You are on page 1of 12

Four causes

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia


Jump to navigationJump to search
See also: Potentiality and actuality

Aristotle's Four Causes illustrated for a table: material (wood), formal (design), efficient (carpentry), final
(dining).

The "four causes" are elements of an influential principle in Aristotelian thought whereby


explanations of change or movement are classified into four fundamental types of answer to the
question "why?". Aristotle wrote that "we do not have knowledge of a thing until we have grasped its
why, that is to say, its cause."[1][2] While there are cases where identifying a "cause" is difficult, or in
which "causes" might merge, Aristotle held that his four "causes" provided an analytical scheme of
general applicability.[3]
Aitia, from Greek αἰτία, was the word that Aristotle used to refer to the causal explanation that has
traditionally been translated as "cause", but this peculiar specialized, technical, philosophical usage
of the word "cause" does not correspond exactly to its most usual applications in everyday English
language.[4] The translation of Aristotle's αἰτία that is nearest to current ordinary language could be
"question" or "explanation". [5][2][4] In this article, the traditional philosophical usage of the word "cause"
will be employed, but the reader should not be misled by confusing this technical usage with current
ordinary language.
Aristotle held that there were four kinds of answers to "why" questions (in Physics II, 3,
and Metaphysics V, 2):[2][6][5]

 Matter: a change or movement's material cause is the aspect of


the change or movement which is determined by the material that
composes the moving or changing things. For a table, that might be
wood; for a statue, that might be bronze or marble.
 Form: a change or movement's formal cause is a change or
movement caused by the arrangement, shape or appearance of the
thing changing or moving. Aristotle says for example that the ratio
2:1, and number in general, is the cause of the octave.
 Agent: a change or movement's efficient or moving
cause consists of things apart from the thing being changed or
moved, which interact so as to be an agency of the change or
movement. For example, the efficient cause of a table is a
carpenter, or a person working as one, and according to Aristotle
the efficient cause of a boy is a father.
 End or purpose: a change or movement's final cause is that for
the sake of which a thing is what it is. For a seed, it might be an
adult plant. For a sailboat, it might be sailing. For a ball at the top of
a ramp, it might be coming to rest at the bottom.
The four "causes" are not mutually exclusive. For Aristotle, several answers to the question "why"
have to be given to explain a phenomenon and especially the actual configuration of an object. [7] For
example, if asking why a table is such and such, a complete explanation, taking into account the four
causes, would sound like this: This table is solid and brown because it is made of wood (matter), it
does not collapse because it has four legs of equal length (form), it is as such because a carpenter
made it starting from a tree (agent), it has these dimensions because it is to be used by men and
women (end).

Contents

 1Meaning of "cause"
o 1.1Matter
o 1.2Form
o 1.3Agent
o 1.4End
 2In modern science
o 2.1Biology
 3Heidegger on technology
 4Tinbergen's four questions
 5See also
 6Notes
 7References
 8External links

Meaning of "cause"[edit]
In his philosophical writings, Aristotle used the Greek word αἴτιον, aition, a neuter singular form of an
adjective. The Greek word had meant, perhaps originally in a "legal" context, what or who is
"responsible", mostly but not always in a bad sense of "guilt" or "blame"; alternatively it could mean
"to the credit of" someone or something. The appropriation of this word by Aristotle and other
philosophers reflects how the Greek experience of legal practice influenced the concern in Greek
thought to determine what is responsible.[8] The word developed other meanings, including its use in
philosophy in a more abstract sense.[9][10] About a century before Aristotle, the anonymous author of
the Hippocratic text On Ancient Medicine had described the essential characteristics of a cause: "We
must, therefore, consider the causes of each [medical] condition to be those things which are such
that, when they are present, the condition necessarily occurs, but when they change to another
combination, it ceases."[11] In the present context, Aristotle used the four causes to provide different
answers to the question, "because of what?" The four answers to this question illuminate different
aspects of how a thing comes into being or of how an event takes place. [12]
Matter[edit]
Aristotle considers the material "cause" (hyle)[13] of an object as equivalent to the nature of the raw
material out of which the object is composed. (The word "nature" for Aristotle applies to both its
potential in the raw material and its ultimate finished form. In a sense this form already existed in the
material: see potentiality and actuality.)
Whereas modern physics looks to simple bodies, Aristotle's physics instead treated living things as
exemplary. However, he felt that simple natural bodies such as earth, fire, air, and water also
showed signs of having their own innate sources of motion, change, and rest. Fire, for example,
carries things upwards, unless stopped from doing so. Things like beds and cloaks, formed by
human artifice, have no innate tendency to become beds or cloaks.[14]
In traditional Aristotelian philosophical terminology, material is not the same as substance. Matter
has parallels with substance in so far as primary matter serves as the substratum for simple bodies
which are not substance: sand and rock (mostly earth), rivers and seas (mostly water), atmosphere
and wind (mostly air and then mostly fire below the moon). In this traditional terminology, 'substance'
is a term of ontology, referring to really existing things; only individuals are said to be substance
(subjects) in the primary sense. Secondary substance, in a different sense, also applies to man-
made artifacts.
Form[edit]
Further information: Platonic realism
Aristotle considers the formal "cause" (eidos)[13] as describing the pattern or form which when
present makes matter into a particular type of thing, which we recognize as being of that particular
type.
By Aristotle's own account, this is a difficult and controversial concept.[citation needed] It links with theories of
forms such as those of Aristotle's teacher, Plato, but in Aristotle's own account (see
his Metaphysics), he takes into account many previous writers who had expressed opinions about
forms and ideas, but he shows how his own views differ from them. [15]
Agent[edit]
Aristotle defines the agent or efficient "cause" (kinoun)[13] of an object as that which causes change
and drives transient motion (such as a painter painting a house) (see Aristotle, Physics II 3, 194b29).
In many cases, this is simply the thing that brings something about. For example, in the case of a
statue, it is the person chiseling away which transforms a block of marble into a statue. Only this one
of the four causes is like what an ordinary English-speaker would regard as a cause. [16]
End[edit]
Main article: Teleology
Aristotle defines the end, purpose, or final "cause" (telos)[13] as that for the sake of which a thing is
done.[17] Like the form, this is a controversial type of explanation in science; some have argued for its
survival in evolutionary biology,[18] while Ernst Mayr denied that it continued to play a role.[19] It is
commonly recognised[20] that Aristotle's conception of nature is teleological in the sense
that Nature exhibits functionality in a more general sense than is exemplified in the purposes that
humans have. As discussed further below, Aristotle observed that a telos does not necessarily
involve deliberation, intention, consciousness, or intelligence. An example of a relevant passage
occurs in Physics II.8, where he writes:
This is most obvious in the animals other than man: they make things neither by art nor after inquiry
or deliberation. That is why people wonder whether it is by intelligence or by some other faculty that
these creatures work, – spiders, ants, and the like... It is absurd to suppose that purpose is not
present because we do not observe the agent deliberating. Art does not deliberate. If the ship-
building art were in the wood, it would produce the same results by nature. If, therefore, purpose is
present in art, it is present also in nature. [21]
For example, according to Aristotle, a seed has the eventual adult plant as its end (i.e., as its telos) if
and only if the seed would become the adult plant under normal circumstances. [22] In Physics II.9,
Aristotle hazards a few arguments that a determination of the end (cause) of a phenomenon is more
important than the others. He argues that the end is that which brings it about, so for example "if one
defines the operation of sawing as being a certain kind of dividing, then this cannot come about
unless the saw has teeth of a certain kind; and these cannot be unless it is of iron." [23] According to
Aristotle, once a final "cause" is in place, the material, efficient and formal "causes" follow by
necessity. However, he recommends that the student of nature determine the other "causes" as well,
[24]
 and notes that not all phenomena have an end, e.g., chance events. [25]
Aristotle saw that his biological investigations provided insights into the causes of things, especially
into the final cause.
We should approach the investigation of every kind of animal without being ashamed, since in each
one of them there is something natural and something beautiful. The absence of chance and the
serving of ends are found in the works of nature especially. And the end, for the sake of which a
thing has been constructed or has come to be, belongs to what is beautiful.

— Aristotle, On the Parts of Animals 645a 21-26, Book I, Part 5.[26]


George Holmes Howison, in The Limits of Evolution (1901), highlights "final causation" in presenting
his theory of metaphysics, which he terms "personal idealism", and to which he invites not only man,
but all (ideal) life; at p. 39:
Here, in seeing that Final Cause – causation at the call of self-posited aim or end – is the only full
and genuine cause, we further see that Nature, the cosmic aggregate of phenomena and the cosmic
bond of their law which in the mood of vague and inaccurate abstraction we call Force, is after all
only an effect... Thus teleology, or the Reign of Final Cause, the reign of ideality, is not only an
element in the notion of Evolution, but is the very vital cord in the notion. The conception of evolution
is founded at last and essentially in the conception of Progress: but this conception has no meaning
at all except in the light of a goal; there can be no goal unless there is a Beyond for everything
actual; and there is no such Beyond except through a spontaneous ideal. The presupposition of
Nature, as a system undergoing evolution, is therefore the causal activity of our Pure Ideals. These
are our three organic and organizing conceptions called the True, the Beautiful, and the Good.
However, Edward Feser argues, in line with the Aristotelian and Thomistic tradition, that finality has
been greatly misunderstood. Indeed, without finality, efficient causality becomes inexplicable. Finality
thus understood is not purpose but that end towards which a thing is ordered. [27] When a match is
rubbed against the side of a matchbox, the effect is not the appearance of an elephant or the
sounding of a drum, but fire.[28] The effect is not arbitrary because the match is ordered towards the
end of fire[29] which is realized through efficient causes.
In their theoretical study of organism, more specifically propagating organisation of process,
Kauffman et al. remark (p30):
Our language is teleological. We believe that autonomous agents constitute the minimal physical
system to which teleological language rightly applies. [30]

In modern science[edit]
See also: Teleology §  Teleology and science
Francis Bacon wrote in his Advancement of Learning (1605) that natural science "doth make inquiry,
and take consideration of the same natures : but how? Only as to the material and efficient causes
of them, and not as to the forms." Using the terminology of Aristotle, Bacon demanded that, apart
from the "laws of nature" themselves, the causes relevant to natural science are only efficient
causes and material causes, or, to use the formulation which became famous later, natural
phenomena require scientific explanation in terms of matter and motion. In The New Organon,
Bacon divided knowledge into physics and metaphysics.
From the two kinds of axioms which have been spoken of arises a just division of philosophy and the
sciences, taking the received terms (which come nearest to express the thing) in a sense agreeable
to my own views. Thus, let the investigation of forms, which are (in the eye of reason at least, and in
their essential law) eternal and immutable, constitute Metaphysics; and let the investigation of the
efficient cause, and of matter, and of the latent process, and the latent configuration (all of which
have reference to the common and ordinary course of nature, not to her eternal and fundamental
laws) constitute Physics. And to these let there be subordinate two practical divisions: to Physics,
Mechanics; to Metaphysics, what (in a purer sense of the word) I call Magic, on account of the
broadness of the ways it moves in, and its greater command over nature. Francis Bacon The New
Organon, Book II, Aphorism 9, 1620
Bacon's position, excluding teleology, is sometimes naïvely regarded as all-sufficient and exhaustive
in modern science, though one may properly bear in mind that it was reached before the theory of
evolution recognised the survival value inherent in biological functionality.
Biology[edit]
Further information: Tinbergen's four questions
Explanations in terms of final causes remain common in evolutionary biology.[18][31] Francisco J.
Ayala has claimed that teleology is indispensable to biology since the concept of adaptation is
inherently teleological.[31] In an appreciation of Charles Darwin published in Nature in 1874, Asa
Gray noted "Darwin's great service to Natural Science" lies in bringing back Teleology "so that,
instead of Morphology versus Teleology, we shall have Morphology wedded to Teleology". Darwin
quickly responded, "What you say about Teleology pleases me especially and I do not think anyone
else has ever noticed the point."[18] Francis Darwin and T. H. Huxley reiterate this sentiment. The
latter wrote that "..the most remarkable service to the philosophy of Biology rendered by Mr. Darwin
is the reconciliation of Teleology and Morphology, and the explanation of the facts of both, which his
view offers."[18] James G. Lennox states that Darwin uses the term 'Final Cause' consistently in
his Species Notebook, Origin of Species and after.[18]
Contrary to the position described by Francisco J. Ayala, Ernst Mayr states that "adaptedness... is a
posteriori result rather than an a priori goal-seeking." [32] Various commentators view the teleological
phrases used in modern evolutionary biology as a type of shorthand. For example, S. H. P. Madrell
writes that "the proper but cumbersome way of describing change by evolutionary adaptation [may
be] substituted by shorter overtly teleological statements" for the sake of saving space, but that this
"should not be taken to imply that evolution proceeds by anything other than from mutations arising
by chance, with those that impart an advantage being retained by natural selection." [33] However,
Lennox states that in evolution as conceived by Darwin, it is true both that evolution is the result of
mutations arising by chance and that evolution is teleological in nature. [18]
Statements that a species does something "in order to" achieve survival are teleological. The validity
or invalidity of such statements depends on the species and the intention of the writer as to the
meaning of the phrase "in order to". Sometimes it is possible or useful to rewrite such sentences so
as to avoid teleology.[34] Some biology courses have incorporated exercises requiring students to
rephrase such sentences so that they do not read teleologically. Nevertheless, biologists still
frequently write in a way which can be read as implying teleology even if that is not the intention.
Heidegger on technology[edit]
In The Question Concerning Technology, Martin Heidegger describes the four causes as follows:

1. causa materialis is the material or matter


2. causa formalis is the form or shape the material or matter
enters
3. causa finalis is the end
4. causa efficiens is the effect that brings about the finished result.
[35]

Heidegger explains it thus:


Whoever builds a house or a ship or forges a sacrificial chalice reveals what is to be brought forth,
according to the terms of the four modes of occasioning. [36]
The educationist David Waddington comments that although the efficient cause, which he identifies
as "the craftsman", might be thought the most significant of the four, in his view each of Heidegger's
four causes is "equally co-responsible" for producing a craft item, in Heidegger's terms "bringing
forth" the thing into existence. Waddington cites Lovitt's description of this bringing forth as "a unified
process".[37][38]

Tinbergen's four questions[edit]


Main article: Tinbergen's four questions
Tinbergen's four questions, named after the ethologist Nikolaas Tinbergen and based on Aristotle's
four causes, are complementary categories of explanations for animal behaviour. They are also
commonly referred to as levels of analysis. The four questions are on function, what
an adaptation does that is selected for in evolution; phylogeny, the evolutionary history of
an organism, revealing its relationships to other species; mechanism, namely the proximate cause of
a behaviour, such as the role of testosterone in aggression; and ontogeny, the development of an
organism from egg to embryo to adult. [39][40]

See also[edit]
 Anthropic principle
 Biosemiotics
 Causality
 Convergent evolution
 Four discourses, by Jacques Lacan
 Proximate and ultimate causation
 Socrates
 Teleology
 The purpose of a system is what it does , Anthony Stafford Beer's
POSIWID principle

Notes[edit]
1. ^ Aristotle, Physics 194 b17–20; see also: Posterior Analytics 71 b9–
11; 94 a20.
2. ^ Jump up to:      "[F]or a full range of cases, an explanation which fails to
a b c

invoke all four causes is no explanation at all."—"Four Causes".


Falcon, Andrea. Aristotle on Causality. Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy 2008.
3. ^ Lindberg, David. The Beginnings of Western Science (1992). p. 53
4. ^ Jump up to:    Leroi 2015, pp. 91–92.
a b

5. ^ Jump up to:    Hankinson, R. J. (1998), Cause and Explanation in


a b

Ancient Greek Thought  (e-book)|format=  requires  |url= (help),


[Oxford]: OUP Premium,
p. 159,  doi:10.1093/0199246564.001.0001, ISBN 9780198237457, A
ristotle famously distinguishes four 'causes' (or causal factors in
explanation), the matter, the form, the end, and the agent.
6. ^ Aristotle, "Book 5, section 1013a",  Metaphysics, Translated by Hugh
Tredennick Aristotle in 23 Volumes, Vols. 17, 18, Cambridge, MA,
Harvard University Press; London, William Heinemann Ltd. 1933,
1989; (hosted at perseus.tufts.edu.) Aristotle also discusses the four
"causes" in his Physics, Book B, chapter 3.
7. ^ According to Reece (2018): "Aristotle thinks that human action is a
species of animal self-movement, and animal self-movement is a
species of natural change. Natural changes, although they are not
substances and do not have causes in precisely the same way that
substances do, are to be explained in terms of the four causes, or as
many of them as a given natural change has: The material cause is
that out of which something comes to be, or what undergoes change
from one state to another; the formal cause, what differentiates
something from other things, and serves as a paradigm for its coming
to be that thing; the efficient cause, the starting-point of change; the
final cause, that for the sake of which something comes about."
8. ^ Lloyd, G. E. R.  (1996), "Causes and correlations", Adversaries and
authorities: Investigations into ancient Greek and Chinese science,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp.  100, 106–107,  ISBN  0-
521-55695-3
9. ^ original text in Posterior Analytics 90a8, 94a20, original text
inMet. 1013a on Perseus
10. ^ Liddell, Henry G.;  Scott, Robert; Jones, Henry Stuart (1843),  The
Online Liddell-Scott-Jones Greek-English Lexicon, Thesaurus Linguae
Graecae
11. ^ Lloyd, G. E. R.  (1979), Magic, Reason and Experience, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, p. 54,  ISBN  0-521-29641-2
12. ^ Lloyd, G. E. R.  (1996), "Causes and correlations", Adversaries and
authorities: Investigations into ancient Greek and Chinese science,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp.  96–98,  ISBN  0-521-
55695-3
13. ^ Jump up to:a b c d Preus, Anthony (2015). "Material cause".  Historical
Dictionary of Ancient Greek Philosophy (2nd ed.). Rowman and
Littlefield. ISBN 978-0810854871.
14. ^ Physics 192b
15. ^ Lloyd, G. E. R.  (1968), "The critic of Plato",  Aristotle: The Growth
and Structure of His Thought, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, pp.  43–47,  ISBN  0-521-09456-9
16. ^ Lloyd, G. E. R.  (1996), "Causes and correlations", Adversaries and
authorities: Investigations into ancient Greek and Chinese science,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, p.  96, ISBN 0-521-55695-
3, It is clear that of these four, only the efficient cause looks like
a  cause  in any ordinary English sense.
17. ^ Aristotle, Physics, II.3. 194  b 32
18. ^ Jump up to:            Lennox, James G.  (1993), "Darwin was  a
a b c d e f

teleologist",  Biology and Philosophy, 8  (4): 409–


421,  doi:10.1007/BF00857687
19. ^ Mayr, Ernst  (10 November 1961), Cause and Effect in Biology, 134,
pp.  1501–1506, PMID 14471768,  The development or behavior of an
individual is purposive, natural selection is definitely not…. Darwin
'has swept out such finalistic teleology by the front door.'
20. ^ Rand, Ayn (January 2000), The Art of Fiction, The Penguin Group,
p. 20,  ISBN  0-452-28154-7
21. ^ The Complete Works of Aristotle Vol. I. The Revised Oxford
Translation, ed. Jonathan Barnes).
22. ^ Aristotle gives this example in Parts of Animals I.1.
23. ^ Aristotle, Physics II.9. 200b4–7.
24. ^ Aristotle, Physics II.9.
25. ^ Physics II.5 where chance is opposed to nature, which he has
already said acts for ends.
26. ^ Lloyd, G. E. R. (1970). Early Greek Science: Thales to Aristotle, New
York: W. W. Norton, p. 105. ISBN 978-0-393-00583-7
27. ^ Compare: Feser, Edward (2009).  Aquinas: A Beginner's Guide.
Beginner's Guides (Reprint ed.). Oxford: Oneworld Publications
(published 2011).  ISBN  9781780740065. Retrieved  2018-03-12.  [...]
three principles are central to Aquinas's general metaphysics [...] the
principle of finality is in a sense the most fundamental of them, given
that the final cause is 'the cause of causes': for, again in Aquinas's'
view an efficient cause can bring an effect in to being only if it is
'directed towards' that effect; and it is ultimately in that sense that the
effect is 'contained in' the efficient cause.
28. ^ Compare: Feser, Edward (2009).  Aquinas: A Beginner's Guide.
Beginner's Guides (Reprint ed.). Oxford: Oneworld Publications
(published 2011).  ISBN  9781780740065. Retrieved  2018-03-12.  A
match, for example, reliably generates flame and heat when struck,
and never (say) frost and cold, or the smell of lilacs, or thunder.
29. ^ Compare:The match is 'directed towards' the production of fire and
heat [...]
30. ^ Kauffman, S., Logan, R. K., Este, R., Goebel, R., Hobill, D., &
Shmulevich, I. (2008). Propagating organization: An enquiry. Biology &
Philosophy, 23(1), 27-45.
31. ^ Jump up to:a b Ayala, Francisco (1998). "Teleological explanations in
evolutionary biology." Nature's purposes: Analyses of Function and
Design in Biology. The MIT Press.
32. ^ Mayr, Ernst W. (1992). "The idea of teleology" Journal of the History
of Ideas, 53, 117–135.
33. ^ Madrell SHP (1998) "Why are there no insects in the open
sea?" The Journal of Experimental Biology 201:2461–2464.
34. ^ Reiss, John O. (2009). Not by Design: Retiring Darwin's
Watchmaker. University of California Press.
35. ^ Heidegger 1977, pp. 289-290.
36. ^ Heidegger 1977, p. 295.
37. ^ Waddington, David (2005).  "A Field Guide to Heidegger
Understanding |  The Question Concerning Technology".  Educational
Philosophy and Theory.  37  (4): 568. doi:10.1111/j.1469-
5812.2005.00141.x.
38. ^ Lovitt, W. (1972). "A Gesprach with Heidegger on Technology, Man
and World".  6 (1): 44–62.
39. ^ MacDougall-Shackleton, Scott A. (2011-07-27).  "The levels of
analysis revisited". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B:
Biological Sciences.  366  (1574): 2076–
2085.  doi:10.1098/rstb.2010.0363. PMC  3130367.  PMID  21690126.
40. ^ Hladký, V. & Havlíček, J. (2013). Was Tinbergen an Aristotelian?
Comparison of Tinbergen's Four Whys and Aristotle's Four
Causes. Human Ethology Bulletin, 28(4), 3-11

References[edit]
 Cohen, Marc S. "The Four Causes" (Lecture Notes) Accessed
March 14, 2006.
 Falcon, Andrea. Aristotle on Causality (link to section labeled "Four
Causes"). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2008.
 Heidegger, Martin (1977). Krell, D. F. (ed.). The Question
Concerning Technology. Basic Writings. Harper & Row.
 Hennig, Boris. "The Four Causes." Journal of Philosophy 106(3),
2009, 137–60.
 Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented
Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1408836224.
 Moravcsik, J.M. "Aitia as generative factor in Aristotle's philosophy."
Dialogue, 14 : pp 622–638, 1975.
 Reece, Bryan C. (2019). "Aristotle's Four Causes of
Action". Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 97 (2): 213–
227. doi:10.1080/00048402.2018.1482932.
 English translation of Study on Phideas, by Pía Figueroa written
with theme of Final Cause as per Aristotle.

External links[edit]
 The Consequences of Ideas: Understanding the Concepts that
Shaped Our World, By R. C. Sproul
 Aristotle on definition. By Marguerite Deslauriers, page 81
 Philosophy in the ancient world: an introduction. By James A. Arieti.
p. 201.
 Doctrine of Being in the Aristotelian Metaphysics. By Joseph Owens
and Etienne Gilson.
 Aitia as generative factor in Aristotle's philosophy*
 A Compass for the Imagination, by Harold C. Morris. Philosophy
thesis elaborates on Aristotle's Theory of the Four Causes.
Washington State University, 1981.

hide
Aristotelianism

ial form)

You might also like