You are on page 1of 27

Luther Seminary

Digital Commons @ Luther Seminary


Faculty Publications Faculty & Staff Scholarship

2003

Paul, Hardships, and Suffering


David E. Fredrickson
Luther Seminary, dfredric@luthersem.edu

Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.luthersem.edu/faculty_articles


Part of the Biblical Studies Commons, and the Christianity Commons

Recommended Citation
Fredrickson, David E., "Paul, Hardships, and Suffering" (2003). Faculty Publications. 212.
http://digitalcommons.luthersem.edu/faculty_articles/212
Published Citation
Fredrickson, David. “Paul, Hardships, and Suffering.” In Paul in the Greco-Roman World : A Handbook, edited by J. Paul. Sampley,
172–97. Harrisburg, Pa. : Trinity Press International, 2003.

This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty & Staff Scholarship at Digital Commons @ Luther Seminary. It has been accepted
for inclusion in Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Luther Seminary. For more information, please contact
akeck001@luthersem.edu.
(§)
PAUL, H A R D S H I P S ,
AND S U F F E R I N G
David £. Fredrickson

I focus m y exam ination of suffering o n the concept of grief (A.ujrr|, type), w hich in
the G reco-R om an w orld w as w idely considered one type of passion. The G reek
term for passio n (7id 0 o<;, pathos) denotes the self being acted u p o n ra th e r than act­
in g u p o n th e external w orld. To suffer (ndayeiv, paschein) is to be m oved by exter­
n a ls .1 From the philosophic perspective, it m attered little w h eth er this m ovem ent
w as occasioned by grief or by the other m ain types of passion (fear, pleasure, lust,
and, in som e sources, anger). This association of suffering w ith passion in general,
th o u g h correct, w o u ld indicate too broad a range of inquiry. For practical reasons,
therefore, I lim it this investigation to w h a t E nglish-speakers norm ally m ean by
suffering— em otional p ain or grief .2 F urtherm ore, I h ighlight aspects of the a n ­
cient discourse ab o u t grief that bear directly on the interpretation of P au l's letters:
som e p ertin en t form s of grief, h ard sh ip s an d h a rd sh ip lists, the role of grief in
m oral reform ation; tw o ancient letter types that m ake grief them atic; an d the n o ­
tion of shared suffering in friendship.

P art I. H ardships and Suffering


in G reco -R o m an Philosophy and Epistolography

T h e Psychology o f S u ffe rin g

G rief as irrational contraction (auGToA.fi, systole) of the soul or heart is a com m on­
place in Stoic psychology (Diogenes Laertius 7.111,118; SVF 1.51.26-31; 3.94.14-
15; 3.95.17-18, 24-25, 41-43; Epictetus, frg. 9; Plutarch, Lib. aegr. 1,7) .3 Cicero
show s th at the m etaphor of grief as soul shrinkage w as so well established in
G reek w riters th at it su rv iv ed the translation of philosophical term s into Latin:
"Distress [aegritudo] then is a new ly form ed belief of present evil, the subject of
w hich thinks it right to feel depression an d shrinking of soul [ileinitti contrahique

172
P a u l, H a r d s h ip s , a n d S u ff e r in g 173

animo]” (Cicero, Tusc. 4.14; cf. Tusc. 1.90; 3.83; 4.66-67; Quint, fratr. 1.1.4; Seneca,
Ep. 99.15). Some of the varieties of grief im ply the idea of contraction. For exam ­
ple, groaning (oxevaypdg, stenagmos) conveys the notion of contraction in the root
cxev (sten; see Rom 8:23, 26; 2 Cor 5:2,4 ).4 Soul shrinkage accounts in the philoso­
phers for the experience of grief at its m ost fun dam ental level .5
N ot all types of em otional pain, how ever, exhibit contraction of soul. O ne
such variety of grief often treated by the philosophers w as regret (pexapeAeia,
mctameleia), a particularly sharp form of suffering. The stan d ard definition of re­
gret w as "grief over sins done as though h ap p en in g th ro u g h one's o w n self ." 6
W hat m akes regret so painful is self-hatred an d self-condem nation: "R egret is a
factious passion of the soul w hich brings unhappiness, for to the extent th at the
one is encom passed by regrets an d is grieved at the things w hich have hap p en ed ,
to this degree he is angry at him self, since he becam e the cause of these things"
(SVF 3.149.20-24; m y translation). A ccording to Plutarch, the soul th at regrets a
deed is filled w ith no other th o u g h t than "h o w it m ight escape from the m em ory
of its iniquities, drive out of itself the consciousness of guilt, regain its purity, an d
begin life anew " (Plutarch, Sera 556A). Such persons condem n their lives, feel re­
m orse, hate them selves, an d are distressed over w h a t they have done (Plutarch,
Sera 566E). The notion that, as Seneca p u t it, "he w ho has sinned has already p u n ­
ished him self," echoed th ro u g h o u t ancient w ritings (Seneca, Ira 2.30.2).7 Seneca
com m ents fu rth er that "no m an is m ore heavily pu n ish ed than he w h o is con­
signed to the to rtu re of rem orse" (Seneca, Ira 3.26.2).
P hilosophers used the notion of self-condem nation to explain the n atu re of
regret. A ristotle form alized a connection probably found already in everyday
speech: "But a good m an does not rebuke him self either at the tim e, like the u n ­
controlled, n or yet his form er self his later, like the p en iten t [6 peTapeA/rynKoi;, ho
metameletikos] . . . because w hen m en blam e them selves they are p u ttin g them ­
selves to death" (Aristotle, Eth. end. 7.6.14-15; m odified translation).
Plutarch d raw s ou t the analogy betw een regret an d punishm ent. Like p riso n ­
ers sentenced to death, every w icked m an suffers "terrors, forebodings, an d the
p an g s of rem orse" (pexapeAefoo;, mctameleias; Plutarch, Sera 554E-F). H e also
w rites that w h en "despots . . . desire to m ake m iserable those w hom they punish,
[they] m aintain executioners an d torturers, o r devise b randing-irons a n d w edges;
vice . . . fills the m an w ith grief an d lam entation, dejection a n d rem orse" (juexape-
Xeiaq, mctameleias; Plutarch, An vit. 498D; cf. Sera 554A-B). C onsciousness of a sin
"leaves behind it in the soul regret [pe'capeA.eiav, metameleian] w hich ever contin­
ues to w o u n d an d prick it. For the other pangs reason does aw ay w ith, b u t regret
[pexavovav, m etanoian] is caused by reason itself, since the soul, together w ith its
feeling of sham e, is stu n g and chastised by itself" (Plutarch, Tranq. an. 476E-477B;
cf. Gen. Socr. 592A-B).
174 P aul in th e G re co -R o m a n W orld

This u n d ersta n d in g of regret in juridical m etap h o rs occurred frequently in


discussions of conscience an d repentance .8 W riters used courtroom im agery for
th e self-exam ination of conscience (Seneca, Ira 3.36.3; Juvenal, Sat. 13.2-3). The
n o tio n of a self-im posed sentence of d eath figures prom inently: "genuine repen­
tance is utterly to root ou t of the soul the sins for w hich a m an has condem ned
him self to d eath " (C lem ent of A lexandria, Quis div. 39; cf. Strom. 4.22.143).

H a rd s h ip s a n d H a rd s h ip Lists

The w o rk of John T. Fitzgerald on h ard sh ip s a n d h ard sh ip lists in ancient m oral


philo so p h y has pro ven to be a rich resource for stu d en ts of the P auline epistles .9
H e sum m arizes w h a t w riters h ad in m ind w h e n recounting hardships:

The intim ate connection betw een v irtu e a n d adversity has been th o r­
oughly do cu m ented in the preceding pages. Since peristaseis [difficulties]
constitute a test of h u m a n character, they have both a revelatory an d a
dem o n strativ e function. The m an w ith little or no integrity collapses
u n d e r the w eight of his burdens. His peristaseis reveal and prove his defi­
ciencies as a person. The proficiens [one w ho m akes progress], by contrast,
show s greater strength of character in dealing w ith his hardships, so th at
his peristaseis reveal his progress, w h a t he is becoming. Since they help to
form his character, they play a crucial role in his paideia [education]. For
the sapiens [wise m an], how ever, peristaseis no longer h av e this educative
character. They provide the proof that he is educated. C onsequently, they
exhibit w h o he is, w h a t he has become?0

F itzgerald h as accounted for tw o functions of the philosophic discourse about


h ard ships. First, the philosophers tau g h t th at reason is su p erio r to all the vicissi­
tu d es of life, a n d because the self is identified w ith reason, noth in g external can
cause h a rm .11 H ard sh ip s provide an o p p o rtu n ity for this lesson to be illustrated in
an actual life .12 Second, by the tim e of Paul, m ost p hilosophers h ad ab an d o n ed the
absolute distinction betw een the w ise m an a n d the fool an d h ad settled o n a doc­
trine of progress in m oral v irtu e .13 The notion th at h ard sh ip s train the proficiens
(one w h o m akes progress) in virtue and th at suffering produces character in the
one striving for w isdom h ad w idespread ap p e al .11
We h av e seen th at h ard sh ip s dem onstrate the sage's virtue or train the person
asp irin g to the serenity of the sage. There w as yet a third function of representing
the sage's endurance: to d em onstrate his philan th ro p y (Epictetus, Diatr. 2.12.17-
25; Lucian, Peregr. 18). Rem iniscent of A ntisthenes' depiction of O d ysseus's d a n ­
gers (A ntisthenes, frg. 15.1-3, 9) , 15 Dio C hrysostom distinguishes him self from
philo so p h ers w ho refused to associate w ith the crow d an d face danger: "For som e
am ong th at com pany do not ap p ear in public at all an d prefer no t to m ake the
P a u l, H a r d s h ip s , a n d S u f f e r in g 175

venture, possibly because they d esp air of being able to im prove the m asses" (Dio
C hrysostom , Alex. 8 ; cf. Alex. 24; 1 Tars. 15).16 The genuine philosopher "stan d s
ready, if need be, to subm it to ridicule an d to the disorder a n d the u p ro a r of the
m ob" (Dio C hrysostom , Alex. 32.11). H e should be com pared w ith Diogenes,
w h o se free speech w as often no t en d u red (Dio C hrysostom , Isthm. 9.7-9 ).17

G r i e f a n d M o r a l R e fo rm a tio n

H arsh Cynic p h ilosophers regarded m oral failure as justification for causing grief
(A.wtr|, lype) (Ps.-Socrates, Ep. 24; Lucian, Pise. 20 ) . 18 From a text representing harsh
Cynicism , w e learn th at the lau g h ter of D em ocritus aim ed to condem n h u m an ity
for its foolishness .19 N ot regarding laughter a strong en o u g h m easure against
h u m a n vice, how ever, D em ocritus w ished "to discover som ething even m ore
p ain fu l [Xwrripov, lyperon] to use against them " (Ps.-H ippocrates, Ep. 17.45 [Her-
cher, Epistolographi Graeci 304, m y translation]). C ynic m oral reproof w as often
p ain fu l because it w as in o p p o rtu n e (Ps.-H ippocrates, Ep. 17.19-20,34). H ippocra­
tes protests th at D em ocritus's lau g h ter at others' m isfortunes does no t consider
th e circum stances of those he m ocks (Ps.-H ippocrates, Ep. 17.20-21). Likewise,
Plutarch denounces those w ho cause suffering w h en the circum stances of the
hearer d em an d en couragem ent a n d consolation (Plutarch, Adul. amic. 69A).
In response to these criticism s, som e Cynics sought to place their frank speak­
in g in a better light by stressing p hilanthropic aim s (Plutarch, Virt. mor. 452D; Sto-
baeus, Flor. 3.13.42).20 They claim ed that alth o u g h w ords of tru th are som etim es
painful, in the en d they are beneficial, because they are no t m otivated by hatred
b u t by a desire to heal others (Seneca, Vit. beat. 26.5). It is the d u ty of the philoso­
p h er to benefit others, even if this requires a painful dose of truth-telling (Epicte­
tus, Diatr. 3.1.10-11; cf. Dio C hrysostom , Alex. 5, 7,11; Lucian, Hermot. 51).
In his in troduction to E pictetus's Discourses, A rrian testifies to the concept of
ap p ro p riate suffering in the reception of m oral exhortation:

Fie w as clearly aim ing at nothing else b u t to incite the m inds of the h ear­
ers to the best things. If, now, these w ords of his should produce that
sam e effect, they w o u ld have, I think, just th at success w hich the w ords
of philosophers ou g h t to have; bu t if not, let those w h o read them be as­
sured of this, th at w hen E pictetus him self spoke them , the hearer could
n o t help b u t feel [naoxetv, paschcin] exactly w h a t Epictetus w an ted him to
feel [rtocSeTv, pathein]. (Arriani epistula ad Lucium Gellium 5-7)

Epictetus him self com pared the lecture hall of the p h ilosopher to a hospital,
from w hich stu d en ts should no t w alk o u t in pleasure "b u t in pain" (Epictetus,
Diatr. 3.23.30; cf. 3.1.10-11; 3.23.37).21
176 P a u l in th e G re co -R o m a n W orld

The role of p a in in m oral im provem ent w as controversial. For the Epicureans,


em otional p ain (A/6 nr|, lype) w as som ething to be avoided, because tranquillity,
th e goal of E picurean m u tu al exhortation, w as the opposite of grief .22 In their
view, p ain w as a sign of m isapplied or m isu n d ersto o d frank speech (Philodem us,
Lib. 12,13, 31, 61-62, XVA, XVIB, XXIIB). This Epicurean ju d g m en t is not far re­
m o v ed from the p osition of the earlier Stoics, w ho argued against the usefulness
of p ain in m oral transform ation. They considered regret over one's errors a char­
acteristic of the b ad person (SVF 3.100.33; 3.149.18-24; 3.150.24-27). The later Sto­
ics, on the o th er h an d , em phasized progress in the m oral life an d m itigated the
absolute distinction betw een the w ise m an a n d the fool .23 In this context, grief
over o n e's errors w as a good thing— the beginning of the m oral life an d a sign of
progress (Cicero, Amic. 90; Lucian, Nigr. 4, 35; P lutarch, Virt. prof. 82C).
P lutarch illustrates the function of grief in m oral transform ation w hen he d e­
scribes the w ay stu d en ts should listen to the frank speech of ph ilo so p h ers .21 Al­
th o u g h cow ardly grief is to be avoided, the stu d en t has to feel som e p ain (Plu­
tarch, Rec. rat. and. 46C). The stu d e n t m u st see th at the teac h er's speech aim s to
reform character. A dm onitions should be allow ed to penetrate like a biting d ru g
a n d cause hum iliation, sw eating, an d dizziness, an d a b u rn in g w ith sham e in the
soul (Plutarch, Rec. rat. and. 46D). Yet P lutarch does not w a n t the stu d e n t to expe­
rience excessive grief:

For this reason h e w h o is taken to task m u st feel an d suffer som e sm art,


yet he sh o u ld n o t be crushed or d ispirited, b ut, as th o u g h a t a solem n rite
of novitiate w h ich consecrates him to philosophy, he should subm it to the
initial p urifications a n d com m otions, in the expectation th at som ething
delectable an d sp len d id w ill follow u p o n his p resen t distress a n d p e rtu r­
bation. (Plutarch, Rec. rat. and. 47A)

G r i e f a n d E p is to la ry T h e o ry

In the epistolary h and b o o k of Ps.-Libanius (fo urth-sixth centuries c.E.) w e dis­


cover the follow ing definition of the grieving style: "The grieving style is th at in
w h ich w e p resen t ourselves as being g riev ed ."25 M ore instructive is his sam ple
letter:

The letter of grief [A'onri'UKfi, Lypetike]. You caused m e extrem ely m uch
grief [AeA,'U7tr|Kaq, lelypekas] w hen you d id this thing. For th at reason I am
very m uch vexed w ith you, and bear a grief [Twtouiaca A,U7ir|v, lypoumai
lypen] th at is difficult to assuage. For the grief [Awioa, lypai] m en cause
their friends is exceedingly difficult to heal, an d holds in greater insults
th an those they receive from their enem ies. (Ps.-Libanius, Charact. Ep. 90,
in M alherbe, Ancient Epistolary Theorists, 80-81)
P a u l, H a r d s h ip s , a n d S u ff e r in g 177

The grieving style has overtones of rebuke (G regory of N azianzus, Ep. 40.1-4;
Basil, Ep. 44.1) .26 F riendship language calls attention to the unexpected pain the
w riter has suffered at the h an d s of his friend and thereby increases the force of the
rebuke.
Two letters attrib u ted to D em osthenes, both of doubtful authenticity, exhibit
the grieving style. In Epistle 2, D em osthenes com plains to the council an d assem ­
bly of the un fair treatm ent he has received. The letter is full of in dignation an d re­
proach (D em osthenes, Ep. 2.1, 3, 8 , 12). D em osthenes portrays him self as grief-
stricken over the w rongs he has received from his readers (D em osthenes, Ep.
2.13, 21-22). N ear the conclusion of the letter, he expresses his suffering one last
time:

Let not one of you think, m en of A thens, th at through lack of m anhood


or from any other base m otive I give w ay to m y grief from the beginning
to the end of this letter. N ot so, b u t every m an is u n g ru d g in g ly indulgent
to the feeling of the m om ent, an d those that now beset m e— if only this
h ad never com e to pass!—are sorrow s an d tears [A-unca Kai S&Kpua, lypai
kai dakrya], longing b oth for m y country an d for you, and p o n d erin g over
the w rongs I have suffered, all of w hich cause m e to grieve. (Dem os­
thenes, Ep. 2.25; cf. Ep. 3.44)

Notice especially D em osthenes' reference to his tears a n d the rebuke they com ­
m u nicate .27
The conciliatory letter w as an o th er epistolary type th at m ade suffering th e­
matic. A ccording to Ps.-Libanius, the conciliatory style w as ap p ro p riate w h en the
w riter h ad grieved the letter's recipient: "The conciliatory style is th at in w hich
w e conciliate som eone w ho has been caused grief by us for som e reason. Some
also call this th e apologetic style" (Ps.-Libanius, Charnct. Ep. 19, in M alherbe, An­
cient Epistolary Theorists, 68-69). As the exam ple below w ill illustrate, the w riter
does n o t den y th at he h ad caused the recipient pain. In fact, he acknow ledges the
p ain his w o rd s h a d inflicted. H e does, how ever, assert th at causing p ain h ad no t
been his intention. F urtherm ore, even if pain d id arise, its real significance, so it
is asserted, is the healing that it bestow ed in the end:

The conciliatory letter. In ad d itio n to m aking the statem ents that I did, I
w e n t on (to p u t them ) into action, for I m ost certainly d id no t think that
they w o u ld ever cause you sorrow [\mr|0fjGeG0ai, lypethesesthai]. But if
y ou w ere u p set by w h a t w as said o r done, be assured, m ost excellent sir,
th at I shall m ost certainly no longer m ention w h a t w as said. For it is m y
aim alw ays to heal m y friends ra th e r than to cause them sorrow [A.vrceTv,
lypeiti]. (Ps.-Libanius, Charnct. Ep. 6 6 , in M alherbe, Ancient Epistolary The­
orists, 76-77)
178 P a u l in th e G re co -R o m a n W orld

T h e conciliatory letter reflects th e philosophic teaching concerning the reform ing


p o w e r of grief b ro u g h t o n by bo ld w o rd s u ttere d in friendship (Cicero, Quint,
fratr. 1.2.12-13; G regory of N azianzus, Epp. 17.1-3; 59.1-4).

Shared S u ffe rin g and Friendship

T he n o tio n of friends sh arin g suffering w as no t the invention of philosophers.


"S u p p o se the m isfortunes of friends to be y o u r ow n," M enander w rote, echoing
w h a t w e can assu m e to be a w id esp read o p in io n .28 Yet the philosophers explored
sh ared suffering in friendship an d , significantly, set lim its u p o n it.
A ristotle recognizes as a friend "o n e w h o shares his frien d 's joys a n d sor­
row s" (Aristotle, Eth. nic. 9.4.1). F urtherm ore, he points o u t th at suffering is in­
d eed "lig h ten ed b y the sy m p ath y of friends" (A ristotle, Eth. nic. 9.10.2; cf. Cicero,
Amic. 22). A ristotle hesitates to answ er definitively w h e th e r the p ain is actually
shared, or w h eth er it is sim ply the pleasure of com rades' com pany a n d "con­
sciousness of their sy m p ath y ” th at m itigates pain. H e does m aintain, how ever,
th a t it is "w o m an ish" for one p erso n to allow another to share in p a in (Aristotle,
Eth. nic. 9.11.4).
Later w riters enforce a sim ilar lim itation. O n the one han d , it is necessary to
risk d an g er on account of friendship (Cicero, Amic. 23; Plutarch, Amic. mult. 96A;
Lucian, Tax. 7 ,9 ). Yet sh ared suffering m u st n o t go so d eep as to touch the soul of
the friend w h o gives com fort (Epictetus, Ench. 16.1). It is also problem atic
w h e th e r a frien d sh o u ld share in a n o th e r's d isrep u te (Cicero, Amic. 61), alth o u g h
som e w riters believe this to b e the case w ith true friends (Plutarch, Amic. mult.
96B; Lucian, Tox. 46; M axim us of Tyre, Or. 14.5). In spite of these lim its im posed
by som e p h ilosophers, w e find the com plete sharing of adversity, even pain, sor­
row, a n d grief, to b e a com m onplace pertain in g to frien d sh ip (Cicero, Amic. 4 6 -
48). In fact, according to Lucian this sh arin g is the first thing th at m u st be said
ab o u t frien d sh ip (Lucian, Tox. 6 ). The g ro u n d for su ch a n o tio n is th at friendship
is a k in d of sharing, th at friends have all things in com m on (Seneca, Epp. 6.2;
48.2-4; T hem istius, Or. 22.269, 270, 274).
T he u ltim ate d em o n stratio n of friendship w as w illingly to suffer d ea th for a n ­
o th er (Diogenes L aertius 10.120; P lutarch, Amic. mult. 96C-D; Lucian, Tox. 20,36-
37; M axim us of Tyre, Or. 14.3).29 Cicero reports th at theatergoers w ere m oved to
stan d in g ov atio n at scenes of such devotion (Cicero, Amic. 24), a n d w e kn o w from
literary sources th at the them e of d ea th for frien d sh ip 's sake w as gaining great
p o p u larity in the first century b.c .e .30 Again, how ever, there w as a lim it. The one
for w h o m suffering a n d d eath are e n d u red m u st be good. This qualification is
based on the req uirem ent th at a friendship be established only w ith the good p e r­
son. F rien d sh ip is possible only after testing to see if the potential friend p o s­
sesses v irtu e (Cicero, Amic. 79, 85).
P a u l, H a r d s h ip s , a n d S u f f e r in g 179

P a rt II. H ardships and Suffering in Paul's L etters


(2 C orinthians 1-7; Rom ans 5:1-1 I; and 8:18-39)

G r i e f a n d th e O c c a s io n o f 2 C o rin th ia n s 1 - 7

Second C orinthians 1 -7 is full of references to suffering a n d hardships. P au l's ac­


kn o w led g m en t of the suffering of the C orinthian com m unity opens (1:3-7) and
closes (7:8-11) this portion of the letter. References to P aul's o w n suffering are fit­
ted betw een the p o rtrayals of the church's grief in tw o w ays. First, h e n arrates his
travel from Asia M inor into M acedonia (1:8—11; 2:12-16; 7:5-6). It is a journey of
w oe. Second, Paul em ploys the philosophic convention of h ard sh ip lists (4:7-12;
4:16-5:5; an d 6:3-10). O ur current task is tw ofold: to reconstruct the occasion of
2 C or 1-7 and to u n d ersta n d its rhetorical strategy, using w h a t w e kn o w ab o u t the
ancient w ays of speaking about suffering an d hardships. We treat the occasion
first.
In 2 C or 2:4, Paul refers to a letter w hich has been n am ed ap propriately "the
letter of tears": "For o u t of m uch affliction [0A.U|/eoo<;, thlipseds] an d contraction of
h ea rt [ouvoxn? KapSiaq, synoches kardias] 1 w rote to you th ro u g h m any tears" (8 ta
noXk(£)V S a K p u c o v , din pollen dakrydn, m y translation). This letter w as a critical event
betw een the w ritin g of 1 a n d 2 C orinthians .31 Paul h ad m ad e an em ergency visit
to C orinth to deal w ith the troubles in the church .32 D uring this interm ediate visit,
an in d iv id u al injured o r insulted P aul (2 C or 1:15, 23; 2:1—11; 7:12; 12:21-13:2).33
The identity of this in dividual is u nknow n, b u t in the secondary literature he is
frequently called 6 dSiKfjoac; (ho adikesas, "th e one w ho caused injury") after 2 Cor
7:12. A fter Paul left C orinth, he w rote a letter that rebuked the church for not tak­
in g disciplinary action against "th e one w ho caused injury ."34
O u r k n o w ledge of the grieving style in ancient epistolography (see above) al­
low s u s to see the rebuking function of this letter an d to assess its im pact on the
C o rinthian com m unity. P aul p o rtray ed him self as w eeping an d m ade his grief the
stated m otivation for w riting. As w e have seen, shrinking soul is a com m onplace
in Stoic psychology, in w hich expressions sim ilar to P au l's "affliction an d contrac­
tion of the heart" signify grief. We also know from 2 C or 7 : 8 th at this letter caused
p ain to the congregation at C orinth.
T here is m ore evidence th at the pain caused by this letter w as a factor in the
occasion of 2 C or 1-7. M any scholars agree that 6:11-13 states P au l's reconciling
p u rp o se in w ritin g 2 C or 1-7, although a full appreciation of his use of the psy­
chology of suffering h as n o t accom panied this correct insight .35 In 6:11, P aul refers
to his fran k speech w ith the phrase "o u r m o u th stan d s o p en tow ard y o u ."36 H e
th e n places his bold speech in the context of friendship. P au l's friendship for the
C orinthians is indicated by the joy that accom panies his speech. Joy, und ersto o d
b y th e ph ilosophers as the opposite of grief, w as often depicted as a w idening of
180 P au l in th e G re co -R o m a n W orld

the h eart (SVF 3.105.17-18; Seneca, Ep. 59.2). In 6:12, Paul reiterates his joy for the
C orinthians by d en y in g th at they are the cause of any grief to him . Reflecting the
philosophic definition of grief as soul shrinkage, he says that the church is no t re­
stricted (aTevo%copeTa0 e, stenochdreisthe) in his heart, even as he, as a friend, uses
frank speech in m oral adm onition. Yet in 6:12b, Paul points out the narrow ness in
the chu rch 's affections tow ard him , an d he exhorts his hearers to retu rn his
frien d sh ip by w id en in g their hearts so th at he m ight exist there. S hrinking soul
covered a range of suffering, including annoyance. Indeed, the term s Paul em ­
ploys to depict the church's attitu d e tow ard him in 6:11-13 are rem iniscent of the
definition of annoyance (Diogenes Laertius 7.111; SVF 3.100.29; Plutarch, Sera
564B-C; Seneca, Dial. 2.10.2-3; Ira 2.6.1; M arcus A urelius 9.32).
So far, w e h ave accounted for tw o w ays in w hich the issue of suffering con­
trib u ted to the occasion of 2 Cor 1-7. P aul suffered grief over the com m unity's in­
difference to th e injury th at he h ad received, an d the congregation w as grieved at
being reb u k ed by Paul th ro u g h the letter of tears. A nother grief m u st be consid­
ered as w ell. In 2 Cor 2:5-11, P aul skillfully m inim izes the w ro n g that "th e one
w h o caused injury" h ad done to him an d pleads w ith the congregation to affirm
love for the m an. A pparently, the "letter of tears" h ad w orked too well. The C o­
rin th ian congregation h ad disciplined the offender too harshly, an d now, alien­
ated from the com m unity, he suffered from excessive grief, possibly in d an g er of
suicide. P au l's plea in 2:5-11 for the com m unity to exhort, love, a n d forgive him
parallels the philosophical concern for ap p ro p riate grief in the context of m oral
reform ation.
To appreciate the grief "th e one w ho caused injury" experienced, attention
m u st be g iven to the term e rtra g ia (epitimia) in 2:6. H ere en v u g ia is synonym ous
w ith en m p riau ; (epitimesis, "rebuke " ).37 R ebuke w as defined as a type of m oral ex­
h o rtatio n (Isocrates, Demon. 1.38; Dio C hrysostom , Alex. 33; Lucian, Demon. 55;
Jupp. trag. 23; Fug. 12; Pseuclol. 3; Stobaeus, Flor. 3.13.42).38 Philo d raw s u p a list of
th e salu tary form s of m oral discourse:

If I sp eak in the general assem bly I w ill leave all talk of flattery to others
a n d resort only to such as is salu tary a n d beneficial, reproving [enragw v,
epitimon], w arning, correcting in w o rd s stu d ied to shew a sober frankness
w ith o u t foolish a n d frantic arrogance. (Philo, Ios. 73; cf. Cicero, Off.
1.38.137; Seneca, Ep. 94.39; C lem ent of A lexandria, Paed. 1.9.75.1;
1.9.77.1 ) 39

Striking is the inclusion of encouragem ent an d com fort in the contexts in


w hich rebuke is treated as a type of m oral exhortation (Plutarch, Superst. 168C;
Lucian, Demon. 7; C lem ent of A lexandria, Paed. 1.9.75.1; 1.9.87.2; Seneca, Ira 1.15.1;
Ep. 99.32; Ps.-D em etrius, Form. Ep. 6 ; Julian, Or. 6.201 C). Because the final goal of
P a u l, H a r d s h ip s , a n d S u ff e r in g 181

rebuke w as m oral im provem ent, once sham e an d grief h ad taken h old an d repen­
tance h ad been b ro u g h t about, w ords of encouragem ent a n d com fort w ere to be
ad d ed lest excessive suffering lead to alienation an d even d eath (Plutarch, [Lib.
ed.] 13D -E ).10This is P au l's stated fear, a n d exhortation an d affirm ation of friend­
ship is the rem edy he pleads for the church to em ploy for the sake of the now
grief-stricken "one w ho caused injury."
O ne last grief rem ains to be described. It is P aul's o w n grief, suffered as he
m ade his w ay from Asia M inor to M acedonia in o rd er to receive from Titus new s
of the congregation's reaction to the severe rebuke in the letter of tears: "W e do
not w a n t you to be u naw are, brothers a n d sisters, of the affliction [0 A.f\|/ecog,
thlipseos] w e experienced in Asia; for w e w ere so utterly, unbearably crushed th at
w e d esp aired of life itself" (2 C or 1:8). Paul exaggerates his suffering for rhetori­
cal purposes, w hich w e will explore m ore fully below .41 It is en o u g h here to p in ­
point th e exact n atu re of the affliction.
In 1:9, Paul indicates to his hearers th at he suffered from regret. H e h ad
passed the "sentence of death" ( t o oaiOKpipa t o o Gavaxou, to apokrima tou thmm-
tou) u p o n him self. We have learned th at the m etap h o r of self-condem nation w as
a com m on w ay of speaking ab o u t regret, a variety of grief. Second C orinthians 7:8
confirm s th at the em otion he describes in 1:9 is regret: "For even if I grieved
[eXtmriaa, elypesa] you w ith m y letter, I do not regret [gexa|ie/\,o|iai, metamelonmi]
it, th o u g h I did regret [pexa|xeX6|J.r|V, metamelomen] it, for I see th at I grieved [eA.x>-
rtrioev, ehjpesen] you w ith that letter, though only briefly." The philosophical u n ­
d erstan d in g of regret as self-condem nation allow s us to connect chapters 1 a n d 7.
Some of P au l's references to his pain in the intervening passages (2:13; 4:8-11;
7:4-7), w hich otherw ise m ight be u n d ersto o d as allusions to the general suffer­
ings of an apostle, can be seen as the regret he claim s to have suffered after w rit­
ing the letter of tears.

S u ffe rin g in th e R h e to ric a l S tra te g y o f 2 C o rin th ia n s 1 - 7

H aving po in ted o u t the w ay grief sets the stage for the letter, w e tu rn now to P aul's
rhetorical strategy w ithin the letter itself. Paul adopts an d ad ap ts philosophic and
epistolographic conventions to reconcile the C orinthian com m unity, w ho h ad been
stu n g by rebuke in the letter of tears. Paul em ploys four aspects of the ancient dis­
course about suffering: the notion that friends share both joy and sorrow ; the epis­
tolographic conventions of the conciliatory letter; the idea of appropriate grief in
the reception of m oral exhortation; and the endurance of hardships.
Second C orinthians 1:3-7 develops the notion that friends share both joy and
suffering. The key term that connects P aul's rhetoric w ith the philosophic d is­
course ab o u t suffering is xoc 7ia 0 i)|iaxct (ta pathemata):
182 P a u l in th e G re co -R o m a n W orld

1:5: the sufferings (to: 7xa0 f||_iaTce, ta pathemata) of C hrist abound in us


1 :6 : the same sufferings (naOrpaTcov, pathematon) w hich w e ourselves
h av e (ndoxogev, paschomen)
1:7: partners in the sufferings (koivcovoi eoxe toov mBrpaTcov, koinonoi este
ton pathematori, my translation)

S hared suffering is the necessary condition for tru e friendship. This goes to
the h ea rt of trad itional teaching on friendship. C hrist, Paul, an d the church are
one because they share em otions. N ot only did this identity of em otions provide
the g ro u n d for friendship, it also defined its task (Plutarch, Adul. antic. 49F; Antic,
mult. 95F-96D; Dio C hrysostom , 3 Regn. 3.100-103; Gnomologium Vaticanum 273;
Cicero, Amic. 48, 64; Seneca, Ep. 6.3). Friends w ere to share sorrow, or in the P aul­
ine idiom in 2 Cor 1:3-7, to share in affliction (0 Xu|ac;, thlipsis). It is no surprise,
then, th at in 1:7 Paul uses the key term for this sharing of em otion in friendship:
Koivcovfa (koinonia) (Aristotle, Eth. nic. 8.9.1; 8.12.1; 9.12.1; Eth. eud. 7.9.1; Plutarch,
Amic. mult. 96D; Lucian, Tox. 6-7; Julian, Or. 8.240A-B; 241C).42
Second C orinthians 1:3 -7 underscores the friendship that P aul claim s exists
betw een the com m unity an d him self. S haring suffering is proof th at they are
friends. H ere P aul does not call attention to the fact th at he caused th e com m unity
its grief. The vocabulary of suffering is vag u e enough to allow P aul to categorize
the sting of rebuke felt by the church a n d his o w n regret to be categorized u n d er
the sam e term s. Later in the letter (beginning in 2:1-4 a n d culm inating in 7:9-10)
Paul deals directly w ith the pain he caused, characterizing it as ap p ro p riate grief.
Before exploring th at strategy in detail, how ever, w e need to exam ine the
w ays 2 C or 1 -7 exhibits characteristics of the conciliatory letter. First, stating one's
regret for acting offensively or having w ritten in severe tones w as an elem ent in
the letter of reconciliation (Cicero, Quint, fratr. 1.2.12-13; C hariton, Chaer. 4.4; Phi-
lo stratus, Vit. soph. 562-563; Fronto, Ad M. Ceas. 5.59).n Paul m akes such state­
m en ts in 1:8-9 an d 7:8. Second, P aul follow s the conventions of the conciliatory
letter by saying th at the intention of his rebuke w as no t to cause p a in b u t to
d em o n strate his friendship (2:4 an d 7:3; see above). Finally, Paul claim s th at the
in ten t an d the effect of his severe w o rd s w ere to prom ote healing. In 7:8-12, Paul
review s for his readers the salutary effects of the rebuke conveyed in the grieving
letter. Behind these verses stands the topos th at a friend does no t intend his frank
speech to cause pain b u t to bring about repentance a n d m oral healing. The pro­
gression in 7:9-10 from grief to repentance and then to salvation places P aul's
characterization of his treatm ent of the church squarely in the psychagogic tra d i­
tion (see above).
T he distinction betw een godly grief an d w orldly grief in 7 :9 b -lla fu rth er
d em o n strates P au l's use of the G reco-R om an tradition of soul-care in o rd er to ju s­
tify the severity of the grieving letter. G odly grief a n d the grief of the w orld w ere
Paul, Hardships, and Suffering 183

distin g u ish ed in their effects: repentance leading to salvation on the one hand,
a n d d eath on th e other.44 Plutarch contrasts the grief th at G od inflicts w ith the
p ain caused by h u m ans. G od causes p ain in o rd er to bring ab o u t repentance; h u ­
m ans sim ply p u n ish w ith o u t a view to m oral im provem ent (Plutarch, Sera
551C-E).45 M oreover, unlike hum ans w ho get angry, cause pain, an d then regret
their severity (Plutarch, Cohib. ira 464C-D; Sera 550E-F; 551C; Seneca, Ira 2.6.2),
G od know s no rem orse an d causes no d am age (Philo, Cotif. 171). In 7:9, Paul
claim s th at godly grief caused by the grieving letter did the church no dam age.
We h ave m oved from the epistolographic conventions of 2 C or 1-7 to the
philosophical topos of ap p ro p riate em otional pain in the context of m oral exhor­
tation. This is natu ral, because the rhetoric of conciliation d raw s from the philo­
sophic trad itio n of soul-care. Paul had already invoked the notion of ap p ro p riate
grief in 2:5-11 an d em phasized th at the grief inflicted by m oral adm onition
sh ould be com bined w ith exhortation a n d affirm ations of friendship. H e reiter­
ates this them e in 7:2-4, only now to am eliorate the suffering he h ad caused the
church. In 7:3a, he denies th at his speech aim s to condem n his readers (Jtpo<;
KaxdKpiciv on Xeyoo, pros katakrisin ou lego).46 The uses of frank speech for m oral
edification, on the one han d , an d condem nation, on the other, w ere w ell-know n
(Stobaeus, Flor. 3.13.63; Isocrates, Paneg. 4.130; 8.72; P hilodem us, Lib. 37-38, IB;
Lucian, Pseudol. 3; Dear. cone. 2; Icar. 30; Ps.-D iogenes, Ep. 29.2-3; M arcus A urelius
11.6.2.).47 As w e have seen, h arsh Cynics w ere w ell-know n for their u n b rid led use
of free speech to condem n the ills of hum ankind. D em ocritus's lau g h ter con­
dem n ed h u m an ity for its inconsistency (Ps.-PIippocrates, Ep. 17.40). The n otion of
the p h ilo so p h er's rebuke of sin as the guilty verdict in a legal proceeding is found
in Cynic self-description (Ps.-Heraclitus, Epp. 7.2; 9.8; Gnomologium Vaticanum
116,487). Similarly, the harsh C ynic u n d erstood bold speech as p u n ish m en t of
h u m an erro r (Ps.-Diogenes, Ep. 29.1, 4; Ps.-Socrates, Ep. 12; Ps.-H eraclitus, Epp.
7A; 9.3; Plutarch, [Vit. X orat.] 842D; Epictetus, Diatr. 3.22.94, 97-98; Dio C hrysos­
tom , Is thru. 8).
Paul distances him self from these harsh practitioners of frank speech by o p ­
posing the excessive grief their w o rd s inflict. This brings us to the last of his
rhetorical strategies in 2 C or 1-7. Paul uses hard sh ip lists to shape his im age as a
bold-speaking friend w hose chief concerns are reconciliation and the salvation of
his hearers.
In o rd er to u n d ersta n d how the h ard sh ip s in 4:7-15 shape P au l's im age, I first
consider his reliance on G od an d abasem ent for the sake of the church. Second
C orinthians 4 :5 -6 anticipates the hard sh ip s in 4:7-15 by raising the issue of the
source of P aul's authority. H e claim s n o t to preach him self b u t Jesus C hrist as
Lord, a n d him self as the church's slave. The h ard sh ip s in 4:7-15 am plify these
tw o claim s. They depict the free an d bold-speaking Paul, w ho nevertheless relies
184 P a u l in th e G re co -R o m a n W orld

entirely on G od, not his o w n virtue, an d w ho subordinates him self to the C orin­
th ian congregation.
A n am b ig u ity in 4:7 prepares the reader to m ove from the them e of G od as
source of p o w e r (4:8-9) to P au l's abasem ent for the sake of the church (4:10-15).
O n th e one h an d , the term Griaccupo^ (thesauros, "treasure") suggests P au l's illu­
m in ed a n d tran sform ed soul.48 T he ph rase " in earthen vessels" evokes the
fragility of his o u ter self in anticipation of 4:16-5:5, a n d the "tran scen d en t pow er"
p o in ts to G o d 's p o w er to preserve the fragile Paul in the m idst of hardships.49 O n
th e o th er h an d , "treasure" could also refer to P au l's m inistry. T hen earth en po t­
tery den o tes the abasem ent he accepts for the sake of the church,50 and "tran scen ­
d e n t po w er" evokes the life-giving p o w er of P au l's m inistry.51 The am biguity of
4:7 reflects the correlation of the salvation Paul has received from G od a n d G o d 's
salv atio n of h u m an ity th ro u g h P au l's m inistry (cf. 1:4; 4:1; 5:18-19).
The catalog of h ard sh ip s in 4:8-9 illustrates the d angers of P au l's m inistry, his
en d u ran ce, and, m ost of all, his source of pow er—G od.52 T hat P au l's pow er d e­
rives n o t from him self b u t from G od distinguishes him from the w ise m an w hose
au th o rity d ep en d s u p o n his ability to m ake all things dep en d u p o n him self. By
m ak in g him self d ep e n d en t u p o n G od in this way, P aul prepares for his self-pres­
entatio n as a reconciler.
The h ard sh ip s in 4:10-15, how ever, p o in t no longer to P au l's G od-given
p o w er to en d u re difficulties b u t to en d u ran ce of ignom iny a n d d eath for the sake
of the church. P aul now becom es a suffering bold-speaker w hose concern is the
salvation of the church. The p u rp o se clauses in 4:10-11 suggest the v o lu n tary n a­
tu re of P au l's suffering. M oreover, if Jiapa8i86p.e0a (paradidometha, "w e h an d o u r­
selves over") is in the m iddle voice, the v o lu n tary quality of P aul's suffering finds
fu rth er em phasis.53 The philanthropic aspects of P au l's h ard sh ip s com e o ut clearly
in 4:12: "So then, death is at w ork in us, b u t life is at w o rk in you." The them e of
P au l's v o lu n tary enslavem ent to the C orinthian church also ap p ears in 4:15, in
w h ich h e asserts that all things he does are for its sake.
In 4:16-5:5, P aul's h ard sh ip s no longer em phasize the enslavem ent them e b u t
und ersco re his spiritual transform ation. T he renew al of P au l's inner self is treated
in 4:16-17, w hile the renew al of his o u ter self is expressed in 5 :l-5 .51 In both cases,
P aul calls u p o n , yet also m odifies, the philosophic them e of h ard sh ip s as the
sag e's train in g in virtue. The them e of training is p resen t in 4:17 w hen P aul claim s
th at affliction produces glory. Yet hard sh ip s p rep are a future w eight of glory, not
a sage train ed a n d perfected in reason. P aul m odifies the philosophic topos by
stressing th e eschatological dim ension of the transform ation th at G od is w orking
in him . H e does n o t yet possess the transform ed self b u t points to G od's daily re­
n ew al of his in n er self an d G od's p reparation of an eternal dw elling (cf. Phil 3:12-
14). By stressing progress instead of perfection, P aul distinguishes him self from
P a u l, H a r d s h ip s , a n d S u ff e r in g 185

the notion in the philosophic tradition th at bold speech derived from the m oral
su p erio rity of the sage.
We turn to the last h ard sh ip list in 2 Cor 1-7. In 6:3-10, P aul uses a list of h a rd ­
ships to com m end him self to the C orinthians.55 A gain, w e see that Paul is n o t sat­
isfied sim ply to reproduce a philosophic topos. In ad d itio n to the h ard sh ip s that
Paul en um erates in 6:4-5, 7b-10, w hich po rtray him as courageous an d steadfast,
w e find term s in 6:6-7a that seem anom alous: "by purity, know ledge, patience,
kindness, holiness of spirit, genuine love, truthful speech, an d the pow er of
G od. . .." These term s m ake sense if they are view ed in light of the G reco-R om an
psychagogical tradition.56 The phrases "tru th fu l speech" an d "genuine love" refer
to frank speech. Paul describes him self, the servant of G od, as a bold speaker.57
P au l's creativity here consists of introducing insights from philosophic soul-care
ab out the w ay m oral criticism is to be applied to avoid excessive grief.
The notion of excessive grief is present in 6:3, although m o d ern translations
an d exegesis obscure it. The nrsv reads: "We are p u ttin g no obstacle [7tpoCTK07tfiv,
proskopen] in any o ne's way, so that no fault m ay be found w ith o u r m inistry." Ex-
egetes have incorrectly regarded the term 7ipooKonq as equivalent to JipoaKoppa
(proskomma, "obstacle").58 A very different u n d ersta n d in g em erges, how ever, if
TtpoaKOTtfi is seen in contexts associated w ith bold speech. In these instances, it
designates arousal of hatred because of the grief inflicted by m oral rebuke (Poly­
bius 38.4.2-4; Sextus Em piricus, Math. 2.54; Cicero, Antic. 88-89).5<) ripooKOJif) is
th e alienation caused by bold speech (Isocrates, Ep. 9.12; D ionysius of H alicarnas­
sus, Ant. rom. 11.9.1; Ps.-Socrates, Ep. 1.7; Dio C hrysostom , Diod. 4; Lucian, Her-
mot. 51; A ristides Rhetor, Or. 3.668). If this lexical insight is b ro u g h t to bear o n 6:3,
then the reason Paul a d d s the ph rase "so th at no fault m ay be found w ith o u r
m in istry " becom es clear. A ccording to 5:18-19, P aul's m inistry aim s at reconcilia­
tion. H e w o u ld su b v ert this p u rp o se if his speech alienated those he aim ed to w in
over. If his speech only caused suffering, it w o u ld be inconsistent w ith the m in­
istry of reconciliation. In 6:3-10, Paul presents him self as one w ho com bines
w o rd s of tru th w ith kindness an d encouragem ent in o rd er no t to alienate those
w hom h e has add ressed w ith bold speech. Yet kindness and patience should no t
be m istaken for tim idity, because the h ard sh ip s he has e n d u red d em onstrate
courage.

T h e P ro b le m o f S u ffe rin g R e c o n s tru c te d : R o m a n s 5 : 1 - 1 1 a n d 8 : 1 8 - 3 9

N o passages better d em o n strate P aul's fam iliarity w ith philosophic discourse


concerning h ard sh ip s a n d suffering than Rom 5:1-11 and 8:18-39. Fam iliarity is
p erh ap s too w eak a w ord. Paul is so acquainted w ith the philosophic tradition
th at he uses its com m onplaces effortlessly. Yet Paul m anipulates theses com m on-
186 P a u l in th e G re co -R o m a n W orld

place sayings a n d ideas in o rd er to criticize p h ilo so p h y 's claim ab o u t the capac­


ity of th e w ise m an to e n d u re suffering. In o th er w ords, Paul both em ploys anti
subverts the p attern ed discourse of philosophy w ith its confidence in reason to
conquer hardships.
H e does this for a purpose. In place of virtue or reason as the solution to the
p roblem of suffering, P aul advances the notion of shared suffering. A lthough he
derives from the philosophic trad itio n the idea that friends share joy, suffering,
a n d ev en d eath, P aul radically expands the pool of friends to include G od, Christ,
th e H oly Spirit, a n d all of creation. The controlling im age in these tw o passages is
n o t th e sage, p ro tected from h ard sh ip s by his reason, b u t the friend su rro u n d e d
b y friends w h o share all things.
A t first glance, Rom 5:3-4 sim ply reproduces the notion th at h ard sh ip s train
th e sage in v irtue.60 Suffering builds character (see above). Paul w rites, " A n d no t
only that, b u t w e also boast in o u r sufferings, know ing th at suffering produces
end u ran ce, a n d en d u ran ce produces character, an d character produces h o p e . . . "
P au l recasts this com m onplace philosophical n otion in a fam iliar rhetorical figure,
clim ax.61
Yet som e unfam iliar aspects of P au l's arg u m en t w o u ld h av e frustrated the a n ­
cient re a d e r's expectations. N otice that P aul com pletes the clim ax in 5:4 b y say­
ing th at "character produces hope." From the philosophic standpoint, this is an
o d d conclusion to an account of the w ay suffering b u ild s character.62 Som e
philo so p h ers reg arded ho p e as a m oral disease, because h o p e placed hap p in ess
in externals, over w hich no one has control. P u rsu it of externals can only lead to
sham e (Seneca, Epp: 5.7; 13.13; 23.2; 24.1; 71.14; 99.5,13; 101.4).“ Thus, by in tro ­
d u cin g ho p e as the p ro d u ct of character, P aul begins his critique of the p hilo­
sophic view of suffering as the training of reason.
In its place, Paul explores the relationship betw een friendship a n d suffering.
I m u st p o in t o u t the w ays P aul w orks the friendship m otif into the arg u m en t as a
replacem ent of philosophic reason. In 5:5 w e read th at hope is secure, "because
the love of G od has been po u red into o u r h earts th ro u g h the H oly Spirit th at has
b een given to us." The p u tativ e exegetical dilem m a th at w ould force a decision
w h eth er "love of G od" is a n objective genitive (the love w e have for G od) or a
subjective genitive (G od's love for us) likely is a false problem . The central m eta­
p h o r of the sentence, love as a liquid, suggests a m u tu ality of love. The idea of
love as a liquid po u red into the heart is found in am atory literature. It depicts the
beloved as the source of the lo v er's affection.64 If Paul is u sin g this notion of m u ­
tu al love, th en the reason w h y hope is secure an d can replace reason in the face of
h ard sh ip s becom es clear: friendship w ith G od m eans a m u tu al sharing of suffer­
ing an d joy. Paul has already alluded to this sharing in 5:2 w h en he boasts on the
ho p e of sh aring the glory of God.
P a u l, H a r d s h ip s , a n d S u ff e r in g 187

In 5:6-8, Paul reiterates the them e of friendship an d suffering from a differ­


ent angle: "For w hile w e w ere still w eak, at the right tim e C hrist died for the u n ­
godly. Indeed, rarely will anyone die for a righteous person—th o u g h perh ap s for
a good p erson som eone m ight actually dare to die. But G od proves his love for us
in th at w hile w e still w ere sinners C hrist died for us." This verse echoes the p hilo­
sophic idea th at the ultim ate proof of friendship w as to u ndergo h ard sh ip s and
even to die for the friend. Paul construes Jesus' d eath for others in just this way.
N otice also that Jesus' death also dem onstrates G o d 's love (5:8). There are som e
im p o rtan t distinctions, how ever, w hich set P au l's argum ent ap a rt from the usual
discussion of this m atter. The philosophers w ere careful to p u t a lim it on friend­
ship. F riendship is possible only betw een the v irtu o u s (see above). Jesus (and by
im plication God) violates this canon of friendship. Jesus dies for the w eak, sin­
ners, an d enemies.
The final w ay Paul w orks the friendship m otif into the arg u m en t is the re­
p eated use of KaxaAA&aaeiv (katallassein) in 5:9-11. This term , translated som e­
w h a t m isleadingly as "to reconcile," does not sim ply m ean the cessation of
anim osity, alth o u g h this is the w ay com m entators invariably regard it. The term
regularly referred to the establishm ent of friendship (Aristotle, Eth. nic. 8.6.7; Dio
C hrysostom , Meow. 11,41,47-48), a n d w ith friendship com es the notion of sh ar­
ing all things. Thus, w e h av e com e again to the p o in t that began the passage:
P au l's confidence resides in his ho p e of sharing G o d 's glory. Paul does n o t take
the p h ilo so p h er's approach of view ing suffering as the occasion to display or to
train h u m a n reason. In the last analysis, h u m a n suffering is a test of divine friend­
ship. Will the sh aring b etw een suffering h u m an ity a n d G od be com plete? If there
is to be a h u m an boasting in G o d 's glory will there also be G o d 's participation in
h u m an suffering?
R om ans 8:18-39 m akes the case for divine participation in h u m an suffering.
This passage takes u p the issue of suffering, as the opening verse clearly indicates:
"I consider th at the sufferings of this present tim e are not w o rth com paring w ith
the glory ab o u t to be revealed to us." There are num erous parallels betw een
8:18-39 an d 5:1-11. The m ost obvious is the h ard sh ip lists in 8:35-39 th at rem ind
the read er of 5:3-4:
W ho w ill sep arate [ycoploei, chdrisei] us from the love of Christ? Will h a rd ­
ship, or distress, or persecution, o r fam ine, o r nakedness, o r peril, or
sw ord? As it is w ritten, "For y o u r sake w e are being killed all d ay long;
w e are accounted as sheep to be slaughtered." No, in all these things w e
are m ore th an conquerors [wtepviKCopev, hypemikomen] th ro u g h him w ho
loved us. For I am convinced that neither death, n o r life, nor angels, nor
rulers, n or things present, n o r things to com e, n o r pow ers, n o r height, nor
d ep th , n o r an y th in g else in all creation, w ill be able to separate [xcopfocu,
chorisai] u s from the love of G od in C hrist Jesus o u r Lord.
188 P a u l in th e G re co -R o m a n W orld

T he item s in the first list (8:35) are typical of the dan g ers en d u red by the w ise
m an. T he provocative aspect of bo th lists, how ever, is their rhetorical function.
N eith er list w o rk s in any of the three w ays h ard sh ip s w ere u sed in the ancient d is­
course ab o u t the w ise m an. V irtue is n either d isp lay ed n o r trained here, n o r is the
p h ilan th ro p y of P aul a n d his readers exhibited. Paul is p u ttin g these hard sh ip
lists to a n o vel use, a n d w h a t h e does no t say ab o u t suffering m ight h av e seem ed
to his hearers to h ave as m uch im portance as w h a t he d id say.
The novelty of P au l's use of these h ard sh ip lists is th at he p u ts them in the
context of friendship. Instead of calling a tten tio n to an in d iv id u a l's v irtu e or p h i­
lanthropy, the lists n am e the things th at cannot separate Paul a n d his readers from
th e love of G od. P aul m entions separation tw ice (8:35, 39) th u s p u ttin g his h ear­
ers in m in d of a problem often treated in discussions of friendship (Aristotle, Eth.
nic. 8.5.1; P lutarch, Amic. mult. 95A; Seneca, Ep. 55.8-11; 63.3). S eparation w as the
greatest grief friends m ight suffer. Yet there w as com fort. Even w h e n physically
ab sent from one another, friends w ere inseparable, because they w ere one soul in
tw o bodies. H a rd sh ip s in P au l's h ands, then, serve the rhetorical p u rp o se of re­
co nstructing the problem of suffering. Suffering is n ot the occasion for the display
o r th e train in g of v irtu e as w o u ld have been the case for Stoics an d indeed for
m uch of th e G reco-R om an w orld. For Paul, h ard sh ip s produce or exhibit noth in g
in them selves; rather, a n d simply, h ard sh ip s do n o t o bstruct the friendship am ong
G od, Paul, an d his hearers.
P aul fu rth er challenges the u n d ersta n d in g of suffering in the philosophic tra­
d ition w h en he em ploys the phrase "w e are m ore than conquerors [tmepviKcouev,
hypernikomen] th ro u g h him w ho loved us." To u n d ersta n d w hy this is a challenge,
w e need first to appreciate the claim the victory m otif m akes for the suprem acy
of reason in the face of m isfortune. The victory m otif w as a p o p u lar m etap h o r in
the philosophic p ortrayal of the w ise m an 's superiority to hardships. The w ise
m an conquers h ard sh ip s (Seneca, Dial. 1.2.2; 2.10.4; Polyb. 17.1-2; Elelv. 2.2), w hile
he him self is invincible (aviKrixog, aniketos; Ps.-D iogenes, Ep. 33; Epictetus, Diatr.
1.18.21-23; Ench. 19.2; Seneca, Ep. 85.29; Vit. beat. 4.2; Elelv. 5.5). F ortune v a n ­
quishes lesser souls (Seneca, Helv. 1.1). Both m ilitary an d athletic victory served
as a point of com parison for the sage's indom itable soul.65 The victory could be
over external d angers or over one's ow n passions.66 Seneca, w ho used the m eta­
p h o r extensively,67 ends a discourse on suffering like Paul w ith the rhetorical
flourish su p p lied by the victory motif:

A nd w h en will it be o u r privilege to despise both kinds of m isfortune?


W hen w ill it be our privilege, after all the passions have been su b d u ed
an d b ro u g h t u n d er o u r control, to u tter the w ords "I have conquered
[vici]l"7 Do you ask m e w hom 1 have conquered [vicerim]? N either the
Persians, n o r the far-off M edes, nor the w arlike race th at lies beyond the
P a u l, H a r d s h ip s , a m i S u ff e r in g 189

Dahae; not these, b u t greed, am bition, an d the fear of death th at has con­
quered the conquerors of the w orld [qui victores gentium vicit]. (Seneca, Ep.
71.37)

The m otif em phasized the im portance of placing all of one's hopes in oneself and
n o t in others (Ceb. Tab. 22-24; Seneca, Vit. beat. 8.3). It also p ointed to the capacity
of reason to protect the self from every m isfortune (Cicero, Tusc. 5.52-54; Seneca,
Epp. 9.18-19; 78.15-21; Dial. 2.5.7; 2.6.6).
Paul seem s to affirm the p h ilo so p h er's confidence in reason by introducing
the victory m otif into a discussion of hardships. N evertheless, h e dism antles the
philosophic view in tw o w ays. First, he claim s th at "w e are more than conquerors"
(em phasis added), im plying th at the m etaphor of victory over suffering m ay not
be adequate. Second, victory over suffering com es no t through an in d iv id u al's
use of reason b u t through friendship w ith God: "w e are m ore th an conquerors
th ro u g h him w ho loved us" (8:37). If anything is clear about the p h ilo so p h er's use
of the victory motif, it is this: the individual soul has w ithin itself all th at is nec­
essary to overcom e suffering. Victory through an o th e r's agency w o u ld have ap ­
p eared ludicrous and an insult to the providence of G od, w ho saw fit to place a
fragm ent of divine reason in every h u m an soul.
If Rom 8:35-39 is the high point of P au l's attem p t to reconstruct the problem
of suffering from the perspective of friendship, then Rom 8:18-34 builds u p to this
conclusion by advocating the pow er of a frien d 's sym pathy (taken in the strong
sense of co-suffering) to console the sufferer.68 In these verses, Paul explores the
consolation of friendship as an alternative to the philosophic m ethod of dealing
w ith suffering th ro ugh rational control.69 H e p o rtray s four agents as friends w ho
share all things w ith h u m an sufferers: creation (8:19-22), the Spirit (8:26), G od
(8:31-33), an d C hrist (8:34). Space allow s only for developing the them e of shared
suffering in term s of creation an d the Spirit.
In 8.T9-22, creation is conceptualized as a person w ith em otions desiring to
share b oth in h u m an ity 's future freedom an d in its present suffering. In short, cre­
ation is a friend:

For the creation w aits w ith eager longing for the revealing of the children
of God; for the creation w as subjected to futility, no t of its o w n will bu t
by the will of the one w ho subjected it, in ho pe th at the creation itself will
be set free from its bondage to decay an d will obtain the freedom of the
glory of the children of God. We know th at the w hole creation has been
groaning in labor pains [awTevo^ei Kai awcoStvei, systenazei kai synodi-
nei] until now.70

Paul d raw s u p o n m otifs found in G reek literature an d philosophy to p o rtray the


frien d sh ip of creation w ith hum ans. W hile for som e m o d ern readers it m ay be
190 P a u l in th e G re co -R o m a n W orld

rem iniscent of the opening chapters of G enesis a n d the developm ent of biblical
them es in Jew ish apocalyptic th ought,71 n atu re 's subjection to futility an d its
b o n d ag e to decay w as a stock them e in consolation philosophy (Philo, Cher. 7 7 -
78; Ps.-C rates, Ep. 35; P lutarch, [Cons. Apoll.] 104C-106C, 112D; Cicero, Tusc. 3.58-
61; Seneca, Ep. 71.11-16; Polyb. 1.1-4; M enander Rhetor, nepi eniSetKXiKcov 2.9).72
It w as th o u g h t th at those grieving m ight derive som e encouragem ent from the
th o u g h t th at all existing things m u st of necessity suffer a n d perish.
The second m otif is decidedly n o t from philosophical sources. The character­
ization of n atu re o r an aspect of n atu re as a p erson in sym pathy w ith h u m an suf­
fering is an ancient literary figure k n o w n in m o d ern parlance as the pathetic fal­
lacy.73 "G ro an (crteveiv, stenein)," a n d "be in anguish (cbSiveiv, odinein)," w ere
frequently em ployed in instances of the pathetic fallacy to com m unicate n atu re 's
sy m p ath y a n d m o u rn in g for h u m a n suffering (Greek Anthology 7.10,142, 241, 268,
292, 328, 393, 468, 476, 481, 547, 549, 599, 633; 8.3; Bion, Epitaph. Adon. 35).74 C re­
atio n is a friend, groaning over h u m an ity 's suffering, subject to the sam e futility,
y et h o p in g to share in the sam e freedom a n d glory.
In 8.26, w e discover th a t the Spirit also groans. This is a rem arkable statem ent,
b u t fits w ith the overall p u rp o se of the passage to assert the shared sufferings of
friends as an alternative to consolation th ro u g h rational self-control. The m oral
p h ilosophers co ndem ned groaning (oxeyayiioq, stenagmos) as a sign of w eakness
an d the lack of reason (Plutarch, [Cons. Apoll.] 113A; Epictetus, Diatr. 2.6.16-17).
N o good m an ever groans (Epictetus, Diatr. 1.1.12, 22; 1.6.29). It is a disgrace to
groan (Cicero, Tusc. 2.30-33). G roaning m ust be resisted (Cicero, Tusc. 2.42-50).
Paul, o n the o th er hand, m akes this particularly acute form of grief p a rt of the
S pirit's experience.75 The Spirit shares h u m an groaning and is therefore in solidar­
ity w ith hum anity. G o d 's friendship w ith hu m an ity is im plied in suffering the
loss of the Son, or m ore accurately, in h an d in g the Son over to d eath (8:32). Finally,
the circle of friends is com pleted. As in the case of 5:6-8, C hrist's friendship is
d em o n strated th ro u g h his death for others (8:34; see above). P au l's reconstruction
of the problem of suffering is finished. H e has em ployed rhetorical form s and
com m onplace ideas associated w ith philosophy's confidence that reason con­
quers suffering. Yet he has disarm ed that confidence. In place of the virtue of self-
control, he has advocated the shared suffering of friends, an d the circle of P aul's
friends includes all of creation and the divine com m unity.

P a rt III. O th e r Relevant Pauline and Paulinist T exts

Rom 2:9,15; 7:24; 8:1.7; 9:1-3; 12:12,15, 21; 15:1-3, 30


1 Cor 4:9-12, 21; 5:2; 7:35; 12:25-26; 13:3; 15:30-33
2 Cor 2:12-16; 5:14-21; 8:2; 11:23-33; 12:7-10; 12:21
Paul, Hardships, and Suffering 191

Gal 6:2
Phil 3:18
1 Thess 1:6; 2:1-2, 7 -8,13-16; 3:3-5; 4:13-18; 5:8,14
2 Thess 1:4-10
Col 1:24
Eph 3:13; 6:10-17
1 Tim 1:18-20; 4:10
2 Tim 1:8-2:13; 3:10-13; 4:6-8

P a rt IV. Bibliography

C lassical, H e lle n is tic , a n d G re c o -R o m a n

B raund, S. M., a n d C. Gill, eds. The Passions in Roman Thought and Literature. C am ­
bridge: C am bridge U niversity Press, 1997.
Buller, J. L. "T he Pathetic Fallacy in Hellenistic Pastoral." Ramus 10 (1981): 35-52.
Fowler, R. L. "The Rhetoric of D esperation." HSCP 91 (1987): 6-38.
Glibert-Thirry, A. Pseudo-Andronicus De Rhodes: I1EPI TIA0S1N. C orpus latinum
co m m en tario rum in aristotelem graecorum . S upplem ent 2. Leiden: Brill,
1977.
Gregg, R. C. Consolation Philosophy: Creek and Christian Paideia in Basil and the Two
Gregories. Patristic M onograph Series 3. C am bridge, Mass.: P hiladelphia Pa­
tristic F oundation, 1975.
H oistad, R. Cynic Hero and Cynic King. Lund, Sweden: Carl Blom, 1948.
Johann, H.-T. Trailer und Trost: Line quellen- und strukturanalytische Untersuchung
der philosophischen Trostschriften iiber Tod. S tudia et Testam onia A ntiqua 5. M u­
nich: W ilhelm Fink, 1968.
Perkins, J. The Suffering Self: Pain and Narrative Representation in the Early Christian
Era. N ew York: Routledge, 1995.
Strubbe, J. H. M. "E pigram s an d C onsolation Decrees for D eceased Youth." L'An-
tiquite classique 67 (1998): 45-75.

N e w T e s ta m e n t

Fitzgerald, John T. Cracks in an Earthen Vessel: An Examination of the Catalogues of


Hardships in the Corinthian Correspondence. SBLDS 99. A tlanta: Scholars Press,
1988.
G lad, C. E. Paul and Philodemus: Adaptability in Epicurean and Early Christian Psych-
agogy. N ovTSup 81. Leiden: Brill, 1995.
M alherbe, A. J. Paul and the Popular Philosophers. M inneapolis: Fortress Press, 1989.
--------- . Paul and the Thessalonians: The Philosophic Tradition of Pastoral Care.
P hiladelphia: Fortress Press, 1987.
Talbert, C. H. Learning through Suffering: The Educational Value of Suffering in the
Neio Testament and in Its Milieu. Collegeville, M inn.: Liturgical Press, 1991.
192 P a u l in th e G re co -R o m a n W orld

N otes
1. A. Glibert-Thirry, Pseudo-Andronicus De Rhodes: FIEPI TIA0QN (C orpus lat-
in u m co m m en tariorum in aristotelem graecorum , S upplem ent 2; Leiden: Brill,
1977), 223.
2. Cicero lim ited the topic in the sam e way. See A. Erskine, "Cicero an d the
E xpression of Grief," in The Passions in Roman Thought and Literature (ed. S. M.
B raund a n d C. Gill; C am bridge: C am bridge U niversity Press, 1997), 41-42.
3. See M. Pohlenz, Die Stoa (2d ed.; 2 vols.; G ottingen: V andenhoeck & Ru-
precht, 1959), 1:149; 2:77.
4. Philo (Leg. 3.111) cites w h a t ap p ears to have been a stan d ard definition:
"g ro an in g is intense a n d excessive sorrow [A,wtr|, hype]." U nless otherw ise in d i­
cated, texts an d translations of ancient w orks are from the Loeb Classical Library.
5. If w e associate soul shrinkage w ith grief, w e are m ore likely to recognize
allusions to em otional p ain in P au l's letters. In ad d itio n to the w ords w ith the root
sten, contraction of soul is present in the follow ing term s in the P auline epistles;
note, how ever, that the English translations provided by the various m o d ern v er­
sions (the nrsv is cited here) fail to convey the physiological aspect of the em o­
tion: "affliction" (0\u|/i£, thlipsis; e.g., Rom 5:3; 8:35; 2 Cor 1:4, 6, 8; 2:4); "an g u ish
of heart" (ouvoyf) rapSfac;, synoche kardias; 2 Cor 2:4); "faint-hearted" (cAr/ovi/nyo^,
oligopsychos; 1 Thess 1:14).
6. Glibert-Thirry, Pseudo-Andronicus De Rhodes, 227, m y translation.
7. See A. C. van G eytenbeek, Musonius Rufus and Greek Diatribe (Wijsgerige
Teksten en S tudies 8; Assen, the N etherlands: Van G orcum , 1963), 138. See also
Plato, Gorg. 472D-479D; Isocrates, Nic. 53; Juvenal, Sat. 13.192-198.
8. See H. D eku, "Selbstbestrafung: M arginalien zu einem sehr alten, aber
no ch nicht g an z lexikonreifen Begriff," Archiv fur Begriffsgeschichte 21 (1977): 4 2 -
58. See also Epictetus, Diatr. 2.22.35; Ench. 34; C lem ent of A lexandria, Strom.
2.12.55; M arcus A urelius, 8.53; 12.16; Lucian, Merc. cond. 42; 1 John 3:19-22.
9. John T. F itzgerald, Cracks in an Earthen Vessel: An Examination of the Cata­
logues of Hardships in the Corinthian Correspondence (SBLDS 99; A tlanta: Scholars
Press, 1988). Critics of Fitzgerald underestim ate the pow er of the G reek philo­
sophical trad ition o n the Jew ish sources that, it is claim ed, w ere m ore of an influ­
ence on Paul. F urtherm ore, they fail to u n d ersta n d F itzgerald's m ain contribu­
tion, to show h ow the rhetorical use of h ardship lists flow ed o u t of the central
teachings of the philosophers o n the relation b etw een virtue a n d endurance. See,
for exam ple, N. W illert, "T he C atalogues of H ard sh ip s in the P auline C orrespon­
dence: B ackground a n d Function," in The Neiv Testament and Hellenistic Judaism
(ed. P. Borgen a n d S. G iversen; A rhus, D enm ark: A rhus, 1995), 217-43.
10. Fitzgerald, Cracks in an Earthen Vessel, 115.
11. Ibid., 51-55.
12. See J. Perkins, The Suffering Self: Pain and Narrative Representation in the
Early Christian Era (N ew York: R outledge, 1995), 77-98.
13. Fitzgerald, Cracks in an Earthen Vessel, 55-70.
14. See N. C. Croy, Endurance in Suffering: Hebreios 12.1-13 in Its Rhetorical, Re­
ligious, and Philosophical Context (SNTSMS 98; C am bridge: C am bridge U niversity
Press, 1999), 139-59.
P a u l, H a r d s h ip s , a n d S u ff e r in g 193

15. See R. H oistad, Cynic Hero and Cynic King (Lund, Sw eden: Carl Blom,
1948), 97. For the readiness of the w ise m an to suffer indignities for the good of
others, see A ntisthenes,/rys. 14.5-6; 15.5, 9. See H. D. Rankin, Antisthenes Sokrati-
kos (A m sterdam : H akkert, 1986), 168-70.
16. For the dangers faced by bold speakers, see Lucian, Pise. 20; Peregr. 32. See
A. M alherbe, Paul and the Popular Philosophers (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1989), 38.
17. See H oistad, Cynic Hero, 195-96.
18. For Cynic m isanthropy, see G. A. G erhard, Phoinix von Kolophon: Texte und
Untcrsuchungen (Leipzig: Teubner, 1909), 3 9,165-67,170-75.
19. Ps.-H ippocrates, Ep. 17.40 (in R. Hercher, Epistolographi Graeci [A m ster­
dam : H akkert, 1965], 303).
20. See G erhard, Phoinix von Kolophon, 32-45.
21. See A. M alherbe, Paul and the Thessalonians: The Philosophic Tradition of Pas­
toral Care (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1987), 21-28.
22. For the E picurean care of souls, see C. E. G lad, Paul and Philodenius: Adapt­
ability in Epicurean and Early Christian Psychagogy (NovTSup 81; Leiden: Brill,
1995), 101-81. N ote the em phasis on reason, truth, an d bold speech in Lucian's
(Alex. 47) account of the Epicurean p ath to tranquillity; no m ention is m ade of a
conversion involving pain, leading in tu rn to repentance.
23. See I. H adot, Seneca und die griechisch-romische Tradition der Seelenleitung
(Berlin: W alter de G ruyter, 1969), 71-78.
24. See H. G. Ingenkam p, Plutarchs Schriften iiber die Heilung der Seele (H ypom -
n em ata 34; G ottingen: V andenhoeck & R uprecht, 1971), 74-90.
25. Ps.-Libanius, Charact. Ep. 43. Text an d translation is A. M alherbe, Ancient
Epistolary Theorists (SBLSBS 19; A tlanta: Scholars Press, 1988), 72-73.
26. For expressions of grief as m oral condem nation in the philosophic trad i­
tion, see th e C ynic ap p ro p riatio n of H eraclitus an d the philosophers w ho im i­
tated his gloom iness: Ps.-H eraclitus, Epp. 5.3; 7.2-10; Lucian, Demon. 6; Vit. auct. 7;
Fug. 18.
27. For o th er exam ples of the grieving style, see Julian, Ep. 68; G regory of
N azianzus, Epp. 7 , 16; Basil, Epp. 45,156, 204, 207, 212, 223, 224, 270.
28. Mertandri sententiae 370. In the sam e w o rk w e read, "Suppose all the b u r­
den s of friends to be in com m on" (534), and, "W hen a friend suffers w ith a friend
h e suffers w ith him self" (803; m y translations; see also 543K).
29. Both Plato (Symp. 179B-180B) an d Seneca (Ep. 9.10-12) recognize blurring
in th e distinction betw een friendship a n d erotic love w hen it com es to dying for
a friend.
30. S. Farron, Vergil's Aeneid: A Poem of Love and Grief (Leiden: Brill, 1993), 19n. 5.
31. See C. K. Barrett, "O AAIKHEAS (2 Cor 7.12)," in Verborum Veritas: Fest­
schrift fiir Gustav Stdhlin (ed. O. Bocher an d I<. H aacker; W uppertal, Germ any:
T heologischer Verlag Rolf Brockhaus, 1970), 149-57.
32. V. Furnish, II Corinthians (AB 32A; G arden City, N.Y.: Doubleday, 1984),
54-55,143.
33. Barrett, "O AAIKHZAE," 149-52.
34. For argum ents against identifying the letter w ith either 1 C orinthians or
2 Cor 10-13, see Furnish, II Corinthians, 163-68.
35. Ibid., 367-71.
194 P a u l in th e G re c o -R o m a n W orld

36. D. Fredrickson, " n a p p r ja ia in the P auline Epistles," in Friendship, Flatten/,


and Frankness of Speech: Studies on Friendship in the Nezv Testament World (ed. J. F itz­
gerald; N ovT Sup 82; Leiden: Brill, 1996), 180.
37. A ncient exegetes view ed e n ra p fa here as e7tm|J.r|ai<; an d thus an aspect o f
m oral exhortation. See, for exam ple, C hrysostom , Horn. 4 in 2 Cor. 4 (PG 61.422).
38. For the goals of m oral exhortation, and rebuke in particular, see Fladot,
Seneca und die griechisch-romische Tradition der Seelenleitung, 168-69. P h ilo d em u s
(Lib. 31, 82, XXIVA) u n d e rsta n d s eitrapriau; as a form of frank speech.
39. See A. M alherbe, " 'P astoral C are' in the T hessalonian C hurch," NTS 36
(1990): 381-85.
40. For rebuke leading to sham e an d suicide, see Plutarch, Adul. amic. 70F-71C.
41. R. L. Fow ler ("The Rhetoric of D esperation," HSCP 91 [1987]: 6-38) h as
identified a rhetorical form em ployed from H om er to R om an tim es, w hich h e h as
n am ed "d esp era tio n speech." Its identifying m arks include indication of the ex­
trem e w eig h t of suffering borne by the speaker, the im possibility of a solution
(atiopfa, aporia), questioning w h eth er life is any longer possible, not k n o w in g
w h e th e r to chose life or death, an d an exclam ation about how w retched one h as
becom e (p arodied in Epictetus, Diatr. 1.12.27). In addition to 2 Cor 1:8, tw o o th er
passages in Paul fit this form very well: Rom 7:24-25 an d Phil 1:21-26. Fow ler
(27-31) calls attention to the fact th at E uripides introduces the sym pathy of
friends as a so lution to the aporia of the speaker. Similarly, Paul introduces the n o ­
tion of frien d ship in each instance of his use of desperation speech.
42. F riends h ave like em otions (see P lutarch, Adul. amic. 51E; Amic. mult. 97A).
F riendship com es into being th ro u g h likeness, an d this includes the identity of
em otions (see A ristotle, Eth. nic. 83.6-7 ; Plutarch, Amic. mult. 96E-F; Cicero,
Amic. 50).
43. D. F redrickson, "P au l's Sentence of D eath (2 C orinthians 1:9)," in Cod,
Evil, and Suffering: Essays in Honor of Paul R. Sponheim (ed. T. Fretheim a n d
C. T hom pson; W ord a n d W orld S u pplem ent Series 4; St. Paul, M inn.: W ord &
W orld, 2000), 103-7.
44. "W orldly grief" recalls P au l's description in 2:7 of the grief suffered by
" th e o ne w h o caused injury."
45. For the role of em otional p ain o r grief in G o d 's intention to b rin g ab o u t
m oral reform , see P lutarch, Sera 549F-550A; 550E-F; 551C-E. Cf. Philo, Det. 144-
146; Conf. 180-182; Somn. 1.91; H eb 12:10-11; Rev 3:19.
46. O th er interpreters (e.g., C. K. Barrett, The Second Epistle to the Corinthians
[BNTC; London: Black, 1973], 203; Furnish, II Corinthians, 369) regard this p h ra se
as P au l's attem p t to m itigate the severity of the previous denials (7:2), w hich they
view as his accusations against the church.
47. See G erhard, Phoinix von Kolophon, 36.
48. For the soul as treasure, see Philo, Leg. 3.104-106; Cher. 48; Det. 35,43; Deus
42, 91-93; Sobr. 41,68; Conf. 69; Plutarch, An. corp. 500D; Seneca, Ep. 92.31-32. Bar­
rett (Second Epistle to the Corinthians, 137) gives good reasons to believe that Paul
is allu d in g to his illum ined soul; in the end, how ever, like o ther interpreters he
does n o t com e to this conclusion for fear of tu rn in g P au l's anthropology over to
H ellenistic ideas ab o u t the b o d y a n d soul. For P au l's ability to m an ip u late philo­
sophic term inology, see n. 54 below.
P a u l, H a r d s h ip s , a n d S u ff e r in g 195

49. So Fitzgerald, Cracks in Earthen Vessels, 167-69.


50. See H. B. W alters, History of Ancient Pottery: Greek, Etruscan, and Roman
(2 vols.; London: M urray, 1905), 1:135-36; 2:455, 479. Cf. Rom 9:21 and esp.
2 Tim 2:20.
51. The p ow er of G od to give life th ro u g h P aul's m inistry is the them e of 5:12.
Cf. 2 Cor 1:6; Gal 3:5; Phil 2:13; 1 Thess 2:13. For a sim ilar notion, in the philo­
sophic tradition, of divine pow er, see Dio C hrysostom , Alex. 15.
52. Fitzgerald, Cracks in Earthen Vessels, 169-76. Fitzgerald believes, how ever,
th at the divine p o w er in P aul's w eakness in 4:8-9 is "one of the w ays in w hich the
C orinthians are to know th at he has been com m issioned by G od an d the w ord
th at he speaks com es from G od (172)." I w o u ld assert th at Paul distinguishes him ­
self from the p o p u lar conception of the philosopher, w hose claim to authority
rested on his ow n power.
53. So ibid., 180.
54. For P aul's use an d critique in 2 Cor 4:16-5:5 of philosophic com m onplaces
such as "b o d y as tem porary dw elling" a n d "d eath as strip p in g the soul of the
body," see D. Fredrickson, "P aul Playfully o n Time an d Eternity," Dialog 39 (2000):
21-23. For these com m onplaces incorporated into discussions of h ard sh ip s an d
suffering, see Seneca, Epp. 24.17-21; 92.30-35; 102.21-30; 120.13-19.
55. The view th at 6:3-10 is apologetic has been challenged w ith good reason
by Fitzgerald (Cracks in Earthen Vessels, 187-88). H e has dem o n strated (191-201)
th at 6:3-10 reflects the philosophic use of h ard sh ip s to depict the sage's courage
an d constancy. I disagree, how ever, w ith his view that P au l's self-com m endation
fosters his hearers' confidence in him . Som ething m ore specific is at stake,
nam ely, the integrity of the flexible approach to the care of souls suggested in
6:6-7. The constancy of Paul portrayed in 6:7-10 g uards against any accusation
th at his gentleness is flattery. For the them e of adaptability in the care of souls, see
G lad, Paul and Philodemus, 15-98.
56. Fredrickson, "riappriofa in the P auline Epistles," 179-80.
57. Ibid., 179.
58. See, for exam ple, R. M artin, 2 Corinthians (WBC 40; Waco, Tex.: W ord
Books, 1986), 170-71.
59. For the sense of hatred, see SVF 3.102.40; Cicero, Tusc. 4.23-24; 4.26; Sen­
eca, Ep. 14.7.
60. S ubstitute "C hristian" for "sage" an d you have P aul's m eaning. So C. FI.
Talbert, Learning through Suffering: The Educational Value of Suffering in the Nczv Tes­
tament and in Its Milieu (Collegeville, Minn.: Liturgical, 1991), 21-22.
61. J. W ettstein, Novum Testamentum Graecum (2 vols.; A m sterdam : Ex officina
D om m eriana, 1752; reprint, G raz, G erm any: A kadem ische D ruck- u n d Verlagsan-
stalt, 1962), 46.
62. A sim ilar su rprise aw aits the reader in 1 Thess 5:8. The "arm o r of the sage"
constructed o u t of reason w as a w idespread philosophic motif. See M alherbe,
Paul and the Popular Philosophers, 95-103. Paul subverts the im age, how ever, by
constructing the arm o r o u t of faith, love, a n d hope. These m ake a person v u ln er­
able to realities external to the soul. P aul's earliest interpreters w ere n o t so eager
to ab an d o n reason. N ote the m ore conventional construction of arm o r in Eph
6:10-17 and 1 Tim 1:18.
196 P a u l i n t h e G r e c o - R o m a n W o r ld

63. N evertheless, P au l's appeal to hope in affliction has parallels. For exam ­
ple, M en an d er (813K) w rites, "In adversity a m an is saved by hope." Does Rom
8:24a echo this saying? Cicero (Amic. 23, 59) believes that friendship provides
ho p e for the fu tu re an d does no t let the spirit grow faint. This connection b etw een
frien d sh ip an d ho pe is crucial for Rom 5 a n d 8.
64. See no tes by M. D avies, Hermes 111 (1983): 496-97, an d O. Vox, Hermes 120
(1992): 375-76. For additional exam ples, see D. Sider, The Epigrams of Philodemus:
Introduction, Text, and Commentary (New York: Oxford U niversity Press, 1997),
95-97.
65. A thletic victory: Ps.-D iogenes, Ep. 31; E pictetus, Diatr. 1.24.1-2; 3.25.1-6;
4.4.30-32; Philo, Agr. 110-21; Mut. 82.1; Prob. 26-27, 110-12. M ilitary victory:
P s.-D iogenes, Ep. 5; a n d m o st of the instances in Seneca, including Polyb. 15.3;
16.3.
66. Victory over external hardships: Seneca, Epp. 98.12, 14; 104.27. Victory
over passions: SVF 3.129.9; Ps.-H eraclitus, Ep. 4.3; Philo, Abr. 48-49; Epictetus,
Erich. 34. External a n d internal are b ro u g h t together in Ps.-D iogenes, Ep. 12; C i­
cero, Tusc. 2.63.
67. For a brief account, see C. E. M anning, On Seneca's "Ad Marciam" (Leiden:
Brill, 1981), 62. Seneca reserves the victory m otif for a final flourish in Ep. 67, a d is­
course on the en d u ran ce of hardships.
68. C om pared w ith the other techniques for m itigating em otional pain, w hich
focused on the irrationality of grief, a frien d 's sym pathy w as a little-utilized
them e in G reco-R om an consolatory literature. See J. FI. D. Scourfield, Consoling
Heliodorus: A Commentary on ]erome, Letter 60 (N ew York: O xford U niversity Press,
1992), 81. A few exam ples can be located: Plutarch, [Cons. Apoll.] 102A; Seneca,
Polyb. 12.2. For the rational th erap y of grief in philosophic consolation, see H.-T.
Johann, Trauer und Trost: Eine quellen- und strukturanalytische Untersuchung derphil-
osophischen Trostschriften fiber Tod (Studia et Testam onia A ntiqua 5; M unich: W il­
helm Fink, 1968), an d R. C. Gregg, Consolation Philosophy: Greek and Christian
Paideia in Basil and the Two Gregories (Patristic M onograph Series 3; C am bridge,
Mass.: P h iladelphia Patristic Foundation, 1975). O utside of the philosophic w rit­
ings, how ever, the notion that sharing em otional pain has consolatory p o w er a p ­
pears to h ave been w idespread. See J. FI. M. Strubbe, "E pigram s an d C onsolation
Decrees for Deceased Youth," L'Antiquitd classique 67 (1998): 45-75. Stobaeus (Flor.
5.48.16-31) p ro v ides a collection of texts aro u n d this them e.
69. We can be certain th at Paul w as aw are of the form s of philosophic conso­
lation, since he ad o p ts som e of them . See M alherbe, Paul and the Thessalonians, 5 7 -
58, a n d idem , Paul and the Popular Philosophers, 64-66.
70. The nrsv' s "in labor pains" is too free a translation of ouvcoStvei (synodi-
nei). The verbal aspect needs to be retained, and it is debatable w h eth er the birth
im agery sh o u ld be given such em phasis. The term cbStvco (odino) in the sense of "I
am in anguish" w as em ployed w ith "I groan" (oTevco, stend) in ep itap h s w ith o u t
calling atten tio n to b irth imagery. The early association of the term w ith b irth p ain
is no indication of actual usage in a later period.
71. O. Christoffersson, The Earnest Expectation of the Creature: The Flood-Tradi­
tion as Matrix of Romans 8:18-27 (ConBNT 23; Stockholm: A lm qvist & W iksell In­
ternational, 1990), 129-32.
P a u l, H a r d s h ip s , a n d S u f f e r in g 197

72. See Johann, Trailer und Trost, 63-67,119-64.


73. J. L. Buller, "The Pathetic Fallacy in Hellenistic Pastoral," Ramus 10 (1981):
35-52; J. M. H u rw itt, "Palm Trees an d the Pathetic Fallacy in A rchaic G reek Po­
etry an d A rt," CJ 77 (1982): 193-99; C. Segal, "D issonant Sym pathy: Song, O r­
p heus, and the G olden Ages in Seneca's Tragedies," Ramus 12 (1983): 229-51; J. D.
Reed, Biun of Smyrna: The Fragments and the Adonis (C am bridge Classical Texts and
C om m entary 33; C am bridge: C am bridge U niversity Press, 1997), 125, 215-16.
74. N atu re's sym pathy for h u m an suffering should no t be confused w ith the
Stoic doctrine of oupnccGeia (sympatheia), w hich tau g h t the im personal, causal in­
terconnection of all things. See H. R. N euenschw ander, Mark Aurels Beziehungen
zu Seneca und Poseidonios (Noctes R om anae 3; Stuttgart: P aul H a u p t, 1951), 14-23.
75. For groaning as a type of grief, see above, n. 4.

You might also like