You are on page 1of 7

eventually raise their hands in response to the

The Pure Theory question of whether they approve a certain


document or not, count the number of people
of Law who say “yes”, and then promulgate a string of
words, etc. Now, of course, the actions and
First published Mon Nov 18, 2002; substantive events described here are not the law. To say
revision Mon Jan 4, 2016 that the description is of the enactment of a new
law is to interpret these actions and events in a
The idea of a Pure Theory of Law was certain way. But then, of course, the question is
propounded by the formidable Austrian jurist why certain acts or events have such a legal
and philosopher Hans Kelsen (1881–1973) (see meaning and others don’t?
the bibliographical note). Kelsen began his long
career as a legal theorist at the beginning of the Kelsen’s answer to this question is surprisingly
20th century. The traditional legal philosophies simple: an act or an event gains its legal-
at the time, were, Kelsen claimed, hopelessly normative meaning by another legal norm that
contaminated with political ideology and confers this normative meaning on it. An act
moralizing on the one hand, or with attempts to can create or modify the law if it is created in
reduce the law to natural or social sciences, on accordance with another, “higher” legal norm
the other hand. He found both of these that authorizes its creation in that way. And the
reductionist endeavors seriously flawed. “higher” legal norm, in turn, is legally valid if
Instead, Kelsen suggested a ‘pure’ theory of law and only if it has been created in accord with
which would avoid reductionism of any kind. yet another, “higher” norm that authorizes its
The jurisprudence Kelsen propounded enactment in that way. In other words: it is the
“characterizes itself as a ‘pure’ theory of law law in the United States that the California
because it aims at cognition focused on the law legislature can enact certain types of laws. But
alone” and this purity serves as its “basic what makes this the law? The California
methodological principle” (PT1, 7). Constitution confers this power on the state
legislature to enact laws within certain
prescribed boundaries of content and
jurisdiction. But then what makes the California
Constitution legally valid? The answer is that
1. The Basic Norm the legal validity of the Constitution of
The main challenge for a theory of law, as California derives from an authorization granted
Kelsen saw it, is to provide an explanation of by the US Constitution. What makes the US
legality and the normativity of law, without an Constitution legally valid? Surely, not the fact
attempt to reduce jurisprudence, or “legal that the US Constitution proclaims itself to be
science”, to other domains. The law, Kelsen “the supreme law of the land”. Any document
maintained, is basically a scheme of can say that, but only the particular document of
interpretation. Its reality, or objectivity, resides the US Constitution is actually the supreme law
in the sphere of meaning; we attach a legal- in the United States.
normative meaning to certain actions and events The problem is that here the chain of
in the world (PT1, 10). Suppose, for example, authorization comes to an end: There isn’t a
that a new law is enacted by the California higher legal norm that authorizes the enactment
legislature. How is it done? Presumably, some of the (original) US Constitution. At this point,
people gather in a hall, debate the issue, Kelsen famously argued, one must presuppose
the legal validity of the Constitution. At some function is to explain the systematic nature of
stage, in every legal system, we get to an legal norms. These three issues are not un-
authorizing norm that has not been authorized related.
by any other legal norm, and thus it has to be
Kelsen rightly noticed that legal norms
presupposed to be legally valid. The normative
necessarily come in systems. There are no free-
content of this presupposition is what Kelsen
floating legal norms. If, for example, somebody
has called the basic norm. The basic norm is the
suggests that “the law requires a will to be
content of the presupposition of the legal
attested by two witnesses”, one should always
validity of the (first, historical) constitution of
wonder which legal system is talked about; is it
the relevant legal system (GT, 110–111).
US law, Canadian law, German law, or the law
As Kelsen saw it, there is simply no alternative. in some other legal system? Furthermore, legal
More precisely, any alternative would violate systems are themselves organized in a
David Hume’s injunction against deriving an hierarchical structure, manifesting a great deal
“ought” from an “is”. Hume famously argued of complexity but also a certain systematic
that any practical argument that concludes with unity. We talk about Canadian law, or German
some prescriptive statement, a statement of the law, etc., not only because these are separate
kind that one ought to do this or that, would countries in which there is law. They are also
have to contain at least one prescriptive separate legal systems, manifesting a certain
statement in its premises. If all the premises of cohesion and unity. This systematic unity
an argument are descriptive, telling us what this Kelsen meant to capture by the following two
or that is the case, then there is no prescriptive postulates:
conclusion that can logically follow. Kelsen
took this argument very seriously. He observed 1. Every two norms that ultimately derive
that the actions and events that constitute, say, their validity from one basic norm
the enactment of a law, are all within the sphere belong to the same legal system.
of what “is” the case, they are all within the 2. All legal norms of a given legal system
sphere of actions and events that take place in ultimately derive their validity from one
the world. The law, or legal norms, are within basic norm.
the sphere of “ought”, they are norms that Whether these two postulates are actually true is
purport to guide conduct. Thus, to get an a contentious issue. Joseph Raz argued that they
“ought” type of conclusion from a set of “is” are both inaccurate, at best. Two norms can
premises, one must point to some “ought” derive their validity from the same basic norm,
premise in the background, an “ought” that but fail to belong to the same system as, for
confers the normative meaning on the relevant example, in case of an orderly secession
type of “is”. Since the actual, legal, chain of whereby a new legal system is created by the
validity comes to an end, we inevitably reach a legal authorization of another. Nor is it
point where the “ought” has to be presupposed, necessarily true that all the legally valid norms
and this is the presupposition of the basic norm. of a given system derive their validity from the
The idea of the basic norm serves three same basic norm (Raz 1979, 127–129).
theoretical functions in Kelsen’s theory of law: Be this as it may, even if Kelsen erred about the
The first is to ground a non-reductive details of the unity of legal systems, his main
explanation of legal validity. The second insight remains true, and quite important. It is
function is to ground a non-reductive true that law is essentially systematic, and it is
explanation of the normativity of law. The third also true that the idea of legal validity and law’s
systematic nature are very closely linked. as we shall see below, Kelsen had no choice
Norms are legally valid within a given system, here. And this is precisely why at least one
they have to form part of a system of norms that crucial aspect of his anti-reductionism becomes
is in force in a given place and time. questionable.
This last point brings us to another observation
that is central to Kelsen’s theory, about the 2. Relativism and
relations between legal validity and, what he
called, “efficacy”. The latter is a term of art in
Reduction
Kelsen’s writings: A norm is efficacious if it is Common wisdom has it that Kelsen’s argument
actually (generally) followed by the relevant for the presupposition of the basic norm takes
population. Thus, “a norm is considered to be the form of a Kantian transcendental argument.
legally valid”, Kelsen wrote, “on the condition The structure is as follows:
that it belongs to a system of norms, to an order
which, on the whole, is efficacious” (GT, 42). 1. P is possible only if Q
So the relationship here is this: efficacy is not a 2. P is possible (or, possibly P)
condition of legal validity of individual norms. 3. Therefore, Q.
Any given norm can be legally valid even if
nobody follows it. (e.g. think about a new law, In Kelsen’s argument, P stands for the fact that
just enacted; it is legally valid even if nobody legal norms are “ought” statements , and Q is
has yet had an opportunity to comply with it.) the presupposition of the basic norm. In other
However, a norm can only be legally valid if it words, the necessary presupposition of the basic
belongs to a system, a legal order, that is by and norm is derived from the possibility conditions
large actually practiced by a certain population. for ascribing legal significance to actions and
And thus the idea of legal validity, as Kelsen events. In order to interpret an action as one of
admits, is closely tied to this reality of a social creating or modifying the law, it is necessary to
practice; a legal system exists, as it were, only show that the relevant legal significance of the
as a social reality, a reality that consists in the act/event is conferred on it by some other legal
fact that people actually follow certain norms. norm. At some point, as we have noted, we
necessarily run out of legal norms that confer
What about the basic norm, is efficacy a the relevant validity on law creating acts, and at
condition of its validity? One might have that point the legal validity has to be
thought that Kelsen would have opted for a presupposed. The content of this presupposition
negative answer here. After all, the basic norm is the basic norm.
is a presupposition that is logically required to
render the validity of law intelligible. This It would be a mistake, however, to look for an
would seem to be the whole point of an anti- explanation of Kelsen’s argument in the logic of
reductionist explanation of legal validity: since Kant’s transcendental argument. (Kelsen
we cannot derive an “ought” from an “is”, some himself seems to have changed his views about
“ought” must be presupposed in the background this over the years; he may have started with a
that would enable us to interpret certain acts or kind of neo-Kantian perspective one can discern
events as having legal significance. Kelsen, in PT1, and gradually shifted to a Humean
however, quite explicitly admits that efficacy is version of his main argument, which is quite
a condition of the validity of the basic norm: A evident in GT. However, this is a very
basic norm is legally valid if and only if it is controversial issue; for a different view, see
actually followed in a given population. In fact, Paulson 2013 and Green 2016.) Kant employed
a transcendental argument to establish the
necessary presuppositions of some categories basic norm of their respective religion, namely,
and modes of perception that are essential for that one ought to obey God’s commands. Thus
rational cognition, or so he thought. They form the normativity of religion, like that of the law,
deep, universal, and necessary features of rests on the presupposition of its basic norm.
human cognition. Suffice it to recall that it was But in both cases, as, in fact, with any other
Hume’s skepticism about knowledge that Kant normative system, the presupposition of the
strove to answer by his transcendental basic norm is logically required only of those
argument. Kelsen, however, remains much who regard the relevant norms as reasons for
closer to Hume’s skeptical views than to Kant’s their actions. Thus, whether you actually
rationalism. In particular, Kelsen was very presuppose the relevant basic norm is a matter
skeptical of any objective grounding of of choice, it is an ideological option, as it were,
morality, Kant’s moral theory included. not something that is dictated by Reason.
Kelsen’s view of morality was relativist all the Similarly, the normativity of law, presupposed
way down. (More on this, below). Second, and by its basic norm, is optional: “An anarchist, for
not unrelated, as we shall see, Kelsen has instance, who denied the validity of the
explicitly rejected the idea that the basic norm hypothetical basic norm of positive law…. will
(in law, or of any other normative domain) is view its positive regulation of human
something like a necessary feature or category relationships… as mere power relations” (GT,
of human cognition. The presupposition of a 413).
basic norm is optional. One does not have to
Relativism, however, comes with a price.
accept the normativity of law; anarchism, as a
Consider this question: What is the content of
rejection of law’s normative validity is certainly
the basic norm that one needs to presuppose in
an option, Kelsen maintained. The basic norm is
order to render positive law intelligible as a
presupposed only by those who accept the
normative legal order? The simple answer is
“ought”, that is, the normative validity, of the
that what one presupposes here is precisely the
law. But one is not rationally compelled to have
normative validity of positive law, namely, the
this attitude:
law that is actually practiced by a certain
The Pure Theory describes the positive law as population. The validity of the basic norm, as
an objectively valid order and states that this we noted briefly earlier, is conditional on its
interpretation is possible only under the “efficacy”. The content of the basic norm of any
condition that a basic norm is presupposed…. given legal system is determined by the actual
The Pure Theory, thereby characterizes this practices that prevail in the relevant community.
interpretation as possible, not necessary, and As Kelsen himself repeatedly argued, a
presents the objective validity of positive law successful revolution brings about a radical
only as conditional—namely conditioned by the change in the content of the basic norm.
presupposed basic norm. (PT2, 217–218) Suppose, for example, that in a given legal
system the basic norm is that the constitution
A comparison to religion, that Kelsen himself enacted by Rex One is binding. At a certain
offered, might be helpful here. The normative point, a coup d’etat takes place and a republican
structure of religion is very similar to that of government is successfully installed. At this
law. It has the same logic: religious beliefs point, Kelsen admits, ‘one presupposes a new
about what one ought to do ultimately derive basic norm, no longer the basic norm delegating
from one’s beliefs about God’s commands. law making authority to the monarch, but a
God’s commands, however, would only have basic norm delegating authority to the
normative validity for those who presuppose the revolutionary government’ (PT1, 59).
Has Kelsen just violated his own adherence to reductionism can be avoided. In fact, what
Hume’s injunction against deriving “ought” Kelsen really offered us here is an invitation to
from an “is” here? One gets the clear provide a reductive explanation of the concept
impression that Kelsen was aware of a serious of legal validity in terms of some set of social
difficulty in his position. In both editions of the facts, the facts that constitute the content of any
Pure Theory of Law, Kelsen toys with the idea given basic norm. (Which is precisely the kind
that perhaps changes in the basic norms of of reduction H.L.A. Hart later offered in his
municipal legal systems legally derive from the account of the Rules of Recognition as social
basic norm of public international law. It is a rules [see Hart 1961, at p. 105, where Hart
basic principle of international law that state alludes to the difference between his conception
sovereignty is determined by actual control over of the rules of recognition and Kelsen’s idea of
a territory/population (PT1 61–62, though in the basic norm.])
PT2, 214–215, the idea is presented with greater
Kelsen’s problem here is not due to the fact that
hesitation; notably, some commentators argue
he was a relativist with respect to every
that Kelsen took the idea of a universal legal
normative system, like morality, religion etc.; it
order much more seriously than suggested here
is not the scope of his relativism that is relevant
—see Green 2016). But this led Kelsen to the
to the question of reduction. The problem stems
rather uncomfortable conclusion that there is
from the fact that Kelsen was quite right about
only one basic norm in the entire world,
the law. Legal validity is essentially relative to
namely, the basic norm of public international
the social facts that constitute the content of the
law. Be this as it may, the main worry lies
basic norm in each and every legal order. Notice
elsewhere. The worry stems from the fact that it
that legal validity is always relative to a time
is very difficult, if not impossible, to maintain
and place. A law enacted by the California
both a profound relativist and an anti-
legislature only applies within the boundaries of
reductionist position with respect to a given
the state of California, and it applies during a
normative domain. If you hold the view that the
certain period of time, after its enactment and
validity of a type of norms is entirely relative to
until a time when it is modified or repealed.
a certain vantage point—in other words, if what
And we can see why: because legal validity is
is involved here is only the actual conduct,
determined by the content of the basic norm that
beliefs/presuppositions and attitudes of people
is actually followed in a given society. The laws
—it becomes very difficult to detach the
in UK, for example, are different from those in
explanation of that normative validity from the
the US, because people (mostly judges and
facts that constitute the relevant point of view
other officials) actually follow different rules, or
(namely, the facts about people’s actions,
basic norms, in Kelsen’s terminology, about
beliefs, attitudes, etc). This is basically what
what counts as law in their respective
was meant earlier by the comment that Kelsen
jurisdictions. Once Kelsen admits, as he does,
had no option but to admit that the validity of
that the content of a basic norm is fully
the basic norm is conditional on its efficacy.
determined by practice, it becomes very
The normative relativism which is inherent in
difficult to understand how the explication of
Kelsen’s conception forces him to ground the
legal validity he offers is non-reductive.
content of the basic norm in the social facts that
constitute its content, namely, the facts about
actions, beliefs, and attitudes actually
3. The Normativity of
entertained by the population in question. And
this makes it very questionable that
Law
Let us now see how Kelsen thought that the of law; however, even the anarchist can make
basic norm helps to explain the sense in which an argument about what the law in this or that
law is a normative domain and what this context requires; and when she makes such an
normativity consists in. The first and crucial argument, she must presuppose the legal point
point to realize is that for Kelsen the idea of of view, she must argue as if she endorses the
normativity is tantamount to a genuine “ought”, basic norm of the relevant legal system. Joseph
as it were; it is a justified demand on practical Raz has called these kinds of statements
deliberation. A certain content is regarded as “detached normative statements”; the anarchist
normative by an agent if and only if the agent argues as if she endorses the basic norm,
regards that content as a valid reason for action. without actually endorsing it. Another example
As Joseph Raz noticed, Kelsen agrees with the that Raz gave is this: suppose that at Catholic
Natural Law tradition in this particular respect; priest is an expert in Jewish Law; the priest can
both assume that the normativity of law can make various interpretative arguments about
only be explained as one would explain the what Jewish law really requires in this or that
normativity of morality, or religion for that context. In such a case, the priest must argue as
matter, namely, in terms of valid reasons for if he endorses the basic norm of Jewish Law,
action (Raz 1979, 134–137; but cf. Paulson but of course, being a Catholic, he does not
2012). But then, the problem for Kelsen is how really endorse it, it does not reflect his own
to explain the difference between the views about what is right and wrong (Raz 1979,
normativity of law and that of morality; if legal 153–157).
“ought” is a genuine “ought”, what makes a
So here is what emerges so far: the concept of
legal obligation distinct from a moral one?
normativity, the sense in which normative
Kelsen’s answer is that the relevant “ought” is
content is related to reasons for action, is the
always relative to a given point of view. Each
same across all normative domains. To regard
and every type of “ought”, be it religious, moral
something as normative is to regard it as
or legal, must presuppose a certain point of
justified, as a warranted requirement on
view, a point of view which is constituted by
practical deliberation. However, the difference
the basic norm of the relevant normative
resides in the difference in points of view. Each
system.
basic norm determines, as it were, a certain
In other words, Kelsen’s conception of legal point of view. So it turns out that normativity
normativity turns out to be a form of Natural (contra Kant) always consists of conditional
Law completely relativized to a certain point of imperatives: if, and only if, one endorses a
view. However, in Kelsen’s theory the relevant certain normative point of view, determined by
point of view is distinctly a legal one, not some its basic norm, then the norms that follow from
general conception of morality or Reason. That it are reason giving, so to speak. This enables
these two basic norms, or points of view, can Kelsen to maintain the same understanding of
come apart, is nicely demonstrated by Kelsen’s the nature of normativity as Natural Law’s
comment that “even an anarchist, if he were a conception, namely, normativity qua reasons for
professor of law, could describe positive law as action, without having to conflate the
a system of valid norms, without having to normativity of morality with that of law. In
approve of this law” (PT2 218n). The anarchist other words, the difference between legal
does not endorse the legal point of view as one normativity and, say, moral normativity, is not a
that reflects her own views about what is right difference in normativity (viz, about the nature
and wrong. Anarchism is understood here of normativity, per se), but only in the relevant
precisely as a rejection of the normative validity vantage point that is determined by their
different basic norms. What makes legal unanswered. Instead of providing an
normativity unique is the uniqueness of its point explanation of what makes the presupposition
of view, the legal point of view, as it were. of the legal point of view rational, or what
makes it rational to regard the requirements of
We can set aside the difficulties that such a
law as binding requirements, Kelsen invites us
view raises with respect to morality. Obviously,
to stop asking.
many philosophers would reject Kelsen’s view
that moral reasons for action only apply to those
who choose to endorse morality’s basic norm Bibliography
(whatever it may be). Even if Kelsen is quite
wrong about this conditional nature of moral Primary Sources
imperatives, he may be right about the law. Kelsen’s academic publications span over
What remains questionable, however, is almost seven decades in which he published
whether Kelsen succeeds in providing a non- dozens of books and hundreds of articles. Only
reductive explanation of legal normativity, about a third of this vast literature has been
given the fact that his account of legal validity translated to English. Kelsen’s two most
turned out to be reductive after all. The trouble important books on the pure theory of law are
here is not simply the relativity to a point of the first edition of hisReine Rechtslehre,
view; the trouble resides in Kelsen’s failure to published in 1934 and recently (2002)
ground the choice of the relevant point of view translated. The second edition, which Kelson
in anything like Reason or reasons of any kind. published in 1960 (translated in 1967) is a
By deliberately avoiding any explanation of considerably extended version of the first
what it is that might ground an agent’s choice of edition. In addition, most of the themes in these
endorsing the legal point of view, or any given two books also appear in Kelsen’s General
basic norm, Kelsen left the most pressing Theory of Law and State. These three works are
questions about the normativity of law cited in text as follows:
[PT1]   1934/2002. Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory, B.L. Paulson and S.L. Paulson, trans.,
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
[PT2]   1960/1967. Pure Theory of Law, M. Knight, trans., Berkeley: University of California Press.
[GT]   1945/1961. General Theory of Law and State, A. Wedberg, trans., New York: Russell & Russell.
Other relevant publications in English include What is Justice?, UC Berkeley Press, 1957, ‘The Pure
Theory of Law and Analytical Jurisprudence’, 55 Harvard L. Rev. (1941), 44, ‘Professor Stone and the
Pure Theory of Law: A Reply’, (1965), 17 Stanford L. Rev. 1128, and ‘On the Pure Theory of Law’
(1966), 1 Israel L. Rev. 1.
For a complete list of Kelsen’s publications that have appeared in English see the Appendix to H.
Kelsen, General Theory of Norms (M. Hartney trans.) Oxford, 1991, pp. 440–454.

You might also like