You are on page 1of 14

what kinds of reasons are involved.

The task of
The Nature of Law justification concerns the question of whether
peopleought to comply—morally speaking or all things
First published Sun May 27, 2001; substantive considered—with law’s demands. In other words, it is
revision Fri Aug 7, 2015 the attempt to explain the moral legitimacy of law and
Lawyers are typically interested in the question: What the subjects’ reasons for complying with it. A theory
is the law on a particular issue? This is always a local about the nature of law, as opposed to critical theories of
question and answers to it are bound to differ according law, concentrates on the first of these two questions. It
to the specific jurisdiction in which they are asked. In purports to explain what the normativity of law actually
contrast, philosophy of law is interested in the general consists in. Some contemporary legal philosophers,
question: What is Law? This general question about the however, doubt that these two aspects of the normativity
nature of law presupposes that law is a unique social- of law can be separated. (We will return to this later.)
political phenomenon, with more or less universal Thus, elucidating the conditions of legal validity and
characteristics that can be discerned through explaining the normativity of law form the two main
philosophical analysis. General jurisprudence, as this subjects of any general theory about the nature of law. In
philosophical inquiry about the nature of law is called, is section 1, we will explain some of the main debates
meant to be universal. It assumes that law possesses about these two issues. In section 2, we will discuss
certain features, and it possesses them by its very nature, some of the methodological debates about the nature of
or essence, as law, whenever and wherever it happens to general jurisprudence. In the course of the last few
exist. However, even if there are such universal centuries, two main rival philosophical traditions have
characteristics of law—which is controversial, as we will emerged about the nature of legality. The older one,
later discuss—the reasons for a philosophical interest in dating back to late mediaeval Christian scholarship, is
elucidating them remain to be explained. First, there is called the natural law tradition. Since the early 19th
the sheer intellectual interest in understanding such a century, natural law theories have been fiercely
complex social phenomenon which is, after all, one of challenged by the legal positivism tradition promulgated
the most intricate aspects of human culture. Law, by such scholars as Jeremy Bentham and John Austin.
however, is also a normative social practice: it purports The philosophical origins of legal positivism are much
to guide human behavior, giving rise to reasons for earlier, though, probably in the political philosophy of
action. An attempt to explain this normative, reason- Thomas Hobbes. The main controversy between these
giving aspect of law is one of the main challenges of two traditions concerns the conditions of legal validity.
general jurisprudence. These two sources of interest in Basically, legal positivism asserts, and natural law
the nature of law are closely linked. Law is not the only denies, that the conditions of legal validity are purely a
normative domain in our culture; morality, religion, matter of social facts. In contrast to positivism, natural
social conventions, etiquette, and so on, also guide law claims that the conditions of legal validity are not
human conduct in many ways which are similar to law. exhausted by social facts; the moral content of the
Therefore, part of what is involved in the understanding putative norms also bears on their legal validity. As the
of the nature of law consists in an explanation of how famous dictum, commonly attributed to Saint Augustine,
law differs from these similar normative domains, how it has it: lex iniusta non est lex (unjust law is not law).
interacts with them, and whether its intelligibility (Augustine, De Libero Arbitrio, I, 5; see also Aquinas,
depends on other normative orders, like morality or Summa Theologica, I-II, Q. 96, Art. 4
social conventions.

Contemporary legal theories define these two main


interests in the nature of law in the following terms.
1. General Jurisprudence
First, we need to understand the general conditions that
would render any putative norm legally valid. Is it, for 1.1 The Conditions of Legal
example, just a matter of the source of the norm, such as
its enactment by a particular political institution, or is it Validity
also a matter of the norm’s content? This is the general The main insight of legal positivism, that the conditions
question about the conditions of legal validity. Second, of legal validity are determined by social facts, involves
there is the interest in the normative aspect of law. This two separate claims which have been labeled The Social
philosophical interest is twofold: A complete Thesis and The Separation Thesis. The Social Thesis
philosophical account of the normativity of law asserts that law is, profoundly, a social phenomenon, and
comprises both an explanatory and a justificatory task. that the conditions of legal validity consist of social—
The explanatory task consists of an attempt to explain that is, non-normative—facts. Early legal positivists
how legal norms can give rise to reasons for action, and followed Hobbes’ insight that the law is, essentially, an
instrument of political sovereignty, and they maintained Many contemporary legal positivists would not
that the basic source of legal validity resides in the facts subscribe to this formulation of the Separation Thesis. A
constituting political sovereignty. Law, they thought, is contemporary school of thought, called inclusive legal
basically the command of the sovereign. Later legal positivism, endorses the Social Thesis, namely, that the
positivists have modified this view, maintaining that basic conditions of legal validity derive from social
social rules, and not the facts about sovereignty, facts, such as social rules or conventions which happen
constitute the grounds of law. Most contemporary legal to prevail in a given community. But, inclusive legal
positivists share the view that there are rules of positivists maintain, legal validity is sometimes a matter
recognition, namely, social rules or conventions which of the moral content of the norms, depending on the
determine certain facts or events that provide the ways particular conventions that happen to prevail in any
for the creation, modification, and annulment of legal given community. The social conventions on the basis of
standards. These facts, such as an act of legislation or a which we identify the law may, but need not, contain
judicial decision, are the sources of lawconventionally reference to moral content as a condition of legality.
identified as such in each and every modern legal The natural law tradition has undergone a considerable
system. One way of understanding the legal positivist refinement in the 20th century, mainly because its
position here is to see it as a form of reduction: legal classical, popular version faced an obvious objection
positivism maintains, essentially, that legal validity is about its core insight: it is just difficult to maintain that
reducible to facts of a non-normative type, that is, facts morally bad law is not law. The idea that law must pass,
about people’s conduct, beliefs and attitudes. as it were, a kind of moral filter in order to count as law
Natural lawyers deny this insight, insisting that a strikes most jurists as incompatible with the legal world
putative norm cannot become legally valid unless it as we know it. Therefore, contemporary natural lawyers
passes a certain threshold of morality. Positive law must have suggested different and more subtle interpretations
conform in its content to some basic precepts of natural of the main tenets of natural law. For example, John
law, that is, universal morality, in order to become law in Finnis views natural law (in its Thomist version) not as a
the first place. In other words, natural lawyers maintain constraint on the legal validity of positive laws, but
that the moral content or merit of norms, and not just mainly as an elucidation of an ideal of law in its fullest,
their social origins, also form part of the conditions of or highest sense, concentrating on the ways in which law
legal validity. And again, it is possible to view this necessarily promotes the common good. As we have
position as a non-reductive conception of law, noted earlier, however, it is not clear that such a view
maintaining that legal validity cannot be reduced to non- about the necessary moral content of law is at odds with
normative facts. the main tenets of legal positivism. To the extent that
The Separation Thesis is an important negative there is a debate here, it is a metaphysical one about
implication of the Social Thesis, maintaining that there is what is essential or necessary to law, and about whether
a conceptual separation between law and morality, that the essential features of law must be elucidated in
is, between what the law is, and what the law ought to teleological terms or not. Legal positivists do not tend to
be. The Separation Thesis, however, has often been seek deep teleological accounts of law, along the lines
overstated. It is sometimes thought that natural law articulated by Finnis, but whether they need to deny such
asserts, and legal positivism denies, that the law is, by metaphysical projects is far from clear.
necessity, morally good or that the law must have some The idea that the conditions of legal validity are at least
minimal moral content. The Social Thesis certainly does partly a matter of the moral content or merits of norms is
not entail the falsehood of the assumption that there is articulated in a sophisticated manner by Ronald
something necessarily good in the law. Legal positivism Dworkin’s legal theory. Dworkin is not a classical
can accept the claim that law is, by its very nature or its natural lawyer, however, and he does not maintain that
essential functions in society, something good that morally acceptable content is a precondition of a norm’s
deserves our moral appreciation. Nor is legal positivism legality. His core idea is that the very distinction
forced to deny the plausible claim that wherever law between facts and values in the legal domain, between
exists, it would have to have a great many prescriptions what the law is and what it ought to be, is much more
which coincide with morality. There is probably a blurred than legal positivism would have it: Determining
considerable overlap, and perhaps necessarily so, what the law is in particular cases inevitably depends on
between the actual content of law and morality. Once moral-political considerations about what it ought to be.
again, the Separation Thesis, properly understood, Evaluative judgments, about the content law ought to
pertains only to the conditions of legal validity. It asserts have or what it ought to prescribe, partly determine what
that the conditions of legal validity do not depend on the the law actually is.
moral merits of the norms in question. What the law is Dworkin’s legal theory is not based on a general
cannot depend on what it ought to be in the relevant repudiation of the classical fact-value distinction, as
circumstances. much as it is based on a certain conception of legal
reasoning. This conception went through two main there are legal principles of the kind Dworkin envisaged.
stages. In the 1970s Dworkin (1977) argued that the There is an alternative, more natural way to account for
falsehood of legal positivism resides in the fact that it is the distinction between rules and principles in the law:
incapable of accounting for the important role that legal the relevant difference concerns the level of generality,
principles play in the law. Legal positivism envisaged, or vagueness, of the norm-act prescribed by the pertinent
Dworkin claimed, that the law consists of rules only. legal norm. Legal norms can be more or less general, or
However, this is a serious mistake, since in addition to vague, in their definition of the norm-act prescribed by
rules, law is partly determined by legal principles. The the rule, and the more general or vague they are, the
distinction between rules and principles is a logical one. more they tend to have those quasi-logical features
Rules, Dworkin maintained, apply in an “all or nothing Dworkin attributes to principles. More importantly,
fashion.” If the rule applies to the circumstances, it notice that if you make the legal validity of norms, such
determines a particular legal outcome. If it does not as legal principles, depend on moral argument, you
apply, it is simply irrelevant to the outcome. On the allow for the possibility that an entire legal community
other hand, principles do not determine an outcome even may get its laws wrong. Any moral mistake in the
if they clearly apply to the pertinent circumstances. reasoning leading to a legal principle might render the
Principles provide judges with a legal reason to decide conclusion about the principle unsound, and the
the case one way or the other, and hence they only have principle itself thus not legally valid. Since there is
a dimension of weight. That is, the reasons provided by nothing to prevent judges and other legal actors from
the principle may be relatively strong, or weak, but they making moral mistakes, there is nothing to prevent a
are never “absolute.” Such reasons, by themselves, result whereby an entire legal community, and for a long
cannot determine an outcome, as rules do. time, gets its laws wrong (Marmor 2011, chapter 4).
The most interesting, and from a positivist perspective, Perhaps Dworkin would have not found this
most problematic, aspect of legal principles, however, problematic, but others might; the idea that an entire
consists in their moral dimension. According to legal community can be systematically mistaken about
Dworkin’s theory, unlike legal rules, which may or may its own laws might strike legal theorists as deeply
not have something to do with morality, principles are problematic.
essentially moral in their content. It is, in fact, partly a In the 1980s Dworkin radicalized his views about these
moral consideration that determines whether a legal issues, striving to ground his anti-positivist legal theory
principle exists or not. Why is that? Because a legal on a general theory of interpretation, and emphasizing
principle exists, according to Dworkin, if the principle law’s profound interpretative nature. Despite the fact
follows from the best moral and political interpretation that Dworkin’s interpretative theory of law is extremely
of past judicial and legislative decisions in the relevant sophisticated and complex, the essence of his argument
domain. In other words, legal principles occupy an from interpretation can be summarized in a rather simple
intermediary space between legal rules and moral way. The main argument consists of two main premises.
principles. Legal rules are posited by recognized The first thesis maintains that determining what the law
institutions and their validity derives from their enacted requires in each and every particular case necessarily
source. Moral principles are what they are due to their involves interpretative reasoning. Any statement of the
content, and their validity is purely content dependent. form “According to the law in SS, xx has a right/duty
Legal principles, on the other hand, gain their validity etc., to yy” is a conclusion of some interpretation or
from a combination of source-based and content-based other. Now, according to the second premise,
considerations. As Dworkin put it in the most general interpretation always involves evaluative considerations.
terms: “According to law as integrity, propositions of More precisely, perhaps, interpretation is neither purely
law are true if they figure in or follow from the a matter of determining facts, nor is it a matter of
principles of justice, fairness, and procedural due process evaluative judgment per se, but an inseparable mixture
that provide the best constructive interpretation of the of both. Clearly enough, one who accepts both these
community’s legal practice” (Dworkin 1986, 225). The theses must conclude that the Separation Thesis is
validity of a legal principle then, derives, from a fundamentally flawed. If Dworkin is correct about both
combination of facts and moral considerations. The facts theses, it surely follows that determining what the law
concern the past legal decisions which have taken place requires always involves evaluative considerations.
in the relevant domain, and the considerations of morals Notably, the first premise of Dworkin’s general
and politics concern the ways in which those past argument is highly contestable. Some legal philosophers
decisions can best be accounted for by the correct moral have argued that legal reasoning is not as thoroughly
principles. interpretative as Dworkin assumes. Interpretation,
Needless to say, if such an account of legal principles is according to this view, long maintained by H.L.A. Hart
correct, the Separation Thesis can no longer be (1961, chapter 7), is an exception to the standard
maintained. But many legal philosophers doubt that understanding of language and communication, rendered
necessary only when the law is, for some reason, positivist tradition, however, the coercive aspect of the
unclear. However, in most standard instances, the law law has given rise to fierce controversies. Early legal
can simply be understood, and applied, without the positivists, such as Bentham and Austin, maintained that
mediation of interpretation (Marmor 2011, chapter 6). coercion is an essential feature of law, distinguishing it
Dworkin’s legal theory shares certain insights with the from other normative domains. Legal positivists in the
Inclusive version of legal positivism. Note, however, 20th century have tended to deny this, claiming that
that although both Dworkin and inclusive legal coercion is neither essential to law, nor, actually, pivotal
positivists share the view that morality and legal validity to the fulfillment of its functions in society. Before we
are closely related, they differ on the grounds of this unpack the various issues involved in this controversy, it
relationship. Dworkin maintains that the dependence of might be worth noting that the debate about law’s
legal validity on moral considerations is coercive aspect is one good example of debates in
an essentialfeature of law that derives from law’s jurisprudence that focus on what might be an essential or
profoundly interpretative nature. Inclusive positivism, on a necessary feature of law, regardless of its particular
the other hand, maintains that such a dependence of legal manifestations in this or that legal system. How to
validity on moral considerations is a contingent matter; it understand these claims about the essence of law, and
does not derive from the nature of law or of legal the question of whether these claims are about
reasoning as such. Inclusive positivists accept the Social metaphysics or something else, perhaps about morality,
Thesis; they claim that moral considerations affect legal will be discussed in section 2.1.
validity only in those cases where this is dictated by the Returning to law’s coercive aspect, there are several
social rules or conventions which happen to prevail in a issues entangled here, and we should carefully separate
given legal system. The relevance of morality is them. John Austin famously maintained that each and
determined in any given legal system by the contingent every legal norm, as such, must comprise a threat backed
content of that society’s conventions. As opposed to both by sanction. This involves at least two separate claims:
these views, traditional, or as it is now called, exclusive In one sense, it can be understood as a thesis about the
legal positivism maintains that a norm’s legal validity is concept of law, maintaining that what we call “law” can
never dependent on its moral content. Legal validity, only be those norms which are backed by sanctions of
according to this view, is entirely dependent on the the political sovereign. In a second, though not less
conventionally recognized factual sources of law. problematic sense, the intimate connection between the
It may be worth noting that those legal theories law and the threat of sanctions is a thesis about the
maintaining that legal validity partly depends on moral normativity of law. It is a reductionist thesis about law’s
considerations must also share a certain view about the normative character, maintaining that the normativity of
nature of morality. Namely, they must hold an objective law consists in the subjects’ ability to predict the chances
stance with respect to the nature of moral values. of incurring punishment or evil and their presumed
Otherwise, if moral values are not objective and legality desire to avoid it.
depends on morality, legality would also be rendered In addition to this particular controversy, there is the
subjective, posing serious problems for the question of further question, concerning the relative importance of
how to identify what the law is. Some legal theories, sanctions for the ability of law to fulfill its social
however, do insist on the subjectivity of moral functions. Hans Kelsen, for instance, maintained that the
judgements, thus embracing the skeptical conclusions monopolization of violence in society, and the law’s
that follow about the nature of law. According to these ability to impose its demands by violent means, is the
skeptical theories, law is, indeed, profoundly dependent most important of law’s functions in society. Twentieth
on morality, but, as these theorists assume that morality century legal positivists, like H.L.A. Hart and Joseph
is entirely subjective, it only demonstrates how the law Raz, deny this, maintaining that the coercive aspect of
is also profoundly subjective, always up for grabs, so to law is much more marginal than their predecessors
speak. This skeptical approach, fashionable in so-called assumed. Once again, the controversy here is actually
post-modernist literature, crucially depends on a twofold: is coercion essential to what the law does? And
subjectivist theory of values, which is rarely articulated even if it is not deemed essential, how important it is,
in this literature in any sophisticated way. compared with the other functions law fulfills in our
lives?
1.2 The Normativity of Law Austin’s reductionist account of the normativity of law,
maintaining that the normative aspect of law simply
Throughout human history the law has been known as a
consists in the subjects’ desire to avoid sanctions, was
coercive institution, enforcing its practical demands on
discussed extensively, and fiercely criticized, by H.L.A.
its subjects by means of threats and violence. This
Hart. Hart’s fundamental objection to Austin’s
conspicuous feature of law made it very tempting for
reductionist account of law’s normativity is, on his own
some philosophers to assume that the normativity of law
account, “that the predictive interpretation obscures the
resides in its coercive aspect. Even within the legal
fact that, where rules exist, deviations from them are not controversy. Be this as it may, Legal Realism paid very
merely grounds for prediction that hostile reactions will little attention to the question of the normativity of law,
follow…. but are also deemed to be a reason or that is, to the question of how the law does guide
justification for such reaction and for applying the behavior in those cases in which it seems to be
sanctions” (Hart 1961, 82). This emphasis on the reason- determinate enough.
giving function of rules is surely correct, but perhaps not A much more promising approach to the normativity of
enough. Supporters of the predictive account could claim law is found in Joseph Raz’s theory of authority, which
that it only begs the further question of why people also shows how such a theory about the normativity of
should regard the rules of law as reasons or justifications law entails important conclusions with respect to the
for actions. If it is, for example, only because the law conditions of legal validity (Raz 1994). The basic insight
happens to be an efficient sanction-provider, then the of Raz’s argument is that the law is an authoritative
predictive model of the normativity of law may turn out social institution. The law, Raz claims, is a de
to be correct after all. In other words, Hart’s fundamental factoauthority. However, it is also essential to law that it
objection to the predictive model is actually a result of must be held to claim legitimate authority. Any
his vision about the main functions of law in society, particular legal system may fail, of course, in its
holding, contra Austin and Kelsen, that those functions fulfillment of this claim. But law is the kind of
are not exclusively related to the ability of the law to institution which necessarily claims to be a legitimate
impose sanctions. authority.
It is arguable, however, that law’s functions in our According to Raz, the essential role of authorities in our
culture are more closely related to its coercive aspect practical reasoning is to mediate between the putative
than Hart seems to have assumed. Contemporary use of subjects of the authority and the right reasons which
“game theory” in the law tends to show that the rationale apply to them in the relevant circumstances. An
of a great variety of legal arrangements can be best authority is legitimate if and only if it helps its putative
explained by the function of law in solving problems of subjects to comply better with the right reasons relevant
opportunism, like the so called Prisoner’s Dilemma to their actions—i.e., if they are more likely to act in
situations. In these cases, the law’s main role is, indeed, compliance with these reasons by following the
one of providing coercive incentives for the mutual authoritative resolution than they would be if they tried
benefit of all parties concerned. Be this as it may, we to figure out and act on the reasons directly (without the
should probably refrain from endorsing Austin’s or mediating resolution). For example, there may be many
Kelsen’s position that law’s only function in society is reasons that bear on the question of how fast to drive on
essentially tied to its coercive aspects. Solving recurrent a particular road—the amount of pedestrian traffic,
and multiple coordination problems, setting standards for impending turns in the road, etc.—but drivers may
desirable behavior, proclaiming symbolic expressions of comply better with the balance of those reasons by
communal values, resolving disputes about facts, and following the legal speed limit than if they tried to figure
such, are important functions which the law serves in our out all the trade-offs in the moment. The legitimacy of
society, and those have very little to do with law’s the legal speed limit would thus be derived from the way
coercive aspect and its sanction-imposing functions. in which it aids people in acting in better compliance
The extent to which law can actually guide behavior by with the balance of the right reasons.
providing its subjects with reasons for action has been Now, it follows that for something to be able to claim
questioned by a very influential group of legal scholars legitimate authority, it must be of the kind of
in the first half of the 20thcentury, called the Legal thing capable of claiming it, namely, capable of fulfilling
Realism school. American Legal Realists claimed that such a mediating role. What kinds of things can claim
our ability to predict the outcomes of legal cases on the legitimate authority? There are at least two such features
basis of the rules of law is rather limited. In the more necessary for authority-capacity: First, for something to
difficult cases which tend to be adjudicated in the be able to claim legitimate authority, it must be the case
appellate courts, legal rules, by themselves, are radically that its directives are identifiable as authoritative
indeterminate as to the outcome of the cases. The Legal directives, without the necessity of relying on those same
Realists thought that lawyers who are interested in the reasons which the authoritative directive replaces. If this
predictive question of what the courts will actually condition is not met, namely, if it is impossible to
decide in difficult cases need to engage in sociological identify the authoritative directive as such without
and psychological research, striving to develop relying on those same reasons the authority was meant to
theoretical tools that would enable us to predict legal rely on, then the authority could not fulfill its essential,
outcomes. Thus Legal Realism was mainly an attempt to mediating role. In short, it could not make the practical
introduce the social sciences into the domain of difference it is there to make. Note that this argument
jurisprudence for predictive purposes. To what extent does not concern the efficacy of authorities. The point is
this scientific project succeeded is a matter of not that unless authoritative directives can be recognized
as such, authorities could not function effectively. The respects the law may be more like a structured game, or
argument is based on the rationale of authorities within an artistic genre, which are actually constituted by social
our practical reasoning. Authorities are there to make a conventions. Such constitutive conventions are not
practical difference, and they could not make such a explicable as solutions to some pre-existing recurrent
difference unless the authority’s directive can be coordination problem. The conventional rules
recognized as such without recourse to the reasons it is constituting the game of chess, for example, are not there
there to decide upon. In other words, it is pointless to to solve a coordination problem between potential
have an authoritative directive if, in order to discover players. Antecedent to the game of chess, there was no
what the directive is, you have to engage in the same particular coordination problem to solve. The
reasoning that reliance on the directive is supposed to conventional rules of chess constitute the game itself as a
replace. Secondly, for something to be able to claim kind of social activity people would find worthwhile
legitimate authority, it must be capable of forming an engaging in. The constitutive conventions partly
opinion on how its subjects ought to behave, distinct constitute the values inherent in the emergent social
from the subjects’ own reasoning about their reasons for practice. Such values, however, are only there for those
action; authority requires some authorship. who care to see them. Constitutive conventions, by
Raz’s conception of legal authority provides very strong themselves, cannot ground an obligation to engage in the
support for exclusive legal positivism because it requires practice they constitute.
that the law, qua an authoritative resolution, be From a moral point of view, the rules of recognition, by
identifiable on its own terms, that is, without having to themselves, cannot be regarded as sources of obligation
rely on those same considerations that the law is there to to follow the law. Whether judges, or anybody else,
resolve. Therefore a norm is legally valid (i.e., should or should not respect the rules of recognition of a
authoritative) only if its validity does not derive from legal system, is ultimately a moral issue, that can only be
moral or other evaluative considerations that the law is resolved by moral arguments (concerning the age old
intended to replace. Notably, Raz’s theory challenges issue of political obligation). And this is more generally
both Dworkin’s anti-positivist legal theory, and the so: the existence of a social practice, in itself, does not
inclusive version of legal positivism. This challenge, and provide anyone with an obligation to engage in the
the controversies it gave rise to, form one of the main practice. The rules of recognition only define what the
topics discussed in contemporary general jurisprudence. practice is, and they can say nothing on the question of
Explaining the rationale of legal authority, however, is whether one should or should not engage in it. But of
not the only component of a theory about the normativity course, once one does engage in the practice, playing the
of law. If we hold the legal positivist thesis that law is role of judge or some other legal official, as it were,
essentially founded on social conventions, another there are legal obligations defined by the rules of the
important question arises here: how can a conventional game. In other words, there is nothing special in the idea
practice give rise to reasons for action and, in particular, of a legal obligation to follow the rules of recognition.
to obligations? Some legal philosophers claimed that The referee in a soccer game is equally obliged to follow
conventional rules cannot, by themselves, give rise to the rules of his game, and the fact that the game is
obligations. As Leslie Green observed, Hart’s “view that conventional poses no difficulty from this, let us say,
the fundamental rules [of recognition] are ‘mere “internal-player’s” perspective. But again, the
conventions’ continues to sit uneasily with any notion of constitutive rules of soccer cannot settle for anyone the
obligation,” and this Green finds troubling, because the question of whether they should play soccer or not.
rules of recognition point to the “sources that judges Similarly, the rules of recognition cannot settle for the
are legally bound to apply” (Green 1996, 1697). The judge, or anyone else for that matter, whether they
debate here is partly about the conventional nature of the should play by the rules of law, or not. They only tell us
rules of recognition, and partly about the ways in which what the law is. Unlike chess or soccer, however, the law
conventions can figure in our reasons for action. may well be a kind of game that people have an
According to one influential theory, inspired by David obligation to play, as it were. But if there is such an
Lewis (1969) conventional rules emerge as solutions to obligation, it must emerge from external, moral,
large-scale and recurrent coordination problems. If the considerations, that is, from a general moral obligation
rules of recognition are, indeed, of such a coordination to obey the law. The complex question of whether there
kind, it is relatively easy to explain how they may give is such a general obligation to obey the law, and whether
rise to obligations. Coordination conventions would be it depends on certain features of the relevant legal
obligatory if the norm subjects have an obligation to system, is extensively discussed in the literature on
solve the coordination problem which initially gave rise political obligation. A complete theory about the
to the emergence of the relevant convention. It is normativity of law must encompass these moral issues as
doubtful, however, that the conventions at the well. (See the entries on political obligation and legal
foundations of law are of a coordinative kind. In certain obligation.)
Recent challenges to general jurisprudence, and work, The Concept of Law (1994). A second sort of view
particularly to legal positivism, have taken an interesting adopts a more skeptical stance towards the methodology
methodological turn. This methodological turn gained of conceptual analysis and takes theories of law to be in
momentum with the publication of Dworkin’s Law’s the business of offering a reductive explanation of law
Empire (1986), arguing that not only the law, as a social itself, not some concept of it. Third, the prescriptive
practice, is a profoundly interpretative (and thus partly, view takes it that the aim of a theory of law is to specify
but necessarily, evaluative in nature), but that any theory the notion of law that it would be most desirable for us
about the nature of law is also interpretative in a similar to adopt. A fourth kind of view, associated with
way, and thus, equally evaluative. Many of those who do Dworkin’s work, and takes it that legal theories are in
not necessarily share Dworkin’s views about the the business of offering a constructive interpretation of
interpretative nature of legal practice, or the specifics of legal practice. In what follows, each of these four views,
his theory of interpretation, have joined him in this as well as some of the main issues they face, will be
methodological skepticism about the traditional aims of discussed in more depth.
general jurisprudence, that is, about the possibility of
developing a theory about that nature of law that would 2.1.1 Conceptual Analysis Views
have general application and remain morally neutral. On conceptual analysis views, theories of law aim to
These, and other resultant methodological challenges to capture the concept of law and they succeed to the extent
traditional general jurisprudence are taken up in the next that they provide a coherent account of the relevant data
section. about that concept and related concepts. In particular, the
data to be systematized are taken to be people’s
intuitions involving some shared concept of law (or
2. The Methodology of cognate concepts like legal validity or legal obligation).
In their simplest form, such intuitions can be thought of
Jurisprudence as judgments about whether the relevant concept does or
does not apply to particular cases. Accordingly, on this
When it comes to the methodology of jurisprudence, we
find two main issues. While one is not directly sort of view, a theory of law aims to provide an account
concerned with normativity, the second is. The first asks of the conditions under which the target concept of law
about the aims and success criteria for philosophical (or one of its cognates) applies.
theories about the nature of law: What’s more, such a theory can be arrived at by
What is the target that first-order theories of law aim employing the method of conceptual analysis,
to capture, and when do they succeed in doing so? undertaken from the proverbial armchair. The idea is that
The second asks about the role of evaluation in the theorist starts with a putative set of criteria for the
jurisprudential methodology: correct application of the target concept, and then she
Are first-order legal theories inherently or necessarily tests this account against her intuitions about that
evaluative or can they be purely descriptive? concept. If the account entails that the concept applies to
Each of these questions will be discussed in turn. particular cases that it intuitively does not apply to, then
this provides reason to reject or revise the account in
2.1 The Target of a Theory of question. By contrast, if the account entails that the
target concept applies to certain cases and this is the
Law intuitively correct result, this tends to provide
affirmative support for the account. The account
The first important class of methodological questions in successfully captures the target concept to the extent that
jurisprudence concerns the target of first-order theories it yields intuitively correct results about particular cases,
of law—that is, what phenomenon such theories aim to and does so in an explanatorily satisfying way (as
provide an account of. In taking a stand on what the opposed to an ad hoc manner). (For a more in depth
proper target of a first-order legal theory is, one incurs a discussion of the methodology of conceptual analysis as
number of other methodological commitments. These applied to the concept of law, see Shapiro 2011, 16–22.)
include adopting a view about when such theories are Jurisprudence has been influenced by two main ways of
successful, taking a stand on what sort of data such understanding the relevant intuitions (or data) that
theories aim to systematize and explain, and determining theories of law aim to systematize. This, in turn, is due
what sorts of arguments are legitimately used in deciding to the fact that one might understand concepts
between one of these theories and its competitors. themselves, and our intuitions about them, in two
There are four main families of views on this question. different ways. Accordingly, we find two main varieties
One view takes jurisprudence to be a form of conceptual of the conceptual analysis view of methodology.
analysis, which is to say that theories of law aim to The first understanding of concepts takes concept
provide an account of some concept of law. This possession to be mainly a matter of linguistic
approach is often associated with Hart’s influential competence. That is, to possess the concept of law is to
know when the word “law” as used in its juridical sense This suggests a second, richer form of conceptual
(not the scientific sense) applies. Thus, intuitions about analysis that legal theorists might be engaged in.
the concept of law are to be understood as linguistic The basic idea behind the richer view is to take it that
intuitions about how to use the word “law.” On the concept possession, rather than merely being a matter of
present view, then, conceptual analysis is a mode of knowing when words apply, involves something meatier:
linguistic analysis. This sort of view was famously namely, the possession of a wide range of substantive
discussed in chapters 1 and 2 of Dworkin’s Law’s beliefs or intuitions about the concept, its essential
Empire (Dworkin 1986, 32, 43–46). It arguably traces features and its proper application. The assumption is
back to the kind of ordinary language philosophy that the intuitions one is disposed to have in virtue of
associated with J.L. Austin and Gilbert Ryle (Marmor possessing the concept of law will be fertile enough to
2013, 210–212). constitute a particular substantive conception of what the
However, this understanding of concept possession has law is and how it functions. The aim of a theory of law,
drawbacks. Perhaps the biggest source of concern in the then, would be to systematize these pre-theoretic
present context is that this sort of view fuels a version of judgments about the concept of law in order to provide
Dworkin’s “semantic sting” argument (Dworkin 1986, an account of some substantive conception of law. (This
43–46). The argument may be summarized as follows. sort of richer view of concept possession is discussed,
Suppose legal theories aim to capture the concept of law e.g., in Raz 2004, 4–7; Stravopoulos 2012, 78–79;
and that concept possession just is a matter of knowing Shapiro 2011, 16–22. It is perhaps also the sort of view
when the word “law” applies. If so, the argument runs, presupposed by Hart.) On this view, legal disagreement
legal theories cannot explain disagreement about the remains possible because while practitioners might all be
grounds of law, that is, about the conditions of legal using the same concept of law, the richness of the
validity. After all, if legal theories are in this way concept allows that they nonetheless might not possess
semantic in nature, then disagreement about what the the concept determinately enough, or understand its
grounds of law are must boil down to disagreement application conditions thoroughly enough, to guarantee
about when the word “law” applies—at least assuming consensus on theoretical questions about what the
the parties to the disagreement are not merely talking grounds of law actually are.
past one another. But now a dilemma arises. Either legal However, also this richer understanding of concept
practitioners possess the same concept of law or they do possession, and the meatier picture of conceptual
not. If they do possess the same concept, then it seems analysis it gives rise to, has been widely criticized
they cannot fail to agree about what it takes for a norm (Marmor 2013, 215–217; Raz 2004, 10; Leiter 2007,
to count as law. After all, they all know when the word 177–79). One question that immediately arises
expressing their shared concept of law applies. But this is which concept of law, exactly, constitutes the proper
is implausible, since legal practice in fact is rife with target of a theory of law. Is it the concept of law that is
disagreement about what the grounds of law are (and possessed by the legal practitioners in a particular
thus, what counts as law or as legal). On the other hand, jurisdiction? Or is it some universally shared concept of
if legal practitioners do notshare the same concept of law? Worries loom either way. If a legal theory only
law, then their disagreement about what the grounds of aims to capture the concept of law employed in a
law are must just be due to the fact that they are talking particular jurisdiction, then that would render the theory
past one another. But that, too, is implausible. Legal parochial and it might lose its interest for those who are
practice, as Dworkin puts it, is not “a grotesque joke” not concerned with that particular jurisdiction. On the
(Dworkin 1986, 44). Accordingly, there must be other hand, one might doubt that there really is a
something wrong with construing legal theories as mere universally shared concept of law that is employed by
semantic accounts of when the word “law” applies. practitioners in all jurisdictions—or if there is one, it is
If, in light of this argument, we are to abandon the idea doubtful that it is anything more than the sort of thin
that first-order legal theories are semantic theories, there concept that one possesses in virtue of knowing what the
are two obvious ways to proceed. First, one might word “law” in its juridical sense means.
simply abandon the idea that legal theories are exercises A deeper worry about all forms of conceptual analysis is
in conceptual analysis. This was Dworkin’s preferred the question of why we should care about
response, though, as we’ll see, one can reject conceptual anybody’s concept of law in the first place (Marmor
analysis without adopting Dworkin’s own favored 2013, 216–217; Leiter 2007, 177–79). After all, as
methodology. (More on that in sub-section 2.1.2.) philosophers, it seems that it is the nature of law
Second, if one wants to still say that legal theories are in itself that we care about understanding (Raz 2004, 7, 10).
the business of analyzing the concept of law, then the Granted, there are interesting sociological questions to
obvious response to the semantic sting argument is to be asked about what various groups of people believe to
deny that concept possession just is a matter of knowing be the case about how law functions. But it is not
how the word “law” in its juridical sense is to be applied. obvious that there is anything distinctively philosophical
about such questions. Insofar as philosophers (qua different explanation of their defensibility would have to
philosophers) are interested in what people believe about be given.)
a given concept, this would be because understanding In particular, reductionist views take it that illuminating
people’s beliefs about the concept is a route to the nature of law is a matter of explaining what the law
understanding that which it is a concept of (Raz 2004, 4, is, and how it operates, in terms of more foundational
10). Accordingly, one might think that what theories of facts. As a result, first-order theories of law succeed to
law aim to capture is not anybody’s concept of law in the extent that they accomplish this in an explanatorily
particular, but rather the nature of law itself. (See also powerful way (Marmor 2013). The goal of a first-order
the entry on concepts, section 5.2.) theory, on this sort of view, is to offer a metaphysical
A possible response to this objection is to assert that reduction of law: that is, to show that the phenomenon of
since law is a social phenomenon and is in part law is actually constituted by, and fully reducible to,
constituted by practitioners’ own understanding of the some other more foundational type of phenomenon (in
practice they are engaged in, collecting evidence about the way that chemistry could in principle be reduced to
the concept of law possessed by legal practitioners is an particle physics). Thus construed, positivism, for
especially useful way to investigate law itself example, would seek to explain the nature of law by
(Stravopoulos 2012, 79). Still, one might wonder reducing facts about what the law is, how it functions
whether this route to investigating the nature of law itself and what it requires, to more foundational social facts—
would be the most effective strategy to employ, given its e.g., about people’s behavior, beliefs and dispositions.
indirectness. Why limit ourselves to asking questions By providing a reduction of this kind, a theory like
about concepts if law can be studied directly? positivism purports to illuminate the phenomenon of law
A very different response would be to adopt a Platonist itself by breaking it down into its constituents and
account of concepts, according to which they are not explaining how they together make up the complex
mental representations at all, but rather abstract objects social practice that is the law. (For more on metaphysical
akin to the objects of mathematical inquiry. The concept reduction in general, see Schroeder 2007, 61–83; see
of law, then, would be the abstract object one must grasp also the entry on scientific reduction.)
in order to think about law. Accordingly, it is this One well-known type of reductionist view is naturalized
abstract object—the concept of law—that philosophers jurisprudence. Brian Leiter has been the most prominent
care about and aim to investigate using the method of defender of this position (Leiter 2007). Like other
conceptual analysis (cf. Bealer 1998). Nonetheless, this reductionist views, naturalized jurisprudence takes the
view of concepts faces familiar objections. For one, an aim of legal theories to be to explain the nature of law
account is needed of how we can have access to the itself (not anybody’s concept of it). But what is
concept of law, conceived of as an independently characteristic of naturalized jurisprudence is that it also
existing abstract object. Moreover, even if we can access insists that a purely empirical methodology should be
it, a puzzle arises about how different people who all used in doing so (Leiter 2007, 180–81, 183–99). (See
determinately grasp the concept of law could possibly also the entry on naturalism in legal philosophy.)
end up disagreeing about its nature (Sarch 2010, 468– Naturalists might part company with adherents of other
73). Finally, while it might be plausible that a reductionist views over whether or not the armchair
priori disciplines like mathematics and logic aim to methods of philosophers, and related appeals to
investigate abstract objects (see the entry on platonism in intuitions, thought experiments and the like, are
the philosophy of mathematics), it is not clear that the misguided. The naturalist is likely to reject this mode of
investigation of a social phenomenon like the law, which inquiry, while other reductionists may be more amenable
is heavily dependent on human beliefs, attitudes and to using it. A reductionist could in principle defend this
behavior, can be understood analogously. While sort of inquiry, for instance, by claiming that our
mathematicians might be investigating the nature of particular-case intuitions involve a concept that we have
abstract objects like numbers or sets, it seems more acquired from experience with legal practice, and so
doubtful that legal philosophers are investigating the such intuitions can be one useful source of information
abstract object law. about the nature of law itself. Moreover, if legal practice
(as a social phenomenon) is partially constituted by
2.1.2 Investigating Law Itself practitioners’ own beliefs and attitudes towards the
Given the above doubts about conceptual analysis, practice they are engaged in, then evidence about legal
several views have been suggested according to which practitioners’ concept of law might prove especially
first-order legal theories are primarily in the business of relevant as evidence about the law itself (Stravopoulos
describing and explaining the nature of law itself, not 2012, 79).
any concept of it. Reductionist and naturalistic views fall By contrast, naturalists tend not to endorse the armchair
into this category. (As noted below, such views need not method of testing theories of law against intuition, given
completely eschew the armchair methods just sketched, their aim of making “philosophical theorizing
but to the extent these methods remain viable, a very
continuous with and dependent upon scientific 1985; see also Campbell 1996; Murphy 2001; Postema
theorizing” (Leiter 2007, 35). Leiter argues that our 1989; Schauer 1996; Waldron 2001). MacCormick
intuitions about law are too unreliable to be afforded argues that there are compelling normative arguments in
much epistemic weight (as others have argued with favor of adopting a positivist conception of law. In
respect to intuitions in other areas of philosophy) (Leiter particular, he suggests that values like autonomy and
2007, 180, 184; cf. Cummins 1998). On Leiter’s view, freedom of conscience demand that the law not regulate
philosophers generally should aim to unpack the with a heavy hand “the sphere of aspirational values, of
“concepts that have been vindicated by their role in duties of self-respect and of duties of love,” a sphere that
successful explanation and prediction of empirical concerns “questing for the good beyond duty, or for the
phenomena” (Leiter 2007, 184). Thus, he suggests a right lines of development of a self, or for the proper
methodology that “tak[es] seriously the…social regard to bestow upon one’s family, friends or
scientific literature on law…to see what concept of law neighbors” (MacCormick 1985, 35–36). Values like
figures in the most powerful explanatory and predictive autonomy and freedom of conscience, McCormack
models of legal phenomena such as judicial behavior” thinks, support the claim that at least within this sphere
(Leiter 2007, 184). This methodological view, however, of conduct, it is desirable to keep the question of what
raises questions about why the legal philosopher should the law requires entirely separate from the question of
study only judicial behavior and not something else. what morality requires. (However, MacCormick also
More generally, the naturalist owes an account of what allows that the law properly can regulate the sphere of
features of law are most in need of explication and why. “duties of justice,” as these duties are in some sense
A different sort of concern that arises for reductionist weightier (MacCormick 1985, 35).) Accordingly, at least
views (and perhaps naturalistic views as well) is that it in some spheres of conduct, the question of what the
may pose particular problems for positivism. law is ought to be held distinct from the question of what
Specifically, if law is a normative phenomenon that morality requires. Thus, MacCormick seems to be
gives rise to legal obligations, one might worry that it is offering a normative argument for a claim that has often
not possible to reduce legal facts (i.e., facts about what been associated with positivism, namely a version of the
our legal obligations are) to a set of purely non- Separation Thesis. (Though, as seen earlier, it is not
normative facts, e.g., social ones. One might think that clear that all positivists must be committed to a strong
this would impermissibly transgress the familiar (though version of this thesis.)
not uncontroversial) is-ought gap. (For a discussion of While the question of what conception of law it is most
this sort of worry about positivism, see Shapiro 2011, desirable that people adopt is surely a significant one, it
47–49.) is important to note that the prescriptive view of
In response, one route that positivists who want to be methodology in jurisprudence is not genuinely in
reductionists could take is to maintain that legal facts competition with either the conceptual analysis view or
really are descriptive in nature, not genuinely normative. the reductionist approach. After all, it might turn out, for
In particular, such positivists might claim that facts example, that positivism provides the best account of our
about what legal obligations we have simply are concept of law, or perhaps is the best reductive account
descriptive facts about what the law holds that we ought of the phenomenon of law itself, even though there are
to do—not normative facts about what we really ought to compelling normative arguments for changing the
do (Shapiro 2011, 188; see also Hart 1994, 110). practice or adopting a new concept of it that, say,
comports with natural law theory. Accordingly, accounts
2.1.3 The Prescriptive View of the concept of law, or reductive theories of law, are
A different sort of approach to methodology in not necessarily inconsistent with prescriptive accounts of
jurisprudence takes it that the proper aim of a legal what legal theory it would be most desirable from the
theory is to specify a substantive conception of law that moral point of view to adopt.
it would be especially desirable for people to adopt.
Moreover, even if the conception of law that this inquiry 2.1.4 Constructive Interpretation of Legal Practice
ends up supporting departs radically from our pre- A fourth methodological view, which deserves separate
theoretical understanding of law, then the resulting treatment both because of its influence and
theory would recommend abandoning that prior sophistication, is Dworkin’s (Dworkin 1986). This view
understanding of law. Accordingly, if jurisprudence is takes it that (i) the target of a first-order theory of law
chiefly a prescriptive endeavor, then theories of law is existing legal practice and (ii) these
might end up being radically revisionist in nature theories succeed to the extent that they offer a defensible
(though, of course, not necessarily). constructive interpretation (in Dworkin’s sense) of that
As explained in the next sub-section, Dworkin’s practice. According to the constructive interpretation
methodological view incorporates some prescriptive view, the aim of a first-order theory of law is not to
elements. But one prominent advocate of an exclusively analyze any concept or to reduce legal facts to other
prescriptive project is Neil MacCormick (MacCormick more foundational facts. Rather, the aim of a legal theory
is to reconstruct the behavior and self-understandings of 2.2.1 Preliminaries
participants in legal practice and, moreover, to do so in a To begin with, one might wonder where the interest in
way that casts this practice in its best moral light. As a the question of whether legal theory is inherently
result, a theory of law is more successful the better it evaluative comes from. Some of this interest likely
both fits with the data about how legal practitioners traces to the skeptical worry that legal theories
understand the practice they are engaged in, while also purporting to be purely descriptive in fact are pushing
normatively justifying that practice (Dworkin 1986; some hidden ideological or political agenda. (For more
Perry 1995, 129–31; see also the entry on legal on this, see, e.g., John Gardner’s introduction to Dickson
interpretivism). 2004.) A second source of the interest in this question
One concern about the constructive interpretation view may be the suspicion (or hope) that if legal theory proves
of methodology in jurisprudence is that it may not be in to be inherently evaluative, that would be an independent
genuine competition with either the conceptual analysis reason to adopt some version of natural law theory.
or reductive views of methodology. After all, one sort of Whether this is so remains doubtful, however, since
project is to explain what law actually is and how it meta-questions about the methodology of legal
operates (perhaps according to our concept of it). But it theory prima facie seem to be independent of questions
is a very different sort of project to explain how in first-order legal theory like what the determinants of
we should conceive of the law in order for legal practice the content of law are. What is more, legal scholars
to be normatively justified. It seems possible that our might be drawn to the present issue through
account of what law actually is tells us one thing (e.g., consideration of Dworkin’s argument that there is a very
that certain features of it are essential and others not), tight connection between the evaluative nature of
while our account of what law should be like in order for theorizing about the law and the evaluative nature of law
the practice to be as justified as possible tells us to think itself, rendering the content of law inevitably dependent,
of law in a rather different way (e.g., as having different at least in part, on moral-political considerations.
essential features). Accordingly, some have argued that Regardless of the motivations for engaging in the debate
the constructive interpretation view engages with the about whether legal theory is inherently evaluative,
other methodological views mentioned above only if it however, this debate has taken on independent
denies what they assert: viz., that legal theories attempt significance and has been a fruitful source of insight in
to provide an explanation (perhaps of some particular its own right.
kind—e.g., reductive) of the actual nature of law (or To avoid confusion, the question we are concerned with
perhaps our concept of it). here must be clarified in several ways. For there are a
One way that adherents of the constructive interpretation number of uncontroversial ways in which legal theory
view might deny what certain other methodological plausibly is or might be evaluative, and these do not go
views assert is by denying that it is even possible to give to the heart of the methodological debates in
a reductive explanation of law. (For discussion, see jurisprudence.
Marmor 2013, 218.) The thought would be to claim that First, there are several trivial ways in which legal theory,
law is a normative practice, and normative facts cannot like theories about any topic, plausibly cannot be entirely
be reduced to purely non-normative facts without losing value-free. In particular, it seems that one cannot engage
something essential. In response, the reductionist might in the business of theorizing about law without
either deny that legal facts are genuinely normative (in evaluating the extent to which various theories are
which case the sought-after reduction would be coherent, simple, clear, elegant, comprehensive, and so
unproblematic), or she might assert that any successful on (Dickson 2004, 32–33). Granted this means that legal
reduction will have to reduce legal facts to a set of facts theorists must engage in a form of evaluation. But there
thatincludes normative facts (in which case a version of is nothing special about legal theory in this regard. After
natural law theory might appear attractive). all, these meta-theoretical virtues are criteria for the
success of theories about any subject matter.
2.2 Is Legal Theory A second seemingly uncontroversial way in which legal
theory is evaluative is that one cannot begin to develop a
Inherently Evaluative? theory of law without determining which of its central
features are to be accounted for (Dickson 2001, 38–45).
A second widely-discussed question about
jurisprudential methodology is whether first-order legal John Finnis, for example, argues that one cannot do first-
theories are inherently evaluative. The above views order legal theory without taking a stand on what the
about the proper target of first-order theories of law have important features of law are that adequate theories must
different implications about this second question. But explain (e.g., the law’s claim to authority). However, this
before explaining that, we must first get the relevant seems to require evaluation (Finnis 1980, 9–15).
question more clearly in view. Nonetheless, it is not likely to be especially controversial
that legal theory is evaluative in this way. To see why,
distinguish between (a) thick evaluative claims, which will see, this is most plausibly the case on the
predicate some kind of moral goodness, or perhaps all- constructive interpretation view of methodology. By
things-considered value, of an item and (b) thin contrast, other answers to the question discussed in
evaluative claims, which do not. (This distinction section 2.1 do not obviously entail that first-order legal
roughly tracks Julie Dickson’s distinction between theories commit their proponents to thick evaluative
directly evaluative propositions and indirectly evaluative claims. In particular, this is the case for the conceptual
propositions. See Dickson 2001, 51–55.) Thus, the analysis and reductive views of jurisprudential
simplest thick evaluative claims have the form: XX is methodology. At least on their face, both these views
morally [all-things-considered] good [bad]. Such claims seem to allow that there can be purely descriptive
might also be comparative in nature, such that they have accounts of law—i.e., accounts that capture the central
the form: XX is morally [all-things-considered] better features of law without being committed to any moral or
[worse] than YY. By contrast, thin evaluative claims all-things-considered evaluation of the law. After all, one
judge how well some item fares relative to a standard might think that a particular account does a good job of
that is neither moral nor all-things-considered normative. capturing some widely shared concept of law, but this
Such claims do not entail any thick evaluative claims does not obviously commit one to saying that law, on
either. Examples of thin evaluative claims thus would this concept of it, isgood. Likewise, one might endorse a
include “XX is important” and “XX is interesting”. reduction of legal facts to some more foundational set of
Accordingly, even if legal theorists must make thin facts (e.g., certain social facts) without this committing
evaluative claims in order to be able to begin the project one to thinking that the law is valuable or morally
of developing a first-order legal theory, this does not justified.
mean that they must make thick evaluative claims in As a result, at least on their face, both the conceptual
order to do so. After all, one might construct a theory analysis and reductive views seem to allow that there can
that captures a range of legal phenomena that are be first-order theories of law that are purely descriptive.
deemed central or important, while still remaining Some argument would be needed if one is to endorse the
agnostic about whether these phenomena are themselves opposite conclusion. Accordingly, let us consider some
valuable. prominent arguments for thinking that legal theory must
A third way in which legal theory could in principle be be inherently evaluative in nature. (For an overview, see
evaluative, though uncontroversially so, is suggested by Marmor 2011, 122–35.)
the prescriptive view discussed in section 2.1.3. If the
job of a first-order theory of law is to identify the The argument from legal functions
concept of law it would be most desirable for us to One central argument to the effect that legal theory must
employ, then there is a sense in which the resulting be evaluative in the relevant sense begins from the idea
theory of law would of course be evaluative. that understanding what the law is requires taking a view
Nonetheless, as seen above, prescriptive theories aim to about what functions it serves (Finnis 1980, 12–17;
answer a different question from theories in the Perry 1995, 114–20). Moreover, one might think that
conceptual analysis, reductive or interpretive categories. functions are evaluative in the sense that attributing a
Thus, what matters to the debate about whether legal function to something is to endorse a standard by which
theory is evaluative is not whether legal theory in that thing may be judged as successful or unsuccessful.
principle could be evaluative, but whether it is inevitably In this way, one might think that legal theory, too, is
or necessarily so. inherently evaluative.
Now we are in a position to fully appreciate the question While this line of thinking plausibly shows that legal
of primary interest here. In particular, it is whether theory requires accepting some evaluative claims, it does
theories about the nature of existing legal practice (or not obviously show that legal theory necessarily
perhaps our concept of it) necessarily involve or involves thick evaluative claims (Dickson 2001, 114–
entail thick evaluative claims about the law. That is, does 125). Claims of the form “the function of XX is FF” are
offering a first-order theory of law of either the naturally classified together with “XX is important” (or
conceptual analysis, reductive or constructive more precisely, “XX is important for some
interpretation varieties require one to accept claims purpose YY”) as thin evaluative claims. Accordingly,
about how valuable the law, or some feature of it, is? asserting that the function of law is FF does not
This is the question to be discussed in the remainder of obviously entail any thick evaluative claims about law.
this entry. After all, it is not obvious why attributing a function to
something requires believing that performing that
2.2.2 Is Legal Theory Evaluative in the Relevant Sense? function is either all-things-considered or morally good.
Some answers to the question that was discussed in Thus, attributing a function to law need not entail any
section 2.1 suggest that theories of law are inherently thick evaluative claims.
evaluative in the sense of committing advocates of these
theories to thick evaluative claims about the law. As we The argument from the internal point of view
A second natural argument in favor of seeing legal of fraud. As a result, saying that the law must be thus-
theory as inherently evaluative in the relevant sense and-so in order to be a good instance of its kind does not
relies on the idea that any adequate theory of law must commit one to any thick evaluative claims. Nonetheless,
take account of the internal point of view that legal there is a deeper or more interesting sense in which
practitioners tend to adopt towards the law. More Dworkin’s view renders legal theory inherently
specifically, taking the internal point of view towards the evaluative. For Dworkin, legal theory is an interpretive
law is a matter of adopting some kind of attitude of enterprise, and offering a constructive interpretation of
endorsement towards it, seeing it as in some sense legal practice requires construing it in its best moral
justified or as providing reasons for action (Shapiro light. Thus, offering an interpretation of legal practice
2011, 96–97; Perry 1995, 99–100; see also the entry would require taking a stand on which of the available
on legal positivism). Moreover, it is common to think ways of construing that practice is morally better than
that a critical mass of the participants in legal practice the others. Of course, this does not necessarily require
must adopt the internal point of view towards the asserting that the law, on any particular construal, isgood
practice in order for the practice to genuinely count as —full stop. But it does seem to require at least saying
law. This is a fact that any adequate theory of law must that some construals of legal practice are
account for, one might think. Accordingly, since the morally better than other construals would be. This looks
internal point of view involves a positive evaluation of to be a thick evaluative claim, albeit a comparative one.
the law, and since any adequate legal theory must Moreover, one cannot make such comparative judgments
account for this point of view, one might infer that any without having a view about what would make one
adequate theory of law must itself be inherently construal of legal practice morally better than another.
evaluative. (One finds versions of such an argument, Thus, in at least this sense, taking legal theory to be an
e.g., in Perry 1995, 121–25; Waldron 2001, 423–28.) endeavor that is interpretive in Dworkin’s sense would
It is unclear whether this argument succeeds, however. make legal theory count as inherently evaluative in the
After all, it seems in principle possible to explain what sense we are concerned with here.
kinds of considerations legal practitioners endorse, and Accordingly, if one wants to maintain the possibility of
why, without oneselfendorsing those considerations. purely descriptive first-order legal theories, a more
Similarly, a first-order legal theory might be able to promising strategy for responding to the argument from
plausibly explain the truism that legal practitioners tend interpretation would be to question its key premise—
to take the internal point of view towards (i.e., endorse) viz., that legal theory necessarily is an interpretive
the law in their respective jurisdictions without the endeavor in Dworkin’s sense. In order for a proponent of
theory thereby being committed to the claim that the law the argument from interpretation to assert this premise,
in any particular jurisdiction (or the law in general) is some rationale would have to be given for it. That is,
valuable or justified. Accordingly, it is not obvious why some argument would be needed to explain why we
a theory of law cannot in principle capture the internal should think that understanding law requires giving a
point of view taken by legal practitioners towards the constructive interpretation of it. A critic of the argument
law without itself being committed to any thick from interpretation, then, might claim that the
evaluative claims about the law. argument’s proponents have not carried their burden of
providing a rationale for this premise, on which the
The argument from interpretation argument crucially depends.
Probably the most influential argument for thinking that One possible rationale that might be offered here is that
legal theory is inherently evaluative proceeds from the since social practices essentially involve communication,
idea that legal theory is an interpretive endeavor in and understanding any form of communication
Dworkin’s sense (Dworkin 1986; for criticism, see necessarily involves interpreting speakers’ claims,
Dickson 2001, 105; Marmor 2011, 126–30). To say that understanding the social practice of law necessarily
legal theory is an interpretive project is to claim that involves interpreting it. However, this rationale is too
fully understanding what the law is requires construing it quick. Even if it is true that understanding any social
as the best instance it can be of the type of thing that it practice requires interpretation of some kind or other, it
is. Moreover, one might think that in order to construe does not follow that doing so requires aconstructive
legal practice as the best instance of the kind of thing interpretation in Dworkin’s sense—i.e., identifying a
that it is requires making thick evaluative claims about construal of the practice that casts it in its best moral
the law. (See the entry on legal interpretivism.) light (Marmor 2011, 127–28). But the latter claim, of
One might attempt to respond to this argument in two course, is what proponents of the argument from
ways. A natural, though ultimately unsuccessful, reply is interpretation need to establish in order to reach their
that construing something as the best instance of its kind desired conclusion that legal theory is inherently
that it can be does not require taking that kind to evaluative.
be good. Saying that Bernie Madoff was (for a time) the
best fraudster in history does not entail that one approves
Accordingly, we seem to be left in the following would be free to maintain that there can be purely
dialectical situation. Whether or not legal theory is descriptive first-order legal theories.
inherently evaluative in the relevant sense depends on Of course, even if the argument from interpretation fails
whether the argument from interpretation succeeds. and purely descriptive legal theories remain possible, it
Whether that argument succeeds, in turn, depends on its could still be a worthwhile project to attempt to give a
key premise, i.e., the claim that understanding the law constructive interpretation of legal practice, and the
necessarily requires giving a constructive output of this project would indeed be a partially
interpretationof it. If a non-question begging argument evaluative theory. Nonetheless, these two types of theory
can be given for this claim, then there would be reason would not genuinely be in conflict, as they would be
to think that legal theory necessarily is evaluative in addressed to answering different questions. In the end,
nature. By contrast, if no non-question begging argument therefore, “methodological pluralism” may be the most
can be given for thinking that understanding apt characterization of the state of play in jurisprudence.
law requires a constructive interpretation, then one

You might also like