You are on page 1of 27

Journal of Economic Literature

Vol. XXXVI (March 1998), pp. 166–192

Hodgson: Institutional Economics

The Approach of Institutional


Economics
GEOFFREY M. HODGSON
The Judge Institute of Management Studies, University of Cambridge

The author is particularly grateful to Peter Corning, Masashi Morioka, Richard Nelson, John
Nightingale, Douglass North, Paul Twomey, and three anonymous referees for discussions,
critical comments, or other assistance. The Japan Society for the Promotion of Science, and
the European Commission, Phare-ACE program are thanked for their financial assistance
with this research.

By means of the old, we come to know the new. Confucius

I. Introduction spread unfamiliarity with the “old”


American institutionalism, despite its
T ODAY, THE TERM “new institutional
economics” is in widespread use and
is associated with a vast literature.
favored geographic location and ac-
cessible language. The second reason
is that since its decline in America
Clearly, the temporal adjective in the
after 1930 the “old” institutionalism
adopted title of this broad set of postwar
has been repeatedly written off, and is
theories and approaches has been in-
dismissed for failing to provide a sys-
tended to demarcate the “new institu-
tematic and viable approach to eco-
tional economics” from the “old” institu-
nomic theory. It is also widely—and
tional economics of Thorstein Veblen,
wrongly—believed that institutionalism
John Commons, and Wesley Mitchell.
was essentially anti-theoretical and de-
This earlier institutionalism had actually
scriptive.
been dominant in economics depart-
However, characterizations of the
ments in American universities just after
“old” institutionalism as purely descrip-
the First World War. 1
tive or anti-theoretical do not bear up
Despite this, little detailed reference
to close scrutiny. Particularly in the
has been made by leading exponents of
writings of Veblen and Commons, there
the “new” institutional economics to
is a strong emphasis on the importance
this predecessor. Two factors may
and priority of the tasks of theoretical
help to explain this oversight. The
explanation and theoretical develop-
first is that the history of economic
ment. Whatever their limitations, the
thought is currently a much neglected
early institutionalists addressed crucial
subdiscipline, and there is now wide-
theoretical issues.
1 Throughout this article, the terms “institution- For example, Veblen (1899, 1919)
alism” and “institutional economics,” when with- was the first social scientist to attempt
out a temporal adjective, will be taken to refer to
the institutionalism in the tradition of Veblen, to develop a theory of economic and in-
Commons, and Mitchell. stitutional evolution along essentially
166
Hodgson: Institutional Economics 167

Darwinian lines (Hodgson 1993). Veb- not because of a naive and unsustain-
len’s work shares common features with able belief that economics can proceed
the much later attempts by economists with data alone, and without any theory.
to use evolutionary metaphors from bi- Although several institutionalists put
ology by Armen Alchian (1950), Fried- their faith in data, they all retained
rich Hayek (1988), Kenneth Boulding some degree of belief in the importance
(1981), and Nelson and Sidney Winter of a theoretical project.
(1982). In addition, Commons (1924, The primary reasons for the failure of
1934) has been acknowledged as a ma- institutionalism lie elsewhere. In par-
jor influence on, for example, the be- ticular, the old institutionalism was
havioral economics of Herbert Simon partially disabled by a combined re-
(1979) and even the “new” institutional- sult of the profound shifts in social sci-
ism of Oliver Williamson (1975). Insti- ence in the 1910–1940 period and of
tutionalists also developed a number of the rise of a mathematical style of neo-
theories of pricing behavior in imper- classical economics in the depression-
fectly competitive markets (Marc Tool stricken 1930s. Behaviorist psychology
1991). Traces of the surviving influence and positivist philosophy displaced the
of “old” institutionalist ideas are found instinct psychology and pragmatist phi-
in many other areas of theoretical and losophy upon which the early institu-
applied economics. Indeed, the influ- tionalism had been built. With their use
ence of institutionalism persisted for of formal techniques, mathematical
some time after the Second World economists caught the imagination of
War. 2 both theorists and policy makers. In
Nevertheless, there is a shred of jus- comparison, institutionalism was re-
tification for the dismissive statements. garded as technically less rigorous, and
Ever since Veblen there has been a fail- thereby inferior.
ure of the “old” institutionalists to An adequate history of American in-
agree upon, let alone develop, a system- stitutionalism remains to be written.
atic theoretical core. American institu- The purpose of the present essay is
tionalism has bequeathed no integrated quite different. The main aims are: to
theoretical system of the stature or outline the institutionalist approach in
scope of that of Karl Marx, Alfred Mar- broad terms, and to address and evalu-
shall, Léon Walras, or Vilfredo Pareto. ate a few “hard core” propositions that
The reasons for this failure cannot be were prominent in early institutional-
discussed here, save to note that it was ism. A key argument in this paper is
that the “old” institutionalism offers a
2 Notably, several institutionalists or their fellow radically different perspective on the
travelers have been elected as Presidents of the nature of human agency, based on the
American Economic Association since 1945: John concept of habit. Habits and rules are
Kenneth Galbraith, Edwin Witte, Morris seen as necessary for human action. A
Copeland, George Stocking, and Boulding. In ad-
dition, the “old” institutionalists Simon Kuznets habit-dominated conception of human
and Gunnar Myrdal received Nobel Prizes in 1971 behavior not only has significant sup-
and 1974 respectively. Other schools of thought port from psychology, it is also worthy
resemble institutionalism. For example, much of
post-Keynes “Cambridge” economics had a strong of development and further elaboration
institutionalist flavor, particularly the work of by economists.
Nicholas Kaldor and Joan Robinson. The more re- In an institutionalist view, the con-
cent work of Robert Boyer, Michel Aglietta, and
other members of the French régulation school cept of habit connects crucially with the
also has strong institutionalist affinities. analysis of institutions. This issue has
168 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXVI (March 1998)

important implications for both micro- II. Institutionalist Approaches to


economic and macroeconomic analysis. Economic Analysis
Some illustrative applications of this
general approach are considered in The core ideas of institutionalism
both these domains, with arguments concern institutions, habits, rules, and
why it is important to take account of their evolution. However, institutional-
habit in human behavior. These ap- ists do not attempt to build a single,
proaches do not rely on the standard as- general model on the basis of those
sumptions of individual rationality. ideas. Instead, these ideas facilitate a
However, while outlining the essentials strong impetus toward specific and his-
of a broadly institutionalist approach, it torically located approaches to analysis.
is conceded that institutionalism itself In this respect there is an affinity be-
requires much more theoretical and tween institutionalism and biology. Evo-
methodological development. lutionary biology has a few laws or gen-
The structure of this paper is as fol- eral principles by which origin and
lows. Section II sketches how institu- development can be explained. Analysis
tional economists proceed in practice. of the evolution of a specific organism
It is noted that institutionalism does not requires detailed data concerning the
attempt to build an all-embracing, gen- organism and its environment, and also
eral theory. Instead, complex phenom- specific explanations relevant to the
ena are approached with a limited num- species under consideration. Evolution-
ber of common concepts and specific ary biology requires both specific and
theoretical tools. Section III of this pa- general theories. In contrast, in physics
per defines and elaborates the core con- there are repeated attempts to formu-
cepts of habits and institutions, as late the general theory of all material
rooted in the early institutionalist the- phenomena—the so-called “theory of
ory of Veblen and Commons. Section IV everything” (Jack Cohen and Ian Stew-
shows how much work in the “new” in- art 1994). In its relatively greater em-
stitutionalist vein, including the prob- phasis upon specificities, institutional
lem of “institutional infinite regress,” economics resembles biology rather
points to a required reformulation of than physics.
the “new” institutionalist project and a The institutionalist approach moves
possible convergence with the thinking from general ideas concerning human
of the “old” institutionalists. Section V agency, institutions, and the evolution-
considers the circumstances in which it ary nature of economic processes to
is necessary or convenient for an agent specific ideas and theories, related to
to rely on habits and rules. Not only are specific economic institutions or types
habits and rules ubiquitous, but we are of economy. Accordingly, there are mul-
typically required to rely on them tiple levels, and types, of analysis. Nev-
whether or not (bounded) optimization ertheless, the different levels must be
is possible. Section VI concludes the es- linked together. A crucial point here is
say. 3 that the concepts of habit and of an in-
stitution (both defined in Section III)
3 Restrictions of space prevent extensive refer- help to provide the link between the
ences to the literature. The reader is referred to specific and the general.
Hodgson et al. (1994) for an encyclopedic treat- In contrast, neoclassical economics
ment of some of the topics discussed here, for
wider references, and for discussions of many moves from an universal theoretical
other issues pertinent to institutionalism. framework concerning rational choice
Hodgson: Institutional Economics 169

and behavior, and moves directly to theory. 5 Unlike the stationary outcomes
theories of price, economic welfare, and of general equilibrium theory, partial
so on. 4 However, institutional econom- equilibrium models could seemingly be
ics does not presume that its habit- placed in an ongoing, evolutionary con-
based conception of human agency it- text. Where institutionalists did agree,
self provides enough to move toward however, was that it was necessary to
operational theory or analysis. Addi- develop specific theories of pricing that
tional elements are required. In par- reflected the institutional and market
ticular, an institutionalist would stress structures of the modern economy. Fur-
the need to show how specific groups of thermore, any attainable general theory
common habits are embedded in, and of prices would necessarily be highly
reinforced by, specific social institu- limited in its explanatory properties, be-
tions. In this manner, institutionalism cause of the variety of institutional pro-
moves from the abstract to the con- cesses of price formation in the real
crete. Instead of standard theoretical world.
models of given, rational individuals, The basis of price theory in institu-
institutionalism builds upon psycho- tionalism is thus quite different from
logical, anthropological, sociological, that in other schools of economics.
and other research into how people be- Neoclassical economics relies on the
have. Indeed, if institutionalism had a universal concepts of supply, demand,
general theory, it would be a general and marginal utility. Adam Smith,
theory indicating how to develop spe- David Ricardo, and Marx relied on the
cific and varied analyses of specific phe- labor theory of value. By contrast, in in-
nomena. stitutionalism prices are social conven-
tions, reinforced by habits and embed-
A. An Illustration: Theories of Pricing ded in specific institutions. Such
As an illustration, consider the theory conventions are varied and reflect the
of price formation. Subsequent to Ve- different types of commodity, institu-
blen’s iconoclastic attacks on rational tion, mode of calculation, and pricing
economic man, institutionalists were process.
themselves divided on whether Mar- If prices are conventions then they
shallian or other neoclassical price depend in part on ideas and habits. A
theories were acceptable and compat- theory of price must in part be a theory
ible with institutionalism. While in- of ideas, expectations, habits, and insti-
stitutionalists generally rejected ra- tutions, involving routines and pro-
tional economic man, this did not nec- cesses of valuation. Without such a the-
essarily mean the abandonment of all ory, there is no adequate explanation of
the apparatus of Marshallian price how individuals calculate or form expec-
tations of the future.
4 Neoclassical economics (a term originally
It was in this vein that a great deal of
coined by Veblen) may be conveniently defined as
an approach which (1) assumes rational, maximiz- empirical and theoretical work on the
ing behavior by agents with given and stable pref- pricing process was carried out by insti-
erence functions, (2) focuses on attained, or move- tutionalists and others in the first half
ments toward, equilibrium states, and (3) excludes
chronic information problems (such as uncertainty of the twentieth century. Instead of a
of the type explored by Frank Knight and John
Maynard Keynes). Notably, some recent develop- 5 Note that “new” institutionalist Ronald Coase
ments in modern economic theory—such as in has also rejected the standard rationality assump-
game theory—reach to or even lie outside the tions while working within a broadly Marshallian
boundaries of this definition. framework.
170 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXVI (March 1998)

general theory of price, attempts were cial markets (Wayne Baker 1984). None
made to develop specific theories of of these studies assumes perfect infor-
pricing, each related to real-world mar- mation or perfect competition. The
ket structures and types of corporate or- starting point is an investigation of how
ganization. It was in this context that prices are actually formed in specific in-
much of the early work on oligopoly stitutional contexts, followed by the for-
pricing was pioneered, including several mulation of a pricing theory that is spe-
theories of “mark-up,” “administered,” cific to the type of institution being
or “full cost” pricing (Tool 1991). No investigated.
less than other economists, institution- Institutionalism has no general theory
alists want to develop theoretical expla- of price but a set of guideline ap-
nations of such crucial real world phe- proaches to specific problems. These
nomena as price. Where they differ, lead to historically and institutionally
however, is in stressing the practical specific studies which are arguably of
and explanatory limitations of any possi- more operational value than any all-
ble general theory of all prices. embracing general theory. Regrettably,
An institutionalist approach to the specific studies of market institutions
theory of pricing proceeds by first ex- and pricing processes have received far
amining the institutions in which the less research resources and prestige
prices are being formed. All aspects of than general equilibrium and other
the institutions that are closely bound highly abstract approaches.
up with the process of price formation
B. Starting from Habit: Some
are relevant. What are the costs and
Macroeconomic Illustrations
how are they evaluated? What routines
govern the calculation of prices? What Much empirical data in economics
information is available and what is un- are consistent with the prevalence of
known? By what routines is information habitual activity, even at the macro-
obtained and used? What routines are economic level. Consider, for example,
used to revise prices in line with the ex- the now neglected theory of the con-
perience on the market? What is the sumption function developed by James
strategy concerning competitive pric- Duesenberry (1949). This theory was
ing? How does this relate to market heavily influenced by Veblen and
structure? stressed the role of habit in consumer
Obviously, a process of abstraction behavior. Duesenberry’s theory did not
and simplification is required to deal fall out of favor because it did badly on
with all this complexity. As a result of empirical tests. In fact it predicted
detailed investigations, it may be possi- rather well. Instead, the theory was dis-
ble to abstract some key processes gov- carded primarily because it was not
erning the formation of prices. One of seen to conform with the presumptions
the best examples of this approach is of rational choice theory (Francis Green
the work on “administered pricing” by 1979). Duesenberry’s theory proceeded
Gardiner Means and his collaborators on the assumption that an established
(Caroline Ware and Means 1936). level of income, plus prevailing cultural
There is also a close institutionalist af- norms, would lead to an habitual pat-
finity with the behavioral theory of the tern of consumer behavior. The con-
firm (Richard Cyert and James March sumer acts imitatively and adaptively,
1964) and with the theory of informa- and also on the basis of ingrained hab-
tion clustering and networking in finan- its. Similarly, the major subsequent
Hodgson: Institutional Economics 171

study of aggregate consumer demand in regularities from micro-stabilities—is


the USA, by Hendricks Houthakker and quite different. In contrast, institutional
Lester Taylor (1966), also found that a economics sees regularities at the sys-
major part of consumer spending is sub- temic level as being reinforced through
ject to inertia, that is, primarily depen- positive feedbacks that act, in part,
dent on preceding consumption. upon the microeconomic elements.
It is beside the point to suggest that Hence the latter are not taken as given.
all such phenomena can be recast into a The institutionalizing function of insti-
more complex model where habit is for- tutions means that macroeconomic or-
mulated as a convoluted result of utility der and relative stability is reinforced
maximizing behavior. In principle, the alongside variety and diversity at the
possibility of such a recasting cannot be microeconomic level. Ironically, by
denied. The point is that the evidence assuming given individuals, the micro-
alone does not bestow theoretical pri- foundations project in orthodox eco-
macy to rational choice modeling. nomics had typically to assume further-
(Theoretical arguments against the pri- more that each and every individual was
macy of the rationality assumptions are identical in order to attempt to make
raised later in this essay.) Furthermore, the analysis tractable. In contrast, insti-
the standard principle of parsimony can tutionalism points not to a spurious su-
be used to support a fundamental as- pra-individual objectivity, nor to the
sumption of human inertia or habit, no uniformity of individual agents, but to
less that the standard axioms of ration- the concept of socio-economic order,
ality. arising upon variety at the micro-level.
In general, institutional economists Individual habits both reinforce, and
approach the analysis of macroeconomic are reinforced by, institutions. Through
systems by examining patterns and this circle of mutual engagement, insti-
regularities of human behavior, expect- tutions are endowed with a stable and
ing to find a great deal of imitation, inert quality. Further, institutions play
inertia, lock-in and “cumulative causa- an essential role in providing a cogni-
tion.” 6 Importantly, regularities or tive framework for interpreting sense-
stability at the systemic level may arise data and in providing intellectual habits
not despite, but because of variations at or routines for transforming informa-
the micro-level. In complex systems, tion into useful knowledge. The strong
macro-stability may depend on micro- influence of institutions upon individual
chaos (Francesca Chiaromonte and cognition provides some significant sta-
Giovanni Dosi 1993; Cohen and Stewart bility in socioeconomic systems, partly
1994). Or systemic constraints may pre- by buffering and constraining the di-
vail over micro-variations (Gary Becker verse and variable actions of many
1962; Dhananjay Gode and Shyam Sun- agents.
der 1993). With this line of argument the rela-
The prominent view that it is neces- tive autonomy of macroeconomics and
sary to build microeconomics on “sound the idea of the workability of aggregates
microfoundations”—to derive macro- is reinstated. This contrasts with reduc-
tionist modes of theoretical analysis
6 Veblen was one of the first to develop the con- that see macroeconomic phenomena as
cept of cumulative causation that directly or indi- necessarily explained by the micro-
rectly influenced Allyn Young, Myrdal, Kaldor,
and others. See Veblen (1919, pp. 70–77, 173–77, economic. Here the institutionalists
240–43, 370, 436) and Hodgson (1993, ch. 9). made a significant contribution. Mitchell
172 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXVI (March 1998)

and his colleagues in the National Bu- 1994). Furthermore, institutionalists re-
reau for Economic Research in the ject the idea of the primary ontological
1920s and 1930s played a vital role in unit of the given, institution-free indi-
the development of national income ac- vidual, upon which the microfounda-
counting and suggested that aggregate, tions project rested. (This issue is ex-
macroeconomic phenomena have an on- plored in more detail below.) Arguably,
tological and empirical legitimacy. This the failure of the mainstream micro-
important incursion against reduction- foundations project points to the need
ism created space for the Keynesian to develop a quite different overall ap-
revolution. Through the development of proach. In this there are both micro-
national income accounting, the work of economic and macroeconomic levels of
Mitchell and his colleagues influenced analysis, each with a degree of relative
and inspired the macroeconomics of theoretical autonomy, but at the same
John Maynard Keynes. Partly for this time both levels are connected by con-
reason, there is a close and explicit af- ceptual links and spanning explanations.
finity between institutionalism and what The abandonment of a standard mi-
is often described as “Post Keynesian” crofoundations approach does not mean
macroeconomics. that institutionalists are necessarily de-
The fact that institutions typically prived of the capacity to build models
portray a degree of invariance over long or make predictions. On the contrary,
periods of time, and may outlast indi- repeated studies—including those cited
viduals, provides a reason for choosing above—have shown that models with
institutions rather than individuals as a strong elements of inertia, explained in
basic unit. Most institutions are tempo- terms of habit persistence, are good
rally prior to the individuals that relate predictors in the macroeconomic
to them. We are all born into and so- sphere. It is also well-known econo-
cialized within a world of institutions. metric folklore that naive prediction
Recognizing this, institutionalists focus models, based on simple extrapolations
on the specific features of specific insti- from the recent past into the future, are
tutions, rather than building a general often much better predictors of macro-
and ahistorical model of the individual economic performance than much more
agent. sophisticated economic models. Institu-
However, the proposed alternative is tionalists regard such results as confir-
not a methodological collectivism where mation of the phenomena of habit per-
individual behavior is entirely explained sistence, and of institutional lock-in and
by the institutional or cultural environ- self-reinforcement.
ment. Complete explanations of parts in Institutionalism works from the “styl-
terms of wholes are beset with prob- ized facts” of the macroeconomic sys-
lems of equivalent stature to those of tem and attempts to uncover the under-
the inverse procedure. Just as struc- lying structural features of the system
tures cannot be adequately explained in that help explain these outcomes. This
terms of individuals, individuals cannot requires analyses that are both quantita-
adequately be explained in terms of tive and qualitative. Consider an exam-
structures. ple, starting from the stylized fact that
The failure of the mainstream micro- productivity growth in the United
foundations project confirms the diffi- States economy has been lower in the
culty of modeling the whole in terms of last 40 years or so than in many East
the individual parts (S. Abu Turab Rizvi Asian and other competing countries.
Hodgson: Institutional Economics 173

Data may also reveal the stylized fact than mere correlation between vari-
that the proportion of GNP devoted to ables. Hence it is important to explain
investment in the United States has the causal mechanisms linking share
been relatively low. But, for the institu- ownership structures with low invest-
tionalist, the analysis does not stop with ment, and, in turn, with lower growth
mere statistical correlation. The task is rates of productivity. Such causal expla-
to explain the institutional constraints nations could involve many factors, in-
and causal processes giving rise to both cluding national cultures, political sys-
low investment and low productivity tems, and so on. Institutionalists are not
growth. wedded to any one hypothesis or any
Consider a tentative hypothesis. The one theory on this issue, but in general
functional and cultural separation of fi- the institutional approach stresses the
nancial from industrial institutions may importance of comparative institutional
have encouraged a short-term orienta- analysis, and the examination of a broad
tion toward investment returns. The set of factors, in searching for an ade-
sparse institutional connections be- quate causal explanation.
tween finance and industry, and the
C. The Institutionalist Approach:
relative lack of shared personnel and
Some General Remarks
shared vested interests, may allow the
financial sector to concentrate on maxi- For some, the general approach out-
mizing its returns to short-, rather than lined above may seem fairly obvious,
long-term, investment. Furthermore, adding nothing new. Several points can
the relatively low degree of cross own- be made in response to such a remark.
ership between industrial corporations First, there is a degree of emphasis on
may further encourage a primary orien- institutional and cultural factors that is
tation of the corporation toward short- not found in mainstream economic the-
term financial markets and short-term ory. Second, the analysis is openly inter-
investment decisions. A first step in ap- disciplinary, in recognizing insights
praising this hypothesis would be to from politics, sociology, psychology, and
validate its key assumptions, for exam- other sciences. Third, there is no re-
ple by looking at the U.S. data on the course to the model of the rational, util-
distribution of share ownership, includ- ity-maximizing agent. Inasmuch as a
ing cross share ownership between fi- conception of the individual agent is in-
nancial and industrial corporations. An volved, it is one which emphasizes both
important next step would be to carry the prevalence of habit and the possibil-
out similar and comparative investiga- ity of capricious novelty. Fourth,
tions in relevant economies with higher mathematical and statistical techniques
rates of productivity growth, such as Ja- are recognized as the servants of, rather
pan. The existence elsewhere of higher than the essence of, economic theory.
degrees of corporate cross ownership of Fifth, the analysis does not start by
stocks and shares would provide a basis building mathematical models: it starts
for attempting to evaluate the hypothe- from stylized facts and theoretical con-
sis still further. Econometric evidence jectures concerning causal mechanisms.
of a significant statistical correlation be- Sixth, extensive use is made of historical
tween the relevant variables would be and comparative empirical material con-
important, but far from enough. Institu- cerning socio-economic institutions. In
tionalists stress the need to outline the several of these respects, institutional
real causal linkages involved, rather economics is at variance with much
174 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXVI (March 1998)

of modern mainstream economic theory. the methodological and meta-theore-


This should not and does not mean, tical foundations of the institutionalist
however, that institutionalists become approach. Constraints of space prevent
mere data-gatherers. No understanding further elaboration. What is clear, how-
nor explanation is possible without the- ever, is that such methodological issues
ory. Veblen and Commons, as founders have become lively topics of debate in
of the “old” institutionalism, knew that the 1980s and 1990s, with a veritable
theory does not arise by induction from explosion of literature in the area of
data. All empirical analyses presuppose economic methodology. Institutionalists
a set of concepts and an implicit or ex- have made significant contributions to
plicit theory. For this reason, to start this literature and are thus playing a
from stylized facts must itself require a part in the development of appropriate
prior conceptual framework. Institu- approaches to economic analysis.
tionalism attempts to provide this broad
D. Some Contemporary Issues
framework in terms of a set of meta-
in Institutionalist Theory
theoretic and methodological guide-
lines. There is no single, agreed set of It has already been admitted that in-
definitive guidelines among institution- stitutionalism lacks a systematic core
alists, but a number of common themes theory. Institutionalism does not seek a
emerge. general theory of everything but it does
For example, a central problem is the require a coherent framework of analy-
identification of what may be termed sis and a workable methodology.
“ideal types.” These are abstract de- In particular, there remains impor-
scriptions of situations, phenomena, or tant scope for the development of an in-
persons that indicate the general fea- stitutionalist microeconomics. Although
tures on which a theorist will focus as past institutionalists made significant
crucial for purposes of explanation. It is progress in the development of theories
impossible to include all details and all of pricing in imperfectly competitive
features in such a venture because so- markets, there is still a great of work
cio-economic systems are too complex that can be done. In economics since
and are open in the sense in which they the Second World War such alternative
interact with their outside environment. approaches have received negligible re-
A process of abstraction must occur search resources. However, alternative
where the essential structures and fea- theories of consumer behavior have
tures of the system are identified. The flowered in other disciplines, such as
crucial question, of course, is which marketing (Roger Mason 1995). Some
ideal type is to be selected in the analy- of this research has a strong institution-
sis of a given phenomenon. To answer alist flavor, in part because it brings to-
this question requires a methodology to gether insights from psychology and
distinguish between the general and the other social sciences. In developing
specific aspects of any given phenome- theories of individual economic behav-
non. By making this distinction, and ior, as well as elsewhere, institutional-
perhaps by using comparative material ists look forward to the possibility of a
from other socio-economic systems, it is much more extensive and fruitful dia-
possible to construct and develop hy- logue across disciplinary barriers.
potheses concerning the key causal link- The institutionalist emphasis on habit
ages behind the observed phenomena. and routine also fits in well with the
This is an all-too-sketchy account of evolutionary models developed by Nel-
Hodgson: Institutional Economics 175

son and Winter (1982) and their follow- they operate, in place of former concep-
ers. As Veblen (1899) himself sug- tions and habits of thought. In particu-
gested, the evolutionary paradigm pro- lar, if the methods and criteria of “opti-
vides a basis for encapsulating both mization” are themselves being learned
continuity and change, both inertia and how can learning itself be optimal?
novelty. Habits or routines may adapt Institutionalists bring a different per-
slowly or “mutate” as agents attempt spective to the analysis of learning by
purposeful improvements. In addition, seeing it, in part, as a transformative
there is some selection process by and reconstitutive process, involving
which some habits and routines are re- the creation of new habits, propensities,
tained and imitated, and others fall out and conceptual frameworks (Veblen
of use. Institutionalism is congenitally 1919; James Murphy 1994; Henry Plot-
an “evolutionary economics.” Like all kin 1994). Institutionalists need to capi-
work in this vein, it is biased toward dy- talize on their prima facie conceptual
namic rather than equilibrium-oriented and methodological advantage in this
modes of theorizing. area and develop theories of learning
Problems of cognition and learning that are appropriate for a knowledge-
have been thematic to institutionalism intensive and rapidly changing world.
since its inception. Instead of the pre- The remainder of this essay explores
sumed bedrock of given individuals, further some of the methodological and
there is the idea of interactive and par- theoretical issues that have been raised.
tially malleable agents, mutually en- The following section outlines some of
twined in a web of partially durable and the core theoretical characteristics of
self-reinforcing institutions. Institution- institutionalism. Subsequent sections
alist theory is admittedly underdevel- address the problem of reductionism in
oped in this area but institutionalists economic theory, and show that main-
may potentially be in a relatively strong stream explanations of economic and in-
theoretical position. Although main- stitutional phenomena in terms of
stream economics has addressed the given, rational individuals are not as ro-
concept of learning in recent years, at bust as is often supposed. These argu-
root there are severe problems in the ments give further credence to the in-
approach based on the assumption of a stitutionalist approach.
rational actor. The key question is what
is meant by “rational learning.” How III. Some Core Characteristics of
can agents be said to be rational at any Institutionalist Theory
given moment when they are in the pro-
A. The “New” and the “Old”
cess of learning? The very act of learn-
Institutionalisms Compared
ing means that not all information is
possessed and global rationality is com- What is the essential difference be-
promised or ruled out. Furthermore, tween the “old” and the “new” institu-
much more than inputting data or esti- tionalism? Answering this question is
mating probabilities is involved. Learn- made more difficult because there is no
ing is more than the acquisition of in- unanimity, even among its adherents, as
formation; it is the development of new to what is precisely to be included in
means and modes of cognition, calcula- the “new” variety. Nevertheless, an an-
tion, and assessment. This means that swer is possible if we focus on the com-
agents are building up new repre- mon theoretical core of some of the
sentations of the environment in which most prominent and influential “new”
176 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXVI (March 1998)

institutionalist writings, such as by


North (1981), Richard Posner (1973), Institutions
Andrew Schotter (1981), and Williamson
(1975). Despite their analytical and pol-
icy differences, there are some common
presumptions behind all these works. Action Information
The characteristic “new” institution-
alist project is the attempt to explain
the emergence of institutions, such as Individuals
the firm or the state, by reference to a
model of rational individual behavior,
Figure 1. The Institutionalist Action-Information Loop
tracing out the unintended conse-
quences in terms of human interactions.
An initial institution-free “state of na- As well as in Menger’s writings, this
ture” is assumed. The explanatory move- important core theme of an action-in-
ment is from individuals to institutions, formation loop is clearly evident, for ex-
taking individuals as given. This ap- ample, in North’s (1981) theory of the
proach is often described as “methodo- development of capitalism, William-
logical individualism.” 7 son’s (1975) transaction cost analysis of
Along these lines, Carl Menger the firm, and Schotter’s (1981) game-
(1892) long ago saw the institution of theoretic analysis of institutions. The
money as emanating in an undesigned value of this core idea should not be de-
manner from the communications and nied.
interactions of individual agents. Once However, despite the temporal adjec-
convenient regularities become promi- tive, the “new” institutionalism is built
nent, a circular process of institutional upon some antiquated assumptions con-
self-reinforcement takes place. Emerg- cerning the human agent, derived from
ing to overcome the difficulties of bar- the individualism of the Enlightenment.
ter, money is chosen because it is con- In this 300–year tradition, a key idea is
venient, and it is convenient because it the notion that the individual can, in a
is chosen. Other similar examples in the sense, be “taken for granted.” Accord-
“new” institutionalist literature include ingly, the individual is taken as the ele-
traffic conventions (Schotter 1981; mental building block in economic the-
Robert Sugden 1986). For example, ory. Strictly, it is not a question of
once a majority of car drivers stick to whether or not a theorist is found to ad-
the right-hand side of the road, it is mit that individuals—or their wants and
clearly rational for all drivers to follow preferences—are changed by circum-
the same rule. Accordingly, the emer- stances. Indeed, many economists admit
gent convention is reinforced and insti- that individuals might so be changed.
tutionalized by imitation, and by effi- What is crucial is the individualistic
cient use of “all relevant information” economist assumes, for the purposes of
(Schotter 1981, p. 160). We may stylize economic enquiry, that individuals and
a core idea involved here in terms of an their preference functions should be
action-information loop, as shown in taken as given. Thus the demarcating
Figure 1. criterion is not the matter of individual
7 The enormous and controversial literature on
malleability per se, but the willingness,
this topic is too large to address here. See Hodg- or otherwise, to consider this issue as
son (1988) for a survey and discussion. an important or legitimate matter for
Hodgson: Institutional Economics 177

economic analysis. The commonplace difficulties with the “new” institutional-


statement by mainstream economists ist approach. It is argued below that to
that tastes and preferences are not the proceed from the assumption of given
explananda of economics thus derives individuals in an institution-free “state
directly from the individualist tradition. of nature” is theoretically misconceived.
Likewise, the conception of economics Accordingly, developments in the “new”
as “the science of choice” takes the institutionalism show some sign of
choosing individual and her preference yielding some ground to the “old,” or at
functions as given. Unlike the “old” in- least creating the possibility of a fruitful
stitutionalism, the “new” institutional- dialog between the two approaches.
ism has also taken such individualistic Notably, some leading mainstream
presuppositions on board. economists seem to be moving toward
A common thread in the literature of the view that the individual should not
“old” institutionalism, from Veblen be taken as given. Joseph Stiglitz (1994,
through Commons and Mitchell, to pp. 272–73) has accepted that “certain
Myrdal and Galbraith, is the idea that in aspects of human nature are endoge-
economic analysis the individual should nous to the system . . . traditional eco-
not always be taken as given. The gen- nomic theory was clearly wrong in treat-
eral use of given preference functions ing individuals as immutable.” A
to model individuals is rejected by insti- foremost agenda item for institutional
tutionalists. Individuals interact to form economics is to incorporate a richer,
institutions, while individual purposes context-dependent conception of hu-
or preferences also are molded by so- man agency within a systematic and rig-
cio-economic conditions. The individual orous theory.
is both a producer and a product of her
B. Agency and Habit
circumstances. 8
It is possible to distinguish the new Rejecting the mainstream approach
institutionalism from the “old” by to economic theory, with its conception
means of the above criterion. This dis- of the utility-maximizing individual, the
tinction holds despite important theo- founders of the “old” institutionalism
retical and policy differences within promoted an alternative conception of
both the new and the old institutionalist human agency. Such an alternative was
camps. 9 However, there are conceptual well developed by the early twentieth
8 The recent work of Becker (1996) might at
century, in the influential writings of in-
first sight appear to “take account of tastes” by stinct psychologists such as William
building a model with “endogenous prefer- James and William McDougall, and
ences”—in which individual utility functions con- pragmatist philosophers such as Charles
tain arguments such as “culture.” This is not
the case because an immanently conceived Sanders Peirce. For all these writers the
(meta)preference function for each individual is influence of Darwinian biology was cru-
still assumed at the outset; it is an unexplored cial. Although instinct psychology was
“black box” that still remains to be explained.
9 Notably, and in contrast to the accounts in subsequently eclipsed by behaviorism
Richard Langlois (1986) and Malcolm Rutherford (Carl Degler 1991) it enjoys a rehabili-
(1994), this criterion places the work of Nelson tation today (Leda Cosmides and John
and Winter (1982) squarely in the “old” institu-
tionalist category. This affinity with the “old” insti- Tooby 1994a, 1994b; Plotkin 1994; Ar-
tutionalism is now recognized by Nelson and Win- thur Reber 1993).
ter themselves. In addition, some of the later Following these leading psychologists
writings of Hayek (1988) come closer to the old
institutionalism, as do recent works by North and philosophers of their time, the early
(1990). institutionalists saw habit as the basis of
178 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXVI (March 1998)

human action and belief. Habit can be It is as if institutionalists and rational


defined as a largely non-deliberative choice theorists have been engaged in a
and self-actuating propensity to engage century-long game of Go. Each has
in a previously adopted pattern of be- been trying to place the pieces of an ar-
havior. A habit is a form of self-sustain- gument in an intricate attempt to encir-
ing, nonreflective behavior that arises cle the postulates of the other. Notably,
in repetitive situations. however, leading advocates of the ra-
Many modern economists have ad- tional choice paradigm, such as Becker
dressed habit. However, mainstream (1962) have demonstrated that an “irra-
economists typically regard habit as an tional” mode of behavior, in which
evocation or appendage of rational agents are ruled by habit and inertia, is
choice, and thereby explicable in its just as capable of predicting the stan-
terms. Habits are seen as the result of dard downward-sloping demand curve
an earlier choice, or as a deliberate and the profit-seeking activity of firms.
means of avoiding endless deliberation. Becker showed how the negatively in-
Rationality thus retains explanatory pri- clined market demand curve can result
macy (Becker 1992; Robert Pollak from habitual behavior. Actors “can be
1970). said to behave not only “as if” they were
The treatment of habit by the phi- rational but also “as if” they were irra-
losophers and psychologists who influ- tional: the major piece of empirical evi-
enced the early institutionalists was dence justifying the first statement can
quite different. The explanatory arrow equally well justify the second” (Becker
ran in the opposite direction: instead of 1962, p. 4).
habits being explained in terms of ra- Kenneth Arrow has also accepted the
tional choice, rational choice was ex- possibility of an alternative approach
plained in terms of habits. Further, based on habit. After outlining a possi-
habit was linked with knowledge and ble “non rational” and habit-based
belief, seeing the essence of belief as model of human behavior, Arrow (1986,
the establishment of habit. All ideas, in- p. S386) remarked: “Without belaboring
cluding beliefs, preferences, and ra- the point, I simply observe that this the-
tional modes of calculation, were re- ory is not only a logically complete ex-
garded as evolutionary adaptations to planation of behavior but one that is
circumstances, established through the more powerful than standard theory
acquisition of habitual propensities. and at least as capable of being tested.”
At first sight, both approaches seem Accordingly, the “accuracy of the pre-
feasible: habit can be regarded as the dictions” or other familiar criteria for
basis of rational choice, or rational theory selection do not give outright
choice can be seen as the procreator of victory to rational choice. Common ar-
habits. The fact that economists display guments for regarding rational choice as
an habitual inclination to assert the lat- pre-eminent do not carry as much
ter should not obscure the possibility of weight as has been supposed. This ques-
a reverse ordering. (If the allegation of tion of the explanatory primacy of habit
the priority of rationality over habit is versus that of rational choice will be ex-
itself simply a matter of habit then it is plored again later in this essay. For
by that fact undermined.) The problem now, there is at least a prima facie case
of adjudication between these two para- for examining the distinctive treatment
digms is not as straightforward as is of habit in the work of the “old” institu-
often assumed. tionalists.
Hodgson: Institutional Economics 179

To many mainstream economists, (1932, p. 84). He saw an institution as


such a habit-driven characterization of “a way of thought or action of some
the agent is excessively deterministic, prevalence and permanence, which is
seemingly denying free will and embedded in the habits of a group or
choice. 10 However, it can be argued the customs of a people.” This elabo-
that the conception of the agent as an rates Veblen’s (1919, p. 239) earlier
utility-maximizer based on fixed prefer- definition of an institution as “settled
ence functions itself denies free will habits of thought common to the gener-
and choice. An individual ruled by her ality of men.” Notably, in the “old” in-
preferences is made a prisoner, not sim- stitutionalism, the concept of habit
ply of her social environment, but also plays a central role both in its definition
of her utility function. It is as if she is a of an institution, as in its picture of hu-
robot, programmed by her preferences. man agency.
Within such a deterministic machinery, Although, by contrast, definitions of
critics find it difficult to find any place an institution in the “new” institutional-
for real choice. As James Buchanan ism do not typically include the notion
(1969, p. 47) once remarked: “Choice, of habit, they often share with the older
by its nature, cannot be predetermined institutionalism a broad, rather than a
and remain choice.” narrow, conception of an institution. In-
In trying to gain a deeper under- stitutions, are regarded as general regu-
standing of the nature of human agency larities in social behavior (Schotter
we are addressing an age-old, highly 1981, p. 11) or “the rules of the game in
complex, and inadequately resolved society or . . . the humanly devised con-
philosophical and psychological prob- straints that shape human interaction”
lem. In some of the best writings in the (North 1990, p. 3).
area we find attempts to reconcile ha- All these definitions, “new” and “old”
bitual behavior, on the one hand, and institutionalist alike, involve a relatively
purposefulness, choice, novelty, and broad concept. They encompass not
creativity, on the other (Michael Po- simply organizations—such as corpora-
lanyi 1967; Murphy 1994; Plotkin 1994). tions, banks, and universities—but also
Common to these approaches is the integrated and systematic social entities
idea of habits being the foundation of such as money, language, and law. The
learned behavior. Accordingly, examin- case for such a broad definition of insti-
ing the ways in which new habits are tutions is that all such entities involve
acquired is as important as a recogni- common characteristics:
tion of their durability. This dual stress
is thematic to the institutionalism of • All institutions involve the interaction of agents, with
Veblen and others, and retains its crucial information feedbacks.
theoretical relevance today. • All institutions have a number of characteristic and
common conceptions and routines.
C. From Habits to Institutions • Institutions sustain, and are sustained by, shared
conceptions and expectations.
One of the most useful definitions of • Although they are neither immutable nor immortal,
an institution was provided by the insti- institutions have relatively durable, self-reinforcing,
and persistent qualities.
tutional economist Walton Hamilton • Institutions incorporate values, and processes of
10 Note that, contrary to a widespread miscon- normative evaluation. In particular, institutions
ception, Veblen (1899, p. 15; 1914, pp. 31–32; reinforce their own moral legitimation: that which
1919, p. 75; 1934, pp. 80, 175) repeatedly asserted endures is often—rightly or wrongly—seen as
that human behavior was purposeful. morally just.
180 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXVI (March 1998)

A broad definition of an institution is and made meaningful by agents. In-


consistent with long-standing practice in deed, as discussed below, rationality it-
the social sciences. More narrowly, or- self is regarded as reliant upon institu-
ganizations may be defined as a special tional props.
subset of institutions, involving deliber- The availability of common cognitive
ate coordination (Viktor Vanberg 1994), tools, as well as congenital or learned
and recognized principles of sovereignty dispositions for individuals to conform
and command. Language is an example with other members of the same group,
of an institution that is not an organiza- work together to mold individuals goals
tion. A business corporation is an institu- and preferences. Accordingly, individu-
tion and also an organization. All institu- als are not taken as given. In main-
tions and organizations exhibit the five stream economics, widespread lip-ser-
characteristics above. vice to notions of individuality and
However, a key difference between choice may have helped to obscure the
the “old” and the “new” institutionalism degree in reality to which conformism
here is that in the former the concept of or emulation actually occur, even in
habit is central. For the “old” institu- modern competitive economies. For an
tionalists, habit is regarded as crucial to “old” institutionalist, such outcomes are
the formation and sustenance of institu- an important part of the institutional
tions. Habits form part of our cognitive self-reinforcing process.
abilities. Cognitive frameworks are From an “old” institutionalist per-
learned and emulated within institu- spective, the institutional action-infor-
tional structures. The individual relies mation loop in Figure 1 stands out in
on the acquisition of such cognitive higher relief. The imitation and emula-
habits, before reason, communication, tion of behavior leads to the spread of
choice, or action are possible. habits, and to the emergence or rein-
Learned skills become partially em- forcement of institutions. In turn, insti-
bedded in habits. When habits become tutions foster and underline particular
a common part of a group or a social behaviors and habits, and help transmit
culture they grow into routines or cus- them to new members of the group.
toms (Commons 1934, p. 45). Institu- The additional emphasis here concerns
tions are formed as durable and inte- the role of habit both in sustaining indi-
grated complexes of customs and vidual behavior, and in providing the in-
routines. Habits and routines thus pre- dividual with cognitive means by which
serve knowledge, particularly tacit incoming information can be inter-
knowledge in relation to skills, and in- preted and understood. Our under-
stitutions act through time as their standing of the durable and self-rein-
transmission belt. forcing qualities of institutions is
Institutions are regarded as imposing enhanced.
form and social coherence upon human The thrust of the “old” institutionalist
activity partly through the continuing approach is to see behavioral habit and
production and reproduction of habits institutional structure as mutually en-
of thought and action. This involves the twined and mutually reinforcing: both
creation and promulgation of concep- aspects are relevant to the full picture
tual schemata and learned signs and (Commons 1934, p. 69). Choosing insti-
meanings. Institutions are seen as a cru- tutions as units of analysis does not nec-
cial part of the cognitive processes essarily imply that the role of the indi-
through which sense-data are perceived vidual is surrendered to the dominance
Hodgson: Institutional Economics 181

of institutions. A dual stress on both more open-ended and evolutionary ap-


agency and structure is required, redo- proach, redolent of the earlier institu-
lent of similar arguments in sociology tionalists.
and philosophy (Roy Bhaskar 1979; An- Two opposite types of error are
thony Giddens 1984; Harrison White possible. The “cultural determinists”
1992). Both individuals and institutions place too much stress on the molding of
are mutually constitutive of each other. individuals by institutions.11 Such
Institutions mold, and are molded by, “oversocialized” views of human be-
human action. havior have been widely criticized
Institutions are both “subjective” (Mark Granovetter 1985). At the oppo-
ideas in the heads of agents and “objec- site end of the spectrum, the “new
tive” structures faced by them. The twin institutional economics” gives no more
concepts of habit and institution may than weak stress to the processes of in-
thus help to overcome the philosophical stitutional conditioning, and focuses
dilemma between realism and subjectiv- primarily on the emergence of institu-
ism in social science. Actor and struc- tions out of the interactions of given in-
ture, although distinct, are thus con- dividuals. This section explores the
nected in a circle of mutual interaction problems that may arise if exclusive
and interdependence. stress is put on the latter direction of
Summarizing the argument so far, it causality.
has been shown in this section that the The distinctive “new” institutionalist
wider recognition of the importance of project has been identified as the at-
institutions and rules in human society tempt to explain the existence of insti-
is endorsed by institutional economics tutions by reference to a given model of
in the Veblen-Commons tradition, but individual behavior, and on the basis of
with an additional and crucial stress an initial institution-free “state of na-
on the role of habit. A circle of interac- ture.” The procedure is to start with
tion between actor and structure is given individuals and to move on to ex-
based on the linked concepts of habit plain institutions.
and institution. Section IV below adds Admittedly, substantial heuristic in-
further credence to this argument by sights about the development of insti-
considering some difficulties that are tutions and conventions have been
raised when the explanatory circle is gained on the basis of the assumption of
broken and the individual is given un- given, rational individuals. The main
warranted ontological and explanatory problem addressed here is the incom-
priority. pleteness of the research program in
its attempt to provide a general theory
IV. Explaining Institutions: The of the emergence and evolution of
Problem of Institutional Infinite Regress institutions. Some tentative and “evolu-
tionary” approaches to solving this
In this section it is argued that at- problem are addressed at the end of
tempts to explain the origin and suste- this section.
nance of institutions on the basis of the
assumption of given individuals have in- 11 Rutherford (1994, pp. 40–41) notes how
ternal flaws and inconsistencies. Ac- American institutionalism itself moved toward cul-
cordingly, attempts to explain institu- tural determinism and methodological collectivism
in the post-1940 period. Such a one-sided empha-
tions in this way may have to be sis was not found in the earlier institutionalism of
abandoned. The door is opened to a Veblen and Commons.
182 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXVI (March 1998)

A. Internal Problems in Explanations “in the beginning there were markets”


Based on Given Individuals (Williamson 1975, p. 20); this starting
point is characteristic of his approach.
Alexander Field (1979, 1984) has ad- From this original context, some indi-
vanced a key problem in the new insti- viduals go on to create firms and hierar-
tutionalist project to attempt to explain chies. These endure if they involve
institutions solely in terms of given, ra- lower transaction costs.
tional individuals. In trying to explain However, the market itself is an insti-
the origin of social institutions from tution. The market involves social
given individuals, the new institutional norms, customs, instituted exchange re-
economics has to presume a social lations, and—sometimes consciously or-
framework governing their interaction. ganized—information networks that
In any original, hypothetical, “state of themselves have to be explained (Dosi
nature” from which institutions are seen 1988; Hodgson 1988). Market and ex-
to have emerged, a number of rules, change relations themselves involve
and cultural and social norms are al- complex rules. In particular, the institu-
ready presumed. No “thought experi- tion of private property itself requires
ment” involving an institution-free explanation. Markets are not an institu-
“state of nature” has yet been postu- tion-free beginning. As if in search of
lated without them. the original, institution-free, state of
For example, game theorists such nature prior to property and markets,
as Schotter (1981) take the individual Williamson (1983) argues that private
“for granted,” as an agent unambigu- property can emerge through “private
ously maximizing her expected pay- ordering,” that is, individual-to-individ-
off. Yet, in attempting to explain the ual transactions, without state legisla-
origin of institutions through game tion or interference.
theory, Field (1984) points out that The question of the possibility of
certain norms and rules must inevitably property and contract without any role
be presumed at the start. There can for the state is debated in legal theory.
be no games without prior rules, and However, there is another fundamental
thus game theory can never explain the objection to the idea of attempting to
elemental rules themselves. Even in a ground explanations of property or in-
sequence of repeated games, or of stitutions on individuals alone. Even
games about other (nested) games, at if the state is absent, individuals rely
least one game or meta-game, with a on customs, norms, and, most em-
structure and payoffs, must be assumed phatically, the institution of language,
at the outset. Any such attempt to deal in order to interact. Interpersonal
with history in terms of sequential or communication, which is essential to all
nested games is thus involved in a stories of institutional emergence, itself
problem of infinite regress: even depends on linguistic and other rules
with games about games about games and norms. The shared concept of indi-
to the nth degree there is still at least vidual property requires some means of
one preceding game left to be ex- communication using common concepts
plained. and norms, both before and after ex-
As another example, Williamson’s plicit or tacit recognition of property
transaction cost theory of the firm takes rights can be established. Even if the
its original state of nature as the mar- state can be absent from these pro-
ket. In a famous passage he writes that cesses, some prior institutions are still
Hodgson: Institutional Economics 183

required. 12 Before an individual may tion. Information cannot be received


choose, he or she requires a conceptual unless the individual has to some de-
framework to make sense of the gree been enculturated through prior
world. 13 More generally, considering engagement with institutions. 14 Com-
the action-information loop in Figure 1 munication requires an institutionalized
above, the reception of “information” in individual.
the new institutionalist story requires a In the “old” institutional economics,
paradigm or cognitive frame to process cognition and habit have a central
and make sense of that information. place. Knowledge and learning are
Further, our interaction with others re- stressed. There is also an insistence that
quires the use of the institution of the perception of information is not
language. We cannot understand the possible without prior habits of thought
world without concepts and we cannot to endow it with meaning. Without such
communicate without some form of habits, agents cannot perceive or make
language. Without the prior use of the data received by their senses.
institutionalization of individuals, the Habits thus have a crucial cognitive
action-information loop cannot be com- role: “All facts of observation are neces-
pleted. As the “old” institutionalists ar- sarily seen in the light of the observer’s
gue, the transmission of information habits of thought” (Veblen 1914, p. 53).
from institution to individual is impossi- Such habits are acquired through in-
ble without a coextensive process of en- volvement in institutions.
culturation, in which the individual The central “new” institutionalist pro-
learns the meaning and value of the ject of explaining institutions from indi-
sense-data that is communicated. The viduals alone is thus misconceived. The
“information” arrow on the right hand problem of infinite regress identified
side the figure always and necessarily here undermines any “new institutional-
involves such a process of encultura- ist” claim that the explanation of the
12 Whether common agreement to and practical
emergence of institutions can start from
enforcement of property can arise without the ex- some kind of original, institution-free
istence of a state is a matter of continuing debate. ensemble of (rational) individuals, in
The classic “old” institutionalist argument that the which there is supposedly no rule or in-
state was required historically in order to establish
labor, land, and money markets is in Karl Polanyi stitution to be explained. At the very
(1944). Despite his celebrated argument concern- minimum, “new” institutionalist stories
ing the undesigned evolution of money from indi- of the development of institutions de-
vidual interactions, even Menger (1936) recog-
nized that the state may be necessary to maintain pend upon interpersonal communica-
the integrity of the monetary unit. tion of information. And the communi-
13 This raises a problem in Young-Back Choi’s
cation of information itself requires
(1993) innovative work. While developing a theory
of conventions and institutions he takes the indi- shared concepts, conventions, rules,
vidual as “the basic unit of analysis” (p. 5). Choi routines, and norms. These, in turn,
(pp. 32–39) is thus impelled to have this individual have to be explained.
somehow choosing the conceptual “paradigm” by
which she makes sense of the uncertain world in
which she is situated. The unanswered question is 14 This raises the question of how a newborn
on what basis has such an individual “elected to infant may acquire information. Our incapacity
adopt” (p. 39) one paradigm rather than another? to learn without prior conceptual frameworks
Surely this choice itself requires a conceptual means—as James argued long ago and Plotkin
framework or paradigm, and norms and criteria of (1994) and others elaborate—that much of our in-
judgement, to make some sense of the situation in itial capacity to learn must be genetically inherited
which the choice is made. The choice of paradigm and instinctive. In the eyes of modern psychology,
itself requires a paradigm. Again we have a prob- Veblen’s adherence to the concept of instinct is
lem of infinite regress. not as old-fashioned as it used to seem.
184 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXVI (March 1998)

B. Which Came First: The Chicken nisms of reproduction and procreation


or the Egg? are very different. Individuals are pur-
poseful, whereas institutions are not, at
What is being contested here is the least in the same sense. Institutions
possibility of using given individuals as have different life spans from individu-
the institution-free starting point in the als, sometimes enduring the passing of
explanation. It is not possible to under- the individuals they contain. Crucially,
stand how institutions are constructed each individual is born into, and molded
without seeing individuals as embedded by, a world of pre-existing institutions:
in a culture made up of many interact- even if these institutions were made by
ing institutions. Institutions not only others and can be changed.
constrain but also influence individuals. We have seen that the new institu-
Accordingly, if there are institutional tionalist project to explain the emer-
influences on individuals and their gence of institutions on the basis of
goals, then these are worthy of explana- given individuals runs into difficulties,
tion. In turn, the explanation of those particularly with regard to the concep-
may be in terms of other purposeful in- tualization of the initial state from
dividuals. But where should the analysis which institutions are supposed to
stop? The purposes of an individual emerge. This does not mean that all
could be partly explained by relevant in- “new” institutionalist research is with-
stitutions, culture, and so on. These, in out value, but it indicates that the start-
their turn, would be partly explained in ing point of explanations cannot be in-
terms of other individuals. But these in- stitution-free: the main project has to
dividual purposes and actions could be reformulated as just a part of a wider
then be partly explained by cultural and theoretical analysis of institutions. The
institutional factors, and so on, indefi- reformulated project would stress the
nitely. evolution of institutions, in part from
We are involved in an apparently infi- other institutions, rather than from a
nite regress, similar to the puzzle hypothetical, institution-free “state of
“which came first, the chicken or the nature.” What is required is a theory of
egg?” Such an analysis never reaches an process, evolution, and learning, rather
end point. It is simply arbitrary to stop than a theory that proceeds from an
at one particular stage in the explana- original, institution-free, “state of na-
tion and say “it is all reducible to indi- ture” that is both artificial and unten-
viduals” just as much as to say it is “all able.
social and institutional.” The key point
C. Toward Evolutionary Explanations
is that in this infinite regress, neither
of Institutional Change
individual nor institutional factors have
complete explanatory primacy. The idea In some cases the “comparative stat-
that all explanations have ultimately to ics” character of such “new” institution-
be in terms of individuals (or institu- alist explanations is obvious. However,
tions) alone is thus unfounded. one of the reasons for the rise of “evolu-
There is thus an unbreakable circle of tionary” thinking in economics since the
determination. This does not mean, early 1980s has been an attempt to
however, that institutions and individu- break the constraints of this mode of ex-
als have equivalent ontological and planation with its two fixed end-points.
explanatory status. Clearly, they have Because there is no answer to the
different characteristics. Their mecha- chicken-or-egg question, the question
Hodgson: Institutional Economics 185

itself has to be changed. The question encompassing assumption of the “ra-


should no longer be “which came first?” tional” agent is deemed to be sufficient.
but “what processes explain the devel- The contention here, however, con-
opment of both of them?” This implies cerns the explanatory primacy of habit
a movement away from comparative over such all-encompassing conception
statics and toward a more evolutionary of rational behavior. We start by posing
and open-ended framework of analysis. a question: under what circumstances is
Some moves in this direction by two it necessary or convenient for an agent
prominent “new” institutionalists have to rely on habits or rules? 15 The ques-
already led to a degree of convergence tions of how habits and rules are repli-
with the evolutionary and open-ended cated and transmitted in society is side-
ideas of the “old” institutionalists. This stepped here to focus on a decision
is apparent in the later works of Hayek situation giving rise to their use. It is
(1988) and the recent writings of North argued that even optimization requires
(1990). the deployment of rules, and for this
Such evolutionary explanations in- reason mainstream economics cannot
volve the search for “a theory of the legitimately ignore these questions.
process of consecutive change, realized This suggests that a detailed analysis of
to be self-continuing or self-propagat- the evolution of specific habits and
ing and to have no final term” (Veblen rules—including the pecuniary rational-
1919, p. 37). Emphatically, abandoning ity of agents in a market economy—
the attempt to explain all institutions in should be installed at the core of eco-
terms of given individuals does not nomics and social theory.
mean the abandonment of theoretical Rules are conditional or uncondi-
explanation. Instead, the origins and de- tional patterns of thought or behavior
velopment of organizations and institu- which can be adopted either con-
tions are seen as an evolutionary pro- sciously or unconsciously by agents.
cess. Today, there is a substantial Generally rules have the form: in cir-
amount of work going on in this area, cumstances X, do Y. Habits may have a
with extensive use being made of evolu- different quality: rule-following may be
tionary metaphors taken from biology. conscious and deliberative whereas ha-
bitual action is characteristically unex-
V. The Necessity of Habits and Rules amined. Rules do not necessarily have a
self-actuating or autonomic quality but
This section extends the argument clearly, by repeated application, a rule
further by showing how rational indi- can become a habit. Often it is easier to
viduals depend on habits and rules. The break a rule than to change a habit, be-
prominent idea of the utility-maximiz- cause our awareness of our own habits
ing individual has permitted economists is often incomplete; they have a self-ac-
to ignore the procedures and rules that tuating character, being established in
are knowingly or unwittingly employed subliminal areas of our nervous system.
by agents. Most explanations of behav- However, habits still have the same
ior, including the role-driven and the general form: in circumstances X, action
habitual, can seemingly be encom- Y follows.
passed within the framework of utility- A familiar question of enduring con-
maximization. Accordingly, the underly-
ing psychological and other explanatory 15 For a treatment of this issue in greater depth
issues have been largely ignored. The see Hodgson (1997).
186 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXVI (March 1998)

troversy is the extent to which optimiz- Conventional accounts sometimes ne-


ing techniques are applicable to deci- glect the universal need for rules of cal-
sion situations in the real world. Much culation to reach optima. One reason
of modern economics is founded on the for this is that optimization processes
assumption that they are. If assump- are often confused with optimal out-
tions of perfect information are comes. However, statements of equilib-
dropped, it is typically assumed that un- rium conditions are not the same thing
certain or complex decision problems as the specification of algorithmic or
can still be accommodated using prob- other procedures required to attain
abilities. Against this, a number of crit- equilibria: outcome is not the same as
ics have argued that a significant pro- process. Another reason for the neglect
portion of decision problems are not is the widespread belief that optimiza-
amenable to probabilistic or other opti- tion involves choice and rule-following
mization techniques (e.g., Veblen 1919; denies it. On the contrary, as argued
Keynes 1937; Simon 1957, 1979). above, mechanical optimization ex-
cludes genuine choice.
A. Optimization and Rules All explicit optimization procedures
However, we shall side-step this well- must involve rules. This raises the sec-
known controversy here, to focus on a ondary but important question of their
(large or small) class of decision situ- origin. Notably, optimization itself can-
ations in which (bounded) optimization not provide a complete explanation of
may be possible. Consider mathematical either the origin of rules or the adop-
optimization problems and their solu- tion of rule-driven behavior. As all opti-
tions. The procedures of linear pro- mization involves intrinsic rules, the
gramming and differential calculus, for idea of explaining all rules on the basis
example, sustain methods of optimiza- of the optimizing behaviors of agents
tion with strict rules. Optimizing proce- involves circular reasoning and is thus
dures always involve rules: namely the misconceived. Hence the question of
rules of computation and optimization.16 “where do the original rules come
from?” remains, and it cannot be an-
16 Notably, Vanberg (1994) has suggested that
swered completely in terms of optimiza-
rational choice and rule-following behavior are in-
compatible. He argues that it is inherently incon- tion itself. It is necessary to consider
sistent to speak of a “rational choice to follow additional explanations of their genesis,
rules” or a “rational choice among rules.” To Van- at least to supplement the optimization
berg, the essence of following a rule is to be par-
tially unresponsive to the changing particularities story. In search of this “first cause” we
of each choice situation. This is contrasted with are forced to consider explanations
the concept of choice, where an individual is other than optimization for the reliance
deemed free of such “pre-programmed behavior.”
However, first, the quality of being unresponsive of the individual upon rules.
to changing particularities is not an universal fea- There is also the case of the intuitive
ture of rule-following behavior. There are condi- optimizer, with tacit skills. Although the
tional rules that discriminate between different
environmental conditions and point to different skills may not be codifiable, they are
outcomes in different circumstances. Second, the embedded in habits of the same general
very idea of rational calculation, as shown below, form: in circumstances X, do Y. Like-
must itself depend on computational rules. Van-
berg has also failed to recognize that strict optimi- wise, the formation of these habits can-
zation must necessarily exclude choice. As noted not be explained by optimization alone,
above, an utility-maximizer is essentially a taste- without addressing the other rules, hab-
satisfying machine. If choice means the possibility
of acting otherwise then it cannot be predeter- its, or instincts that led to their origin.
mined by either preference functions or rules. This primary reliance on habits or
Hodgson: Institutional Economics 187

rules limits the scope of rational optimi- involve acquired habits. Habits are used
zation. Rationality always depends on even by firms or individuals attempting
prior habits or rules as props (Hodgson to optimize in some way. As the “old”
1988). Hence rational optimization institutional economist John Maurice
alone can never supply the complete ex- Clark (1918, p. 26) noted, “it is only by
planation of human behavior and insti- the aid of habit that the marginal utility
tutions that some theorists seem to be principle is approximated in real life.”
striving for. Given that explanation in It is an institutionalist tenet that habit
social science requires more than this has ontological and explanatory primacy
powerful idea at its core, arguably we over rational choice. Again this implies
must rely on more complex, contingent, a greater level of generality for the core
and multifaceted behavioral specifica- institutionalist approach.17
tions. In practice, the human agent cannot
As a result, neoclassical economics be a “lightning calculator” (Veblen
could be regarded as a special and 1919, p. 73), quickly, effortlessly, and
(highly) restricted case of the “old” in- inexplicably finding the optimum just as
stitutional economics, which accepted we can readily locate the lowest point of
the ubiquity of habits and rules. In con- a U-curve in a simple textbook diagram.
trast to their image as myopic and anti- Even with given and unambiguous in-
theoretical data-gatherers, institutional- formation, complex optimization prob-
ists have the potential to achieve a lems typically involve difficulties not
higher level of theoretical generality. only of specification but of comput-
Winter (1971) has argued that neoclas- ability. Artificially intelligent systems
sical economics is a special case of be- even in moderately complex environ-
havioral economics. We may conclude, ments require “inherited” framing pro-
further, that both behavioral economics cedures to structure the incoming infor-
and neoclassical economics are special mation (Zenon Pylyshyn 1986).
cases of institutional economics. At its
foundations, institutional economics has C. Evolution and the Limits
greater generality and encompasses to Rationality
neoclassical economics as a special case.
Strikingly, recent developments in
B. The Ubiquity of Habits and Rules evolutionary psychology (Cosmides and
The importance of habits and rules is Tooby 1994a, 1994b; Plotkin 1994; Re-
underlined by consideration of types of ber 1993) give strong support to the
decision situation or procedure other “old” institutionalist idea of the primacy
than optimization, such as decision of habits. The key argument in this lit-
making in the context of complexity or erature is that postulates concerning
uncertainty. In particular, Ronald the rational capacities of the human
Heiner (1983) has shown that individu- brain must give an explanation of their
als are obliged to rely on relatively sim- evolution according to established prin-
ple procedures and decision-rules in ciples of evolutionary biology.
such situations. There are long and es- What may be termed the Principle of
tablished arguments that individuals 17 Clark (1918, p. 25) also wrote: “a good hedon-
must rely on “conventions” or “rules of ist would stop calculating when it seemed likely to
thumb” in situations of radical uncer- involve more trouble than it was worth.” Hence
Simon’s concept of satisficing behavior finds a
tainty (Keynes 1937; Simon 1957). clear precedent in the work of an “old” institu-
Skilled deployment of rules must also tional economist.
188 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXVI (March 1998)

Evolutionary Explanation demands that as adaptive or (near) optimal behavior


any behavioral assumption in the social differs markedly from situation to situ-
sciences must itself be capable of expla- ation. Second: “Combinatorial explosion
nation along (Darwinian) evolutionary paralyzes even moderately domain-gen-
lines. 18 However, the empirical and eral systems when encountering real-
theoretical work of modern evolution- world complexity. As generality is in-
ary psychologists suggests that, even in creased by adding new dimensions to a
highly intelligent organisms, global ra- problem space or new branch points to
tionality is very unlikely to emerge a decision tree, the computational load
through evolution. In other words, the increases with catastrophic rapidity”
standard assumption of the rational ac- (Cosmides and Tooby 1994a, p. 56).
tor fails to satisfy the Principle of Evo- Third, the generality of all-purpose
lutionary Explanation. mechanisms undermines their perfor-
In an evolutionary view of intelli- mance: “when the environment is
gence it is recognized that tacit knowl- clueless, the mechanism will be too.
edge and implicit learning of an habit- Domain-specific mechanisms are not
ual character are ubiquitous even in limited in this way. They can be con-
higher animals, including humans. This structed to fill in the blanks when per-
is because higher levels of deliberation ceptual evidence is lacking or difficult
and consciousness are recent arrivals on to obtain” (p. 57). As a result: “The
the evolutionary scene, and certainly mind is probably more like a Swiss army
came after the development of more ba- knife than an all-purpose blade” (p. 60).
sic mechanisms of cognition and learn- In evolutionary terms, time does not
ing in organisms. That being the case, “hammer logic into men.” Cosmides
many of our evolved cognitive processes and Tooby produced evidence that hu-
must be able to proceed below the level mans are generally poor at solving gen-
of full deliberation and awareness. eral, logical problems. However, when
Cosmides and Tooby (1994a) postu- these problems are reformulated in
late that the mind is riddled with func- terms of social interactions, our ability
tionally specific circuits. This contrasts to solve them increases markedly, de-
with what they describe as the “Stan- spite the fact that the logical structure
dard Social Science Model,” where the of the problem has not changed. This is
mind harbors general cognitive pro- clear evidence of special design in
cesses—such as “reasoning,” “induc- brain, rather than ability to solve gen-
tion,” and “learning”—that are “con- eral logical problems. 19
text-independent,” “domain-general,” Theories of human behavior must be
or “context-free.” They show that this consistent with our understanding of
abstract and generalist view of the mind evolutionary origins: “The human brain
is difficult to reconcile with modern did not fall out of the sky, an inscruta-
evolutionary biology, giving experimen- ble artefact of unknown origin, and
tal evidence to support their argument. there is no longer any sensible reason
A key argument is that all-purpose for studying it in ignorance of the
optimizing techniques are difficult to causal processes that constructed it”
construct and utilize. First, what counts
19 Significantly, Plotkin has distanced evolution-
18 Without giving it a name, Veblen (1934, pp. ary psychology from genetic reductionism. He ar-
79–80) clearly made use of this principle, in his gues that intelligent behavior “cannot be reduc-
discussions of the origins of habits, purposeful be- tively explained by genetics or genetics and
havior, and so on. development” (Plotkin 1994, p. 176).
Hodgson: Institutional Economics 189

(Cosmides and Tooby 1994a, p. 68). Ap- more widely accepted—and equally
plied to economics itself, this principle valid—notion that institutions, know-
establishes the untenability of the ingly or unknowingly, are formed and
prominent assumption “that rational be- changed by individuals.
havior is the state of nature, requiring It has been suggested above that the
no explanation” (Cosmides and Tooby breakdown of the microfoundations
1994b, p. 327). If rational behavior is to project provides institutionalism with a
be assumed, then its evolution has to be significant entrée. Its focus on institu-
explained. tions as durable and typically self-rein-
The reintroduction of the concepts of forcing entities provides a convenient
habit and instinct into a theory of hu- micro-macro link. To see the role of the
man behavior helps to provide a founda- individual in relation to institutions is to
tion upon which a theory of institutions focus on the micro aspect. To take the
can be built. We have shown that the institution as a socially constructed in-
grounding of such a theory on the idea variant—or emergent property—is a ba-
of the given, rational individual is both sis for consideration of macroeconomic
unsuccessful, and untenable in ongoing, dynamics and behavior. Accordingly,
evolutionary terms. The introduction of “old” institutionalists and mainstream
habit and instinct provides a consis- economists have a great deal to learn
tency between the socio-economic and from each other.
biotic levels of analysis, and establishes However, some would dismiss those
an important link between the socio- scholars that reject the rational actor
economic and the natural world. The in- paradigm as being outside “economics,”
stitutional action-information loop no and consign them to “sociology.” In re-
longer hangs in empty space: it has a sponse, these vigilantes of “economic
biotic grounding. correctness” have to face two severe
This does not mean that explanations problems. First, leading economists
of socio-economic phenomena have to such as Smith, Ricardo, Marx, Keynes,
be in biological terms. Socio-economic Hayek, Simon, and Coase, all failed to
reality has emergent properties that incorporate the standard picture of “ra-
defy such a reduction. They are differ- tional economic man” in their writings
ent levels of analysis, but, ultimately, or expressed profound misgivings about
propositions at one level do have to be his behavior. Second, the problem also
consistent with those at another. This is has to be faced that much of “sociology”
a key reason why economics has to take has now embraced rational choice (for
account of evolutionary biology (Hodg- example, James Coleman 1990).
son 1993). Among twentieth century economists
the prevailing practice has been to re-
VI. Conclusion gard the subject as being defined not as
a study of a real object—the economy—
By institutions, individuals are not but in terms of a single approach and
merely constrained and influenced. set of core assumptions. If the subject is
Jointly with our natural environment defined in this way then not much
and our biotic inheritance, as social be- theoretical pluralism within economics
ings we are constituted by institutions. is possible; we are stuck with a single
They are given by history and constitute type of theory or approach. Elsewhere,
our socio-economic flesh and blood. however, a science is normally defined
This proposition must cohabit with the as the study of a particular aspect of ob-
190 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXVI (March 1998)

jective reality: physics is about the na- and fundamental precepts will be the
ture and properties of matter and en- principles of evolution themselves, still
ergy, biology about living things, psy- taking strong inspiration from the meth-
chology about the psyche, and so on. It odology and approach of Darwin. We
is on the basis of their wish to study and shall thereby take a huge step back in
understand real world economies that time and visit the evolutionary contro-
the “old” institutionalists can retain versies of the 1890s and early 1900s—
claim to the title of being economists. and the intellectual world of Peirce,
In fact, the boundary between eco- James, Veblen, and Commons—and dis-
nomics and sociology that has endured cover that much of what we want to say
by the prevailing consensus for the last has already been said before. Only then
60 years or so is now being violated on will we be able to read the works of the
both sides. The line of demarcation de- “old” institutionalists and fully appreci-
fined by “the science of rational choice” ate their achievement.
is thus losing its legitimacy, and the REFERENCES
most reasonable alternative is to at-
A LCHIAN, ARMEN A. “Uncertainty, Evolution and
tempt once again to redefine economics Economic Theory,” J. Polit. Econ., June 1950,
as the intellectual discipline concerned 58(2), pp. 211–21.
with the study of economic systems. In A RROW , K ENNETH J. “Rationality of Self and Oth-
ers in an Economic System,” J. Bus., 59(4), Oct.
other words, it should be defined, as in 1986, pp. S385–99; reprinted in R OBIN M.
other sciences, in terms of its object of H OGARTH AND MELVIN W. R EDER, eds. Ra-
analysis, rather than by any set of prior tional choice: the contrast Between economics
and psychology. Chicago and London: U. of
tenets. Chicago Press, . 1986, pp. 201–15.
It may be conjectured that the loss of B AKER, WAYNE E. “The Social Structure of a Na-
the reigning twentieth-century bounda- tional Securities Market,” Amer. J. Sociology,,
Jan. 1984, 89(4), pp. 775–811.
ries between the social sciences fore- B ECKER , G ARY S. “Irrational Behavior and Eco-
shadows a great centennial climacteric nomic Theory,” J. Polit. Econ. 70(1), Feb.
in these intellectual disciplines. For 1962, pp. 1–13.
———. “Habits, Addictions, and Traditions,” Kyk-
long the butt of the critic from the het- los, 1992, 45(3), pp. 327–45.
erodox fringes, rational economic man ———. Accounting for tastes. Cambridge, MA:
has increasingly come under challenge Harvard U. Press, 1996.
B HASKAR , R OY. The possibility of naturalism: A
from the mainstream in recent years, philosophical critique of the contemporary hu-
partly because of developments in game man sciences. Brighton: Harvester, 1979.
theory. It has been suggested by leading B OULDING , KENNETH E. Evolutionary economics.
Beverly Hills, CA: Sage Publications, 1981.
economists such as Frank Hahn (1991) B UCHANAN, J AMES M. “Is Economics the Science
that one of the central responses to the of Choice?” in Roads to freedom: Essays in
developing crisis will be the deconstruc- honor of Friedrich A. von Hayek. Eds.: E RICH
STREISSLER ET AL.. London: Routledge and
tion of the rational actor that has long Kegan Paul, 1969, pp. 47–64.
ruled economics. Optimizing activity CHIAROMONTE , FRANCESCA AND DOSI ,
will be recognized as no more than a GIOVANNI . “Heterogeneity, Competition, and
Macroeconomic Dynamics,” Structural Change
special case of a larger set of possible and Economic Dynamics, June 1993, 4(1), pp.
modes of behavior, with all of them be- 39–63.
ing required to render viable explana- CHOI , Y OUNG B ACK . Paradigms and conventions:
Uncertainty, decision making, and en-
tions of their origin and evolution. trepreneurship. Ann Arbor: U. of Michigan
Biology is widely seen as the science Press, 1993.
of the twenty-first century. Following CLARK , J OHN M AURICE . “Economics and Modern
Psychology” Parts I and II, J. Polit. Econ., Jan.-
this lead—and to conjecture further—in Feb. 1918, 26(1–2), pp. 1–30, 136–66; reprinted
the renewed social sciences the uniting in J OHN MAURICE CLARK . Preface to social eco-
Hodgson: Institutional Economics 191
nomics. New York: Augustus Kelley, 1967, pp. Friedrich August Hayek. Vol. I. Ed.: W. W.
92–169. B ARTLEY III. London: Routledge, 1988.
COHEN , J ACK AND S TEWART , I AN. The collapse of H EINER , RONALD A. “The Origin of Predictable
chaos: Discovering simplicity in a complex Behavior,” Amer. Econ. Rev., Dec. 1983, 73(4),
world. London and New York: Viking, 1994. pp. 560–95.
COLEMAN , J AMES S. Foundations of social the- H ODGSON, G EOFFREY M. Economics and institu-
ory. Cambridge, MA: Harvard U. Press, 1990. tions: A manifesto for a modern institutional
COMMONS , J OHN R. The legal foundations of economics. Cambridge: Polity Press; Philadel-
capitalism. New York: Macmillan, 1924. phia: U. of Pennsylvania Press, 1988.
———. Institutional economics: Its place in politi- ——— . Economics and evolution: Bringing
cal economy. New York: Macmillan, 1934. life back into economics. Cambridge: Polity
COSMIDES, LEDA AND TOOBY, J OHN. “Beyond Press; Ann Arbor, MI: U. of Michigan Press,
Intuition and Instinct Blindness: Toward an 1993.
Evolutionarily Rigorous Cognitive Science,” ——— . “The Ubiquity of Habits and Rules,”
Cognition, Apr.-June 1994a, 50(1–3), pp. 41– Cambridge J. Econ., Nov. 1997, 21(6), pp. 663–
77. 84.
———. “Better than Rational: Evolutionary Psy- H ODGSON, GEOFFREY M.; S AMUELS , WARREN J.
chology and the Invisible Hand,” Amer. Econ. AND T OOL , M ARC R., eds. The Elgar compan-
Rev., May 1994b, 84(2), pp. 377–32. ion to institutional and evolutionary economics.
CYERT , R ICHARD M. AND M ARCH , J AMES G. A Aldershot: Edward Elgar, 1994.
behavioral theory of the firm. Engelwood Cliffs, H OUTHAKKER , H ENDRICKS S. AND T AYLOR ,
NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1963. LESTER D. Consumer demand in the United
D EGLER , CARL N. In search of human nature: States, 1929–1970: Analyses and projections.
The decline and revival of Darwinism in Ameri- Cambridge, MA: Harvard U. Press, 1966.
can social thought. Oxford and New York: Ox- KEYNES , J OHN M AYNARD . “The General Theory
ford U. Press, 1991. of Employment,” Quart. J. Econ., Feb. 1937,
D OSI , G IOVANNI . “Institutions and Markets in a 51(1), pp. 209–23; reprinted in Keynes, John
Dynamic World,” Manchester School of Eco- Maynard. The collected writings of John May-
nomics and Social Studies, June 1988, 56(2), nard Keynes. Vol. XIV. The General Theory and
pp. 119–46. after: Part II: Defence and development. Lon-
D UESENBERRY , J AMES S. Income, saving and the don: Macmillan, 1973, pp. 109–23.
theory of consumer behavior. Cambridge MA: L ANGLOIS , R ICHARD N., ed. Economics as a pro-
Harvard U. Press, 1949. cess: Essays in the new institutional economics.
F IELD , A LEXANDER J. “On the Explanation of Cambridge and New York: Cambridge U. Press,
Rules Using Rational Choice Models,” J. Econ. 1986.
Issues, Mar. 1979, 13(1), pp. 49–72. M ASON, R OGER . “Interpersonal Effects on Con-
———. “Microeconomics, Norms, and Rational- sumer Demand in Economic Theory and Mar-
ity,” Econ. Devel. Cult. Change, July 1984, keting Thought, 1890–1950,” J. Econ. Issues,
32(4), pp. 683–711. Sept. 1995, 29(3), pp. 871–81.
GIDDENS , ANTHONY. The constitution of society: M ENGER , CARL. “On the Origins of Money,”
Outline of the theory of structuration. Cam- Econ. J. , June 1892, 2(2), pp. 239–55.
bridge: Polity Press, 1984. ——— . “Geld,” in The collected works of Carl
GODE , D HANANJAY K. AND S UNDER , S HYAM . “Al- Menger. Vol. IV. Schriften über Geldtheorie
locative Efficiency of Markets with Zero-Intelli- und Währungspolitik. London: London School
gence Traders: Market as a Partial Substitute of Economics, 1936, pp. 1–116.
for Individual Rationality,” J. Polit. Econ., Feb. M URPHY , J AMES B. “The Kinds of Order in Soci-
1993, 101(1), pp. 119–37. ety,” in Natural images in economic thought:
GRANOVETTER , M ARK . “Economic Action and So- Markets read in tooth and claw. Ed.: P HILIP
cial Structure: The Problem of Embeddedness,” M IROWSKI . Cambridge and New York: Cam-
Amer. J. Sociology, Nov. 1985, 91(3), pp. 481– bridge U. Press, 1994, pp. 536–82.
510. N ELSON, R ICHARD R. AND WINTER , S IDNEY G.
GREEN , FRANCIS . “The Consumption Function: A An evolutionary theory of economic change,.
Study of a Failure in Positive Economics,” in Cambridge, MA: Harvard U. Press, 1982.
Issues in political economy: A critical approach. N ORTH , DOUGLASS C. Structure and change in
Eds.: FRANCIS GREEN AND PETTER NORE . economic history. New York: Norton, 1981.
London: Macmillan, 1979, pp. 33–60. ——— . Institutions, institutional change, and eco-
H AHN , F RANK H. “The Next Hundred Years,” nomic performance. Cambridge: Cambridge U.
Econ. J. , Jan. 1991, 101(404), pp. 47–50. Press, 1990.
H AMILTON, W ALTON H. “Institution,” in Encyclo- PLOTKIN, H ENRY C. Darwin machines and the
paedia of the social sciences. Eds.: EDWIN R. A. nature of knowledge: Concerning adaptations,
SELIGMAN AND A LVIN J OHNSON. New York: instinct, and the evolution of intelligence. Har-
Macmillan, 1932, Vol. 8, pp. 84–89. mondsworth: Penguin, 1994.
H AYEK , FRIEDRICH A. VON The fatal conceit: The POLANYI, K ARL . The great transformation. New
errors of socialism. The collected works of York: Rinehart, 1944.
192 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXVI (March 1998)
POLANYI , M ICHAEL . The tacit dimension. Lon- T OOL , M ARC R. “Contributions to an Institutional
don: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1966. Theory of Price Determination,” in Rethinking
POLLAK , R OBERT A. “Habit Formation and Dy- economics: Markets, technology and economic
namic Demand Functions,” J. Polit. Econ., July- evolution. Eds.: GEOFFREY M. H ODGSON AND
Aug. 1970, 78(4), pp. 745–63. ERNESTO SCREPANTI . Aldershot: Edward El-
PYLYSHYN, ZENON W., ed. The Robot’s dilemma: gar, 1991, pp. 19–39.
The frame problem in artificial intelligence. V ANBERG , V IKTOR J. Rules and choice in econom-
Norwood, NJ: Ablex, 1986. ics. London: Routledge, 1994.
POSNER , R ICHARD A. Economic analysis of law. V EBLEN , T HORSTEIN B. The theory of the leisure
Boston: Little, Brown, 1973. class: An economic study in the evolution of in-
R EBER, A RTHUR S. Implicit learning and tacit stitutions. New York: Macmillan, 1899.
knowledge: An essay on the cognitive uncon- ———. The instinct of workmanship, and the state
scious. Oxford: Oxford U. Press, 1993. of the industrial arts. New York: Augustus
R IZVI , S. A BU T URAB . “The Microfoundations Pro- Kelley, 1914.
ject in General Equilibrium Theory,” Cam- ———. The place of science in modern civilisation
bridge J. Econ., Aug. 1994, 18(4), pp. 357–77. and other essays. New York: Huebsch, 1919.
R UTHERFORD , M ALCOLM C. Institutions in eco- ———. Essays on our changing order. Ed.: L EON
nomics: The old and the new institutionalism. ARDZROONI . New York: The Viking Press,
Cambridge and New York: Cambridge U. Press, 1934.
1994. WARE , C AROLINE F. AND M EANS , GARDINER C.
S CHOTTER, ANDREW . The economic theory of so- The modern economy in action. New York: Har-
cial institutions. Cambridge and New York: court Brace, 1936.
Cambridge U. Press, 1981. WHITE , H ARRISON C. Identity and control: A
S IMON , H ERBERT A. Models of man: social and structural theory of social action. Princeton:
rational; Mathematical essays on rational hu- Princeton U. Press, 1992.
man behavior in a social setting. New York: WILLIAMSON, O LIVER E. Markets and hierar-
Wiley, 1957. chies, analysis and anti-trust implications: A
———. “Rational Decision Making in Business study in the economics of internal organization.
Organizations,” Amer. Econ. Rev., Sept. 1979, New York: Free Press, 1975.
pp. 69(4), 493–513. ———. “Credible Commitments: Using Hostages
S TIGLITZ , J OSEPH E. Whither socialism? Cam- to Support Exchange,” Amer. Econ. Rev., Sept.
bridge, MA: MIT Press, 1994. 1983, 74(3), pp. 519–40.
S UGDEN , R OBERT . The economics of rights, co- WINTER , SIDNEY G., JR . “Satisficing, Selection,
operation, and welfare. Oxford: Blackwell, and the Innovating Remnant,” Quart. J. Econ.,
1986. May 1971, 85(2), pp. 237–61.

You might also like