You are on page 1of 8

Review of General Psychology © 2015 American Psychological Association

2015, Vol. 19, No. 3, 207–214 1089-2680/15/$12.00 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/gpr0000051

Why Psychology Isn’t Unified, and Probably Never Will Be


Christopher D. Green
York University

Over the past few decades, a large literature has emerged on the question of how one might unify all or
most of psychology under a single, coherent, rigorous framework, in a manner similar to that which
unified physics under Newton’s Laws, or biology under Darwin’s theory of natural selection. It is argued
here that this is a highly unlikely scenario in psychology given the contingent and opportunistic character
of the processes that brought its original topics together into a new discipline, and the nearly continuous
institutional, social, and even political negotiating and horse-trading that has determined psychology’s
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

“boundaries” in the 14 decades since. Psychology, as the field currently stands, does not have the
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

intellectual coherence to be brought together by any set of principles that would enable its phenomena
to be captured and explained as rigorous products of those principles. If there is a kind of unification in
psychology’s future, it is more likely to be one that, paradoxically, sees it broken up into a number of
large “super-subdisciplines,” each of which exhibits more internal coherence than does the current
sprawling and heterogeneous whole.

Keywords: psychology, history, philosophy, theory, unity

The question of whether psychology can be “unified” is one that In psychology, there have been many proposals for a similar
has long occupied the discipline. In order to be “unified” in the kind of unification. American Psychologist was long a prime venue
sense I intend here, the discipline would have a common set of for such work (Kimble, 1989, 1994, 1999; Staats, 1981, 1991;
foundational principles from which detailed descriptions of its Sternberg & Grigorenko, 2001). Since the founding of The Review
phenomena could be rigorously derived and by which they could of General Psychology, it has become a popular vehicle for them
be explained.1 It seems that if only psychologists could agree on as well (Marsh & Boag, 2014; Staats, 1999; Yanchar & Slife,
these fundamentals—the mental and/or behavioral “elements,” and 1997), highlighted by a special issue on the topic in 2013 (Ander-
the basic principles of their interactions—then the discipline would son, 2013; Catania, 2013; Charles, 2013; Chemero, 2013; Clegg,
start making the kind of impressive progress that we have seen in 2013; Heft, 2013; Henriques, 2013; Hutto, 2013; Lerner, Agans,
natural science over the past few centuries. DeSouza, & Gasca, 2013; Lickliter & Honeycutt, 2013; Marken &
The most commonly raised example of this kind of unification Mansell, 2013; Mayer & Allen, 2013; Petocz & Mackay, 2013).
is found in physics, which is often said to have been unified under Proposals for the unification of psychology have hardly been
Newton’s Laws which were, in turn, reliant on his mathematical confined to these two journals, however. There have been others as
discoveries. Another prime example is in biology, large parts of well (e.g., Goertzen, 2008, 2010; Henriques, 2004, 2011; Kimble,
which were unified under Darwin’s theory evolution by natural 1996; Staats, 1983; Kristensen, Slife, & Yanchar, 2000; Stam,
selection.2 One of the most significant aspects of these two epoch- 2004, 2015). An interesting counterpoint to these diverse efforts
making scientific developments is that they not only provided a can be found in Sigmund Koch’s call to concede that psychology
common explanatory framework for disparate aspects of complex cannot be unified and to rename the field “psychological studies”
fields of study (e.g., respectively, the motions of both terrestrial (Koch, 1993).3
cannon balls and of celestial planets; the seemingly ubiquitous
hierarchical arrangement of species in both the animal and plant
kingdoms), but they were later extended and adapted to provide 1
I contrast this sense of unification with another that is often offered:
explanations for phenomena that were either unknown or poorly mere descriptions of high-level similarities among diverse research areas.
understood at the time the framework was first proposed (e.g., These do not unify a discipline in any important sense. They serve mainly
electrical force; the development of antibiotic resistance), thereby as appeals to common ideas that hold psychologists together as an insti-
strengthening the unity of the field even further. tutional community, but do not show that diverse psychological phenom-
ena spring from the same fundamental bases.
2
Of course, both of these unifications have been superseded in their
respective fields by more recent developments—relativistic and quantum
This article was published Online First August 17, 2015. mechanics in the case of physics, and the “synthesis” of evolutionary
This research article was written while the author was the recipient of an theory with genetics in the case of biology, but these details need not detain
us here.
Insight Grant from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council 3
Some have argued that psychology can never be unified in the ways
of Canada. I thank Thomas Teo and Andrew S. Winston for their com- that physics and biology were because the field is inherently embedded in
ments on earlier drafts of this article. historically contingent sociocultural practices (e.g., Teo, 2010; Walsh-
Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Christo- Bowers, 2010). If these critics are correct, then unification may be blocked
pher D. Green, Department of Psychology, York University, Toronto, for reasons that are even more fundamental than those discussed in this
Ontario M3J 1P3, Canada. E-mail: christo@yorku.ca article.

207
208 GREEN

Perhaps ironically, the various proposals for unification have predictive accuracy and broad scope, they have fallen dramatically
come from a diverse range of epistemological and ontological short (e.g., Hull, 1943).4
perspectives. All too often, however, they have amounted essen- There was a time when it was popular to argue that psychology
tially to the author asserting that the perspective on psychology to was following Thomas Kuhn’s famous formula for the progress of
which he or she is already committed on prior grounds—whether mature science under the auspices of successive “paradigms” (see,
behavioristic, humanistic, evolutionary, computational, and so e.g., Coleman & Salamon, 1988 for a summary and assessment).
forth—is, in principle, sufficient to capture and explain all of This happened (and continues, to some degree) despite the coun-
psychology, or at least enough of it to create a kind of dominant tervailing fact that the early psychological systems—Structural-
subdiscipline within the broader psychology that implicitly chal- ism, Functionalism, Psychoanalysis, Gestalt, Behaviorism, and so
lenges all other areas to either get on board or find another boat. forth—were obviously overlapping, competing “schools of
This tactic, popular as it might be, is highly unlikely to succeed thought,” rather than consensual “paradigms” that successively
because the perspective that is put forth as the basis for unification captured the entire field. This state of affairs is precisely what
is already well-known to the audience to whom it is proposed, and Kuhn himself said characterizes the state of science is in its
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

those individuals who did not accept it before in the area where it “pre-paradigmatic” phase: “schools of thought.” There is also the
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

first gained credibility are virtually certain not to accept it as the glaring fact that Kuhn specifically excluded the social sciences
basis for psychology more broadly. from his scheme, using psychology as a key example (see, e.g.,
What is required from a unification proposal is a theory, prob- Kuhn, 1970, p. 160). Kuhn’s model of paradigmatic science is
ably framed in a mathematical or otherwise formal language, inapplicable to psychology, whether or not it is true elsewhere in
which rigorously captures apparently disparate phenomena. The the sciences.
chief reasons to employ a formal language are essentially three- Wilhelm Wundt, as is well known, strove from the 1860s
fold. First, a formal language can bridge across areas that differ in forward to render psychology scientific by employing the methods
terms of their concrete content, but that have similar underlying and, perhaps more important, the equipment that had succeeded in
structural properties. Second, it is in formal languages that the reshaping physiology as an experimental science in previous de-
work of prediction, and the sort of explanation that relies upon cades to address his questions about the mind. He achieved a fair
prediction, can be most satisfactorily achieved. I am not among degree of success, founding the first university-authorized institute
those who believe that these are the only legitimate goals of dedicated exclusively to experimental psychology at Leipzig in
science, but the accurate prediction of new phenomena is certainly 1879, and drawing dozens of students from all over the world to
an impressive achievement when it can be attained, and it is most study with him and learn his methods. But even he recognized that
the range of psychological phenomena that he could tame into a
convincingly accomplished in the context of a formal language.
form suitable to laboratory investigation was highly restricted.
That is to say, formal language (the “right” language, not just any
Fractionating reaction times into sensations, perceptions, acts of
superficial formalism) enables one to achieve both breadth of
will, muscular reactions, and, at the center of these, the all-
scope and fidelity to detail at the same time. Finally, formal
important apperceptions—impressive as the feat might have
languages often have the ability to short-circuit the all-too-
been—was only a small part of the totality of the mind (see
common impulse to become mired in endless (and often pointless)
Robinson, 2001). Although he continued to manage his very
a priori disputes about which theoretical ideology is to be pre-
productive laboratory into the 1910s, Wundt devoted his own
ferred—for example, behavioral, evolutionary, humanistic, and so
greatest efforts to writing the 10-volume Völkerpsychologie, in
forth. If the predictions work, they work.
which he described the artistic, religious, and broader cultural lives
Newton’s laws of motion did precisely this— explaining why
of various peoples—all human mental activities that he did not
the apple falls directly to the ground, why the cannon ball flies for
believe to be amenable to the constraints of the laboratory.
some distance before returning to the ground, and why the moon
Many of Wundt’s American students brought his ideas about the
revolves about the earth in apparent perpetuity. The Newtonian psychological utility of kymographs and chronoscopes back across
framework was later successfully extended to matters such as fluid the ocean, and they established similar laboratories in their home
dynamics and electromagnetism, among others—areas that are colleges and universities. This importation of the physical mani-
different in content from those that Newton began with, but that festations of German expertise was very impressive to college
turned out to be structurally similar. Darwin’s theory was not trustees and presidents, but it left many of the psychologists
framed in formal language at first, but neither did it immediately themselves frustrated with the inherent limitations of such a view
capture its field. Its gradual integration with Mendelian genetics in of the field. The momentary reactions of the well-prepared normal
the early decades of the 20th century, and the later rise to domi- adult male human mind to a sparse array of artificial laboratory
nance of the “Modern Synthesis” (Huxley, 1942) was, in no small stimuli did not bring them intellectual satisfaction. Instead, many
part, dependent on its redescription in formal terms (e.g., Hardy, sought to found scientific psychology anew on the basis of Dar-
1908; Weinberg, 1908). As a result, evolutionary models have winian evolutionary theory. They sought to expand the repertoire
been successfully applied to topics far removed from the biological of mentalities explored to include children and women, workers
realm where Darwin first developed them.
By contrast, psychological attempts at unification have rarely
4
even aspired to this degree of formal rigor and, as a result, they Various interesting candidates for “rigorous, formal over-arching psy-
chological framework” have appeared over the decades: for example,
have been unable to facilitate psychological prediction or expla- psychophysics, signal detection theory, decision theory, game theory.
nation to any significant degree. Even when psychological theo- While all have been valuable, none has gone on to attain the range of
rists have attempted to develop a formal language to achieve both application that would be needed to unify the discipline as a whole.
WHY PSYCHOLOGY ISN’T UNIFIED 209

and asylum patients, cats and chickens and fish, and even insects. Cave” studies of group behavior, Adorno’s “authoritarian person-
In short, they wanted psychology to cover the full array of mental ality,” Ash’s studies of compliance, Festinger’s theory of cognitive
variation, and to consider what forces— both internal and exter- dissonance, to name just a few. These were in no significant way
nal—might have led it to evolve in the way it had, and how it dependent on behaviorist theory (though sometimes attempts were
might evolve further in the future (see, e.g., Green, 2009). made to shoehorn them into some version of behaviorism, often in
This extremely tumultuous state of affairs was given the name order to shield them from the judgmental eye of one disciplinary
“Functionalism” by its most vocal opponent, E. B Titchener (an authority or another).7
Englishman who was trained in Germany and then employed, Beyond the observation that much important mid-20th-century
sometimes to his chagrin, in America).5 Functionalists shared American psychology was not behavioristic, there is also a certain
some broad aspirational themes, to be sure, but Functionalism by level of unreflective nationalism lurking beneath the claim that
no means represented a unification of the discipline of psychology. behaviorism was “dominant,” considering that the movement was
Quite to the contrary, its ethos was more in line with letting a never ascendant in Europe, only ever gaining a modest following
hundred flowers bloom. Indeed, G. Stanley Hall was fairly explicit there (not to mention the rest of the world).8 Thus, although
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

about this in an 1894 article, though, in his customary promotional behaviorism may have been an important metatheoretical move-
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

style, he presented it as a strength; a measure of the wide range of ment, it never commanded ascent in the discipline as a whole; it
material covered by the new discipline: was certainly never the stuff of Kuhnian paradigms.
Of course, Kuhn’s model of scientific unification is only one of
It [psychology] studies the instincts of animals from the highest to the
myriad models of how science develops, and it is now mainly of
lowest . . . It shows how the highest intuitions of reason and con-
science are rooted in the lowest animal instincts . . . It studies the
historical interest to most philosophers and historians of science.
myths, customs, and beliefs of primitive man . . . It devotes itself to Contra Kuhn, the course of events may well proceed along differ-
the study of insanity and nervous disease, and has already begun to ent lines in different sciences, according to the unique features of
introduce new methods and utilize new results. It has a special different disciplines (see, e.g., Dupré, 1993; Hacking, 1996;
department of neurology for exploiting all the properties of brain, Lakatoš, 1970; Laudan, 1978).
nerve, and sense . . . It has transformed and shaped the problems of Looking specifically at the history of psychology we can begin
logic and ethics; is slowly rewriting the whole history of philosophy, to see that there are certain aspects to its historical “assembly” as
and . . . is showing itself not only to be the long hoped for, long a discipline that would seem to make it highly unlikely that the
delayed science of man . . . but is introducing a period that will be
particular constellation of topics that currently fall under the head-
known hereafter as the psychological era in scientific thought. (Hall,
ing of “psychology” would ever be unified into a strongly coherent
1894, pp. 160 –161)6
scientific discipline (in any way tantamount to post-Newtonian
It would only require the exchange of a few obsolete turns of physics or post-Darwinian biology).
phrase for more current ones for this paragraph to have been If, for instance, one looks at the sheer variety of topics that G.
written by a psychological enthusiast of the past decade. Stanley Hall invited into the new discipline back in 1887 when he
Behaviorism, which began just a couple of decades later, of launched the very first U.S.-based periodical specializing on the
course, is a special case. Indeed, it is probably the main source of new field of inquiry—the American Journal of Psychology – it is
psychology’s Kuhnian misapprehension and, as such, it requires easy to see that they did not have much in common with each other
special attention. Many believe that behaviorism constituted the either ontologically or epistemologically: experimental work on
first broad unification of psychology, that we somehow “lost” that perception, qualitative writing on (what we would now call) cog-
unity, and that we must now recapture it either under a more nition, historical studies of mind, case studies in psychiatry, and
adequate formulation of behaviorism or under some other overar- physiological work on the nervous system. What is more, some of
ching framework. It must be recalled, however, that there were these early invitees soon moved on to other disciplinary venues,
many species of behaviorism—Watson, Tolman, Hull, Skinner, only to be replaced by new invitees, or by Hall’s own creations:
among others. Some attempted to “redescribe” conventional psy-
chological language in behavioral terms (e.g., Tolman, 1932) 5
Titchener’s fervent hope was to establish the first psychology labora-
while others attempted to eschew the entire traditional vocabulary tory at his alma mater of Oxford. Such a move not seeming imminent, he
in favor of a new behavioral language (e.g., Skinner, 1945). This tried at least to “return to British soil” by repeatedly inquiring about
situation hardly recapitulates the compelling unity of F ⫽ ma or of positions in Canada (Ferguson, 1982; Myers, 1982).
6
evolution ⫽ reproductive variation ⫹ natural selection by fitness. Robert S. Woodworth (1943, pp. 17–18), who quoted this passage even
more extensively than I have, claimed that the article “doubtless closely
Second, although behaviorism (collecting its various conflicting paralleled” Hall’s long-lost inaugural presidential address to the APA in
forms together) may have been the ascendant American metatheory 1892. Because two (far from identical) abstracts of the 1892 speech are all
during the middle of the 20th century, even in its heyday there that are left to us, we will probably never know, but it remains interesting
remained large areas of psychology that it was unable to effectively that this was the vision of psychology that Hall chose to present to
nonpsychologists in the middle of the 1890s: not of a tightly unified
address. Consider that many of the classic studies from the 1930s, discipline, but of one with an enormous range of interests, from the activity
1940s, and 1950s—studies so important that we continue to teach of the individual neuron to complexities of human social life.
7
them to our students even today—stand as monuments against the It is interesting to note that the second-best-known work of Dollard and
claim that psychology was unified under behaviorism: Stevens’ Miller was their attempt to rewrite Freudian psychoanalysis into a form
consistent with Hull’s drive theory.
psychophysical power law, Gesell’s studies of childhood develop- 8
To be entirely fair, behaviorism did have an important presence in both
ment, Terman’s longitudinal studies of intelligence, Dollard and Latin America and Japan, but it would go too far to describe it as having
Miller’s frustration-aggression hypothesis, Sherif’s “Robber’s been the dominant form of psychology in either place.
210 GREEN

intellectual and moral development in children, animal behavior, already-existing campaigns to police the boundaries of its “legit-
and so forth (see Green & Feinerer, 2015). imate” use. Behaviorists, of course, began to reject any (behavior-
Of course, Hall’s journal was soon followed by other similar ally unreduced) mention of mind, psyche, or consciousness as
ventures, most notably James McKeen Cattell and James Mark being “unscientific.” The rapidly expanding psychological testing
Baldwin’s Psychological Review in 1894. The Review was estab- movement—intelligence, vocation, and later personality— only
lished specifically to compete with Hall’s AJP (see Sokal, 1997) crossed behaviorists’ strictures when they sought to reify the
and, consequently it had a somewhat different profile of research various dispositions they were testing, but it was a simple enough
communities: Large sections were devoted to philosophical psy- matter to use the new testing technologies profitably without
chology and psychological metatheory, much of the early Func- taking a strong ontological stance on the matter (see, e.g., Boring,
tionalist experimentation and interpretation, and vision research 1923). The explosive expansion of clinical, educational, voca-
into both color and depth/distance (Green, Feinerer, & Burman, in tional, industrial, and various other species of applied psycholo-
press, 2015). But, again, there was hardly an overarching set of gy—much of it outside of the academy—led to the ranks of such
principles guiding this jumble of different interests. Most research- practitioners soon outnumbering their university-bound cousins.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

ers of the era would have agreed that they were working on one or Although they sometimes drew upon the theoretical constructions
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

another aspect of “consciousness,” but (a) this was a term of art of academic psychologists, many of them worked within disciplin-
often deployed to fend off those who argued, at the time, that ary languages that would be better understood and trusted by their
experimental psychology was not an autonomous discipline but employers and their clients, whether medical, mentalist, psycho-
only a branch of physiology; and (b) appeals to “consciousness” analytic, or something else again.
only provided a broad tent under which many different kinds of I could continue to summarize the history of 20th century
researchers could do their work, not an underlying set of principles psychology—the integration of the American Association for Ap-
to guide the explanatory vocabulary of the new discipline. It is plied Psychology with the APA in the 1940s; the simultaneous
important to recall that as soon as William James (1904a, 1904b) emergence of the Bolder Model; the rise and fall of “third wave”
called consciousness into question, the entire rickety structure humanism; the partial retreat of behaviorism as a theoretical basis
began to fail and Behaviorism burst on to the scene less than a for psychology and its reformulation as a leading basis for various
decade later (one can find the reactions of many of James’ con- therapies; the splintering off from the APA, first, of the Psycho-
temporaries collected together in Taylor & Wozniak, 1996). nomic Society and, later, of the American Psychological Society;
The internal conflicts of the early American Psychological As- the appearance of the Psy. D.; the rises of cognitivism, computa-
sociation reflect some of the differences of opinion over who was tionalism, evolutionism, neuroscience, and so forth. Many readers
truly to count as a psychologist. Some wanted to throw the phi- will already be familiar with these more recent historical turns,
losophers out, even though nearly all of them had originally trained
however. The point I am trying to establish is that “psychology”
in philosophy departments. (The philosophers formed their own
did not originate in a well-circumscribed set of scientific problems
associations just after the turn of the 20th century.) Others wanted
that were pursued by a small group of like-minded intellectuals.
to restrict membership to laboratory researchers only, excluding
Psychology has been a hodge-podge from its very creation, and
those who worked on psychological “applications.” (E. B. Titch-
none of the various efforts to create a theoretically unitary disci-
ener even tried to enforce this ban by forming his own separate
pline out of that miscellany has ever been remotely successful. The
by-invitation-only society—The Experimentalists, later reorga-
unsteady and always-changing alliances of a number of distinct
nized as The Society for Experimental Psychology, which contin-
researcher and practitioner groups under the umbrella term “psy-
ues on to this day.) Various independent associations of applied
chology” has long been more a matter of economic, political, and
psychologists eventually sprung up as well.
institutional contingency than it has been of a clear and consensual
Psychology became extremely popular in its early decades, and
vision of the intellectual problems to be tackled and the methods to
its embrace expanded rapidly. Many new scholarly journals ap-
be used to resolving them.
peared in the early 20th century to satisfy the needs of new
Of course, many will object, correctly, that “origin is not es-
specialties: Journal of Abnormal Psychology (founded 1906), Psy-
chological Clinic (1907), Journal of Educational Psychology sence;” that history is not destiny. The fact that psychology started
(1910), Journal of Animal Behavior (1911), Journal of Experi- out as a congeries of idiosyncratic interests bundled together more
mental Psychology (1916), Psychobiology (1917), Journal of Ap- through administrative and diplomatic efforts than by underlying
plied Psychology (1917), and so forth (see Osier & Wozniak, intellectual coherence does not in any way prevent some clever
1984). After being buffeted, but also nourished, by the trials of person down the line from devising or discovering a means by
World War I, the discipline emerged in the 1920s into what was at which they can be recognized as diverse manifestations of a small
the time described as an “outbreak of psychology” (Leacock, 1924, set of powerful underlying principles. That is, it is not impossible
cited in Benjamin & Baker, 2004, p. 54). Not only was its profes- that these disparate parts might be unified. The entire aim of
sional footprint growing rapidly—new university departments,
new journals, new associations— but the wider public began to 9
The Cummings Center for the History of Psychology at the University
clamor for advice from popular psychology magazines to enhance of Akron, in Ohio, holds a large collection of these rare and fascinating
the quality of their lives, whether romantic, intellectual, religious, publications: Herald of Psychology, Everyday Psychology and Inspiration,
commercial, athletic, or what have you.9 Current Psychology and Successful Living, Brain Power, and Golden Rule
Magazine: The New Psychology are just a few of the titles. The collection
All of this public attention, however, did nothing to “unify” the was first assembled by Ludy T. Benjamin, Jr. who has published about the
discipline. Indeed, the term ”psychology” started being used so history of the public view of psychology in various venues (e.g., Benjamin,
variously that academic psychologists further intensified their 2012).
WHY PSYCHOLOGY ISN’T UNIFIED 211

scientific unification, after all, is to show that what seems to be (though there are ontological implications of speaking in this way
anarchy is, in fact, merely the superficial appearance of an under- that I, personally, would be reluctant to endorse). Later, some large
lying harmony. Who would have guessed, for instance, that the part of the remaining portion of “psychology” might be unified
phenomena of the magnet and of lightning are really just different under another set of principles entirely, separate and distinct from
aspects of a single basic reality until it was shown to be so? Things the first unification. Whether either of these distinctly unified
are darkest before the dawn, and all that. pieces of today’s psychology would continue call itself “psychol-
On the other hand, having conceded the sheer possibility that the ogy” is anyone’s guess, but it would be only a matter of nominal
wildly multifarious psychological phenomena of today might importance, in any case. What is more, it is likely that numerous
eventually be synthesized by some as-yet-undiscovered set of problems now considered to be “psychological” would fail to be
unifying principles, I see little reason to expect that this particular integrated into either of the major unifications that had taken place
assemblage is ripe for unification, especially given the fairly and, thus, become “orphan” problems, just as growth did during
arbitrary social and institutional processes that brought them to- the Newtonian unification of motion. The ultimate fate of these
gether in the first place. What reason might there be for the “orphans” is uncertain. Some might turn out to be special cases of
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

particular set of facts that we call “psychological” today to be any phenomena that are already understood in other disciplines. Some
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

more susceptible to unification than, say, some other more or less might be the bases of yet other new disciplines. Some may,
arbitrarily selected group of happenings in physiology, medicine, instead, turn out to be pseudoproblems: mere words appearing as
education, sociology, anthropology, and the like? problems.
It seems more likely that any sizable unification in the near I have ventured into this bit of “science fiction” not because I
future will not capture the bulk of what is today called “psychol- have any particular knowledge of how psychology’s future will
ogy” (and only that). Instead, it seems more reasonable to expect
play out but, rather, to show imaginatively that there are indeter-
that the discovery of powerful coherent principles would pull
minately many possibilities beyond psychology simply “being
psychology apart into a set of large “super-subdisciplines” that are
unified” or “not being unified,” and many of those possibilities
no more closely related to each other than, say, biology, psychol-
seem, given the somewhat jumbled history of the field, at least as
ogy, economics, sociology, and political science are today. Indeed,
likely as either a Newtonian-style unification or simply continuing
one can see an illustrative historical example of this “pulling apart”
on indefinitely as we have for the past several decades.
in the way that Newton’s Laws “unified” mechanics: One of the
Shifting to a related issue, there is a great deal of debate in
concepts that was discussed and explained in the earlier Aristote-
philosophy of science these days among “realists” and “anti-
lian understanding of motion was “growth.” This was not simply
the growth of a mathematical curve, but growth in the fuller realists.” My guess is that the antirealists are winning at present.
“biological” sense10 that a seed grows into a mature plant (Aris- That, I suspect, would come as something of a surprise to most
totle, ca. 340 bc/1996, pp. 50; 198b16 –21 in the citation format scientists, who, by and large, see themselves as working to get a
that is conventional for ancient works). Growth is, of course, a better understanding of the world “as it is.” Most antirealists’ view
kind of movement, generally speaking, but it was not captured by of science, however is not that “anything goes” or that “all stories
the laws of motion that Newton put forth and, as a result, it was are equally valid,” as they are sometimes caricatured by their
simply abandoned as a concept in physics. It would seem, there- critics.11 Rather, the key assertion is that the history of science,
fore, that it is not only the phenomena that dictate the success of examined over a period of centuries, shows not steady progress by
a theory. Sometimes the success of a theory can dictate which a single scientific method toward some single Truth (as the high
phenomena are to be included in the category the theory covers, school textbooks would have it). Instead, it shows that the foun-
and which are not. Because Newton’s laws of motion did such a dations, methods, aims, and configurations of the sciences are all
good job of describing so wide an array of physical phenomena, constantly subject to negotiation among its “players” and, as a
their failure to illuminate “growth” was regarded as a kind of result, they all experience more or less continuous change—some-
evidence that growth was not properly a part of the natural kind times slow and gradual, other times violent and sudden, but never
called “motion.” Growth became an “orphan” problem that even- wholly stable for very long.
tually migrated to other branches of science where it could be That observation doesn’t undermine science by showing it to
better accommodated. be “nothing but” political subterfuge, social fashion, or arbi-
Similarly, rather than unifying today’s “psychology” as a whole,
it seems more likely that some portion of contemporary psychol- 10
I am reluctant to use the term “biological” here because “biology” is
ogy may be unified according to some set of principles. These will, a concept and a term that was available neither to Aristotle nor to Newton.
perhaps, capture a large chunk of the current discipline, but not all “Biology,” is a 19th-century invention. I have overcome that reluctance for
of it, by any means. It may well be that the portion unified will, in the sake of expository clarity, but wish to note that some of that apparent
addition, be integrated with other phenomena that are not currently “clarity” is actually anachronism.
11
considered to fall within the boundaries of “psychology.” (Con- There are a few antirealists who go to these radical lengths, to be sure,
but the attention they receive, especially by critics whose main aim is to
sider how porous the boundaries already are between various parts discredit philosophy and humanistic studies of science more broadly, far
of psychology and the neighboring disciplines of neuroscience, outweighs their numbers or their influence on those fields. Be those issues
sociology, anthropology, philosophy, education, economics, etc.) as they may, the point here is that there is another, antirealist view of
The result of this partial unification of (a subset of) psychology science that aims not to undermine science but, rather, to see clearly and to
explain important phenomena within the evolving historical institution
would be the formation of a new discipline with new boundaries. called “science” which are often ignored or hastily covered over by those
Such an event, it might be said metaphorically, would show that who might be termed naïve scientific triumphalists. Science is grand, but
the current form of psychology fails to “cut nature at its joints” its path has been crooked.
212 GREEN

trary verbiage. It is, indeed, exactly as we should expect it to be objects? Yes, it is possible, but now we are asking that a unifica-
because it is our underlying ontological conceptions, our epis- tion we do not yet understand do something we aren’t able to do
temological values, and our apprehension of methods that are for ourselves. It is, in effect, asking not just for unification, but for
often in error and need to be revised. As they change, the a unificatory miracle. That seems unreasonable.
content of the science that depends on them shifts as well. To
give a simple example, up into the 19th century, probability was
Conclusions
thought by many to be something primarily associated with
gambling and, thus, could have little to offer the serious scien- Where have we been? First, I noted that scientific unification is
tist who was interested in attaining Certain Truth. However, as an issue which has generated quite a bit of literature of the past few
it gradually came to be accepted that science rarely deals in decades. I also noted that many of these efforts have been rather
certainties (even if that is its ultimate aim), but almost always partisan, attempting to show that one “school of thought” or
in various likelihoods, and that the apparatus of probability another can expand its boundaries to cover all of psychology, and
theory could be used to measure the degree of uncertainty that this is unlikely to succeed. I offered the suggestion that a
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

associated with particular claims, probability came to be ac- successful unification would probably have to be couched in rather
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

cepted among scientific methods. It is difficult to even imagine more neutral, and in much more rigorous (e.g., formal) terms.
modern science without the extensive use of probability and its Then I looked to psychology’s history to show that the disci-
associated statistical machinery. pline has been a mashup of different interests from the time its
This more tumultuous, but also more authentic history of sci- very first American journals appeared. It was not the result of a
ence gives us scientists of the present day no more reason to assume group of like-minded scientists coming together to solve problems
that we, now, have finally “got it right” than pre-Einsteinian physicists they had in common. It was more the result of talented diplomats
had space and time “right” or than pre-Darwinian botanists and and administrators inviting relatively disparate groups of research-
zoologists had species “right.” The one thing we can be fairly ers to come together for the purposes of publication and institu-
certain of is that there will be change, even in some of the things tional entrenchment. There may have been all kinds of good
we believe to be foundational to the knowledge we have managed practical reasons for the discipline to proceed this way in order to
to so acquire through our most arduous efforts. This doesn’t mean “get off the ground,” but they probably do not constitute a prom-
that we have accomplished nothing of import. It means that we are ising intellectual basis for the future unification of the field. Then
a vital bridge from the less adequate understandings of the past to I suggested, in light of this history, that if unification comes to
the (we hope) more adequate understandings of the future. That psychology, it may well be piecemeal—various portions of the
said, much of what we stand on is probably not bedrock. discipline unifying and breaking away from the “mother” disci-
Although I just presented an argument that favored antirealism pline until there are a number relatively independent “offspring”
(because I think that it is more widely misunderstood than real- disciplines (and some remnant “orphan” problems) rather than a
ism), personally I have never been entirely comfortable on either single unified psychology.
side of the debate. I am fairly realist about some scientific objects Finally, I took a short excursion into philosophy of science,
(e.g., trees, mountains, stars) and I am fairly instrumentalist (an- trying to explain how antirealism is not, in the main, antiscience
tirealist) about others (e.g., the implicit memory system, the but, rather, an effort to come to terms with the history of science
openness-to-experience personality trait, dissociative identity dis- as it has actually proceeded over the past several centuries. One
order). What does any of this have to do with unification? Psy- need not conclude that there are no “real objects out there” in
chologists, it seems to me, perhaps more than most scientists, order to see the power of the antirealist narrative. The point is,
cannot rely on the terms that they use to refer to “real” objects and rather, that at any point in time, we have little reason to believe
processes. By “real” here I mean something like “permanent parts that we, of all the people in history, happened to have arrived at
of the science.” If even so ancient and apparently straightforward the uniquely correct concepts by use of the precisely attuned
a term as “planet” can be subject to debate, negotiation, and methods. It is much more likely that we are like the people who
revision, as we saw recently in the dispute over the status of Pluto came immediately before us: We have descriptions of the world
(and, by extension, of Eris, Ceres, Makemake, and Haumea), then that are more or less adequate to our current finite set of
what hope can there be, over the long haul, for things like intel- observations, but we are always only a day way from observa-
ligence, extraversion, racism, attachment, and autism (all of which tions that will render those descriptions inadequate. Even some
have seen important shifts within our lifetimes)? Consider, by of our most cherished current concepts and principles will be
contrast, how quickly once seemingly indispensible terms like abandoned in favor of other new ones in our collective effort to
“hysteria” and “neurosis” slipped out of the disciplinary vocabu- get a more adequate grip on matters: better resolution of detail
lary entirely. and wider scope. Psychology, at its current stage, seems par-
None of this bodes well for the possibility of a stable unification ticularly prone to fairly dramatic shifts in its concepts and
of the discipline. Principles of unification, whatever they might be, methodological principles. We are a fairly heterogeneous
would seem to require, at minimum, a relatively stable set of group, ontologically and epistemologically, to begin with. What
concepts (and objects) in order to do their work. But so much in is more, the ontological bases of many of the “objects” we deal
psychology remains highly malleable that it is hard to see how with are still fairly poorly understood. The odds that we are
principles could be formed to rigorously capture them when their conceiving as a single kind of object a set of things that would
meanings might change by the time of the next textbook edition. Is be better handled as two or more kinds of objects, or that
it possible that principles of unification would play a significant something we conceive of as a set of two or more kinds of
role in stabilizing the network of psychological concepts and things would be better handled as one, seems fairly high. There
WHY PSYCHOLOGY ISN’T UNIFIED 213

is a bare possibility that a successful unification would simul- view, 1894 –1908. History of Psychology, 18, 15–31. http://dx.doi.org/
taneously help us to stabilize our concepts; that we might see 10.1037/a0038406
better and more consensually what objects they refer to. Al- Green, C. D., Feinerer, I., & Burman, J. T. (in press). Searching for the
though possible, this seems to be more an exercise in wishing structure of early American psychology: Networking Psychological Re-
view, 1909 –1923. History of Psychology, 18.
rather than in making any concrete progress toward a unifica-
Hacking, I. (1996). The disunities of science. In P. Galison & D. Stump
tion of the field.
(Eds.), The disunity of science. Boundaries, contexts and power (pp.
Although unification in psychology may well seem to be a 37–74). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
laudable goal, psychology may not have been configured histori- Hall, G. S. (1894). On the history of American college text-books and
cally in a way that will allow it to happen. We must, in a sense, let teaching logic, ethics, psychology and allied subjects. Proceedings of the
unification come to us, perhaps in a series of fragments, and then American Antiquarian Society, 9, 137–174.
we will see what becomes of the larger psychology as a result, Hardy, G. H. (1908). Mendelian proportions in a mixed population. Sci-
rather than explicitly attempt to pursue unification for the disci- ence, 28, 49 –50. http://dx.doi.org/10.1126/science.28.706.49
pline as whole. Heft, H. (2013). An ecological approach to psychology. Review of General
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

Psychology, 17, 162–167. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0032928


This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

Henriques, G. R. (2004). Psychology defined. Journal of Clinical Psychol-


References ogy, 60, 1207–1221. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/jclp.20061
Henriques, G. R. (2011). A new unified theory of psychology. New York,
Anderson, N. H. (2013). Unified psychology based on three laws of NY: Springer Science. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4614-0058-5
information integration. Review of General Psychology, 17, 125–132. Henriques, G. R. (2013). Evolving from methodological to conceptual
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0032921 unification. Review of General Psychology, 17, 168 –173. http://dx.doi
Aristotle. (1996). Physics (R. Waterfield, Trans.). Oxford, UK: Oxford .org/10.1037/a0032929
University Press. Hull, C. L. (1943). Principles of behavior: An introduction to behavior
Benjamin, L. T., Jr.. (2012). A history of popular psychology in America. theory. New York, NY: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
In R. W. Rieber (Ed.), Encyclopedia of the history of psychological Hutto, D. D. (2013). Psychology unified: From folk psychology to radical
theories (pp. 22– 47). New York, NY: Springer-Science. enactivism. Review of General Psychology, 17, 174 –178. http://dx.doi
Benjamin, L. T., Jr., & Baker, D. B. (2004). From séance to science: A .org/10.1037/a0032930
history of the profession of psychology in America. Belmont, CA: Huxley, J. (1942). Evolution: The modern synthesis. London, UK: Allen &
Wadsworth. Unwin.
Boring, E. G. (1923). Intelligence as the tests test it. New Republic, 36, James, W. (1904a). A world of pure experience. The Journal of Philoso-
35–37. phy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, 1, 561–570. http://dx.doi.org/
Catania, A. C. (2013). A natural science of behavior. Review of General 10.2307/2011912
Psychology, 17, 133–139. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0033026 James, W. (1904b). Does “consciousness” exist? The Journal of Philoso-
Charles, E. P. (2013). Psychology: The empirical study of epistemology phy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, 1, 477– 491. http://dx.doi.org/
and phenomenology. Review of General Psychology, 17, 140 –144. 10.2307/2011942
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0032920 Kimble, G. A. (1989). Psychology from the standpoint of a generalist.
Chemero, A. (2013). Radical embodied cognitive science. Review of Gen- American Psychologist, 44, 491– 499. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-
eral Psychology, 17, 145–150. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0032923 066X.44.3.491
Clegg, J. W. (2013). The fragmented object: Building disciplinary coher- Kimble, G. A. (1994). A frame of reference for psychology. American
ence through a contextual unit of analysis. Review of General Psychol- Psychologist, 49, 510 –519. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.49.6
ogy, 17, 151–155. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0032926 .510
Coleman, S. R., & Salamon, R. (1988). Kuhn’s structure of scientific Kimble, G. A. (1996). Psychology: The hope of a science. Cambridge, MA:
revolutions in the psychological literature, 1969 –1983: A descriptive MIT Press. Retrieved from http://search.proquest.com.ezproxy.library.
study. Journal of Mind and Behavior, 9, 415– 446. yorku.ca/PsycINFO/docview/619015069/C775EBDAAAD5473CPQ/
Dupré, J. (1993). Metaphysical foundations of the disunity of science. 1?accountid⫽15182
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Kimble, G. A. (1999). Functional behaviorism: A plan for unity in psy-
Ferguson, G. A. (1982). Psychology at McGill. In M. J. Wright & C. R. chology. American Psychologist, 54, 981–988. http://dx.doi.org/10
Myers (Eds.), A History of academic psychology in Canada (pp. 33– 67). .1037/h0088209
Toronto, Canada: C. J. Hogrefe. Koch, S. (1993). “Psychology” or “the psychological studies?” American
Goertzen, J. R. (2008). On the possibility of unification: The reality and Psychologist, 48, 902–904. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.48.8
nature of the crisis in psychology. Theory & Psychology, 18, 829 – 852. .902
http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0959354308097260 Kristensen, K. B., Slife, B. D., & Yanchar, S. C. (2000). On what basis are
Goertzen, J. R. (2010). Dialectical pluralism: A theoretical conceptualiza- evaluations possible in a fragmented psychology? An alternative to
tion of pluralism in psychology. New Ideas in Psychology, 28, 201–209. objectivism and relativism. Journal of Mind and Behavior, 21, 273–288.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.newideapsych.2009.09.013 Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed., en-
Green, C. D. (2009). Darwinian theory, functionalism, and the first Amer- larged). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
ican psychological revolution. American Psychologist, 64, 75– 83. http:// Lakatoš, I. (1970). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research
dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0013338 programmes. In I. Lakatoš & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the
Green, C. D., & Feinerer, I. (2015). The evolution of the American Journal growth of knowledge (pp. 91–196). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Uni-
of Psychology, 1887–1903: A network investigation. American Journal versity Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139171434.009
of Psychology, 28, 387– 401. http://dx.doi.org/10.5406/amerjpsyc.128.3 Laudan, L. (1978). Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of
.0387 scientific growth. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Green, C. D., Feinerer, I., & Burman, J. T. (2015). Searching for the Leacock, S. (1924, March). A manual for the new mentality. Harper’s, 47,
structure of early American psychology: Networking Psychological Re- 480.
214 GREEN

Lerner, R. M., Agans, J. P., DeSouza, L. M., & Gasca, S. (2013). Describ- Staats, A. W. (1983). Psychology’s crisis of disunity: Philosophy and
ing, explaining, and optimizing within-individual change across the life method for a unified science. New York, NY: Praeger.
span: A relational developmental systems perspective. Review of Gen- Staats, A. W. (1991). Unified positivism and unification psychology: Fad
eral Psychology, 17, 179 –183. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0032931 or new field? American Psychologist, 46, 899 –912. http://dx.doi.org/10
Lickliter, R., & Honeycutt, H. (2013). A developmental evolutionary .1037/0003-066X.46.9.899
framework for psychology. Review of General Psychology, 17, 184 – Staats, A. W. (1999). Unifying psychology requires new infrastructure,
189. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0032932 theory, method, and a research agenda. Review of General Psychology,
Marken, R. S., & Mansell, W. (2013). Perceptual control as a unifying 3, 3–13. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/1089-2680.3.1.3
concept in psychology. Review of General Psychology, 17, 190 –195. Stam, H. J. (2004). Unifying psychology: Epistemological act or disciplin-
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0032933 ary maneuver? Journal of Clinical Psychology, 60, 1259 –1262. http://
Marsh, T., & Boag, S. (2014). Unifying psychology: Shared ontology and dx.doi.org/10.1002/jclp.20069
the continuum of practical assumptions. Review of General Psychology, Stam, H. J. (2015). Indeterminate functionalism and possessive individu-
18, 49 –59. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0036880 alism. In G. B. Sullivan, J. Cresswell, A. Larrain, A. Haye, & C. A.
Mayer, J. D., & Allen, J. L. (2013). A personality framework for the Morgan (Eds.), Dialogue and debate in the making of theoretical psy-
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

unification of psychology. Review of General Psychology, 17, 196 –202. chology (pp. 385–392). Toronto, Canada: Captus Press.
Sternberg, R. J., & Grigorenko, E. L. (2001). Unified psychology. Amer-
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0032934
ican Psychologist, 56, 1069 –1079. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X
Myers, C. R. (1982). Psychology at Toronto. In M. J. Wright & C. R.
.56.12.1069
Myers (Eds.), A History of academic psychology in Canada (pp. 68 –99).
Taylor, E. I., & Wozniak, R. H. (Eds.). (1996). Pure experience: The
Toronto, Canada: C. J. Hogrefe.
response to William James. Bristol, UK: Thoemmes Press.
Osier, D. V., & Wozniak, R. H. (1984). A century of serial publications in
Teo, T. (2010). Ontology and scientific explanation: Pluralism as an a
psychology, 1850 –1950. Millwood, NY: Kraus.
priori condition of psychology. New Ideas in Psychology, 28, 235–243.
Petocz, A., & Mackay, N. (2013). Unifying psychology through situational
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.newideapsych.2009.09.017
realism. Review of General Psychology, 17, 216 –223. http://dx.doi.org/
Tolman, E. C. (1932). Purposive behavior in animals and men. New York,
10.1037/a0032937 NY: Century.
Robinson, D. K. (2001). Reaction time experiments in Wundt’s institute Walsh-Bowers, R. (2010). Some social-historical issues underlying psy-
and beyond. In R. W. Rieber & D. K. Robinson (Eds.), Wilhelm Wundt chology’s fragmentation. New Ideas in Psychology, 28, 244 –252. http://
in history: The making of a scientific psychology (pp. 161–197). New dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.newideapsych.2009.09.018
York, NY: Kluwer. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4615-0665-2_6 Weinberg, W. (1908). Über den Nachweis der Vererbung beim Menschen
Skinner, B. F. (1945). The operational analysis of psychological terms. [On the evidence of heredity in humans]. Jahreshefte des Vereins für
Psychological Review, 52, 270 –277. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/ Vaterländische Naturkunde in Württemberg, 64, 368 –382.
h0062535 Woodworth, R. S. (1943). The adolescence of American psychology.
Sokal, M. M. (1997). Baldwin, Cattell and the Psychological Review: A Psychological Review, 50, 10 –32. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0056814
collaboration and its discontents. History of the Human Sciences, 10, Yanchar, S. C., & Slife, B. D. (1997). Pursuing unity in a fragmented
57– 89. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/095269519701000104 psychology: Problems and prospects. Review of General Psychology, 1,
Staats, A. W. (1981). Paradigmatic behaviorism, unified theory, unified 235–255. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/1089-2680.1.3.235
theory construction methods, and the Zeitgeist of separatism. American
Psychologist, 36, 239 –256. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.36.3 Received June 15, 2015
.239 Accepted July 14, 2015 䡲

E-Mail Notification of Your Latest Issue Online!


Would you like to know when the next issue of your favorite APA journal will be available
online? This service is now available to you. Sign up at http://notify.apa.org/ and you will be
notified by e-mail when issues of interest to you become available!

You might also like