You are on page 1of 4

Enactivism

Varela’s Sixth Step Steve Torrance

with certain biological structures of our or- tioned, from Edmund Husserl to Maurice to scientific practices). If VE is committed
ganisms, especially of our brains. Based on Merleau-Ponty and to Jonas, despite their to phenomenology, then it has to admit the
shared similar biological structures, we are differences, share a basic set of methodologi- methodologically and ontologically irreduc-
then justified in attributing an (analogical) cal concerns: the inseparability of being and ible status of the experiential dimension. The
counterpart of our own qualia (the phenom- appearing; the transcendental function of alternative is a (mis)use of some phenom-
enality of vision) to the nonhuman being. the human first-person perspective; the crit- enological insights for other purposes. How-
But Villalobos and Ward’s presentation gives ical rejection of the “natural attitude” and of ever, it should be noted that this description
rise to another ambivalence with regard to reductionism as an explanatory strategy; the of the situation is not tantamount to denying
the meaning of “experience”: either, by al- reference to the prescientific lifeworld as the every possibility of naturalizing phenom-
lowing a “narrower range of experiential grounding source of sense and knowledge enology by rethinking the modern concept
[i.e., epiphenomenal; P. G.] properties” (§36), (Zahavi 2007: 13–35). According to this, any of nature according to a “redefined non-re-
it differs only gradually from anthropomor- phenomenological analysis, in its default ductionist naturalism” (Gallagher 2012: 89);
phist VE; or it implicitly assigns to the vague setting or starting position, strictly implies but what it rejects is to construe the relation
term “experience” an entirely third-person a – not necessarily idealistic (Gaitsch 2014) between naturalization and anthropomor-
“structural” meaning, devoid of any expe- – kind of correlationism of human subjec- phism as an unresolvable conflict.
riential or phenomenal dimension – this, tivity and world. Concerning the phenom-
of course, despite assertions to the contrary enological inter-subjective analysis of non- Peter Gaitsch gained his PhD from the University
(§37). What is worse, Villalobos and Ward’s human life, it may well be the case that the of Vienna in 2013 with a thesis in metaphilosophy.
reading of Maturana provides us with a phenomenological default setting could be He is a faculty member at the Department of
rather mutilated or poor phenomenology methodologically transformed in order to Theology, University of Graz. His current research
of the living being. Because they focus nar- correspond to nonhuman forms of life ­– this interests are in the fields of phenomenology,
rowly on similarities with respect to sensory is precisely the important role of Husserl’s philosophy of biology and philosophy of religion.
systems and moreover postulate the “incom- genetic method of Abbau ­(“unbuilding” or
mensurability” (§32) between human (“lin- “dismantling” the full-blown human sub- Received: 8 February 2015
guistic”) and nonhuman (“non-linguistic”) jectivity) with regard to biological life (Hus- Accepted: 16 February 2016
experiences, they do not consider the high serl 1973: 112–117). However, due to this
phenomenological relevance of factual “be- methodological structure, phenomenology
havioural interactions” (§28) between hu- cannot do without attributing at least a basic
man and nonhuman beings. They end up by kind of minimal subjectivity, characterized Varela’s Sixth Step:
describing nonhuman organisms as epiphe- as a site for the appearing of the world, to
nomenal living systems, insofar as all caus- the nonhuman “minimal organism” (Varela
Teleology and the Re-
ally relevant dimensions of experience, in 1997: 81). Note that these conditions also Visioning of Science
particular all volitional aspects with their apply to the work of Merleau-Ponty – to
“intrinsic teleology” (Weber & Varela 2002: whom the authors refer to as being a more Steve Torrance
110), are ruled out (§36). Probably, it is their promising alternative to Jonas (§23, §38) – University of Sussex, UK
intent to save the causal closure of the physi- since Merleau-Ponty’s general focus on the stevet/at/sussex.ac.uk
cal that leads them to the biased phenom- living and lived body – on “the dynamics 221
enology of pigeons, since taking into account of our bodily engagement with the world” > Upshot • Jonas was not defending an
certain behavioural interactions, between (§38) – is not meant to lead to an objectiv- unrestrained anthropomorphism but,
the pigeon hunter and the pigeon, in the istic or utterly third-personal grounding of rather, a “zoomorphism,” which offered
course of poisoning pigeons in the park, may subjectivity, but precisely to a primordial a rigorous, considered view of the deep
have easily led to the conviction that these kind of subjectivity. Therefore, providing a phylogenetic origins of purpose and
creatures indeed strive to stay alive. reductive explanation “of how our subjective mind. Jonas did not reject science per se,
« 5 »  Since Villalobos and Ward still lives emerge” (§38) is not a job that can ever but an alienated, rigid conception of the
defend the idea of incorporating phenom- be assumed by phenomenology, because latter. His work helped pave the way to a
enology into cognitive science, they opt for phenomenology is methodologically intrin- richer science of mind.
a phenomenology without anthropomor- sically linked with top-down anthropomor-
phism (§23), which should provide “a natu- phism in the style of MA. Given this, it is The five steps – and a sixth
ralistically acceptable explanation of how our highly questionable how a “bottom-up phe- « 1 »  There is no doubt that Andeas We-
subjective lives emerge from the dynamics nomenology of biological systems” (Welton ber and Francisco Varela’s (2002) celebrated
of our bodily engagement with the world” 2011: 102) could operate at all. paeon to Hans Jonas was considered a land-
(§38; my emphasis). At this point, I have the « 6 »  From a phenomenological per- mark within the enactivist community. But
impression that they overstate the “heteroge- spective, I finally want to suggest a philo- was it a “wrong turn”? And how distinctive
neity of phenomenology” (§3). For it seems sophical answer to the initial question a contribution anyway did Jonas’s thought
well-established that all the authors men- (which we may still leave open with regard make to enactivism?

http://constructivist.info/11/2/204.villalobos
« 2 »  In order to answer that question, rela how he saw Jonas’s strongly teleological or slugs have intrinsic purposes? Let us not
we must first consider the key elements of stance, given the anti-teleological slant that judge that either way for now: but we cer-
“canonical enactivism.” One source for this Varela had inherited from his original work tainly cannot assume at the outset that any
(among many that could be selected) is to be with Maturana on autopoiesis. Varela was attribution of purpose to non-human agents
found in Evan Thompson’s tribute to Varela initially tentative: he preferred to see auto- or processes must be inescapably anthropo-
presented at a commemorative meeting in poiesis as a source of original intentionality morphic. To do so is to beg the question of
Paris (Thompson 2004; see also Thompson (aka sense-making) rather than of original how and where intrinsic purpose is found in
2007: Part II). Thompson’s lecture explic- teleology. However, in a later exchange Va- the natural world.
itly considers Jonas’s contribution to Varela’s rela indicated that he had come to have a « 9 »  In order to establish Jonas’s unac-
thought, among many other currents in Va- “broader view” about what autopoietic theo- ceptable anthropomorphism, the authors
rela’s work. ry implied: “in a funny way you do recover a quote variously from The Phenomenon of
« 3 »  Thompson elaborates five key full fledged teleology … [that is] intrinsic to Life (Jonas 1966; hereafter PL) They start by
steps, which offers one way of summing life in action” (Thompson 2004: 395 fn 9; see reproducing at some length (§12) the open-
up the core of mature Varelian enactivism. also Thompson 2007: ch. 5 fn 7). This was ing remarks of that book. However – again
I here reduce Thompson’s already concise the additional Jonasian step, which was de- puzzlingly – the quotation from Jonas starts
outline (2004: 386f)1 to a set of paraphrases. fended with some vigour by Andreas Weber with a critique of anthropomorphism, or at
(I) Life = Autopoiesis: the conditions of au- and Varela in their paper “Life after Kant” least of anthropocentrism:
topoiesis are necessary and sufficient for the (Weber & Varela 2002; see also Weber 2002).
organization of minimal life. (II) Autopoiesis Is it a mis-step? “ Contemporary existentialism,  obsessed with
Philosophical Concepts in Enactivism

entails minimal selfhood: an organic iden- « 6 »  VW claim that Jonas’s existential man alone, is in the habit of claiming as his unique
tity. (III) Selfhood entails the emergence of a slant on biological facts assumes an egre- privilege and predicament much of what is rooted
world – “a correlative domain of interactions
proper to that self.” (IV) Self + world jointly
gious anthropomorphism, which is incom-
patible with enactivism’s claims to provide

in organic existence as such … (PL: ix; empha-
ses added)
entail sense-making: the world of an organ- an alternative science of mind. I challenge
ism is a source of appetitive significance. (V) VW’s case for convicting Jonas of an il- « 10 »  Jonas wishes to distance him-
Sense-making = cognition, in the minimal legitimate anthropomorphism; and I also self from the stress on the human sphere
sense of sensorimotor activity to maintain argue that their notion of what makes for a that he found to dominate contemporary
autopoietic viability within the organism’s legitimate scientific enquiry is rigid and un- existential and phenomenological writing.
world of significations. examined, and ignores or misunderstands a Instead, his project was to apply a phenom-
« 4 »  I suggest that Jonas’s major con- distinctive enactivist conception of science enological perspective across the organic
tribution is that he enabled Varela to take already well-elaborated by Varela and oth- world. But in doing so, he was not trying
a further step: (VI) Sense-making/cognition ers prior to the “Jonasian turn.” Jonas’s work to impose anthropic categories upon non-
entails immanent teleology. Any autopoi- should continue to be taken seriously as a human living species in a simple-minded
etic system defines itself as an intrinsically key source for elaborating the strong life– and anti-scientific way. His aim was not to
purposive identity. This was an important mind continuity – although his importance eliminate science but to transform it. He saw
new step – a definite move away from the within enactivism can be overstressed. the mechanistic scientific wisdom of his day
222 original conception of autopoiesis. As Mario as wedded to a conception of biology that
Villalobos and Dave Ward (hereafter VW) Is the Jonasian turn a wrong turn? problematized the subjective, experiential
point out (e.g., § 26), the classical theory « 7 »  Anthropomorphism, as VW char- dimension of life, and foreclosed the ques-
of autopoiesis “conceives of living beings acterise it, is “the practice of attributing hu- tion of teleology in organic existence.
as mechanistic and deterministic systems, man features to nonhuman entities” (§5). « 11 »  In the face of overly man-obsessed
hence as entities without purpose, freedom An illustration they give of an illegitimate phenomenology, and of overly mechanism-
of action or intentional properties.” Or as use of anthropomorphism is that of talking obsessed science, Jonas proposed a unifying
Humberto Maturana and Varela put it them- of a river as “wanting to reach” or “having perspective that coalesced the  human into
selves: “Living systems, as physical autopoi- the purpose of reaching” the sea. While fine the broadly organic sphere. This is surely a
etic machines, are purposeless systems” as a figurative description, this cannot, they profoundly non-anthropomorphic stance.
(Maturana & Varela 1980: 86) say, be part of serious scientific theorising. Admittedly, Jonas’s outlook is human-cen-
« 5 »  In a footnote to his Paris lecture, « 8 »  However, the way they present tred in that it reverses a scientized “alien-
Thompson refers to email exchanges he had their illustrative example is puzzling. When ation of man from himself ” (cf. PL: 37, cited
with Varela in 1999. Both had recently been purposes are attributed to rivers, etc. in this by VW at §18) But it also reverses the alien-
reading Jonas’s work. Thompson asked Va- way, there is usually no specific mention of ation of humans from our fellow-creatures
human purposes. The allusion is to purpo- implied by anthropocentric viewpoints. For
1 | See Thompson (2007: ch. 6) for a revised sive action in general – and that could just Jonas, the significant demarcation was be-
version of these five steps and associated discus- as easily cover a lion stalking its prey or a tween the living and the non-living – more
sion. slug edging towards a lettuce-plant. Do lions specifically, between systems endowed with,

Constructivist Foundations vol. 11, N°2


Enactivism
Varela’s Sixth Step Steve Torrance

and systems lacking, a self-maintaining me- book, and in many different ways – a point to be expanded to incorporate rigorous phe-
tabolism. In this respect, of course, he is on summed up in his often-quoted phrase that nomenology. So, too, with the hard prob-
all fours with autopoiesis theorists, except, “life can only be known by life.” A proper lem of teleology: Varela came finally to see,
of course, he was not aware of the theoretical understanding of the “needful freedom” of through the lens of Jonas’s work, that this
machinery of autopoiesis and how it might the organism can be achieved only because could be treated in a similar way.
support his view. the scientist is also herself a needful, organic
« 12 »  VW cite various passages from centre of concern. Far from rejecting sci- Jonas situated
the early parts of PL to show Jonas’s unac- ence, this is to re-vision science, to re-score « 17 »  So – at least on the basis of the
ceptable anthropomorphism. In relation to the scientific enterprise in a new key. Such selections of PL that they have quoted in
one such passage, they observe that Jonas an approach is wholly of a piece with a key their target article – VW’s case against Jonas
“finds that ‘the anathema on any kind of message of The Embodied Mind (Varela, seems weak. Where Jonas appears to write
anthropomorphism’ proves to be, on closer Thompson & Rosch 1991) and later writings in defence of “anthropomorphism” he is be-
examination, more ‘a prejudice’ than an em- by Varela and other enactivists: a science of ing rhetorical, and is in any case putting for-
pirically demonstrated principle” (§19; PL: mind must be more than a merely third- ward a “zoomorphism” rather than any spe-
23). They see this and other of his remarks person statement of the causal processes of cifically human-centred account of life. His
as evidence that Jonas is rejecting “science” an objectivised world. It must also embrace rich attribution of psychological categories,
and allowing himself simply to spread hu- the first-person perspective of the scientist’s including teleological notions, to primitive
man-like purposes across organismic nature lived experience – the embodied, concernful organisms is found in many other writers,
in a way that evades scientific rigour or justi- subjectivity that is inescapably part of own- both within and outside the enactivist tra-
fication. However, for some reason VW have ing a mind. (This is not to do with the spe- dition.
chosen to suppress, from the latter citation, cifically human nature of how we come to « 18 »  A general doubt can be raised
an important element in this passage. A recognize subjectivity and purpose in crea- as to propriety of applying such terms as
fuller quotation from the original text reads: tures, but with our animate being.) “sense-making,” and other rich psychologi-
« 15 »  In the Paris lecture referred to cal terms, to a variety of primitive organ-
“ The anathema on any kind of anthropomor-
phism, even of zoomorphism, in connection with
earlier, Thompson expands on how this es-
sential message from The Embodied Mind
isms, including bacteria moving up sugar-
gradients. It could also be debated whether
nature… may turn out to be, in this extreme form, has been taken less seriously than other metabolic or autopoietic organization alone

a prejudice. (PL: 23, emphasis added) messages from that work. He writes: is sufficient to justify such attributions. But
this is an issue that has to be discussed in
And compare this remark, not cited by VW: “  if I may be bold, I think that … the book’s
central theme has yet to be fully absorbed. That
relation to a whole variety of writers, not to
Jonas alone. (See, for example, Ezequiel Di
“  Anthropomorphism at all events, and even
zoomorphism in general, became scientific high
theme is the need for back-and-forth circulation
between scientific research on the mind and dis-
Paolo 2005; Thompson 2007, for discussion
of one dimension of criticism; and Margaret

treason. (PL: 37; emphasis added) ciplined phenomenologies of lived experience.
(Thompson 2004: 382)
” Boden 2000 for a more robust skepticism;
also Lynn Margulis and Dorion Sagan 1995;
« 13 »  Contrary to VW’s claims, Jonas Maxine Sheets-Johnstone 1999 for a defence
should surely be read, in these passages, as « 16 »  Thompson traces the way in of such rich attributions) 223
asserting, in the face of a scientific ontologi- which the development of Varela’s ideas on « 19 »  To sum up, Jonas does not seek
cal correctness, the right to apply psycho- neurophenomenology in the mid-1990s to reject science but to deepen and en-
logical attributions to organic nature, where provided a blueprint for an enhanced form hance it in the light of his phenomenology
necessary: this is hardly a chauvinist form of scientific understanding of mind, which of the organism. And his scientific critique
of anthropomorphism. On the basis of the engendered this circulation between science is very much in harmony with that already
quotations given in the target article, when and lived experience. Varela’s (1996) key embraced by Varela prior to the latter’s en-
properly contextualized, Jonas can hardly be paper on neurophenomenology targeted dorsement of Jonas’s work. The distinctive
seen as a committing a deep methodological the “hard problem of consciousness,” the step that Jonas enabled Varela to take was
error. If it is one, then it is endemic through- explanatory gap between brain and lived ex- to affirm that autopoietic or metabolic au-
out writings defending enactivist and auto- perience. As Thompson puts it: “Francisco’s tonomy entailed an intrinsic teleology in liv-
poietic approaches. insight was that no purely third-person, the- ing creatures. Varela was perhaps hampered
oretical proposal or model would suffice to by making such a move earlier because of
Not rejecting but re-visioning overcome this gap” (Thompson 2004: 383). his reluctance to cast himself loose from
science And, quoting directly from Varela’s paper: the mechanistic constraints of classical au-
« 14 »  In fact, throughout this part of “the experiential pole enters directly into topoietic theory. But such a move was in
PL, Jonas is using his discussion of anthro- the formulation of the complete account” any case already encapsulated in the core
pocentrism to make a deep epistemological (Varela 1996: 345). To provide a full scien- enactivist doctrine that autopoiesis implied
point, one that he develops over much of the tific account of consciousness, science had a “surplus of signification” (Varela 1991,

http://constructivist.info/11/2/204.villalobos
1992) or “sense-making” (Varela 1984). If activists fail to draw a terminological as well with respect to teleology, it is a matter of
this richness of psychological attribution to as phenomenal distinction between human inspiration more than endorsement. “The
primitive organisms is to be criticised, it is a agents’ directedness and the directedness theory of autopoiesis can be called upon to
general issue concerning enactivist and re- of other types of biological agents (e.g., Di complement this [Jonas’s] account,” writes
lated approaches, rather than one specific to Paolo 2005; Thompson 2007; Weber & Va- Thompson (2007: 153), by specifying (ibid:
Jonas’s work. rela 2002). 145f) the organizational characteristics of
« 2 »  Despite this initial agreement, we living systems (spelled out on ibid: 97–107)
Steve Torrance is a visiting senior research fellow think that V&W’s overall criticism is mis- that justify speaking of them in intentional
at the Centre for Research in Cognitive Science guided. The reason for this is twofold: first, terms. Di Paolo (2005: 31) suggests that au-
(COGS), University of Sussex, UK. He has written V&W entirely leave aside VE’s attempt to topoiesis “provides a serious scientific ac-
articles and edited collections on issues in enactivist offer scientific justification for their use of count” of the “initial step” of the continual
philosophy, and on the relation between ethics teleological terms such as “intention” and back-and-forth between science and experi-
and the sciences and technologies of mind. “purpose,” and second, while V&W are right ence that is essential to a successful inves-
to criticize VE for its problematic concep- tigation of cognitive phenomena. VE draws
Received: 10 February 2016 tion of intentionality, that conception is on Jonas for a perspective on the study of
Accepted: 11 February 2016 problematic primarily because it pays insuf- living systems, supported by certain use-
ficient attention to human experience, rather ful concepts such as needful freedom. They
than over-generalizing it. We will show that also sometimes appear to have adopted the
their criticism misses its mark for these rea- specific anthropomorphic aspect of Jonas’s
Phenomenological Teleology
Philosophical Concepts in Enactivism

sons, although we agree that fundamental work picked out by V&W, but they do so
aspects of VE are a challenge to its paradig- first and foremost because it is a logical con-
and Human Interactivity matic aspirations. sequence of their interpretation of autopoi-
Rasmus Gahrn-Andersen etic theory, and subsequent development of
Syddansk Universitet, Denmark
Justifying enactive teleology it in terms of immanent purposiveness.
« 3 »  Jonas’s reasons for his anthropo- « 5 »  It is in this specific sense that VE
rga/at/sdu.dk morphic stance on teleology are endorsed speaks of “purposes,” “intentions,” “norms,”
by VE, in the passages indicated by V&W and other anthropomorphically-derived
Matthew Isaac Harvey (§21), but in all cases the endorsement is concepts (Barandiaran, Di Paolo & Rohde
Syddansk Universitet, Denmark either prefatory or ancillary to an argument 2009; Barandiaran & Egbert 2014). For VE,
harvey/at/sdu.dk that relates to Jonas in a different way. Rath- the activity of an organism is intentional
er than choosing one side of the distinction because – or rather, in that – it is organized
> Upshot • We argue that Villalobos and between ontologies that either explicitly into patterns that maintain its organization
Ward’s criticism misses two crucial as- relate to human experience (and so also to over time. This is, or at least can be read as,
pects of Varelian enactivism. These are, teleology) or those that utterly deny that a perfectly legitimate piece of scientific theo-
first, that enactivism attempts to offer phenomenology can play a role in science, rizing, one that can be disputed by present-
a rigorous scientific justification for its VE builds on Jonas’s recognition of a differ- ing evidence that some systems fail to dis-
224 teleological claims, and second, that en- ence between living and non-living systems. play precarious operational closure.
activism in fact pays too little attention For Evan Thompson (2007) and Ezequiel « 6 »  In light of this, V&W’s failure to
to the nature of human phenomenology Di Paolo (2009b), the key point in Jonas is mention this seems very odd, given that they
and intentionality, rather than anthropo- not a phenomenological one but rather an approve of Humberto Maturana’s observer-
morphically over-valuing it. ontological one, namely that only living sys- dependent position (Maturana 2002), and
tems actively regulate their own interactions take it to be unproblematic in its anthropo-
« 1 »  Mario Villalobos and Dave Ward with the environment. VE, following Jonas, morphism, precisely because it is based in
(V&W) criticize Varelian-inspired enactiv- argues that for living systems it is sensible to biological science:
ism (VE) for its apparent anthropomorphic talk of “purposes” and “intentions” as speci-
inclinations. Allegedly, Varela and col-
leagues use human cognition as a model for
fiable patterns in the dynamics of the sys-
tem’s operation. Non-living systems are tak-
“  [Maturana’s autopoietic theory’s] inference
from properties of human sensory experience to
cognition in general. V&W build their argu- en to be non-teleological because they fail to properties of its nonhuman relatives is grounded
ment on several observations with which display these same patterns. This means that by the conviction that our empirically determined
we agree, including (a) that Hans Jonas’s speaking of “purposes” with respect to non- grasp of the structural dynamics of the physiol-
biological phenomenology builds on hu- living systems is strictly metaphorical and so ogy of our sensory systems is our best guide to
man subjectivity in a way that, by his own scientifically inadmissible. the properties of our sensory phenomenology. If
admission, is incompatible with the ontol- « 4 »  This means that V&W mischar- this is right, then we may conclude that similar-
ogy behind the modern scientific method, acterize the relation between VE and Jo- ity in biological structure goes with similarity in
and (b) that Francisco Varela and other en- nas’s biological phenomenology. Especially ”
sensory experience. (§35)

Constructivist Foundations vol. 11, N°2

You might also like