, New York. Ihde D. (1979) Technics and Praxis. A Philosophy of Technology. D.
Cooper M.C. (1993) The intersection of technology and care in the Reidel, Dordrecht.
ICU. Advances in Nursing Science 15, 23±32. Lock M. (1996) Death in technological time: locating the end of
Cowan R.S. (1983) More Work for Mother: The Ironies of House- meaningful life. Medical Anthropology Quarterly 10, 575±600.
hold Technology from the Open Hearth to the Microwave. Basic Locsin R.C. (1995) Machine technologies and caring in nursing.
Books, New York. Image: Journal of Nursing Scholarship 27, 201±203.
Cussins C. (1996) Ontological choreography: agency through objec- Lupton D. (1994) Medicine as Culture. Illness, Disease and the Body
ti®cation in infertility clinics. Social Studies of Science 26, in Western societies. Sage, London.
575±610. Mann R.E. (1992) Preserving humanity in an age of technology.
Cussins C.M. (1998) Ontological choreography. Agency for women Intensive and Critical Care Nursing 8, 54±59.
patients in an infertility clinic. In Differences in Medicine: Unrav- May C. & Fleming C. (1997) The professional imagination: narrative
eling Practices, Techniques, and Bodies (Berg M. & Mol A. eds), and the symbolic boundaries between medicine and nursing.
Duke University Press, Durham, pp. 166±201. Journal of Advanced Nursing 25, 1094±1100.
Davis-Floyd R.E. (1992) Birth as an American Rite of Passage. Mazlish B. (1967) The fourth discontinuity. Technology and Culture
University of California Press. Berkeley. 8, 1±15.
Donahue M.P. (1985) Nursing: The Finest Art. An Illustrated McConnell E.A. (1998) The coalescence of technology and
History. Mosby, St Louis. humanism in nursing practice: It doesn't just happen and it doesn't
Duden B. (1993) Disembodying Women. Perspectives on Pregnancy come easily. Holistic Nursing Practice 12, 23±30.
and the Unborn. Harvard University Press. Cambridge. Mitcham C. (1994) Thinking Through Technology: The Path
Eakins P.S. (ed.) (1986) The American Way of Birth. Temple Between Engineering and Philosophy. The University of Chicago,
University Press. Philadelphia, PA. London.
Ellul J. (1964) The Technological Society. Alfred A Knopf, New Munro R. (1997) Ideas of difference. Stability, social spaces and
York. labor of division. In Ideas of Difference: Social Spaces and the
Ellul J. (1990) The Technological Bluff. Continuum, New York. Labor of Division (Hetherington K. & Munro R. eds), Blackwell,
Feenberg A. (1999) Questioning Technology. Routledge. New Oxford, pp. 3±24.
York. Ohnuki-Tierney E. (1994) Brain death and organ transplantation:
Fletcher J.F. (1988) The Ethics of Genetic Control. Ending Repro- Cultural bases of medical technology. Current Anthropology 35,
ductive Roulette. Prometheus, New York. 233±254.

374 Ó 2001 Blackwell Science Ltd, Journal of Advanced Nursing, 34(3), 367±375
Nursing theory and concept development or analysis Technology and humane nursing care

Oldenziel R. (1998) Review of Bernice L. Hausman's changing sex: Sandelowski M. (1997) (Ir)Reconcilable differences? The debate
transsexualism, technology, and the idea of gender. Technology concerning nursing and technology. Image: Journal of Nursing
and Culture 39, 179±181. Scholarship 29, 169±174.
Orlikowski W.J. (1992) The duality of technology: rethinking the Sandelowski M. (2000) Devices and Desires: Gender, Technology,
concept of technology in organizations. Organization Science 3, and American Nursing. University of North Carolina Press, Chapel
398±427. Hill.
Orr J.E. (1996) Talking About Machines: An Ethnography of a Seymour J.E. (1999) Revisiting medicalization and `natural' death.
Modern Job. ILR Press/Cornell University Press, New York. Social Science & Medicine 49, 691±704.
Ozbolt J.G. (1996) Nursing and technology: a dialectic. Holistic Sharp L.A. (1995) Organ transplantation as a transformative experi-
Nursing Practice 11, 1±5. ence: anthropological insights into the restructuring of the self.
Pelletier D. (1994) Technology. In Critical Care Nursing (Romanini Medical Anthropology Quarterly 9, 357±389.
J. & Daly J. eds), Harcourt Brace & Company, Sydney, Simon C.M. (1999) Images and image: technology and the social
pp. 1039±1063. politics of revealing disorder in a North American hospital.
Pfaffenberger B. (1988) Fetishized objects and humanised nature: Medical Anthropology Quarterly 13, 141±162.
towards an anthropology of technology. Man 23, 236±252. Timmermans S. (1996) Saving lives or saving multiple identities? The
Pickstone J. (1994) Objects and objectives: notes on the material double dynamic of resuscitation scripts. Social Studies of Science
cultures of medicine. In Technologies of Modern Medicine 26, 767±797.
(Lawrence G. ed.), Science Museum, London, pp. 13±24. Timmermans S. (1997) High touch in high tech: the presence of
Prout A. (1996) Actor-network theory, technology and medical relatives and friends during resuscitative efforts. Scholarly Inquiry
sociology: an illustrative analysis of the metered dose inhaler. for Nursing Practice 11, 153±168.
Sociology of Health & Illness 18, 198±219. Timmermans S. (1998a) Mutual tuning of multiple trajectories.
Purnell M.J. (1998) Who really makes the bed? Uncovering techno- Symxbolic Interaction 21, 425±440.
logic dissonance in nursing. Holistic Nursing Practice 12, 12±22. Timmermans S. (1998b) Resuscitation technology in the emergency
Ray M.A. (1987) Technological caring: a new model in critical care. department: towards a digni®ed death. Sociology of Health &
Dimensions of Critical Care Nursing 6, 166±173. Illness 20, 144±167.
Rhodes L.A., McPhillips-Tangum C.A., Markham C. & Klenk R. Van Manen M. (1998) Modalities of body experience in illness and
(1999) The power of the visible: the meaning of diagnostic tests in health. Qualitative Health Research 8, 7±24.
chronic back pain. Social Science & Medicine 48, 1189±1203. Walker D.J. (1970) Our challenging world. Nursing Forum 9,
Robillard A.B. (1997) Communication problems in the intensive care 328±339.
unit. In Re¯exivity and Voice (Hertz R. eds), Sage, California, Walters A.J. (1995) Technology and the lifeworld of critical care
pp. 252±264. nursing. Journal of Advanced Nursing 22, 338±346.
Rothenberg D. (1993) Hand's End. Technology and the Limits of Wiener C., Strauss A., Fagerhaugh S. & Suczek B. (1979) Traject-
Nature. University of California Press, Berkeley. ories, biographies, and the evolving medical technology scene:
Sandelowski M. (1984) Pain, Pleasure, and American Childbirth: Labor and delivery and the intensive care nursery. Sociology of
From the Twilight Sleep to the Read Method, 1914±1960. Health & Illness 1, 261±283.
Greenwood Press, Westport. Williams S.J. (1997) Modern medicine and the `uncertain body': from
Sandelowski M. (1988) A case of con¯icting paradigms: nursing corporeality to hyperreality? Social Science & Medicine 45,
and reproductive technology. Advances in Nursing Science 10, 1041±1049.
35±45. Winner L. (1977) Autonomous Technology. MIT Press, Massachu-
Sandelowski M. (1993) With Child in Mind. Studies of the Personal setts.
Encounter with Infertility. University of Pennsylvania Press,
Philadelphia.

Ó 2001 Blackwell Science Ltd, Journal of Advanced Nursing, 34(3), 367±375 375

You might also like