You are on page 1of 377

The Continuum

Companion to Plato

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd i 3/17/2001 4:05:32 PM


The Continuum Companions series is a major series of single volume companions to key
research fields in the humanities field aimed at postgraduate students, scholars and libraries.
Each companion offers a comprehensive reference resource giving an overview of key topics,
research areas, new directions and a manageable guide to beginning or developing research in
the field. A distinctive feature of the series is that each companion provides practical guidance
on advanced study and research in the field, including research methods and subject-specific
resources.

The Continuum Companion to Aesthetics,


edited by Anna Christina Ribeiro
The Continuum Companion to Continental Philosophy,
edited by John Mullarkey and Beth Lord
The Continuum Companion to Epistemology,
edited by Andrew Cullison
The Continuum Companion to Ethics,
edited by Christian Miller
The Continuum Companion to Existentialism,
edited by Jack Reynolds, Felicity Joseph and Ashley Woodward
The Continuum Companion to Hume,
edited by Alan Bailey and Dan O’Brien
The Continuum Companion to Kant,
edited by Gary Banham, Dennis Schulting and Nigel Hems
The Continuum Companion to Leibniz,
edited by Brendan Look
The Continuum Companion to Locke,
edited by S. J. Savonious-Wroth, Paul Schuurman and Jonathan Walmsley
The Continuum Companion to Metaphysics,
edited by Robert W. Barnard and Neil A. Manson
The Continuum Companion to the Philosophy of Language,
edited by Manuel Garcia-Carpintero and Max Kolbel
The Continuum Companion to Philosophy of Mind,
edited by James Garvey
The Continuum Companion to Pragmatism,
edited by Sami Pihlström
The Continuum Companion to Spinoza,
edited by Wiep van Bunge

Forthcoming in Philosophy
The Continuum Companion to Berkeley,
edited by Bertil Belfrage and Richard Brook
The Continuum Companion to Hegel,
edited by Allegra de Laurentiis and Jeffrey Edwards
The Continuum Companion to Hobbes,
edited by S. A. Lloyd
The Continuum Companion to Political Philosophy,
edited by Andrew Fiala and Matt Matravers
The Continuum Companion to Socrates,
edited by John Bussanich and Nicholas D. Smith

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd ii 3/17/2001 4:05:32 PM


THE CONTINUUM
COMPANION TO PLATO

EDITED BY

Gerald A. Press

Associate Editors: Francisco Gonzalez, Debra Nails and Harold Tarrant

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd iii 3/17/2001 4:05:32 PM


Continuum International Publishing Group
The Tower Building 80 Maiden Lane
11 York Road Suite 704
London SE1 7NX New York NY 10038

www.continuumbooks.com

© Continuum International Publishing Group 2012

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced


or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical,
including photocopying, recording or any information storage or
retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers.

British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data


A catalog record for this book is available from the British Library.

EISBN: 978-1-4411-6141-3

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data


The Continuum companion to Plato / edited by Gerald A. Press.
p. cm. – (Continuum companions to philosophy)
Includes bibliographical references (p. ) and indexes.
ISBN 978-0-8264-3535-4 (hardcover) – ISBN 978-1-4411-6141-3
(ebook pdf) 1. Plato. I. Press, Gerald A. (Gerald Alan), 1945-
II. Title: Companion to Plato.

B395.C643 2012
184–dc23

Typeset by Newgen Imaging Systems Pvt Ltd, Chennai, India


Printed and bound in Great Britain

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd iv 3/17/2001 4:05:33 PM


CONTENTS

Acknowledgements x
List of Abbreviations xi
Other Ancient Authors xii
Other Abbreviations xiii
List of Contributors xiv

INTRODUCTION 1
1. PLATO’S LIFE – HISTORICAL AND INTELLECTUAL
CONTEXT 8
Plato’s life 8
Aristophanes and intellectuals 10
Education (paideia) 12
Eleatics 13
Isocrates and logography 16
Orality and literacy 17
Poetry (epic and lyric) 20
Pre-Socratic philosophers 21
Pythagoreans 24
Rhetoric and speechmaking 27
Socrates (historical) 28
Socratics (other than Plato) 30
The sophists 33
2. THE DIALOGUES 36
The platonic corpus and manuscript tradition 36
Alcibiades I 38
The Apology of Socrates 39
Charmides 41
Clitophon 44
Cratylus 46
Crito 47
Dubia and Spuria 49
Euthydemus 52

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd v 3/17/2001 4:05:33 PM


CONTENTS

Euthyphro 55
Gorgias 56
Hippias Major 58
Hippias Minor 61
Ion 62
Laches 63
Laws 65
Letters 67
Lysis 69
Menexenus 71
Meno 72
Parmenides 74
Phaedo 76
Phaedrus 78
Philebus 81
Politicus (Statesman) 83
Protagoras 85
Republic 87
Sophist 91
Symposium 93
Theaetetus 96
Theages 98
Timaeus and Critias 99
3. IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES 101
Anonymity 101
Argument 103
Character (feature) 103
Drama 105
History 107
Humour 108
Irony 110
Language 111
Literary composition 113
Musical structure of the Dialogues 115
Myth 118
Pedagogical structure of the Dialogues 119
Pedimental structure of the Dialogues 121
Play 123
Proleptic composition 125
Socrates (the character) 126
4. TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES 129
Account 129
Aesthetics 129
Akrasia (incontinence, weakness of will) 131
Antilogy and eristics (eristic) 133

vi

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd vi 3/17/2001 4:05:33 PM


CONTENTS

Appearance and reality (reality) 135


Appetite 137
Argument 137
Art (technê) 137
Beauty (kalon) 139
Being and becoming (on, onta; gignesthai) 141
Cause (aitia) 143
Cave, the allegory of the 145
Character (topic) 147
City (polis) 148
Convention 150
Cosmos (kosmos) 150
Cross examination 152
Daimôn 152
Death 155
Desire (appetite, epithumia) 157
Dialectic (dialektikê) 159
Divided line 161
Education 163
Elenchus (cross examination, refutation) 165
Epistemology (knowledge) 167
Eristic 169
Erôs 169
Ethics 169
Eudaimonia 171
Excellence (virtue, aretê) 171
Forms (eidos, idea) 173
Friendship (philia) 175
Goodness (the Good, agathon) 177
Happiness (eudaimonia) 179
Idea 180
Image (eikôn) 180
Imitation 182
Incontinence 182
Inspiration 182
Intellectualism 184
Justice (dikaion, dikaiosynê) 186
Knowledge 188
Language 188
Law (convention, nomos) 191
Logic 192
Logos (account, argument, definition, statement) 194
Love (erôs) 196
Madness and possession 198
Mathematics (mathêmatikê) 200
Medicine (iatrikê) 202

vii

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd vii 3/17/2001 4:05:33 PM


CONTENTS

Metaphysics 205
Method 205
Mimêsis (imitation) 207
Music 209
Myth (muthos) 211
Nature (phusis) 213
Nomos 215
Non-propositional knowledge 215
The One (to hen) 217
Ontology (metaphysics) 218
Paiderastia (pederasty) 220
Participation 222
Perception and sensation (aisthêsis, aisthanomai) (sensation) 225
Philosophy and the philosopher 227
Phusis 229
Piety (eusebeia, hosios) 229
Pleasure (hêdonê) 231
Poetry (poiêsis) 233
Polis 235
Politics and the figure of the Politicus 235
Reality 237
Reason 237
Recollection (anamnêsis) 240
Refutation 241
Rhetoric (rhetorikê) 241
Self-knowledge 243
Sensation 245
Sophists 245
Soul (psychê) 247
The sun simile 250
Theology 251
Virtue 253
Vision 253
Weakness of will 255
Women 255
Writing (topic) 257
5. LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND
INFLUENCE OF PLATO AND THE DIALOGUES 260
Section A: The Interpretation and Influence of Plato
in the Ancient World 260
Ancient hermeneutics 260
Aristotle 262
Academy of Athens, ancient history of 264
Jewish Platonism (ancient) 267
Neoplatonism and its diaspora 269

viii

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd viii 3/17/2001 4:05:34 PM


CONTENTS

Section B: The Influence of Plato in the Middle Ages and


Renaissance 272
Medieval Islamic Platonism 272
Medieval Jewish Platonism 274
Medieval Christian Platonism 276
Renaissance Platonism 278
The Cambridge Platonists 281
Section C: The Influence and Interpretation of Plato in
Modern and Contemporary Philosophy 282
Early modern philosophy: from Descartes to Berkeley 282
Nineteenth-century Plato scholarship 284
Nineteenth-century Platonic scholarship 286
Developmentalism 288
Compositional chronology 289
Analytic approaches to Plato 292
Vlastosian approaches 294
Continental approaches 296
Straussian readings of Plato 298
Plato’s ‘unwritten doctrines’ 300
Esotericism 301
The Tübingen approach 303
Anti-Platonism, from ancient to modern 305

Bibliography 309
Index 349

ix

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd ix 3/17/2001 4:05:34 PM


ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS

The editor would like to thank the Continuum International Publishing Group for support-
ing this project, as also several members of the staff who assisted in it over the years: Evander
Lomke, Sarah Campbell and Tom Crick. I especially appreciate the ongoing help and advice
Merilyn Holme has provided over several years.
I am grateful to the President, Provost and Dean of Hunter College for a sabbatical in
2009–10 that gave me the extra time I required for organizing, managing and writing the
project. I want to thank the Research Foundation of the City University of New York for
a PSC-CUNY Research Grant that enabled me to hire an Editorial Assistant to edit contri-
butions as they were received. My thanks goes to Elvira Basevich, the Editorial Assistant,
for her dedicated and painstaking work in editing individual contributions and compiling
the Bibliography. Thanks also to Gregory Smulewicz-Zucker for compiling and editing the
List of Contributors and John Storm for editorial advice on several of the articles and the
Introduction.
I would like to thank each of the contributors for their work on this project and their will-
ingness to adapt their articles to the overall plan and needs of the volume and to say in fewer
words than they often wished what might have been said in more. Special thanks to Sarah
Hutton and Samuel Scolnicov for advice at moments of special need.
Most of all, I want to thank the Associate Editors of this volume, Francisco Gonzalez,
Debra Nails and Harold Tarrant, for their collaborative hard work over the 3 years of work-
ing on the project in defining the contents, selecting the contributors, editing the submissions
and providing specific advice and suggestions in instances too numerous to count. They have
been examples throughout of the intellectual moderation, courage, wisdom and justice that
make the scholarly life happiest and best.

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd x 3/17/2001 4:05:34 PM


LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS

In this work, after the first mention of a Platonic dialogue or other Platonic work, the follow-
ing abbreviations are used:

Alcibiades (Alc. I, 2) Ion


Amatores (Amat.) Laches (La.)
Apology (Ap.) Laws/Leges (Lg.)
Axiochus (Ax.) Lysis (Ly.)
Charmides (Chrm.) Menexenus (Mx.)
Clitophon (Clit.) Meno (Men.)
Cratylus (Cra.) Minos (Min.)
Critias (Criti.) On Justice (Just.)
Crito (Cri.) On Virtue (Virt.)
Definitions (Def.) Parmenides (Prm.)
Demodocus (Demod.) Phaedo (Phd.)
Epigrams (Epigr.) Phaedrus (Phdr.)
Epinomis (Epin.) Philebus (Phlb.)
Epistles (Ep. I, 2, etc.) Protagoras (Prt.)
Eryxias (Erx.) Republic (R.)
Euthydemus (Euthd.) Sisyphus (Sis.)
Euthyphro (Euthphr.) Sophist (Sph.)
Gorgias (Grg.) Statesman/Politicus (Plt.)
Halcyon (Hal.) Symposium (Smp.)
Hipparchus (Hipparch.) Theaetetus (Tht.)
Hippias Major (Hp. Ma.) Theages (Thg.)
Hippias Minor (Hp. Mi.) Timaeus (Ti.)

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd xi 3/17/2001 4:05:34 PM


OTHER ANCIENT AUTHORS

‘DK’ Diels-Kranz, Hermann Diels and Walther Kranz. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker.
This is a standard source for fragments of the pre-Socratic philosophers. ‘A’ numbers refer
to testimonies about the philosopher; ‘B’ numbers refer to fragments of their actual words.
D. L. Diogenes Laertius. Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers.
This is a third-century CE doxography that is an important source of the views of ancient
philosophers.

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd xii 3/17/2001 4:05:34 PM


OTHER ABBREVIATIONS

Antid. (Antidiosis) no. (number)


b. (born) nos. (numbers)
bk (book) n.s. (new series)
bks (books) n.d. (no date of publication)
c. (circa) Od. (Homer, Odyssey)
cf. (confer, compare) passim (often)
ch. (chapter) pt (part)
chs (chapters) q.v. (quod vide, see the article
d. (died) entitled)
ed. (editor/edited by) repr. (reprint/ed)
edn (edition) rev. (revised)
eds (editors) sc. (scilicet)
f. (fragment) Theog. (Theogony)
ff. (fragments) trans. (translated by, translator/s)
fl. (floruit) vol. (volume)
Il. (Homer, Iliad) vols (volumes)

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd xiii 3/17/2001 4:05:34 PM


LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS

Hayden W. Ausland Hugh H. Benson


Professor of Classics Professor of Philosophy
University of Montana University of Oklahoma
Missoula, MT Norman, OK
USA USA

Dirk Baltzly Robbert van den Berg


Associate Professor of Philosophy Lecturer
Monash University Leiden University
Victoria The Netherlands
Australia
David Blank
Frederick Beiser Professor of Classics
Professor of Philosophy University of California
Syracuse University Los Angeles, CA
Syracuse, NY USA
USA
Ruby Blondell
Elizabeth Belfiore Professor of Classics
Professor of Philosophy, Emerita University of Washington
University of Minnesota Seattle, WA
Minneapolis, MN USA
USA
Thomas C. Brickhouse
Eugenio Benitez Professor of Philosophy
Associate Professor of Philosophy Lynchburg College
The University of Sydney Lynchburg, VA
Australia USA

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd xiv 3/17/2001 4:05:34 PM


LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS

Luc Brisson Jacques Antoine Duvoisin


Director of Research St. John’s College
Centre Jean Pépin Santa Fe, NM
CNRS, Paris USA
France
Rafael Ferber
Stuart Brown Professor of Philosophy
Professor Emeritus University of Lucerne
The Open University Switzerland
Milton Keynes, Buckinghamshire
UK Richard Foley
Assistant Professor of Classical Studies
Margaret Cameron University of Missouri
Assistant Professor of Philosophy Columbia, MO
University of Victoria USA
Canada
Dorothea Frede
Timothy Chappell Mills Adjunct Professor of Philosophy
Professor of Philosophy University of California
The Open University Berkeley, CA
UK USA

Antonio Chu Francesco Fronterotta


Associate Professor of Philosophy Associate Professor in History of Ancient
Metropolitan State College of Denver Philosophy
Denver, CO University of Salento, Lecce
USA Italy

Catherine Collobert Alessandra Fussi


Associate Professor of Philosophy and Associate Professor of Philosophy
Classics University of Pisa
University of Ottawa Italy
Canada
Francisco Gonzalez
John Dillon Professor of Philosophy
Emeritus Fellow University of Ottawa
Trinity College, Dublin Canada
Ireland
Jill Gordon
Monique Dixsaut Professor of Philosophy
Emeritus Professor Colby College
Panthéon-Sorbonne University, Paris Waterville, ME
France USA

xv

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd xv 3/17/2001 4:05:34 PM


LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS

Herbert Granger Mark Joyal


Professor of Philosophy Professor of Classics
Wayne State University University of Manitoba
Detroit, MI Canada
USA
Rachana Kamtekar
Stephen Halliwell Associate Professor of Philosophy
Professor of Greek University of Arizona
University of St. Andrews Tucson, AZ
Fife, Scotland USA
UK
George Karamanolis
Verity Harte Lecturer in Ancient Philosophy
Professor of Philosophy and Classics University of Crete
Yale University Greece
New Haven, CT J. B. Kennedy
USA Centre for the History of Science, Technology
and Medicine
Angela Hobbs
Manchester University
Associate Professor of Philosophy
Manchester
University of Warwick
UK
UK
David Konstan
Carl A. Huffman Professor Emeritus of Classics and
Professor of Classical Studies, of Greek Comparative Literature
Language and Literature Brown University
DePauw University Providence, RI
Greencastle, IN USA
USA
Taneli Kukkonen
Sarah Hutton Professor of History
Professor of English University of Jyväskylä
Aberystwyth University Finland
Wales
UK Melissa Lane
Professor of Politics
Christopher Janaway Princeton University
Professor of Philosophy Princeton, NJ
University of Southampton USA
UK
Oliver Leaman
Thomas Johansen Professor of Philosophy
Reader in Ancient Philosophy University of Kentucky
Brasenose College, Oxford University Lexington, KY
UK USA
xvi

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd xvi 3/17/2001 4:05:35 PM


LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS

Gabriel Richardson Lear Michail Maiatsky


Professor of Philosophy National Research University
University of Chicago Moscow
Chicago, IL Russia
USA
Richard Marback
Mi-Kyoung Lee Associate Professor of English
Associate Professor of Philosophy Wayne State University
University of Colorado Detroit, MI
Boulder, CO USA
USA
Marina McCoy
Fiona Leigh Associate Professor of Philosophy
Department of Philosophy Boston College
University College, London Boston, MA
UK USA

Mark McPherran
J. H. Lesher
Professor of Philosophy
Professor of Philosophy
Simon Fraser University
University of North Carolina
Vancouver
Chapel Hill, NC
Canada
USA
Fred D. Miller, Jr.
Susan B. Levin Professor of Philosophy
Associate Professor of Philosophy Bowling Green State University
Smith College Bowling Green, OH
Northampton, MA USA
USA
David Mirhady
V. Bradley Lewis Associate Professor of Classics
Associate Professor of Philosophy Simon Fraser University
The Catholic University of America Vancouver
Washington, DC Canada
USA
Christopher Moore
A. A. Long Lecturer in Philosophy
Professor of Classics and of Literature The University of Texas
University of California Austin, TX
Berkeley, CA USA
USA
Kathryn A. Morgan
Menahem Luz Professor of Classics
Senior Lecturer in Philosophy and History University of California
University of Haifa Los Angeles, CA
Israel USA

xvii

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd xvii 3/17/2001 4:05:35 PM


LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS

Debra Nails Sandra Peterson


Professor of Philosophy Professor of Philosophy
Michigan State University University of Minnesota
East Lansing, MI Minneapolis, MN
USA USA

Andrea Nightingale Ronald Polansky


Professor of Classics and Comparative Professor of Philosophy
Literature Duquesne University
Stanford University Pittsburgh, PA
Stanford, CA USA
USA
Jean-François Pradeau
Noburu Notomi Professor of Philosophy
Professor of Philosophy University of Lyon
Keio University France
Japan
Gerald A. Press
Nickolas Pappas Professor of Philosophy
Professor of Philosophy Hunter College and C.U.N.Y. Graduate
City College of New York and the CUNY Center
Graduate Center New York, NY
New York, NY USA
USA
William Prior
Richard D. Parry
Professor of Philosophy
Emeritus Professor of
Santa Clara University
Philosophy
Santa Clara, CA
Agnes Scott College
USA
Decatur, GA
USA
Naomi Reshotko
Richard Patterson Professor of Philosophy
Professor of Philosophy University of Denver
Emory University Denver, CO
Atlanta, GA USA
USA
Gretchen Reydams-Schils
E. E. Pender Professor of Philosophy
Senior Lecturer, Department of Classics University of Notre Dame
University of Leeds, Leeds Notre Dame, IN
UK USA

xviii

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd xviii 3/17/2001 4:05:35 PM


LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS

T. M. Robinson Nicholas D. Smith


Emeritus Professor of Philosophy and Classics Professor of Humanities
University of Toronto Lewis & Clark College
Canada Portland, OR
USA
David Roochnik
Professor of Philosophy Richard Stalley
Boston University Emeritus Professor of Ancient Philosophy
Boston, MA University of Glasgow
USA UK

David T. Runia Thomas Alexander Szlezák


Master of Queen’s College Ordinarius for Greek Philology and Director
Queen’s College, University of Melbourne of Plato Archives
Australia Eberhard Karls University, Tubingen
Germany
Daniel C. Russell
Harold Tarrant
Professor of Philosophy
Professor of Classics
Wichita State University
University of Newcastle
Wichita, KS
Australia
USA
Holger Thesleff
Kenneth Sayre Emeritus Professor of Greek
Professor of Philosophy University of Helsinki
University of Notre Dame Finland
Notre Dame, IN
USA Christine J. Thomas
Associate Professor of Philosophy
D. C. Schindler Dartmouth College
Associate Professor of Philosophy Dartmouth, NH
Villanova University USA
Villanova, PA
USA Andrea Tschemplik
Associate Professor of Philosophy and
Samuel Scolnicov Religion
Emeritus Professor of Philosophy American University
The Hebrew University of Jerusalem Washington, DC
Israel USA

Allan Silverman Joanne B. Waugh


Professor of Philosophy Associate Professor of Philosophy
Ohio State University University of South Florida
Columbus, OH Tampa, FL
USA USA

xix

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd xix 3/17/2001 4:05:35 PM


LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS

Silke-Maria Weineck James Wilberding


Associate Professor of Germanic Languages Lecturer in History
and Literature University of Newcastle
University of Michigan Newcastle upon Tyne
Ann Arbor, MI UK
USA
Charles M. Young
Roslyn Weiss Professor of Philosophy
Professor of Philosophy Claremont Graduate University
Lehigh University Claremont, CA
Bethlehem, PA USA
USA
Catherine Zuckert
A. Gabrièle Wersinger Professor of Political Science
Professor of Philosophy University of Notre Dame
University of Rheims Notre Dame, IN
France USA

xx

9780826435354_Pre_Final_txt_print.indd xx 3/17/2001 4:05:35 PM


INTRODUCTION

People usually think of Plato as a philosopher. Plato was not only a philosopher, however;
That is correct, as far as it goes; but it can be and his importance and influence extend far
argued that Plato was not merely a philoso- beyond the specific field of philosophy. By
pher. He actually created and gave the initial common consent, he was the greatest writer
definition to the specific intellectual practise of the ancient Greek language, even includ-
and way of life that has been called philoso- ing classical Greek oratory, poetry, drama
phy ever since, even though his own philo- and history; he was also a superb tragic and
sophic work was far less narrow than what comic dramatist, a fine poet, a composer of
has been common under the label philosophy brilliant speeches, a ferocious social critic and
in the last century. He is also the most influ- reformer, a political, musical, educational
ential of all the ancient philosophers, and and medical theorist, a mathematician, myth-
perhaps of all philosophers. The other major maker, cosmologist and even, perhaps, a city
ancient philosopher usually mentioned in planner. Due to this extraordinary richness in
this regard, Aristotle, was a member of his writings, Plato’s influence can be found
Plato’s school, the Academy, for 20 years and in many fields other than philosophy. He is
can be seen as a kind of Platonist. Besides a truly ‘interdisciplinary’ figure. In recent
the sustained influence that these two have years, discussions of Plato are to be found in
exerted on the subsequent history of Western professional books and journals on aesthet-
philosophy, there was a third major ancient ics, anthropology, archaeology, art history,
philosopher, Plotinus. Although Plotinus con- classical philology, city planning, drama, edu-
sidered himself only to have explained more cation, geography, Greek, history, law, litera-
clearly what Plato said obscurely, he is today ture, mathematics, medicine, music, penology,
thought to have founded a rather different philosophy, politics, psychology, religious
line of thought, now called Neoplatonism. studies, rhetoric and sociology. Besides their
Neoplatonism turns out to have been a very extraordinarily complex and persistent influ-
powerful influence from late antiquity to ence on philosophers from his own day to
the nineteenth century even though this was the present, Plato’s dialogues have inspired
unrecognized until one hundred and 50 years poetry, dramatic performances, movies, sculp-
ago. In a way, then, all of the most influential tures, paintings and musical compositions.
ancient philosophy is Platonic. A computer program is named after Plato.

9780826435354_Intro_Final_txt_print.indd 1 3/8/2001 5:12:11 PM


INTRODUCTION

Mathematical discussions of Platonic num- quickly encounter difficulties. Different and


bers and Platonic solids still occur. Scholars even mutually exclusive views of the same
have written about Platonism in Music and matter – for example, the composition of the
the Platonics are a Rumanian rock band. soul or the characteristics of the best human
Plato is unique among the most prolific society – seem to be put forward in different
ancient authors in that every single text men- dialogues. How could it be that Plato really
tioned by an ancient source as having been thinks that the soul is simple and has no parts
written by him has survived somehow into (Phaedo) and that it has three parts (Phaedrus,
the present, something not true, for exam- Republic)? How could Plato hold that the
ple, about the tragedies of Aeschylus and best city would be governed by philosophers
Sophocles or the dialogues and treatises of selected for their intellectual qualities and rig-
Aristotle. Yet we have less certain factual orously educated (Republic) and that it would
knowledge about him than about many oth- be ruled by elected magistrates and a citizen
ers and disputes continue about the authen- assembly (Laws)? And what true Platonic
ticity of Letters attributed to him and about views are we to extract from the many dia-
political involvements on his part described logues that end by explicitly stating that the
in some of those Letters. Similarly, there participants have not discovered the correct
are more and more fundamental disagree- answer to the question under discussion and
ments about Plato than about any other phi- that they must therefore begin again?
losopher. It is notorious that Plato scholars One of the most widespread modern ideas
dispute not only about the proper interpreta- about Plato to grow out of the pursuit of
tions of his works but also about the proper his true views was ‘developmentalism’, the
principles on which interpretations are to be belief that apparent doctrinal inconsisten-
based. Even so, his dialogues retain an appar- cies among the dialogues can be explained as
ently endless capacity to inspire interest and products of Plato’s intellectual development
motivate discussion. from a youthful and uncritical follower of
In the scholarly world of the last 100 to Socrates to a much more systematic and dog-
150 years, the study of Plato has developed matic thinker in his middle and later years.
important divisions and conceptual antino- Based on either or both thematic considera-
mies. Since the Renaissance, and especially tions and statistical analysis of certain details
since the late eighteenth and early nineteenth of the dialogues’ style, it was believed that
centuries, a distinctly modern interest in his- one could clearly distinguish groups of ‘early’,
torical accuracy has increasingly supplanted ‘middle’ and ‘late’ dialogues and correspond-
the more ancient interest in Plato because ingly different phases in Plato’s philosophic
of the impersonal and eternal truths to be development. This developmental view was
found in his writings. Pursuing the question very widely accepted for much of the twenti-
‘What did Plato really think?’ has motivated eth century, but opposed by a smaller group
the continuing clarification of the differences of interpreters, notably Paul Shorey and
between Plato and the various Platonisms of Harold Cherniss, who held that Plato’s true
the later tradition and has generated a number views had an underlying unity throughout.
of influential interpretive commitments. As far reaching as the division between a
Interpreters who turn to the dialogues developmentalist and a ‘unitarian’ interpre-
to discover Plato’s true doctrines, however, tation, as the latter is sometimes called, and

9780826435354_Intro_Final_txt_print.indd 2 3/8/2001 5:12:11 PM


INTRODUCTION

reflecting the increased specialization and separation from the rather different Socrates
disciplinary separation in educational curric- that is found in the contemporaneous writ-
ula, another division grew between the Plato ings of Xenophon and Aristophanes.
whose written texts are taught in depart- In Plato scholarship of the last 25 to 30
ments of Greek or of classics and the Plato years, however, four major developments
whose theories and arguments are taught have undermined and resolved these divi-
in departments of philosophy. This discipli- sions. First, through the work of Holger
nary division reflected and, at the same time, Thesleff, Debra Nails and others, it has come
encouraged the belief that literature was to be widely recognized that despite the
something separate and distinct from philos- general developmental consensus, there was
ophy, so that, in the study of Plato one could never, in fact, agreement about exactly which
separate the literary and dramatic aspects of dialogues went into the three groups. More
the dialogues for study by philologists and significantly, it was shown that neither the-
assign the study of theories, arguments and matic nor stylistic evidence unambiguously
ideas to philosophers. The literary and dra- supports the division of Plato’s dialogues
matic aspects could be thought of as the form into three groups. Evidence of revision and
in which content was presented that was school accumulation has provided further
independent of that form. evidence that assuming the dialogues to have
Finally, among philosophers, two further been written in the way modern books are, at
divisions developed in the mid-twentieth cen- one time and by the author alone, is mislead-
tury. The first was between those who sought ing. This has led to the demise of the develop-
to recover the truth from Plato’s dialogues mental consensus that existed 50 years ago
by emphasizing minute logical analysis of and a considerable weakening of the devel-
arguments extracted from their dialogical opmental-unitarian opposition. They also
contexts and those who thought the truth serve to undermine the project of finding an
lay in a broader confrontation with funda- historically significant Socratic philosophy in
mental assumptions. The latter were some- Plato’s ‘early’ dialogues, and, in fact, those
times referred to as ‘continental’ because who pursue ‘Socratic philosophy’ now do so
they tended to be from continental Europe without making historical claims.
while the former tended to be from England Second, interpreters in many disciplines
and the English speaking countries. They are have increasingly recognized that Plato made
sometimes referred to as ‘analytical’ both for extensive use of a large variety of literary and
their methods of logical analysis and assess- dramatic elements. The dialogues are rich in
ment and for selecting only overtly ‘logical’ images and metaphors, puns, jokes and other
parts of dialogues for study. forms of humour like multiple kinds of irony.
A second division was created by those Plato has borrowed story lines from mythol-
who, following the lead of Gregory Vlastos, ogy and literature, language from poetry and
thought that study of a subset of Plato’s rhetoric and characters and settings from his-
‘early’ dialogues could be used as sources tory, but has transformed them so as to cre-
for the discovery of the true philosophy of ate connections and resonances between the
Socrates, rather than the philosophy of Plato, literary elements on the one hand and central
although debates existed from the beginning philosophic themes and ideas on the other.
about the historicity of Plato’s Socrates in Evidence of reworking and revising his own

9780826435354_Intro_Final_txt_print.indd 3 3/8/2001 5:12:11 PM


INTRODUCTION

material suggests that this was deliberate on Fourth, reflection on facts and reports
Plato’s part. The tendency of current work is about the writings and views of Plato’s stu-
to recognize, therefore, that form and content dents in the ancient world by John Dillon,
cannot be detached from each other without Harold Tarrant and others has led to a clearer
misrepresenting the complex wholes that understanding of the evolution of Platonic
Plato worked so hard to produce. Similarly, thinking, the ways in which the ancients
Platonic doctrines should not simply be read understood the dialogues and the Platonic
off of the dramatic, dialectical conversations thought in them. Thus, we have come to a
of which most dialogues consist, nor should clearer recognition of the similarities and
arguments be extracted for analysis and differences between the Old Academy in
assessment in separation from their dialogical the first generation after Plato’s death and
settings, specific characters, settings, topics the later, ancient New Academy, Middle
and overall conversations. The more inter- Platonism and Neoplatonism. This, in turn,
disciplinary and holistic approach in recent has enabled us to see more clearly the sources
scholarship has generated a growing appre- of beliefs about Plato’s thought that are, to
ciation of the philosophic importance of dra- some extent, still influential today and to see
matic and literary characteristics and has led that they are not simply part of Plato’s own
to identification of a variety of structures in thought as expressed in the dialogues. (more
the dialogues – pedagogical, pedimental and detailed treatments of each of interpretive
musical – other than the logical structure of developments will be found in Chapter 5)
arguments and conclusions, and to recogni- We are in a period of significant change in
tion that Plato’s dialogues are philosophical the orientation and content of thinking about
texts of an essentially different kind from the Plato. The trend is towards more holistic, con-
expository writings of most philosophers in textual and interdisciplinary approaches. Due
the Western canon. to this, the time is ripe not only for a new guide
In line with this, third, interpreters have book to Plato, but for a new kind of guide or
come to appreciate the character of Socrates companion. This volume is unlike existing ones
in the dialogues as something other than the in several important ways. Rather than limit-
two-dimensional mouthpiece for Platonic ing the topics included to philosophy, in our
doctrines he was long thought to be. On the choice of contents we have also gathered arti-
contrary, his character is forever inquiring, cles on characters, education, language, myth,
viewing all conclusions as open to recon- poetry, rhetoric, textual history and a variety
sideration and revision. This resonates with of special features of the dialogues as written
what happens in nearly all of the dialogues: texts. Contributors include not only philoso-
they end by explicitly denying that the par- phers, but specialists in Classics, Comparative
ticipants have come to know the answer to Literature, English, Greek, History and
the question they have been discussing. These Political Science; and they are professors in
facts are consistent with Plato’s choice to write Australia, Canada, England, Finland, France,
no treatises, but only dialogues in which he Germany, Greece, Ireland, Israel, Italy, Japan,
himself never speaks and suggest that Plato’s the Netherlands, Russia, Scotland, Switzerland,
philosophizing might be, unlike much of the the United States and Wales.
subsequent Western tradition, nondogmatic, Rather than a small number – perhaps 10
open-ended and nonauthoritarian. to 20 – of long articles on a proportionally

9780826435354_Intro_Final_txt_print.indd 4 3/8/2001 5:12:11 PM


INTRODUCTION

limited array of subjects, we have gathered body of Platonic writings and the manuscript
a rather large number – more than 140 – on tradition. After this, in alphabetical order are
a very large array of subjects. And rather individual articles on each dialogue, as well
than articles that share single methodology as one each on the dubious and spurious
or interpretive approach, we have been plu- ones and on the Letters. Chapter 3 includes
ralistic, seeking to include many different articles on a variety of specific features of the
approaches. In fact, our aim was to have dialogues as texts, such as their use of drama,
all of the current approaches represented in humour and irony and a variety of structures
order to give as complete a picture as pos- that recent interpreters have identified as
sible of the current state of knowledge and ways of understanding Plato’s thought as
research about Plato. Pluralism in interpreta- expressed in the dialogues. Chapter 4, the
tion is not only a fact, however, it is, impor- longest, deals with a wide variety of themes
tantly, how error and vacuity are avoided and topics explicitly treated in the dialogues.
(Heath 2002). Chapter 5 concerns the Later Reception,
In sum, the aim was for the greatest pos- Interpretation and Influence of Plato and the
sible breadth of coverage so that the volume Dialogues. It begins with the history of the
would be encyclopaedic in what it offers Academy in antiquity, and continues through
readers. It should be useful to undergradu- later ancient Platonisms, the medieval, ren-
ates and graduate students as well as inter- aissance, modern and contemporary inter-
ested general readers, and even professionals pretive approaches.
who may need a quick orientation on an
aspect of Plato’s work, thought or later influ-
ence. Articles are designed to offer a concise,
lucid ‘starting point’ or introduction to their TECHNICAL TOOLS AND
topics and to indicate the main problems CONVENTIONS
that have been debated and the main lines
of these debates. But beyond providing basic The volume makes use of several technical
knowledge of a topic, it is hoped that the tools and conventions of which the reader
extent of the topics treated and the diversity should be aware. Translations of Plato, unless
of specializations and scholarly orientations otherwise indicated, are taken from those in
represented will help keep readers’ precon- Cooper, J.M. (ed.) (1997), Plato: Complete
ceptions open to revision, so that we, like Works. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.
Plato’s Socrates, may be reflective and criti- Since its appearance, this has been the stand-
cal, constantly evaluating and reevaluating ard English collection of translations.
our own assumptions. Important Greek terms are transliterated
The volume is divided into five chapters. into the Roman alphabet and set in ital-
Chapter 1, Plato’s Life – Historical and ics, for example, akrasia (lacking control
Intellectual Context, begins with Plato’s biog- of oneself) and paideia (education). We use
raphy and then includes a number of individu- macrons to distinguish the Greek eta (ê) from
als, groups, cultural practises and movements epsilon (e), for example, epistêmê (knowl-
that elucidate the intellectual context in which edge), merê (parts), genê (kinds) and eidê
Plato lived and wrote. Chapter 2 is intro- (forms). We also use macrons to distinguish
duced by a general discussion of the entire the Greek omega (ô) from omicron (o), for

9780826435354_Intro_Final_txt_print.indd 5 3/8/2001 5:12:11 PM


INTRODUCTION

example, erôs (love) and logos (account). The Classical Texts. London.’ Similarly, ‘Gerson
Greek letter upsilon is sometimes transliter- 2003:79–88’ uniquely refers to Lloyd P.
ated as y (as in psychê) and sometimes u (as Gerson, Knowing Persons published in
in muthos). Although this is inconsistent, it Oxford and to pages 79–88 in that volume.
accurately reflects the absence of a scholarly Full information about all citations is given
consensus on the question. in the Bibliography, pp. 309–47. Other exam-
Although the words Form and Idea are ples are given below:
often used interchangeably, in discussions
of Plato we use ‘form’ only and do not
capitalize. Reference Full citation
Multiple forms of crossreferencing are in the text
used in this volume. Besides the Table of
Derrida Derrida, J. (1972a), ‘Plato’s
Contents that lists each article by title in each
1972a. pharmacy,’ in B. Johnson
section, there is an Index of Names and an
(Trans.), Disseminations.
Index of Topics at the back of the volume.
Chicago (repr. of
The most frequent form of crossreference is
‘La pharmacie de Platon,’
the abbreviation, q.v., used within articles to
Quel Tel, pp. 32–3).
refer interested readers to a related article by
title. Thus, the sentence ‘The dialogues offer Ferber Ferber, R. (2002), ‘The
many more candidate methods (q.v.) for dis- 2002:189 Absolute Good and the
covering reality amid appearances’ refers the Human Goods,’ in G. Reale
reader to the article on Method, which can be and S. Scolnicov (eds), New
found either through the Table of Contents Images of Plato: Dialogues
or through the Index. The titles of the dia- on the Idea of the Good.
logues and the names Plato and Socrates are Sankt Augustin, pp. 187–96.
not crossreferences because they are used so
Kraut Kraut, R. (2008), ‘Plato,’ The
often.
2008:pt4 Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, E.N. Zalta (ed.),
http://plato.stanford.edu/
archives/fall2008/entries/
BIBLIOGRAPHY
plato/>, accessed 1 June
2008.
Each article is intended to give the reader
a clear, concise introduction to the subject Rowe Rowe, C. (1989), ‘The Unity
or topic indicated in its title. To inform the 1989:177 of the Phaedrus: A Reply
reader where to learn more about the topic to Heath,’ Oxford Studies
and specific aspects of it, secondary sources in Ancient Philosophy. 7,
are indicated through references within the 175–88
article in an abbreviated form: author’s last
name and a year of publication and, per-
haps specific page numbers. Thus ‘Heath The understanding of Plato – or any other
2002’ cited to above will be found to refer author – is a collaborative, dialectical and
uniquely to ‘Heath, M. (2002), Interpreting historical process. The hope of the editors is

9780826435354_Intro_Final_txt_print.indd 6 3/8/2001 5:12:12 PM


INTRODUCTION

that the present volume will be a part of that and varieties of reception and interpreta-
process. It is collaborative in that contribu- tion of Plato. Views of the right answers as
tors offer together their views of topics on the well as identification of the important ques-
study of which they have spent a great deal of tions are always – as a matter of fact – under
time and energy. It is dialectical both because discussion. This is the nature of the world
the reasoned views of contributors disagree of knowledge. Collaboration in pursuit of
on various points and because we try to make truth happens both through cooperation and
clear to the reader the reasons for our some- through disagreement. Rational criticism and
times differing views. It is historical insofar disagreement, as Plato’s Socrates might agree,
as we offer more than a dozen articles on are intellectual, social and ethical goods.
the historical contexts in which Plato wrote
and more than 20 articles on the history Gerald A. Press

9780826435354_Intro_Final_txt_print.indd 7 3/8/2001 5:12:12 PM


1
PLATO’S LIFE – HISTORICAL
AND INTELLECTUAL CONTEXT

PLATO’S LIFE and intellectual preferences, Plato could seek


compensation for the depressive circum-
Holger Thesleff stances in poetry and drama, rhetoric and
Little is certain, but some facts and hypoth- philosophy (qq.v.), private discussions and
eses can be sifted from a great variety of homoerotic play in gymnasia.
sources and traditions about Plato. Modern Some detect lines of escapism in Plato’s
accounts include Davies (1971), Friedländer attitudes. In spite of his professed early
(1958), Guthrie (1975), Nails (2002), Ryle interest in Athenian politics, there is little
(1966) and Thesleff (1982:20–39), on which evidence that he appeared in public or took
the following is based. physical risks, although it is reported that he
We know that Plato died in 347 BCE; his served in the army three times (D. L. 3.8).
year of birth was 426 or later. Both parents Problems of ethics were in the foreground of
belonged to the old Athenian aristocracy. His his thinking from his early years. His politi-
father died early, and his mother remarried to cal sympathies passed from the Thirty to the
her uncle who also died, perhaps before Plato moderate democrats (who then contributed
was 13. Plato, his sister and brothers grew up to the death of Socrates), ending in deep dis-
with his mother’s family in Athens. This ‘clan’, illusionment with human society (see Ep. 7
impoverished in the Peloponnesian War like 324b–6b).
many other landowners, was dominated by The impact of Socrates and his circle was
Critias, a gifted sophist and dramatist, later of fundamental importance to Plato. Socrates
leader of the Thirty, who sought peace with was a moral model for him and gave the dia-
Sparta to stop the Periclean democracy-based lectical frame to his thinking (q.v. Dialectic,
Athenian imperialism. Elenchus). But Plato’s early commitment to
When Plato had reached his early teens, speculative theory is due to influence from
life in Athens was marked by prolonged war, various pre-Socratics (q.v.) and mathema-
poverty, political cynicism and ideological ticians. After the death of Socrates, Plato
confusion. Yet, cultural life flourished in the seems to have spent some time with the
city. As a sensitive young man with literary Socratic Euclides in Megara. The theory

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 8 3/8/2001 5:13:03 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

of the utopian state may have taken shape search into the basics of the good, of being,
before 392 when Republic bks 2–5 was per- and of knowledge (q.v. Epistemology), and to
haps parodied in Aristophanes’ Ecclesiazusae themselves become part of a new philosophi-
(Thesleff 1997). Plato’s mathematical orien- cal elite. This latter ambition was supported
tation was stimulated by his brilliant young by Dion in particular who had some hopes
friend Theaetetus. His Apology did not set- for a ‘philosophers’ rule’ in Syracuse. Most of
tle the anti-Socratic sentiments. In the 390s Plato’s prominent students (D. L. 3.46) were
he seems also to have presented entertaining in fact non-Athenians.
and provocative sketches of Socratic discus- Plato was averse to practical politics,
sions to groups of friends (q.v. Public), but preferring spirited philosophical elenchus
the preserved written dialogues are almost and a private ‘being together’ (sunousia).
certainly written at a later date. The Athenians tended to mistrust esoteric
The date and circumstances of Plato’s clubs, so it is understandable that Plato
first voyage to the West are controversial, acquired the stigma of haughty arrogance
but there can be little doubt about the fol- to outsiders (Xenophon, Ap. 1). Plato’s
lowing general lines. Plato left Athens about alleged Pythagorean models were already
386 BCE, possibly frustrated by lack of exaggerated in antiquity. Contrary to the
intellectual response in Athens. In Tarentum Pythagoreans, Plato made no point of secrecy
in southern Italy he met Archytas, a local or mystic initiation, despite some play in
political leader who knew Pythagorean tra- Symposium (q.v. Esoterism; Love), and to
ditions better than Socrates’ friends did (q.v. accept women ‘officially’ in the school in
Pythagoreans; Phaedo); he was later in com- Athens may be doubted, though Diogenes
munication with Plato’s circle. Probably from lists two by name (D. L. 3.46).
Locri, famous for its ancient laws, Plato went The apparently unexpected death of
over to Sicily. At the court of Syracuse he met Dionysius I (367 BCE) meant a sudden new
the ruler’s twenty-year old relative, Dion, turn. Dion immediately invited Plato to assist
who became his lifelong intimate friend and him in organizing a philosopher-led state in
whose role in Plato’s political experiments Sicily. The new ruler, Dionysius II, did not
should not be underestimated. After Plato’s meet the expectations of Dion and Plato
return home (after dramatic events vari- (whatever they were), and court intrigues
ously described in the sources), Anniceris the soon forced Dion into exile; but Plato was
Cyrenaic purchased a piece of land in the persuaded to stay until the following spring.
Akadêmeia park that became Plato’s school The explanations given in Ep. 7, reflect
(D. L. 3.1; q.v. Academy). Plato’s own loyalty to Dion, his uncertainty
From the mid-380s onwards, Plato spent and his idealism when confronted with life’s
his time quietly in the Academy outside the practicalities.
city walls. He had perhaps started to teach his Back in Athens, where the Academy kept
own philosophy in partial contrast to other contacts with Syracuse, Plato was engaged in
Socratics, the sophists and Isocrates (q.v.). new challenges from younger friends, includ-
Some of his written works now reached a larger ing Aristotle and his third voyage to Sicily in
public. He gathered around him a small group 361 signalled the end of his Sicilian adven-
of intellectual friends who were prepared to ture. Dionysius had been reported to ‘have

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 9 3/8/2001 5:13:03 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

time’ for Platonic philosophy now, but Plato ARISTOPHANES AND


soon discovered that he was bluffing. Dion’s INTELLECTUALS
enemies saw their chance. Only with the help
of Archytas did Plato escape an imminent Harold Tarrant
death. Dion later managed to seize power in The plays of Aristophanes and his rivals offer
Syracuse, in spite of Plato’s warning, and was something of a comic mirror of the intellec-
murdered as a ‘tyrant’. tual world in which Plato’s Socrates is situ-
By Greek standards, Plato was now an ated. Plato’s boyhood had coincided with a
old man. His younger friends had taken over period of intellectual ferment at Athens.
many Academic activities. The dialogues Pericles had associated with intellectuals
from Plato’s later years reflect a wide variety such as the cosmologist Anaxagoras and the
of new philosophic stimuli and polemics. music-theorist Damon (Alcibiades 118c), and
During Plato’s last years the scene in Athens another prominent Athenian, Archelaus, had
was dominated by the Macedonian question. studied with Anaxagoras and developed cos-
Athenian nationalism did not appeal to the mological ideas of his own. Particularly rich
internationally oriented Academy. The old individuals like Callias, son of Hipponicus,
master preferred to stay far from the glow- host character in the Protagoras, were also
ing political debates. But by his friends, liable to play host to visiting itinerant intel-
including Aristotle, Plato was venerated as lectuals, including those we know as ‘soph-
an architect of philosophy and a benign and ists’. However, there was probably little
wise moral leader. After his death in 347 he immediate impact on ordinary Athenians
was the subject of some kind of hero cult in until, as Thucydides reports when discuss-
the Academy. We have copies of a bust by ing the effects of the plague at Athens (2.53),
Silanion which, though posthumous, is not war forced people to rethink their attitudes
particularly idealized. to the gods and to morality. His work shows
The third-century BCE biographer, Dio- an Athens little interested in discussing tradi-
genes Laertius, cites some 43 sources indis- tional moral values as opposed to civic expe-
criminately, including Alcimus, Alexander, diency and personal hedonism.
Alexandrides, Alexis, Amphis, Anaxilaïdes, The comic playwright Aristophanes,
Anaxilas, Antigonus, Antileon, Antisthenes, whose creative life began in 427 BCE and
Apollodorus, Archytas, Aristippus, Aristo- extended into the 380s, like his fellow comic
phanes (grammarian), Aristoxenus, Athen- poets, presented various intellectuals on
odorus, Chamaeleon, Clearchus, Cratinus, stage, most obviously in Clouds, produced in
Dicaearchus, Euphorion, Eupolis, Favorinus, 423 BCE. The very fact that the new ideas
Heraclides, Hermippus, Idomeneus, Mnesi- had become suitable material for comedy
stratus, Molon, Myroninus, Neanthes, Onetor, suggests that ordinary citizens were certainly
Pamphila, Panaetius, Polemo, Praxiphanes, aware of them and perhaps concerned about
Sabinus, Satyrus, Speusippus, Theopompus, their implications. The leading intellectual
Thrasylus, Timon, Timotheus and Xenophon. here is none other than Socrates himself, but,
Apollodorus and Favorinus and Philodemus in spite of several details that seem to cap-
and Olympiodorus are also important to the ture Socrates’ idiosyncrasies rather well, his
biographical tradition, and Plato’s controver- portrait is so different from anything found
sial Ep. 7 is crucial. in Plato that many suppose him to be simply

10

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 10 3/8/2001 5:13:03 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

a convenient figure on whom to father virtu- identified with him), and that airy stuffs,
ally all of the new ideas regardless of who including Air, the Gulf (between heaven and
had first propounded them. Insofar as this earth), Clouds, Respiration and perhaps
‘Socrates’ figure runs an intellectual school Mist (Derveni Papyrus 424, 627, 814), are
or phrontistêrion, the play is an exercise of the intelligences that Socrates acknowledges
the imagination. Yet, that granted, one should and swears by in Clouds.
note that Plato’s Socrates expresses some Also prominent in Clouds are theories
interest in virtually all new ideas, in spite of about poetry and music (636–54), and about
his professed lack of expertise in any. Some, the correct naming of things (658–93). In
however, read more into Aristophanes’ por- Plato, the character Protagoras encourages
trait of Socrates, and Vander Waerdt (1994b) the study of poetry (Prt. 338e–9a) in which
notes that the playwright seems to have a Hippias and Ion claim expertise (Hippias
good understanding of many contemporary Minor; Ion), while correct naming is asso-
theories that could have influenced Socrates, ciated with the sophist Prodicus (Cratylus
especially those of Diogenes of Apollonia. 384b; Prt. 339e–41e ) and less decisively
At 314–426 the emphasis falls on cosmol- with the neo-Heraclitean Cratylus – with
ogy and a consequent naturalistic explana- whom Aristotle says that Plato studied. More
tion of the usual manifestations of divine worrying, though not directly associated
power. Socrates’ ‘gods’ are the Clouds, who with Socrates or his fellow proprietor of the
are employed in the explanation of rain phrontistêrion, Chaerephon, who appears
and thunderstorms in preference to Zeus. to be involved with the minutiae of biology
Yet, Socrates also comes across as a priestly (Clouds 143–66), are the two arguments,
character (compare Birds 1553–64) who Superior and Inferior, that reside with them
is both aloof and aloft (212–25), and con- and have taken on a life of their own. It is
ducts private ceremonies while invoking not so much the strange, new, technical and
deities (254–66). This combination of pre- cosmological ideas that threatened society,
Socratic-style cosmology and priestly atti- but the new interest in those using the courts
tudes and functions can now be matched in and deliberative bodies of Athens in making
the Derveni Papyrus, particularly since the the inferior (and amoral) argument appear
reconstruction and publication of the first superior (and justified). Plato (Theaetetus
fragmentary columns in 1997. The author, 172a–c) shares the worries of Aristophanes
who discusses rituals designed to avert hos- about the moral relativism that results from
tile spirits (presumably on death), and then the application to civic life of Protagoras’
subjects a poem of ‘Orpheus’ about Zeus theory that there are two arguments on every
to a consistently allegorical reading, quotes matter (Antiope fr. 189; D. L. 9.51 = A1 ‘DK’;
Heraclitus and is influenced by the ideas of cf. Euripides). Techniques include appeals to
Anaxagoras and his immediate followers. the questionable conduct of the gods and
The date of this work could in theory be of heroes (Clouds 1048–82; cf. Euthyphro
anywhere between 430 and 350 BCE, but 5e–6a; Republic 378b).
an early date would have made it more topi- The tragic playwright Euripides must
cal. It is noteworthy that air in the papyrus also be placed among the intellectuals sati-
is the physical manifestation of intelligence rized by Aristophanes (Acharnians, Thesmo-
(meaning Zeus, and some other divinities phoriazousai, Frogs), for he is regularly

11

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 11 3/8/2001 5:13:03 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

credited with words and ideas that recall Education was deemed the responsibility
the comedian’s portrait of Socrates: indeed of the parents until the eighteenth year. From
a fragment of the first version of Clouds preclassical times, infants were left at home
(Aristophanes. fr. 376K = D. L. 2.18) makes with their mothers until the age of seven.
Socrates the source of Euripides’ clever, In classical times, elementary education
tricky-talking tragedies. On Euripides and the was provided by professional teachers, usu-
intellectual world both Wildberg (2006) and ally of low social status, thus easily afford-
Conacher (1998) are useful. Religious experts able, to whom the children were taken by a
including Hierocles (Peace) are another of his household slave, the paidagogos. Education
comic targets, and the urban-design expert consisted mainly in the learning of read-
Meton appears in Birds. Ameipsias’ comedy ing and writing and memorizing poetry, in
Connus (423 BC, as Clouds) revolves around particular Homer. Literacy was apparently
a teacher of new music referred to by Plato’s already rather widespread in Athens, and
Socrates as his teacher (Euthydemus 272c), in general in Greece, before classical times
and also brought Socrates on stage, while (Harris 1989). Poetry was taught for its edu-
Eupolis’ Flatterers of two years later depicts cational value, as offering role models for
the would-be intellectuals who tried to emulation. It was to this function of poetry
sponge off the riches of Callias, among them that Plato was to be opposed. In addition,
Protagoras (ff. 157–8) and Socrates’ strange better-to-do families would also provide
colleague Chaerephon (f. 180). instruction in music, including singing and
Insofar as the plays of Aristophanes gave some basic numeracy.
a vivid picture of intellectual life, Plato was The physical aspect of education was not
influenced by them, though lamenting the disregarded in youth, as in adulthood, and
bad publicity that Clouds had given Socrates. the competitive spirit remained unabated,
Euthd. seems to allude to Clouds a number as evidenced by the wide appeal of the pan-
of times; the depiction of Callias’ house in hellenic games and the Athenian penchant
Prt. appears to owe something to the phron- for legal disputation. Education was very
tistêrion, and Clouds is even quoted with much the same for both sexes except in
approval (Symposium 221b). Athens where girls learned only what was
adequate for the running of a household.
Girls elsewhere were taught wrestling, run-
ning and javelin throwing. In some places,
EDUCATION (PAIDEIA) there were also ‘finishing schools’ for girls,
like that of Sappho in Lesbos in the sixth-
Samuel Scolnicov century BCE.
Education can be described as Plato’s central Sparta was apparently the first Greek city
concern. Since before Homeric times, Greek to develop an institutionalized system of
education consisted, on the whole, of athletic education, whose aim was avowedly milita-
training and instillation of heroic values. The ristic. Boys were taken from their mothers
chief educational aims were manly valour at the age of seven and lived in communal
(aretê, a word that would later be used to barracks until after military service, to which
designate human excellence in general) and they returned periodically. Literacy was not
competitiveness. much prized. The evidence about education

12

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 12 3/8/2001 5:13:04 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

in other parts of the Greek world is rather The sophists’ main interest was in man and
more sketchy and circumstantial in society and they were rightly described, in
In classical times, the heroic ideal was modern times, as the ‘fifth-century human-
gradually superseded by paideia – initially, ists’. They developed the beginnings of what
in aristocratic circles, ‘a profound and inti- we would now call psychology, sociology,
mate relationship, a personal union between anthropology and political science. Some of
a young man and an elder who was at once them also dealt with mathematics, astron-
his model, his guide, his initiator’ (Marrou omy and the like, always with a view to their
1956) and later as an ideal of culture and human relevance. Common to all was a keen
education, akin to the German concept of interest in language and its uses.
Bildung. From Protagoras’ speech in the pla- Plato and Isocrates (q.v.) established the
tonic dialogue named after him, no doubt first institutions of higher learning. Little is
voicing the current opinion, we know that known about their organization. Isocrates
education was thought of primarily as social- continued the sophistic line and taught rhet-
ization and society was regarded as the chief oric, as preparation for public life. Plato’s
educational agent. Academy (q.v.) was arguably the first institu-
In the fifth-century BCE, democratic tion of research. An inkling of Plato’s edu-
Athens attracted those that became known cational programme in the Academy may
as the sophists (literally ‘experts’), itinerant probably be had from the curriculum pro-
intellectuals from all over Greece who intro- posed by him in bks 3 and 7 of his Republic.
duced the idea of higher education for those Plato recognized the place of the mathemati-
who could pay. Democracy meant the demise cal sciences in his educational programme,
of aristocratic values in favour of the idea of yet was opposed, on grounds of principle, to
pragmatic success in private and public life. the separation of disciplines within philoso-
Any free man, and eventually anyone, could phy, though perhaps subordinated to the pri-
become kalos k’agathos (fine and good), ini- macy of ethics. Many of his associates went
tially a denotation of aristocracy but, with on to serve as political advisors in Greek
democracy, coming to designate ‘the good cities. Aristotle, in his Lyceum, possibly insti-
man’. tuted division of labour in research. Higher
The sophists (q.v.) taught the art of a education was later formalized in ‘schools’ as
flourishing life, eudaimonia (generally, but the Academy, the Lyceum, the Stoa, Epicurus’
misleadingly translated as ‘happiness’; q.v.) Garden, etc.
readily understood as political success. They
developed and perfected rhetorical and dia-
lectical skills as tools of success in public
life and in the courts. Gorgias of Leontini ELEATICS
wrote manuals of rhetoric, now mostly lost,
which included model speeches such as the Herbert Granger
extant Encomium of Helen. The anonymous ‘Our Eleatic tribe’, reports Plato’s Eleatic
Dissoi logoi (Double arguments) is a rather Stranger, begins with Xenophanes of
schematic textbook of exercises developing Colophon, and even earlier (Sophist
Protagoras’ dictum that on every issue two 242d). But the true founder of the school
opposing arguments can be developed. is Parmenides of Elea, whose most notable

13

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 13 3/8/2001 5:13:04 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

disciples are limited to Zeno of Elea and the shape of a sphere. Some contemporary
Melissus of Samos. Scholars accept a date of scholars, however, deny Parmenides’ belief
515 for Parmenides’ birth, calculated from in numerical monism, but Plato (Sph. 242d),
Plato’s depiction, very likely highly fictional, as well as Aristotle (On Generation and
of an encounter between the old Parmenides Corruption 325a13–15), do not hesitate in
and the young Socrates (Parmenides 127b–c). attributing the doctrine to him.
Parmenides published his only work in the The goddess is not deterred by the mis-
first quarter of the fifth century, a poem in match between her description of reality
heroic verse, which is remarkable for its doc- and what sensation reveals to be a world
trines, but above all for its deft use of exten- of a multitude of changing, diverse objects,
sive philosophical argumentation for the first and she requires the youth to judge her
time. Despite the poem’s rational exposi- words with his ‘reason’ (‘DK’ B7.5–6).
tion of doctrines, in its elaborate proem an Nevertheless, when the goddess ends her dis-
unnamed youth narrates his supernatural course on truth and takes up the ‘opinions
journey to an unnamed goddess lodged in of mortals’, she lays out in detail a natural
some unknown place, who welcomes him philosophy that includes a cosmogony and
warmly and tells him she shall reveal to even a theogony. She justifies her discourse
him the ‘truth’ and the ‘opinions of mor- by maintaining that it lays bare the funda-
tals’, which possess no ‘true trust’ (‘DK’ mental mistake inherent in mortal thinking,
B1.29–30). These two subjects make up the in its positing two opposing first principles,
two expository parts of the poem. light and night. These in mixing with one
Although no aspect of the goddess’ another yield the cosmos, although light and
argument is beyond dispute, plausibly she night in their eternity and homogeneity are
grounds her speculation on the supposition each like the single object of reality revealed
that thought, speech and knowledge require in ‘truth’. The goddess explains to the youth
for their subject something that exists. that her cosmology has plausibility, presum-
Accordingly, what does not exist, or ‘non- ably satisfies the testimony of the senses, and
being’, cannot be thought about, expressed that armed with this knowledge no mortal
or known, and any conception that presup- opinion shall ever ‘outstrip’ him (B8.60–1).
poses what does not exist is as much non- Zeno and Melissus indicate no interest in
sense as ‘non-being’ itself. natural philosophy, but plausibly the ‘opin-
The goddess proceeds a priori to deduce ions of mortals’ provides the model for the
the basic features of reality. ‘Being’, or reality, fifth-century BCE natural philosophers who
does not suffer generation and destruction, succeeded Parmenides.
since if it came to be it must have previously Zeno and Melissus are the heirs of
not existed, and if it perished it must pass Parmenides, not merely in doctrine, but
away into nonexistence. Furthermore, since above all in their argumentative prowess.
the goddess takes any change to be a variety Parmenides has no such effect on the pre-
of generation and destruction, reality is free Socratic natural philosophers, who venture
from any sort of change, ‘alteration in place little in the way of argument, and before
and exchange of bright colour’ (B8.40–1). Socrates and Plato it is the sophist Gorgias of
Reality is also indivisible, a single object, Leontini who exemplifies best someone who
uniform in character and limited in extent in emulates Eleatic argumentation (B3).

14

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 14 3/8/2001 5:13:04 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

Zeno, the younger friend and fellow citi- something cannot come to be from nothing
zen of Parmenides, may be appreciated as (‘DK’ B1). What exists has no temporal begin-
marshalling his extraordinary argumenta- ning, and thus, Melissus infers invalidly, it has
tive skills in support of his teacher’s extraor- no temporal end. Unlike Parmenides, Melissus
dinary doctrines. Plato’s Socrates prods describes eternal reality in temporal terms, as
him into confessing that his book defends existing in the past, present and future, not
Parmenides’ monism from his critics by dem- an eternal present. Melissus infers wildly and
onstrating that their pluralism yields even fallaciously from the eternity of what exists
more absurdities than Parmenides’ monism to its infinite magnitude, unlike Parmenides
(Prm. 128d). Zeno largely limits himself to who speaks of ‘being’ as limited in the shape
demonstrating the absurdities inherent in of a sphere. Where Parmenides gives no argu-
pluralism and locomotion. His arguments ment for monism, Melissus argues cleverly
against pluralism proceed by deducing from that the infinite extent of what is requires it to
its assumption of a pair of contradictory con- be one, because if two things existed they can-
sequences. For example, a plurality of objects not be infinite since they would have bounda-
entails that they be both limited in number ries upon one another. Further, since what is
and unlimited in number. If things are many is one it must be homogeneous, alike in every
they must be just as many as they are, and way, because otherwise it would form a plu-
thus they must be of a certain number. If rality. There can be no change of any sort, be
things are many, they are unlimited because it a change in quality, size or arrangement of
between any two objects there is a third, parts, because change would entail the com-
but similarly there must be objects between ing-into-existence of what did not exist and
the third object and the two it lies between, the passing away into nonexistence of what
and so on to infinity. Presumably, objects are had existed. Melissus uses the ‘empty’, or the
distinct only because another object sepa- void, which he identifies with ‘nothing’, to
rates them. The ‘stadium’ is the best known formulate a novel argument against locomo-
of Zeno’s arguments against locomotion. A tion. What there is is completely ‘full’, and
moving object must first arrive at the half- thus there is no place empty of what is that
way point to its goal before reaching its goal, would allow what is to move into it. Although
but before it arrives at the halfway point it Aristotle dismisses Melissus as an intellectual
must first arrive at the point halfway to the lightweight, he develops careful arguments,
initial halfway point, and so on to infinity. often clearly expressed, and he makes origi-
But no object may traverse in a finite time nal contributions to the Eleatic school.
infinite arrival points. Zeno’s argumentative Plato has profound respect for Parmenides,
dexterity prompted Aristotle to proclaim him whom his Socrates describes as ‘venerable and
the discoverer of ‘dialectic’ (D. L. 8.57), the awesome’ (Theaetetus 183e). Outstanding
argumentative style Socrates made famous. in Plato’s considerable debt to Parmenides
Melissus, who commanded the Samian fleet are his beliefs that thought and knowledge
that defeated the Athenians in 441, follows, require an existing object and that real-
but also deviates from, Parmenides. Reality ity is discovered not through sensation but
remains eternal, one, uniform and change- through thought alone. Plato’s transcendent
less. If what is should have come to be, then forms, which are beyond space and time,
previous to its existence it was nothing, but provide the basis of his metaphysics and

15

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 15 3/8/2001 5:13:04 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

epistemology, and, although Plato is commit- afresh as a logographer (or speechwriter) for
ted to a multitude of forms, in much of his others who were presenting cases in the law
exposition he conceives of them individually courts. We have six such speeches (including
after the fashion of Parmenides’ ‘being’, each one for a trial on Aegina), but Isocrates later
as being eternal, changeless and uniform in disavowed such forensic logographic activ-
nature (e.g. Phd. 78d–9a; Ti. 27a–d). But ity (Antidosis 15.36–7). The vast majority
when it comes to ‘non-being’ Plato cannot of the more than 100 extant speeches of the
follow Parmenides. Plato explicitly shuns Attic orators were written for the law courts,
‘non-being’ as the contrary of ‘being’ (Sph. however, so that ‘logography’ in general is
258e), and he reduces ‘is not’ to ‘differs from’ identified with them. In Plato (Phdr. 257c)
(Sph. 257b, 258d). and elsewhere (e.g. Demosthenes 58.19) the
For further information, see Barnes term ‘logographer’ is used disparagingly and
(1979), Gallop (1984), Guthrie (1969) and identified with forensic chicanery. Isocrates’
Mourelatos (1970). oeuvre actually contains several other genres
of written discourse, including letters and
epideictic speeches, as well as ‘speeches’, but
none of them were intended for oral delivery.
ISOCRATES AND LOGOGRAPHY Isocrates’ early educational programme
is revealed in his Against the Sophists (13),
David Mirhady which shares many of the commonplace crit-
At Phaedrus 278e–9b Phaedrus describes a icisms of the sophists that appear in Platonic
then youthful Isocrates (c. 436/5–338 BCE) dialogues: their unconcern for the truth, their
as a companion of Socrates. Socrates himself selfishness, their aim of gratifying rather than
then both characterizes Isocrates as nobler educating listeners, and their distrust of their
than Lysias and prophesies a great career for students (see Benoit 1991). It also reveals
him in philosophy. Since Isocrates and Plato Isocrates’ understanding of ‘philosophy’ – he
were contemporaries and headed the most never uses the term ‘rhetoric’ in reference to
well known philosophical schools in Athens his teaching. For Isocrates, philosophy entails
during the time, the temptation is very strong devotion to a career of political leadership,
to see the passage as ironic, Plato casting an particularly as that career involves engag-
implicit criticism at his rival. According to ing in political discourse, such as his own
this view, the Lysias who in the dialogue is so written ‘speeches’. Scholars such as De Vries
roundly criticized for the moral and intellec- (1953:39–40) have seen Platonic parody-
tual weakness of his logography actually rep- ing of Against the Sophists (13–18) in Phdr.
resents the historical Isocrates. Several works (268c and 269d), but not all are convinced.
from both Plato and Isocrates suggest such an More clearly, anti-Platonic views appear
ongoing rivalry. Since Isocrates was devoted in Isocrates’ mythological Encomium of
to written discourse, particularly logography, Helen. Isocrates criticizes those who believe
there is a fundamental difference between that there is a single epistêmê for courage,
him and Plato on the issue of writing (q.v.), wisdom and justice (Just. 10.1) and those
but there are other differences as well. who pretend to do elenchoi (4): ‘It is much
After his family fortune was wiped out better to conjecture reasonably about use-
in the Peloponnesian war, Isocrates began ful things than to have precise knowledge

16

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 16 3/8/2001 5:13:04 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

of what is useless’ (5, Trans. Mirhady). It is others’ works of the subject – Isocrates criti-
hard to avoid seeing Plato as the object of this cizes Gorgias’ Helen – and both make men-
criticism. The most recent commentary on tion of Stesichorus’ palinode.
Isocrates’ Busiris (Livingstone 2001:48–56), Aside from Plato and Isocrates, Alcidamas
unlike the more widely held view, stresses also addresses the issue of writing and log-
similarities between it and Plato’s Republic ography in his short polemic On Those Who
rather than the criticism. In both Helen Write Written Speeches, or On Sophists.
and Busiris Isocrates engages in the sophis- Scholars have debated the relative chronolo-
tic practises of paradoxical encomia and gies of Alcidamas’ essay and the works of
making the weaker argument the stronger, Plato and Isocrates without consensus (see
of praising the unpraiseworthy. Ever since O’Sullivan 1992:23–31). It could well be that
Homer’s Iliad Helen’s behaviour in going to Alcidamas is criticizing Isocrates, especially
Troy and abandoning her family was seen since the latter was so devoted to written
as irresponsible, and Busiris was generally composition. Alcidamas argues that a train-
characterized as a brutal Egyptian king who ing in ex tempore speaking will be superior
killed every Greek he could get his hands on to that for logography (see esp. 6 and 13).
until Heracles put an end to him. Isocrates’ In Isocrates’ epistemology doxa is approved
rehabilitation of Helen and Busiris seems as more practical than epistêmê, especially
part of a broader strategy to use mythologi- in decisions about the future (see Antidosis
cal examples as positive and not negative 15.271 and On the Peace 8.8). He appears,
lessons. Rather than rejecting and replacing however, not to criticize dialectic, acknowl-
traditional Greek mythology, as Plato does, edging that face-to-face communication is
Isocrates seeks to reform it, which would be best for many of the same reasons discussed
a dissimilarity between them. in Phdr. (Letter to Dionysius 2–3; Phdr.
Plato’s Gorgias clearly entails a thorough 274b–8b). He also seems to share Plato’s
critique of rhetorical teaching in general, but view of the sophist’s use of argumentative
it seems unlikely that the Gorgias of that dia- question and answer (Antid. 15.45; Sophist
logue represents Isocrates. In the dialogue, 225b–6a). For Isocrates the political aims of
Gorgias concedes that if his students do not Greek unity and Athenian hegemony were
have moral knowledge then they will acquire also almost inseparable from philosophy
it through association with him (Grg. 459c– (Panathenaicus 12.2). In his later writings,
60a4). Isocrates never makes this claim, however, he argues that Greek unity can best
although he does say that his training will be be achieved under the leadership of Athens’
an aid to acquiring moral knowledge (Against rival, Philip of Macedon (5. To Philip).
the Sophists 13.31; Antidosis 15.274, 278).
In the Phdr. Socrates argues that while writ-
ing speeches is not in itself a disgrace, writing
them badly is (Phdr. 258d). Inasmuch as the ORALITY AND LITERACY
theme of the speeches criticized by Socrates is
erotic desire, and Helen was the mythologi- Joanne B. Waugh
cal object of erotic desire, it seems possible Orality and literacy became topics relevant
that Plato was indirectly criticizing Isocrates’ to the study of Plato with the publication
Encomium. Both works include criticisms of of Eric Havelock’s Preface to Plato (1963).

17

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 17 3/8/2001 5:13:04 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

Havelock argued that Socrates attacked primary cultural and political occasion until
poetry in the Republic because from the well into the fourth century. This explains the
Greek Dark Ages, if not before, the archetype persistence of meter, verse and rhythmical
for Greek paideia (q.v. Education) had been prose, poetic and rhetorical language and tra-
oral poetry – poetry that singers composed ditional themes and fanciful stories in Greek
extemporaneously in performance, without texts and inscriptions – political, philosophi-
the aid of writing. The evidence for the exist- cal or legislative – from the advent of the
ence of such poetry in early Greece was pro- polis to its acme. Inscriptions of ‘state’ docu-
vided by Milman Parry’s analyses of Homeric ments on stone were found as early as the
epics, analyses that demonstrated how such late sixth-century BCE, but inscribing public
composition was possible. documents on stone did not become a regular
Oral composition-in-performance is a practise before the middle of the fifth century
means of preserving and communicating (Sickinger 1999:4; Thomas 1992:137). In any
culture. Human societies have existed with- case, an inference from the existence of stone
out literacy for much longer than they have inscriptions to a substantial body of writers
existed with it. The burden of proof rests not and readers and the material culture to sup-
with those who assert that early Greek soci- port literacy is problematic. Written inscrip-
ety was an oral culture, but with anyone who tions often function as symbolic objects
claims that it was a literate one. Making this the meanings of which are not confined to
claim is complicated by the fact that views the words inscribed, and thus have signifi-
of what constitutes a literate society differ cance even for those who cannot read them
markedly. At one extreme, a society is deemed (Thomas 1992:74–100). Still, the creations
literate if a majority of adults can write and and uses of written documents proliferated
read their names. At the other, a society is during the fifth century, and in its closing dec-
considered literate if (a) it relies on written ade the Athenians established the Metroön as
texts to preserve and to transmit its cultural a repository for some or all state documents
traditions and to conduct matters of govern- (Sickinger 1999:1–3; Thomas 1992:143).
ment, commerce, inquiry and law; (b) to be a Only in the fourth century, however, did writ-
functioning member of that society one must ten documents cease to be supplementary
be able to read and write fluently; and (c) it and subordinate to oral testimony, and begin
has a sufficiently robust material culture to to be accepted as proof in the courts (Robb
support these practises, including educating 1994:139–41; Thomas 1992:89 ff., 148 ff.).
its citizens and workers. What evidence we The extent and limits of classical literacy are
possess does not make it easy to determine summed up by Harris, who observes that ‘the
the extent to which the Greeks during the notion that every citizen male should know
classical period were literate. how to read and write made its appearance
Alphabetic writing was introduced into during the classical period of Greek culture,
Greece in the eighth-century BCE (Carpenter but came nowhere near to realization even
1933) and after a time performers began to use in Athens’ (1989:114). He concludes that for
fixed texts. From the archaic until the classical the period in question, the per cent of liter-
periods, writing was used more widely and in ates among the population of Attica as whole
the service of the polis, but the public perform- probably lies in the range of 5–10 per cent
ance of artfully composed speech remained a (1989:114).

18

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 18 3/8/2001 5:13:04 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

Thus we find rhapsodes continuing to alphabetic writing was sufficient for the
recite – indeed, perform – fixed texts in the emergence of Greek philosophy rather than
classical period, especially those purporting necessary.
to be the whole or part of Homer’s Iliad or Still, with a few notable exceptions such as
Odyssey (cf. Ion). In the R. Socrates com- Robb (1994), the importance of orality and
ments on Homer’s popularity and impor- literacy to the study of Plato has not been
tance, pointing out that some will claim that as widely recognized among contemporary
Homer and the tragic poets know all about philosophers as it should be, the result of the
technical matters, human conduct and reli- widespread but waning practise of ‘ration-
gion (598d10–e2) and the admirers of Homer ally reconstructing’ arguments alleged to
say ‘Homer educated Hellas’ and that on be implicit in texts from the history of phi-
matters of conduct he should be studied as losophy. These arguments need not take into
a guide by which one regulates one’s whole account the historical and sociocultural con-
life (606e2–7). According to Havelock, the text of a text’s author and audience, the occa-
persistence of these public performances of sion and medium of its presentation and the
artful speech was what Plato found objec- choice to write – and to read – philosophy
tionable. The rhythm on the levels of syn- in a particular way. Absent such considera-
tax, diction, actions and events, the vivid tions, philosophers from any period can be
and memorable imagery and the compelling read as formulating doctrines on perennial
narratives of anthropomorphic gods and philosophical problems.
heroes – the very things that made the speech When history and context are taken
artful and the performances memorable for into account, the resulting interpretations
their audiences – developed in them habits may differ greatly from conventional ones.
of mind inimical to philosophical modes of Consider passages in the Phaedrus (274b6–
thought. Philosophical modes of thought, 8e2) and in the Epistles (7.341b2–5;
Havelock argued, are developed as writing 2.314b10–c6) that are sometimes cited as
and reading permit and encourage reflection relevant to discussions of orality and liter-
on, and analysis of, the language and content acy. Socrates’ remarks about writing in the
of traditional explanations. Phdr. have been taken to refer to writing
Questions about how, when and why simpliciter, but a strong case has been made
ancient Greece moved from being a society that Socrates is referring to the technai of
that relied on oral performance in transmit- the sophists, an innovative form of paideia
ting culture to one that employed writing that rivals Plato’s own (Cole 1991:123). The
and reading in many of its cultural affairs are passages in Ep. 2 and 7, from which some
now central to classical scholarship. These readers conclude that Plato never committed
studies contest general claims about orality his philosophical views to writing yet sub-
and literacy per se identified at various times scribed to philosophical doctrines intimated
with Havelock, Jack Goody and Walter Ong in the dialogues, look different when viewed
as technologies of the intellect, but for the in relation to other artful speech of Plato’s
most part support Havelock’s specific claims day. The statements from these letters under-
about the oral poetic tradition in Greece and score that the point of the dialogues is not to
its gradual acquisition of literacy. Current present philosophical doctrines but to teach
scholarship provides reasons to doubt that their audience philosophia, thereby replacing

19

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 19 3/8/2001 5:13:04 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

other artfully composed speech that for so Thanks to the Muses, the goddesses of
long had constituted Greek paideia. poetry, the poet sings human and divine
deeds. Despite the doubtful etymological
relation between muse and memory, there
is an acknowledged parentage between
POETRY (EPIC AND LYRIC) the muse and memory and the song and
memory: Pindar conceives of memory as
Catherine Collobert the mirror of fine deeds (Nemean 7.14–15).
Epic and lyric poetry, which flourished in the The Muses’ omniscience and omnipres-
archaic period (eighth-century BCE to fifth- ence (Homer, Il. II.485) are imparted to the
century BCE), is often quoted, referred to or poet who has, therefore, access to the past
discussed in Plato’s dialogues. and possesses a universal and divine knowl-
Hesiod (Theogony, Works and Days, Shield edge. The divine gift of poetry does not only
of Herakles) is more or less a contemporary allow the poet to transmit knowledge to his
of Solon and Archilochus (seventh-century audience but also gives pleasure. According
BCE). Ancient Greek poetry, especially epic, to Hesiod, Zeus created poetry first for his
has to be understood in the context of oral own pleasure (Theog. 37, 51), and second, to
tradition, which shaped the epics in vari- grant mankind ‘a forgetting of ills and a rest
ous ways. The most significant is that oral from sorrows’ (55) and lighten their suffer-
composition is based upon a formula, which ings (98–9). Regarding themselves as masters
allows for improvization. Moreover, a salient of both truth and pleasure, the poets did not
feature is performance: poetry is a perform- consider these two ends to be incompatible
ance rather than a ‘text’. Parts of the epic because pleasure does not necessarily address
cycle, the Iliad and the Odyssey, whose poet the irrational part of the soul, as Plato has it
was taken to be Homer, were sung by bards (Republic 603a–c, 605a–7b).
and later rhapsodes, as Plato describes them The invocation of the Muses does not
in the Ion, in the context of festivals like the lead the poet to consider himself as merely
festival of the Panathenaia in Athens. a mouthpiece of the divine. Even though the
Epic poetry introduces itself as poetry of invocation is a kind of inspiration (Od. 8.499;
the past, that is, the Heroic Age: the kleea Theog. 33) it does not equate with possession
proteron anthropon (Theogony 100), that is (q.v. Madness and Possession), contrary to
to say, the heroes of the Trojan war and their Plato’s claim in Ion and Phaedrus. The equa-
return, as in the Iliad and the Odyssey, and tion allows him to deprive the poet not only
the very beginnings of the cosmos, as in the of a technê but also of knowledge. Possessed,
Theog. However, the Homeric epics were not that is, under the spell of the divine and ‘out
regarded as historical reports and they con- of his mind’, the poet is in an irrational state
tain a mixture of elements from different time of mind, contributing nothing to his poetry.
periods. Yet, the song is not only a celebration However, although the human and the divine
of the past but also of the future (Theog. 31) parts in the making of the song are not clearly
and the present. According to the poet of the distinguished, the poet acknowledges a kind
Hymn to Apollo, the song bears on the gods’ of autonomy through the common idea that
happiness and the miserable state of human the Muses teach the poet (Od. 8.481, 8.487,
affairs (Hymn to Apollo 190–3). 17.518; Solon, 1.51–2; Th. 22; Hesiod,

20

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 20 3/8/2001 5:13:05 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

Works and Days 662). Divine inspiration (sixth-century BCE) could be the target of
does not deprive the poet of a poetic skill Plato according to whom the poet gives an
(Od. 14.131), contrary to what Plato claims inconsistent view on virtue in his Elegies
(Ion). Pindar speaks of an inventive ability (Men. 95d–6a). Inconsistency is one of
(eumachania) that prevents him from being Plato’s favourite criticisms against the poets
merely the follower of Homer (Pythian (e.g. Lg. 719c).
7b8–20). Comparing the poet with a seer, The sayings of lyric poets are considered
Pindar tells us that the skill consists chiefly to be wise and true by various characters in
of interpreting the Muses’ sayings. He thus the dialogues and, in consequence, are sub-
makes the art of the poet an art of interpre- jected to Socrates’ elenchus, as in the case of
tation (Snell P. 6.6, f. 94a5, f. 150), which Simonides in R. bk 1 and Protagoras. Plato
is under attack in Ion (535a). The broad maintains on the one hand that poetry con-
range of topics that poetry embraces makes sists of an illusory, dangerous and deceitful
it a kind of encyclopaedia, especially the Il. art, and on the other hand, that it is the prod-
and the Od. (see Plato, R. 606e2; Xenophon, uct of ignorance. However, even though lyric
Symposium 3–6). Plato’s critique of Homer’s poetry is banished from the ideal city along
and the poets’ alleged polymathia leads him with epic, it is not, like Homer and to a lesser
to condemn their role in education. Poetry extent Hesiod, the main target of Plato’s
conveys a certain ethical insight whose val- attacks. The reason may be that Homer, as
ues, for the most part Homeric, are called ‘the best of the poets’, embodies par excel-
into question on account of their detrimen- lence the figure of poetic authority against
tal consequences (R. bk 3). Heroes are poor which Plato wages war (R. 606e–7a).
models whose imitation perverts the soul.
However, this critique of the heroic posture
is not only Plato’s but also that of the lyric
poets, though the perspective is very different PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHERS
in each case. Lyric poetry (iambic, melic and
elegiac poetry) is centred on the individual J. H. Lesher
and the present, and expresses itself in the Plato refers frequently to the views held by
first person. Archilochus rejects the Homeric earlier thinkers, typically while lining up wit-
idealized hero and his search for kleos – nesses for or against a philosophical thesis.
Simonides of Ceos and Hipponax depict the His characters speak approvingly of the doc-
triviality and poverty of life. However, hark- trines of Parmenides and the Pythagoreans
ing back to Homer, the last representatives but repudiate in the strongest terms the
of lyric poetry like Bacchylides and Pindar teachings of ‘atheistic materialists’ – think-
define poetry as an art of immortalization. ers such as the Milesian inquirers into nature
By bestowing fame on mortals who no we today regard as the founders of Western
longer accomplish warlike deeds but only philosophy and science. The chief failings of
athletic ones, the poet gives them immortal- the materialists were not acknowledging the
ity. Whether or not it is a criticism of hero- priority of soul over matter and not believ-
ism, lyric poetry does not renounce the aim ing that a cosmic intelligence has arranged all
of conveying a moral message and content. things for the best. On occasion Plato states
This is why the poet Theognis of Megara a view held by a thinker he has elsewhere

21

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 21 3/8/2001 5:13:05 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

criticized and he is not above borrowing the different terms (cf. B16 and Lg. 10.889e) and
ideas of others without identifying his source. that god ‘shakes all things by the thought of
Thus, while Plato’s dialogues are an invalu- his mind’ (B25) but is otherwise uninvolved
able source of information for the views of in human affairs (see further, Lesher 1992).
earlier thinkers, his representations must be Pythagoras of Samos appears only once
read with caution. in the dialogues, when (at R. 10.600a) Plato
Plato’s Thales is the familiar combination identifies him as ‘the founder of a way of life’.
of scientific inquirer (Theaetetus 174a) and But Philebus 16d alludes to a ‘Prometheus
practical sage (Hippias Major 281c; Epistle like figure’ who taught that ‘all things consist
2.311a; Protagoras 343a; Republic 10.600a). of a one and many, and have in their nature a
Thales is also credited with the view that ‘all conjunction of limit and unlimited’ and that
things are full of gods’ (Laws 10.899b), which ‘we must go from one form to look for two, if
exempted him from the indictments of mate- the case admits of this, otherwise for three or
rialist cosmologies levelled in the Epinomis some other number of forms’. Although the
(988b) and Lg. bk 10 (886e). The story of evidence relating to ancient Pythagoreanism
Thales and the serving girl (Tht. 174a) sug- (q.v. Pythagoreanism) is often unreliable,
gests that Plato saw Thales as a prototype of it seems certain that at some point Plato
the philosopher whose inquiries expose him became enamoured of Pythagorean doctrine.
to public ridicule and scorn. His most extensive account of the physical
At Sophist 242d Plato presents Xenophanes cosmos is presented by Timaeus, an imagi-
of Colophon as one of the early thinkers who nary Pythagorean statesman and scientist. In
affirmed that ‘all things are one’, but else- the R. he describes the study of mathemat-
where Plato follows Xenophanes’ lead on ics as essential preparation for philosophical
a number of points. For example, the pro- dialectic and an essential component in the
posal to censor poetic depictions of the gods training of the guardians (Ti. 536d). His tri-
put forward in R. bk 10 echoes sentiments partite view of the soul echoes a Pythagoras
Xenophanes expressed in fragments ‘DK’ B1, anecdote about the three kinds of lives
11, 12 and 22; the call at Apology 36e and (Diogenes Laertius 8.8). The simile of the
R. 5.465d to honour the city’s wise counsel- divided line in R. bk 6 (q.v.) embodies the
lors more than victorious athletes tracks the same fourfold progression Pythagoras’ fol-
language of Xenophanes B 3; and the dis- lowers identified as the tetractys their master
tinction between knowledge and true opin- had passed down to their generation (Aëtius
ion (endorsed at Men. 98a and elsewhere) I, 3, 8). Plato’s definition of justice assumes
appears first in Xenophanes B34. Plato’s the conception of harmony described by the
unwillingness to acknowledge his indebt- Pythagorean Philolaus of Croton (‘DK’ 44,
edness to Xenophanes may derive from B6). These and other points of contact clearly
Xenophanes’ endorsement of the kind of indicate that Plato knew and embraced many
materialist view (B27 and 29) the Athenian of the Pythagorean doctrines of his own era
of Lg. bk 10 claimed warranted a minimum (see Huffman 1993).
of 5 years of solitary confinement or the Plato credited Heraclitus of Ephesus with
death penalty (Lg. 909). Plato might also the mistaken (indeed, self-defeating) doctrine
have disliked Xenophanes’ claim that people of ‘flux’ or ‘radical change’, that is, that all
in different regions conceive of the gods in things are changing in all respects all the

22

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 22 3/8/2001 5:13:05 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

time (Cratylus 401d, 402a, 411b; Phlb. 43a; or is destroyed. Moreover, since knowledge
Tht. 152e, 160d, 177c). But the most likely must be a secure possession, it must have as
basis for Plato’s interpretation – the ‘river its objects things that remain forever in pos-
fragments’ ‘DK’ B12, 49a and 91b – can be session of their attributes, which can only be
read instead as affirming the unity of the the Forms or Ideas we apprehend in thought
opposites and the measured character of all (see further, Palmer 1999 and q.v. Eleatics).
change (see Kirk 1954). Moreover, at least Plato refers frequently to doctrines associ-
one aspect of Heraclitean reality remained ated with Empedocles of Akragas, but with
exempt from change, namely the logos that little approval. At Men. 76c Socrates draws
‘holds forever’ (B1). Plato also expressed on an Empedoclean theory of ‘effluences’
contempt for Heraclitus’ aphorism-spouting to define colour but disparages the result-
followers (Tht. 180) and accused him of fail- ing definition as ‘pompous’. At Tht. 152e
ing to understand his own doctrine of oppo- Socrates includes Empedocles among the ear-
sites (Symposium 187a). But Plato concurred lier thinkers who mistakenly thought that all
in many other aspects of Heraclitus’ phi- things are in the process of becoming. Phd.
losophy. Plato held that the doctrine of flux 96b contains what is probably a reference to
holds true for all things located in the sensi- Empedocles’ view of blood as the medium of
ble realm, including human beings (cf. Smp. thought (‘DK’ A30, 86 and 97). Timaeus 48b
207d). The Stranger at Sph. 242d has no introduces a geometrical improvement on
difficulty in attributing to a ‘certain Ionian the Empedoclean doctrine of ‘roots’ (B6 and
muse’ the view that ‘the real is both many A30). And the Sph. alludes to ‘a certain muse
and one and is held together by enmity and in Sicily’ who held that ‘the real is both many
friendship [and that] in parting asunder it is and one and held together by enmity and
always being drawn together’. In addition, at friendship’ (Sph. 242d, 243a; cf. B26). But
Phaedo 65a and R. 6.508 Plato indicts the Plato appears to have shared Empedocles’
senses as unsuitable sources of knowledge, conception of philosophy as a guide to life as
much as Heraclitus had indicted ‘eyes and well as his view of the present life as merely
ears as bad witnesses’ (‘DK’ B107). The con- one stage in the soul’s long journey (cf. B111
trast of sleeping with waking, a leitmotif in and 115 with the myth of Er in R. bk 10).
many of the surviving Heraclitus fragments, Plato credited Anaxagoras of Clazomenae
became one of Plato’s favourite themes. with four doctrines: that the sun and moon
Parmenides of Elea (q.v. Eleatics) provided are not gods but merely stone and earth
Plato with both the terminology and philo- (Apology 26d), that the moon receives its light
sophical foundations for two key doctrines in from the sun (Cratylus 409b), that ‘all things
his philosophy: a dualistic metaphysics and are together’ (Gorgias 465d; Phd. 72c) and
rationalist theory of knowledge (cf. Diotima’s that ‘Mind produces order and is the cause of
description of Beauty Itself at Smp. 211a, the everything’ ( Cra. 413c, 400a; Lg. 10.886d,
linking of knowledge with being at R. 5.476, 12.967b; Phd. 98b). In the Phd. Socrates
and the denigration of sense perception in the faults Anaxagoras for failing to stick to his
simile of the divided line at R. 6.508–11). On hypothesis that the Mind orders all things,
the Parmenidean-Platonic view, ‘what is’ can- resorting instead to causes such as ‘air, aether,
not fail to be in any way, and therefore never water, and many other absurdities’ (Phd.
changes, moves, is divided, comes into being 98c). In ‘DK’ B12, however, Anaxagoras

23

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 23 3/8/2001 5:13:05 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

speaks of Mind as ‘itself’ and ‘all by itself’ 1992c) make only a few, mostly passing, ref-
(auto and eph’ eautou), phrases Plato will erences to Pythagoreanism, thus suggesting
employ in characterizing the Forms or Ideas that Plato is explicable with little mention of
(cf. Ti. 51b8). Anaxagoras would certainly the Pythagoreans.
have been among those ‘earlier thinkers’ Plato refers explicitly to Pythagoras and
praised in the Philebus for affirming ‘that the Pythagoreans only once each. Many
reason and a marvellous organizing intelli- scholars think, however, that a single sen-
gence (noun kai phronêsin) pilot the whole tence from the Metaphysics indicates that
universe’ (Phd. 28d). Aristotle thought Plato heavily indebted to
The fact that the names of the founders Pythagoreanism. In the survey of his prede-
of atomic theory, Leucippus and Democritus, cessors, Aristotle asserts that Plato’s philoso-
appear nowhere in Plato’s writings provides phy ‘agrees with these men in most respects’
some measure of his animosity towards (987a29–31). Although many see ‘these men’
materialist cosmologies. The possibility that as the Pythagoreans, the context, suggests the
reality consisted entirely of material bod- reference is to all the pre-Socratics (Huffman
ies jostling about in empty space, and that 2008). Moreover, Aristotle explains Plato’s
events could be fully accounted for in terms central achievement in metaphysics, the
of physical causes, were ideas Plato regarded theory of forms, in terms of the combined
as anathema. So, when (at Ti. 53 ff.) Plato influence of Socrates and Heracliteans
offers his own theory of matter his geometri- (Metaphysics 987a32–b10, 1078b12–30),
cal ‘atoms’ are so richly endowed with aes- without mention of the Pythagoreans. It is
thetic, moral, and mathematical properties as with principles that are even more fundamen-
to hardly count as material bodies at all. The tal than forms that he sees the closest con-
silent treatment Plato gave to the atomists nection between Plato and Pythagoreanism.
provides a useful reminder that his represen- Even here he stresses differences. Plato’s
tations of the views held by his predeces- one and indefinite dyad correspond to the
sors were neither disinterested nor entirely Pythagoreans’ limit and unlimited, but Plato
dispassionate. separates his principles from the physical
world, while the Pythagoreans identify theirs
with it. Plato also replaces the unlimited with
the indefinite dyad.
PYTHAGOREANS Plato’s sparse references to the
Pythagoreans are in accord with Aristotle’s
Carl A. Huffman presentation. The sole reference to Pythagoras
Some have thought that the Pythagoreans (Republic 600b) is positive and indicates that
played a powerful role in shaping Platonic Plato thought of him as a private educator
thought (Guthrie 1975:35). In late antiquity, who left behind a way of life. There is no
Plato could be presented as a member of the suggestion of any close connection to or ven-
Pythagorean School (Photius 438b17). The eration for Pythagoras. The single reference
evidence suggests, however, that Pythagorean to the Pythagoreans (R. 530d) praises them
influence on Plato has been considerably for treating harmonics and astronomy as
exaggerated. Indeed, recent overviews of sister sciences but criticizes them for looking
Plato’s philosophy (e.g. Benson 2006; Kraut for numbers in heard harmonies rather than

24

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 24 3/8/2001 5:13:05 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

ascending to problems and treating numbers was always thinking of Pythagoreans when
apart from sensibles (R. 531c). he mentioned it.
Plato’s clearest nonexplicit reference to the Other aspects of Plato’s account of the fate
Pythagoreans is found at Philebus 16c–17a. of the soul are even less securely traced to
Socrates describes a method that ‘was hurled Pythagoreanism. The unnamed ‘wise’ man
down from the gods by some Prometheus who teaches (Grg. 493a) that we are dead in
along with fire’ and that men before his this life and that the body (sôma) is the tomb
time adopted. This method regards limit (sêma) of the soul is not Orphic; the Orphics
and unlimited as inherent in all things and are assigned a competing view at Cratylus
knowledge as arising when we grasp the pre- 400c. He might be a Pythagorean, but later
cise number that applies to each thing. In the sources also point to Heraclitus (Dodds
later tradition, where Pythagoras becomes 1959:300). The Sicilian or Italian mytholo-
the source of all philosophical wisdom, this gizer mentioned in the same passage, who
Prometheus was inevitably identified with made the soul a leaky jar, is also not likely to
Pythagoras. Nothing in Plato’s reference to be a Pythagorean. Nor is it true that, when-
Pythagoras in the R., however, suggests that ever Socrates refers to ‘the wise’, he is refer-
he saw him as a divine figure and it is likely ring to the Pythagoreans (Burkert 1972:78
that Plato was simply referring to a revised correcting Dodds 1959:297). The wise man
Prometheus, who hurled down the method of R. (583b; cf. Phlb. 44b), who regards pleas-
along with fire as gifts to humanity (Huffman ure as unreal is not a Pythagorean as Adam
1999). The men before our time who adopt (1902:378); suggested he was Pythagoreans
the method are undoubtedly Pythagoreans. distrusted pleasure but regarded it as all too
Aristotle explicitly identifies limit, unlim- real (Huffman 2005:323–37). The ‘wise men
ited and number as basic principles of the and women’ of Men. (81a), who are ‘priests
Pythagoreans and these principles are also and priestesses who have made it their con-
found in the fragments of Philolaus. cern to given an account of their practices’
Pythagorean influence appears earlier in are likely to be Orphics or others engaged in
Plato’s career in two areas, the fate of the soul mysteries, since Pythagoreans are not called
and mathematics (Kahn 2001:3–4). Vivid priests in our sources. Women did have a
accounts of the judgement and reincarnation prominent role in Pythagoreanism, but they
of the soul, which appear abruptly in Gorgias, were also initiated into the Bacchic mysteries
Meno, Phaedo and R. are often traced to (Burkert 1985:294). The view that all nature
Pythagorean influence arising from his visit is akin (Men. 81d) may be a Platonic adap-
to Italy and Sicily in 387 BCE. Pythagoras tion of the Pythagorean view that all animate
was perhaps the first to introduce the doctrine creatures are related (Dicaearchus Fr. 40,
of metempsychosis into Greece (Dicaearchus Mirhady).
Fr. 40 Mirhady). It was, however, also found The Phd. is peopled by Pythagoreans such
in Orphism, in Empedocles and possibly in as Philolaus and Echecrates, but Plato does
Bacchic rites (Burkert 1985:294; Burkert not call them Pythagoreans and is not sim-
1987:87). At Laws 870d–e, Plato presents it ply presenting Pythagorean views. Socrates
as something taught in religious initiations assigns the theory that the body is a prison,
(teletai), which suggests Orphic or Bacchic in which the soul is undergoing punish-
practises. It is, thus, far from clear that Plato ment from which it should not escape by

25

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 25 3/8/2001 5:13:05 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

suicide (Phd. 62c), to the mysteries and not was Pythagorean. The southern Italian who
to Philolaus. The Pythagorean idea that the gives his name to Plato’s Timaeus, has been
soul is a harmony is heavily criticized (Phd. thought to represent Archytas. The situa-
86b; see Huffman 1993:328; Huffman tion is not so simple. The construction of the
2009). To argue that the Phd. myth follows world soul relies on the mathematics of the
a Pythagorean source in the smallest details Pythagorean diatonic scale, but it is the scale
(Kingsley 1995:79–171) is implausible, since used by Philolaus not Archytas. Moreover,
the supposed Pythagorean source has not sur- features of the cosmology of the Ti. are in
vived. There may be Pythagorean elements in direct conflict with Pythagoreanism. Archytas
the Grg. myth, but Dodds shows that it draws argued that the universe was unlimited in
on a great variety of sources. Plato’s typical extent (Huffman 2005:540), whereas Plato’s
transformation of his sources is clear in the universe has a limit. Philolaus makes the
case of metempsychosis. He borrows the idea earth a planet orbiting around a central fire.
that the soul goes through a series of rebirths, Plato, like Philolaus, apparently has a spheri-
remembering things encountered previous to cal earth, but it is firmly in the centre. The
this existence. His theory of recollection grafts moral cosmology of the Phd. and R. myths,
onto this religious idea – the distinctly Platonic and the conception of a heavenly music in
notion of a separation between an intelligible the latter, owe something to Pythagoras’ own
world of forms and the sensible world. What cosmology and to Philolaus’ description of
we recollect is our encounter with the forms the cosmos as a harmony (Huffman 2010).
in a disembodied state, whereas Pythagoras At Grg. 507e, the Pythagoreans are undoubt-
only claimed to remember his previous physi- edly included among ‘the wise’, who say that
cal incarnations. As an epistemological doc- heaven and earth are held together by friend-
trine, the doctrine of recollection owes very ship, order and justice and hence call the
little to Pythagoreanism. whole a kosmos (order), although Empedocles
Similarly, mere mention of mathemat- and Anaximander are probably included as
ics is no indication that Plato is drawing on well. Pythagoras’ invention of the word kos-
Pythagoreanism. Rigorous mathematics is mos is a later fabrication (Burkert 1972:77).
Greek rather than specifically Pythagorean. Socrates’ warning to Callicles that he is ignor-
The most prominent mathematicians in the ing mathematical proportion (Politicus 508a)
dialogues, Theodorus and Theaetetus, are may be an allusion to Archytas (Huffman
not Pythagoreans. In R. bk 7, although aware 2005:208–11); in the Plt. (284e) ‘the clever
of Archytas’ achievements in mathemat- who say that measure is concerned with all
ics (Huffman 2005:385–401), Plato finds things’ could be Pythagoreans, although the
its value in the ability to turn the soul from passage is problematic. In all these cases, how-
the sensible to the intelligible realm, while ever, as in the Ti., while Plato borrows spe-
he criticizes the Pythagoreans for locating cific aspects of Pythagoreanism, he integrates
numbers in sensible things. Part of the termi- them into a system that is distinctly Platonic
nology used to describe the nuptial number and often profoundly un-Pythagorean. With
(R. 546c; cf. sunêkooi at Lg. 711e (Burkert the exception of Plato’s later theory of prin-
1972:84)) is drawn from Pythagorean ciples, Pythagoreanism was just one among
sources (Huffman 2005:439–42), but there many influences on Plato rather than being
is no reason to think that the number itself central to his development.

26

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 26 3/8/2001 5:13:06 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

RHETORIC AND SPEECHMAKING Troy against any blame she carries for leav-
ing Sparta with Paris and causing the Trojan
Richard Marback War. Gorgias claims Helen could have been
The term rhêtorikê, or rhetoric, understood persuaded to go with Paris in four ways: by
as the art of using words to persuade others the gods, by force, by love or through speech.
in assemblies and courts of law, first appears The first three means of persuasion – divine
in Plato’s Gorgias. The term is a derivation intervention, physical force and the passion
of an older, commonly used word for poli- of love – are, according to Gorgias, irresist-
ticians who spoke in assemblies and courts, ible, and so leave Helen innocent of acting in
rhêtôr. The speeches given by politicians in a blameworthy manner. The fourth means by
assemblies were deliberative. Speeches given which she may have been persuaded, speech,
in courts of law were judicial (see Schiappa is also irresistible, and so Helen is again
1991:39–58). In Grg., rhetoric is used to found to be not blameworthy. The persuasive
refer less to the practises of giving speeches power of speech is irresistible because
in assemblies and courts of law and more
to the art of teaching others to deliver such The effect of speech upon the condition
speeches. The passage where the term rhê- of the soul is comparable to the power of
torikê first appears is one in which Socrates drugs over the nature of bodies. For just
as different drugs dispel different secre-
is questioning Gorgias about the identity of
tions from the body, so also in the case
his art and the associated nature of the wis-
of speeches, some distress, others delight,
dom he professes to teach. The conclusions some cause fear, others make the hearer
of the dialogue – that rhetoric is like cookery bold, and some drug and bewitch the
in that both are arts of flattery, gratification soul with a kind of evil persuasion (14,
and indulgence, at the same time the soph- trans. Kennedy 1963).
ist is like the tyrant in that both possess the
power to do what they please but lack the In this passage the word for speech is logos
wisdom to know and do what is best – are (q.v.), a general term that denotes word or
cynical conclusions about the roles of rheto- speech or language as well as principle or
ric and speechmaking in civic life. Many were reason. Here Gorgias would seem to be say-
sceptical about the teaching of speechmaking, ing through his comparison to drugs that the
worried about the potential created for insin- effects of speech on souls is less a consequence
cerity. At the same time, rhetoric and the art of the idea communicated and more a result
of speechmaking did contribute to Athenian of the language of the idea’s communication.
democracy by standardizing competence and Expressing the persuasive and, at least in
encouraging scepticism (see further, Guthrie this case, deceptive power of words over the
1971a; also Poulakos 1995:11–46). We get a soul through appeal to magic and the effects
broader sense of the ancient Greek art of per- of drugs on bodies is no mere flourish or
suading through speeches by turning directly imagery. As far back as the oral culture of
to the words of the sophist Gorgias himself. the Homeric tradition speech was consid-
In ‘Encomium of Helen’, Gorgias dis- ered a divine gift. To speak well was to be
plays his flair for language at the same time inspired as well as inspiring. Not only could
as he delves into the mysterious power of epic poets be inspired and inspiring speakers,
words. The speech is a defence of Helen of speechmaking itself was a prevalent feature

27

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 27 3/8/2001 5:13:06 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

in epic poetry as well as in the later tragedies than persuasive. Such is the view often found
(Kennedy 1994:11–29). As Gorgias remarks, in the dialogues of Plato, portraying rhetoric
poetry is speech with meter and if poetry and speechmaking as deceptive and so as an
could be understood as speech with meter, illicit drug that contributes to the diseases
then speech could draw on the stylistics of of soul and to the state instead of to their
poetry to exert influence over the emotions health and well-being. Although Socrates
and perceptions of an audience. Conscious himself sometimes gives speeches and seems
arrangement of rhythm and meter could to envisage a proper philosophic rhetoric in
drug and trick the souls of an audience by the Phdr., for Plato the speaking that cured
compelling emotional responses that confuse, souls was to be had less in speechmaking and
overwhelm and manipulate the limitations of more in the give and take of dialogue. The
human memory, understanding and foresight tension between dialogue and speechmaking
(de Romilly 1975:3–22). reflects the question of how best to establish
The persuasive power of a speech, then, is through language the bonds of philosophical
visceral. The sounds of words were experi- friendship that hold people together in socie-
enced and understood as more than auditory ties. An art of rhetoric that had as its explicit
representations communicating ideas to dis- goal a training in the making of speeches
embodied intellects. The soul and body were which could have therapeutic effects on state
inextricably intertwined. We need only recall and soul was a later historical development,
from Phaedrus (246–54) Plato’s myth of the most fully articulated after Plato by Aristotle
charioteer of the soul to get a sense of the close (see further, Nussbaum 1994).
relationships among reason, moral sentiments
and irascible appetites. Words were indeed
magical as well as medicinal. Words could and
did quicken the heart, steel the nerves, inflame SOCRATES (HISTORICAL)
or extinguish the passions and mesmerize the
soul. People are susceptible to the persuasive William Prior
and deceptive power of speeches because they
are by nature social creatures vulnerable to, (I) LIFE
and dependent on, each other.
With the realization that, through an art Socrates, one of the greatest philosophers
of rhetoric, they could manipulate words in of the ancient Greek world and for several
ways that ‘drug and trick the soul’, sophists ancient schools an exemplar of what the
recognized the potential power to be had philosophical life should be, was an Athenian
over the souls of others through the deliv- citizen born in 469 BCE. He was the son of
ery of carefully crafted speeches. Teaching Sophroniscus, a stonecutter, and Phaenarete,
the powerful art of speechmaking, sophists a midwife; and he was married to Xanthippe,
taught the deliberative and judicial speak- with whom he had three children (Phaedo
ing that became increasingly important to 60a, 116a–b). His adult years coincided
the political functioning of ancient Athenian with the ‘Golden Age’ of Athens, and he was
democracy. Of course such an education present during Athens’ decline and fall during
could not but run the risk of being seen by the Peloponnesian War (431–404). Socrates
more traditional thinkers as more deceptive was a public figure during at least part of this

28

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 28 3/8/2001 5:13:06 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

period: the comic playwright Aristophanes particular, Plato’s uncle Critias and his cousin
made him the target of his play the Clouds Charmides). Even more important may
(423; later revised). His odd physical appear- have been his association with Alcibiades,
ance and his way of life made him a ready a highly controversial Athenian political
target for the comic poets. Socrates served as leader, though a democratic one. Alcibiades
a hoplite (a heavy-armed infantryman) in at and Socrates had an erotic relationship,
least three of Athens’ military campaigns in comically described by Alcibiades in Plato’s
the Peloponnesian War (at Potideia in 429 Smp. (217a–19d; see also, Alcibiades I and
BCE, Delium in 424 BCE and Amphipolis Protagoras). Socrates’ status as the leading
in 422 BCE). Plato notes his courage dur- intellectual in Athens and as a central figure
ing the retreat from Delium (Laches 181b; in the intellectual revolution that took place
Symposium 221a). in the latter half of the fifth century doubt-
lessly aroused antipathy among many jurors.
(II) PHILOSOPHICAL ACTIVITY
(IV) THE SOCRATIC PROBLEM
Socrates seems to have spent most of his
time in the agora, the public market place, The above information is generally accepted
discussing philosophy. He denied that he concerning Socrates. He examined others in
was a teacher, and he did not accept pay as public as well as in private and he discussed
did numerous other thinkers of the day, but ethics. The Socratic dialogue form presum-
he did attract a coterie of young followers, ably reflects the dialectical activity of the his-
most importantly including Xenophon and torical Socrates. Beyond this, it is difficult to
Plato. Several of these followers made contri- be certain what, if anything, Socrates believed
butions to the Socratic literature, dialogues or taught or what kind of person he was. The
written with Socrates as the central figure problem is that we have four early sources:
(Kahn 1996:1–35). Except for the writings Aristophanes, Aristotle, Plato and Xenophon,
of Xenophon and Plato, however, only frag- and they do not always agree. Three of these
ments of their works remain. sources were contemporaries of Socrates
who knew him personally (Aristophanes,
(III) TRIAL Plato and Xenophon); the other was a mem-
ber of Plato’s Academy who had access to eye
In 399 Socrates was brought to trial on witness accounts of Socrates (Aristotle). The
charges of impiety (lit. ‘not believing in the discrepancies among our sources have pro-
gods in whom the city believes, but in other duced the ‘Socratic Problem’, and its persist-
new spiritual things’ Apology 24b) and cor- ence in the literature may be a sign that it is
rupting the youth. He was found guilty, sen- insoluble.
tenced to death and executed by hemlock The problem arises from the fact that
poisoning. Several reasons for his conviction Socrates wrote nothing, so that all of our
and execution have been offered. At least one earliest accounts of his views come from
scholar (Burnyeat 1998) has argued that he the sources mentioned above. Though there
was guilty of impiety. Others note his arro- are areas of overlap in these sources’ por-
gance before the jury, or his relationship with traits of Socrates, there are important dif-
antidemocratic elements within Athens (in ferences. Controversially (cf. Dover 1968),

29

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 29 3/8/2001 5:13:06 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

Aristophanes portrays Socrates in the Clouds riches philosophical doctrines in the area
as a philosophical mountebank, a purveyor of ethics. Other scholars (including Penner
of doctrines in all areas, who dispenses these 1992) have attributed to Plato’s Socrates a
doctrines from a school called the phrontis- theory of the nature of the soul. Still others
terion (think tank). Aristophanes’ Socrates have attributed to him an early version of the
combines features of a philosopher of nature theory of forms (Allen 1971; Prior 2004).
with that of a sophist. It is difficult for us to Socrates remains a mystery. His influ-
know, at this distance from the Clouds, how ence on other philosophers, however, is not.
serious this portrait is to be taken (though He was more influential on Plato than any
Socrates takes it seriously enough to respond other philosopher, as is shown by the fact
to it in the Ap. 18a–d, 19c–d). that he is present in all the dialogues save the
For Plato and Xenophon, however, very late Laws and is the leading speaker in
Socrates is a revered figure with the highest most of them. We may not know precisely
ethical standards. They differ to some degree where the historical Socrates ends and the
on what these standards entail. For Plato, Platonic Socrates begins, but we can detect
Socrates rejects the lex talionis, the repayment his influence on Plato throughout most of the
of ‘an eye for an eye’, whereas Xenophon’s corpus.
Socrates does not (Vlastos 1991a:179–99).
Plato’s Socrates has a developed theory of
virtue, equating virtue with knowledge and
denying the possibility of moral weakness; SOCRATICS (OTHER THAN PLATO)
Xenophon’s Socrates is more of a homespun
moral philosopher offering practical, moral Menahem Luz
advice. Aristotle does not offer a complete The term ‘Socratic philosophers’ (Sôkratikoi)
portrait of Socrates, but he offers interest- is an ancient one employed to denote either
ing bits of information, many of which Socrates’ pupils or later philosophers who
seem to confirm the portraits in the Platonic regarded him as their founder (Goulet-Cazé
dialogues. 1999:161–5). Since Plato and Xenophon are
Plato’s portrait of Socrates has proved to often considered his principal representa-
be the most compelling for most contempo- tives today, modern scholars invented the
rary scholars. Even if we confine ourselves terms ‘Other Socratics’ (Nails 2002:xxviii)
to the Platonic portrait of Socrates, however, or ‘Minor Socratics’ to denote Socrates’
it is difficult, if not impossible to form a other followers and sometimes their pupils
single coherent picture of his views. Socrates as well (Giannantoni 1985:1–2). Plato gives
in the Ap. (23a–b) professes scepticism about a select list of Socrates’ ‘inner circle’ at the
the existence of knowledge in humans. In time of his execution (Phaedo 59b–c), but of
the Theaetetus (149a–51d) Plato portrays these only five are examined in any detail by
Socrates as a midwife who, though barren the ancient biographers (D. L. 2.60–105, vi.
himself, elicits philosophical truths from 1–19) and considered leading Minor Socratic
his interlocutors. For Alcibiades in the Smp. today (Kahn 1996:1–35): Antisthenes
(221d–2a), Socrates’ barrenness is only an of Piraeus, Aeschines of Sphettus, Euclides
ironic mask for philosophical riches hidden of Megara, Phaedo of Elis and Aristippus of
within. Numerous scholars have seen in those Cyrene. By the late fourth century, ‘Socratic

30

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 30 3/8/2001 5:13:06 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

compositions’ (Sôkratikoi logoi) were a rec- for interactions between the Socratics, Plato
ognized literary genre (Aristotle, Poetics and Xenophon (Kahn 1994:1–35). A nota-
1447b11; Rhetoric 1416a21) and sources ble example is the question of political virtue
of imitation for Socratic literature composed denied in Plato’s Gorgias, but later limited to
during the Hellenistic Roman era when the heroes of Athenian history in Aeschines’
leading Minor Socratics were anachronisti- Miltiades, and ironically subservient to divine
cally considered the founders of the Cynics, providence in the Men. (Bluck 1964:117–18;
Hedonists, Megarian dialecticians and neoE- Dodds 1985:29–30). More provocative is the
leatics (Vander Waerdt 1994a:Part II). Some absence of Socrates’ aporia in their work,
of these imitations were associated with other thus questioning its historicity in the Platonic
lesser Socratics featuring in the works of Plato Socrates.
and Xenophon (Field 1967:133–74): for Modern scholarship has reassessed each
example, Crito, Simon the Cobbler, Glauco, of the five Minor Socratics as independent
Simmias and Cebes (Goulet-Cazé 1999: notes thinkers aside from the Hellenistic schools
to pp. 202–3, 333–42). The genuine works of allegedly descended from them:
the leading Socratics survive only as a mass of
ancient quotations supplemented by recently (1) Antisthenes of Piraeus (c. 445–c. 340
discovered papyrus fragments. Xenophon BCE) was said to have first been a paid
encapsulates many of their ideas but refor- sophist composing artificial speeches
mulated as conversations held between concerning the Homeric heroes (Rankin
them and Socrates (e.g. Symposium i, iv; 1986:ch. 7). Even after his daily con-
Memorabilia II. i, iii). A more reliable though versations with Socrates, his dialogues
selective source is Aristotle who criticizes the were characterized less by dialectic and
logic of Antisthenes and the Antistheneans more by imaginary speeches presented by
(Metaphysics 1024b32–4, 1043b24–6), mythological heroes as in the Hercules
Aristippus (Metaphysics 996a32; Rhetoric (Luz 1996:89–92) – or by foreign histori-
1398b30–3) and the style of Aeschines cal figures as in the Cyrus (Giananntoni
(Rhetoric 1417b1–2). The Minor Socratics 1983:II, VA, ff. 92–9). In both dialogues
did not form a single unified Socratic school he showed how virtue was achieved at a
although modern scholars have attempted universal level and through effort rather
to extract features common to them and than through contemplation, a point
Plato in order to uncover the teaching of that much influenced the early Stoa (Luz
the historical Socrates (Vlastos 1997:63n, 1994:115–17). Even his definition of phi-
103, 208). Former scholars viewed them losophy ‘as a discussion with one’s self’
as Plato’s companions (Field 1967:Part 3) (Giananntoni 1983:II, VA ff. 100) stands
while more recent research has contrasted in contrast to Plato’s dialectic. Moreover,
them: for example, the non-transcendental his theory of language that each word
understanding of the good in Aeschines and denotes one single concept to be defined
Antisthenes with Plato’s theory of ideas only by itself – as in the new fragment
(Rankin 1986:ch. 1); or the teachability of ‘disgracefulness is disgraceful’ (Luz
virtue in Antisthenes (Giannantoni 1983:II, f. 2000:92–3) – recalls Prodicus’ linguis-
99) and Aeschines with Plato’s Men. (Bluck tic interest rather than Plato’s search for
1964:117–18, 368). Yet others have looked universal definitions (Navia 2001:ch. 4).

31

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 31 3/8/2001 5:13:06 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

Much of this may be connected with his explains how Socrates’ divinely inspired
direct assault on Plato in the dialogue erôs enables him to instil self-knowledge
‘That Willy (Sathon) or on Contradiction’ in Alcibiades. Though this theory of
criticizing Plato’s metaphysics and sum- Socratic erôs has been termed ‘innova-
marized in the saying ‘I see a horse but tive’ (Kahn 1994:87), the fragments have
not Horseness’ (Giannantoni 1983:II, striking similarities to Plato’s dialogues
ff. 147–59). Citations from his work as well as divergences with regard to the
on nature (Physikos) reformulate attainment of political epistêmê (Kahn
Xenophanes but are more sophisticated: 1996:19–23). In the Miltiades, Socrates
there are many gods by convention, but persuades Miltiades to complete an edu-
only one in nature (ff. 179–83; Caizzi cation of the soul in addition to that of
1966:100–1). Much of his ethical theory the body, turning to Euripides for advice,
was passed down to the Cynics and Stoa who refers them back to ‘the wisest of the
though his relationship with them was Greeks’ (Socrates?) for teaching (Slings
through his writings (Long 1996:28–46): 1975:307). In the Aspasia, we have
virtue was a ‘Socratic strength’ to be themes recalling Plato (Menexenus) and
grasped through reason and example Xenophon (Oeconomicus) but where
rather than Academic study, but once Pericles’ mistress instructs Socrates on
learned it becomes a ‘weapon that can- married love.
not be lost’. While he saw that true riches (3) Euclides of Megara (c. 450–368 BCE)
lay in virtue (Giannantoni 1983:II, VA, allegedly sheltered Plato after Socrates’
ff. 80–3), he did not reject possessions execution (D. L. 2.106). Although he
in themselves like the Cynics. Though composed six ‘eristic’ dialogues of ‘ques-
‘preferring madness to pleasure’ (Ibid. ff. tion and answer’ (ibid. 106–7), very
118–28) he did not reject easily attained little survives of them (Giannantoni
enjoyment (43–4). 1985:49–57; Doering 1972:ff. 15–49)
(2) Aeschines of Sphettus (c. 435–c. 355 but his Socratic memoirs and style were
BCE) was a less original thinker than allegedly used by Plato in the Theaetetus
Antisthenes though his seven genuine (143b5–6). His methodology attacked his
dialogues were much admired in antiq- opponents’ conclusions rather than their
uity (Field 1967:146) for their unembel- suppositions (Goulet-Cazé 1999:366) ‘in
lished ‘Socratic character’ (D. L. 2.61). a manner Parmenidean’ (D. L. 2.106),
Since the last publication of his frag- that is, Zeno (Doering 1972:83–4). His
ments (Dittmar 1912; Krauss 1911), pupils in the ‘dialectic school’ of Megara
there have been substantial papyrologi- hence developed a number of logical-
cal additions to his Alcibiades (CPF I dialectical paradoxes confuting claims to
1989:120–34; Lobel 1919:no. 1608) and real knowledge (ibid. 108) while his own
Miltiades (CPF I 1989:134–48; Patzer appearance in the Plato (Tht. 142a–3c)
1975; Slings 1975:301–8) dialogues. In is in a dialogue questioning the mean-
the former, Socrates deflates Alcibiades’ ing of knowledge. Euclides may none-
political aspirations in that he has less theless have held positive doctrines as
epistêmê even than his hero Themistocles in his identification of the Socratic good
(Field 1967:147–9). The dialogue also with the Parmenidean One (Goulet-Cazé

32

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 32 3/8/2001 5:13:07 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

1999:316, n. 1), sometimes seen as a sign pleasure (hêdonê) to be the highest good
of Platonic influence (Kahn 1996:13–14). and end (Mannebach 1961, ff. 155–62).
However, it is unlikely that Euclides was Xenophon (Mem. II.i.1–34, III.viii.4–10)
in philosophical agreement with Plato see- depicts him as a sybarite corrected by
ing that his ‘eristical’ method of ‘question Socrates, but it is clear from the argument
and answer’ (D. L. 2.106) was a sophistry that Aristippus sought pleasure, not lux-
Plato much criticized in the Euthydemus ury, and for comfort’s sake, social seclu-
and elsewhere. Elsewhere he compared sion. Perhaps in reply to the antihedonist,
sleep and death (Doering 1972:80–1, Antisthenes, Aristippus claimed that he
f. 19) in almost determinist tones (ibid. learned from philosophy ‘how to speak
ff. 12, 13), an attitude he jokingly main- extravagantly’ (D. L. 2.68). Scholars have
tained in relation to the gods (ibid. f. 11). contrasted his thought to Plato’s discus-
Logicians have been interested in his use sions of pleasure (Gosling and Taylor
of Zeno’s argumentation, wondering if it 1984:42–3; Kahn 1996:17–18), but some
reached him directly or through Socrates concluded that he was a serious Socratic
(Kneale and Kneale 1964:8–9). though much misunderstood in his time
(4) Phaedo of Elis (born c. 417 BCE) returned (McKirahan 1994:377–82). Since his rel-
to his native land after Socrates’ execu- ative Aristippus II (Mannebach 1961:ff.
tion, but we know little of his Elian School 163–7) developed the details of this the-
of philosophy, which was absorbed by ory, it has been difficult to draw a clear
the Eretrian school of eristics within a distinction between them (Giannantoni
few generations (Giannantoni 1983:I. 1985:123–8, 161–70) and by the Roman
IIIA fr. 1–7). In his dialogue, Zopyros, period there was difficulty even in assign-
he discussed traditional physiognomy ing his dialogues (D. L. 2.83–5). The rela-
whereby a person’s character is read tionship between these hedonists and the
from his features and likely criticized as Epicureans (Giannantoni 1985:171–2)
‘grandfatherly stupidity’ (ibid. f. 9). His could only have occurred after Aristippus’
description of the effect of the wise as death.
an unnoticed sting perceived by its later
effect may contain his answer to physi-
ognomy (Clay 1994:29, no. 11). In the
Simon he probably discussed Socrates’ THE SOPHISTS
conversations with Simon the cobbler
(Goulet-Cazé 1999:312), a genre later Richard Marback
to influence the Cynics. Since the anec- The Greek term from which the name
dotes describe Phaedo’s early life as sophistês, or sophist, is derived is sophos,
a slave, it may be speculated that this translating as wise or the wise man. Wisdom
dialogue presents the philosophy of the is the knowledge of an expert, knowledge in
workingman in contrast to the ‘executive’ a particular art, craft or skill, such as music,
Cephalus (Republic 329e). navigation or sculpture. A person wise in
(5) Aristippus of Cyrene (c. 430–355 BCE) an art such as navigation could teach that
was much disparaged by his contempo- art. Such teaching was never purely practi-
raries as a hedonist (D. L. 2.65), believing cal in nature as it was more than a handing

33

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 33 3/8/2001 5:13:07 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

down of technical skill. To acquire wisdom or virtue, is not what is given by nature but
in an art required learning when, how and to what people become aware of, what they
what effect one’s knowledge should be put, invent for themselves, for it is through their
it was to acquire a capacity for judgement. interactions with each other that they create
General instruction in moral judgement was the possibility of their attaining virtues and
considered the responsibility of ancient poets becoming good (see Jarratt 1991). The point
(see Guthrie 1971a). In the fifth century, the is developed in Protagoras’ recounting of the
class of professional teachers grouped as myth of Prometheus distributing to humans
sophists – a grouping that included Gorgias, the various arts by which they secure survival
Protagoras and Prodicus – taught not poetry (Protagoras 321c–2d). As animals, humans
but eloquence and persuasion in speaking are not adapted to survival. They depend for
and writing, especially the speaking and their survival not only on wisdom in specific
writing associated with political life. Gorgias Promethean arts such as saddle-making and
drew from the poetry of Empedocles to metal-working but also on the more general
cultivate a poetic style in political oratory. political arts delivered by Hermes, the moral
Other sophists, such as Protagoras, claimed virtues of aidos and dikê, or the senses of jus-
that lessons in persuasion taught wisdom in tice (q.v.) and shame, which make it possible
statecraft as well as virtue of character (see for humans to form bonds of civic friend-
Kennedy 1994). ship. These are not virtues that all humans
The claim that someone could possess the possess in equal amounts at birth, although
wisdom of virtue (q.v.) and teach it to some- they are virtues all humans have the potential
one who did not possess it had among its sup- to acquire and develop through lives lived in
porters those suspicious of the possibility that civic friendship. The educational and politi-
such virtues as aristocratic excellence were cal institutions created by humans cultivate
not strictly inherited (see Jaeger 1939–44). the specific character that humanity achieves.
In the fifth century the distinction between To be human, then, is to be responsible for
nomos and physis, or convention and nature, achieving virtue for oneself, independent of
made it possible to think of wisdom as some- the dictates or limits of nature.
thing more akin to ingenuity or cleverness, If to be human is to make one’s self,
a human capacity for overcoming natural then anything becomes possible. The soph-
limitations. Those who were truly clever pos- ist Gorgias exploits possibility, driving a
sessed a knowledge of, and so a facility with wedge between the man-made and the natu-
manipulating, the customs, habits and prac- rally given when he argues: Nothing exists.
tises of an art. Such cleverness had negative If it exists, it cannot be known. If it can be
as well as positive connotations (see Atwill known, it cannot be expressed (see Sprague
2009). Someone dexterous enough in an art 1972). While the extreme scepticism of
such as rhetoric could potentially deceive oth- Gorgias differs from the extreme relativ-
ers about what is and what is possible. One of ism of Protagoras, their views together sug-
the so-called first sophists, Protagoras, made gest a period of critical self-awareness and
great use of the distinction between nomos increased confidence in the power of human
and physis. His observation that ‘Man is the thought, a period that has been characterized
measure of all things’ suggests that what can as the Greek enlightenment. It was a period
come to count as the wisdom of statecraft, during which the Greeks cultivated their

34

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 34 3/8/2001 5:13:07 PM


PLATO’S LIFE

humanity by cultivating their capacities in a wisdom (see Solmsen 1975). Because of their
wide variety of technical and political arts. verbal abilities, and because their lessons
Prodicus contributed to the cultivation of were only available to those who could pay,
political wisdom an insistence on precision in the sophists were often envied, disdained and
the definition of terms and clarity in political ridiculed. Since the sophists charged fees for
oratory that heightened critical self-reflec- their wisdom they could, unlike their rival,
tion. His concern for distinguishing clearly Socrates, become corrupted by economic
the meanings of words may have influenced necessity, constrained to craft their lessons
Socrates to dissect the precise meaning of in excellence and virtue so as to fetch from
what his interlocutors say in response to his their patrons the highest prices. Socrates,
questions. Certainly, Prodicus and Socrates unconstrained by the pursuit of fees in his
were acquainted (see Guthrie 1971a). In the quest for wisdom, was freed to discover the
Men. (96d), Socrates remarks that he had unfettered truth of excellence and virtue with
been trained by Prodicus. In the Theaetetus others who were also lovers of wisdom for
(151b), he explains that he has sent pupils to its own sake.
Prodicus to learn his art. Plato’s critical presentation of the soph-
Sophists such as Gorgias, Protagoras and ists as the rivals of Socrates may encourage
Prodicus travelled from city to city giving a reading that opposes Plato and Platonism
performances of their persuasive and verbal to the sophists and sophistry. Such a reading
skills. They also taught the arts of eristic, removes the drama of the dialogues from the
forensics and rhetoric to those who could sophistic claims to which they respond. To
afford their fees. With access to education in read Plato in this way, to read the dialogues
the arts of persuasion citizens of the ancient outside the intellectual ferment regarding
Greek cities could more skilfully declaim human wisdom, is to miss recognizing issues
and debate the ideas of justice, statecraft and that most concerned the ancient Greeks, issues
virtue. The sophistic claim to teach an art of Plato could not consider except through ear-
virtue may have resonated with confidence nest engagement with the sophists – the
in human ambition and the demands of a intertwined issues of appearances, being and
democracy, but it also aroused concern about becoming, deliberation, desire, education,
the very possibility of ethical and political friendship, justice, persuasion and virtue.

35

9780826435354_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 35 3/8/2001 5:13:07 PM


2
THE DIALOGUES

THE PLATONIC CORPUS AND (tetralogies 8, 9, and Spuria) and Bodleian


MANUSCRIPT TRADITION B (tetralogies 1–6). Together they cover
most of corpus, except the short tetralogy 7.
Harold Tarrant Manuscript A has Armenian origins (Saffrey
Our Platonic corpus, consisting of nine 2007), and MS D is an important additional
‘tetralogies’ (groups of four works), goes witness for the R. MS B incorporates the
back at least to the time of Thrasyllus, court scholia of Arethas, while MSS T and W are
intellectual of the Roman Emperor Tiberius the best representatives of different families
in the first-century BCE. The same first tetral- that supplement B, both preserving most of
ogy is also attributed by Albinus (Prologue 4) tetralogies 1–7 with some of 8. For a differ-
to a Dercyllides of uncertain date. Tetralogies ent part of the W-group P is the main rep-
were systematically furnished with second resentative, while Duke (1995:ix–xi) has
titles based on the topic under investigation afforded more weight than is customary to
rather than the participant (Diogenes Laertius Q. F, which is the principal representative of
D. L. 3.57). Some second titles unsurprisingly a different arm of the tradition (Dodds 1959),
antedate Thrasyllus, but he presumably added is accordingly a valuable, if erratic, resource
others for the sake of completeness. Some for selected dialogues, in addition to MSS A
manuscripts preserve both second titles and (Slings et al. 2005:195) and B, etc.
each dialogue’s ‘character’ as determined by While not good enough to make scholarly
a dichotomic classification at D. L. 3.49–51, emendation redundant, the combined MSS
though what standing the classification had preserve their contents much better than
is unclear, since most ancient Platonists from MSS of most classical Greek authors. The
Plutarch to Olympiodorus afford little atten- ancient commentators, particularly Proclus,
tion to characters, second titles and tetralo- Damascius and Olympiodorus, preserve evi-
gies alike. dence of readings that have since disappeared,
In the tetralogies the multibook works while occasionally being unaware of our read-
(Republic; Laws) and the thirteen Epistles ings. However, since ancient copyists were just
count as one item each. Many MSS pre- as prone to making mistakes as Byzantine and
serve part of the Thrasyllan order. The two medieval ones, even the earliest papyri of frag-
oldest date from the ninth century, Paris A ments of Plato’s text, going back to Hellenistic

36

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 36 3/8/2001 5:12:38 PM


THE DIALOGUES

times, are more likely to be wrong than right It is usually assumed that some kind of
when deviating from the principal MSS tra- important collection of texts was organized
ditions. The most recent editions make con- and retained in the Old Academy, and, by the
siderably more use of the indirect tradition in time of Zeno of Citium’s youth (Antigonus
the apparatus, but this does not result in very of Carystus at D. L. 3.66), a fee set for con-
much change to the printed text. sulting it. It is well known that Philip of
Already, in the second century CE authors Opus, alleged author of Epin. (q.v.), was
were aware of emendations to the text of held responsible for the arrangement of the
Plato that had been inspired by doctrinal Lg. into 12 books, and the Suda also credits
rather than scholarly concerns (Dillon 1989). him with the less-than-natural arrangement
Galen, in his Commentary on the Medical of R. into 10. The difference in the number
Aspects of the Timaeus, prefers to check at of books employed, 10 rather than 12, sug-
77b–c a copy stemming from one Atticus, pos- gests that the R. was meant to be read with
sibly Cicero’s friend (Alline 1915:104–12). Timaeus and Critias. This evidence is plau-
Whether it was possible to check superior sible, not compelling, and nothing is known
copies of other dialogues is unknown. about other early groups, though two fur-
It seems improbable that the Thrasyllan ther groups of 12 may have been intended,
order, found at D. L. 3.56–61, was firmly est- omitting most of the dubia (q.v.). However,
ablished much before his time. Rival reading the early inclusion of the dubia in the cor-
orders were promoted by other Platonists and pus would have soon obscured the rationale
scholars of the period, and Theon of Smyrna behind any ordering of the scrolls. Besides
probably postulated different tetralogies Philip, early Academics known to have had
(Tarrant 1993:58–84). In any case, it is clear some role connected with the books include
that ancient Platonists generally refused to Hermodorus (trading in them), Crantor (as
allow the Thrasyllan order any special status. first exegete, at least of Ti., Proclus in Ti.
Aristophanes of Byzantium (D. L. 3.61–2), 1.76.1–2) and Arcesilaus (‘coming to pos-
at the close of the third-century BCE, had sess’ them, presumably those once available
arranged 15 works into trilogies. What seems to his close friend Crantor, D. L. 4.32). The
to have persisted was the belief that Plato had evidence suggests an important role relating
arranged dialogues in groupings reminiscent to the books, separate from the scholarch’s
of tragic performances at the Dionysia, and more public position.
the fact that some dialogues were intended to The early history of the corpus is in fact
constitute sequences (e.g. Theaetetus-Sophist- somewhat mysterious, and inseparable from
Politicus) seems incontestable. the intractable questions of (a) the state in
A recently published papyrus (Sedley which Plato had left his writings (especially
2009b) reveals the rationale for seeing the but not solely Lg.; Nails and Thesleff 2003),
second tetralogy as a single coherent study. and (b) the origin of the dubia. Among these
In it the Cratylus is seen as a prelude, while was Min., which Aristophanes of Byzantium
the remaining dialogues are said to deal with already grouped with Lg. (plus the similarly
methods of definition and division; the Tht. dubious Epin.) in his arrangement, presum-
is seen as the more tentative as it is keen to ably because its proper place was by then
expose errors about knowledge, whereas the believed to be with the corpus. The authorship
Sph. and Plt. are seen as confident. of Alcibiades II, Hipparchus and Amatores

37

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 37 3/8/2001 5:12:38 PM


THE DIALOGUES

was debated even in antiquity (Aelian VH virtually every page there is some connection
8.2; Athenaeus 11.506c; D. L. 9.37). with something elsewhere in the Platonic dia-
In antiquity, the preoccupation with under- logues, usually in those deemed to be early –
standing the full corpus seems to have been if only because what is at issue is the Platonic
confined to the early Roman imperial period, understanding of Socrates, whose picture
following Andronicus’ work on the Corpus is more vivid there. These connections con-
Aristotelicum. Platonists from Plutarch sciously set the work in the Platonic (rather
onward concentrated on the exegesis of than Socratic) tradition (cf. Theages 128a,
what we should regard as ‘mature’ works, 130a), a fact which some see as confirming
and Neoplatonists from Iamblichus onward Platonic authorship, others as undermining
employed a reduced curriculum of 12 dia- it. There are oddities of both language and
logues (plus R. and Lg.). In this the only Socratic philosophy, but such are to be found
works sometimes (if controversially) thought in most genuine works. It may be argued
‘early’ today are Alcibiades I, Grg. and Cra. that its presence in the Corpus speaks for
authenticity, or that its actual placement, in
the unusually suspicious Fourth Tetralogy,
speaks against it.
ALCIBIADES I The work adds to the mythology sur-
rounding the allegedly erotic relationship
Harold Tarrant between Socrates and Alcibiades, and cap-
The Alcibiades I is a dialogue of moderate tures a brief but allegedly important episode
length in dramatic form, between two speak- in Athens’ history, from the first word that
ers only: Socrates in the guise of a divinely- Socrates addresses to Alcibiades until the
inspired lover and educator, and the youthful latter’s agreement to reciprocate his love. In
Alcibiades who is slightly too old to prove doing so it fulfils some of Aristotle’s impor-
attractive to men seeking physical gratifica- tant requirements for a tragic plot. It opens
tion. His guardian Pericles is still alive, and he with Socrates explaining to Alcibiades why
is on the threshold of embarking on a politi- after following him about for years he is
cal career – prematurely in Socrates’ view. It finally speaking to him, especially when no
is clear that Plutarch (Life of Alcibiades IV) other lover has been well received. He credits
regards it as historically sound, though Attic the divine sign, here firmly associated with
comedy ignores any relationship between the a guiding god, with having prevented him
Socrates and Alcibiades, both of whom are until now. He expects acceptance because
satirized separately. Alcibiades has Alexander-like ambitions to
The authorship of the Alc. I has, since rule the world, and he is the only one who
Schleiermacher in the early nineteenth cen- can prepare him to achieve them – if the god
tury, been more hotly contested than that of allows (Alc. I 105e).
any other dialogue. Conclusive arguments The dialogue naturally falls into three
for settling the issue are elusive (for opposing parts. The first, seen as employing Socrates’
views, see Denyer 2001:14–20; Smith 2004). traditional elenchus by Neoplatonist inter-
Similarly there is no agreement among those preters, demonstrates to Alcibiades that he
who defend Platonic authorship about has learned nothing relevant to public poli-
whether it is early or late in his output. On cymaking, in particular that he has learned

38

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 38 3/8/2001 5:12:38 PM


THE DIALOGUES

nothing of justice and injustice precisely with the welcome consequence that Socrates
because he had supposed from childhood loves Alcibiades alone rather than Alcibiades’
that he knew enough about them (110b). attractive assets (131e). Self-knowledge is
Accused of never seeking a credible teacher, like self-seeing, in that it requires a bright
Alcibiades suggests that he has learned from and lively mirror (133a), so that rather than
ordinary citizens, whose authority is then gaze into the pupil of another’s eye (a suitably
undermined with reference to their internal erotic image), we must apparently gaze into
disagreement. Alcibiades claims that expedi- the finest core of a soul, in which its wisdom
ency is more germane to public debate than and its divinity reside (133c).
justice, but is forced to admit that there is no Interpretation of this passage was hotly
conflict between the two (116d). He remarks contested in late antiquity, resulting in tex-
on his shaken confidence and vacillating tual difficulties (Tarrant 2007); a passage
ideas, which Socrates shows to be linked (133c8–17), absent from manuscripts, is
with his false assumption that he knows the sometimes supplied with too little caution
most important things when he does not in from Christian sources. Reconstruction is
fact know: the most lamentable form of igno- uncertain. Pagan commentators assume
rance (118b). It is then implied that Pericles’ that Alcibiades is being invited to gaze upon
record suggests that he knew no better. Socrates’ mind and upon a god operating
Alcibiades’ tactic now changes. Thrown within, not upon an external god as the addi-
the lifeline that Athenians generally are igno- tional lines assume. This section from 128e,
rant, he claims that his abilities can at least which gave the work its ancient subtitle On
prevail over them. Socrates shows that it is the Nature of a Human Being, also attracts
not prevailing over the Assembly that counts, most attention in modern times from propo-
but prevailing over the enemy. Alcibiades has nents of authenticity and spuriousness alike.
to educate himself above the level of Spartan From that point Alcibiades is easily shown
and Persian rivals (120a). In the second main that he must aim at personal excellence
part, a long, central speech, Socrates com- rather than at tyrannical power (135b), and
pares Alcibiades’ credentials with those of that excellence alone is the choice for a free
Spartan and Persian kings and imagines how man. Alcibiades returns Socrates’ love, and,
unworthy an opponent for their sons the while the ending is neither aporetic nor para-
royal mothers would hold him to be. doxical, it includes an ominous warning that
Now chastened, Alcibiades asks Socrates the power of the people may overpower their
how to correct his condition (124b). Seeing friendship.
that he needs self-care, he is led to search
in the final part for the right kind of self-
improvement, but the idea of good deliberation
proves inadequate. Eventually Socrates helps THE APOLOGY OF SOCRATES
with the observation that self-care requires
self-improvement, not improvement of things Thomas C. Brickhouse and
we have an interest in (128e), so that, first Nicholas D. Smith
and foremost, we must know ourselves. This It is impossible to know precisely when Plato
is shown to be neither of the bodies nor the wrote the Apology of Socrates, although
combination of body and soul, but soul alone, most scholars believe that it was written

39

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 39 3/8/2001 5:12:38 PM


THE DIALOGUES

early in Plato’s career (q.v. Compositional the older accusations, explaining that his
Chronology). The work has the outward reputation for wisdom comes from his
appearance of being a set of three speeches failed attempts to find a counter example to
that Socrates actually made when he was a Delphic oracle that no one is wiser than
tried for impiety in 399 BCE. No one thinks Socrates himself. He concludes that what the
that Plato’s Ap. expresses Socrates’ words oracle meant is that he ‘. . . is aware that he
verbatim. Some argue, however, that Plato’s is in truth worth nothing with respect to wis-
version must have captured the substance dom’ (23b2–4). Socrates responds to the for-
and tone of what Socrates said, since Plato’s mal charges by means of an interrogation of
intent must have been to show how unjust his chief accuser, Meletus, in which Socrates
was Socrates’ condemnation, and Plato shows that Meletus’ own conception of his
would have defeated his own purpose had accusations is self-contradictory. There is
he significantly distorted Socrates’ actual little credible evidence that the prosecution
words. There were hundreds of witnesses to was relying on unspoken, distinctly political
the speech itself who would have been able charges (Irwin 2005:127–49). For the view
to identify serious distortions of the truth that Socrates’ was actually guilty of impiety,
(e.g. Burnet 1924:63–4; more recently, Kahn see Burnyeat 1997:1–12. For the view that
1996:88–9). the charge of ‘introducing new divinities’
Others, impressed by the work’s exquisite was especially damaging to Socrates, see
crafting, argue that Plato’s version must be McPherran (1996:169–74).
a fabrication, perhaps an account of what The centrepiece of the defence speech is
Socrates’ could have or should have said (De Socrates’ explanation of why he has engaged
Stryker and Slings 1994:1–8). However, the in philosophy. He declares that he has actu-
fact that Plato’s Ap. is undeniably the prod- ally been ordered by the god to do philosophy
uct of literary mastery is obviously compat- and that this is a kind of service to the god
ible with its capturing both the central claims (Ap. 23b7–c1, 30a5–7). His mission on behalf
Socrates’ made and the manner in which he of the god is one he must pursue as long as
made them. Yet another position notes the he ‘draws breath and is able’ (29d2–4). The
many incompatible reports about Socrates purpose of his mission is to exhort his fel-
made by his contemporaries and urges scep- low Athenians to pursue virtue and to under-
ticism regarding the historical question (e.g. stand that ‘. . . from virtue comes money and
Morrison 2000:235–65; Prior 2001:41–57). all good things for men in private and public’
No one denies the importance of the work (30b2–4). Since his fellow citizens have failed
for Plato’s portrait of Socrates. to grasp this truth, the god has attached him
According to Plato, Socrates thought he to the city ‘like a gadfly’ (30e5). Socrates
had to answer two sets of accusations, the explains that his ‘divine voice’, his daimo-
slanders that had been spread for many years nion (q.v.), warned him not to try to improve
that he was an atheistic nature philosopher the city by going into politics because, were
and an amoral sophist (Ap. 19b4–c1), and he to do so, he could not possibly survive as
the newer, formal accusations that he cor- an honest person (31c4–2a4).
rupted the young, did not believe in the Socrates is convicted by a narrow major-
gods the city believed in, and introduced ity – had only 30 more jurors found him inno-
new divinities (24b8–c1). He flatly denies cent, he would have been acquitted (36a5–6).

40

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 40 3/8/2001 5:12:38 PM


THE DIALOGUES

The closeness of the vote is remarkable given philosophy, he could neither be indifferent to
the long-standing prejudices against him in continuing this mission nor could he end his
the minds’ of many jurors (see 18b1–c1). mission by seeking his own death. Trying to
Because the penalty for conviction was not gain acquittal in a manner consistent with
set by law, Socrates had the opportunity to his moral commitments appears then to have
offer a counter penalty to Meletus’ proposal been his only option (Brickhouse and Smith
that he be put to death. Socrates thinks he 1989:37–47, 210–34).
has been a great benefactor to Athens, and so
says he deserves ‘free meals in the Prytaneum’,
an honour reserved for Olympic victors and
other distinguished Athenians (36d4–7a1). CHARMIDES
He explains why he cannot offer any penalty,
including exile, which would preclude his Gerald A. Press
philosophizing. In the end, he offers to pay a The Charmides is set in a gymnasium on
fine of thirty minas, a substantial sum, which the day following Socrates’ return from
he can pay with the help of four friends, one military service in a siege at the outset of
of whom was Plato himself (38b1–9). the Peloponnesian War (429 BCE). Socrates
In Socrates’ third speech, he first ‘proph- narrates to an unnamed ‘friend’ his discus-
esies’ to those who voted for his condemna- sion about sôphrosynê (temperance or mod-
tion that there will be others who will come eration) with Charmides and Critias, Plato’s
after him to ‘test’ them as he had tried to do uncle and cousin respectively. Our awareness
and they will find these others even more of their later historical lives as notoriously
difficult. To those who voted for his acquit- immoderate members of the tyranny that
tal, he says that death is nothing to fear: it is ruled Athens for a short time after it had lost
either a dreamless sleep or a transmigration the war establishes situational irony (q.v.)
to Hades, where he can converse with the and a political context. The dialogue falls
other dead. A good person cannot be harmed naturally into three parts or acts.
in life or in death (41c8–d2). He closes by A long prologue (Chrm. 153a–9a) intro-
exhorting this group of jurors to ‘trouble’ his duces Plato’s familiar thematic contrasts
sons in the same way as he has troubled his between ordinary socio-political concerns
fellow citizens (41e2–2a2). and philosophy, beauty and wisdom and
Scholars have been divided over what body and soul. Whereas everyone in the gym
Socrates, as Plato portrays him, sought to wants to hear the war news, Socrates is only
accomplish. The traditional view is that interested in knowing about the current state
Socrates was either indifferent to the outcome of ‘philosophy’ and whether any young men
of the trial or that he was actually inviting are notable for their beauty and wisdom
martyrdom for the cause of philosophy (e.g. (153a–d). Through the ruse that Socrates has
Taylor 1960:156). Against this, recent com- medical knowledge and knows a cure for the
mentators, noting the closeness of the vote to headaches Charmides has been experiencing,
convict Socrates, argue that Socrates actually he begins to discuss with the young and very
convinced many jurors that he deserved to be beautiful Charmides the nature of the sôph-
released. Moreover, if, as he claims, Socrates rosynê that his guardian, Critias, has attrib-
sees himself as divinely ordained to practise uted to him.

41

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 41 3/8/2001 5:12:38 PM


THE DIALOGUES

In the second act, Charmides initially itself and other sciences or types of knowl-
proposes (159b–62b) that sôphrosynê is edge, knowledge of knowledge for short
quietness and that it is modesty. These are (epistêmê epistêmês, 166c). Responding to
private and behavioural accounts appro- Critias’ proud but mistaken confidence that
priate to his age, but easily refuted. For he has knowledge and his misappropriation
although sôphrosynê, being an excellence of Socrates’ ideas, Socrates’ refutation of
(q.v.) must always be admirable (kalon, this view has two stages. First, he argues,
159c), good and beneficial (agathon, 160e), it seems strange, perhaps impossible, for
quiet behaviours are not always admirable something to exercise its specific power on
and modest behaviour may not always be itself, for example, a seeing of seeing or a
good. Instead of thinking for himself as hearing of hearing (169b). Second, he argues
agreed, Charmides now proposes something that, even if knowledge of knowledge were
he has heard, that sôphrosynê is ‘minding possible, it would not be beneficial either
one’s own business’ or ‘doing one’s own to know that one knows something or to
things’ (to ta heatou prattein, 161b). The know what one knows; but if it is not ben-
same phrase appears in the Republic (433a) eficial, then it cannot be sôphrosynê since
as an account of justice (q.v.), and was a it was agreed that excellences are always
political slogan (North 1966:101f.). Here, beneficial. This is true even though a soci-
however, Socrates calls it a riddle, because ety in which individuals did all and only
reading, writing and practicing productive what they know might seem ideal (a uto-
arts such as healing and house building are pia of knowledge or expertise, 173a–d), to
doing other people’s business (Chrm. 161e) which Critias agrees. Real benefit, however,
and a city would not be governed temper- would not derive from this sort of knowl-
ately or well ordered if every citizen did eve- edge, but only from knowledge of good and
rything for himself. evil (174d). Socrates concludes that they
The shift to a social and political scope for have failed to discover what sôphrosynê is
sôphrosynê coincides with a shift of inter- (175b) and Charmides, with Critias’ collu-
locutor from Charmides to the elder politi- sion, declares that he will continue discuss-
cally active Critias from whom Charmides ing things with Socrates, even if they have
heard this idea. It exemplifies the pedimen- to force Socrates into it (176c).
tal structure (q.v.) often to be found in the Until the last few decades, most scholars
dialogues, with discussion moving from an focused on a few specific questions about
outer, behavioural to an inner, intellectual the last act, particularly the complexities
focus and from lower, existential to higher, of epistêmê epistêmês (Chen 1978; Dyson
conceptual accounts, returning later to the 1974; McKim 1985), which seemed relevant
behavioural and existential level. to issues in contemporary epistemology. To
The argumentation in this third act many, the ending suggests that sôphrosynê
(162c–75d) is far more complex and dif- is knowledge of good and evil, consistent
ficult than the earlier ones. In response with the unity of the virtues thought to be
to a series of Socrates’ objections, Critias Socrates’ or Plato’s doctrine (Santas 1973;
explains ‘doing one’s own’ as doing or mak- Stalley 2000). Others have seen the Chrm.
ing good things (163e), then as knowing more generally as teaching an interrogative
oneself (165b) and finally as knowledge of philosophical stance (Hyland 1985) or as a

42

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 42 3/8/2001 5:12:38 PM


THE DIALOGUES

microcosm of Socratic philosophy, the life of Given Critias and Charmides as important
critical reason (Schmid 1997). oligarchs, their use of the Spartan-oligarchic
Recent scholars have more diverse inter- political slogan, the epistemic utopia ideal-
ests. Some investigate the psychosomatic ized by Critias (Chrm. 172a, 173d), his oli-
medicine that is a recurrent Platonic theme garchic reinterpretation of Delphic motto
(cp. Laín Entralgo 1970; McPherran 2002; to evade its traditional sense of controlling
Murphy 2000). It has been recognized that oneself and remaining within the bounds of
the twist given to self-knowledge by Critias appropriate human behaviour (164d f.), the
contradicts the traditional sense of the Chrm. is a broad investigation of sôphrosynê
Delphic admonition ‘Know thyself’ (Benson that subsumes ethical and political meanings
2003; Tuozzo 2000). The broadly political both traditional and contemporary.
dimensions of the dialogue and false utopias As is usual in the dialogues, the con-
that Socrates rejects have also been noted ceptual theme, sôphrosynê, is dramatized
(Landy 1998; Tuozzo 2001). Several have in the resonances of characters’ histori-
observed a puzzling pattern, Socrates criticiz- cal lives with their dialogical words and
ing ideas here he elsewhere champions: doing deeds. Chaerephon, Critias and Charmides
your own thing, self-knowledge, knowledge enact lack of sôphrosynê in different ways
of knowledge, culminating in his paradoxi- as Socrates enacts its possession both by his
cal, seeming rejection of sôphrosynê itself as carefully described recovery from sexual
either impossible or useless (Carone 1998; arousal (155d) and by his modest, playful
Tsouna 1997). but rigorous philosophic inquiry. Critias and
These problems can be resolved by a more Charmides, the future intemperate oligarchs,
holistic and contextual approach beginning both speak and act here in ways that are
from the observation that Socrates’ thera- intemperate and quasityrannical. Socrates
peutic educational mission with his interlocu- shows us the true sôphrosynê in contrast
tors, like Plato’s with his readers, is guidance with them and with the ‘mad’ (153b) demo-
towards recognizing their lack of knowledge cratic Chaerephon as well.
and sôphrosynê and pursuit of them through The Chrm. thus canvasses many major
open-ended conversational dialectic (q.v.) contemporary uses of sôphrosynê, suggesting
rather than by propounding doctrines. It is their limits, and the importance of a cogni-
important that sôphrosynê was semantically tive component. Given Socrates’ regular role
rich, aligned in various contexts with individ- in the dialogues as representative in word
ual shame, self-control, moderation, purity, and deed of an alternative way of life called
personal orderliness and good political order ‘philosophy’ (q.v.), the dialogue also suggests
and opposed to folly, insolence or violence, that unreflective traditionalism, sophistic
courage, intemperance or licentiousness and rationalism and the contested contemporary
wantonness (North 1966; Rademaker 2005). political and rhetorical uses to which sôph-
At the dialogue’s dramatic date, sôphrosynê rosynê was being put are transcended by
was the locus of conflict between a tradi- something at once more rational, critical and
tional value and sophistic criticism while also intellectual than tradition and more modest
politically contested as a term for Spartan and self-controlled than was understood by
identity but used rhetorically by Athenian the politicians, democratic and oligarchic
oligarchs (Thucydides, History 3.82.8). alike.

43

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 43 3/8/2001 5:12:39 PM


THE DIALOGUES

CLITOPHON the latter issue, Slings (1999:128–34) and


Gaiser (1959:30, 110–11) have both seen
Francisco Gonzalez the Clit. as bringing out the protreptic char-
Lacking a setting or dramatic date, the acter of the Socratic elenchus, even if they
Clitophon begins with Socrates reproaching have interpreted this differently. Depending
the eponymous pupil for speaking badly of on one’s view of the relation between the
him behind his back. Clitophon replies that Socratic method and Plato’s own philosoph-
while he has been critical of some things in ical method, the dialogue could also be seen
Socrates he also been always ready to praise as addressing the protreptic character of
other things. Socrates asks to hear of both Plato’s philosophy. At issue in the dialogue
his positive and negative points so as to learn would then be whether this characteristic is
and become better, and then remains silent a weakness (with Clitophon, as did Grote
while Clitophon delivers what proves to be 1865: vol. 3:22–3) or a strength (against
rather more blame than praise. Praising and Clitophon).
even imitating Socrates’ exhortations to vir- Already in antiquity Plato’s dialogues
tue, Clitophon complains that Socrates never were criticized for having a primarily pro-
takes the next step of teaching us what virtue treptic function. Cicero has Varro in the
is. Clitophon claims to have been converted Academica observe that the Socratic writings
and to want nothing more than to be a just of Plato and others show that ‘Socrates’ dis-
person, but when he has asked Socrates’ com- course was exhausted in the praise of virtue
panions and Socrates himself for an account and in the exhortation of people to study
of what justice is and how it is to be attained, virtue’ (I.4.16). But an important early tes-
he has received only unsatisfactory and even timony of Dicaearchus, the pupil of Aristotle
contradictory answers. Imagine being per- and Theophrastus (Dorandi 1991:125–6),
suaded to become a doctor, but then finding shows that not long after Plato’s death criti-
no one who can tell you what medicine is cisms like Clitophon’s were directed against
and how it can be learned! Clitophon there- the protreptic character of the dialogues: the
fore claims to have arrived at the conclusion very success of the dialogues in exhorting so
that Socrates either does not know what many to the pursuit of philosophy was seen
he is talking about or is keeping his knowl- as encouraging a superficiality that does not
edge from others. In either case, Clitophon go beyond such exhortation and its obvious
has no use for him and would rather go to truisms.
Thrasymachus (q.v. sophists), who does have Why then would Plato write a dialogue
something to say about justice and is willing that appears to confirm such criticisms? Even
to teach it. The only other time we encoun- if Plato wanted to draw attention to the pro-
ter Clitophon in the Platonic corpus is in treptic character of the Socratic method and
the Republic where he has already become perhaps of his own dialogues, why would
a pupil of Thrasymachus and comes to his he do so in the form of an unanswered cri-
defence. tique? One way of avoiding this question is
As many scholars consider the Clit. to be to deny that Plato is the author. The best
spurious, much of the scholarship has focused recent discussion is Slings (1999:222–7),
on the related questions of the dialogue’s who concludes that no linguistic case can
authenticity and its purpose. With regard to be made against authenticity. Slings also

44

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 44 3/8/2001 5:12:39 PM


THE DIALOGUES

rejects arguments based on formal com- response, but instead to listen demurely
position and overall style, concluding with (Clit. 15).
some hesitation that the dialogue is authen- If one believes that the dialogue is com-
tic. Yet, that such arguments are subjective plete and that it was written either by Plato
is confirmed by the fact that in the 1981 himself or by a faithful if perhaps somewhat
version of his book, Slings, on the basis of clumsy student, then one is left with the fol-
the very arguments rejected in 1999, con- lowing interpretative options: (a) that the
cluded that ‘the Clitophon was not written ‘Socrates’ criticized in the dialogue is not
by Plato, but by a very close and intelligent Socrates (ibid.:3–4, 209–15); (b) that Plato
pupil of Plato, who wished to advertise his saw the critique as valid against Socrates
master’s ideals of philosophical literature’ but as not applying to himself and therefore
(Slings 1981:257). sought through the dialogue to distance him-
Whether one follows Slings in 1981 or self from Socrates (Stefanini 1932:I.192–3,
Slings in 1999, the question of the meaning 204, 206–7); (c) that Plato saw the critique
and purpose of the dialogue of course remains. as unanswerable but not damning; for exam-
Even if one believes for stylistic reasons that ple, Roochnik holds that there can be no
the dialogue was not written by Plato, one response to Clitophon because Clitophon is a
could still hold that ‘The Clitophon is written radical relativist and philosophy is incapable
from a wholly Platonic point of view’ (Slings of refuting radical relativism (1984:139–42);
1999:227; see also 127) and therefore could (d) that the dialogue implies an answer to
have been written only by a student who fully the critique and can for some reason only
understood Plato’s aims (Slings 1999:231). imply it. Since Clitophon’s case rests on
Indeed, apparently the only reason for the a sharp dichotomy between protreptic as
switch in Slings’ position between 1981 and what turns one to the pursuit of virtue, and
1999 is that he comes to find the hypothesis teaching as what provides virtue, one way of
of such a perfect pupil too far-fetched. But defending the fourth option is to argue that
then we are back to our question: why would the dialogue wants us to question, weaken
either Plato or a faithful pupil write an unan- and perhaps even reject this dichotomy. For
swered critique of Socrates? example, Gaiser (1959) and Gonzalez (2002)
One other external solution has been pro- argue that Socrates’ protreptic is constructive
posed: the absence of a concluding response because it is capable itself of in some way
to Clitophon’s criticism has led many mod- providing the virtue towards which it turns
ern scholars (though apparently no one in one. Since virtue, as such a process, cannot
antiquity) to the view that the Clit. is unfin- be taught to someone who, like Clitophon,
ished. Slings (1999) documents the history belittles the process, Socrates’ silence at the
of this view (Slings 1999:10–13) and then end can be explained.
proceeds to present arguments against it Nonetheless, even if the Clit. were neither
(ibid.:13–18). One argument appears espe- by Plato nor Platonic in content, it would
cially strong: through his ironic assump- still be a valuable record of an ancient cri-
tion that Clitophon’s praise and blame will tique of Plato’s Socrates that is undoubt-
accurately describe his strengths and weak- edly shared by many readers of the Socratic
nesses, Socrates shows at the very beginning dialogues today and hence merits serious
of the dialogue that he intends to make no consideration.

45

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 45 3/8/2001 5:12:39 PM


THE DIALOGUES

CRATYLUS we next agree to call them the other way


around, ‘man’ will be the correct name of
Robbert van den Berg a horse and vice versa. Against this thesis,
In the Cratylus Socrates explores the thesis of Socrates argues as follows. There exist sta-
the eponymous character that the correctness ble natures of things and actions, which may
of names (orthotês tôn onomatôn) depends be used as criteria against which to judge
uniquely on nature (physis) and does not particular things or actions: a good knife is
involve convention (nomos) in any way. a knife that has been made in accordance
Names in this context include both personal with its nature and thus performs its func-
names (e.g. ‘Socrates’) and common names tion of cutting well. The same holds for
(e.g. ‘horse’). The issue of the correctness of an activity. Therefore, if names are tools
names was a topic discussed in Sophistic cir- and naming is an activity, correct names
cles, as Socrates reminds his audience (Cra. and naming correctly depend on nature,
384a–b), yet his own discussion of it is clearly not on convention. Names are the tools of
informed by Plato’s own philosophical theo- (Platonic) dialecticians, who use them to
ries, including that of the forms (q.v.). In part teach by dividing up reality. A correct name
for this reason the Cra. is often considered to functions as a didactic tool since it is some-
belong to the middle period dialogues that how capable of expressing the nature of its
were written before the Republic (q.v.), even object. A name does so because of its ‘form’
though some scholars tend to date it later, (eidos). This name-form is best understood
while it is also possible that Plato at a later as the meaning of a word. The name-form
time in his career updated an earlier version is the same in all languages, be it that it is
of the text (Sedley 2003:6–14). expressed in different pieces of phonetic
The dialogue can be divided into three matter (i.e. in the sounds of the various lan-
parts. In the first part Socrates examines, guages). Take the names for horse in Greek
together with Hermogenes, Cratylus’ rid- and English: the sounds ‘hippos’ and ‘horse’
dling claim that the correctness of names may be different, yet they contain the same
depends on nature alone and that this cor- name-form, that is, they both mean the same
rectness is the same for those who speak thing. Note that even though the name-form
Greek and other languages alike. Cratylus ‘horse’ is somehow related to the nature,
refuses to clarify his position and during that is, form of horse, these forms are not
the greatest part of the dialogue stands by identical. The name ‘horse’ is after all not
silently while Socrates attempts to make itself a horse (Kretzmann 1971:130).
sense of his claim. Elsewhere (Theaetetus In the second part of the dialogue Socrates
179e–80c; q.v.), this behaviour is associated shows how names may actually instruct us:
with the followers of Heraclitus and at the when analysed correctly they reveal the rea-
very end of the dialogue Cratylus indeed sons of the name-givers of old to name the
declares himself to be one. Socrates starts by things as they did. The gods, for example,
refuting Hermogenes’ view that the correct- are called theoi because the visible gods,
ness of names is merely a matter of conven- that is, the heavenly bodies, can be seen to
tion. Hermogenes holds that when we agree ‘run’ (thein, 397c–d). Modern scholarship
to call one type of animal ‘man’ and another frequently refers to this type of analysis as
‘horse’, these are their correct names. When ‘etymology’, originally a Stoic term, and

46

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 46 3/8/2001 5:12:39 PM


THE DIALOGUES

which should not be confused with etymol- however, turns a deaf ear to Socrates’ appeal
ogy in the modern sense. Socrates contin- to investigate the matter and leaves.
ues to produce a massive collection of these What, then, is the bottom line of the Cra.?
etymologies, the function of which has been Many scholars assume that it is the condem-
much debated in recent scholarship. In part, nation of etymology as a source of knowl-
it is certainly intended to criticize widespread edge. The Cra., however, is not just about the
contemporary attempts to derive a deeper philosophical abuse of names, but also about
understanding of the nature of things by their proper use. Dialectic is the method to
studying their names (Baxter 1992:86–163), investigate things for ourselves – precisely
yet Socrates’ etymologies seem too good to what Cratylus declines to do – and names are
be merely a parody (see Barney 2001:49–80; the instruments by means of which this is to
Sedley 2003:75–146). be done, as the Eleatic visitor demonstrates
It is only in the third and final part (Cra. in the Sophist and the Statesman (Van den
427d ff.), though, when he finally manages Berg 2008:8–13).
to draw Cratylus into the discussion, that
Socrates openly criticizes etymology as a
source of knowledge. Having seemingly vin-
dicated Cratylus’ claim, Socrates now con- CRITO
fronts him with the fact that just as portraits
allow for degrees of likeness, so names may Charles M. Young
have varying degrees of correctness. When a In 399 BCE, Socrates of Athens was tried
name is in certain respects unlike its object, and convicted of impiety, and given the
however, it may still continue to function death penalty. Plato’s Crito purports to
as a name, since we still understand what it relate a conversion between Socrates and a
refers to. Socrates puts this down to conven- friend and age-mate, Crito, shortly before
tion, which thus appears to play a role in the Socrates’ execution is to be carried out.
correctness of names after all. We judge the After some preliminary banter (Cri. 43a1–
degree of correctness of names by compar- 4b5), at times poignant (see esp. 44a1–b5),
ing them to the things themselves. But if we Crito urges Socrates to take advantage of
have direct access to the things themselves, plans that Crito and others have made to
why bother about examining them indirectly secure Socrates’ escape (44b5–6a8). As
by etymologizing their names? More in par- considerations in favour of Socrates’ acqui-
ticular, Socrates asks Cratylus to reconsider escence, Crito first claims (a) that Socrates’
his Heracleitean belief that everything is for- execution will cost Crito an irreplaceable
ever in flux. For, from Socrates’ etymologies friend (44b6–8) and (b) that it will make
it had emerged that the ancient name-givers Crito look bad in the eyes of the many,
all subscribed to Heraclitus’ flux doctrine. whether deservedly so or not (44b9–c5). He
Yet, since they may well have been mistaken, also alleges (c) that Socrates would be doing
we should investigate for ourselves the ques- wrong in allowing his enemies to succeed
tion whether Heraclitus was right or that in bringing about his death when he need
there exist at least some unchanging entities not do so (45c5–8); (d) that it would also
such as beauty (q.v.) itself, a rather explicit be wrong to abandon his children to the
reference to the theory of forms. Cratylus, fate of orphans (45c8–d8); and, to sum up,

47

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 47 3/8/2001 5:12:40 PM


THE DIALOGUES

(e) that if the execution takes place, every- The Laws’ speech is dense, complex and
one – Socrates and all his friends – will have highly rhetorical. But they do want to be
behaved badly in every stage of the busi- understood, and so they tell us at 51e how
ness (45d8–6a4). In between these points in to disentangle their various lines of thought.
favour of escaping, Crito tries to defuse var- They say that he who disobeys them does
ious points against escaping, arguing that wrong in three ways, because he disobeys us
the costs to himself and others for aiding who are his parents, because he disobeys us
and abetting the escape would be minimal who are his benefactors and because he diso-
(45a6–b7) and that Socrates will be safe in beys the laws without persuading them that
exile (45b7–c4). they are in some way wrong. By this they
Socrates responds by moving to the level mean that they have three arguments leading
of principle (46b1–c6). Ignoring (a) as irrel- to the conclusion that he who disobeys does
evant, he first disposes of Crito’s opinion, wrong, one involving an alleged similarity
explicit in (b) and implicit in (e), that it mat- between the Laws and one’s parents, another
ters what other people think (46c6–7c7). appealing to the fact that the laws have ben-
He also ignores (c) and (d), except for their efited him and a third invoking an agreement
presupposition that it matters whether what they think he has made to ‘persuade or obey’
one is doing is right or wrong. In fact, he (hereafter, simply ‘obey’) them.
argues, given (f) that what really matters is The Laws’ strategy in each of these three
living well and rightly (48b3–9); the only arguments is the same. They take obligations
thing that matters in acting is whether one is that anyone will agree one has – that it is
doing right or wrong (48b12–c2), with doing wrong (a) to harm or do violence to (hereaf-
wrong understood to include harming people ter, simply ‘harm’) one’s parents, (b) to harm
(49c7–8). Thus he reaches the conclusion (g) one’s benefactors and (c) not to do what
that one should never do wrong (49b8) and one has agreed to do – and argue that each
the question whether Socrates should diso- applies to a citizen who disobeys the law.
bey the law according to which the judge-
ments of courts are authoritative (50b6–8) (1) Since it is wrong to harm one’s parents
and escape comes down to the question (51c2), and worse to harm the laws than
whether it would be right for him to escape to harm one’s parents (51c1–2) and diso-
(48b11–c2). beying the law harms the laws (50a9–b5),
To settle this question, Socrates advances it is wrong to disobey.
a further principle: (h) that one should do (2) Since it is wrong to harm one’s benefac-
what one has agreed to do (49e6–7). He also tors (unstated), and the laws are one’s
suggests (j) that escaping would harm those benefactors (see 50d5–e1; see also 50e2
least deserving of harm (49e9–50a3) and and 51c7–d1) and disobeying the laws
(k) that escaping would involve breaking an harms the laws (50a9–b5), it is wrong to
agreement (50a2–3). Crito accepts (h) but disobey.
pleads incomprehension in the face of (j) and (3) Since it is wrong not to do what one has
(k). Socrates then at 50a8–4d1 personifies agreed to do (borrowed from Socrates at
the Laws of Athens and imagines what they 49e6–7), and a citizen has agreed to obey
might say to him if he did choose to disobey the laws (51e1–4), it is wrong for a citi-
the law. zen to disobey.

48

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 48 3/8/2001 5:12:40 PM


THE DIALOGUES

When Crito has no response to these argu- Brickhouse and Smith (1994:sec. 5.2), Kraut
ments, Socrates decides to remain in prison (1984:ch. 3) and Young (1997).
and await his execution (54e1–2).
Several points about these arguments are
worthy of note. First, the first argument
does not depend on the idea that it is wrong DUBIA AND SPURIA
to disobey one’s parents (pace Brickhouse
and Smith 1994:143–9; Kraut 1984:92– John Dillon
103). It rather depends on the idea that it A notable feature of the Platonic Corpus
is wrong to harm one’s parents; suitably (like some other ancient collections) is the
qualified, this has a chance of being true. inclusion of works the majority of modern
Second, Socrates himself thinks that harm- scholars – and in some cases ancient schol-
ing is always wrong; the Laws say only that ars – deem spurious. Suspected works include
harming one’s parents or one’s benefactors is Alcibiades I, Clitophon, Epinomis (often
wrong; their claims, suitably qualified, have credited in antiquity to Philippus of Opus,
a better chance of being true than Socrates’. probably correctly) and even Hippias Major;
This is one reason to think that the Laws their authenticity has also found defenders in
may not speak for Socrates; for others, see recent years, some strenuous. This article con-
Young 2006: notes 4, 8 and 11. Third, (1) centrates on two further categories to be cov-
and (2) depend on the idea that disobey- ered here: (a) works now almost universally
ing causes harm; (3) does not. So to win regarded as un-Platonic, but included by the
the day, the Laws need only the claim that first-century CE editor Thrasyllus in his tetra-
disobeying causes harm or the claim that logical system (and hence classified as dubia);
a citizen has agreed to obey them, but not and (b) works which had in antiquity been
both. Finally, the requirement to obey enters relegated to an Appendix (and so categorized
into all three arguments. But according to as spuria). The former group comprises the
(1) and (2), one is alleged to have an obliga- following: Alc. II, Amatores (or Anterastae,
tion to obey because of the consequences of ‘Rivals in Love’), Hipparchus, Theages,
disobeying (the harm such failure causes), Minos; the latter: Axiochus, Definitions,
whereas according to (3), the obligation to On Justice, On Virtue, Demodocus, Eryxias,
obey is itself alleged to be a consequence of Sisyphus. They vary from the relatively well
one’s having agreed to obey. turned and interesting to the schematic and
Nearly everything about the Cri. is contro- simpleminded. I will deal with them in turn,
versial. Perhaps the most important questions after first contributing some reflections on
are how to understand Socrates’ defence of the composition of the corpus as a whole.
his idea (g) that one should never do wrong We cannot be sure whether any dubia,
(49b8) and how to understand the Laws’ for example, Epin., Hp. Ma., Clit. or Alc. I,
claim that a citizen is required to ‘persuade were already incorporated in the original edi-
or obey’ them (51b3–4, 51b9–c1 and 51e7). tion of Plato’s works, probably put together
For a sense of the range of interpretative under Xenocrates (Alline 1915:46–50) and,
options for the first question, see Gomez- if so, on what grounds. Xenocrates may have
Lobo (1999:chs 6–9), Vlastos (1991a:chs welcomed such documents as useful prod-
7–8) and Young (1997). For the second, see ucts of the Academy, compatible with what

49

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 49 3/8/2001 5:12:40 PM


THE DIALOGUES

Plato would have accepted, and thus the edi- subversion of this in a ‘Socratic’ direction. A
tion was not intentionally confined to Plato’s distinctly ‘Xenophontic’ (i.e. rather senten-
works. We should try to penetrate the state of tious) Socrates, starting from this Stoicizing
mind of whoever initially included these and position, proceeds to argue that it is actually
other works that we do not deem genuine, better not to possess ‘technical’ knowledge
and of whose origin they must surely have unless one also knows what is best, that is,
been aware. If the concept of an official Old how and when best to apply one’s knowl-
Academic edition or collection is rejected, edge (Alc. II 146e–7d). The work exhibits
the next candidate will be Aristophanes of echoes of Alc. I; so, it must postdate Alc. I. It
Byzantium (c. 257–180 BCE), second Head is probably a product of the New Academy,
of the Alexandrian Library, who arranged at designed to upstage the Stoics.
least fifteen of the dialogues into trilogies. Rather different is the case of Amat., the
However, since Aristophanes only arranged topic of which, as indicated in its subtitle, is
some dialogues, he hardly concerned himself the nature of ‘philosophy’. Couched in a nar-
with dubia or spuria, but internal evidence rative by Socrates (on the model of Charmides
(both of language and of philosophical con- or Lysis), this involves a dispute between
tent, including antistoic themes) suggests that two rivals in love whom Socrates engages
many of them crept into the corpus some- over the relative merits of physical training
how during the period of the New Academy. (gymnastikê) or cultural pursuits (mous-
Otherwise, prior to Thrasyllus, we have only ikê). The supporter of the latter, who defines
the shadowy Dercyllides (Albinus, Isagoge 4) philosophy as the acquisition of ever more
to whom one might plausibly attribute the technical knowledge (Amat. 133c), might be
tetralogical arrangement, but we have no expected to find support from Socrates, but
idea what his contribution may have been. Socrates cuts him down, by dismissing this in
We must, however, assume that during favour of the ideal of self-knowledge. Unlike
the evolution of our corpus, works which Alc. II, this could be a product of the later
were plainly not Platonic (e.g. Alc. II, Just., Old Academy, and embodies an attack on
Virt. or Demod.) were admitted to the col- Peripatetic philosophy, which could be seen
lection, albeit in a subordinate capacity, by as encouraging polymathia.
editors aware of their spuriousness, who felt Hipparch., about which doubts were
that they contributed to Platonist doctrine, expressed by Aelian (Varia Historia VIII.2), is
perhaps as teaching aids for beginners (a a curious production, involving a disputation
role later played by both Alc. I and Thg.). At of Socrates with an unnamed ‘companion’ on
any rate, we need not imagine that ancient the moral status of ‘gain’ (kerdos). The com-
editors or readers, either of these or of the panion begins with a simpleminded denun-
collected Epistles, were necessarily deceived ciation of the money-grubber, or ‘lover of
concerning their status. gain’, which Socrates then picks apart by get-
The topic of the short Alc. II is overtly (as ting him to agree that gain is useful, and so,
represented by its subtitle in MSS), ‘prayer’ is a good, and all men desire it. The dialogue
(proseukhê) – Socrates finds Alcibiades on acquires its name not from a participant, but
his way to offer a prayer to the gods – but in from the Athenian tyrant Hipparchus, son
reality it concerns rather the Stoic ‘paradox’ of Peisistratus, who is dragged into the dis-
that all those not wise are mad, and then the cussion as the author of the precept ‘Do not

50

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 50 3/8/2001 5:12:40 PM


THE DIALOGUES

deceive a friend’. The purpose of the work consolation-literature. It may be dated to the
seems dialectical rather than ‘ethical’, which last period of the New Academy.
would be consistent with a New Academic Def. was attributed in ancient times to
date. Speusippus (Anon. Proleg. 26), and an item
Thg. is more polished, centring on a request by that name is listed among his works by
by Socrates’ old friend Demodocus for advice Diogenes Laertius (D. L. 4.5), but what we
on the education of his son Theages, who is have seems rather to be a product of multiple
badgering him to be allowed to study state- authorship. It consists of a list of 185 defini-
craft with a sophist. The employment of the tions of philosophical terms, in no obvious
Socratic elenchus is here rather ham-handed, order and often providing multiple explana-
as is usual in doubtful works, but its most un- tions. More precisely, there is a first section
Platonic aspect is a long speech by Socrates (Def. 411a–14e), in which the terms are
concerning his daimonion, or divine sign. arranged according to the scholastic division
The statement that its influence is always of philosophy, first formalized by Xenocrates,
negative is Platonic enough, but Socrates’ into physics, ethics and logic (including epis-
description of its power in respect of his temology), followed by a somewhat shorter
would-be students, is quite un-Platonic. It section (414e–16d), exhibiting no order
seems designed almost to elevate Socrates to whatever. While it may partly originate with
the status of a divine man. It could, from the Speusippus, it has the appearance of a work
linguistic and stylistic point of view, conceiv- to which anyone could add, and a number of
ably be a product of the Old Academy, but the definitions reflect Stoic formulations.
may be much later. Its genuineness, however, Just. and Virt. are among several dia-
was never doubted in antiquity. logues described as akephaloi (‘headless’) in
Min. is a brief discussion between Socrates a list preserved by Diogenes Laertius (3.57),
and an unnamed companion, and begins with which contained many lost works along
an attempt to define ‘law’. There is a central with Halcyon (a lively little work, preserved
digression involving the excellent education in the corpus of Lucian, though much ear-
given directly by Zeus to Minos, the legen- lier). ‘Headless’ cannot mean simply that
dary Cretan law giver, from whom the work they lack a frame-story or conversation,
gets its name. Superficially it serves as a more since that is common. It highlights rather
Socratic introduction to the topic of Laws, their extreme lack of any introductory ele-
but its dialectical nature and structure are ment. The Just. begins ‘Can you tell me what
reminiscent of Hipparch. is the just?’, and the Virt., ‘Is virtue some-
Among works relegated to the Appendix as thing teachable?’ In either case, Socrates
spuria, Ax. takes the form of a protreptikos, is presented as addressing an anonymous
calculated to dispel the fear of death, in which interlocutor. Both dialogues last for just
Socrates, at the urging of Cleinias, delivers a over three pages. In the former, we are faced
discourse to Cleinias’ father Axiochus, who mainly with a scholastic exercise in method,
thinks that he is dying. It is well composed but the conclusion is reached that no one is
and quite lively, but its language is notably willingly unjust. In the latter, Socrates con-
un-Platonic, many forms being otherwise cludes that virtue is neither teachable nor a
unattested before late Hellenistic times. It gift of nature. These may be no more than
also draws upon an established tradition of student exercises, drawing respectively on

51

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 51 3/8/2001 5:12:41 PM


THE DIALOGUES

such works as Gorgias, Republic bk 1 and that town, Sisyphus, who had to miss an
Men., and cannot be dated. interesting talk by the musician Stratonicus
Demod. is also ‘headless’. It falls into the previous day by reason of having to
four parts, only the first of which explicitly attend a meeting of the City Council. The
involves Demodocus (father of Theages). wisdom of consulting with one’s peers, irre-
This part comprises an argument by Socrates spective of their expertise or wisdom, had
against the coherence of the concept of tak- plainly become something of a topos in the
ing counsel together (symbouleuesthai). The Hellenistic period, if not before. This would
other three parts address other questions seem to be a product of the New Academic
of ‘practical ethics’: (a) is it right to con- period.
demn someone after listening only to their
accuser? (b) who is at fault (hamartanei),
he who asks unsuccessfully for a loan or he
who refuses? (c) in whom is it better to put EUTHYDEMUS
one’s trust, in strangers or in friends and rela-
tions? The arguments appear to be exercises Monique Dixsaut
in ‘equipollence’, and compatible with the The Euthydemus is entirely governed by
New Academy rather than with the Platonic ambiguity. The Socratic art of argument, dia-
tradition. lectic (q.v.), is introduced facing its double,
Eryx. concerns the ethical status of wealth, the art of ‘fighting with words’ or eristic. The
and the nature of true wealth, consequent aim is to bring their differences to the fore,
on Socrates and a group of friends viewing but the dialogue also reveals to what extent
a Syracusan ambassador – described as the their practises are formally identical. The
richest man in Sicily, but also the wickedest. characters move in couples: Euthydemus and
Socrates argues that only the wise man is rich, his elder brother Dionysodorus, who late in
while Critias counters that without some life have discovered the most refined version
wealth one cannot even exercise one’s wis- of pancratium, the art of refuting any asser-
dom. Socrates, however, comes back with the tion whether true or false; young Cleinias
argument that riches are only advantageous and his lover Ctesippus, Socrates and Crito,
to those who know how to use them, viz. or Socrates (who relates) and Socrates (who
the wise. The dialogue is well composed and dialogues). A conversation between Socrates
exhibits no distinctively late features. It has and Crito at the beginning and at the end
been argued that the examination of the dis- provides the framework of the dialogue:
tinctively Stoic thesis that ‘only the wise man Socrates’ long account of the discussion he
is rich’ necessitates a New Academic prov- had the previous day. It is divided into three
enance, but the theme of the self-sufficiency eristic sections separated by two dialectical
of virtue was also explored in the Academy ones.
under Polemon. The two sophists pretend that they can
The Sis., lastly, is concerned, like Demod. I, teach excellence (q.v.; aretê) and exhort
with the theme of ‘taking counsel’. The scene anyone to philosophize, the rules being that
appears to be set, most oddly, not in Athens, the interlocutor agrees to answer, that he
but in Pharsalus in Thessaly, where Socrates does not answer by means of another ques-
is conversing with a prominent citizen of tion and that he adds no determination or

52

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 52 3/8/2001 5:12:41 PM


THE DIALOGUES

qualification, thus committing a ‘parapht- Socrates is quite familiar with the latter argu-
egm’. In order to make a demonstration ment, having heard it from the followers of
(epideixis) of their ‘protreptic’ knowledge, Protagoras, but the Socratic Antisthenes may
the sophists first ask Cleinias whether those be the target (Brancacci 2005:217–23). Since
who learn are wise or ignorant, and whether their teaching has turned out to consist in
they learn what they know or what they do nothing but refutation, the sophists make
not know. By compelling the boy to agree themselves ridiculous when they argue that
that in any case it is impossible to learn, refutation is impossible.
the two brothers state from the outset what Before resuming his discussion with
essentially differentiates them from the phi- Cleinias, so as to give an example of how a
losopher: a sophist never learns anything, dialogue should be conducted, Socrates insists
whatever the length of time he spends ‘rolling that the sophists must be listened to because,
about among arguments’ (Sophist 264a2). in spite of everything, they urge one to phi-
Due to his refusal to cram his memory with losophize (that is probably the reason why,
what he may have said, he is doomed to an the day before, his daimonion had prevented
indefinitely repetitive present. Socrates from leaving the palestra). The high-
Socrates explains to a perplexed Cleinias est good has been identified with a knowledge
that the sophists are only preparing him to that must be both a science of production
find out about ‘the correctness of names’, and and a science of use, but now neither the art
then he questions the boy in his turn to give particular to the orator nor the art of leading
the conversation a more serious turn. Both men (strategy or politics) fulfils that demand.
agree that all men certainly wish to be happy For just as the general does not know what
(eu prattein) and believe that it means hav- to do with his quarry and hands it over to the
ing many good things, but Socrates shows statesman, so the geometer hands his to the
that what matters is not possessing them, for dialectician, Cleinias explains (Crito doubts
nothing can benefit us unless we make good Cleinias could have said that, and Socrates is
use of it. Since nothing can bring about right not quite sure he did: the story comes to us
use except knowledge (epistêmê), knowledge as filtered all along through ‘Socrates’ ironic
(q.v.) is in fact the only good worth having. screen’) (Friedländer 1964:179). A royal art
But the nature of such knowledge remains has emerged into view, but if it makes men
unspecified. good and useful, that will be only thanks to
Socrates then surrenders the conversation a knowledge which has no object but itself,
to the two eristics, who seize the occasion to that is, the art of making others good and
complement a first series of paradoxes follow- useful (cf. Charmides 166e ff.). Socrates is no
ing from the sophistic theory of logos. Each more a teacher than the sophist since neither
single argument is cut to the familiar Eleatic of them is able to teach something.
pattern: ‘is’ and ‘is not’ obey a strict law of The eristics make a pretence of coming
contradiction, any middle being excluded. to the rescue. From Socrates’ admission that
So, to wish that Cleinias becomes virtuous is he knows one thing, they move on to the
to wish him not to be (i.e. not virtuous): to be conclusion that Socrates knows, has always
dead; similarly, knowing excludes every form known and will always know, everything.
of not knowing, hence the impossibility of Confounding that which is other with that
ignorance, false statement and contradiction. which is not, and using the equivocation of

53

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 53 3/8/2001 5:12:41 PM


THE DIALOGUES

words such as ‘his’ or ‘yours’, the sophists and passive, due measure, the existence of
establish that any man who is a father is a an opposite of being, sameness and differ-
father of all and that Ctesippus’ father is a ence, otherness and not being, etc. Each
dog. So the reader is led to understand the will prove to be dealt very seriously in later
necessity to introduce qualifications in the dialogues.
law of contradiction by specifying ‘when’ and When Socrates suggests again that Crito
‘to what respect’. Next it is the theory of par- and his sons should follow the eristics’
ticipation (q.v.) which comes in for its share teaching his friend remains reluctant. He
of derision: to say that a beautiful thing is does not seem to consider, however, that
beautiful because a certain beauty is present Socrates would be a decent teacher – a
with it (para) amounts to saying that if an doubt strengthened by the conversation he
ox is present with you, you are an ox. Since just had with ‘somebody’ who, after listen-
Socrates and the ox are both physical par- ing to the debate, has concluded that phi-
ticulars, the only possible mode of presence losophy ‘is worth nothing’. It hardly matters
is a physical one, and any difference between whether Isocrates is referred to here (as is
forms and particular objects is denied. probably the case) or not. Socrates con-
Dionysodorus’ ox is the comic equivalent structs an hybrid type who stands halfway
of Parmenides’ sail (Parmenides 131B–C; between philosophy and politics and claims
cf. Sprague 1962:29), and both point to the that his sophia betters that of those he calls
danger of using spatial terms like being ‘in’ ‘sophists’ (Dixsaut 1986), those to whom
or ‘over’: here, the sophists come nearest to philosophy deals only with words, not reali-
being philosophers. ties – and that it also betters the sophia of
Are those sophisms borrowed from some those to whom politics is just a question of
collection or from a treatise written by action. By borrowing from politics its ‘great
Euthydemus, or did Plato make them up subjects’, he wants to avoid the logomachy
himself? No one will ever know, but in any threatening any philosophical discussion,
case it is clear that he groups and connects while at the same time he refrains from get-
them after a strategy of his own, and in such ting involved in the dangers and fights of
a way as to provide a key to them. While public life. Socrates does not tackle the heart
Aristotle’s Soph. El. proceeds according of the matter and seems to hold that a logic
to an ordered listing of the causes of par- of the value of the intermediate (metaxu)
alogisms, Plato is more interested in their is enough to refute this anonymous char-
content: the problems they raise. Socrates acter, since it shows that what stands mid-
clarifies the semantic equivocation of learn- way between two good things is inferior to
ing (manthanein), ‘acquiring knowledge’ or both.
‘understanding’, but for him the difficulty The outcome of the dialogue is the rejec-
remains and will be solved only by ventur- tion of philosophy conceived as the pursuit
ing the hypothesis of reminiscence (Meno of an eristic as well as a rhetorical sophia.
80e f.). The Eleatic denial of change and Dialectic alone has the power of converting
becoming, along with an eristic technique, the souls of those who, like Cleinias, are able
is applied to major problems of Plato’s phi- to learn by themselves, which is arguably the
losophy: learning, is virtue teachable, forms only possible meaning in Plato of the word
and participation, capacity (dunamis) active ‘protreptic’.

54

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 54 3/8/2001 5:12:41 PM


THE DIALOGUES

EUTHYPHRO not dear to them or hated by them (6e–7a).


Third, he suggests that the holy is what is
Roslyn Weiss dear to all the gods (9e). Fourth, that the holy
Plato’s Euthyphro raises the question, ‘What is tendance (therapeia) of the gods (12e). And
is holiness?’, one of the many ‘What is x?’ fifth, that it is providing service or assistance
questions that are central to Socrates’ con- (hupêretikê) to the gods through prayer and
versations with his interlocutors. (Other dia- sacrifice (13d–14c).
logues explore the nature of virtue, justice, Each of Euthyphro’s attempts at defini-
courage, temperance and friendship.) The tion is thwarted by a fatal Socratic objection.
Euthphr.’s question is prompted by Socrates’ The first, as Socrates sees it, hardly qualifies
indictment in 399 BCE on the charge of as a definition at all: it offers an example of
impiety (and of corrupting the youth), which holiness but misses its core. Geach (1966),
brings him to the court of the King Archon objects to Socrates’ dismissal of Euthyphro’s
where he fortuitously meets Euthyphro who first definition, challenging what has come to
is there to prosecute his father for murder. be known as Socrates’ priority of definition
Euthyphro’s justification for prosecuting his principle. Geach contends that there is little
father relies on an odd mixture of principle reason to believe that one cannot know any-
and self-serving protectionism (McPherran thing, and hence that one cannot give exam-
2005; for Weiss 1994:263–4, it is mainly ples of anything, before or without knowing
the latter; so, too for Burnet 1924:23). In its ‘essence’. The second falls short in that it
Allen’s view (1970:23), Euthyphro is con- specifies a definition not exclusively of the
cerned for his father’s purity as well as for holy but of what is both holy and not holy –
his own). Although Euthyphro speaks of a since some gods may well love what others
duty to prosecute anyone who has commit- hate. The third is found lacking because even
ted injustice, he is concerned about the pollu- if all the gods love the same thing, that accord
tion (miasma) that affects the close associates remains accidental or coincidental; indeed,
of the offender. He emulates Zeus, the god when the gods are not themselves just, it
he regards as most powerful, never question- makes little difference whether or not they
ing the justice of Zeus’ own slaying of his all agree (Friedländer 1964:87). Moreover,
father. Euthyphro’s arrogant confidence in unless there is something inherently holy in
his expertise concerning the gods’ ways and the object of the gods’ love by virtue of which
their likes and dislikes make him a fit target all the gods love it, their loving it is irrelevant
for Socrates’ withering elenchus. On the pre- to its status as holy. The fourth fails because
tence that only instruction in holiness or piety the gods do not need, and do not stand to
by Euthyphro will save him from death by benefit from, anything human beings can
hemlock, Socrates turns to him for enlighten- provide. And the last collapses because the
ment as to the nature of the holy. prayer and sacrifice involved in tending the
Euthyphro tries to oblige. His first attempt gods reduce to a commercial exchange and
to define the holy yields: ‘The holy is what ultimately to a means of pleasing the gods –
I am doing now’ (Euthphr. 5d–e), namely, and so are tantamount to a return to the first
prosecuting anyone who commits injus- definition. The dialogue’s significance and
tice. His second proposal is that the holy is continued relevance owe much to its pivotal
what is dear to the gods, the unholy what is argument in which Socrates asks Euthyphro,

55

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 55 3/8/2001 5:12:41 PM


THE DIALOGUES

‘Is a thing holy because the gods love it, or and related secondary literature (Wolfsdorf
do the gods love it because it is holy?’ In the 2005:32–49) faults Plato for taking being
hands of the ethicists and theologians who seen and being loved as states that involve
later appropriated this question, right and change. For a defence of Plato and the ambi-
wrong were substituted for the holy, as fol- tiousness of his project, see Judson (2010).
lows: are right and wrong determined by Vlastos (1991a) sees in this central argument
god’s will and command (a view known as of the dialogue a rejection of the traditional,
voluntarism), or do the divine will and com- or ‘magical’, Greek religious understanding
mand reflect what is (independently) right of the gods as essentially powerful and capri-
and wrong? The Euthphr. strongly suggests cious beings who need to be pampered and
that the latter is the case: god may apprehend placated.
what is good and just but that does not make One lingering question is whether any
it so. acceptable definition of holiness emerges
The argument proceeds by distinguish- from the Euthphr. Might holiness indeed be
ing between a thing’s being god-loved (the- the assistance human beings provide to the
ophiles) and its being holy: a thing attains its gods in producing a noble product (Euthphr.
character as god-loved by the gods’ loving it 13d–14a)? If so, the nature of that prod-
(just as a thing acquires the status of being a uct needs to be specified: a likely candidate
carried thing by virtue of someone’s carrying would be human virtue. Socrates in the
it), but a thing’s being holy does not await the Apology (29e–30b) certainly portrays him-
gods’ loving it; on the contrary, it is its holi- self as the god’s servant or messenger whose
ness that inspires the gods’ love. Some schol- task it is to encourage those he encounters
ars – for example, Friedländer (1964:87); to care above all for prudence, truth and the
McPherran (1985:289) – have credited virtuous state of their souls. Perhaps he is, for
Euthyphro with successfully identifying if not this reason, a paragon of piety.
the ousia (essence) of the holy, then at least a
relevant pathos (attribute) (Euthphr. 11a–b).
Yet, all Socrates says in fact is that Euthyphro
has spoken in pathos- (as opposed to ousia-) GORGIAS
terms – not that the pathos he has provided is
a correct one. The best-known reconstruction Harold Tarrant
(and critique) of this argument is Cohen’s The Gorgias is a work of ethics with impor-
(1971). In Cohen’s view, Socrates has proved tant political implications. Political questions
not that the holy cannot be defined as god- generally cause Plato to write at greatest
loved, but that it cannot be defined as god- length, as in Republic and Laws. Grg. is
loved when the gods’ reason for loving it is accordingly the longest of his single-book
that it is holy. Geach (1966), too, is critical dialogues, and not unexpectedly shows con-
of the argument; he contends that the gods siderable complexity, both in its philosophic
love a thing not because it is holy but because ideas and in their literary presentation. There
they know or believe it to be so; moreover, are three interlocutors, Gorgias the rhetorical
there is no reason that they could not love teacher, Polus his pupil and the writer of a rhe-
what is intended to please them. A recent torical handbook and Callicles, an otherwise
and thorough discussion of the argument unknown Athenian with undisguised political

56

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 56 3/8/2001 5:12:41 PM


THE DIALOGUES

ambitions. Also present, and contrasted with hard to satisfy Socrates’ requirements for a
Gorgias’ understudy Polus, is Socrates’ com- definition that excludes all other practises.
panion Chaerephon. Anachronistic refer- It transpires that it is productive of mass
ences to Archelaus of Macedon obscure a persuasion concerning matters of justice,
setting in the 420s (Tarrant 2008). injustice and the like, but does not profess
Like other putatively ‘early’ dialogues, to impart knowledge (455a). Pointing to the
Grg. contains long stretches of Socratic walls and dockyards of Athens as examples of
argument known as elenchus (q.v.), but is rhetoric’s power (455d–6a) Gorgias seems to
perhaps the first to show Socrates (a) reflect- impress Socrates, who politely conceals his
ing on the nature of proper elenctic prac- true evaluation of such ‘defences’ until 519a.
tise (metaelenctic: Grg. 473b–5e, 505d–6a, Socrates pounces at 457c when Gorgias
508e–9b), (b) going over the steps of an refers to people who use rhetoric for unjust
argument with an imaginary rather than a purposes. Does this mean that they have not
real interlocutor (506b–7c), (c) explaining a been taught regarding what was allegedly
complicated theory of real and false crafts of the subject matter of rhetoric, including jus-
his own involving dichotomic classification tice? Gorgias is shamed into answering and
(464b–6a) and (d) twice assuming the role of agreeing that any pupil of rhetoric who does
myth-teller (493a–c, 523a–4a), while using not know what justice is could learn it from
myths to illustrate a view of his own. him (460a). This Socrates finds inconsistent
The dialogue moves from polite but tough with the view that teachers should not be
engagement with Gorgias (whose concern is blamed for unjust uses – though it is doubt-
the reputation of his own discipline), through ful whether Gorgias meant to imply that this
somewhat impatient argument with the ‘learning’ of justice involved acquiring just
younger Polus (who is more intent on scoring habits.
points than on solving issues), to an urgent This infuriates Polus, who accuses
discussion of how one should live one’s life Socrates of boorishness, and is in turn lured
in the real world of fifth-century Athens with into a conversation, in which he asks ques-
the somewhat better-intentioned Callicles. tions – following Socrates’ prompts. Socrates
The futures of Socrates (486a4–d1) and of explains that he regards rhetoric as a non-sci-
Callicles (526e1–7a4) are both at stake. As entific knack rather than an art (q.v.), since
in Theaetetus, the material becomes increas- it aims at the pleasure of the listeners rather
ingly challenging as the dialogue progresses, than at their benefit. It competes with justice,
making scholars wonder why it is named the genuine art of restoring psychic health.
after Gorgias rather than Callicles, the domi- The disjunction of what is (for the present)
nant interlocutor for three fifths of the work pleasant and what is genuinely good is vital
(481b6–527e7). to the dialogue, central to the explanation
The dialogue opens with Socrates and of the term ‘fine’ or ‘honourable’ (kalon) at
Chaerephon arriving too late for Gorgias’ 474d–5a and the following argument about
demonstration of his rhetorical skills. Gorgias why doing injustice is worse than receiving
agrees to answer some of Socrates’ questions, it; central to the dispute between Socrates
and Chaerephon is told to ask what Gorgias and Callicles about how life should be lived
is, that is, what profession he practises. Polus at 495a–9b; and central to Socrates’ view of
tries to answer, but even Gorgias finds it the shortcomings of Athenian politicians.

57

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 57 3/8/2001 5:12:42 PM


THE DIALOGUES

Polus, shocked to hear Socrates deny that satisfying the desires and identifying pleasure
rhetoric is a fine thing, resumes the theme of and the good. Socrates counters with myth,
rhetoric’s power, as evidenced by the slick- didactic images and two powerful arguments
speaking tyrant’s unrestrained opportunity against the hedonistic thesis (493a–9b).
for injustice. Distinguishing between what Callicles, he claims, has failed to see the
one (genuinely) wants and what one should importance of orderliness in the world and
do to achieve it, Socrates denies such per- in the human soul, which underpins all
sons’ power, since they mistake for ends human virtues. By vindicating the distinc-
the means by which they can achieve them tion between good and pleasure he renews
(467c–8e), so that tyrannical power is ‘unen- the attack on rhetoric (particularly Athenian
viable’ (469a). Polus ultimately claims that political rhetoric) as pleasure-giving flattery,
getting wronged is worse (kakion), yet less which fails to do what is good for citizens
fine/honourable (less kalon, i.e. aischion) and encourages their vices. Condemnation of
than wronging another (474c). Socrates him- Pericles and other democratic heroes presents
self would normally identify ‘good’ and ‘fine’ a radical and uncompromising challenge to
and hence ‘bad’ and ‘dishonourable’, but sug- democratic assumptions.
gests that Polus employs twin criteria when The final myth (523a–4a) speaks of
applying the terms ‘fine’ and ‘dishonour- Zeus’ introduction of the naked judgement
able’, goodness and pleasantness (474d–e). of the soul, so that nobody can avoid pun-
If wronging another is more dishonourable ishment by deception from Hades: identified
than getting wronged it should therefore be in the earlier myth with the unseen workings
either (a) worse or (b) more painful. But it is of the inner soul (493b). Whether the myth
less painful. Therefore it is better. Similarly really concerns punishment and cure in this
avoiding punishment is more dishonourable life or the next (Sedley 2009a), it offers an
than getting punished, so, being less painful, unreformed Callicles nothing to look for-
it is worse. Debate arises over whether the ward to.
argument is flawed (Klosko 1984; Vlastos The Grg. achieves a powerful philosophic
1967), but being ad hominem, it needs Polus unity, underpinned by its insights into the life
to refute it. Otherwise Socrates is free to con- and death of Socrates (Stauffer 2006); in so
clude for him that orators wanting the best doing it sees Socrates transformed from the
outcome should ensure that they and their tricky interrogator into an independent polit-
friends are punished for any injustices they ical thinker, armed with new tools of persua-
had committed (Grg. 480a). The underlying sion, the beginnings of a complex psychology
medical notion of injustice as disease that and a powerful vision of the role of justice
undermines its agent’s soul, and requires the and order in the world.
cure of punishment, fleshes out the picture.
Callicles’ entry introduces the sophistic dis-
tinction between what is naturally just, good
and fine, and what is conventionally so, and HIPPIAS MAJOR
with it an attack on the uselessness of philos-
ophy in the real world. He advocates pursuit Jacques Antoine Duvoisin
of natural justice, that is, becoming better off Socrates meets the sophist (q.v.) Hippias
in every respect than others, encouraging and somewhere in Athens and they discuss the

58

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 58 3/8/2001 5:12:42 PM


THE DIALOGUES

nature of to kalon (the beautiful, noble or pleasing through hearing and sight – leads
fine). to a lengthy digression on the meaning of
The dialogue begins with a discussion of the phrase ‘both and each’. Can two things
Hippias’ achievements as a private teacher together be something (fair, strong, just, etc.)
and as an envoy of his city. Socrates engages that each is not, or vice versa? Hippias thinks
in teasing flattery as well as some quite subtle not and tries to embarrass Socrates, accus-
wit at Hippias’ expense. This lays the ground- ing him of dialectical hairsplitting and fail-
work for the central theme of the main argu- ing to consider ‘the wholes of things’ (301b).
ment – How can anyone praise or blame Socrates gives a series of arithmetical exam-
anything without being able to articulate the ples (e.g. each is one but both together are
principle whereby one judges? – but also for two, both together are even but each one is
the dialogue’s central comic conceit. Socrates odd) which, while intriguing, do not further
invents an alter ego who chastises him for the the inquiry into the beautiful. The dialogue
flaws in the positions Hippias offers so as to ends, returning briefly to an earlier proposal:
protect Hippias’ enormous vanity from being what is pleasant through sight and hearing,
bruised in the interchange. which suggests that the beautiful is beneficial
This passage culminates in Hippias’ pleasure. But Socrates points out that this
account of his recent and popular exhibition fails for the same reason that the beneficial
in Sparta, which he intends to present 2 days failed earlier. Hippias laments the tendency of
later in Athens. The exhibition consists of an Socrates’ conversation to reduce everything
imaginary conversation between Nestor and to slivers and bits, and reminds him of the
Achilles’ son, Neoptolemus, after the fall of value of being able to produce a well shaped
Troy. Hippias, speaking as Nestor, gives a discourse in the courts or the assembly, while
long speech outlining the noble deeds that Socrates points out that speaking about
lead to great reputation. In response, Socrates noble deeds in public without being able to
announces that he recently discovered, at the say what the noble is constantly reminds him
hands of an insolent questioner, that he is of the wretchedness of his own condition.
unqualified to find fault with speeches or to In ancient Greek, to kalon covers a wide
praise them as beautiful or noble, since he is range of moral and aesthetic ground unlike
unable to say ‘what the beautiful is’ (Hippias any single word in English. The beautiful or
Major 286d). This introduces the subject of the noble each cover part of what to kalon
the rest of the conversation. means, but neither is adequate by itself. The
Hippias proposes several accounts of what fine has both a moral and an aesthetic sense,
the beautiful is: a beautiful maiden, gold and but is perhaps too weak.
finally ‘to be rich, healthy and honoured by The Hp. Ma. resembles other early dia-
the Greeks, to reach old age and, having logues like the Euthyphro, Laches and
buried one’s parents, to be buried lavishly Meno, in which a moral issue is reduced to
by one’s own children’ (291e). Each is more an underlying question of the form ‘What is
extravagant than the last, and each is rebutted __?’ As in those other dialogues, the question
with considerable comic wit. Socrates then remains unanswered and the conversation
offers several of his own: the appropriate, ends in perplexity (aporia). But comic inflec-
the useful and the beneficial. Each of these tion is much more evident in the Hp. Ma.
falls short as well. A final suggestion – the than elsewhere. Also, perplexity concerning

59

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 59 3/8/2001 5:12:42 PM


THE DIALOGUES

to kalon is not the end point of this dialogue, eiron (Socrates), the alazon (Hippias), but
but rather its starting point: Socrates intro- also the beautiful maiden of ambiguous cir-
duces the main question with reference to cumstances and the wayward son. The only
a perplexity that he was thrown into prior figure missing is the negligent father. But that
to meeting Hippias. Finally, the activity in may be the philosophical point. The father – a
relation to which Socrates professes to be moral, educational authority – is absent, here
perplexed is different. He is thrown into per- as in so many other dialogues, and there is a
plexity ‘. . . while criticizing things in certain contest to take his place. Hippias’ exhibition
speeches as ugly, and praising other things as makes his claim to the educational authority
beautiful . . .’ (286c). The praising and blam- of the absent father. Socrates effectively punc-
ing of things in speech is central to Socratic tures Hippias’ pretensions, even if he cannot
dialectic, and accordingly the dialogue might persuade him to give them up. But Socrates
be viewed as the aporetic dialogue, since it also cannot claim the father’s authority for
examines the perplexity of dialectic itself. philosophy. The father is a guarantor of legit-
In the sequence of answers Socrates pro- imacy, and in his absence everything shows
poses – the appropriate, the useful and the itself to be inauthentic, even dialectic, since it
beneficial – each falls short, giving way to a cannot articulate the relationship between the
syntactically similar successor formed out of noble and the good except in the paradoxi-
its own failure. It might seem that this series cal image of negligent paternity: the beautiful
could continue indefinitely, but here the turns out to be the father of the good, but
beneficial is the end of the line. No further a father who does not resemble his child. If
answer is possible. Since the beneficial is the comedy is the genre most suited to inauthen-
cause or father of the good, it cannot itself ticity, it may also be suitable to philosophical
be good. But to say that the beautiful is not inquiry as Plato conceives it. The question of
good is absurd. Other early dialogues fail to the generic constitution of philosophy has
define courage or piety or virtue because the not received much attention in the scholarly
interlocutors are unable to proceed further. literature, but the Hp. Ma. is an invitation to
But here the failure grows out of dialectic take it up for ourselves.
itself. Socrates apparently introduces the The authenticity of the Hp. Ma. was
question concerning to kalon to discourage much debated in the previous two centuries.
Hippias from holding his exhibition. But he Arguments for rejecting it were based on
is not persuaded to call it off even though judgements of its comic style and vocabulary,
he cannot say what to kalon is. By contrast, or on a concern that it seems to combine
Socrates makes explicit for himself (and us) mature theoretical motifs with the aporetic
the inability of dialectic to resolve the per- shape of the earliest dialogues. But in the
plexity concerning to kalon. The distinction absence of decisive evidence against it the
between the philosopher and the sophist Hp. Ma. has quietly been received back into
could not be clearer. the canon in recent years. Ironically, how-
The comedy of this dialogue is not just an ever, the question of authenticity in various
occasional witty exchange, or a borrowed forms is a central concern of the text, and
phrase. The narrative structure of the Hp. so the question of textual provenance should
Ma. is comic in shape. The usual stock char- not be simply forgotten even as the text has
acters of the comic tradition are here: the come to be accepted.

60

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 60 3/8/2001 5:12:42 PM


THE DIALOGUES

HIPPIAS MINOR profess in the dialogues, a doctrine accord-


ing to which excellence or virtue (aretê) is
Francesco Fronterotta and a form of knowledge or reflection (Jantzen
Jean-François Pradeau 1989). On the other hand, if one maintains
The dialogue takes place following a lec- that knowledge is morally ‘neutral’, insofar
ture Hippias has just given on the Homeric as its application may vary according to the
poems, before a large audience (Pottenger subject practicing it, it can no longer be iden-
1995–6). Socrates, who has attended the tified with moral excellence. We then witness
lecture, wants to question the sophist on a the ruin of another major thesis of Platonic
particular point of his Homeric exegesis: the ethics, according to which the freedom of
definition he has given of the characters of an individual finds its limit, according to
Achilles and Odysseus. Achilles, more simple Plato, in the demand for a self-realization
and sincere (or the most veridical, haplous- that affirms that no one can wish for his own
tatos kai alêthestatos) is supposedly better destruction and his own death, his own ‘evil’,
than Odysseus, who is ‘double’ (polutropos). but that every individual desires to be happy,
It is thus Achilles’ ‘simplicity’ that should by conquering his happiness or his well-be-
reveal his sincerity, whereas the ‘duplicity’ ing (cf. for instance Gorgias 509e, Meno 78a,
(or ‘multiplicity’) of Odysseus, for its part, Protagoras 345d).
indicates an ambiguous and deceptive char- The most radical consequence of these
acter (Mulhern 1984). These are the moral premises, which Hippias and Socrates are
qualities that will form the subject of the obliged to accept on several occasions (par-
discussion. ticularly at 366b–c, 367a, 367e, 368b–9a,
A large part of the text is devoted to the etc.), is the following: if having knowledge
examination of the examples that the two and being capable of something means that
interlocutors propose – and oppose – to one is ‘good’ (agathos) at it, or that one is
one another in the course of the discussion; ‘the best’ (aristos) at it, then the man who
first on the basis of Homer (Hippias Minor is ‘good’ or ‘the best’ will necessarily be the
364b–5d, 369a–71e), then by examining one who deceives, that is, the one who ‘does
the various domains of knowledge of the wrong’ (366c–7a). At first glance, the Hp.
sophist (366c–9a), the activities of the body Mi. thus ends with an admission of defeat
(372a–5a) and the properties of the soul (376b–c), for Socrates and Hippias cannot
(375a–6b). The sequence of arguments in accept that it pertains to a good man to
the Hi. Mi. is rather simple, and is summa- choose deception and voluntary wrongdo-
rized as early as 366a–7a. The starting point ing; yet they cannot succeed in correcting
is the hypothesis that all deception comes the argument. Yet, it is possible to read the
from knowledge and a capacity (or power: course of the discussion in another way, by
dunamis), for the deceiver must be capable asking, Do the competence and capacity that
(dunatos) of deceiving, and can be so only enable one to tell the truth or to deceive, to
on the condition of having knowledge in the distinguish and then to practise the true or
field in which he is to carry out his decep- the false by exercising free choice presup-
tion (sophos kai dunatos, 366a; Weiss 1981). pose a genuine indifference with regard to
It is this affirmation that collides head on good and evil on the part of the agent? In
with the ethical theory Plato makes Socrates other words, do ‘knowing’ and ‘being able to

61

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 61 3/8/2001 5:12:42 PM


THE DIALOGUES

do’ evil necessarily imply that one does it? between good and evil and is therefore not
Is the knowledge that leads one to do evil genuine knowledge. If, however, they deceive
genuine knowledge? As Aristotle empha- unintentionally, this can obviously only be
sizes, alluding explicitly to these difficulties through ignorance of the good.
(see Metaphysics 5.29, 1025a2–1; cf. also Taking the measure of the conflict between
Nicomachean Ethics 7 3, 1145b), the demon- the paradoxical ethics assumed in the Hp.
stration of the Hp. Mi. puts to the test a cer- Mi. and the Platonic doctrine of excellence
tain idea of knowledge (sophia), understood (aretê), one is able to see more satisfacto-
as the neutral possession of several items rily the meaning of the dialogue, and the
of theoretical knowledge, which are trans- direction Socrates wishes to impose upon
lated into technical competence and practi- the discussion. We are invited to do this by
cal capacities. This conception of knowledge the discussion at 376b, when Socrates adds
is characteristic of the epistemological and a restriction to his conclusion according to
ethical doctrine of the sophists (q.v.), at least which ‘the person who behaves and works in
insofar as Plato depicts and refutes it. In this a shameful and unjust way . . . can only be
sophistic perspective, ‘knowledge’ indeed the man who is good’, adding nonchalantly,
leads to a ‘know-how’, indifferent in itself ‘if a man of this kind exists. . . .’ However, for
to good and evil, and the choice of good or the reasons that have just been indicated, this
of evil, detached from knowledge, remains man cannot exist if aretê is really a form of
up to the agent. Reading the Hp. Mi. in this knowledge.
way, and imputing the aporiai of the dia-
logue to the sophistic conception of knowl-
edge, one immediately realizes what must be
opposed to the sophist, at the same time as Ion
the result of these aporiai: the Platonic ethi-
cal doctrine of excellence as knowledge. For, Christopher Janaway
the knowledge that coincides with excellence Ion, Plato’s shortest dialogue, is often
consists, according to Plato, in the posses- assigned to an early Socratic period. There
sion of a knowledge that contains its good are two characters: Socrates and Ion. The
(agathon) within it: that is, the element that latter (not a known historical character) is
guides and orients the agent’s will and his a professional rhapsode, a public reciter and
choice. One must concede that all knowl- commentator on poetry. Ion appears to con-
edge implies the knowledge of good and evil tain the beginnings of Plato’s philosophical
(with regard to its objects and with regard reflection on the arts (q.v. Aesthetics), and
to its eventual implementation), so that no has been treated as a foundational document
neutral knowledge exists, nor, consequently, in Western aesthetics (Schaper 1968:20–1;
does any will that is indifferent to good and criticized by Stern-Gillet 2004).
evil. The sophoi kai dunatoi, who were to Percy Bysshe Shelley’s appreciation of Ion
deceive intentionally, according to Hippias, and his influential translation (1821) epito-
turn out to be bereft of genuine knowledge: mize attempts to find a positive account of
if they choose in full cognizance that they poetry in Socrates’ evocation of inspira-
are deceiving, their knowledge lacks the tion (q.v.) at the heart of the dialogue (Ion
indispensable awareness of the distinction 533c–5a, 535e–6d). In a long display speech,

62

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 62 3/8/2001 5:12:42 PM


THE DIALOGUES

markedly different from the surrounding Ion gives evidence of being good at nothing
question-and-answer style, Socrates por- except rhapsody, so had better accept the epi-
trays poets as lacking rational understanding thet ‘divine’ on pain of appearing dishonest
of the process by which they compose, and (542a–b).
subject to powerful external influence from The dialogue has been found puzzling and
one of the Muses. Like rings attracted to a even contradictory, in that Socrates talks
magnet, they acquire magnetic power them- repeatedly of ‘rhapsodic expertise’ (rhap-
selves, inspiring a performer such as Ion, who soidikê technê), while apparently arguing
recites scenes from the Iliad and Odyssey, that there is no such thing. The contradiction
transmitting the magnetism and moving his may be removed if the assumption of rhap-
audience. sodic expertise is merely ironic throughout
‘Good poets’ owe their finest productions (Flashar 1958), or if Plato recognizes the
to their being divinely inspired (entheios) and possibility of rhapsodic and poetic technai,
may even be called divine (theios). But this but denies them any role in the ‘artistic suc-
is no unequivocal praise of poetry (q.v.), or cess’ or fineness of the best poetry (Janaway
perhaps no praise of it at all, given the fram- 1995:14–35; opposed by Stern-Gillet 2004),
ing parts of the dialogue in which Socrates or if he allows poet and performer each a
refutes Ion’s claims to expert knowledge – technê, but denies this status to the rhap-
epistêmê or technê, the latter term being sode’s critical discourse about poetry (Ferrari
preponderant. The main force of the divine 1989).
inspiration story is to deny that poetic com-
position, performance and exegesis arise ‘by
technê’, by expertise or skill (q.v. Art). While
performing, Ion is said to be ‘taken out of LACHES
himself’, abandoned to emotions elicited by
the Homeric scene he recites: evidence of Eugenio Benitez
his place in the chain of sheer inspiration According to the canon of Thrasyllus (see
(535b–e). D. L. 3.59), Plato’s Laches is about cour-
When Ion claims he is expert on the age and employs, to borrow a term from
poetic virtues of Homer, but can say noth- Theaetetus 149a–51d, an ‘obstetric’ method,
ing worthwhile about other poets, Socrates in which the ideas of Socrates’ interlocu-
refutes his claim to master a technê on the tors are delivered into the light of day and
grounds of his commanding no general prin- examined. These Thrasyllan labels correctly
ciples that apply across all relevant subject identify the simple theme and tactic of the
matter (531a–3c). Later Ion asserts that he La., but as with all of the Socratic dialogues,
is well versed in all forms of expertise that apparent simplicity disguises enormous sub-
Homer portrays well, such as charioteering tlety of structure and composition. One thing
and generalship, conflating knowing about that seems hidden from most readers is the
the poetic representation of some expertise special relation between theme and tactic,
with possessing that expertise. Socrates elicits namely that the practise of Socratic dialogue
from him the absurd statement that he is the requires and exhibits courage in examining
best general among the Greeks – ‘That, too, what one really thinks. The La. seems also
I learned from Homer’s poetry’ (541b). But to be a ‘proleptic’ dialogue, in the sense of

63

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 63 3/8/2001 5:12:43 PM


THE DIALOGUES

anticipating philosophical views presented prearranged meeting with Nicias and Laches
more fully in later works (see Kahn 1998); at a demonstration of hoplitics or ‘fighting-
at least, many strands of its argument are in-armour’ by a mercenary sophist named
taken up in other dialogues, especially the Stesilaus. Scholars have not treated Stesilaus
Protagoras. The conversation in the La. itself or his art as a paradigm of courage, either
ends inconclusively. The La. is a dramatically for Plato or the characters in the dialogue.
rich dialogue in the sense that its interpre- The pretext merely allows Lysimachus and
tation must be guided by knowledge of its Melesias to introduce their sons to two of
characters (q.v.), setting and dramatic date. the most influential men in Athens. Socrates
Specific behaviours of Socrates’ interlocu- is the spanner in the works. He is present by
tors (such as Nicias’ attempt to avoid being some chance, but he is already acquainted
drawn into the conversation) display attested with the sons of Lysimachus and Melesias,
features of their character (e.g. Nicias’ cir- and his bravery in battle, attested in the La.
cumspection) in relation to the theme of as in the Symposium, gives him the right
courage. While a basic understanding can to speak and ask questions about courage.
be acquired from reading the La. on its own, Socrates’ tactic of direct examination appears
the appreciation gained from examination of as counterpoint to the indirectly domineering
historical events surrounding the dialogue is tactics of Lysimachus.
invaluable (q.v. History). The conversation is not initially about
The La. is set during the Peloponnesian courage but about Stesilaus’ art of fighting
War, possibly during the Peace of Nicias, in armour. Lysimachus and Melesias make it
certainly after the retreat from Delium, and clear, however, that what they want most is
certainly before the Sicilian Expedition. for their sons to become prominent. Socrates
There are possible allusions to the Battle of steers the conversation towards what would
Mantinaea, at which Laches was killed (La. make them deservedly prominent. Everyone
193a), and the debacle at Syracuse, follow- agrees that excellence (q.v. aretê) would do
ing which Nicias met his death (199a). The the trick, but as to what that is, they can
fact that two generals are chosen interlocu- neither say themselves nor point to anyone
tors is almost universally agreed to reflect who can say. The theme of courage is then
their appropriateness to the topic; never- introduced as part of the investigation into
theless, their deaths in battle may signal an what excellence is. Thus questions about the
intention on Plato’s part to look beyond the nature of excellence, whether it can be taught
art of war for the source of courage. Other and whether the cardinal virtues are proper
characters of the La. have only a minor part parts of excellence or something else lie at
in the conversation, yet their role is impor- the foundation of the philosophical argu-
tant in establishing the context within which ments of the La.
an examination of courage becomes neces- Socrates first discusses courage with
sary. Lysimachus and Melesias, who initiate Laches. The direct results of their discussion
the discussion, are shadowy figures in his- are not very significant, but the examina-
tory, although there is some suggestion that tion reveals three principles characteristic of
Melesias at least may have been anti-demo- Plato’s approach to ethics. The first is that the
cratic (Thucydides, History 8.86). The pre- cause of excellence is distinct from its effects.
text under which the dialogue takes place is a In this connection, the scope of courage is

64

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 64 3/8/2001 5:12:43 PM


THE DIALOGUES

widened considerably. The La. displaces the La. is often forgotten, however (for further
Greek focus on military exploits, first by the discussions, see Benitez 2000; Schmid 1992).
reminder that even standing one’s ground
takes courage, and then by expanding the
concept of endurance to cover bearing up
under all sorts of circumstances, including LAWS
cross-examination. The courage to persist
in an inquiry introduces a second princi- Eugenio Benitez
ple, namely, the say-what-you-think rule The Laws is the longest and, according to tra-
of Socratic conversation (La. 193c, 194a). dition, the last of Plato’s dialogues. It was left
This principle of openness stands in direct ‘in the wax’ at the time of Plato’s death and
opposition to the assumption of Lysimachus, brought into publication by Philip of Opus
Melesias and Nicias that safety is to be found (D. L. 3.37). Whether Philip had a hand in
in cover. It is connected with a third principle editing the work or whether he merely tran-
introduced by Laches, namely the harmony scribed it is uncertain (for one recent account,
of word and deed (188c–9c). This principle see Nails and Thesleff 2003). The most recent
seems fundamental to explaining the failure analyses of its style indicate significant affini-
of the La.: none of the characters exhibit ties with the Sophist, Politicus and Philebus,
it (193e), yet without such harmony there though there are stark differences in places.
appears little hope of understanding what These, however, might be explained in vari-
courage really is. ous ways, and there has never been any ques-
Socrates’ conversation with Nicias adds tion that the Lg. substantially contains the
a cognitive dimension to the conception thought of Plato. If we set special problems
of courage, and shows partly why the har- of composition aside, including admittedly
mony between word and deed has not been serious questions about the overall coher-
attained. Even animals perform brave deeds; ence of the dialogue, then the chief difficul-
human courage must involve some sort of ties remaining for an interpreter of the Lg.
understanding, forethought or wisdom. The include (a) its dramatic date and structure,
refutation of Nicias (who gets his idea about (b) its relation to other political dialogues
courage from what he has heard Socrates of Plato, especially the Republic and the Plt.
say) is mostly a lesson about what sort of and (c) the extensive discussion of cosmology
understanding courage does not involve. It is and theology in Lg. bk 10.
not tactical understanding, nor is it the art The Lg. is the only dialogue set at any
of prognostication. It seems to be an under- distance from Athens. It is set in Crete,
standing of value, but Nicias is unable or where three elderly gentlemen – an unnamed
unwilling to look far enough into himself to Athenian, a Spartan (Megillus) and a Cnossian
find out more. (Clinias) – pass the day in conversation about
Plato does not hide the principle of word a political constitution as they wind their way
and deed in the La. As Chaucer pointed out, from Cnossos to the cave of Zeus on Mt. Ida.
anyone who can read Plato will see it (Man Along the way the trio frequently remind us
of Laws Tale, prologue 741–2). The implica- that they are old and that despite the serious-
tion that comparing the characters to their ness of their topic, their discussion is a diver-
words is fundamental to understanding the tissement. These two dramatic features alone

65

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 65 3/8/2001 5:12:43 PM


THE DIALOGUES

(the age of the interlocutors and their pen- book against book, to reveal treatments of
chant for mild amusement) may account for similar themes, such as education, censor-
the tendency of the Lg. towards digression, ship, the relation of justice to happiness, the
anacolouthon and inconsistency at least as role of women as citizens, the different kinds
well as the uncharitable supposition of ‘the of constitution and the role of a philosopher
failing powers of the author’ (Bury 1942:vii; or council of philosophers in providing ulti-
for a thorough recent account of amusement mate guidance for the city. A sensitive and
in the Lg. see Jouët-Pastré 2006). At any rate, careful comparison of the Lg. and R. in terms
the Lg. loudly trumpets the view, expressed of fundamental themes in ethics and moral
elsewhere in Plato’s dialogues, that writ- psychology can be found in Bobonich (2002).
ten works are a form of play (see Phaedrus Another point of comparison, the develop-
276d). The choice for interpreters here seems ment of Plato’s political philosophy from the
straightforward. R. to the Lg. has been a preoccupation of
A more difficult, but nevertheless signifi- much scholarship. It is widely held that Plato
cant choice concerns the dramatic date of the gradually moves away from the rule by phi-
Lg. No specific date is given or determined by losopher-kings prescribed in the R. and turns
internal historical reference. Recently, how- towards reliance on the rule of law, first in the
ever, Zuckert has argued that the Lg. is set Plt. and then even more emphatically in the
before the Peloponnesian War (see Zuckert Lg. The progression from personal authority
2009:11–13, 51–8). Zuckert points out to rule of law is discussed at length in Klosko
that the Lg. describes the Persian Wars and (2006). Brown (2004) treats the similarities
Persian culture in detail while it never once between the two dialogues’ ethical implica-
mentions the Peloponnesian War. Around tions of early childhood rearing.
this she builds a case that is circumstantial In addition to the points of comparison
but difficult to resist. If Zuckert is right, with the R., the Lg. discusses at length some
then certain features of the Lg. – such as the political themes that are not given much
absence of philosophy from the proposed attention in other dialogues, including the
curriculum for the fictional city of Magnesia, philosophy of punishment, the general con-
or the attention to habituated virtue rather ception of law (including its rationale and
than the virtue that involves genuine under- function), family law and the law of the
standing of itself, or the separation of cour- marketplace. Despite the protestations of the
age from the other virtues – need not be Athenian that he can only outline a constitu-
interpreted as signalling a change in Plato’s tion, the Lg. provides a very thorough sketch
philosophical views, or as demanded by the of civil administration, including detailed
general practical needs of establishing a city. discussion of executive, legislative, judicial,
An alternative view of the dramatic date is diplomatic, economic and religious offices, as
that of Dušanić (1990:364–5) who notes well as arrangements for police, wardens, real
that the Spartan ambassador Megillus was estate officers and lesser functionaries. The
active in about 408. Lg. also contains the only extensive example
Whatever choices an interpreter makes, of a penal code to be found in Plato’s works.
however, it is impossible to avoid compari- The code, which includes provisions for the
sons between the R. and the Lg. The two law of both free persons and slaves, has been
dialogues can easily and usefully be mapped, thoroughly discussed in Saunders (1994).

66

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 66 3/8/2001 5:12:43 PM


THE DIALOGUES

The tenth book of the Lg. contains an (Epistles 1–4, 7, 8, 13). Four are addressed
unexpected digression into matters of phi- to Dionysius II (1–3, 13) – two to the
losophy, cosmology and theology. The friends and followers of Dion (7, 8) and
attachment of this digression to the law of two to Archytas of Tarentum (9, 12) – one
impiety seems contrived, and the philosophi- to Perdiccas of Macedonia (5) and one each
cal level of discussion – as seen in arguments to Dion (4), Hermias, the tyrant of Atarneus
concerning the types and origin of movement and Plato’s students, Erastus and Coriscus
in the universe, naturalism and the existence (6), Aristodorus, a friend of Dion (10) and a
of god – is well beyond anything else in the Laodamas, whose identity is uncertain (11).
Lg. The Athenian even makes excuses for Both 2 and 6 also contain, like 7, some mate-
the level of difficulty (Lg. 892d–3a). The rial of a cryptic, metaphysical nature.
relation of this book to the rest of the Lg. The lengthiest and most significant letter
remains a difficult and unresolved matter. It is the well known seventh, which purports to
may be that Plato was not able to integrate have been an answer to a request by Dion’s
this material adequately before his death. friends for advice in the wake of Dion’s assas-
(For discussion that tends to support this sination in 353 BCE, but which also has the
view, see Dillon 2003a.) For Platonists, Lg. apologetic character of an open letter. It con-
bk 10 must appear to be the central book, to tains an autobiographical passage in which
the exclusion of practically everything else. Plato recounts his early political ambitions,
For political philosophers, it appears inci- which were disappointed by the degenerate
dental. In much of the recent literature, the character of Athenian politics but especially
theology and politics of the Lg. are treated by the judicial murder of Socrates. Plato con-
separately. Excellent scholarship on the cluded that real reform could only be accom-
Lg. has emerged in recent years, including plished from the perspective afforded by
the publication a very useful bibliography true philosophy and with the aid of virtuous
(Saunders and Brisson 2000). For historical and philosophical comrades under the right
context the work of Morrow (1993) remains circumstances. He accordingly drew away
indispensable. from politics (324b–6b). His later Syracusan
intervention is explained largely by refer-
ence to his friendship for Dion, whom Plato
had befriended on his first visit to the island
LETTERS between 390 and 387. Dion wrote to Plato
of Dionysius II’s passion for philosophy and
V. Bradley Lewis suggested that Syracuse could provide a kind
Thirteen letters (epistulai) are included of proving ground for Plato’s political ideals.
in the traditional canon of Plato’s works While there is some dispute about just what
(q.v. Corpus). While both Aristophanes of Plato’s hopes were in Syracuse, Ep. 7 pro-
Byzantium and Thrasylus include the let- vides little evidence that he aimed to estab-
ters in their collections (third-century BCE lish a government there like that described
and first-century BCE, respectively), mod- in the Republic; rather it emphasizes Plato’s
ern scholarship has cast doubt on their attempts to persuade Dionysius to abandon
authenticity. Seven of the letters concern tyranny, give Syracuse a proper legal code and
Plato’s involvement in Syracusan affairs establish the city as a bulwark in the defence

67

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 67 3/8/2001 5:12:43 PM


THE DIALOGUES

of Hellenic civilization in the west against the scholar has accepted all thirteen of the let-
Carthaginians (see Morrow 1935:140–5). ters. Brisson’s 1987 survey shows that among
The letter also contains a famous but con- 32 authors since Ficino in 1484 Ep. 7 and 8
troversial discussion of knowledge and learn- have enjoyed the greatest support, with 26
ing, the so-called philosophical digression scholars defending the authenticity of 7 and
(342a–4e). 25 that of 8. Ep. 6 was defended by 18 of
Ep. 8 picks up from the seventh explain- Brisson’s authors; Ep. 3 has had 14 defend-
ing in somewhat more detail the application ers. Most scholars have rejected the rest
of Plato’s political principles to the erstwhile although all save the first has had a number
reform of Syracuse. The content seems to of advocates (Brisson 1987:72). An earlier
closely track the proposals contained in the and somewhat less systematic tabulation by
Laws. Of the other letters concerned with Guthrie (1978:401) yielded similar findings.
Syracuse, Ep. 1–3 are addressed to Dionysius The modern debate on the authenticity of
II: Ep. 1 portrays Plato as a kind of vice-regent the letters has focused mainly on three issues:
with Dionysius and is certainly spurious; Ep. the coherence of the content of the letters with
2 presents advice about both governing and the content of the dialogues; stylometric com-
philosophical study that is similar to that parison of the letters and the dialogues; and
in Ep. 7; Ep. 3 purports to have been writ- agreement between the content of the letters
ten between Plato’s second and third visit and other ancient historical sources, especially
(although some suggest that, if authentic, it but not exclusively concerning the Syracusan
may have been written after Dion’s coup) affairs in which Plato was involved. Not sur-
and offers a defence of his conduct as well as prisingly, given its potential value, most of the
of the then-exiled Dion. Ep. 13 concerns the controversy has concerned Ep. 7, which crit-
same time period, but it is more personal and ics have argued contains important contra-
suggests that Plato hoped to influence the dictions with Plato’s established views about
tyrant in a way favourable to Dion’s inter- the theory of knowledge and about politics
ests. Ep. 4 is addressed to Dion and claims (see especially Edelstein 1966). Others have
to have been written between Dion’s victory argued that the content of the letter does fit
over Dionysus and his assassination. It sup- with Plato’s views about both matters (see
ports Dion’s work and advises political mod- Lewis 2000; Morrow 1935:61–79). Some
eration. Among the remaining letters are the have also suggested that the ‘philosophical
two brief missives to the Pythagorean math- digression’ in particular could be an interpo-
ematician-statesman Archytas and relatively lation in what is otherwise an authentic letter
brief letters to associates and letters of intro- of Plato (see Brisson 1987:145–58). Ledger’s
duction and recommendation for others. comprehensive 1989 stylometric analysis
Most scholarship on the letters has con- argues strongly that Ep. 7 was the product
cerned the question of authenticity. While of the same author as the Lg., and also sup-
the antiquity of the letters is impressive, the ports the authenticity of Ep. 3, 8 and 13. The
ancient practise of pseudonymous composi- other main approach to the authenticity ques-
tion – especially of letters – is well known tion has focused on external evidence. Here,
and doubts about some of Plato’s Epistles the strongest case can be made for Ep. 7 with
(especially the first, but also the twelfth) long the other letters facing more and more seri-
predate modern textual criticism. No recent ous objections. Overall the balance of recent

68

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 68 3/8/2001 5:12:43 PM


THE DIALOGUES

scholarly opinion has tended towards accept- beautiful. But because we clearly love some
ance of Ep. 7 as either genuinely Platonic or good things as a means to other good things,
the product of a contemporary with intimate this account threatens to produce an infinite
knowledge of Plato’s thought and deeds regress unless we postulate a ‘first beloved’
(Brunt 1993:312–25), but the matter remains for the sake of which everything else is loved
controversial. but which is not itself loved for the sake of
anything else. But this creates another prob-
lem: why is the ‘first beloved’ loved if not
for the sake of something else? The sugges-
LYSIS tion that it is loved, as a means of eliminat-
ing what is bad, is rejected because not all
Francisco Gonzalez desire appears to depend on the existence of
The dialogue opens in front of a newly con- something bad. The final suggestion is that
structed wrestling school where Socrates we love the ‘first beloved’, that is, the good,
learns, in response to his usual inquiry after because in being lacked by us it also natu-
‘the beautiful’, of the beautiful boy Lysis rally belongs to us. But is not claiming that
and his quite maladroit and fruitless pursuit the object of friendship is what is akin to us
by the hopelessly enamoured older youth the same as claiming that it is what is like us:
Hippothales. Offering to show Hippothales an account already refuted? With this aporia,
how such a boy can be won, Socrates enters their guardians forcefully take the two boys
the school and engages Lysis along with his home.
friend Menexenus in a discussion concern- For a long time the Lysis was, especially in
ing the nature of friendship (q.v.; and, more English language scholarship, either ignored,
broadly, love). After humiliating Lysis by dismissed as a failure (Guthrie 1975) or
arguing that his parents do not entrust their judged spurious (Tejera 1990), though it had
things to him and therefore cannot love him a few defenders (e.g. Bolotin 1979; Glaser
as their own because of his lack of wisdom, 1935). Some interpreters have been repelled
he humiliates the combative Menexenus by its seemingly ‘utilitarian’ conception of
by catching him in the dilemma of whether love (Vlastos 1973). In recent years, schol-
friendship is a nonreciprocal relation (as arship on the dialogue has grown exponen-
seemingly attested by the possibility of being tially and has proven nearly unanimous in
a philos of wisdom) or is necessarily recip- judging it successful and indispensable to
rocal (as seemingly attested by the absurd- Plato’s thought. In what follows I will note
ity of calling yourself the philos of someone the problems that originally led to the dia-
who hates you). Socrates then shows the two logue’s neglect and how these problems have
friends how difficult it is to give an adequate been addressed in the recent literature.
account of friendship. Arguing that neither The main problem was not its dubious
opposites nor those who are alike (spe- arguments or inconclusive ending, which
cifically, alike in goodness) can be friends, characterize other dialogues as well, but that
Socrates suggests that perhaps the relation- while in other aporetic dialogues the argu-
ship exists between what is neither good ment could be easily seen as at least making
nor bad (which would appear to describe progress, the argument of the Ly. seemed
the human condition) and what is good or particularly disjointed and inclined towards

69

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 69 3/8/2001 5:12:44 PM


THE DIALOGUES

preying on verbal ambiguities, that is, eris- and Menexenus, are philoi and are explic-
tic (Annas 1997; Guthrie 1975:143; Price itly described as instantiating, at least in
1989). This problem has been addressed in appearance, what the discussion is about.
the recent literature in three ways. First, more Those claiming the discussion is about
careful analyses of the argument have shown erôs (e.g. Bolotin 1979:206; Friedländer
that it actually builds towards an increas- 1958–64:1:50–1, 2:102; Haden 1983) could
ingly better account of the subject. Second, point out that the impetus for the discus-
in line with a more general trend in recent sion is Hippothales’ erotic pursuit of Lysis
Platonic scholarship, the dramatic richness and Socrates’ offer of showing that young
of the dialogue has been shown to provide man how to conduct such a pursuit properly,
an indispensable context for understanding as well as pointing out that the discussion
the direction and point of the argument. (see explicitly returns to eros at the very end.
Gonzalez 1995a, 2000, 2003; Penner and Ironically both interpretations of the dia-
Rowe 2005:204–5). Third, this more care- logue’s topic only encouraged its neglect. If
ful analysis of the argument that also situ- taken to be about erôs, then it was largely
ates it in its dramatic context has found the overshadowed by the much more exhaus-
dialogue suggesting a positive solution to the tive and seemingly positive treatments in
problems it raises; that we, as neither good the Symposium and Phaedrus. If taken to
nor bad, love that ultimate good of which we be about philia, it was overshadowed by the
have been deprived but which belongs to us much more thorough, systematic and con-
(Penner and Rowe 2005:182–4) and that this clusive treatment of the topic in Aristotle’s
shared erotic affinity with the good grounds ethics. Scholars have recently vindicated the
that affinity between two people that charac- independence and unique contribution of
terizes philia (Bordt 1998:89–92; Gonzalez the Ly. by recognizing it to be about both
1995a, 2000, 2003; Penner and Rowe erôs and philia together (Penner and Rowe
2005:167–9). Justin (2005) and Rudebusch, 2005:270). It differs from the Smp. and the
on the other hand, interpret philia in the Phdr. in applying, through its emphasis on
dialogue as only an instance of desire for philia, their metaphysical interpretation of
the good that depends on finding something erôs to interpersonal relationships. And it
good in another person. differs from Aristotle’s treatment of philia in
Without denying the utilitarian character grounding this relation on the erotic drive
of the friendship described in the Ly., schol- towards some transcendent good.
ars have been able to give this characteristic a Another disputed question has been the
much more positive interpretation (see Bordt place of the Ly. in the Platonic corpus. The
1998:139–40, 214; Gonzalez 2003; Penner metaphysical content of the dialogue has
and Rowe 2005:280–91). created problems for dating: while in terms
Another debated question is the seem- of topic and form it appeared to belong to
ingly basic one of the dialogue’s topic. Those the ‘early’ dialogues, its sophisticated meta-
who think the dialogue is about philia (e.g. physical distinctions appeared to place it
Annas 1977; Guthrie 1975:154; Hoerber at least among the ‘middle’ dialogues. The
1959; Price 1989:9–10; Robinson 1986) question of dating has ceased to be press-
could argue that this is the concept explic- ing given the growing abandonment of
itly addressed and that the two boys, Lysis any attempt to establish a chronology of

70

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 70 3/8/2001 5:12:44 PM


THE DIALOGUES

Plato’s dialogues. The recent literature has (II) THE FUNERAL SPEECH
also shown the dialogue to contribute to
Plato’s metaphysics and thus to differ from Socrates’ speech endorses the custom of such
other ‘Socratic’ dialogues. Whether due to speeches (Mx. 236d–e), then praises Athens.
its distinction between two kinds of being- The praise begins with a myth (q.v.) about
present-in (see Bordt 1998:105, 191–2) or the first Athenians’ birth from the earth
its analysis of how something can be ‘ours’ (237b–8b) and continues with a synopsis of
without being possessed or its elaboration Athenian history (239a–46a). The history
of the notion of ‘real reference’ (Penner and tracks Athens’ dominance from the Persian
Rowe 2005:210), the Ly. has become a ref- Wars (490 BCE) until the King’s Peace (386).
erence text for understanding the Platonic Next, the speech turns to moral instruction.
forms and their relation to us and the sen- In the voice of the dead soldiers, it exhorts
sible world. (And the long debate about their survivors to moderation and courage
whether forms are present or not in the Ly. (246d–8d). A dismissal follows.
appears to be settling towards the former
alternative. See Bordt 1998:203–4; Penner (III) PARODY OR IMPROVEMENT?
and Rowe 2005:278.) The Ly. has thus gone
from being at best a marginal and negligible One sentence from the Mx. (235d) is quoted
text in the Platonic corpus to being now one twice by Aristotle (Rhetoric 1267b8, 1415b30);
of the key texts for understanding Plato’s if not for this evidence of authenticity, the dia-
philosophy as a whole. logue’s peculiarity might have caused it to be
classed as spurious (q.v. Corpus). Instead, read-
ers debate whether Plato meant the speech as
serious rhetoric (Huby 1957; Kahn 1963) or
MENEXENUS as parody (Long 2003; Loraux 1986; Pownall
2004; Salkever 1993).
Nickolas Pappas Certain features of the dialogue suggest a
The Menexenus is almost entirely a sample of joke is afoot: the playful opening conversa-
funeral rhetoric (q.v.) whose purpose remains tion, the claim that Aspasia wrote this speech
fundamentally controversial. (Bloedow 1975; Henry 1995), Socrates’
exceeding praise for Athens, with a history
(I) CHARACTERS AND SETTING wiped clean of Athenian misdeeds (Trivigno
2009), and the anachronism in Socrates’
Socrates meets Menexenus, who wants account of events down to thirteen years
to speak at the annual public funeral for after his death (Rosenstock 1994). Instead of
Athenian soldiers (Mx. 234b). Socrates says countering this interpretation with unprov-
such rhetoric is magical (234c–5c) but not able appeals to ‘seriousness’ of tone, one can
difficult. His own rhetoric teacher Aspasia argue that Plato intends the speech to be
(courtesan, companion to Pericles) taught better than Pericles’ on the grounds that the
him a fine example (235e–6c). Socrates differences between the speeches harmonize
delivers a speech in the manner of Pericles’ with other Platonic criticisms of Pericles.
famous funeral oration (Thucydides, History The speeches differ in how they praise
2.35–46; Monoson 1992). and how they characterize moral education.

71

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 71 3/8/2001 5:12:44 PM


THE DIALOGUES

Moreover, the Mx. speech differs from the dialogue begins with an exploration of
Thucydides’ History in the form of macro- the nature of virtue, the notion of teaching
historical narrative it offers. Pericles’ speech inevitably raises questions about knowledge
stinted on praise and ignored the possibility or expertise and its relationship to belief or
that the city might improve its citizens. He opinion.
disparaged rhetoric, elevating ergon ‘deed’ The dramatic date of the dialogue is
above logos ‘speech’. The Mx. deliberately widely put at some time during 403–02 BCE,
raises logos to the status of ergon in recogni- since it is thought that the Meno character
tion of how one inculcates virtue. Its report of the Platonic dialogue is the same Meno
from the dead soldiers urges moral improve- who, according to Xenophon’s Anabasis,
ment; its myth of autochthony includes abo- was employed as a mercenary in Cyrus’
riginal divine instruction within the city’s unsuccessful attempt on the Persian throne,
founding (Mx. 238b). Again, unlike Pericles, and who would therefore have been in Asia
Socrates praises Athens unrestrainedly. Praise Minor by the year 401 and executed by the
is excessive language proper to magnificent king of Persia in 400 BCE. The appearance of
objects and bespeaks moral elevation and Anytus in the dialogue provides another clue:
exhortation. if Anytus currently holds office as a demo-
Plato’s Gorgias (q.v.) and Protagoras crat, the dialogue must take place after the
(q.v.) take Pericles to task for neglecting to democracy was restored in Athens following
improve either his sons’ souls or his fellow the fall of the Thirty in 403.
citizens’ (Grg. 503c, 515e; Prt. 319e–20b). The dialogue begins as Meno, a wealthy
And in all the ways indicated, the Mx. speech and well born Thessalian, young enough still
aims at the educational function for rheto- to have suitors but not too young to com-
ric that Pericles declined to attempt. It can mand a company and head a household,
be called an attempt to produce something confronts the older Socrates, now in his late
better than its original: rhetoric in a philoso- sixties, with the question whether virtue can
pher’s hands. be taught or whether it comes by practise, is
Finally, the speech reads as a rebuttal to learned, is possessed by nature or has some
Thucydides. Socrates recounts a history pow- other source (Men. 70a). The abruptness
ered by psychodynamic forces. The world with which the dialogue begins precludes
order deteriorates depressingly but coher- any proper setting of the scene; we learn
ently along lines reminiscent of the city’s only later (90b) that Meno’s host in Athens
decline in Republic 8–9 (q.v.), an order that is Anytus, a democrat who is nevertheless
Thucydides would not give to world events. staunchly conservative and who is known to
have been one of Socrates’ three accusers at
the infamous trial at which Socrates was sen-
tenced to death.
MENO Socrates swiftly turns Meno’s question
concerning the manner of virtue’s acquisi-
Roslyn Weiss tion into the more basic one with which he
The Meno is a dialogue whose ethical and is more at home: what is virtue? A confident
epistemological concerns are bridged by the Meno, having studied with the prominent
question, ‘can virtue be taught?’ Although fifth-century rhetorician Gorgias, is certain

72

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 72 3/8/2001 5:12:44 PM


THE DIALOGUES

that he knows: there is a distinct virtue for Socrates’ reformulation (Moravcsik 1970:57;
each kind of person – for men in their prime, Scolnicov 1976:51).
for women, for children, for slaves and for Socrates counters the paradox with a myth
old men. As Socrates presses Meno for a of recollection, which is intended to estab-
definition of virtue, for the specification of lish that inquiry into what is not yet known
that which all the virtues have in common, will succeed if one is sufficiently dogged,
a somewhat more diffident Meno ventures, since one’s soul contains all that it has
first, rather obtusely, that virtue is the ability learned in previous incarnations. The myth
to rule men (70c), and second, that virtue is has spawned much controversy, with some
justice (70d). scholars convinced that what the soul ‘recol-
Meno’s definition of virtue as justice lects’ are Platonic forms (Gulley 1954:195;
launches an extended foray into the matter Guthrie 1975:253–4; Taylor 1926:130) and
of definition. Since justice is agreed to be only others remaining far more sceptical (Ebert
a part of virtue, it cannot define virtue any 1973:180, n2; Ross 1951:18n3, 22; Sharples
more than roundness can define shape. Once 1985:14; Weiss 2001:75). One reason that
Socrates has supplied models of definition scholars have come to believe that it is forms
that are acceptable to Meno (particularly the that the myth’s soul ‘sees’ is that Socrates
Empedoclean definition of colour in terms chooses the nonempirical subject matter of
of effluences), it falls to Meno once again to geometry for his demonstration of how recol-
define virtue. No more successful this time lection works. He has Meno summon a slave
around – relying on a poet, he defines virtue untutored in geometry and, by means only of
as desiring fine things and having the power asking questions, appears to elicit from the
to attain them – Meno becomes belligerent, slave the correct answer to the puzzle he has
attacking Socrates for deliberately confound- posed, namely, on which line of a square is a
ing those with whom he engages, for numb- second square whose area is twice that of the
ing them much as a sting ray does. He then original square constructed? Since Socrates
produces his notorious ‘paradox’, in which asks the slave rather leading questions, how-
he contends, first, that it is impossible to ever, it is unclear how much ‘recollecting’ is
search for what one does not already know actually going on as the slave pursues the
for one would not know what one is search- puzzle’s solution, and how much he is in fact
ing for and, second, that even if one were to being taught by Socrates. For some scholars
happen upon that for which one searched, (Bluck 1961:13; Guthrie 1975:255), all is rec-
one would not know it (80d). Scholars have ollection; for others, recollection ends at the
been divided in their views of how seriously demonstration’s final stage (Klein 1965:107;
Plato takes Meno’s paradox. Some think he Vlastos 1991a:119); for still others, there is
regards it as an unworthy attempt to obstruct only teaching (Anderson 1993:135; Weiss
the discussion (Ritter 1933:102; Shorey 2001:98). Scott (2006:102–9) hopes to
1933:157; Taylor 1926:235–6), particularly salvage recollection by deflating its sense:
given its strikingly ad hominem form (Bluck recollection is the ability to follow a demon-
1961:272; Moline 1969:153–61; Thompson stration. Yet, Socrates contends that the only
1901:116–17; Weiss 2001:52n12); others explanation for the slave’s achievement is
think Plato takes it quite seriously, if not that true opinions were always in him (Men.
in Meno’s formulation of it, then at least in 85c–6b).

73

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 73 3/8/2001 5:12:44 PM


THE DIALOGUES

As the dialogue proceeds, Meno revives whose virtue depends not on knowledge but
his initial question: how is virtue acquired? on true opinion? Or, in the end, is Socrates,
Socrates introduces a new method, the for all his talk of true opinion, committed to
‘method of hypothesis’, as a fruitful way to the view that there can be no genuine virtue
approach questions whose answers are not without knowledge (Wilkes 1979)?
yet known. Employing this new method,
Socrates establishes that virtue is teach-
able: virtue is teachable if and only if it is
knowledge; all good things are associated PARMENIDES
in some way with knowledge; and virtue
is a good thing. No sooner, however, does Samuel Scolnicov
Socrates confirm virtue’s teachability than he Interpretations of Parmenides have ranged
challenges his own conclusion by citing the from reading it as an introduction to
empirical fact (if it is a fact) that there are no the whole of Platonic – and more often
teachers and students of virtue. Neoplatonic – metaphysics (e.g. Dodds
The dialogue concludes with an important 1928), sometimes in an esotericist variation
distinction between true opinion and knowl- (e.g. Migliori 1990), to viewing it as a record
edge. Socrates associates knowledge once of unsolved (and perhaps unsolvable) ‘hon-
again with recollection, recasting recollection est perplexities’ (Vlastos 1954), as protreptic
as the ‘tethering’ of true opinion (97e–8a). ‘mental gymnastics’ (Grote 1875), as a col-
Interestingly, Socrates in the Men. applauds lection of sophistic tricks (e.g. Owen 1970)
true opinion for its capacity to guide aright, or even as an elaborate (though admittedly
faulting it only for its tendency to take tedious) joke (e.g. Taylor 1934). Logical
flight. Having determined, then, that virtue, reconstructions of the dialogue have been
since it has neither teachers nor students, offered by Brumbaugh (1961) and recently
is not knowledge, Socrates supposes that it by Rickless (2007).
is a kind of true opinion (or good repute – The first problem in the interpretation of
eudoxia), and settles finally on the rather the dialogue is the relation between its first,
unsettling insight that virtue must come to aporetic part (Prm. 130a3–7c3), following
human beings by ‘divine dispensation with- the proem (126a1–30a2), and the longer
out intelligence’ (99e). second part, containing a set of ostensibly
How seriously one takes the dialogue’s self-contradictory arguments (137c4–66c5).
conclusion may turn on one’s view of the Ryle (1939b) followed Apelt (1919) and
sudden appearance of the term eudoxia, Wundt (1935) in surmising that the two parts
‘good repute’, in place of the expected true or were composed at different times and are only
right opinion (compare Thompson 1901:225 loosely connected. Cornford (1939) practically
for whom it is insignificant with Klein ignores the first part. More recent interpreta-
1965:253): does the shift intimate that for tions (Gill 1996; Meinwald 1991; Scolnicov
Socrates good statesmen succeed not because 2003) have tried to present a unified view of
they think well but because they are well the dialogue. For a useful summary of previ-
thought of? Or does Socrates hold that there ous interpretations, see Migliori (1990).
are in principle (Bluck 1961:39–40) or even The structure of Prm. is not unknown
in fact (Scott 2006:186–92) good leaders from other dialogues (Meno; Republic):

74

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 74 3/8/2001 5:12:44 PM


THE DIALOGUES

a relatively short aporetic first part and a IV, VI, VIII) or in relation to something else
longer euporetic part aimed at solving the (Arguments II, III, V, VII).
problems raised in the first part. As usual The first Argument (137c4–42a8) reiter-
with Plato, whatever is said in it is to be ates and expands, in formal terms, the aporia
understood from the point of view of the of the first part. Let us take the Parmenidean
speaker who says it. In the first, aporetic view of being as being in itself. This con-
part of the dialogue, the Platonic Socrates’ strains us to recognize that the one (what-
proposal of ideas (or forms (q.v.), as they ever it is) cannot be in relation to anything
are sometimes termed in English) and par- else. Hence, it cannot have any properties,
ticipation is criticized by Parmenides from cannot be named, spoken about, thought,
an Eleatic point of view. In Parmenidean perceived, etc., and any participation is
terms, participation (q.v.) is impossible. impossible (142a1–6). But if participation
It requires not only two types of entities, is impossible, thought too is impossible, as
rational and sensible (something the his- any relation between ideas or between them
torical Parmenides was prepared to con- and he who thinks them is ruled out. The
sider, albeit only in his Way of Opinion, aporia, however, is pragmatic, not logical.
f. 8.52–9), but also two modes of being, The impossibility of thinking and speaking
being in itself and being in relation to about the one poses a problem only for the
something else (which Parmenides did not person who is actually engaged in inquiry
accept, cf. f. 8.56 ‘apart’, 58 ‘in itself’). about it.
Types of entities are categories and are, as According to the method (q.v.) intro-
such, mutually exclusive: cats are not dogs, duced by Plato in the Men., such a reductio
and sensible things are not ideas. Modes of ad absurdum does not block the way to a
being are different ways in which the same conclusion intuitively accepted (such as that
thing can be: a portrait is, in itself, without true opinion and knowledge are possible)
reference or relation to anything else, col- but requires a change of hypothesis, self-
our on canvas; in relation to its sitter, it is evident as the original one may be. Instead
his or her portrait. of accepting as the main premise that what
The second part of the Prm. proceeds in is one cannot be many (137c4–5) – accord-
eight arguments (commonly, but erroneously ing to the strong, Parmenidean principle of
called ‘hypotheses’). Neoplatonists and inter- noncontradiction (f. 7.1), that opposites
pretations of Neoplatonic inspiration have must be mutually exclusive – an alternative
seen in it nine ‘hypotheses’, counting IIa (see premise is proposed, that what is one can
below) as a separate argument. But this goes be many, but not in the same respect. Thus,
against the method set out at Prm. 135c8– what is one can have different, even opposed,
6e4. There, the method yields four argu- attributes. The whole of the second part
ments. The entity under investigation, the of this dialogue is hypothetical, that is, its
‘one’, viz. any one thing but in particular the conclusions depend on the premise of each
idea, is hypothetized to be or, alternatively, argument and refer to possibilities rather
not to be. The consequences of the result- than to actualities. (Note the subjunctive
ing propositions are considered for that one or optative throughout this part of the dia-
and for the others than it. But, in each case, logue, with the exception of Prm. 146a6–8,
the one is taken either in itself (Arguments I, for stylistic variation, as recognized by

75

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 75 3/8/2001 5:12:44 PM


THE DIALOGUES

Aristotle, Metaphysics 5.7; 1077a35). The PHAEDO


list of properties potentially ascribed to the
one in the various arguments, and especially E. E. Pender
in argument II, can be seen as Plato’s list of At the height of his powers as a com-
categories, culled, in fact, from Parmenides’ poser, Plato presents a masterpiece. Phaedo
f. 8. Argument IIa (Prm. 155e3–7b5) is an responds to Echecrates’ opening question –
appendix on entities that are specifically how did Socrates die? – by narrating his
in relation to time, that is, sensible beings. account of the philosopher’s final conver-
Argument III (157b6–9b1) establishes the sations and death. The choice of Phaedo as
same consequences for the others than the narrator reflects the historical circumstance
one, showing that each of the others is also of his presence at Socrates’ death but also
a one. Argument IV (159b2–60b2) demon- the possibility that he was the absent Plato’s
strates that if the one is only in itself, the actual informant on the events (Phaedo
consequences true of it in Argument I are 59b). In addition, Phaedo’s life story, as a
true also of the others. former prisoner of war liberated from slav-
Argument V (160b5–3b6) gives us ery by Socrates and now practicing philoso-
a detailed analysis of participation as phy, gives further point to the main theme
restricted to those aspects of the idea that of death as liberation for the philosopher, a
make it this, rather than that, idea, not theme prominent in the dramatic scenario
those, such as atemporality or oneness, that of the imprisoned Socrates, whose soul
are common to all ideas and establishes the is about to be freed from the final bonds
interdependence of being and not being as of the body. The frame dialogue between
a requisite of participation (162a4–b8). Phaedo and Echecrates is set in Phlius in the
Argument VI (163b7–4b4) establishes that Peloponnese, where Echecrates is a member
nothing can be true of the one that is not in of the Pythagorean community (D. L. 8.46;
relation to anything, Argument VII (164b5– q.v. Pythagoreans). Within the reported dia-
5e1) presents a purely perspectival ontol- logue Socrates’ interlocutors are Simmias and
ogy, in which to be is to be only in relation Cebes – both Socratics but also familiar with
to something or to someone, and merely to Pythagorean thought (Phd. 61d). The setting
be different for something else. From Plato and characters thus establish a Pythagorean
such an ontology is not impossible, but is complexion for a debate which has at its cen-
epistemologically unsatisfactory. This con- tre the, notably Pythagorean, claim that soul
clusion leads directly to Argument VIII is immortal and able to survive the death of
(165e2–6c2), to the effect that if the one is the body.
not in itself but only in relation to some- The first main argument is Socrates’
thing or someone else, there can be no truth. defence of his confidence in the face of
The general conclusion (166c2–5) is that the death, which rests on his conviction that, as
one has to be, paradoxically but necessarily, a philosopher, he will enter the presence of
both in itself and in relation to something or gods and gain a welcome release from the
someone else so as to be able truly to bear body (63b–9e). The argument that death is a
all attributes, even contradictories, under blessing for the wise man motivates the four
different aspects. arguments for immortality of soul which in

76

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 76 3/8/2001 5:12:45 PM


THE DIALOGUES

turn demand the exposition of forms (q.v.) ends, there is silence (84c). But Cebes’ critical
as causes. In this way Socrates’ defence struc- objection and demand for proof that the soul
tures the dialogue and the final metaphysical will definitively exist after death (86e–8b)
account is revealed as the underlying cause forces a radically new approach: the final arg-
and guarantee of Socrates’ hope and gladness ument, from opposites (102a–7b). Socrates
at death, as the fulfilment of his purpose to now recounts how he rejected explanations
gain phronêsis (68a2). of the world deriving from physical causes
The first argument for immortality is that and instead turned to theories as the only
from cyclical processes (70c–2e) life and way to find truth (99e). To explain his new
death are opposites and there is balanced method of reasoning, he speaks of different
reciprocity between dying and coming-back- entities each of which exists ‘itself by itself’
to-life. Since living people are born from the (100b) – the forms. Discussion of largeness
dead, the souls of the dead must exist to allow and smallness leads to the key principle that
this cycle to continue. The second argument, opposites cannot admit opposites (102e–3a).
from recollection (72e–7a), maintains that Following various examples of opposition,
our understanding of abstracts such as ‘the the dénouement is reached at Phd. 105d as
equal itself’ (74a10) depends on knowledge soul is identified as the principle of life and
which must have been gained before our its opposite as death. Since soul as life-force
first sense-perceptions and therefore that cannot admit its opposite, death, then soul is
our souls must have existed and been able necessarily immortal and imperishable.
to learn before birth. The third argument, Given the difficulty of the issues raised,
from affinity (78b–84b), turns to the nature it is not surprising that Phd. continues to
of the soul itself and rests on the principle occupy much critical attention. Scholars
that ‘like knows like’. Socrates distinguishes disagree on the purpose, details and valid-
the naturally composite from the naturally ity of each one of the arguments and
non-composite: the former liable to change advance differing interpretations on every
and dissolution, visible, apprehended by the key aspect of the text: soul-body dualism
senses and mortal; the latter constant, invis- (Pakaluk 2003), recollection (Dimas 2003;
ible, known only to the intellect and divine. Franklin 2005); how the non-composite
The body’s greater affinity to the composite soul relates to tripartition; how reincarna-
and the soul’s to the noncomposite is then tion can be reconciled with an immortal-
established dialectically, with Cebes accept- ity deriving from contact with the Forms;
ing wholeheartedly (81e11) the conclusion whether continuity of experiences and
that the purified soul is stronger and more consciousness across different lives is fea-
independent than the body and so is able sible; the hypothetical method (Rowe
to depart after death to the invisible, with 1993:227–49); the nature of forms – as
which it shares affinity. Within this argument causes (Sedley 1998), reasons or explana-
Socrates explains how contact with the body tions; the question of immanence, and their
contaminates the soul while philosophy pro- precise role in sense-perception and recol-
vides its only means of freedom and purifi- lection (Osborne 1995).
cation through detached reasoning (82e–3b). In contrast, within the text at the conclu-
When this apparently climactic argument sion of the four arguments, Cebes’ objections

77

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 77 3/8/2001 5:12:45 PM


THE DIALOGUES

to the immortality of soul have been met and also 115c–d). While the narrative attention
his doubts overcome. Simmias too is satis- is fixed on the physical experiences of tak-
fied ‘as far as the arguments go’ but admits ing the poison, Socrates’ own thought lies
that he remains doubtful due to the nature of elsewhere. So the dialogue ends with its main
the discussion and his low esteem of human message played out in the dramatic action:
enquiry (Sedley 1990). Socrates has thus led the increasing detachment of the philoso-
an investigation that is a model of coopera- pher’s soul from body, and his consequent
tive dialectic. He has stimulated reactions and serenity.
challenges, probed responses and welcomed The huge scope of the dialogue provides
admissions of doubt. He has offered encour- Plato’s comprehensive response to his philo-
agement and reassurance, and, crucially, at sophical predecessors: to the mystery-reli-
the close guides his followers towards the gions on the true nature of imprisonment and
further testing of hypotheses necessary to purification (62b, 67c–d, 69c–d); to the nat-
reach a definitive account (Phd. 107b). ural scientists on coming-to-be and passing
It is only at this conclusion that Socrates away (96a–c); to Anaxagoras on what nous
turns to myth: the story of the afterlife is as a cosmic force really entails (97b–9d); and
presented not as confirming or superseding to the Pythagoreans on why their theories of
the arguments for immortality of soul but immortality and reincarnation need revision
as simply taking a different approach. The in the light of the forms. Since Plato presents
myth offers a detailed geographical account his distinctive metaphysics and teleology as
of the regions of the afterlife and the jour- a development of Socrates’ principles, Phd.
neys of the souls after death. It provides a asserts his position in the Socratic succession
teleological perspective of the universe as a (Most 1993) and their shared preeminence in
place of intelligent design where goodness is the Greek philosophical tradition.
rewarded. While the mass of souls after death
remain bound in the physical realm, the phi-
losopher’s soul alone gains its freedom to live
‘bodiless’ forever, in beautiful dwelling places PHAEDRUS
beyond the earth (114c). The myth therefore
justifies the gladness of the philosopher at Alessandra Fussi
death and, for the rest, calls attention to the The dialogue (dramatic date:418–16; cf.
urgent need to philosophize in the here-and- Nails 2002:314) can be divided into a pro-
now in order to seize this brief chance to logue, three speeches on erôs, love (q.v.) and
escape from the horrors of the underworld a discussion of good and bad speaking and
and eternal reincarnation (Pender 2011). writing. In contrast with the Symposium (a
While the grandeur of the myth opens narrated dialogue on erôs whose main scene
an eternal perspective, the spell is broken takes place at night, in a private house, with
as Socrates turns to the practical need to many speakers) the Phaedrus is a performed
bathe before drinking the poison – to save dialogue with only two characters, who con-
the women the trouble of washing a dead verse during the day and mostly in the coun-
body (115a). This detail intensifies the grow- tryside. Phaedrus is the dramatic link between
ing divergence between Socrates as an eter- the two dialogues: the ‘father of the logos’ in
nally living soul and Socrates as a corpse (see the Smp. (177d5) plays a similar role in the

78

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 78 3/8/2001 5:12:45 PM


THE DIALOGUES

Phdr. (cf. Socrates’ comment to this effect their promises (Phdr. 234ab); in the second
at 242a7–b4). Socrates and Phaedrus walk speech, delivered by Socrates in competition
along the Ilissus River and exchange speeches with Lysias, the fictional speaker is a con-
while lying under the shade of a plane tree, cealed lover who passes as a non-lover. Here
with the sun reaching its zenith at the end of the relationship between erôs and beauty is
Socrates’ second speech (Griswold 1986:34). more complex, because envy enters the scene
In the highly refined cultural setting of the (Fussi 2006). The lover is initially allured by
Smp., the speakers compete to deliver the the beauty of the boy (Phdr. 238b7–c4), but,
best encomium of erôs (Smp. 177d2–5, being a slave to pleasure, he ‘will turn his boy
198c5–9b5; on encomiastic discourse in the into whatever is most pleasing to himself’
two dialogues, cf. Nightingale 1995:110–13, (238e; trans. Nehamas and Woodruff 1995).
138–9, 154–7). Not the positive, but the Since, however, ‘a sick man takes pleasure
negative sides of erôs are highlighted in the in anything that does not resist him, but
first two speeches of the Phdr. (cf. Rosen sees anyone who is equal or superior as an
1988:78–101). It is only as an afterthought enemy’ (238e–9a), the lover (older and uglier
that Socrates decides to pronounce a speech than the beloved: 240d8–e1) comes to resent
in praise of erôs, the so-called palinode, the beauty of the boy. Rather than honouring
because, if erôs is a god or something divine, and protecting the beloved, he degrades his
the previous accusations were shameful and physical beauty (239c3–d8), and hampers his
blasphemous (Phdr. 242de). potential for mental growth (239a2–c2).
Glaring light, extreme heat, the chorus of This view of erôs derives from the con-
the cicadas (230c3, 258e6–9d8) are carefully cealed lover’s thesis that two principles fight
marked off as a background to the conver- for rule in the soul: when acquired opinion
sation, and central themes of the dialogue rules through reason, it aims at the best, but
emerge from the characters’ response to their when the innate desire for pleasure prevails,
natural surroundings. Socrates emphatically the person becomes sick and completely
highlights the beauty of the place (230b2–c5), unreliable (whether this conception exempli-
while Phaedrus, a valetudinarian, finds the fies Plato’s previous theories is a matter of
surroundings only fit for physical exercise debate: cf. Nussbaum 1986; Price 1989). In
(cf. Ferrari 1987:4–9). Phaedrus’ insensitivity the palinode, however, Socrates presents a tri-
to natural beauty matches his philosophical partite image of the soul (q.v.). He likens the
insensitivity: when Socrates’ palinode is over, human soul to a winged chariot composed
he fails to raise any questions and rushes to by a charioteer (reason) and two horses
imagine how Lysias, the rhetorician, might (spiritedness and appetite). Arguably, the
compete (Phdr. 257c). soul’s wing symbolizes erôs (Griswold:94–9),
The relationship between beauty (q.v.) as it mediates among the parts of the soul,
and erôs is central in the dialogue (Hyland transforming the natural run of the horses
2008:64–90). In the first speech in defence of into upward movement to the hyperuranian
the non-lover (a written text by Lysias read region, where the soul can contemplate the
aloud by Phaedrus) lovers are criticized for forms (q.v.). Socrates’ reflection moves from
their fickleness: attracted by the beautiful the nature of the divine soul to that of the
body of the beloved, as the bloom of youth human soul, and from the condition that
fades they abandon the boy and break all the latter enjoys before incarnation, to the

79

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 79 3/8/2001 5:12:45 PM


THE DIALOGUES

travails encountered during its worldly life. unity of the dialogue, Burger 1980; Griswold
When a soul loses its wings, it falls and takes 1986:157–201; cf. Hackforth 1972:136–7).
on an earthly body. Only those souls which Rhetoric, present in the first half of the Phdr.
contemplated true being, however, can take in the form of a written speech and two
on human bodies, and, of these, only that extemporaneous ones – all aimed at persuad-
soul which was nourished on the forms ing a young beloved – becomes thematic
long enough will take the body of a man in the second half, where those speeches
who will become a ‘lover of wisdom or of are analysed in light of their being artfully
beauty or who will be cultivated in the arts composed or not (Phdr. 262c5–6b1). True
and prone to erotic love’ (248d). Philosophy, rhetoric (q.v.) is distinguished from art-
erôs and beauty are, therefore, closely linked less practise (259e4–60e5), and defined as
together. Only the form of beauty, among the the art of ‘directing the souls by means of
beings that truly are, can be perceived by the speech’ (psychagogia tis dia logon, 261a6–7,
senses. The process of recollection (q.v.) from cf. 271c10). According to Socrates, rhetori-
earthly beauty to beauty itself can be set in cians ought to know the truth concerning
motion in a philosophical soul through fall- the subjects they want to address (259e4–6,
ing in love (250d). The beautiful face of the 273d1–3), since a good composition mir-
beloved allows the wings of the soul to grow rors in its structure the natural structure of
back, radically transforming the behaviour its object, exhibiting the organic unity of a
of the person who, as both Lysias’ non-lover living creature (264c2–5). Good rhetoricians,
(231d4–6) and Socrates’ concealed lover therefore, are also dialecticians (266c1),
(241a4b3) had pointed out, when in love capable of mastering the art of collection
acts as if he was no longer himself. The sight and division (263b6–c, cf. 273e1–4). Indeed,
of beauty, however, can have different out- in Socrates’ account, only philosophers can
comes, since it initiates a struggle among the become good rhetoricians (cf. 261a3–5,
three parts of the soul. When reason loses, 273d–e), since rhetoricians ought to acquire
behaviours like those criticized in the first knowledge concerning not only the subjects
two speeches are likely to ensue, and love can they discuss but also the souls of those they
become a shameful affair. Paradoxically, rea- strive to persuade (271a1–2). The ideal rhet-
son wins the struggle with the bad horse not orician will study the nature of the soul in
when it tries to control its team, but when its general – whether it is uniform or composite
concentration shifts from the team to beauty (270d1, cf. 230a) – as well as the different
itself, that is, when the beauty of the beloved kinds of souls and characters in particular
reminds the lover of his ‘prior’ experience of (271b1–d8). Furthermore, he will be able
divine beauty. Controlling the two horses, to detect in practise which speeches are best
thus, is not the goal, but the outcome of rec- suited to whom (271d8–2a8), and to grasp
ollection (Ferrari 1992:266). the right occasions for speaking and being
Different kinds of souls react differ- silent (272a4). The Phdr. ends with a cri-
ently to beauty: when the palinode is over, tique of writing (274–9), which has attracted
Socrates and Phaedrus turn to discuss which much discussion among scholars, especially
kinds of speeches and writings are beauti- in light of Plato’s choice to write dialogues
ful, which are shameful, and why (Phdr. (Derrida 1972a; Hyland 2008:115–35; cf.
258d1–5; 259e1–2; on the supposed lack of Szlezák 1999).

80

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 80 3/8/2001 5:12:45 PM


THE DIALOGUES

PHILEBUS digressions into abstruse matters of method-


ology and ontology. A principal challenge for
Verity Harte interpreting the Phlb. is making sense of its
The Philebus is one of Plato’s later works. structure.
Among these, it is unusual in featuring The first digression follows Socrates’
Socrates as lead speaker. This return of and Protarchus’ disagreement over whether
Socrates goes with the Socratic character of or not pleasure – and Socrates’ intellectual
the dialogue’s topic: the nature of the good candidates also – come in various kinds,
and of the good human life in particular. The kinds that make a difference to their value.
dialogue stages a contest between pleasure Socrates’ insistence that they do leads to his
and a family of intellectual candidates includ- more general claim that such structural com-
ing reason and knowledge to determine plexity is omnipresent in objects of system-
which, if either, is ‘that state or disposition of atic investigation. Socrates proposes a general
soul capable of providing the happy life for method for systematic investigation based on
all people’ (Phlb. 11d4–6). It concludes that a claim about the nature of things: that eve-
neither pleasure nor the intellectual candi- rything is composed of one and many, having
dates win first prize: a life containing a mix- within it both limit (peras) and unlimited-
ture of pleasure and reason is better than a ness (apeirian) (Phlb. 16c9–10). Given this
life containing pleasure or reason alone. But ontology, Socrates’ method proposes serial
the intellectual candidates are more highly division and enumeration of each complex
ranked in an evaluation of what contributes unity into its constituent kinds, ceasing – ‘let-
to the value of this victorious mixed life. ting each one of them go into the unlimited’
The Phlb. is a ‘direct dialogue’, a direct (16e1–2) – only when every component has
conversation involving the principal inter- been enumerated.
locutors without introduction or narration. Protarchus baulks at applying such sys-
It purports to begin in the middle of a con- tematic investigation to pleasure and asks
versation. Outside the frame of the dialogue, that Socrates do so. Instead, Socrates con-
Socrates has been defending the claim of the jures one of the swiftest and most impor-
intellectual candidates in this competition tant of the dialogue’s arguments (20b–2c).
with pleasure against the hedonism of one Faced with a choice between two lives – a
Philebus. Philebus, however, ‘has withdrawn’ life in which there is pleasure, but none of
(11c8), leaving one Protarchus to be Socrates’ the intellectual candidates and an intellec-
interlocutor in defence of pleasure’s claim. tual life with no pleasure – Protarchus rejects
This pointed offstage placement of Philebus not only the purely intellectual life, but also
may itself be part of an argument against an the life containing pleasure alone, conclud-
extreme form of hedonism as defending a ing that a life in which both are present is
life removed from the human rational sphere better than either. Protarchus rejects the life
(Frede 1997:94–5; McCabe 2000:128–34). of pleasure alone because a life in which
Given its topic and vivid presentation, one constantly experiences maximal pleas-
one might expect the dialogue to be among ure, but does not know one is doing so nor
Plato’s more popular works. That it is not so remember one has is not a life that he – or
is largely due to the interruption of the other- any person – would rationally choose to
wise smooth flow of its contest by apparent live. This ‘Choice of Lives’ argument could,

81

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 81 3/8/2001 5:12:45 PM


THE DIALOGUES

in principle, mark the end of the contest of body or soul (Phlb. 31c–2b). Deprived
between pleasure and the intellectual can- of such optimal conditions, an animal can,
didates, giving victory to neither. In fact, it through perception, recognize this depriva-
leads to a version of the promised system- tion as painful; through memory, identify and
atic investigation of pleasure and the intel- desire what would restore its optimal condi-
lectual candidates in the service of a second tion; and, through human imagination and
contest – as to which of these competitors reason, derive pleasure from the confident
is responsible for the value of the victorious expectation of its restoration. When these
mixed life – and to a more detailed descrip- mechanisms err – in particular, when our
tion of this victorious life. confident expectations about future pleas-
Socrates does not immediately embark ure are wrong or exaggerated – we experi-
on the systematic investigation of pleasure ence one or another kind of ‘false pleasure’.
and the intellectual candidates, but starts (Plato’s understanding of the falsity of false
further back, dividing beings in general into pleasures has been the subject of much dis-
four kinds (23c–7c). Two – ‘unlimited’ (apei- pute, for which see Evans 2008; Frede 1985;
ron) and ‘limit’ (peras) – pick up the claim Harte 2003–4.) By the same token, even
about the nature of things that underlay realistically appraised restorative pleasures
his earlier method, although it is disputed are mostly irretrievably mixed up with pain:
whether these terms are used consistently in mostly – Socrates identifies as ‘true’ certain
the two different passages. (Contrast Striker perceptual and intellectual pleasures that
1970 and Frede 1997:202–5 with Gosling replenish painless lacks of which we are una-
1975:186 and Meinwald 1998. For my own ware (Phlb. 51a–3c). Nevertheless, all such
view, see Harte 2002:78–208). Third is the restorative pleasures are dependent for what-
mixture of limit and unlimited, to which the ever value they have on the value of the opti-
victorious mixed life is assigned. Pleasure is mal condition they restore. Hence, this – not
agreed, on somewhat dubious grounds, to be pleasure – must be the locus of value.
of the kind, unlimited. Socrates’ intellectual Brief by comparison, Socrates’ investiga-
candidates are assigned to a fourth kind, the tion of the intellectual candidates (55c–9d)
cause of mixture, in an early version of the also uses truth as a criterion to evaluate dif-
argument from design (28d–38d), according ferent intellectual activities, based on the use
to which the order apparent in the universe therein of forms of measurement. This appeal
is explicable only by appeal to an intelligent to measurement foreshadows its role in the
cause or designer. (See Frede 1997:213–21 final awarding of prizes in the dialogue’s
for appropriate caution in drawing this com- contest. Though noteworthy for its inclusion
parison. For the history of ‘design arguments’ of both pleasure and practical crafts in its
in antiquity, see Sedley 2007a.) victorious, mixed life, the dialogue’s ‘practi-
This assignment of the intellectual candi- cal’ turn is offset by the abstract character of
dates presages the way in which, in the ensu- first and second prize-winners in its fivefold
ing examination of pleasure, Plato’s most prize giving (66a–c). These go to geometrical
detailed psychology is used to show how features of the life’s construction: proportion,
pleasure is dependent upon Socrates’ candi- measure and so on. Third and fourth prizes
dates. Pleasure is identified with perceived go to Socrates’ intellectual candidates. Fifth
processes of restoration of optimal conditions prize goes to true pleasures, the only kind

82

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 82 3/8/2001 5:12:45 PM


THE DIALOGUES

of pleasure to make it into the prizewinning distinct from beasts. This definition is judged
components of the winning life. erroneous because human herd-rearing is
The Phlb. – its discussion of pleasure only a small part of herd-rearing gener-
especially – was influential in antiquity, for ally and does not by itself comprise a form
example, providing important background (eidos 262b; q.v.). There follows a tutorial on
to the psychology developed by Aristotle in proper definition in which Young Socrates
de Anima and Parva Naturalia, as well as to (YS) is advised to divide according to forms
his treatment of pleasure in Nicomachean (kat’eidê 262e) by cutting things ‘through the
Ethics. middle’ (dia meson).
After testing YS with a few less-than-
serious definitions of human being (including
‘featherless biped’), the Eleatic observes that
POLITICUS (STATESMAN) they have not yet distinguished the statesman
from other human care providers like farm-
Kenneth Sayre ers, bakers and doctors. Making that distinc-
Plato’s Politicus is introduced (Plt. 258a) tion, he says, requires a new beginning. He
as third in a projected quartet of dialogues: then recounts a myth contrasting the age of
the Theaetetus (a discussion of knowledge Zeus (the present age) with the age of Cronus
between Socrates and the young mathemati- (for detailed commentary on the myth, see
cian, Theaetetus), the Sophist (a conversation Lane 1998; Miller 2002; also q.v. Myth).
between Theaetetus and a master dialectician Under Cronus the universe runs back-
from Elea on the art of verbal deception), the wards and order is maintained by divine con-
Plt. (between the Eleatic master and another trol. Human beings spring full grown from
young mathematician named Socrates) and a the earth and become increasingly younger
fourth dialogue on philosophy between the until they disappear. All needs are satisfied
two Socrateses which was never written. by a bountiful earth and animals live with-
The Plt.’s ostensible topic is the art of out preying on one another. When Cronus
statecraft (kingship). At the very middle of releases control, however, the world becomes
the dialogue (283c–5c), however, there is a increasingly disorderly, creatures fend for
succinct analysis of normative measurement themselves at each other’s expense and
on which statecraft is said to depend, imme- humans require god-given gifts of fire and
diately following which we are told explicitly craft for sheer survival. At the chaotic end of
that the conversation’s primary concern is this sequence the universe reverses direction
not with statecraft but with making its par- and the age of Zeus begins.
ticipants better dialecticians. Statesmanship The express purpose of the myth is to
is the subject with reference to which the dia- show that the paradigm of shepherding, epit-
logue teaches its dialectical lessons. omized by Cronus, is a mismatch for civic
One tactic followed by the Eleatic master leadership in the age of Zeus. This paradigm
is to make mistakes deliberately for instruc- gives rise to the confusion between states-
tional purposes. Statesmanship is defined men and care providers like farmers and doc-
initially as a self-directive kind of theoreti- tors, and it provides no help in studying the
cal knowledge dealing with care for living manner of kingly rule. Another paradigm is
subjects, specifically with herds of humans as needed. After a brief examination of the use

83

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 83 3/8/2001 5:12:45 PM


THE DIALOGUES

of paradigms in learning grammar (a ‘para- In beginning the final definition of states-


digm of paradigms’, Plt. 277d), the Eleatic manship (Plt. 287b), the Eleatic cautions
proposes weaving as a more helpful para- that the divisions will not always be dichoto-
digm for statecraft under present conditions. mous. Nor will they be confined to the right
Weaving is defined first as a skill of fab- hand side. Indeed, nondichotomous division
ricating woolen garments for protective along the left was previously introduced in
wear. Like the initial definition of statecraft, the definition of weaving, a departure from
however, this attempt fails to distinguish its the format followed earlier in the dialogue.
definiendum from related arts (e.g. carding The final definition begins by separat-
and fulling). A revised definition classifies ing civic arts into direct and contributory
these associated arts as merely contributive causes, which later are then subdivided
and singles out weaving as the manufacture into seven parts (e.g. tool making, vehicle
of woolen clothing by intertwining warp and manufacture). Direct causes are divided into
woof (283a). governors and servants, the latter further
Both weaving and statesmanship, like all divided into classes typified by slaves, mer-
other arts, depend upon due measure (to chants, clerks and priests. Here the Eleatic
metrion 284a). The same holds for dialectic expresses concern that the statesman might
(q.v.) itself. In a brief discussion at the very become hidden in a group described as ‘the
heart of the dialogue (283c–5c), the Eleatic greatest enchanters among the sophists’
contrasts two kinds of measurement. One (291c). This danger is forestalled by divid-
compares excess and deficiency (also termed ing governors into leaders of genuine and
the great and the small 283e) with respect imitative (303c) polities, including kingly
to each other, the other measures them with and tyrannical monarchies, aristocracies and
respect to normative standards (the mean, oligarchies and lawful and lawless democra-
the fitting, the timely and the requisite 284e). cies. Among leaders of genuine polities, the
The latter (normative measurement) is pre- statesman is finally divided from his gover-
requisite not only for art (q.v.) but for the nor subordinates, notably generals, judges
difference between good and bad in human and rhetoricians.
affairs (283e). If ‘due measure’ did not exist, At the end of this formal definition
there would be no arts, no products of arts (305e), statesmanship emerges as the civic
and no difference between good and bad. art controlling all other arts involved in the
This key passage on measurement employs life of a genuine polity. After this paradig-
terminology characteristic of Plato’s late matic illustration of dialectical procedure,
(post-Parmenides) ontology. Both excess and the Eleatic returns to matters of practical
deficiency and great and small are designa- statesmanship.
tions of the principle which, according to The paradigm of weaving is brought to
Aristotle’s rendition of Plato’s views, coop- bear once again at Plt. 305e with a discus-
erates with unity in producing forms and sion of the statesman’s practical task of
with forms in generating sensible things. The weaving opposing temperaments into an
Plt. is one of several dialogues expressing integrated social fabric. ‘Warp’ and ‘woof’ for
such views, sometimes referred to as Plato’s this fabric are provided by the polity’s more
Unwritten Doctrines (q.v.) (for details, see courageous and more peaceable characters,
Sayre 2005, 2006). respectively. When these groups interbreed

84

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 84 3/8/2001 5:12:46 PM


THE DIALOGUES

and are imbued with civic virtue (true opin- something common – and offers a myth to
ion about the beautiful, the just and the good illustrate how virtue binds civilized society
309c), the result is a unified and prosperous (see Shortridge 2007) – still virtue is teach-
state (311c). able: for example, punishment of criminals
and naughty children alike aims to instil
virtue in them. Moreover, some people
even excel in virtue, which can be taught
PROTAGORAS by specialists. This issue is very important
to Plato, since if virtue is teachable, then it
Daniel C. Russell should be some kind of knowledge (q.v.). It
Protagoras, a so-called Socratic dialogue, is also important in his assessment of the
features conversations between Socrates sophists (q.v.): they claim to teach virtue,
and the sophist Protagoras, a self-professed but can they explain what sort of knowl-
teacher of virtue (q.v.). The focus of the edge virtue is?
dialogue is whether virtue can be taught, Prt. 328d–4c. In order to understand
and along the way Plato also examines sev- whether virtue is teachable, Socrates says, he
eral other issues: whether virtue is a unity; needs to know how the several virtues are
whether virtue is knowledge; the possibility related to each other. As the dialogue unfolds,
and nature of akrasia (q.v.); and the value Socrates’ concern becomes clear: if virtue is
of pleasure (q.v.). The dialogue falls roughly teachable, then it must be a unified body of
into five sections. knowledge; but does Protagoras think virtue
Prt. 309a–17e. Socrates narrates how is knowledge, or a unity? Socrates first asks
he was awakened early by a young friend, questions about unity, and in reply Protagoras
Hippocrates, eager to meet and study with says that the virtues are not the same but all
Protagoras, recently arrived in Athens. distinct parts of virtue; moreover, these parts
Socrates suggests that they meet Protagoras are heterogeneous, like the parts of the face,
to see whether he is a fit teacher, and this separable from each other and dissimilar to
sets the tone of the dialogue: sophists pro- each other. Socrates then asks Protagoras
fess to alter their students’ very souls, and about three pairs of virtues – justice (q.v.)
students have reason to be cautious. They and piety (q.v.), wisdom and temperance,
find Protagoras at the home of his Athenian and temperance and justice – in each case
patron, where he has been giving presenta- suggesting that Protagoras accepts more
tions of his rhetorical prowess before several cohesion within these pairs than his previous
prominent Athenians (the extended fam- statements suggest.
ily of Pericles), other sophists (Hippias and The heart of this discussion is Protagoras’
Prodicus) and his own ‘chorus’ (315b) of view as to whether to have any one of the vir-
hangers-on. tues is to have them all, what scholars often
Prt. 317e–28d. Socrates questions call the ‘reciprocity of the virtues’ or the
Protagoras about whether virtue really is ‘unity of the virtues’ (see Manuwald 2005).
teachable. Protagoras replies with a long, Plato takes up this thesis in several other dia-
eloquent discussion – often called his ‘Great logues, but it is significant here for the con-
Speech’ – on the nature and the teaching nection that Plato clearly draws between it
of virtue. He argues that while virtue is and the very idea that virtue is teachable.

85

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 85 3/8/2001 5:12:46 PM


THE DIALOGUES

Prt. 334c–49a. Protagoras soon tires of that pleasure and pain are the fundamental
giving short answers, preferring to make motivational drives. In that case, they would
speeches instead, and the conversation agree that the ‘art of measurement’ guaran-
breaks down. After a struggle over how to tees right action: right action, on this view,
proceed, Protagoras questions Socrates, is also one that there is most motivation to
focusing on an apparent inconsistency in do, and the ‘art of measurement’ identifies
a poem of Simonides, viz. that it is both such action. Such an advertisement would
hard to become good and not hard (rather, both appeal to Protagoras’ audience and por-
impossible) to be good. Thus begins what is tray virtue as both teachable and immune to
sometimes called a literary digression, in the wilful wrongdoing. However, it also makes
middle of the dialogue. Socrates discusses courage a form of knowledge, like the other
the poem briefly with the sophist Prodicus, virtues (and wisdom in particular), contra
and is eventually persuaded to make his Protagoras’ earlier assertion. Protagoras
own speech, which includes a good deal of then breaks off the discussion, and in part-
humour and irony. To eliminate the apparent ing, Socrates says that whereas originally
inconsistency, Socrates distinguishes between Protagoras affirmed and Socrates doubted
the process of becoming good and the state that virtue is teachable, their positions have
of being good (see Baltzly 1992 for discus- now reversed. Like many Socratic dialogues,
sion). But what is most significant about Prt. is ‘aporetic’, ending apparently without
Socrates’ speech is his insistence there that solving its central puzzles.
no one does wrong willingly – the so-called This passage is among the most contro-
Socratic paradox. Plato revisits this provoc- versial in the corpus (see the commentaries
ative idea throughout his career, and there is of Denyer 2008 and Taylor 1976). On one
enormous scholarly controversy over how to hand, it puts forth normative and psycho-
characterize the progression of his thought logical hedonism, as well as a quantitative
on this issue. This idea is also a central issue model of virtue, but such ideas seem to
in the dialogue’s final arguments, which fol- conflict with Plato’s other dialogues; on the
low immediately. other, it also defends such Socratic theses as
Prt. 349a–62. Socrates finally steers the the reciprocity of the virtues and the Socratic
discussion back to the relations between the paradox (on the latter see Wolfsdorf 2006).
virtues. Protagoras now says that while there Much controversy surrounds the relation
may be connections between some virtues, between Prt. and Gorgias particularly, since
‘courage is completely different from all the in Grg. Socrates is highly critical of hedon-
rest’. In reply, Socrates focuses on Protagoras’ ism. This controversy has not been conclu-
view that the knowledge he imparts is some- sive: some deny that these dialogues actually
thing fine and powerful. Socrates suggests disagree on this point (e.g. Rudebusch 1999);
presenting this knowledge as a skill – the ‘art and even if they do, perhaps Plato simply
of measurement’ – for measuring the quanti- changed his mind. Yet others argue that Prt.
ties of pleasure and pain an action produces itself gives no evidence that Plato endorsed
(see Nussbaum 1986:ch. 4; Richardson hedonism, other dialogues aside (e.g. Russell
1990). This is because laypersons would 2005). But at present, there is little reason
accept that an action is right when there is to anticipate scholarly consensus on these
preponderance of pleasure over pain, and points.

86

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 86 3/8/2001 5:12:46 PM


THE DIALOGUES

REPUBLIC Bk 2 replaces these interlocutors with


Plato’s brothers Glaucon and Adeimantus.
Nickolas Pappas They restate Thrasymachus’ challenge sys-
The Republic is among Plato’s greatest works tematically, asking Socrates not merely to
and likely his most controversial. Its subject silence one critic but to defend morality
is dikaiosunê ‘justice’ (q.v.), both as an indi- against all critics (357a–b). Thereafter they
vidual human virtue (q.v.) and a feature of let Socrates lead them through the thicket of
political existence. The dialogue also ranges the R.’s argument. They are civilized, even
over topics in metaphysics, education (q.v.) placid; they want to learn.
and aesthetics (q.v.); but its proposals for The R. thus represents two genres of
political reform have inspired both the most Platonic dialogue, bk 1 resembling those con-
enthusiastic revolutionary thinking and the tentious, inconclusive dialogues called ‘early’
most horrified anti-utopianism. or ‘Socratic’ while the remainder belongs
Whether Plato wrote the R. all at once or in with ‘Platonic’ dialogues about Forms, soul
stages, it was later editors who divided it into and other positive doctrines. Some schol-
10 books, those divisions sometimes registering ars believe Plato wrote bk 1 earlier as a
turns in the conversation (beginnings of bks 2, freestanding dialogue, revisiting it later to
5, 8, 10). The change after bk 1 separates its ren- expand and improve its argument. More
dered scene and characters from the drier con- often it is thought he wrote bk 1 deliberately
structive argumentation that takes up bks 2–10. in the style of his own shorter dialogues, to
Bks 2–10 rarely acknowledge that their conver- contrast their negative and personal cross-
sation is unfolding anywhere special; bk 1 sets examinations with another mode of phi-
the stage in Piraeus, the port of Athens, at the losophizing, something less embattled and
home of Polemarchus, the son of Cephalus, a therefore less exciting, but with the promise
noncitizen who has grown old and wealthy. It to issue in conclusions – something closer to
is summer, the year perhaps around 422 BCE, teaching philosophy (Kahn 1993).
although scholars have debated this consensus, The R. as a whole is powered by an anal-
many arguing for a dramatic date a full decade ogy that Socrates introduces in bk 2: A soul
later (Nails 1998). If it is 422 the Peloponnesian is like a city (R. 368e–9a). Justice and other
War has paused in a truce; Socrates is about 50. virtues in a human soul (q.v.) share struc-
(Plato wrote the R. decades later, when its active tural characteristics with the justice and
participants were dead.) other virtues of a state. The parallel between
Socrates spends bk 1 trying to define and individual and collective virtues emerges
defend justice (Lycos 1987; Sparshott 1966). from an underlying tripartite organization
His host’s father is a pious man possessed of functions common to city and soul. This
of virtues but no skill at justifying them. analogy lets the R. explore ethical and politi-
Polemarchus represents the new ideas of cal matters together (Cooper 1977; Ferrari
Sophists and poets. Socrates reduces him to 2005).
silence too. Then Thrasymachus mounts an
attack on morality: ‘Justice’ refers to nothing (I) POLITICAL THOUGHT
but what benefits those in power (R. 338c).
For that reason behaving justly is never in As a document of political philosophy the
anyone’s interests (343c). R. is sometimes called utopian. But it makes

87

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 87 3/8/2001 5:12:46 PM


THE DIALOGUES

concessions to economic and political reali- Will the best city contain the best individuals
ties (abandoning the simple town Socrates after all?
first proposes to examine a sophisticated city The R. focuses on the rulers and soldiers,
that Glaucon considers more widely attrac- collectively ‘guardians’. They live commu-
tive: 372d–e); and it worries how to imple- nally, sharing meals and sleeping in bar-
ment its reforms (e.g. 471c–d). The city it racks without privacy (416d–17b). Men
proposes is meant to follow from axioms and women (q.v.) rule and fight side by side
applicable to every society: A1: People come (452a; Bluestone 1987); ‘marriages’ are tem-
together to create a new social unity (369c). porary breeding assignments, orchestrated by
A2: In a well-run society people specialize the rulers so that the fittest guardians repro-
their labour (369e–70a). The R. appeals to duce (459a–60a). Their children are reared
A1 when mandating policies that promote in nurseries not knowing who their parents
concord, while A2 keeps each citizen assigned are (460b–d).
to a single task. Indeed, since Platonic justice The abolition of the family leaves children
is cooperation among disparate groups in a attached only to fellow guardians. Their iden-
city (433a), justice combines the axioms. tity is their public identity. Athenian tragedy
A2 also yields Plato’s class analysis, when worried how to coordinate family loyalties
‘labour’ means very broadly the three civic with loyalties to the state; Plato undoes this
functions. People serve their society by pro- problem at a stroke by eliminating families.
ducing goods and services. Citizens perform Finally the rulers must be philosophers –
another civic function by fighting in the mili- ‘philosopher-kings’ as they are popularly
tary. And they serve to the extent that they known – though it is important to remember
participate in governance. So Plato divides that they are both men and women (473c–d).
the city into three classes: a small group of If the R. creates its classes by dividing actual
rulers, a selective army and the productive Athenians into two or three functions, then
mass of the population (414a–b). This is not the philosopher-kings and -queens reflect
a simplification of class divisions in Athens the forcible concatenation of two types, the
but the invention of new classes. The Greek executive and the contemplative. Scholars
cities’ mesoi ‘middle ones’ were farmers who debate whether this figure violates A2, and
worked their land, wore armour to serve in how philosophers might be persuaded to be
the infantry and voted in the assembly. Thus, governed, when by their natures they have
Plato’s stratification divides the hoplite- something much better to do (Brown 2000;
farmer-assemblyman into three, signalling Mahoney 1992).
that the idealized citizen of classical Greece Plato’s solution to the tensions inherent
was untenable in a philosophical city. in the philosopher-king recalls his earlier
The functional analysis may make trouble solution to a lesser tension. When Socrates
on Plato’s own terms. Athenian citizens had proposes a standing army he specifies that
to exercise their reason in the assembly, fight these guardians be gentle to fellow citizens
courageously in the army and work as self- but fierce towards enemies (R. 375c). How
interested producers on the farm. They had to to produce a gentle fierce soldier? Education
have the complete souls described by Plato’s (410e): Socrates launches into a treat-
psychology (see below). But those complete ment of poetry and other arts, followed by
humans disappear from the Platonic city. extensive physical education (376c–412b).

88

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 88 3/8/2001 5:12:46 PM


THE DIALOGUES

Analogously, those higher-flying birds, the function expands to include desire for knowl-
philosopher-kings, need intensive intellectual edge (475b); so possessing a soul governed
education. They study the forms and ‘the by reason means both coordinating your
good’ (503e–6a; Sedley 2007b). Their educa- motives and practicing philosophy. Reason
tion also covers mathematics (q.v.) and dia- knows two native activities, as the philoso-
lectic (q.v.) (521d–34e; Burnyeat 2000). pher-kings have two jobs to do.
Socrates argues that the soul is immortal
(II) PSYCHOLOGY AND ETHICS (608d–11a). He recounts a myth (q.v.) of
otherworldly judgement and reincarnation
Socrates discovers a tripartite structure (614b–21b). However religious this argu-
within the soul: reason, spiritedness, desire ment sounds, it accords with the R.’s pattern
(440e–1a). Examples of internal conflict of removing ‘body’ from accounts of motive
show that these are distinct elements or (411e, 518d). All actions can be accounted
motives (437b–40a; Lorenz 2006). for in terms belonging exclusively to soul; no
The most innovative of the three is thumos wonder the soul persists without a body.
‘spirit’ or ‘anger’ (439e), the element that The city and soul work together, rather than
engenders shame and indignation. Without in parallel, in the R.’s overarching argument.
some such element the soul would only pos- They also join in one subsidiary argument.
sess reason and desire, the outcome always
threatening that desires can overpower the (III) THE BENEFITS OF JUSTICE
quiet voice of reason. The spirited part of the
soul possesses irrational energy and therefore The R.’s overarching argument says that the
the strength to resist desires, yet it stands just life is preferable to the unjust life. Justice
near enough to reason to take instruction in the city denotes an establishment in which
from it. If the body is a cage and reason is rulers and ruled respect each other’s func-
the little human trapped inside with desire, a tions and interests, and cooperate in running
many-headed monster, spirit is the lion that the city (433b–d). The many kinds of injus-
this homunculus tames to keep the monster tice are presented as a sequence of decline
at bay (588b–9a). in constitutions, from the best state to an
Desire (q.v.) first appears simple, a self- honour-loving martial aristocracy (timoc-
gratifying wish that moves without thinking racy), then downward through oligarchy and
(437c). But desires vary from sexual desire, the democracy to tyranny (bks 8 and 9).
maddest of all (329c, 458d), through desires Meanwhile, the just soul possesses the
for food and drink, to the most rational seem- appeal of a balanced mental state (443a–b).
ing among them, money love. Most desires co- This sounds intrinsically desirable. But along-
exist: one eats, sees a play. But sexual desire side his history of worsening regimes Socrates
tyrannizes the others (572e) until the sexual recounts the decline among souls, naming
obsessive seeks nothing but forbidden inter- the ever-worse souls after the regimes they
course (572c–d). At the other extreme, love of resemble. Each unjust soul makes the just
money imparts self-discipline (554c–d). type look better off, as bad cities enhance the
Reason is differently ambiguous. First appeal of the good city.
it is the motive that governs other motives, Socrates lingers over the contrast between
the soul’s executive branch. Later reason’s a tyrant and a philosopher. Focusing on the

89

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 89 3/8/2001 5:12:47 PM


THE DIALOGUES

superiority that intellectual pleasures enjoy (q.v.), objects of greater being than ordinary
over unnecessary bodily pleasures – all lust things.
and illusion – Socrates concludes that the Philosophers, who love learning, differ
best person’s life is far happier than the worst from ‘spectacle-lovers’ thanks to the difference
person’s (587e; Parry 2007). between forms – what philosophers pursue in
their studies – and the sights and sounds of
(IV) POETRY AND THE OTHER ARTS particular objects that a fan of entertainment
rushes to see and hear: tragedies, music and
The R.’s politics and psychology combine dif- paintings (475e–6b). Individual things can only
ferently in its attacks on poetry (q.v.). The first be objects of doxa ‘belief, opinion’ (479d–e).
treatment (bks 2–3) emphasizes politics and Forms are objects of knowledge (476d).
the young guardians’ education. Socrates eval- Often, as here, Plato’s Socrates introduces
uates the content of epic poems and Athenian forms as if his interlocutor knew what they
tragedies: What do they say about gods and were. He speaks of those objects that phi-
heroes (377a–91e)? His assessment becomes losophers love to learn about as ‘the beautiful
formalist when it banishes drama and narra- itself’, for example, Glaucon acknowledges
tives containing direct speech by characters. them (476a). Then (as elsewhere) the R. fol-
Mimêsis ‘representation, enactment’ amounts lows an argument for insiders with one directed
to inauthenticity or deception (392b–4c). to open audiences, in this case the experience
Anyone who acts out the part of an inferior lovers being differentiated from philosophers
person will pick up bad habits (395d). (479a–e). This argument says: Particular
The arguments in bk 10 view mimêtic objects hold their properties equivocally, being
poetry from the soul’s perspective (595a), beautiful in one respect and ugly in another;
understanding mimêsis as representation likewise both large and small, good and bad.
or imitation (q.v.; Nehamas 1982b). Like What is and is not F (for any property F) can-
painting, mimêtic poetry is the imitation of not be clearly known as a form can be. For,
appearance (598b); therefore it strengthens by hypothesis a form simply is F. Largeness
the worst part of the soul, the part that feeds is large, not large and small (Nehamas 1979;
on illusions (602c–d; cf. 585d). Tragedy stirs Patterson 1985). One knows what is and has
up pity and grief and weakens the soul’s opinions about what is and is not.
capacity to govern itself (606a–d). If Socrates is right that non-forms cannot
Bk 10 extends the claims of bk 3. Not be known, the argument offers a pragmatic
only children but nearly everyone risks being consideration in favour of forms’ existence.
corrupted by mimêtic poetry. Not only the Without them there is no knowledge. If any-
depictions of bad characters corrupt but one knows anything, the philosopher knows
depiction as such, for it trades in appearance forms. The lover of spectacles, sensations and
alone, not truth. things possesses mere opinions about the vis-
ible world.
(V) METAPHYSICS
(VI) THE GOOD
A digression from the tight analogy between
city and discussion of the ruler leads the R. The form of the good (q.v.) is the conscious
to its central metaphysical subject: the forms goal and consummation of the philosophers’

90

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 90 3/8/2001 5:12:47 PM


THE DIALOGUES

education (504a–6a). The good is not one thing? The text is tempted by both possibili-
form among many but in some way a greatest ties. Socrates ranks mental states according
form. To show how they are related Socrates to their objects’ reality (511d–e). But math-
uses a simile (sun), a geometrical image (line) ematical and empirical people look at the
and an allegory (cave). same round bowl and the mind of one goes to
What the sun (q.v.) is among visible objects bodiless circles while the other stays focused
the good is among things understood by intel- on the material bowl (510d). How one thinks
lect (508a–9b). The sun is the cause of other determines what one thinks about.
objects and also provides the light by which The allegory of the cave (q.v.) brings poli-
those who see can see those objects. The good tics back into the metaphysics. The sun again
causes the existence of the forms and makes represents the good; trees and animals stand
it possible for those who can reason to know for forms; the visible world is symbolized by
forms. As the eye is guided by sunlight to see the inside of a huge sunless cave. Within the
what the sun has caused to be, the mind is cave, shapes of trees and animals correspond
guided by the good to know what it has made. to three-dimensional things. Those shapes
The divided line (q.v.) complicates this cast shadows on the cave wall and the shack-
analogy (509d–11e). Socrates divides a line led prisoners experience only these shadows.
into two segments of unequal length, then Socrates tells of one prisoner unchained and
subdivides each segment. The main division turned to see the shapes whose shadows he
separates visible from intelligible; within the had been watching, then the fire that cast
visible domain the subdivision sets objects those shadows (515c–e). Finally he leaves the
against their shadows and reflections. As a cave and truly sees. But he has to return to
tree has greater reality than its reflection, so lead his former fellows, despite the ridicule
too does the intelligible world as a whole awaiting him (516e–17a).
compared to the visible world (Denyer 2007; Why should the prisoner feel obligated to
Smith 1996). go back into the cave; why should the phi-
Within the intelligible realm the opposi- losopher deign to reign? Socrates addresses
tion between being and image (q.v.) distin- that problem (519d–20c) but passes over
guishes forms from mathematical objects. another: If this returning figure is the good
As an object of thought, the circle deserves city’s philosopher, the jeers that greet him
a place in the world known to thought. But sound like the abuse that Socrates endured in
because mathematicians use such objects in a Athens. After all the improvements that the
way that Plato calls ‘hypothetical’ – he seems good city promised, are these its citizens, the
to mean: without defining their terms – same know-nothings who shouted Socrates
imagistic cognition remains mixed into their down in court?
understanding (R. 510c–11a). Mathematicals
stand below those objects of dialectic that
philosophers know through rigorous defini-
tions, the forms (511b–d). SOPHIST
Are there four different grades of objects on
the line, each causing a distinct type of cogni- Noburu Notomi
tion; or do different ways of understanding a Plato’s late dialogue, the Sophist, starts with
single object let it be more than one type of the reference to ‘yesterday’s agreement’ of

91

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 91 3/8/2001 5:12:47 PM


THE DIALOGUES

reunion (Sph. 216a), made at the end of the the soul by means of refutation. These defini-
Theaetetus (210d), and thus dramatically tions show the aspects of the sophist’s activ-
succeeds that dialogue, by introducing a new ity, which were depicted in earlier dialogues
speaker, the visitor from Elea. (Protagoras, Gorgias, Euthydemus, etc.).
When Theodorus introduces the Eleatic However, the sixth definition called ‘soph-
visitor as a ‘philosopher’, Socrates raises a ist of noble lineage’ looks like Socrates, and
question about the confusion between elen- this resemblance casts a strong doubt upon
chus and eristic; he says that it is difficult to the whole inquiry of definition. Also, the
discern many appearances of the philosopher, plurality of definitions causes a serious prob-
for the philosopher is like a god and some- lem because each object must have a single
times appears to be a sophist, a statesman definition of its essence. A new attempt at a
and even a mad person (Sph. 216a–d). On final definition then reveals that the essence
the general assumption that the philosopher, of the sophist’s art lies in the very act of
sophist and statesman constitute three sepa- making such appearances. But when the art
rate kinds, the speakers agree to define these of image making is divided into the mak-
three one by one, starting with the sophist. ing of likenesses (correct images) and that of
This setting of the inquiry may be taken as phantasmata (wrong images), the inquirers
indicating a tripartite project to define the face a series of difficulties, as if the soph-
three figures in three dialogues, namely the ist counterattacks them. From this point,
Sph., the Politicus and the Philosopher. But a long digression of the middle part of the
the last one was never written, so many com- dialogue (Sph. 236d–64b, which modern
mentators conjecture about various reasons scholars see as central and most important)
why Plato gave up the project. On the other starts.
hand, some argue (Frede 1996; Notomi 1999) The difficulties are concerned with
that, as far as the initial purpose is to distin- appearance, image, falsehood and not-being
guish the philosopher from his appearances, (to mê on): ‘appearing without really being
the extant two dialogues suffice to show the so’ and ‘stating a falsehood’ presuppose that
philosopher by defining the other two. If this ‘not-being is’, what was strictly forbidden by
is the case, Plato had no intention to write an Parmenides (236d–7b). The inquirers now
independent dialogue, but Sph. is expected to have to prove, against Parmenides, the proper
provide a key to defining the philosopher as combination of not-being and being (to on),
distinct from the sophist. For an alternative as if committing a ‘parricide’ (241d–2a).
view, see Davidson (1985). Examinations are made in a parallel way
A definition is pursued by dividing a concerning not-being and being. First, it is
genus into species. This method of division shown that self-contradiction results from
is originally proposed in Phaedrus, and fully any attempt to treat ‘not-being’ in isolation:
used in Sph. (see Brown 2010; Gill 2010). it is totally unspeakable or unthinkable, but
The sophist is first defined as a hunter for this conclusion already involved the speaker
rich young men, but then other definitions in speaking of it. Next, it is also shown that
follow: a merchant, a retail dealer and a various attempts to define ‘being’ fail. First,
manufacturing trader of learning, an eristic, both pluralist and monist positions turn out
who fights and earns money in private argu- to be inconsistent and contradictory. Then,
ments and a purifier of wrong opinions in the materialists, who maintain that only

92

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 92 3/8/2001 5:12:47 PM


THE DIALOGUES

bodily things are, and the idealists, called rather than the verb ‘to be’ (see Brown 2008;
‘friends of forms’ (whose theory resembles Notomi 2007).
the earlier theory of forms in Phaedo), are The final inquiry succeeds in defining the
made to accept that being is both things sophist as the imitator of the wise without
changing and things unchangeable. However, really being wise (Sph. 268b–d). This dia-
since this definition does not properly grasp logue thus settles a crucial issue and a long
being as distinct from change and rest, all the concern in Plato’s philosophy, that is, what
attempts fail. Now the inquiry needs ‘joint the sophist is, and how Socrates’ true phi-
illumination’ or ‘parity assumption’ of being losophy differs from sophistry. It provides
and not-being (250e–1a). a basis of ‘logic’ for Aristotle, who makes
The second half of the middle part seeks a full use of its fruits in his logical treatises,
a solution of the difficulties of not-being especially De interpretatione and Sophistici
and falsehood. To prove the correct relation elenchi.
between not-being and being, the inquir-
ers have to secure the proper combination
of kinds in general. They demonstrate how
the greatest kinds (change, rest, identity, dif- SYMPOSIUM
ference and being) relate to each other. This
demonstration itself belongs to the art of dia- Angela Hobbs
lectic (253c–e), and therefore it shows what The Symposium tells of a drinking party in
the philosopher should do, in contrast to the which a variety of characters meet to cel-
sophistic argument that confuses these con- ebrate the tragedian Agathon’s victory in a
cepts so as to produce falsehoods, contradic- dramatic contest; they decide to forgo the
tions and refutations. customary sensuous entertainments and give
After proving the proper combination of speeches instead on erôs, erotic love. Plato
not-being and being (as principles of separa- explores questions about the origins, defini-
tion and combination), and thus by securing tion, aims, objects and effects of erôs both
the possibility of logos in general, the inquir- through what the symposiasts say in their
ers next show that a false statement com- formal speeches and by how they interact;
bines a statement (logos, as the combination he thus gives an indication of what sort of
of a subject and a verb) and not-being. Thus, life and moral character a particular view of
the inquiry of the middle part of the dialogue erôs might promote and reflect. The distance
defends the definition of the sophist as a between the date of composition (c. 384–379
maker of false statements. BCE) and the dramatic dates of the sympo-
The topic discussed most in the latter half sium and the framework conversation (416
of the twentieth-century scholarship was BCE and c. 405 BCE) allows Plato to make
whether, and how, Plato distinguishes dif- ironic references to future events known
ferent uses of the verb ‘to be’. Does he dis- to his readers, such as the downfall of the
tinguish between copula and existence or soldier-statesman Alcibiades, the death of
between identity and predication, or not at Socrates, and the connection between their
all? (see Brown 1986; Owen 1971) However, two fates.
recent studies focus more on the nature of The choice of a relaxed symposium set-
logos (q.v.; discourse, argument or statement) ting enables Plato to reveal different facets

93

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 93 3/8/2001 5:12:47 PM


THE DIALOGUES

of Socrates’ complex personality, such as his presence; the gods will in turn reward us
ability to drink without becoming drunk (cp. after death for self-sacrifice inspired by love.
Laws 633c, on the importance in a state of Phaedrus believes he is portraying love as
regular drinking parties as a means of testing entirely desirable and beneficial; the reader,
self-control). The occasion also allows the however, may feel that his lovers tend to
beautiful Alcibiades to recount how Socrates die young. A more pragmatic view is taken
resisted all his youthful attempts to seduce by Pausanias, who distinguishes between
him; in this respect at any rate, Plato implies, ‘heavenly’ and ‘popular’ erôs; he anticipates
Socrates did not corrupt the young. Diotima to the extent that the quality of erôs
The tale of the drinking party is intri- depends on the nature of its object, and the
cately nested: Apollodorus, a follower of manner in which it is performed. ‘Popular’
Socrates, recounts it to a group of unnamed love is concerned with the body and can be
businessmen, having heard it himself from directed by the male lover (Pausanias envis-
Aristodemus, another Socratic acolyte who ages a male subject) towards either women
was actually present; one of the central or boys; ‘heavenly’ erôs occurs when a man
speeches, that of Socrates, relates Socrates’ is attracted to a boy’s intellect, and is con-
purported conversation with a priestess cerned to further his cultural and political
named Diotima. Furthermore, Aristodemus education. Pausanias depicts heavenly love
cannot remember all the details clearly (Sym. as perfect, but its time limit (the passive
180c) and admits to having fallen asleep role of the boy ‘beloved’ was not considered
towards the end. Plato thereby creates even appropriate for a man) means that it con-
more distance than usual between himself as tains inherent tensions.
author and the content of the speeches and The doctor, Eryximachus, continues the
compels his readers to participate in inter- distinction between good and bad erôs, but,
pretation; we are also invited to reflect on in a further anticipation of Diotima, the
the crucial but unreliable nature of interme- concept of erôs is widened. It is now a cos-
diaries – a central theme of the dialogue – mic force, the attraction of one element for
and how best to get at the truth of different another, and has both physical and moral
kinds of subject matter. What is the relation dimensions: the right kind of attraction leads
between mythos (q.v. Myth) and logos (q.v.)? to harmony and health, the wrong kind to
Can there be a logos of love? conflict and disease. The good erôs recon-
Considerable emphasis is placed on the ciles opposites in fields as diverse as medi-
order of the speeches, which anticipates the cine, music and the climate; it is, critically,
importance of an orderly rational and emo- the force that mediates between humans
tional progression up the rungs of the ladder and gods. Eryximachus assumes that erotic
of love in Diotima’s speech; in general, order, love, properly conducted, is essential for our
not disorder, is seen as the more creative physical and mental well-being. The comic
force in the dialogue (note the banishment of playwright Aristophanes expands on this,
the aulos-girl at 176e; q.v. Women). claiming that to understand love we need to
The first speaker, Phaedrus, gives an know first about the nature of human beings
encomium to romantic love of a particular (189d). Plato thereby invites us to consider
individual. We want our beloved to admire which speaker (and which kind of exper-
us and we thus behave at our best in their tise) gives the most accurate account of our

94

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 94 3/8/2001 5:12:47 PM


THE DIALOGUES

human needs. According to Aristophanes’ reason. We begin by loving a beautiful body,


myth of our origins, humans were once but, if we are guided aright, we will re-chan-
spherical beings (some all male, some all nel this erotic energy onto beautiful souls,
female and some hermaphrodite), but were laws and sciences, until finally we come to
split in two when they challenged the gods. apprehend and love the form of beauty itself,
Bereft, they search the world for their miss- in which blessed state life is truly ‘liveable’
ing half, and this desire for and pursuit of the (211d). Whether this ascent up the ‘ladder of
whole is what we call erôs (192e): the lost love’ requires us to give up our risky attach-
half does not have to be good or beautiful, ments to individual humans is vigorously
but simply one’s own. Those that find their debated: what does contemplation of the
other half yearn to accept Hephaistus’ offer form of beauty actually involve? And can it
and be fused into one. still accurately be described as a state of erôs
Aristophanes’ myth raises profound ques- or has erôs transformed into something else?
tions. If love is defined as a search, then would Furthermore, if the form of beauty is itself
not the completion of this search cancel out beautiful, then would it not be vulnerable to
the conditions that make love possible? Do the Third Man argument?
lovers perceive and love each other as unique, The counter claims of love for a unique
separate individuals or simply as the miss- and irreplaceable individual are movingly put
ing part of themselves? The host Agathon’s forward by Alcibiades, who declines to give
speech, in contrast, self-referentially depicts an account of erôs, offering instead a history
the god Erôs as a beautiful, winsome and of his personal (and sexually unrequited) love
perfectly good youth, but Plato’s intentions for Socrates. Both the creative and destruc-
in including his anodyne poetics become tive possibilities of such an attachment are
clear when Socrates subjects them to an manifest both in his speech and in his inter-
elenchus, arguing (pace Aristophanes) that changes with Socrates and Agathon. Here too
as love is of the beautiful and good things there is keen debate as to how seriously Plato
that it lacks, love itself cannot be beautiful or views Alcibiades’ challenge: he is allowed to
good – an argument that depends on beauty be glamorous and charismatic, and to give
being homogeneous and coextensive with the last speech; on the other hand, his cha-
equally homogeneous goodness. otic and clouded exit perhaps provides the
These conclusions form the basis (201d) dangerous cômus to Plato’s own symposias-
of Socrates’ account of Diotima’s teachings tic entertainment. Socrates then debates with
on love (q.v. Love, Women). Diotima claims Agathon and Aristophanes whether the same
that erôs is a daimonic intermediary between man can write both tragedy and comedy –
god and humans. Its object is permanent maybe Plato believes that in the Smp. he has
possession of what is good (206a), and it achieved both feats with Alcibiades’ help –
achieves this ‘through giving birth in the and, after they too fall asleep, leaves for the
beautiful, in relation to both body and soul’ Lyceum to begin a new day of philosophical
(206b); as personal immortality is not avail- inquiry.
able for mortals, these creations are the best For further information, see Ferrari
substitutes we can achieve. There are differ- (1992), Hobbs (2000:ch. 9; 2006), Hunter
ent grades of creation, and physical offspring (2004), Lesher et al. (2006), Murray (1990),
are the lowest; the highest are the products of Price (1989) and Santas (1988).

95

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 95 3/8/2001 5:12:48 PM


THE DIALOGUES

THEAETETUS youths fertile with conceptions, and delivers


and tests their conceptions (148e–51d).
Ronald Polansky Theaetetus then suggests that knowledge
Shorey (1933) considered Theaetetus is some sort of perception (aisthêsis, 151e),
‘arguabl[y] . . . the richest in thought of all as he has ‘perceived’ the two sorts of num-
the Platonic dialogues’. The dialogue opens bers project into squares. Since Theaetetus
the dramatic series surrounding Socrates’ is vague about ‘perception’, Socrates deliv-
trial and death: Tht., Euthyphro, Sophist, ers the conception by identifying as its ‘par-
Statesman, Apology, Crito and Phaedo, by ents’ Protagorean relativism and Heraclitean
raising the fundamental question, ‘What is flux. These parents are necessary and suf-
knowledge?’ Two great mathematicians, ficient conditions for the conception to be
Theodorus and the young Theaetetus are viable. Extreme individual relativism based
Socrates’ interlocutors. A frame dialogue set on removing any unity and being leaves only
outside Athens, like the Phd., has Euclides relational becoming so that whatever appears
and Terpsion probably in 369 BCE recall- to any sentient being seems ‘knowledge’.
ing Socrates’ death and linking it with the Much of the dialogue is Socrates deliv-
impending death of Theaetetus. Far from ering the conception by linking it with its
corrupting the youth Theaetetus, Socrates ‘parents’ and countering each part of the
seems to have contributed to his intellectual conception (151e–86e). Thus he introduces
success and bravery in battle. and undermines some classic arguments for
The dialogue seeks knowledge of knowl- relativism and scepticism, such as whether
edge. The elderly Theodorus resisting philo- we are now dreaming (158b–d), nothing
sophical conversation, the young Theaetetus universal exists except names (157a–c) and
becomes the main interlocutor led through only shifting aggregates, rather than wholes,
four progressively stronger accounts of truly are (159c). Protagoras is imagined back
knowledge. Theaetetus first names what to life in the dialogue. Forced to defend his
Theodorus teaches and the productive arts as own claim to wisdom if each sentient being
knowledge (Tht. 146c–d), which only offers measures what is true for it, he argues that
instances of knowledge rather than disclosing the wise change perceivers so that they
what knowledge is. Theaetetus is provoked have better, though not truer, perceptions
to recall earlier mathematical insight that (166d–7d). But this Protagorean wisdom
may be pertinent (147c–8b). He had divided presupposes superior insight into the future,
the integers into ‘square numbers’, for exam- so not all appearances are true (177c–9b).
ple, 4, 9, 16 (=n2), with the other integers Protagorean relativism also refutes itself
being ‘oblong numbers’. When squares are by conceding that those disagreeing with
made with areas equal to ‘oblong numbers’, him are correct, for they think themselves
their sides will be incommensurable with the absolutely rather than just relatively correct
sides of the squares of ‘square number’ area, (170a–1c). Heraclitean flux makes things
but the areas of the squares are all commen- change so much that no statement such as
surable. Yet, Theaetetus cannot fashion an ‘knowledge is perception’ has stable truth
account of knowledge like this mathemati- (181b–3b). And Theaetetus’ proposal that
cal work, so Socrates encourages him by perception is knowledge fails since each sense
professing to practise midwifery that detects perceives only its own sort of object, yet we

96

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 96 3/8/2001 5:12:48 PM


THE DIALOGUES

make judgements about objects of all the about which the true judgement is made
senses (184b–6e). Either perception can (206e–8b) or (c) saying what is uniquely dif-
make no judgements at all and does not get ferent about what we would know (208c–
to any truth, or perception cannot get to the 10a). But none of this helps. Anyone can
essence of things to know what they really vocalize a true judgement, which does noth-
are. In what he calls a ‘digression’ at the dia- ing to supplement it. Going through all the
logue’s centre, Socrates contrasts the hustling elements still does not guarantee knowledge
Protagorean courtroom orator with a philos- since a child may spell his entire name but
opher, holding it wisdom to escape this realm be unable to spell the same syllables within
and to liken himself to god (176a–d). other names. And adding the difference to a
The account of knowledge as perception true judgement that must already have the
rejected, Theaetetus suggests that knowl- difference to be about just this thing adds
edge is true judgement (187b). But unless nothing.
there can be false judgement, true judgement They are left with no account of knowledge.
adds nothing to judgement. Several efforts But if the four accounts they have considered
to account for false judgement explore the are all the really likely accounts of knowl-
obstacle of non being, define thought as silent edge, and the accounts of account offered
internal conversation, depict the soul as wax are all the plausible accounts of account or
receiving impressions (191c–5b), and intro- justification, then this dialogue has engaged
duce levels of actuality and potentiality in in comprehensive reflection. Moreover, the
the aviary image (196c–200a). Inadequately four accounts of account at the end can be
accounting for false judgement, which might seen in one-to-one correspondence to the
be ignorance, they can reject true judgement four major accounts of knowledge through
as knowledge since judges in court might be the dialogue. Thus, they may manage to
persuaded to make the right decision, but do overcome the incommensurability of true
not know as a firsthand witness (201a–c). judgement with knowledge since the last
Theaetetus proposes that knowledge part’s reconsideration of all that preceded is
could be true judgement supported by an ‘squaring’ that raises true judgement to com-
account (201c–d). Socrates explicates this mensurability with knowledge, as suggested
‘dream theory’ (201–6) to mean that ‘sim- by Theaetetus’ mathematical work. Merely
ple’ elements permit no further account but adding an account as additional judgement
the ‘syllables’ they compose have an account does little, but reviewing perspicuously all
through these elements. This applies to math- they have gone through they get beyond true
ematicians who make demonstrations from judgement. This interpretation has the dia-
unaccountable hypotheses and other sorts of logue enacting just what it is about, human
positions based on beliefs taken to be self- understanding.
justifying or self-evident. Since Theaetetus Other prominent interpretations seek to
is dissatisfied with unaccountable elements, explain the dialogue’s apparent failure. Some
Socrates works out three further accounts of suppose we should see that without intro-
‘account’ that might convert true judgement ducing the forms knowledge could not be
into knowledge. Account giving might be: (a) understood (e.g. Cornford 1935). But though
vocalizing the true judgement (206d–e), (b) unchanging objects are needed for knowledge,
going through all the elements of the whole this hardly tells what knowledge is. Burnyeat

97

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 97 3/8/2001 5:12:48 PM


THE DIALOGUES

(1990) suggests that Plato leaves the reader tells a series of stories to illustrate the behav-
to pull the dialogue together, which is com- iour of his sign. These do nothing to dissuade
patible with the large interpretation offered, Theages, who even proposes that he will pla-
though the offered interpretation already cate the divine sign with prayers and sacri-
pulls it together. Sedley (2004) supposes that fices, if he must.
the Tht. has the late Plato reutilizing Socrates Most discussion about this work has
to show how Plato came to be dissatisfied focused on its authenticity, its depiction of
with some of his earlier positions, and hence Socrates’ divine sign and its purpose. The
Socrates serves as midwife for Plato’s later three issues are interrelated, since judgements
thought. This version of chronological inter- about authenticity have usually depended in
pretation has the attraction or limitation of large measure on the character of the divine
all such interpretation. sign (q.v. daimon) as it appears in Thg., and
many interpreters have seen the dialogue’s
purpose as tied to the prominent role that the
sign seems to play (more space is devoted to it
THEAGES in Thg. than in any other Platonic dialogue).
The divine sign differs here from its presen-
Mark Joyal tation in other dialogues whose authenticity
The dialogue’s setting is the Stoa of Zeus in is generally unchallenged. Above all, in Thg.
the Athenian agora. Demodocus and his son it is given a wider and more active role than
Theages have travelled to Athens from their the purely personal and inhibitory charac-
rural home in order to consult Socrates. ter that it displays elsewhere in the Platonic
Inspired by reports from his friends, Theages Corpus: the sign occurs to Socrates not only
wants his father to put him under the tute- when he should desist from an act on which
lage of a sophist who will make him ‘wise’ he has embarked but also when a companion
(sophos; Theages 121cd). Through probing of his should desist; it provides Socrates with
from Socrates, Theages is driven to acknowl- the ability to foretell the outcome of future
edge reluctantly that the ‘wisdom’ he seeks is events; and it is said here to participate in the
really the desire to become an absolute ruler. improvement which Socrates’ companions
An inquiry follows whose goal is to identify make through their association with him.
the ideal teacher for Theages. Several pos- This portrayal raises doubts about authentic-
sibilities are discarded; both Theages and ity not simply because of its differences from
Demodocus then turn to Socrates himself to representations of the divine sign in indisput-
assume this role. Socrates protests, alleging ably genuine Plato, but also because it antici-
his near complete lack of knowledge (apart pates emphases that we find in much later
from expertise in matters of eros, ‘love’ or conceptions of the sign (Joyal 1995).
‘desire’; Thg. 128b). Theages, however, There is no unanimity about the authentic-
thinks that his educational progress depends ity of Thg., but the majority opinion is against
upon Socrates’ willingness to associate with its Platonic authorship. There is likewise no
him. Not so, says Socrates; the progress consensus on the dialogue’s date of composi-
which his ‘associates’ make results from the tion (q.v. compositional chronology): propos-
willingness and participation of his ‘divine als range from the early part of Plato’s literary
sign’ (to daimonion sêmeion; 128d). Socrates career to the half-century or so after his death.

98

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 98 3/8/2001 5:12:48 PM


THE DIALOGUES

The dialogue’s value, however, is not neces- why there can be no certainty about the like-
sarily diminished by doubts about author- ness seems to be that its features are not the
ship: even if the dialogue is un-Platonic, it is same as those of the original but only analo-
important as a relatively early expression of gous. So, for example, the cosmos is spheri-
the intellectual preoccupations of an other- cal as an analogue to the completeness of the
wise unknown Socratic writer. Accordingly, shapeless forms (Johansen 2004:49–60).
several interpreters in recent years have made Timaeus characterizes his account alter-
sincere attempts to understand the dialogue on nately as logos and muthos, ‘reason’ and
its own terms (e.g. Bailly 2004; Döring 2004; ‘myth’ (q.v.). It may be that the quali-
Joyal 2000). There now seems widespread fier ‘likely’ cancels out the customary
agreement that the theme and purpose of Thg. logos/muthos contrast (Vlastos 1965).
are not simply to describe one author’s under- Alternatively ‘muthos’ may serve to down-
standing of the nature of Socrates’ divine sign. grade the account available to humans com-
Instead, the sign is viewed as an important pared to one obtainable by a god (Johansen
element in Socratic ‘association’ (sunousia) 2004:62–4).
(e.g. Joyal 2000:48–9, 59–61; Tarrant 2005). Cosmology relies on two causal princi-
In Thg. the nature of this remarkable associa- ples (Johansen 2008): the desire of a divine
tion serves to distinguish Socrates from other craftsman to make the world as good as pos-
candidates for the role of Theages’ teacher (e.g. sible and ‘necessity’, that is, necessary con-
Friedländer 1965). junctions or consequences of properties that
are, as it were, brute facts of nature. So, for
example, fire is necessarily mobile because it
is composed of small pyramid-shaped parts
TIMAEUS AND CRITIAS (Ti. 55e–6a). Necessity can be employed to
further the good, as a ‘co-cause’ (sunaition,
Thomas Johansen 46d–e), but intelligence cannot alter the way
The Timaeus and the Critias are the first two necessity itself works.
parts of an unfinished trilogy, presented to ‘Necessity’ relates to the nature and motions
Socrates as a single project (Ti. 17b) in return of the simple bodies and these depend on the
for his account of an ideal state much like that so-called receptacle. The simple bodies appear
of Republic. The speeches are thematically fleetingly in the receptacle without any sub-
linked: Timaeus’ cosmology (q.v.) shows how stantiality. It is unclear whether Timaeus is
goodness is represented in nature (q.v.), while characterizing bodies as they are now (cf.
Critias’ Atlantis story further shows how citi- Theaetetus 156a–7c) or as they were before
zens of Socrates’ ideally just city will conquer the cosmos. According to whether it enters
evil, given the support of Timaeus’ natural into composition of bodies, the receptacle may
order. The Ti.-Criti. as a whole presents a be seen as matter, the stuff bodies are made of
world in which goodness prevails, from the or as that ‘in which’ bodies occur, that is, the
planets down to the human sphere. place or space (chôra) that bodies occupy.
Timaeus argues that the cosmos is a like- The cosmos is an ensouled body, com-
ness of the eternal forms (q.v.) and that an posed according to geometrical principles
account of such a likeness can at best be that ensure order and unity. The soul is
‘likely’ (29b–d) (Burnyeat 2005). The reason made from a mixture of the divisible and

99

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 99 3/8/2001 5:12:48 PM


THE DIALOGUES

indivisible kinds of being, sameness and dif- degree of irrationality. Thereby the cosmos
ference. The composition explains both (cf. becomes complete with all the kinds of liv-
Aristotle, De Anima 406b28–31) the soul’s ing beings.
ability to move (57d) and its ability to make Criti. sets out to show how ancient
judgements about sameness and difference, Athenians, with Timaeus’ nature and
on the principle that ‘like is known by like’. Socrates’ education, prevailed against
The mixture is structured according to the Atlantis. Where Athens is a projection of
harmonic scale, and then divided and bent to the intellectually spirited, Atlantis is from its
form seven circular hoops, which move the inception appetitive. So, the virgin Athena
seven planets according to different ratios. founded Athens to produce philosophy-
To fit the world-soul its body is spherical. warriors like herself (Criti. 24c–d), while
Its constituents, earth, water, fire and air, are Poseidon instituted Atlantis to protect his
proportionately ordered in the same way as mistress. While originally virtuous, its luxu-
the soul (Cornford 1937:49). Each body is rious, variegated designs and its location
composed of one of two sorts of triangle, by the sea (cf. Laws 705d) make Atlantis
which combine according to geometrical susceptible to vice. Its dynastic constitution
principles (53c–7c) (Vlastos 197:66–97) and recalls Asian tyrannies, while also resem-
allow the bodies (with the exception of earth) bling fifth-century democratic Athens (Vidal-
to change into each other (54b–c). Naquet 1981), not a contradiction given
The human, immortal soul (q.v.) is created that both tyranny and democracy, according
in the same way as the world-soul, albeit to R. 571a ff., are political manifestations
with less pure ingredients. When embodied, of the appetitive soul. If Atlantis looks like
the soul is disturbed by irrational desires. a utopia, it is an appetitive utopia, and so,
But because the soul is in origin rational, it in Plato’s eyes, a dystopia. While various
can, through the study of the cosmos, assimi- historical events (such as the volcanic erup-
late its motions to those of the world-soul, tion at Thera) may have inspired Plato (Gill
thereby again becoming orderly and temper- 1979:viii–xii), Atlantis was clearly conceived
ate (47b–c, 90c–d) (Sedley 2000). by him as a foil for his ideal city.
To help us in this task, god’s assistants Criti. ends with Zeus about to announce
in creating human nature, the ‘lesser gods’, his punishment of Atlantis. One theory is
have divided the soul into the three parts that the work was left incomplete to reflect
familiar from R., the rational, the spirited Critias’ limited abilities or devious character
and the appetitive. This arrangement allows (Welliver 1977:44). However, Critias (Ti.
for each part to perform its proper func- 26a–b) had already delivered his speech to his
tion without interference from the others. companions the same morning. Another sug-
The human body has three distinct regions, gestion is that Plato abandoned the project in
head, heart and lower abdomen, which favour of the Lg, whose third book tells of the
service the three parts of the soul. The near destruction of civilization by a deluge
entire human organism is thus designed for and its subsequent history down to Plato’s
the promotion of our good while embodied day. This further suggests that Hermocrates
(Johansen 2004:142–52). Those men who might have spoken about the different kinds
fail will be reincarnated as women or as the of constitution now also contained in the Lg.
various lower animals, according to their (Cornford 1937:7–8; Gill 1979).

100

9780826435354_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 100 3/8/2001 5:12:48 PM


3
IMPORTANT FEATURES
OF THE DIALOGUES

ANONYMITY less reliable (Symposium, Parmenides) or to


conceal himself as their author (Prm.; Phd.;
Gerald A. Press Theaetetus). The Letters purport to be Plato
Paradoxically, Plato is silent and almost speaking in his own name. However, all but
completely absent in the dialogues. This the seventh are widely considered inauthen-
Platonic anonymity constitutes a problem tic and the seventh, whatever authority it
for those who read the dialogues expecting may have, includes the puzzling statement
to learn Plato’s philosophical doctrines. The ‘There is no writing of mine about these mat-
most common solution is the assumption ters [viz., “with which I am concerned”], nor
that Socrates and other characters are Plato’s will there ever be one. For this knowledge
mouthpieces, that the views and arguments is not something that can be put into words
they put forward are Plato’s own. But the like other sciences’ (Ep. 7 341c).
assumption contradicts the evident character We expect philosophers to tell us what
of the dialogues and Plato’s many strategies they think and we want to know what Plato
of self-concealment. Although anonymity thinks. He is one of the most influential phi-
is often ignored, in recent decades schol- losophers, inspiration of various ‘Platonisms’
ars have proposed various alternatives that (q.v. Academy) and Neoplatonism (q.v.). It
involve rethinking Plato’s approach to phi- seems natural to suppose that Plato had doc-
losophy (q.v.) and philosophic writing (cf. trines or definite views that he propounded
Press 2000). in his writings. But this reflects a modern
Plato ‘never speaks in his own name’ historical interest (Tigerstedt 1977). Ancient
(Edelstein 1962:1). There is no character readers were often more interested in the
called Plato who speaks in any dialogue. truth and wisdom to be found in the dia-
Plato is named only twice: as present, offering logues than in what exactly Plato’s views were
money for Socrates’ penalty, in the Apology (Tarrant 2000). Plato’s authorial absence and
(38b) and as absent, ‘sick’, the day Socrates silence, his denial that he ever did or will
died (Phaedo 59b). Although we assume that write his views down and Socrates’ recurrent
Plato wrote all of the authentic dialogues devaluation of writing (especially Phaedrus
(q.v. Corpus; Dubia and Spuria), in some dia- 275d–8b; cp. Protagoras 347c–8a) suggest it
logues he takes pains to render the narrative may be futile to read the dialogues seeking

101

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 101 3/8/2001 5:12:54 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

explicit statement of Plato’s philosophical than treatises indicates that his model of the
doctrines in any strong sense of that term. practise of philosophy is unlike the doctrinal
The most common response to this, model of philosophic writing.
already recognized by Diogenes Laertius Several twentieth-century pragmatists saw
(3.52), has been to assume that Socrates and the dialogues as dramatizations of the life of
other characters are Platonic mouthpieces reason rather than assertions of philosophic
(Kraut 1992a:25–6). Thus, in most dialogues doctrine (Woodbridge 1929:54 followed
what Socrates says represents Plato’s own by Randall 1970 and Tejera 1984). This
views, whereas elsewhere the Eleatic visitor approach troubles some interpreters because
(Sophist, Politicus), Timaeus (Timaeus) and it seems to reduce philosophy to ‘mere’ lit-
the Athenian visitor (Laws) have this role. erature. Slightly more dogmatically, the dia-
The assumption seems natural, since most logues have been seen as ‘presentations of a
major philosophic texts try to prove theories possible philosophical standpoint . . . which
directly. It is convenient, since it provides [Plato] acknowledges conditionally’ (Merlan
an easy way to get what readers want: an 1947:415) and their purpose as to induce
authoritative statement of Plato’s views. And, in us a ‘sense of being at a loss’ (Ibid 430).
after 2,000 years it has become traditional. Plato’s refusal to dogmatize may look like
But it is incompatible with the dialogues’ scepticism, as it did to the ‘New Academy’ of
obvious character as literary fiction, rather Arcesilaus (q.v., Academy, history of), but this
than didactic treatises or discursive history seems inconsistent with the fervour of Plato’s
(q.v.). It also requires explanation why Plato Socrates about learning the truth. On more
would switch mouthpieces from a dominant mitigated approaches, Plato is not a sceptic,
one, Socrates, to an unnamed Eleatic, a char- but merely withholds the certitude desired
acter named Parmenides, and an Athenian by dogmatists, as for Philo of Larisa. Thus
Stranger, whose views and practises do not Stefanini (1949, v.1:xxxii–xxxiv) suggested
seem consistent with those of the Socrates’ of that Plato’s view is a ‘constructive skepsis’. A
the Socratic dialogues. Moreover, indications quite different response to Platonic anonym-
in the dialogues and other ancient testimonies ity is taking the dialogues to withhold Plato’s
suggest that Plato was tireless in his writing true doctrines, because those were made
and editing habits (q.v. Compositional chro- available only orally and esoterically (q.v.,
nology). He took care to conceal his own Esoterism, Tübingen approach).
views and to avoid presenting himself as an These proposals assume that propound-
authority, as his character Socrates (q.v.) usu- ing doctrine is somehow the essence of the
ally avoids it in the dialogues. philosopher’s task. But Plato may have had
Instead of taking Platonic anonymity and a quite different, non-dogmatic view of
the literary character of the dialogues as philosophy. It has been argued that Plato
problems to be solved, many recent inter- saw himself as a moral guide, in the man-
preters have taken them as guidance to dif- ner of the pre-Platonic poets (cf. Edelstein
ferent ways of understanding what Plato is 1962:9). More specifically, the dialogues
trying to do and how the dialogues work. can be viewed as working in a way essen-
Anonymity along with Plato’s use of myth tially different from that of a treatise, as
(q.v.), irony (q.v.), characters (q.v.), play something ‘pedagogical’ rather than doctri-
(q.v.) and the writing (q.v.) of dramas rather nal (Gordon 1999; Sayre 1995a; Thesleff

102

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 102 3/8/2001 5:12:54 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

1999), providing the reader guided acqui- of Xanthippe, Socrates’ wife, who laments
sition of the habit of philosophic thought his imminent death in Phaedo and is there-
rather than specific doctrines. The dialogues’ upon escorted away at her husband’s request
‘double open-endedness’ – both conclusions (Phd. 60a). The only female characters who
reached and their premises remain tenta- speak at length are a courtesan (Aspasia) and
tive – has been taken to show that for Plato a foreign priestess (Diotima), both of whom
as for Socrates, philosophy consists in oral are licensed to associate with men by their
dialectic (Nails 1995:218–31), which shifts special status and neither of whom is directly
intellectual responsibility to the audience or dramatized.
reader. The dialogues can also be viewed as Characters other than Socrates (q.v.) fall
generating enactments of Plato’s principles, loosely into three types, marked by conven-
orientations and vision of reality within the tional wisdom, youthful enthusiasm and pro-
reader’s mind rather than seeking to gain fessional expertise respectively. Members of
rational adherence to propositional truths each type are individuated along a number
(Press 2007). of axes, whether social, characterological
or intellectual. They vary, for example, in
age (from adolescents to very old men), the
size of their speaking role (from the mini-
ARGUMENT (see Logos (Ch. 4)) mally scripted slave of Meno to the voluble
Athenian Stranger), their activity or passiv-
ity (from silent bystanders to the aggres-
CHARACTER (FEATURE) sive Thrasymachus), the specificity with
which they are characterized (from nameless
Ruby Blondell ciphers to the colourful Alcibiades), their
Plato’s dialogues present us with dozens of philosophical acumen (from the talented
characters, most of them (loosely) based on Theaetetus to the manipulable Hippias) and
historical figures (for a full prosopography, the degree of sympathy with which they are
see Nails 2002). They range in social status presented (from the endearing Lysis to the
from the nameless slave who learns geometry obnoxious Callicles). Employment of such
in the Meno to members of the gilded aristoc- variables serves to locate each character
racy; but most are drawn from the educated somewhere on a scale between the generic
male elite of Athens and other Greek cities. and the uniquely particularized. Yet, some of
Their social class is often reinforced by the Plato’s most memorable characters embody
dramatic settings, which typically represent generic and individual identities simultane-
such cultural institutions as gymnasia, festi- ously. Hippias, for example, is a ‘representa-
vals, the court and prison system, sophistic tive’ sophist, but at the same time retains
education and the symposium. On the mar- a distinctive identity easily distinguishable
gins of the dialogues, as of Athenian public from Thrasymachus, Gorgias or Protagoras.
life, can be found female entertainers, crafts- This paradox is most fully embodied in
men, children, slaves and non-Greek-speak- Socrates, who is simultaneously the ideal
ers, all of whom are mentioned frequently in type of the philosopher and a detailed, con-
passing. Married women and citizen girls are cretely imagined and richly embodied idi-
not represented, with the notable exception osyncratic personality.

103

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 103 3/8/2001 5:12:54 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

In the vast majority of the dialogues primary (though not exclusive) responsibility
Socrates plays a privileged role. The function is to understand what they are told and help
of other characters tends to vary along with to develop it constructively. This Socrates
his persona and methods. When he employs needs interlocutors who are at once more
the elenchus (q.v.), Socrates examines not sympathetic and more open-minded than
just arguments but individual people in ways his elenctic victims tend to be. This can be
that cast doubt not merely on their beliefs but seen clearly in the transition from bk 1 of the
also on the personality, way of life and social Republic (which is elenctic in style) to bks
roles that condition those beliefs and are in 2–10. In the latter books the respondents
turn conditioned by them. This method is are Glaucon and Adeimantus (Plato’s broth-
thus intrinsically ad hominem in a peculiarly ers), who exemplify the kind of respondent
personal way. If its force is to be fully appreci- Socrates needs if he is to move towards a
ated, the interlocutor’s particular character – more positive kind of dialectic: they are intel-
those aspects of his life and personality that ligent, cooperative, good-humoured, encour-
make him respond as he does – must be made aging, committed to Socratic values and open
present to the reader. Most of these respond- to new ideas. Their sympathetic support ena-
ents are either more or less promising young bles him to run the risk of exposure entailed
men – usually Athenians of good family – or by positive discourse.
mature claimants to wisdom, especially pro- To many readers these interlocutors seem
fessionals, patriarchs and representatives of bland and generic compared to the vivid
traditional education. Sophists are promi- characters of bk 1. This makes them less
nent for various reasons, including their role entertaining, but gives them a more universal
as educators, their public availability, their mimêtic function (q.v. Character as a Topic).
agonism (which both invites and legitimates Moreover the traits in Plato’s brothers that
verbal confrontation), their role as profes- are linked to their dialectical promise over-
sional intellectuals and the importance of lap substantially with the qualifications for
their cultural influence. In each case Plato guardianship, and ultimately for rulership, in
uses ‘literary’ characterization in conjunc- Callipolis. This exemplifies Plato’s tendency
tion with Socratic questioning to bring out to explore issues of character on dramatic
the limitations of the interlocutor’s point of and discursive levels simultaneously: ideas
view, often showing how this is rooted in his about character aired within the dialogues
particular social status and personality. The are explored obliquely through the portrayal
respondents’ various reactions bring out the and interactions of the very characters who
strengths and weaknesses of Socrates’ elenc- are engaged in the discussion (see further,
tic method as an educational tool. Some seem Blondell 2002).
inspired to embrace philosophy but others In several late dialogues Socrates’ role
grow angry, give up or fall silent, without any is much smaller or even non-existent: he is
sign of changing the way they live. replaced by dominant speakers with few
In other dialogues Socrates plays a more individual character traits beyond an ability
constructive role, airing substantive and chal- to hold forth authoritatively at considerable
lenging ideas, often at considerable length. length. The interlocutors are also minimally
This Socrates uses his interlocutors largely characterized, and have little to do besides
as a sounding board for his own ideas. Their agree with the dominant speaker. As a result,

104

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 104 3/8/2001 5:12:55 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

the characterization in many of these dia- speech on love. And, in the same dialogue,
logues often seems dull and lifeless compared Alcibiades’ claim that he chose ‘the crowd’
to the Socratic works. This shift is often seen over Socrates – political power over phi-
in terms of a Platonic literary decline; but losophy – has a tragic resonance. Alcibiades
it represents, rather, a different set of ‘liter- had convinced the Athenians to send the dis-
ary’ choices, including a move towards the astrous expedition to Sicily and he himself
generic that reflects ancient ideals about both turned traitor to Athens after being recalled
literary and ethical character (q.v. Character to stand trial for profaning the Eleusinian
as a Topic). Mysteries. Indeed, the very presence of
Alcibiades in the Smp. reminds us that the
Athenians suspected Socrates of teaching
Alcibiades and other Athenian aristocrats
DRAMA the wrong political views – a suspicion that
led, in part, to Socrates’ trial and execu-
Andrea Nightingale tion. In the Smp., then, we find a blend of
Plato drew on the genres of tragedy and com- comedy and tragedy. As Socrates says at the
edy in creating his dialogues. At times, Plato end of the dialogue, the ‘skilled’ playwright
offers pure ‘dramatic representation’ (mimê- should be able to write both tragedies and
sis, q.v.) in his dialogues; in other cases, he comedies (in ancient Greece, tragedians only
has a narrator describe the speech and action wrote tragedies and satyr plays and come-
in the dialogue, thus using the combination of dians only wrote comedies). Plato implicitly
‘simple narration’ (haplê diêgêsis) and ‘dra- identifies himself as the one man who can
matic representation’ (mimêsis), categories write in both genres. In short, Plato created
that are outlined in Republic bk 3. In both an entirely new kind of genre – a dialogue
cases, however, we find dramatic exchanges that was at once philosophical and dramatic.
over issues central to human life. Of course, He thus creates urgent situations in which
Plato attacks comedy and tragedy in R. bk 10 characters’ hopes rise and fall and which
for fostering emotions at the expense of rea- convince readers that the issues need to be
son; he certainly did not want his own dia- resolved.
logues to evoke the audience responses that In the Laws, Plato distinguishes between
the Greek dramatists did. Even in the seem- genres concerned with the ‘ridiculous’
ingly tragic case of Socrates’ execution in the (geloios) and the ‘serious’ (spoudaios; q.v.,
Phaedo, Plato portrays Socrates as someone Play and seriousness). He places Homer,
to be admired rather than pitied. Socrates is Hesiod and the tragedians in the latter cat-
not a tragic figure but a heroic martyr. egory (indeed, Plato often conflates epic with
Plato uses both comic and tragic dis- tragedy) and iambic poetry and comedy in
courses in his dialogues in part as a philo- the latter. But what is truly ‘ridiculous’ and
sophic attack on Greek drama (q.v. Poetry ‘serious’? In R. bk 10, Plato banishes the
in Chapter 4). But Plato did not simply over- seemingly ‘serious’ tragedy from the ideal
turn comedy and tragedy: his own dramatic city: tragedy wrongly portrays ‘good’ men
dialogues reveal Plato’s debt to these genres. becoming worse men (ethically and emotion-
In the Symposium, for example, the comic ally) when they confront pain or loss. The
poet Aristophanes delivers a very humorous philosophic individual, in contrast, remains

105

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 105 3/8/2001 5:12:55 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

good and virtuous even when he is harmed comedian turned the people against him and
or in pain. Yet, Plato did not simply dismiss thus prepared the ground for his eventual
the genre of tragedy. In Lg. bk 7, the Athenian trial (he refers here to Aristophanes’ Clouds,
contrasts the ‘so-called serious’ creations of which offered a very negative portrayal of
the tragedians with the ‘most beautiful and Socrates).
finest tragedy’ that he and his interlocutors Plato also uses powerful and ‘dramatic’
have produced in their construction of the myths that take the form of mini narratives
city of Magnesia with its unique law code. within the dialogues. These myths reflect
In the Lg., then, Plato denies that tragedy scenes from the genres of epic, tragedy and
is truly ‘serious’ and confers upon his own comedy. In the allegory of the cave (q.v.), for
creation the title of ‘serious tragedy’. Clearly, example, we find a scene from the ‘under-
this new mode of ‘tragedy’ is ‘serious’ and world’: Plato in fact compares the world
deals with ‘noble’ characters, but does not we live in here on earth to Hades. Clearly,
feature unhappy individuals. Indeed, the edu- Homer’s depiction of Hades in the Odyssey
cational system in Magnesia is designed to was used by many tragic and comic play-
train the citizens to be ‘truly virtuous’ and to wrights. But Plato transforms the traditional
resist emotions such as fear and lamentation. literary notions of the underworld by com-
Plato’s new ‘drama’ borrows from tragedy paring the ‘shades’ in Hades to people on
its presentation of serious, noble and ethical earth. In the Statesman, moreover, Plato
characters while abandoning the tragic plot creates a myth where people live in a world
line. which moves backwards in time: in the ‘Age
In R. bk 10, Plato also lashes out against of Cronos’, people are born old and get
low or ‘ridiculous’ poetry; here, he clearly younger and younger until they die as infants.
targets the genre of comedy. Yet, Plato This myth borrows from Hesiod’s myth of
himself chose to defend a number of ideas the Golden Age, yet it suggests that this age
that find direct parallels in Aristophanes. was not at all ‘golden’. The people living in
For example, Aristophanes’ Ecclesiazusae the ‘Age of Cronos’ cannot practise philoso-
set forth an upside down world in which phy or become virtuous because they are get-
women have the capacity to rule and the ting younger all the time. Of course, Plato’s
citizens jointly share property and even their myths are embedded in a larger dialogue that
children. In R. bk 5, Plato adopts these very deals with philosophic issues. These ‘literary’
ideas for his own ideal city: women can creations take on philosophic meaning when
serve as ‘philosophic’ rulers, and the ruling interpreted in the context of the dialogue as
class will raise their children in common and a whole.
own no private property. While borrowing In sum, Plato borrowed from literary gen-
these ideas from Aristophanes, Plato none- res even as he attacked their traditional use.
theless attacks the comedian for presenting In order to place his mode of philosophy on
these ideas as ‘ridiculous:’ in fact, he says, we the map, Plato had to reckon with the pub-
should take these ideas seriously. Here and lic and authoritative voices in democratic
elsewhere, Plato makes it quite clear that Athens: epic, tragedy and comedy. In using
he considers comedy a force to be reckoned (and abusing) these genres, Plato offered a
with in the Athenian democracy. Indeed, new ‘philosophic voice’ in fourth-century
in the Apology, Socrates suggests that a Greek culture.

106

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 106 3/8/2001 5:12:55 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

HISTORY The ‘illusion of historicity’ (Sayre 1995a:2)


derives from the dialogues’ independently
Gerald A. Press known (often important or influential) char-
First-time readers often take the dialogues to acters (q.v.), real world settings and refer-
be historical; but Plato is not a history writer ences to specific known events. They contain
and the dialogues are not history. With cau- so many such characters and details and are
tion they may sometimes provide evidence so internally consistent that generations of
about historical persons or events, but, for students and scholars have conflated Plato’s
understanding Plato, the important point Socrates (q.v. Socrates character) with the
is that he uses historical material for philo- historical Socrates (q.v.). Even though Plato’s
sophic purposes. Socrates is a literary construct (however
Some older scholars (e.g. Burnet 1920) much he may based on the Socrates Plato
took the dialogues as historical accounts. knew), he has dominated our understand-
Gregory Vlastos influentially argued that ing of the historical Socrates until recently,
the historical Socrates’ philosophy could a richly ironic measure of Plato’s success as
be extracted from a group of dialogues a writer.
he considered ‘early’ and ‘Socratic’ (q.v. When a reference in a Platonic dialogue
Vlastosian approaches). However, schol- coheres with external evidence, it may be
ars now generally agree that the dialogues used for historical purposes (e.g. Taylor
are not historical records of actual Socratic 1976:78–9), but this requires caution for
conversations. Many take place before Plato Plato is not an historian and he regularly
was born or was old enough to have heard redeploys historical material for philosophic
them, and for the rest, no plausible account purposes. On the other hand, the mention
explains how Plato could have learned such of established historical events is used to
detailed conversations (Sayre 1995a:1–4). give dialogues what modern scholars call
In context, they are part of an ancient lit- ‘dramatic dates’ which enable us to read
erary-philosophic genre called ‘Socratic the dialogues in relation to Athens’ political
accounts’ (Sokratikoi logoi) that was also and cultural history as well as in relation to
practised, less famously and influentially, by the philosophic biography of the character
Antisthenes, Aeschines, Xenophon and oth- Socrates (Zuckert 2009).
ers (q.v. Socratics). Nearly all Plato’s characters – their names,
Although Plato’s characters sometimes families, interests and deeds – are modelled
refer to events that have happened in the on historical figures (Nails 2002:xxxvii).
recent or more distant past (e.g. a specific Fluidity in the representation of histori-
battle is mentioned Charmides 153a), he cal characters was common among ancient
does not write about that event, attempting writers and Plato exploits the resulting ‘ten-
to ascertain exactly what happened or why. sion between abstraction and embodiment’
Instead, he uses it to construct a plausible but (Blondell 2002:34–6). By being precisely
fictional representation of the aristocratic who they are, they more powerfully symbol-
intellectual world of the last half of the fifth ize Platonic character assessments and philo-
century BCE and, in this case, to give a politi- sophic points. Socrates discusses piety (q.v.)
cal context to the discussion of a politically with a religious zealot in the Euthyphro,
charged excellence. temperance with notoriously intemperate

107

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 107 3/8/2001 5:12:55 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

oligarchs in the Chrm., and rhetoric with opponent’s views fairly, the philosopher sum-
sophists and orators in the Gorgias. Settings mons him from the earth. The dead man
also add vividness, depth and complexity. The emerges, but only up to his neck. The con-
Apology is in the courtroom where Socrates versation continues in the presence of his
gives his defence speech. The Phaedo is in protruding head. (c) A philosopher proposes
his prison cell, culminating in his death. The a theory that so shocks his interlocutor that
Republic’s discussion of justice is set in the he responds as follows: imagine, he says,
home of Polemarchus, who was later put to that the men hearing your theory become so
death and his family property unjustly con- enraged that they rip off their clothes, grab
fiscated by the oligarchs. whatever weapon is available and attack
Plato’s frequent and complex use of his- you. Unperturbed, the philosopher begins
torical characters, settings, dates and events explaining his ideas to the naked men attack-
heightens the reader’s intellectual interest, ing him. (d) Two dim-witted lawyers are
intensifies the thematic focus and elicits the practicing their skill in cross-examination on
close attention to arguments and ideas in a younger man. Like tag team wrestlers they
which all philosophic teaching and learn- take turns jumping into the ring to pelt their
ing consist. It also subtly evokes the reader’s hapless opponent with arguments like this:
emotional and imaginative involvement, since you have a dog, the dog is yours. Your
generating a commitment to orientations dog is the mother of some puppies. Since the
and ideas expressed that transcends the dog is both yours and a mother, you must be
intellectual persuasiveness of the arguments a son-of-a-bitch.
alone. As in great fiction, paradoxically, the These scenes were all conjured by Plato.
specificity and plausibility of Plato’s dramas The first paraphrases the opening of the
enhances the universality of their meaning Charmides (153c), when young Charmides
and the effect on readers of their philosophic enters the room. The second comes from the
message. Theaetetus (171d), when Socrates summons
the dead Protagoras. The third is Glaucon’s
response to Socrates’ announcement in the
Republic (473e–4a) of the philosopher-
HUMOUR kings. The fourth depicts, with some liberties,
the sophists Euthydemus and Dionysodorus
David Roochnik in the Euthydemus (298d–e). What is striking
Despite their profound seriousness, the is that all four are situated in a serious philo-
Platonic dialogues are often quite funny. To sophical context. (a) The Chrm. scene triggers
illustrate, consider the following scenes: (a) Socrates’ remarkable discussion of ‘modera-
A group of older men are sitting on a bench, tion’ (sôphrosunê). (b) In the Tht. Socrates is
when a half naked, gorgeous young thing refuting Protagorean relativism. (c) The naked
approaches. In their eagerness to make room men imagined by Glaucon force Socrates to
for the young beauty the men start pushing discuss the nature of philosophy in the cen-
each other, and the two on the end fall off the tral books of R. Note that Socrates says, ‘we
bench. (b) A philosopher is arguing against must distinguish for them [the naked attack-
a position held by a distinguished rival, one ers] whom we mean when we venture to say
who is now dead. In order to represent his that philosophers must rule’ (R. 474b4–6).

108

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 108 3/8/2001 5:12:55 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

(d) With their absurdly fallacious arguments wholeness is paradigmatically expressed in


the sophistic brothers unwittingly raise the sexual intercourse, an activity we take with
issue of the nature of predication. In sum, ‘great seriousness’ (megalês spoudês:192c7).
Plato both takes these issues seriously – most The problem is that the original wholeness
important, he provides a great deal of sugges- to which this activity aspires was neither sex-
tive material for the serious reader’s to pursue ual – in the earliest stages of human history
and develop on their own – and leavens their we procreated like cicadas by depositing egg
treatment with stunning humour. and sperm on the earth (see 191c) – nor was
Plato’s humour is not designed simply to it truly satisfying. Even when we were whole
provide a respite from the toil of concep- we felt the need to attack the gods. On this
tual labour. Instead, it is itself serious. For account, our love lives, our very selves, are
Platonic humour suggests that every human largely ridiculous. As Aristophanes puts it,
pursuit, even philosophy, is partial, precari- the soul of every lover wants something more
ous, of limited value and therefore deserving than sex, but ‘cannot say what it is’ (192d1).
of criticism. As the Athenian Stranger puts it Underneath its hilarious veneer, then,
in the Laws, ‘human affairs are not worthy Aristophanes’ story is grim. For it offers no
of great seriousness’. We are neither wise nor prospect of human transcendence. The best
divine and so none of our ‘affairs’ can ever be we can do (through sex) is attempt to recover
entirely flawless. Nonetheless, he continues, a wholeness that in fact is inaccessible. But
‘we must be serious about them’ (Lg. 803b). Plato himself, despite being almost as funny
We are constrained by our own humanity as Aristophanes, does not share this view.
to take seriously what is not truly serious, For the Smp. moves beyond comedy, first to
namely, ourselves. As a result, we are often Agathon’s praise of beauty (see 197b), and
ridiculous. then to Diotima’s description of the erotic
From the above one might infer that ascent towards philosophy (see 210a–12b).
Platonic philosophy is itself comedic. But In other words, comedy expresses only one
this would be a mistake. Plato explains why side of the human condition. Despite their
in the Symposium, when he has Aristophanes limitations and, perhaps, the ultimate impos-
tell the following story. Briefly put: we were sibility of fully attaining wisdom, philoso-
once spherical double beings with eight limbs, phers should nonetheless be serious in their
two faces, two sets of genitals and so on. We quest to articulate the beautiful, the good and
were terribly arrogant and attacked the gods. the true. But they should always consider the
Zeus punished us by cutting us in half. As a possibility that they might be making fools
result we spend the rest of our lives seeking of themselves. The Smp. urges the reader to
our lost other half. This seeking is known as pursue this form of self-criticism by ending
love. As Aristophanes puts it, ‘love (erôs) is not with Socrates, but with Alcibiades, who
the name of the desire and pursuit of whole- condemns the philosopher for being too seri-
ness’ (192a10–11). ous about ideas and thereby oblivious to
The image of the spherical beings is funny. the flesh and blood human beings who are
But what makes the story truly comedic is standing before him (or lying beside him; see
that, given the logic of Aristophanes’ myth, 216e and 219c.)
love or human striving itself is doomed to Plato’s humour is expressed in a vari-
fail. For him, the human impulse towards ety of guises. He is an inveterate punster.

109

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 109 3/8/2001 5:12:55 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

(Note his play on tokos, both ‘interest’ Irony is not deceit. Deceit depends on the
and ‘offspring’ at R. 507a1.) He can con- speaker being believed. Irony always involves
jure up wild images. (Consider Phaedrus an element of double talk: the speaker says
247e where the disembodied soul is said to what he says and hopes, without saying as
munch on the eternal forms.) He can poke much, that his interlocutor (or a third party,
fun, sometimes painfully, at Socrates’ oppo- present or presumed) will see the dispar-
nents. (Note that he has Critias, famous as ity between what is said and the context in
an excessively cruel tyrant, defend the defi- which it is said.
nition of moderation as ‘self-knowledge’ at Three types of irony should be distin-
Chrm. 165d.) His Socrates is often won- guished. The first is simple irony, when the
derfully ironic (q.v. Irony) and he can be ‘opposite of what is said is to be under-
immensely playful in his writing (q.v. Play). stood’ (Cicero, de or. 2.67; Quintilian,
Indeed, there are a vast number of exam- Inst. or. 6.2.5, 9.2.44; cf. Rhetoric Alex.,
ples of Platonic humour. All are serious and 134a17). When Strepsiades describes his son
perhaps are finally designed to give voice to as ‘this excellent boy’, he wants the audi-
what Socrates in the Philebus calls ‘the trag- ence to understand that the son is a good-
edy and comedy of life’ (Phlb. 50b). (For for-nothing (Aristophanes, Clouds 8). In the
more on Plato’s use of humour, see Press second, ‘complex’ type of irony (attributed
2007 and Rankin 1967.) by Vlastos (1987) to Socrates), the hearer
is left undecided between the two opposing
poles. When Socrates says that he is aware of
knowing nothing, great or small (Ap. 21b), it
IRONY is unclear whether we are intended to believe
him or not. Cf. Hippias Minor 376b–c: Can
Samuel Scolnicov we trust the argument that the good man is
In Attic comedy, the eirôn is the character he who does wrong of his own accord?
who gets the upper hand by subterfuge, Typically, however, Socrates’ irony is
feigning weakness. Eironeia, in this context, ‘open’ irony. We are made aware of what
before Cicero gave it the milder, urbane tone is not the case; but we are never told what
it has today, had always had a negative con- the alternative is. Socrates uses the same
notation, which it still carries in Plato’s use words as his interlocutors, but with a dif-
of the term. Socrates’ most bitter opponents ferent meaning. But the Platonic dialogue is
accuse him of eironeia (Callicles, Gorgias; not an exercise in disambiguation, as if there
Thrasymachus, Republic 1); or else the were two meanings of the term under con-
term refers to such accusations (Apology sideration and Plato’s task was to tell them
38a1). Alcibiades, with a touch of bitterness, apart. Before Plato’s Socrates, ‘learning’ did
describes Socrates as speaking ironically not mean ‘recollecting’ (Meno 81d ff.) and
(Symposuim 219a). At Euthydemus 302b3, courage was not equated with knowledge
in a nice ironical inversion, Socrates imputes (Laches; Protagoras 360d).
irony to Dionysodorus. Cratylus 384a1 is a For Plato, following Gorgias (‘DK’ f. 3),
special case of Cratylus being accused by language is basically incommunicative, at
Hermogenes of being ironical, with a pos- least insofar as critical terms, such as ‘justice’
sible oblique reference to Socrates. or ‘good’ are concerned. It is always context

110

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 110 3/8/2001 5:12:55 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

dependent (e.g. Euthd. 277e ff.). Thus, all whether or not it is ironical. Plato’s use of
speech is potentially ironical between speaker myths is similar (cf. Men. 86b; Phaedo 114d;
and hearer, and only the pragmatic context q.v. Myths).
can tell irony from serious talk – or so one Plato’s use of myths is intrinsically ironi-
should hope. In advocating an ethics in which cal. In an obvious sense, they are not to be
the good is identified with knowledge arising taken as literally true. Yet, in another sense,
from one’s own soul and in which ethical con- not specified, they do express some ethical
cepts can only be expressed by existing terms, truth. Even if this truth is given at the end
with peculiar, at least arguably idiosyncratic of the myth, it is clear that its formulation
meanings, Plato’s Socrates can only use irony in mythical terms is not unproblematic, and
to try to arouse in his interlocutors the intui- Plato says so expressly (cf. Men. 86b; Phd.
tion of what is, for him, the real meaning of 114d). But for open irony to be at all effec-
those terms. There is no manner in which tive, it must have a definite anchoring point
that meaning can be straightforwardly con- from which the intended meaning can be
veyed by words. One has to see for oneself derived. Nothing within the dialogues can
the truth, to be reminded of it, without actu- serve as such a point, free of every context.
ally being told (Men. 85b–e). Socrates hopes Socrates’ death, however, is an absolute point
the disparity between the accepted meaning of reference, an event outside the dialogues.
of the terms used and their epistemic or prag- Socrates did not die in jest. From this event
matic context will disabuse his interlocutors one can learn that his saying that ‘the unex-
of their unreflective opinions. He can make amined life is not worth living for human
one aware of the contradictions aroused by beings’ (Ap. 38a) was not ironical. Against
the usual meanings of these terms, but he this sentence, establishing the absolute,
cannot go any further. unconditional value of logos (q.v.), all other
Plato’s Socrates is bound to proceed dia- doctrines proposed in the dialogues should
lectically. All his arguments proceed from be measured. Plato cannot prove the value of
premises accepted by his interlocutors, on living an examined life; such a proof would
pain of not being understood and by Socrates presuppose the very value of examining
himself arguably only for the sake of the argu- one’s opinions. Those present at the death of
ment. The irony of the Platonic dialogues is Socrates were convinced of it with no need
double. On the one hand, Socrates is ironical for argument. For those who were not there,
towards his interlocutors; on the other hand, Plato tries to reconstruct that occasion in the
Plato is ironical towards his readers. What hope that its emotional impact will lead us
he writes cannot be taken unquestionably at beyond his inevitable ironical dissimulation.
face value as representing his own views, or
one will often find oneself being led astray,
as notoriously happens in the aporetic dia-
logues, and not only in these. Even in the LANGUAGE
nonaporetic dialogues, in which Plato is sup-
posed to propose positive doctrines, one has Holger Thesleff
to be careful in ascribing such doctrines to Plato’s fourth-century BCE Attic Greek is
Plato. There is in his writings hardly a pas- unproblematic, as such, to today’s special-
sage that has not been hotly disputed as to ists; and the text tradition is on the whole

111

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 111 3/8/2001 5:12:56 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

reliable. His linguistic choices, however, are in Menexenus, Protagoras, Symposium and
often remarkable and highly relevant to Phaedrus. Plato’s Socrates stands in a cat-
a more subtle interpretation. The stylistic egory of his own, also linguistically. He may
nuances (Thesleff 1967) and allusions offer imitate others, but he is most at home with
considerable difficulties for us. a vivid, fluent colloquial Attic with playful
Translations are in various ways defective; ingredients, avoiding vulgarisms. It is impos-
the reader is recommended to compare dif- sible to distinguish linguistically the historical
ferent modern translations (preferably in dif- Socrates from Plato’s character Socrates, but
ferent languages). in passages with pathos or otherwise strong
It is important always to keep in mind that emotionality we may hear Plato’s own voice
Plato wrote ‘literature’ even in philosophi- (notably in the latter part of Gorgias, and in
cally argumentative parts of his dialogues. Republic bks 5, 6 and 9).
His writings are imitations or enactments A rough categorization of the different
(Press 2007:137–40) of oral discussions with styles used in different dialogues and differ-
a wide range of allusions and emotional and ent passages may be of considerable help for
imaginative appeal (cf. McCabe 2008:96–8 our interpretation (Thesleff 1967). Changes
‘philosophical fiction’). The artistic compo- in the structure and technique of the dia-
nents of his dialogues are sometimes very logue bring with them shifts of style (q.v.
significantly interwoven with their explicitly Pedimentality). In fact, linguistic criteria can
cognitive content. Plato’s often deplored lack to some extent be used for determining shifts
of esteem of arts and poetry (q.v.) and other between ambivalent play, irony or serious
emotional aspects of human life, is somewhat emphasis (q.v. Play).
compensated by his indulgence in linguistic The all-pervading importance of dia-
expression. logue for Plato is reflected in his notorious
Ancient literary critics were well aware of denunciation of written texts (except for
Plato’s quite unique artistry (cf. Rutherford memoranda) which are ‘unable to answer’
1995), though they do not seem to have stud- when questioned (Phdr. 277de; q.v. Orality,
ied it systematically. The rhetorical breadth Writing).
and force of his language in some sections of The proper meaning of words was a ques-
his works was noted more often than his play tion of profound interest to some sophists
with colloquialisms or poeticisms. Aristotle (notably Prodicus, in Prt. 337a–c; Cratylus
compared his prose to poetry. 384b) and, apparently, to Socrates as well.
Except for some late works, Plato uses This issue affected Plato’s use of language
linguistic means to characterize persons and in various ways. The play with etymologies
moods. Since the persons are often seen as in Crat. (q.v.) has, besides its philosophical
types, rather than as historical individu- aim, to find a way through the debate about
als (q.v. Character), we very seldom find the conventional versus natural meaning of
strict imitations of idioms or dialects (as in words (q.v. Language (topic)). Plato takes a
Phaedo 62a); but the tenor of the text very delight in the semantics and connotations of
often reflects the personality of the speaker words and neologisms. Such etymological or
(Thesleff 1967:160–4). Plato is a good imi- ambiguously allusive wordplay (q.v. Play)
tator of conventional rhetoric and other is more common in most dialogues than is
public manners of speech, as can be seen normally realized. To take just one example,

112

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 112 3/8/2001 5:12:56 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

in Meno (85c–6c) there is some suggestive by the Greek tendency to formulate abstract
play with alêthês ‘true’ in the sense of ‘not nouns by means of suffixes and the article.
forgotten’. Ambivalent wordplay is also Since the 1860s, Plato’s linguistic practise
applied to the old search for the ‘true’ mean- has been studied more consistently in order
ing of poetry (Prt. 338c–47a; R. 1.332b). to determine the chronology and authenticity
The Socratic/Platonic search for definitions of his writings (Thesleff 1982). It was noticed
grew from the commitment to the ‘proper that a group of dialogues, called ‘late dia-
meaning’ question (q.v. Forms). The fact that logues’ because of their stylistic affinity with
the answers are often or even normally left the posthumously published Laws, displayed
open aporetically is a sign of Plato’s deeply characteristic mannerisms such as heavy and
felt sense of the ambiguity of spoken or writ- rare words, archaisms and a twisted word
ten words. order. Possibly, the most typical characteris-
In Plato’s view, language does not carry tics of Plato’s ‘late style’ reflect a mannerism,
truth in itself, but a spoken or written ‘argu- not of Plato himself, but of younger assist-
ment’ or ‘discussion’ conveys more of ration- ants who contributed to the formulation of
ality (logos, q.v. Dialectic; cf. Desjardins the written texts.
1988:110–25) than various other suggestive
ways of expression such as poetry or oratory
or myths.
Typically, Plato avoids the coining of phil- LITERARY COMPOSITION
osophical terms, though his language appears
to be at times quite sophisticated. The most Jill Gordon
notorious example is his flowing terminol- Greek literature left a distinctive mark on
ogy for the so-called theory of forms (q.v., Plato’s works, as he employed a variety of lit-
also Thesleff 1999:50–90). Translations are erary forms and devices. The literary forms
easily misleading here. Plato used included letters, dramas in which
One aspect of Plato’s semantics is his characters speak directly in their own voices,
method of ‘division and collection’ (q.v. and dramas in which a narrator recounts
Dialectic), which has to follow the ‘natu- for the reader what each character said (q.v.
ral joints’ of concepts and things (cf. Phdr. Letters, Drama). To great effect Plato used
265de; Politicus 287c). One of its aims is a the literary devices of character develop-
classification of things into genus and species, ment, irony, puns and plays on words, meta-
though the playful analyses in Sophist and Plt. phor, mythmaking, detailed dramatic settings
only approximate to consistency. Its ultimate and powerful imagery (q.v. Characters,
end is, rather, to reach the upmost ideas and Irony, Myth, Myths and Stories, and Image).
forms of the universe (see R. bk 6; Phdr.). The He was extremely talented in crafting vari-
linguistic expressions of the parts and wholes ous speaking and writing styles among his
discussed tend to be abstract denominations; characters. And he evoked both laughter
concrete objects do not seem to have been sys- and pathos, sometimes together in a single
tematically analysed in Plato’s circle (though dialogue.
the examining of a pumpkin is ridiculed in A small but illustrative set of exam-
a comedy fragment, Epicrates f. 11). For his ples of Plato’s literary achievements would
large use of abstractions, Plato was aided include the following. The Republic presents

113

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 113 3/8/2001 5:12:56 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

arguably the best known philosophical poetry (q.v.). This belief is based primarily on
image in all of Western thought: the analogy passages in R. in which Socrates raises con-
of the cave (q.v.), which continues to have cerns about the effects of poetry on the soul
power and relevance. It is a detailed meta- and the role of poets in the ideal city (377a–
phor for the emergence from ignorance to 83c, 386a–95b, 598d–608b); Socrates even
enlightenment. Socratic irony (q.v.) pervades refers to an ‘ancient quarrel between phi-
Plato’s dialogues, most notably, though not losophy and poetry’ (607b). Ancient philoso-
exclusively, in Socrates’ praise of the intel- phy and what we would now call ‘literature’,
ligence of interlocutors who, the reader is however, cannot easily be separated – by form
able to see, remain unaware of their own or content – into distinct categories. Several
ignorance. Though Plato uses this device in figures who are considered philosophers
many dialogues, it is particularly accessi- wrote in metered verse (e.g. Xenophanes
ble in Euthyphro and Meno. Aristophanes’ and Parmenides): Heraclitus wrote in cryptic
speech in Symposium (q.v.) contains a myth, oracular aphorisms, many tragic and comic
which is Plato’s original creation, but which poets addressed philosophical issues, the
is nevertheless traditional in feel. The myth sophists (q.v.) engaged important epistemic
contains imaginative and vivid descriptions and metaphysical issues in their books and
of human erôs, and it has distinct comic public speeches, and Plato wrote philosophi-
and tragic elements. Several dialogues also cal dialogues that are among the best works
include myths depicting the fate of the soul of literature to emerge from the classical
(q.v.) in the afterlife (e.g. Gorgias, Phaedo period. Plato’s dialogues leave us therefore in
and R.). Socrates’ final hours before he drank a quandary: how to understand his broad use
the hemlock, depicted in Phd., are quite mov- of literary techniques and devices, a trait he
ing, despite Socrates’ admonitions to his shares with other philosophers of the time,
friends not to cry about his imminent death. against the backdrop of Socrates’ criticisms
Phaedrus contains a critique of writing, a of various aspects of poetry and writing in
paradoxical and provocative critique since it the dialogues. Plato appears to be crafting lit-
appears in a written work. Phdr. also pro- erary works that at the same time interrogate
vides a speech that mimics the style of fifth- the literary project deeply and critically.
century Attic speechwriter and orator, Lysias. With this enigma in mind, modern schol-
The Smp., in which several characters give ars approach the dialogues with a variety of
extensive speeches, is perhaps the best single interpretive strategies. In the twentieth cen-
example of Plato’s ability to mimic and cre- tury in some Anglo-American philosophical
ate in the style of various other writers and circles, the literary aspects of the dialogues
speakers. And finally, the profound effect of were mostly ignored in order to focus on
Plato’s ideas on Western philosophy emerges the arguments, which could be formal-
in part from his detailed and powerful liter- ized and whose validity and soundness
ary characterization of Socrates across the evaluated (e.g. Vlastos 1978a, 1978b). The
dialogues (q.v. Characters and Socrates as implicit assumption in this scholarship was
Character). that the arguments were philosophical, but
Despite Plato’s extensive use of these and the literary aspects of the dialogues were
other literary devices, there is a common not. By contrast, Leo Strauss and his stu-
belief that he was an enemy of the poets and dents (q.v., Straussian approaches), paid

114

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 114 3/8/2001 5:12:56 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

careful attention to dramatic details, look- contributions of their own and they provide
ing there for signs of esoteric meaning (q.v., a critical perspective on the cultural, ethical
Esotericism), although some scholars say and philosophical function of literature.
that the Straussians imputed disproportion-
ate importance to them. Yet others focus on
Plato’s literary composition in the historical
context of the Greek transition from oral to MUSICAL STRUCTURE OF THE
literate culture. They aim to explore facets of DIALOGUES
both Plato’s inheritance from and tensions
with the older, oral poetic traditions from J. B. Kennedy
which his dialogues emerge (e.g. Havelock Recent research suggests that Plato may have
1965; Hershbell 1995; Waugh 1995, opposed inserted symbolic passages in his dialogues
by Harris 1989 and Knox 1968). Still oth- at regular intervals to give them a musical
ers turned to stylometric analyses of Plato’s structure. Struck (2004), Ford (2002), Sedley
dialogues to determine the order in which (2003) and others have shown that ancient
they were composed. The belief was that by Greek symbolism and allegory were common
exploring the compositional style of each themes of discussion in the late fifth century
dialogue and differences between dialogues, and especially in the circles around Socrates.
one could determine whether they were writ- Plato’s musical structures are another kind of
ten earlier or later in Plato’s career, or at the symbolism and fit within this context.
very least, determine which dialogues were The musical structures shed new light on
written in close proximity to one another. some well known puzzles about the struc-
These studies, however, have been somewhat ture of Plato’s narratives. Plato mocked his
discredited as relying on faulty assumptions contemporaries for failing to organize their
and as delivering inconsistent results (Nails compositions (e.g. Phaedrus 264a4–e4), but
1993, 1994). Gradually and more exten- his own dialogues can seem disjointed and
sively, English speaking scholars have studied meandering. The structure of the Republic
the arguments and the dramatic and literary is thought by some to be a hodgepodge of
aspects in more synthetic, holistic ways (e.g. tracts written at different times (Annas 1981;
Gonzalez 1995b; Press 1993; Scott 2007). Lear 1992; Rutherford 1995). The conclu-
There is now an extensive body of secondary sions of many of the dialogues have also
literature exploring the relationship between puzzled Plato’s readers. Some end without
Plato’s dialogues and ancient tragedy (e.g. propounding a definite doctrine, which has
Nussbaum 1986), comedy and mime (e.g. led a minority in ancient and modern times
Clay 2005; Howland 2007; Miller 2008) and to suppose that Plato had no positive, philo-
other ancient literary genres (e.g. Nightingale sophical programme. Musical structures give
1995). Scholars also investigate how Plato the dialogues an underlying unity and coher-
uses various literary techniques to accom- ence and provide an explanation for Plato’s
plish philosophical ends (e.g. Blondell 2002; aporetic conclusions.
Gordon 1999). Plato had strong motivations for using
While Plato’s dialogues are deeply embed- such symbolic structures. The dialogues
ded in, and indebted to, Greek poetic tra- often discuss the idea that ‘forms’ lie beneath
ditions, they also make innovative literary appearances and give the objects we observe

115

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 115 3/8/2001 5:12:56 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

their properties and structures. Students of and 11). Music theorists also held that the
philosophy are urged to compare, count and smallest useful musical interval was a ‘quar-
measure objects to find the general forms ter-interval’ (from say eight to eight and a
they instantiate. The Philebus suggests that quarter). These musical ideas lead to a natu-
identifying musical scales, for example, is ral interpretation of the structure embedded
a paradigm of this search for the forms in the dialogues (Kennedy 2010, 2011). Plato
(Phlb. 17c11–e1). The philosophy ascribed divided each of his dialogues into 12 parts.
to Pythagoras provides another motivation. At each twelfth he inserted a passage which
Pythagoras taught that every object, and even was a symbol for a musical note.
the whole cosmos, has an underlying musical In a given dialogue, the 12 passages each
and mathematical structure (Burkert 1972; describe a species of some given genus. In
Kahn 2001). Although the dialogues hardly the Symposium, for example, they describe a
mention Pythagoras, many believe that Plato species of ‘harmony’, which in Greek meant
was influenced by him (q.v. Pythagoreans). ‘attunement’, ‘blending’, ‘fitting together’ or,
Giving the dialogues an underlying musical more narrowly, ‘mode’ or ‘musical harmony’.
structure thus conforms to the core doctrines Plato also divided each twelfth into four
of both Platonism and Pythagoreanism. parts and inserted similar passages to mark
Introducing a few ideas from Greek music the quarter intervals. The conversations in
(q.v.) theory will clarify Plato’s musical struc- Plato’s dialogues were organized around
tures. Notes harmonize when their frequen- the underlying musical structure. Episodes
cies form simple ratios such as 1 : 2, 2 : 3 or arguments tend to fill out one or more
and 3 : 4. In fact, these ratios are the most quarter intervals. Major concepts or major
important musical intervals. The 1 : 2 ratio, turns in the narrative tend to be lodged at
for example, is called an ‘octave’ (Barker the locations of musical notes. Generally,
2007; West 1992). Since the number 12 has passages about virtue, truth, goodness and
many factors, it was common even before other Platonic ideals mark the harmonious
Plato to illustrate these musical intervals notes; dissonant notes are marked by vice,
with the numbers 6, 8, 9 and 12. Thus the lying, evil, Hades, etc.
octave was said to be a 6 : 12 ratio. Music To insert these musical symbols at the
theorists would demonstrate these intervals proper places Plato or his scribe probably
on monochords or instruments with many counted the number of lines in his dialogues.
strings. Some theorists ‘divided’ their string Classical Greeks counted lines in book
or a ruler alongside it into 12 equal parts, scrolls just as we count pages in a book or
which made it easy to sound the major musi- words in a file. Scribes were paid by the line
cal intervals (Creese 2010). The lowest note and this determined the costs of book scrolls.
on a monochord is sounded by the whole The standard line, even for prose, contained
string. If the other notes are compared with the same number of syllables as a line in
this ground note (say by playing them succes- Homer’s poems (Ohly 1928). That Plato is
sively), some will harmonize with it and some aware of line counting is indicated by Laws
will not. The Greeks therefore distinguished 958e9–9a1. The lengths of the Stephanus
the more harmonious notes (3, 4, 6, 8 and 9), pages in modern editions of Plato are irregu-
which formed low whole number ratios with lar and cannot be used as an accurate meas-
12, from the more dissonant notes (5, 7, 10 ure of location.) Moreover, classical Greek

116

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 116 3/8/2001 5:12:56 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

had little or no punctuation and no spaces the locations of the musical notes: the envis-
between words or sentences. A word proces- aged fusion of true lovers (third quarter note
sor can strip out the punctuation and spaces after four-twelfths), Eryximachus’ discussion
from modern, scholarly texts and return of musical harmony (second quarter note
them to a format with accurate line counts. after three-twelfths) and so on. The quarter
Plato’s musical structure can be seen in the intervals in the opening frame provide a par-
Smp. The locations of its twelfths are listed ticularly clear introduction to the nature of
below and Kennedy (2011) includes a close Plato’s symbolism. The Lg. says that music
reading and commentary on all its symbolic has two components: ‘rhythm’ is a motion
passages. The philosophical climax of the dia- through time and ‘harmony’ is a blending of
logue is the vision of the form of beauty (q.v.) high and low frequencies to produce some
at the top of Diotima’s ladder. The descrip- intermediate pitch (Lg. 664e8–a2; cf. Smp.
tion of beauty’s unity occurs nine-twelfths of 187a8 ff.).
the way through the dialogue and so coin- The Smp.’s first four musical notes are
cides with the very harmonic ninth note. The marked by passages describing motions like
extreme unity of the form of beauty is a kind walking. Moreover, in each passage, a wiser
of extreme ‘harmony’ in the Greek sense, and character like Socrates agrees with an igno-
so appropriately marks this harmonic note. rant character, which is a kind of harmony
The eighth note, which is also very harmonic, between high and low. These descriptions of
is marked by a vivid passage describing copu- motion and harmony are symbols marking
lation with beauty (another species of blend- musical notes. The frame’s narrative is also
ing or mixing). The dissonant notes, however, shaped by the musical notes. The opening
are marked with failures to ‘harmonise’. The episode, in which the narrator recollects an
eleventh note is marked by the extreme sense earlier request to recite the speeches, lasts
of shame felt by Alcibiades when Socrates for one quarter interval. Socrates’ famous ‘fit
rejected his romantic overtures. The tenth of abstraction’, in which he remains station-
note is marked by the comparison of Socrates ary in a neighbour’s porch, also fills out one
to an ugly satyr. Thus, these dissonant notes quarter interval. (Locations of the 12 musi-
are marked by strikingly negative passages cal notes in the Smp. using the OCT edition:
which describe conflict and emotional disso- 1/12 = 176c5, 2/12 = 181e3, 3/12 = 185b6,
nance in a relationship. 4/12 = 189d5, 5/12 = 193d8, 6/12 = 198a8,
The lengths of the speeches show that Plato 7/12 = 202c7, 8/12 = 206e1, 9/12 = 211b4,
used the musical structure as a kind of out- 10/12 = 215c2, 11/12 = 219d6, 12/12 =
line. Pausanias finishes speaking a few lines 223d12. The quarter intervals in the frame
after the third note. Eryximachus finishes end at 1q: 173c3, 2q: 174c8, 3q: 175c7.)
before the fourth note. Aristophanes finishes In sum, these musical structures can
at the fifth note. Agathon’s noisy peroration resolve many puzzles, if other dialogues are
precedes the sixth note. Socrates begins his composed by the same principles. They could
speech at the quarter note just after note show that each dialogue is given a coherent
six (Smp. 199b4) and finishes at the quar- organization by a musical form which is
ter note just after note nine (212c2) and so embedded in the surface narrative and, like
speaks for a fourth of the entire dialogue. other forms, is accessible only to those who
Many species of ‘harmony’ are used to mark count and make comparisons. They also

117

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 117 3/8/2001 5:12:57 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

explain why the dialogues end negatively. The has retained the memory. Gods, demons,
final tenth and eleventh notes are dissonant. heroes and inhabitants of Hades are situated
The philosophical climaxes of the dialogues between the world of intelligible forms and
are at the ninth, more harmonic note. the world of sensible things, at the level of
the soul and all that is immortal about it.
The gods, demons, heroes and immor-
tals are either living beings in the full sense
MYTH of the term, of the offspring of immortal-
ized mortals. Man is endowed with a soul
Luc Brisson (q.v.) of which one part is immortal, and is
For Plato, myth has two defects. It is an thereby akin to the gods, who must use it
unverifiable discourse, which must often be as a puppet (Laws 1.644d–5c), and hence it
considered false when it departs from a doc- is also akin to the demons and the heroes.
trinal point defended by Plato. And it is a The destiny of this immortal part must
story whose elements are linked together in be described before it falls into a body
a contingent way, unlike argumentative dis- (Phaedrus 259b–d), and especially after
course, whose inner organization features a it has left this body, that is, according to
necessary character. Yet, this does not mean popular belief in ancient Greece, when it
that Plato renounces traditional myths, which is in Hades. Such myths as those found at
he uses abundantly in his work. What is the end of the Gorgias, Phaedo (107d–14d)
more, he adapts some of them, and he some- or R. (10.614a–21d, the Myth of Er) have
times even creates new ones, as a function of precisely the destiny of the immortal part of
circumstances. Why? There are two reasons, the soul as their subject.
one theoretical in nature, and the other prac- Moreover, the domain of myth that evokes
tical. Plato recognizes the indispensable effi- men of the past covers roughly the same ter-
cacy of myth in the fields of ethics and politics ritory that was later to be claimed by the
for the large number of people who are not historians, as can be observed in the myth
philosophers and in whose soul the desiring of Atlantis (Timaeus 21e–6d; Critias), and
part (epithumia) predominates. Plato knows, in bk 3 of the Lg., which evokes the begin-
moreover, that he can only speak in mythical nings of human life. Quite naturally, it is
terms of the soul, and hence of certain sub- with the help of a myth that Plato evokes the
jects of a metaphysical and epistemological various origins: of writing (Phdr. 274c–5b,
nature (see further, Brisson 2004; Havelock the myth of Theuth), of human nature
1963). (Symposium 189d–93d, the Aristophanes’
The characters who appear in myths, as myth of double beings), of the cicadas (Phdr.
enumerated in bks 2 and 3 of the Republic – 259b–d) and even of the universe (Ti.). The
that is, gods, demons, heroes, the inhabitants idea that the soul has an existence separated
of Hades and the men of the past – cannot from all bodies, in the course of which it has
be the subject of a discourse that could be acquired a particular knowledge that it must
declared to be ‘true’ or ‘false’ in a Platonic recall in its subsequent existences, is explicitly
context. Myths recount the exploits accom- tied to religious traditions in the Meno, the
plished in a very distant past by men living Phd., the Phdr. and the Smp. The idea that its
in the sensible world, of whom tradition previous behaviour is subject to retribution

118

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 118 3/8/2001 5:12:57 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

is affirmed in several eschatological myths, obedience to the law that is, as it were, auto-
particularly at the end of the Grg., the Phd. matic. For Plato, therefore, myth has a two-
and the R. Finally, the idea that it is incar- fold function, practical and theoretical.
nated in various bodies, human or animal, is On the level of ethics and politics, myth
formulated in the Phdr. and the Ti. In addi- leads the individual to obey the moral rules
tion, everything concerning the intelligible is and the laws established by persuasion, with-
associated with myth through the intermedi- out the necessity of involving coercion. On
ary of these beliefs about the soul: the myth a properly speculative level, myths constitute
of the cave (R. 7.514a–17; q.v.), prolonged the starting point for a reflection on the soul
by the ‘allegory’ of the sun (R. 6.506d–9b; and the intelligible forms, the two themes that
q.v.) and that of the line (R. 6.506d–9b; were to impose themselves upon tradition as
q.v.). It follows that myths constitute a ter- the characteristics of Platonic philosophy.
rain on which fundamental philosophical
speculations take root: those concerning the
soul and the intelligible forms. Myths thus
constitute a reservoir of axioms or premises PEDAGOGICAL STRUCTURE
for the philosopher in the fields of metaphys- OF THE DIALOGUES
ics and epistemology.
Myth also plays an essential role in ethics Kenneth Sayre
and politics. In the R., the myth of autoch- Plato could have written in the form of
thony (R. 3.414d–e), also evoked in the Lg., verse, like Parmenides, in that of orations,
along with that of the metals, serves to con- like Isocrates, or even that of philosophic
vince the inhabitants that the city is one and essays. Instead he chose the form of dramatic
indivisible, although it is made up of diverse conversations (dialogues). Reasons for this
groups. The myth of Gyges (R. 2.359d–60b) choice are not immediately apparent.
provides a marvellous illustration of the the- One possible explanation is that the dia-
sis rejected by Socrates, according to which logues are records of actual Socratic con-
injustice is something naturally good. In the versations which themselves occurred in
Lg., myth plays a considerable role in legisla- dialogue form. Commentators generally
tion. In bk 4 (Lg. 719c–24a), Plato enquires consider this unlikely, however, since (among
into the practise of the legislator, comparing other reasons) many dialogues depict conver-
him to the poet and the doctor. Unlike the sations which Plato could not have attended
poet, who does not hesitate to develop con- (compare Kahn 1981).
tradictory discourses on the same subject, Another possibility is that Plato wrote pri-
the legislator must maintain a coherent dis- marily to present his own philosophic views
course. Although he maintains one discourse and chose this form to make his presentation
on one and the same subject, however, the more engaging. But this too seems unlikely.
legislator need not necessarily limit himself Among reasons are (a) that conflicting views
to a simplistic discourse. He must have the are expressed in different dialogues (e.g. the
prescription of a law preceded by a declara- soul is incomposite in the Phaedo and tripar-
tion that tries to substitute persuasion for tite in the Republic), (b) that protagonists
the fear of punishment. It is thus persuasion in the dialogues often speak disingenuously
that must obtain, right from the outset, an (consider Socratic irony) and (c) that several

119

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 119 3/8/2001 5:12:57 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

dialogues contain arguments that appear Smp. 210e) in the mental vision of someone
deliberately faulty (see Sprague 1962). well trained in love.
A further argument against this second In these dialogues, as in Ep. 7, the path
possibility is found in the Epistle 7, which to philosophic understanding is portrayed as
most Plato scholars today accept as genuine laborious, involving sustained conversation
(q.v. Letters). In this document the author with a master of elenchus and culminating
states that philosophic understanding can- in a spontaneous flash of insight within the
not be conveyed in language and that he mind of the learner. The metaphor of illumi-
has never undertaken to commit his knowl- nation ‘at the end of the path’ is also promi-
edge of the subject to writing. Taken at nent in R. (508d), Phdr. (250b) and Philebus
face value, this statement precludes read- (16c). One thing this imagery signifies is
ing the dialogues as repositories of Platonic that philosophic enlightenment is induced
teaching. But if the dialogues are neither in the mind of the learner, rather than being
records of actual conversations nor engag- conveyed from without by demonstrative
ing expressions of Plato’s own philosophy, argument.
what then? This portrayal of philosophic fulfilment
Hints towards a more plausible explana- probably was based on Plato’s own expe-
tion come with further reading of the Ep. 7. rience in conversation with the historical
After stating that philosophic understanding Socrates (q.v.). Such fulfilment also must
cannot be conveyed by words, the author have been a major factor underlying Plato’s
observes that it comes with hard work, per- adoption of the conversational format for
sistence and discipline, along with repeated his writings. What Plato got from Socrates,
conversations with a master that employ first and foremost, was not a set of doctrines
‘friendly elenchus’ and ‘well intentioned subsequently recorded in written form, but
question and answer’. For the successful rather an ingenious method of guiding stu-
learner, the outcome is a ‘sudden (exaiph- dents along a path to philosophic enlight-
nês) flash of insight’ bearing knowledge of enment. Plato’s dialogues, in effect, are
the subject concerned. Subjects mentioned teaching instruments structured to provide
include ‘the good, the beautiful, and the just’ his readers the kind of learning experience
(Ep. 342D). that he himself received in conversations
Similar accounts of philosophic training with Socrates.
appear in several dialogues. In developing the To drive the point home, we may look
midwife analogy in the Theaetetus, Socrates at various features of the dialogues that
speaks of the ‘many beautiful discoveries’ help them play this pedagogic role. Primary
(Tht. 150c) engendered in the minds of stu- among such is that the Socrates of the dia-
dents who maintain conversation with him logues (q.v. Socrates as a character), like his
and benefit from his inquisitive art (elen- historical counterpart, is a master of entice-
chus). In the Phaedrus, he talks about ‘lessons ment (flattery, irony and innuendo) as well
on what is just, beautiful, and good’ (Phdr. as probative refutation. The actual Socrates
276c) that result in knowledge impressed engaged listeners by sheer power of person-
as discourse ‘in the soul of the learner’. And ality. Countless readers have been inspired
in the Symposium, he extols the ‘wondrous subsequently to a life of philosophy by the
beauty’ that appears suddenly (exaiphnês; charismatic character in Plato’s dialogues.

120

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 120 3/8/2001 5:12:57 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

Another factor is the way Plato uses dra- are structured in layers ready to be unpacked
matic markers to highlight crucial moments in successive readings. An example is the
in a pedagogical conversation. In the Meno, Sophist, which invites being read progres-
for example, the theory of recollection is sively as (a) a mundane attempt to define
introduced in conversation with a new sophistry, (b) an exploration of the seman-
respondent (the slave replaces Meno), and tics of falsehood, (c) an examination of the
the method of hypothesis is dramatized by nature of not-being and finally, (d) an expli-
the arrival of Anytus. And both the nadir cation of truth and falsehood themselves.
(Phd. 89a) and the zenith (Phd. 102a) of the This accounts for the experience many read-
philosophic drama in Phd. are punctuated by ers have of learning more from a dialogue
the re-entry of Phaedo and Echecrates from each time they read it (see Sayre 1995a for
the outer dialogue. The purpose of signposts more detail).
like these, presumably, is to focus attention An alternative account of Plato’s pedagog-
on key developments as the conversation ical use of dialogic structure may be found in
progresses. Miller (1986). Also instructive in this regard
Other pedagogical devices involve the use is Frede (1992b).
of distinctive characters (q.v.) to set the stage
for the conversations ensuing. Thus, the story
of Smp. is recounted by Aristodemus (a par-
ticipant in the party who fell asleep before PEDIMENTAL STRUCTURE
it ended) and Apollodorus (self-described OF THE DIALOGUES
as crazy), which imbues the main conversa-
tion with a dreamlike atmosphere. Similar Holger Thesleff
contrivances are used in other dialogues Most of Plato’s dialogues, including many
(Euthydemus, Protagoras, Parmenides), with dubia (q.v.), are carefully composed (q.v.
the effect of establishing a unique context Literary composition). They have a ‘literary’
in which the conversation can be read most stamp. This is interesting, since they were
fruitfully. not on the whole meant for presentation to
Also worth mentioning is Plato’s knack for general anonymous audiences used to public
imparting momentum to his dialogues, which performances of poetry, drama or oratory, the
carry the reader forward once the conversa- main genres of ‘literature’ in Plato’s days. The
tion has ‘officially’ ended. At the end of Tht., refinements of the compositional patterns of
for example, alert readers will realize that the dialogues, like the philosophical contents,
several senses of logos especially relevant to the language and style (q.v. Language) and
knowledge have not yet been examined and the irony (q.v.) and allusive play (q.v.), are
will be motivated to test these senses on their rather adapted to small groups of relatively
own. Similar effects are found in Men., R. well informed persons and their friends who
and Phlb. By pointing to things never explic- appreciated such moves.
itly stated, these dialogues invite readers to One can easily detect a certain rhythm
continue the investigation by themselves (for or pulse in the composition and technique
further discussion, see Sayre 1992). of the dialogue. There is normally an intro-
Most noteworthy pedagogically, however, duction, sometimes in two or more stages,
is the way Plato’s more successful dialogues gradually leading ‘into’ the place where the

121

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 121 3/8/2001 5:12:58 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

philosopher meets his interlocutors. Then The most manifest example, easily under-
there are variations between argumentative stood by every reader, is the pyramidally cen-
passages and interludes with different types tral place of Diotima’s speech in Symposium
of dialogue. At the end there comes a com- (q.v.). There is a gradual rise to it, and then a
paratively brief conclusion which, interest- slope beginning with Alcibiades’ joining the
ingly, tends to leave the discussion somehow company. Other very obvious cases include
open. Even explicitly ‘aporetic’ conclusions Socrates’ musings on inspiration in Ion (q.v.),
suggest that something is bound to follow. and the first part of his palinodic speech on
A study of the compositional rhythm of the the cosmic flight of the soul in Phaedrus
texts may, like the study of shifts of style (q.v.), an illustration of true ‘psychagogy’
(Thesleff 1967), contribute to our under- (Phdr. 271c), so different from myths and
standing of where and how the author wants oratory.
to place the emphasis. The relevance of pedimentality in the
It has sometimes been noticed that the Republic (q.v.) is worth specific notice
majority of Platonic dialogues follow a gen- (Dorter 2006:3–8; cf. the challenge by
eral pattern which can be termed ‘pedimen- Roochnik 2003:4–7). The beginning and the
tal’ (Thesleff 1993) or ‘ring composition’ end concern rather concrete human realities
(Douglas 2007), the archaic compositional or myths seen from a human perspective, but
principle of returning to the beginning at from the opening onwards, and backwards
the end. Plato’s pedimentality, however, is a from the end, we find ever more abstract
refinement of classical ring composition since philosophical themes which culminate in the
the central section of dialogues often rises to a three, mutually interdependent analogies in
higher intellectual or conceptual level before the centre of the work (bks 6, 7), the sun, the
returning to the mundane level where the line and the cave (qq.v.). These are actively
conversation began. The central parts or sec- illuminating symbols pointing to the fact that
tions of a dialogue often form a core where metaphysics and its application to the edu-
essential thoughts or new aspects or a crucial cation of philosophers constitute the central
phase are introduced. As in the triangular nucleus of this work. The other themes are
‘pediment’ or tympanum of a Greek temple, arranged around it in a kind of descending
symbolically important ideas are placed in order.
the centre. More peripheral or more ordi- Metaphysics is often more prominent in
nary facts and suggestions, and less signifi- the central sections than in other parts of the
cant circumstances, are pushed towards the dialogues. Pedimentality can make a push,
beginning and the end. Reflections of simi- as it were, towards the higher level of Plato’s
lar principles can be found in other classical two-level universe (Thesleff 1999). The dis-
Greek genres of literature, notably in tragedy cussion on the whole concerns human mat-
(the peripety) and old comedy (the paraba- ters, but the central sections give glimpses of
sis). Plato was influenced by drama (q.v.), the (metaphorically) ‘divine’.
though a direct dependence is unlikely. The pedimental composition is seldom
A closer consideration of the character of as spectacularly evident as in the examples
the central sections and their function within just mentioned, yet it may offer an impor-
the pedimentality may give useful clues to the tant aid to the interpreter. In the Phaedo
interpretation of the dialogues. (q.v.), where innumerable generations of

122

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 122 3/8/2001 5:12:58 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

readers have sought towards the end for and in Crito (less obviously in Philebus), the
the ‘definite’ proof of the immortality of the rhetorical principle of ‘climactic’ arrange-
soul, the resumption of the frame dialogue ment is dominant. In both dialogues Socrates
at the centre (Phd. 88c) in fact indicates a is intent on persuading his interlocutor and
retardation and a concentration on an idea his listeners by consistent argumentation,
which is emphasized in various ways: what- an approach not normally used so explicitly
ever hopes or myths or arguments there are by Plato. The principle of pedimentality is
for the survival of the human soul, dialectic better suited to the reflective mood of most
ought not to be rejected and Socrates’ logos dialogues.
with its metaphysical reach will live on even
if he does not do so as a person. But at the
beginning and the end of the dialogue, the
perspectives of living human individuals are PLAY
in the foreground.
A similar framing of the central section Holger Thesleff
occurs in Euthydemus (q.v.) where Clinias Since a solemnly serious Plato has dominated
unexpectedly hints that the Royal Art will the picture of Platonism since antiquity, it
give a lasting solution to the problems at is particularly important to note his use of
hand. This probably refers to the schooling playful wit and humour (q.v.). Indeed, this
of philosophers, treated with banter at the general feature, taken in a very large sense,
beginning and the end. In Protagoras (q.v.), is essential not only as a literary device in the
the two-level contrast of ‘becoming’ or ‘being’ dialogues but basic for the interpretation of
good, an implicit clue to the entire dialogue, his philosophy.
is playfully alluded to in Socrates’ sophistic Awareness of the aspect of play is a pri-
answer to Protagoras’ speech in the cen- mary challenge for readers of Plato, even if
tre. Meno (q.v.), again somewhat playfully, they do not feel Platonic play is amusing.
introduces the recollection doctrine in the Though Plato often hints that he is jest-
pedimental central section. And Theaetetus ing, his playfulness (paidia, derived from
(q.v.), to take a last rather obvious example, the word for child, like English ‘kidding’)
has a digression on the two paradigms of involves various degrees of seriousness: it is
human life in its centre: one of the implica- always ambiguous to some extent, but nor-
tions seems to be that an orientation towards mally with an earnest point. ‘ “Play” . . . com-
the upper level is essential in epistemology, in bines interested detachment with cautious
spite of all the different perspectives opened engagement and enables the philosopher to
by the discussion. Some scholars regard the give both the rational and sensuous worlds
provocative ‘philosophical digression’ in the their due’ (Plass 1967:359). Like most kinds
Seventh Letter (342a–4d) as a sign of its of humour, Platonic play has two significant
authenticity; others, the sure sign of a prac- constituents, distancing or perspective, on
tised imitator. one hand, and a simultaneous confrontation
The aspect of pedimental composition with two different paradigms, a double expo-
ought to be observed in almost all Platonic sure, on the other. The latter corresponds to
dialogues. Occasionally, however, it is not his non-dualistic two-level model of thought
very easily traceable. Notably in Gorgias (Thesleff 1999). Play and earnestness belong

123

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 123 3/8/2001 5:12:58 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

together (e.g. Symposium 216e, 223d), but It is reflected in much of his two-level play
suggestive play may reach higher than mere in mime-like or even farcical confrontations
statements of facts (see Press 2007:104–29). of his always odd Socrates (who has more
The two-level approach is manifestly truth inside him than others, see Smp., espe-
present in the Platonic irony (q.v.), which cially 215ab) with his interlocutors. Good
is normally a gently ambivalent reference humoured banter often creates an every-
from what appears to be the case to what day background to more serious elements
is really true. Most of Socrates’ apparent of thought. While others may laugh, Plato’s
aporiai are understatements of this type. philosopher rather smiles (Rankin 1967). In
Plato’s philosopher has nothing of the cynic’s the Phaedo such play is reduced to quiet gen-
laughing scorn from below, and his moral tleness, but reflections of oral banter occur in
polemics are seldom explicitly bitter (as the late works (see Sph.; Philebus).
in Gorgias and parts of Republic; note the Oral communication can be deeply serious
regret 7.536c). Occasional overstatements even if writing is play or pastime (q.v. Writing;
may involve some playful disdain, such as Guthrie 1975:56–66). Plato’s famous censure
the profuse praise of the sophist in Hippias of poetry (q.v.) has traits of active mockery
Major. Sometimes Socrates’ self-irony clearly motivated both morally and epistemologi-
includes the author (e.g. Theaetetus 174ab). cally; but his appreciation of artistic quali-
Ambivalent word play is an integral part of ties notable in poetry is beyond doubt (e.g.
Plato’s reasoning. This is indirectly reflected see R. 10.607b–8b). His satirical handling
in his notorious lack of consistent terminol- of rhetoric (q.v.) indicates the same ambiva-
ogy: language can be played with. He plays lence. More one-sidedly extreme is the cen-
semiseriously with the belief that words have sure of ridicule in Lg. (e.g. 7.816de; cf. Phlb.
a covert meaning (q.v. Language), and this 48a–50c). Playful seriousness can be recom-
belief somehow lies behind his two-level mended (Lg. 7.803d), and all learning ought
dihaeretic method (q.v. Dialectic), pedanti- to be accompanied by play (e.g. R. 7.536e;
cally overplayed in the Sophist and Politicus. note the pun on paideia in Lg. 1.643bc).
But other kinds of word play also abound in The play inherent in parts of Plato’s pow-
the dialogues, sometimes boisterously as in erful imagery also illuminates the ambiva-
Euthydemus, very often with cognitive allu- lence of his two-level thinking. His well
sions, as the musings about what might be known myths (q.v.), which can be regarded
forms in Meno (72a–5c). Translations usu- as constructive thought-play (below), often
ally miss such points. contain some bizarre ingredients (e.g. R.
A humorous distance from everyday trivi- 10.607b–8b). The tentative, partly comical
alities and duties is implied in the concept similes in Tht. (191a–200d) of how epis-
of ‘leisure’ (scholê, in Tht. 172cd), neces- temic memory works perhaps reflect some
sary for play and the pursuit of philosophy. frustration on Plato’s part. Numerous other
Plato has a delicate sense of the bizarre in similes are humorously suggestive, such as
human behaviour. Though he perhaps lacks Socrates the gadfly (Apology 30e) or the
a humorously warm understanding of ordi- torpedo fish (Men. 80a). Even in the natu-
nary people, he makes his chosen dialogue rally earnest Epistle 7 there is vivid imagery,
characters (q.v.) subject to intellectual wit. and the notorious ‘digression’ has a touch of

124

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 124 3/8/2001 5:12:58 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

irony. Mathematical passages may be play- PROLEPTIC COMPOSITION


fully complicated (as the Nuptial Number
in R. 8.546c–7a). However, the three central Hayden W. Ausland
allegories in the R. 6–7 (see Pedimentality) Proleptic composition is a concept used
are primarily serious with very slight touches in the modern literary criticism of ancient
of humour (e.g. 509c). The modern reader poetry that has been adapted for understand-
has to listen very carefully to the tone of ing the relation between what is held to have
the wording, which was made clearer by the been composed earlier and later in Plato’s
original oral delivery. dialogues. The literary category has distant
A particular challenge to all interpret- origins in ancient grammatical and rhetorical
ers of Plato comes from an attitude that theory, where ‘prolepsis’ denotes a deliber-
can be generally called ‘thought-play’. He ately partial anticipation of something greater
rarely gives explicitly unambiguous ‘proofs’ yet to come (Ausland 2008). The notion was
for the position his philosopher takes (but first extensively brought to bear on the devel-
cf. Grg. 509a; q.v. Account). The atten- opment of poetic imagery in the tragedies
tive reader will often find signs in the con- of Aeschylus, notably by A. Lebeck (1971),
text to indicate a thought experiment (or following whom Charles Kahn has, since the
‘abduction’) or a provocative step without late 1960s, sought to use it in associating a
firm ground in the author’s convictions. number of apparently doctrinal passages in
Given Plato’s sense of wit and amusement, Plato’s dialogues that have for some time
we have to be aware of the playful aspect been held instead to reflect a less than delib-
of such instances. Sweepingly generalizing erate development in their author’s thought
claims such as the remarks on recollection (1968). In a subsequent series of articles and
as the basis of true knowledge in Men. (81b, one book, Kahn argues (e.g. 1988 with 1996)
etc.) and Phd. (72e–6c, but not really fol- that partial or otherwise inchoate allusions to
lowed up elsewhere), or the utopian vision acknowledged Platonistic views in aporetic
of the ideal state (cf. R. 9.592ab; Lg. dialogues normally held to be early composi-
5.739a–e), or the implications of the kingly tions do not in themselves show that Plato
art at the centre of Euthd. (291cd), or per- was himself experiencing perplexity, while
haps the so-called unwritten doctrines (see in the process of forming such theories, since
Thesleff 1999:104–7) are worth consider- they may be read as deliberately designed
ing as thought-play. Sometimes there is less to point only partially to fuller expositions
humour than human hope and belief in found in dialogues normally held to belong
Plato’s thought experiments, notably in the to a middle period in Plato’s literary activity.
main lines of his eschatological myths and in The relation of Republic bk 1 to its
Socrates’ personal expectations in the Phd., remaining books constitutes a special case of
too often interpreted as Platonic doctrines. the same general phenomenon. By allowing
It has been occasionally suggested that for such philosophical anticipation, Kahn
perhaps there is more play than consistently would appear to revert to the approach to
serious thinking in Plato’s dialogues. It is bet- the dialogues characteristic of the early nine-
ter to describe his attitude, generally, as play- teenth century, inaugurated by Friedrich
ful seriousness open to much ambivalence. Schleiermacher, who held the dialogues

125

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 125 3/8/2001 5:12:58 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

constituted a series in which the earliest ele- service to received views about the content of
ments already aimed methodically at the Plato’s philosophy. A possibility comes into
expositions found in the dialogues Plato view that the units of Platonic expression to
produced at the end of his literary efforts which it is best applied might better be con-
(cf. Kahn 1993:137–8f. with Schleiermacher ceived in the first instance along the same
1828:11). His approach would thus appear lines as the artistic anticipation found in
to call into serious question the romanti- Aeschylean tragedy, allowing the theoretical
cizing and idealizing style of interpretation results of such a reading to emerge independ-
later inaugurated by K. F. Hermann, accord- ently of any prior assumption of a personal
ing to which a reconstructed chronology of Platonic development.
the dialogues reflects their author’s specially
representative spiritual and personal devel-
opment (cf. Nineteenth-Century Platonic
Scholarship). SOCRATES (THE CHARACTER)
While revolutionary in principle, Kahn’s
approach does not go far enough to cohere Jill Gordon
with readings positing an unstated, inner Because the historical Socrates (q.v.) did not
meaning to the dialogues (Griswold 1999, write anything, our impressions and knowl-
2000; Kahn 2000). It has at the same time edge of him come through depictions of
gained but limited credence with the main- him in other ancient authors’ texts, Plato’s
stream (e.g. Gill 1998), and has at length dialogues being arguably the best-known
approximated once more to the biographi- among them. Other Socratic texts, written
cally developmental approach conventional by authors who were directly acquainted
for the twentieth century (e.g. Kahn 2007). with the historical Socrates, include the
The tension within the approach thus reflects comic poet Aristophanes’ Clouds and three
alternative attitudes towards the possibility of Xenophon’s works, Apology, Symposium
that Plato practised esotericism (q.v.), or, and Oeconomicus. Aristotle implies (Poetics
more generally, that his writings were writ- 1447b8–9) that several ancient authors wrote
ten with a view to some end beyond merely Socratic dialogues, and some corroborating
documenting their author’s philosophical textual evidence survives (cf. Socratics other
doctrines, for instance as flexibly philosophi- than Plato). Some Platonic scholars believe
cal dramas, or ‘enactments’, irreducible to a they can separate the historical Socrates from
systematic exposition. his characterization in Plato’s dialogues, but
Desultory results of further applica- this is disputed (e.g. cf. Kahn 1998; Vlastos
tion of a notion of proleptic composition 1991a). The various depictions of Socrates are
to the interpretation of Plato’s theories, as consistent in many respects, although each is,
these are understood within the conven- at least to some degree, a literary characteri-
tional approach, have been disappointing zation of the historical Socrates (q.v. Literary
(e.g. Wilson 1995), with otherwise parallel Composition). Socrates is not even charac-
dramatic readings showing greater promise terized by Plato entirely consistently across
(e.g. Rudebusch 2002), raising a question the dialogues. Blondell (2002) discusses vari-
regarding the validity, not of some category ous avatars of Socrates in Plato’s dialogues,
of proleptic composition per se, but of its and Plato’s possible reasons for writing some

126

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 126 3/8/2001 5:12:59 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

dialogues that do not feature Socrates in a corpulent body. He is compared to a satyr,


primary role. the over-sexed, half human, half goat mytho-
The profound influence of Plato’s Socrates logical figure (Smp. 221e1), a creature also
can be attributed in part to the character’s depicted with bulging eyes and wide nose.
utterly compelling, and even strange (atopos), Despite his ugliness, however, Socrates is
singularity (see Ap. 31c4; Gorgias 494d1; erotically linked to Alcibiades (Alcibiades I;
Smp. 221d2), and to the alluring vision of Grg.; Protagoras; and Smp.), the most beau-
philosophical activity that he enacts. Plato’s tiful young man in Athens, who declares a
character, Socrates, has become definitive of strange attraction to Socrates’ special kind of
the ‘Socratic’, both popularly and philosoph- enchanting beauty (Smp. 218c ff.). Socrates
ically. He is the paradigm of principled mar- describes himself as an expert in erotic mat-
tyrdom in the face of illegitimate political ters (Smp. 177d–e) and others agree (Phdr.
power; he informs our understanding that 227c). He always seeks out the most beauti-
philosophy consists in asking questions, what ful, in body and soul, among the Athenian
is popularly called the ‘Socratic method’, and youths (e.g. Alc. I; Charmides; Lysis; Smp.
he voices a unique and powerful type of 216d; Tht.), and yet it is unclear whether
irony that also bears his name (q.v. Irony). he ever consummates his erotic relations
Intensifying his already profound array of physically with these young men (Smp.
extraordinary attributes, Socrates is charac- 216b–19d).
terized by paradoxes and extremes, both in Socrates’ inner, psychic character is also
body and in soul. the locus of contradiction and extreme. He
In his bodily persona, Socrates tries to is intellectually precocious (Parmenides),
live unconcerned with bodily matters, sepa- and characterized by great wisdom, if noth-
rating body from soul as far as is possible ing else. And although the Oracle at Delphi
(Phaedo 64a–8b). And yet his body is physi- declared that no one was wiser than he,
cally strong and resistant to many exigen- Socrates comes to understand this pro-
cies that would affect a normal person’s nouncement to mean that his wisdom resides
body, including extreme cold, hunger and in his ignorance, or rather, that whereas oth-
sleep deprivation (Smp. 219e–20b, 223d). ers think they are wise when they are not,
Socrates typically wanders in his bare feet Socrates does not think he knows what he
(Phdr. 229a3; Smp. 173b2, 220b6). He is does not know (Ap. 20d ff.).
characterized as impervious to the effects of Socrates exhibits human excellence (q.v.
wine (Smp. 176c, 220a) and more resistant aretê) to a greater degree than most human
than most humans to pain and discomfort, beings, having a robust soul to complement
a contributing factor to his valour in battle his robust body. The Athenians convicted
(Smp. 219e ff.). Capable equally of physi- Socrates of corrupting the young, and yet the
cal vigour and corporeal stillness, he some- young Phaedo describes him as ‘the best, and
times stands perfectly still for long periods also the wisest and the most upright’ of all
of time, apparently lost in thought (Smp. the men he has known (Phd. 118a). And even
174d, 175a–b). with regard to Socrates’ excellences, Plato
Socrates is ugly by Greek standards (Men. plays with paradox. In a dialogue focusing
76c; Smp. 218d–e; Theaetetus 143e–4a), on the excellence of sôphrosunê, or self-
with bulging eyes, a broad, flat nose and a control, for example, Socrates describes his

127

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 127 3/8/2001 5:12:59 PM


IMPORTANT FEATURES OF THE DIALOGUES

sexual arousal at the moment when young he is an ironist and a gadfly. He devotes his
Charmides’ cape falls open and Socrates entire life to improving souls, but claims not
gets a glimpse inside (Chrm. 155d). Socrates to be a teacher. He exhorts interlocutors to
emphasizes the importance of self-knowledge live well, but he eschews acolytes.
in this dialogue, a theme that also appears in Socrates’ manner of death is most defini-
Alc. I and Phdr. tive of his character, especially as it is por-
Socrates was also charged with impiety, or trayed in the dialogues Ap., Crito and Phd.,
not believing in the gods that the city believed and Plato wraps even these events in paradox.
in (Ap. 24b), and yet Plato’s Socrates con- By stridently opposing the Athenian democ-
stantly and provocatively invokes the divine, racy and refusing to live anything but the
and his entire life is devoted to fulfilling a philosophical life to which he is committed,
divine mission (Ap. 29a–d). He even scolds he puts an end to his philosophizing – at least
the Athenian jury that convicts him, saying in his embodied life. For both interlocutors
he is literally the god’s gift to Athens (Ap. and readers, he is an object of love, admira-
30d–e). He is also distinct for his unique tion, irritation, fear, esteem, hatred, wonder
communication with the daimon (q.v.), indi- and misunderstanding. Plato’s characteriza-
cating his special connection to the divine. tion of Socrates’ life and death has ensured
Plato’s Socrates is both playful and serious; the Socratic legacy for 2,500 years.

128

9780826435354_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 128 3/8/2001 5:12:59 PM


4
TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED
IN THE DIALOGUES

ACCOUNT (see Logos) least prominently display the aims, condi-


tions and principles of art (technê, q.v.). Thus
it can be said that aesthetic themes are prom-
AESTHETICS inent throughout the works of Plato. There
are two dimensions of Plato’s aesthetics,
Eugenio Benitez however, that are arguably more fundamen-
Many of Plato’s dialogues explicitly discuss tal to his philosophy than any of the specific
matters that today fall under the umbrella themes just mentioned. They are the dimen-
of aesthetics. Literary criticism occupies sions of mimêsis (q.v.), or representation,
a prominent place in the Ion, Menexenus, and the dimension of mousikê, or ‘music’
Symposium, Republic, Phaedrus and Laws. in the broad sense that includes all the arts
Arguments about the standard of aesthetic (q.v. music). When these are taken into con-
judgement occupy most of the Hippias sideration it becomes plain that aesthetics is
Major, as well as portions of the Smp. and not just prominent in, but central to Plato’s
the second book of the Lg. Some dialogues thought.
even venture into territory that we might According to several dialogues, all writ-
describe as ‘pure aesthetics’, in that they dis- ing, and indeed all art, is a form of mimêsis
cuss specific perceptible properties of form, (e.g. Criti. 107b; Lg. 668b). It is not always
colour or sound (Hp. Ma. 298 ff.; Philebus appreciated how comprehensive this claim
51c), the manner by which art objects appear is for Plato. It includes even philosophical
as they do to spectators (Sophist 236a), the writing, which is admitted to be a form of
characteristics of an artwork purely in terms poetry (Lg. 817a), and so it applies both to
of art (Lg. 667d) or the ontological status of the dialogues themselves (811c), and to their
art objects (R. 596a ff.). A few dialogues inci- function (Phdr. 276d). We should therefore
dentally discuss painting, sculpture or music expect that Plato’s dialogues are composed
(narrowly construed), by way of illustrat- according to their own explicit ideas about
ing a more general topic (R. 472d ff.; Phlb. aesthetic representation. The most impor-
17d; Critias 107b), and some dialogues, such tant of these ideas is the distinction drawn
as the Gorgias and Timaeus, delineate or at in the Sph. between two ways that an image

129

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 129 3/17/2001 9:20:56 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

might represent its original. One way is by Once we see that for Plato all disclosure
really being like the original. Such images occurs by means of images, we can better
are called ‘likenesses’ (Sph. 235d6). Another understand his deep concerns about music
way is by seeming, but not really being like and musical education. Music is for him not
the original. Such images are called ‘phan- merely cultural study, it is a matter of ontol-
tasms’ (236c3). To be genuinely philosophi- ogy. As the Athenian Stranger puts it, ‘anyone
cal, the dialogues must attain the standard who would not err about a poem must rec-
of likenesses. Yet, even if the dialogues ognise what it is (hoti pot’ esti); he must rec-
attain that standard, they remain distinct ognise its reality (ousian) – what it wants to
from their originals. The inability of an art- be and what it is really a likeness of (ti pote
work ever to copy its original perfectly has bouletai kai hotou pot estin eikôn ontôs, Lg.
implications for the interpretation of Plato 668c4–7)’. The skills basic to education in
in general, since it seems unlikely, based the arts are the very same skills that appear
on the aesthetics of original and image, in more developed form in the philosopher.
that Plato would ever suppose that his dia- In that case images that fail to resemble how
logues stated the truth simply and exactly. things really are, in particular images that
The best they might do is to disclose truth present an attractive but skewed perspective
to one who could see them from the right of things, are not only deceptive but mentally
perspective. On this view, doctrine would be distorting. They warp mental processes so
avoided in preference of a variety of conver- that it becomes hard to see correctly. A child
gent likenesses. whose mental processes were warped by long
There is an even more comprehensive exposure to distortions would have difficulty
implication of the view that all art is mimêtic. in acquiring the skill to see what is reflected
In the Ti., we are told that the world itself in images (cf. Lg. 653a–c). An adult whose
is a work of art, that it is in fact ‘a moving mental processes were so distorted would be
image of eternity’ (Ti. 37d5). Because the like someone chained to the way of mistake
relationship of the world to eternity is one (cf. R. 514a).
of likeness, the status of the world as image Fortunately, thinks Plato, the intellectual
implies that the appearance–reality distinc- appeal of beauty, symmetry and truth far
tion is, for Plato, an aesthetic one. Reality outweigh the hedonistic attractions of a false
does not underlie the appearances like some perspective (Phlb. 65b–e). Moreover, the nat-
sort of primary substance; it is represented in ural desire for all things beautiful is capable
them, as in a work of art. On this view there of being trained and focused (Smp. 210a ff.).
is not any fundamental difference between Anyone who has once caught a glimpse of
the way one discovers reality through art or what is truly fair will be eager to behold it
through natural science – in either case one again. That is the motivation to philosophy.
is finding the real in a reflection. As a result, Considered from the point of view of beauty
musical skills (in the broad sense) become an and symmetry, it seems like a fundamentally
all-inclusive conduit to reality. Music, when aesthetic motivation. Considered from the
genuinely harmonious, provides the pattern point of view of truth, it seems like a fun-
for discovering anything true. In this sense all damentally epistemological motivation. At
music is philosophical, and philosophy is ‘the the deepest level, however, it is nothing more
greatest music’ (Phaedo 61a3). than a motivation for the good (R. 504e).

130

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 130 3/17/2001 9:20:57 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

AKRASIA (INCONTINENCE, is pleasure, and to judge that something is


WEAKNESS OF WILL) better or worse is to judge that it is more
pleasant or less pleasant, respectively; so
Daniel C. Russell since practical reason (in the form of either
Although Aristotle (Nicomachean Ethics VII) knowledge or belief, 358b–c) and desire have
made akrasia the standard term in ancient the same targets, they do not oppose each
(and modern) discussions of acting against other. Apparent cases of akrasia must really
one’s better judgement, Plato more often be cases of ignorance that one is doing the
writes of doing wrong willingly or know- worse thing.
ingly (hekôn) as opposed to doing so unwill- Since desire has the same target as practi-
ingly or unknowingly (akôn). Like Aristotle, cal reason, desire must always seek what is
though, Plato recognized a problem in good, that is, beneficial for one. That is, no
explaining how such a thing is possible. one does wrong willingly:
Plato characterizes akrasia (or rather
akrateia, as he calls it at Timaeus 86d) as Now, no one goes willingly toward the
voluntarily acting badly against one’s bet- bad or what he believes to be bad; nei-
ter judgement due to being overcome by a ther is it in human nature, so it seems, to
desire to go toward what one believes to
desire, despite being able to do otherwise.
be bad instead of to the good. And when
Consider someone who voluntarily overeats
he is forced to choose between one of
despite meaning to stick to a diet. One might two bad things, no one will choose the
characterize his behaviour as akratic – a greater if he is able to choose the lesser.
breakdown between judgement and choice – (358d)
and then explain how such breakdowns
occur. Alternatively, perhaps characteriza- Earlier in Prt. Socrates declared it ‘unedu-
tion is mistaken and the behaviour should be cated’ to suppose ‘that any human being
explained in some other way. Plato appears willingly makes a mistake or willingly does
to have taken each of these approaches in anything wrong or bad’; rather, educated
different places. persons know ‘very well that anyone who
In some dialogues Plato rejects the pos- does anything wrong or bad does so involun-
sibility of akrasia on the grounds that there tarily’ (345d–e). Similarly, in Meno (77a–8a)
is no opposition between such motivating Socrates argues that if people did bad things
forces as practical reason and desire (q.v.). knowing them to be bad, then they would
In the Protagoras, Socrates puts forward know that such things were harmful for
the thesis that no one does wrong wittingly. them and thus would make them miserable
Whereas most people think that knowledge is and unhappy. But since nobody desires to be
often ‘dragged around’ by desire ‘as if it were miserable and unhappy, anyone who desires
a slave’, Socrates suggests that ‘knowledge is what is in fact bad must mistakenly believe
a fine thing capable of ruling a person’ and that that thing is beneficial for him. Likewise,
that ‘if someone were to know what is good responding to Callicles who espouses akrasia
and bad, then he would not be forced by any- in Gorgias, Socrates says that ‘no one does
thing to act otherwise than knowledge dic- what’s unjust because he desires to’, but
tates’ (Prt. 352c). Socrates’ argument for this that ‘all who do so do it unwillingly’ (Grg.
thesis focuses on pleasure: what we desire 509e). This, he says, is because we desire to

131

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 131 3/17/2001 9:20:57 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

do only those things that benefit us: ‘when due to ‘lack of self-control’ (734b). (Although
one desires some act for the sake of some 644d–5b also seems to suggest that the
end, that end must be something beneficial soul is divided into parts, Bobonich 1994 has
for one, since when one learns that an act challenged this; see Gerson 2003 for a reply.)
would be harmful for one, one stops desiring Yet the Athenian also says that ‘every unjust
it’ (467c–8c). The denial of akrasia – often man is unjust against his will’, since no one
called the ‘Socratic paradox’ – rests on the willingly embraces things that are harmful
idea that what desire seeks is also what prac- for him in his ‘most precious part’ (731c; see
tical reason seeks, so that there can be no also 860d–4c; Philebus 22b). The Athenian
opposition between them. brings these two thoughts together by saying
Elsewhere, however, Plato argues that desire that succumbing to akrasia is succumbing
does not seek what practical reason seeks. In to doing what one does not really desire to
Republic, Socrates famously divides the soul do (Lg. 863d–e; see also Clitomachus 407d).
(q.v.) into ‘reason’, ‘spirit’ and ‘appetite’, and But this is puzzling: if to act against practi-
argues that whereas reason and spirit seek cal reason is to do what one does not really
what is beneficial, appetite (not distinguished desire to do, then how can desire also lead
from desire) does not (R. 437b–41c). Indeed, one to act against practical reason?
Socrates compares spirit and reason to a lion Some help may come from Ti., where it
and a tamer united against appetite, depicted is said that a corrupted person has excessive
as a hydra (588b–90d). On this view, one desires but is not willingly in such a condi-
can desire to do what one judges to be bad, tion (Ti. 86b–7b). Perhaps Plato’s thought is
as when Leontius succumbed to a desire to that in its uncorrupted condition desire seeks
look at corpses (439e–40b). Likewise, in what practical reason seeks, and that ‘will-
Phaedrus (237d–8c) Plato depicts reason ingly’ must be understood in terms of desire
as a charioteer with one noble and obedi- in its uncorrupted condition. So akrasia is the
ent horse (spirit) and one ugly, disobedient result of a corrupted condition, which is bad
horse (appetite/desire) that is deaf to reason for one, and no one is ‘willingly’ in that cor-
and occasionally gets its way. And in Sophist, rupt condition. Moreover, since wrongdoing
Plato distinguishes going wrong out of igno- is bad for the one who does it, it follows that
rance from going wrong out of vice, that is, no one does wrong ‘willingly’.
a ‘discord’ between ‘beliefs and desires, anger Many scholars believe that Plato denied
and pleasures, reason and pains’ (Sph. 228b). the possibility of akrasia (when he did) on
In these dialogues, apparently one can desire the grounds that desire is a species of practi-
what reason judges to be bad for one, mak- cal reason (e.g. Penner 1991), a view often
ing akrasia possible. called ‘Socratic intellectualism’; but there is
However, in yet other dialogues Plato no consensus on this point (e.g. Brickhouse
seems to hold both that akrasia is possi- and Smith 2007; Devereux 1995). Moreover,
ble and that no one does wrong willingly. the apparent shifts in Plato’s thinking on
In Laws, the Athenian says that there can akrasia and the nature of the soul have been
be discord between one’s ‘feelings of pleas- central to modern debates about the unity
ure and pain and [one’s] rational judgment’ (or otherwise) of Plato’s philosophy across
(Lg. 689a), and that while some people are his career (e.g. Annas 1999:ch. 6; Vlastos
‘immoderate’ due to ignorance, some are so 1991a:48, 86–91).

132

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 132 3/17/2001 9:20:57 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

ANTILOGY AND ERISTICS (ERISTIC) antilogical eristics, the conclusions were


often based on an ambiguous, if not on a rel-
Menahem Luz ativistic, understanding of the goals of phi-
Antilogy (antilogia) is an ancient concept losophy (Guthrie 1971a:176–81). Although
mentioned as early as Herodotus (VIII.77, many scholars have followed the ancients in
IX.88) and etymologically corresponding to denigrating Eristics, some have considered it
the English term ‘contradiction’ (anti = con- and antilogy more objectively as the first ten-
tra, logia = diction), but broader in scope with tative steps towards logical thinking (Kneale
a secondary meaning of ‘dispute’ or ‘gainsay’ and Kneale 1964:12).
where no formal contradiction is implied. The relativistic sophist Protagoras was
Although the art of antilogical contradic- said to have been the first to develop antilogy
tion (antilogikê technê) was occasionally as a principle of argumentation: ‘there are
employed by Socrates in order to disprove two arguments (logoi) on every theme con-
a mistaken opinion (Theaetetus 197a), the traposed (antikeimenoi) to each other’ (D. L.
art of ‘antilogy and disputation’ was chiefly 9.51.13–5). This was probably discussed in
employed in competitions for profit by the his lost work: ‘Antilogies vols.1, 2’ (54.19;
sophists as part of their art of eristic (Sophist cf. 9.38) and a surviving text of his school
226a). reads:
The word Eristics is derived from the term
‘rivalry’ (eris) since the sophists competed There are two logoi cited by the philoso-
against one another or a prospective client phers in Greece concerning the good and
in disputation (Lysis 211b) employing any bad, for some claim that the good is one
thing and the bad another while others
verbal trick or captious ‘sophism’ even if
[claim] that they are the same thing for
reached through false assumptions as exem-
something is good for some but bad for
plified throughout Plato’s Euthd. (Kneale others – and even for the same person it
and Kneale 1964:12–15). Plato thus did not is sometimes good and sometimes bad.
regard eristic ‘rivalry’ as serious philosophy (D. L. 2.90.1.1)
but ‘a game’ in disputation (Sph. 237b–c) –
that is, argument for argument’s sake – and In this quotation from the Dissoi Logoi not
employing antilogy for this purpose (216a, only are ‘good’ and ‘bad’ relative, but even
232b). Although there are many cases where the arguments for and against this claim are
antilogy and eristics should be distinguished relative in that they comprise two logoi in
(Kerferd 1989:62–5), antilogical eristics were the form of an antilogy. Plato later criticized
also employed as part of a sophist’s training the sophists who wasted their time in ‘anti-
in order to enhance expertise in the art of logical arguments (logoi)’ in that they lacked
persuasion. They were also employed in pub- ‘the art of logos’ to distinguish between truth
lic rhetorical displays (epideixeis), in which and the falsehood (Phaedo 90b–c; cf. 101e).
a sophist would give a public lecture contra- Since Protagoras maintained that the indi-
dicting or disputing conventionally accepted vidual is the sole ‘measure’ of truth not only
norms – for example, Gorgias’ Encomium for the phenomena but also for the truth of a
to Helen defends the immorality of Helen logos or its antilogos, the decision on which
of Troy. Since the search for the truth was of them is to become the accepted norm
often secondary to the art of persuasion in depended on a speaker’s power of persuasion

133

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 133 3/17/2001 9:20:57 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

rather than the objective truth of his argu- make generalizations that do not distin-
ments (D. L. 9.51.14–16). While Protagoras guish between the different species of sub-
might contradict (antilegei) accepted social ject (R. 454a–b). Besides Plato’s criticism of
norms and logoi by democratic persuasion, sophistic contradiction (antilogikos) as hav-
an extreme sophist like Thrasymachus would ing no part in true philosophy (Tht. 164c–d),
use antilogical eristic to justify tyranny he also includes philosophical questioning
through the use of fallacy and ambiguous that contradicts the opponents’ conclusions
argument (Republic 343b–4c). The anti- rather than their hypotheses (Sph. 225b–d).
logical method was also used in eristic exer- This has been plausibly interpreted as a refer-
cise whereby rival students vied with each ence to Euclides’ Megarian school (Cornford
other to justify the case of either one of the 1964:176–7) where antilogical paradox was
two antilogies. However, as early as Plato employed precisely for this purpose.
(Phaedrus 261d–e), it was also used in foren- Like Plato, who incorporated the princi-
sic training, juridical theory (one must hear ple of antilogies into his method of diaire-
both sides prior to judgement) and later in sis (q.v. Method) whereby each species
sceptical enquiry (for every logos there is an could be divided into a class that is like and
antilogos). unlike, Aristotle’s early logical work ‘On the
Conservatives like Aristophanes (Clouds Opposites’ (peri enantion) established that it
889–1104) and philosophers in the Socratic is not contrasting (antikeimena) subjects that
circle viewed this relative and nonnorma- are syllogies (e.g. wisdom and ignorance) but
tive approach as undermining belief in logoi their definitions that are (Ross 1970:108,
that supported accepted morality since in f. 3). This however was to be replaced by his
their view only one of the two antilogies doctrine in the Categories where substance
could be true by nature or reason at any one has no opposite itself and while the other cat-
time. Nonetheless, it has been claimed that egories (quality, quantity, etc.) may contain
Socrates’ method of dialectic refutation (elen- opposites (black and white, heavy and light)
chus; q.v.) can be seen to be derived from the they are not opposites in themselves. Just
antilogical methods of the sophists in that he as he treated the examination of sophistic
too sought for inconsistencies in the argu- rhetoric in an objective, nonmoralizing way,
ments of his conversants (Gulley 1968:31). so Aristotle turned to sophistries, eristics and
A method of countering the Sophists antilogies in his work Sophistical Refutations,
was formulated by Antisthenes (q.v. Other where he drew the distinction between differ-
Socratics) that each definition and statement ent forms of logical reasoning (‘syllogism’),
(logos) can denote only one thing (e.g. ‘gold is for reasoning can be either true or false, but
gold’) and statements in other terms (e.g. ‘gold it is the duty of the true reason not only to
is a yellow metal’) are contradictions referring prove something but also to refute false rea-
gold to something else (Luz 2000:92). Thus, soning (Sophistical Refutations 176b29–31).
Antisthenes concluded that it is impossible to In the Topics, Aristotle carefully worked out
contradict (antilegein) since each logos refers rules by which the dialectical syllogism can
to a separate entity. Plato recognized that the avoid this and confute the antilogy (Topics
art of contradiction (antilogikê technê) can 105a:18–19). His answer to the Protagorean
intrude itself into serious dialectic as well as antilogy (Metaphysics 4; 1011b23–24)
false eristic especially when the conversants is found in his principle of the Law of the

134

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 134 3/17/2001 9:20:58 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

Excluded Middle (metaxu antiphaseos): it is • doxa: a ‘belief’, an ‘opinion’, a ‘thought’;


impossible to maintain (phanai) and contra- what seems (dokein) so to someone, in
dict (apophanai) the same thing in the same contrast to what really is the case, for
relationship at the same time (Metaphysics 4; example, knowledge (epistêmê) or under-
1005b.19–20, 26–34n). However, he did find standing (nous)
a use for antilogies in Metaphysics 2: in order • ta legomena: ‘things said’; what a com-
to understand a problem we have to list all of munity of speakers accepts (compare
its quandaries (aporiai) and arguments pro muthoi), in contrast to what really is so
et contra. There he set forth 14 quandaries • to phainetai: ‘what appears so’; how
of metaphysics, each by thesis and antithesis, things received by the senses (aisthêseis)
but strictly avoided any formal solution for are perceived or thought about, in con-
either side. Aristotle, however, did not believe trast to what is or exists (to einai)
that each thesis and antithesis had equal • to mê on: ‘what is not’; what some people
weight in the end, but that we must attain mistake for what really exists (to on)
positive knowledge of a subject by weighing • to genomenos: ‘what comes to be’; what
both sides beforehand. In this way he clears changes and has changing appearances, in
the table for his positive apodeictic discus- contrast to whatever is unchanging (and
sion of metaphysics in the following books. may be invisible)
Without the antitheses of bk 2 we would not • dream-appearances, shadows, reflections,
know which arguments to set aside. paintings and mimêtic activity

(I) ETHICS

APPEARANCE AND REALITY In the dialogues, understanding a virtue may


(REALITY) start in, but cannot stop at, specifying either
those people who appear to exemplify that
Christopher Moore virtue or those sets of traits which seem typi-
Plato’s dialogues prompt reflection on at least cal of those people who exemplify that virtue.
four related questions about reality. Ethical: Many of Plato’s characters come to accept
how does living well take apprehending what that understanding a virtue requires propos-
is real? Epistemological: in what ways does ing an abstract definition and then testing it
apprehending what is real differ from believ- against counter-examples. That the reality of
ing what is merely apparent? Metaphysical: a virtue or some other object of moral reflec-
what does accepting a distinction between tion may be discovered through conceptual
reality and appearance mean for the nature analysis seems likely to be a cultural presup-
of things? Methodological: by what means position preceding Socrates but elaborated
might one come to know what is real? by Plato’s Socrates.
People act on their thoughts about their
• Plato’s characters distinguish diverse moral obligations, circumstances and
kinds of appearances from reality: resources, but their thoughts may not reflect
• eikos: ‘plausible’, ‘probable’, ‘reasonable’; reality. Protagoras sees himself as a com-
what is persuasive in a speech, in contrast pletely capable educator; Crito worries he
to what is true (alêtheia) will be seen as a shameful friend. Yet the

135

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 135 3/17/2001 9:20:58 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

dialogues suggest that they fail to know what about what makes our apprehension of real-
they really can, and thus ought, to do. They ity distinctive (Burnyeat 1990).
lack self-knowledge (q.v.). This has bad conse-
quences for their students, the city (Phaedrus (III) METAPHYSICS
277e1–3), their associates (Theaetetus 201c)
and themselves, either at present or hereafter Degree of reality seems proportional to
(Gorgias 524d). explanatory scope: whatever most explains
Rather than emphasizing the ‘depth’ of the order of the universe is the most real;
self-knowledge when writing about getting how things appear to us is less real (though
to the reality of one’s nature, Plato uses the not entirely unreal).
tropes of matching inward with outward In the Tht., Socrates impersonates a
(Phdr. 279b9; Symposium 215b), comparing Protagoras who argues that the world is just
oneself to ideals (Phdr. 230a), working with as it seems to each of its perceivers. The bulk
others (Alcibiades 1 133b) and being able to of the dialogue goes to undermine (some
say what one means (Laches 194b). version) of this relativistic thesis, thus sup-
porting the view that something constant
(II) EPISTEMOLOGY underlies everyone’s perceptions. Talk about
appearance or seeming or opinion makes
The myth of the cave (q.v.) in Republic bk 7 sense only against an assumption that there
suggests that what we now accept as real we is something more real.
may later reject as mere shadow, reflection It is traditional to call Plato, in contrast
or image. The myth does not tell us how to to Aristotle, an idealist, someone who sus-
assess the match between our beliefs and the pects or is committed to the belief that the
world. But bk 1 depicts refutative exchange, really real is not the changing particulars
the revelation of beliefs and their (inconsist- but something imperceptible, immutable and
ent) consequences to show that some of what intelligible. While Plato likely did not pioneer
one thought cannot be true. Bks 2–3 and 10 distinguishing between appearance and real-
dwell on the effects of attending to imitations ity with ‘form’ (eidos, idea) language, his dia-
of reality (mimêsis) (cf. Sophist 267e1; Grg. logues did draw implications from such talk.
462b–5d). Bk 6’s divided line image (q.v.) It may be impossible to articulate a theory
gives a symbol of the distinction between of forms from these dialogues, either because
reflections, material objects, hypothetical Plato did not have one; or if he did, did
knowledge and grounded knowledge. Bk not use the dialogues to set out and defend
7’s system of education identifies the way a it, or because his views changed over time.
person might become practised at acquiring Nevertheless, the dialogues might show the
knowledge of immutable things (universal value of thinking about what could explain
forms), particularly through mathematics how the world seems to us (Moravscik 1992;
and deliberate conversation. Thesleff 1999).
The Tht. discusses the nature of knowl-
edge, in particular how to distinguish it from (IV) METHODOLOGY
(mere) perception, (mere) true belief and
(mere) true belief with an account, but does In the Ion, Socrates wonders how Ion could
not conclude with any explicit agreement know what Homer really thought. Socrates

136

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 136 3/17/2001 9:20:58 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

suggests he has no rational skill but is served resource is always what seems so to us (Tht.
instead by ‘inspiration’ (q.v.). Whether Plato 171d3–5) – we may seem caught in a web of
believes any aspect of reality could be appre- appearances. Plato’s Socrates seems to have
hended via inspiration, prophecy or direct responded by (tentatively) taking as real
intuition, is hard to say, but it is doubtful those theses that survived continuous testing.
he thinks such means could verify their own Plato may further have thought that math-
accuracy. ematics or similar practises could reveal sig-
What seems clearer is that in that dialogue nificant parts of reality, though which parts,
Socrates removes the appearance of Ion’s and with what significance, remains a diffi-
great wisdom and reveals that Ion really just cult question.
has a knack with Homeriana. Socrates finds
this out by asking Ion questions (erôtesis),
examining the things he says (exetasis), and
refuting him (elenchos). These three revela- APPETITE (see Desire)
tory activities Socrates together calls ‘philos-
ophizing’ (Ap. 29de). What Plato thinks this ARGUMENT (see Logos)
kind of talking can establish is uncertain.
The dialogues offer many more candi- ART (TECHNÊ)
date methods (q.v.) for discovering reality
amid appearances. One might remember David Roochnik
what the wise have said (Men. 81a5; Phdr. Technê, typically translated as ‘art’, ‘exper-
260a5–6), study with those who know (Lg. tise’, ‘craft’ or ‘skill’, is a word used widely
186c–d), run deductions (Phdr. 245c6–6a2), and with great significance in Plato’s early
look at a diagram (Men. 82b9), hypothesize dialogues, for example consider Laches
(Men. 86e7–7b7; Phd. 100a3–8; Parmenides 184e–5e. Here Socrates is faced with the
136a1–2) and practise dividing and col- question of how to educate a young man
lecting (Sph. 218c; Phdr. 277b5–9). The R. in ‘virtue’ or ‘excellence’ (aretê). He insists
appears to encourage ‘dialectic’ (q.v.) as a that only ‘an expert’, someone who is tech-
way to knowing how things really are (R. nikos (La. 185a1) – that is, has mastered a
454a, 511b–c), though it is not clear what technê – in the matter under deliberation
this term means beyond deliberate, reason- is qualified to provide an answer. To con-
able and sustained examination (cf. Prm. vince his interlocutors that this is the case he
135c2). To be a philosopher on the model of deploys an analogy: if one wished to know
Socrates involves trying to live on the basis what physical exercise the boy should prac-
of good reasons, reasons based in what is tise in order to develop an excellent body, he
real and true, on facts and valid inference. (It would consult an expert or technical ‘trainer’
is debatable whether the other philosophers (paidotribê:184e3). In an analogous fashion,
in Plato’s dialogues stand for this.) Many when the question concerns the excellence
of our reasons are good, but our accepting of the young men, someone who is ‘expert
them is insufficient reason for continuing (technikos) in the care (therapeian) of the
to accept them. Yet, deciding which to keep soul (psuchê)’ (185e4) is required.
involves a conceptual difficulty. Since beliefs Apology 20a–c presents a second exam-
are checked only against other beliefs – our ple. If, Socrates argues, Callias’ two sons

137

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 137 3/17/2001 9:20:58 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

were colts, he would hire an experienced, subordinate themselves to the one who pos-
well-trained and well-regarded professional sesses such answers: to what Jenks calls the
to supervise their upbringing, for only such ‘moral expert’ (Jenks 2008:xv). As a result, it
an expert would be able to cultivate the is arguable that there is a direct connection
excellence ‘appropriate’ (prosêkousan:Ap. between Socrates’ use of the technê-anal-
20b1) to horses. His sons are young men but ogy in the early dialogues and the political
no less, Socrates suggests, do they require authoritarianism that he seems to defend in
someone ‘knowledgeable’ (epistêmôn:20b5) the Republic where ‘philosopher-kings’ are
to educate them in their specific excellence; firmly in control of the lives of the citizens. In
namely, in ‘human and political excellence’ other words, a political implication of a strict
(20b4–5). Again, the analogy is manifest: as reading of the analogy is that it becomes rea-
the technical horse trainer is to the excellence sonable for citizens to obey an epistemically
of colts, so the technical educator is to the authoritative ruler.
excellence appropriate to young men. Many scholars such as Parry (1996) read
Since an ‘expert’, or technitês, has mas- Socrates’ use of the technê-analogy in this
tered his subject thoroughly, his knowledge fashion. In other words, they take technê
can be readily identified. He can, in many to be a positive model for Plato’s early
cases, simply point to the results of his work attempt to develop a moral theory. (See Irwin
to give evidence of his skill. For example, 1977a:71–5 for a clear summary of this posi-
after months of training by someone knowl- tion.) For at least three related reasons this
edgeable in hippikê, the technê of horseman- view must be challenged. First and most gen-
ship, the young colt will be visibly improved. erally, the notion of a ‘moral expert’ implied
For this reason its owner is willing to pay the by a positive reading of the analogy conflicts
expert horse trainer for his services. (Indeed, with the aporetic or interrogative character
at times ‘technitês’ can even be translated as of so many of Socrates’ dialogues. Second, if
‘professional’.) In general, it is reasonable it is the case that as the horse trainer is to
for ‘laymen’ (idioteis) who are not knowl- horses, so the expert in human virtue is to
edgeable in the field – and every technê has human beings, then human aretê must, like
a specific or determinate field – to defer to the specific excellence of horses, be a deter-
the expert’s judgements. Even though the colt minate epistemic object. It must constitute a
belongs to a wealthy aristocrat, its owner, if bounded conceptual field that can be thor-
he truly wants an excellent horse, will rigor- oughly mastered. Again, the aporetic char-
ously follow the regimen prescribed by the acter of the dialogues should call this into
horse trainer. question. Third, if the field of expertise is,
With this in mind, consider the conse- as the La. passage cited above suggests, the
quences of a strict reading of Socrates’ use human soul, then the psuchê must also be
of the technê-analogy. On the simplest level, determinate, for it must be capable of becom-
if there were a technitês in human excel- ing a subject matter of an expert’s technê. It
lence then the endeavour to live a good is arguable on the basis of a reading of the
life would become a question that could be Symposium such as that presented in Hyland
answered, a problem that could be solved. (2008:39–41), for example, that the psuchê is
Second, if the analogy holds strictly, it would not such an object. As a result, a strict read-
be reasonable for other human beings to ing of the analogy becomes problematic.

138

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 138 3/17/2001 9:20:58 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

The above does not imply that the analogy of reason (Republic 401d–2b). Erotic expe-
is without philosophical significance. Instead, rience of a beautiful body can turn one’s life
it suggests that it should be read as quite towards the pursuit of wisdom (Symposium
limited. Virtue may indeed be analogous to 210a–12a; Phaedrus 250d–6e). And all the
technê but only in the minimal sense of being interlocutors assume that virtue is kalon,
some kind of knowledge, even if not a techni- including the great amoralist Callicles, who
cal one. In fact, it is conceivable, as Roochnik is presented as claiming against Socrates that
(1996) argues that Plato has Socrates deploy pleonectic power is more genuinely kalon –
the analogy precisely to develop a concep- and thus more truly virtuous – than the tra-
tion of virtue as non-technical knowledge. To ditional moral virtues (Gorgias 482c–6d,
clarify, consider Vlastos’s distinction between 508c–e; cf. Sophist 228e, 230d–e). Plato
‘knowledgec’, a rigorous form of knowl- does assume that good art will be kalon (R.
edge whose hallmark is ‘infallible certainty’ 377b, 401c; Laws 668a, 669a) and estab-
(Vlastos 1985:14) and ‘knowledgee’ (Vlastos lishes a criteria of poetic beauty, but he does
1985:15), ‘elenctic knowledge’ that Socrates not make the modern assumption that art
derives through his familiar argumentative provides an especially pure or philosophi-
strategies. Even though it does not invoke the cally illuminating case of the experience of
technê model this distinction is useful. The beauty. That experience in Plato’s view is the
‘elenctic knowledge’ Socrates both encour- experience of love (q.v.).
ages and may even possess is not strictly The Greek term kalon can be translated
technical. Instead, it emerges only from dia- by a number of English words: beautiful,
logue with others. fine, admirable, noble and good. In its adver-
bial form, kalôs, it is typically used as the
equivalent of the adverbial form of agathos
(good). Some scholars doubt that Plato’s dis-
BEAUTY (KALON) cussion of the kalon really concerns beauty
at all, especially in moral contexts (Irwin
Gabriel Richardson Lear 1979:154). But although the two concepts
The notion of beauty (to kalon) is surpris- are not exactly the same (Kosman 2010), it
ingly pervasive in Plato’s dialogues (ugly = is unlikely that Plato’s kalon is simply the
aischron). Whereas modern philosophers praiseworthy in general, only sometimes
tend to treat beauty as the special concern referring to what is admirable in a specifi-
of aesthetics, Plato finds a significant role cally aesthetic way (i.e. by eliciting a special
for it in his metaphysics, cosmology, epis- sort of pleasure in an observer). For example,
temology and ethics. For example, Socrates Plato often has characters assert that things
argues that beauty, along with proportion are kalon when their parts are well-propor-
and truth, is the cause of the good life and, tioned, harmonious and measured (Phlb.
more generally, of good mixtures (Philebus 64e; R. 402d; Sph. 228a, 235e–6a; Ti. 30c,
65a). The beauty of the cosmos (q.v.) marks 87c–8c). This analysis coincides with one
it as formed in the image of eternal models traditional account of beauty. Furthermore,
(Timaeus 28a–9a). Love of genuinely beau- he emphasizes the way we are ‘struck all of
tiful poetry and people is a necessary, or at a sudden’ by kala people and ideas, suggest-
least useful, preliminary for the development ing that the kalon is distinguished in part by

139

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 139 3/17/2001 9:20:59 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

the way it affects our receptivity (Smp. 210e; functions – numerical proportions, patches
Phdr. 250b–d). The kalon forces itself on our of pure colour might be examples – can be
awareness, either through our eyes or on the explained in terms of their relation to the
mind. Since this experience of being struck is good. This raises the question of whether
vital to Plato’s story of how erôs can be chan- and how to distinguish beauty and good-
nelled into a process of intellectual develop- ness (Barney 2010; Hobbs 2000:222–7;
ment – the kalon object of love is, at each Lear 2007; Price 1989:16; White 1989).
stage, a ‘summoner’ of philosophical thought Insofar as we experience something as
(Ferrari 1987:144–6) – we should take care beautiful, we feel pleasure (q.v.). Sometimes
not to disown the kalon’s kinship with beauty the pleasure is pure (Phlb. 51c–d), other
in this respect. times it is ‘mixed’ with pain (Phdr. 251c–d).
In the R. Socrates claims that the form This connection between pleasure and
of the good (q.v.) is the cause of ‘all that is beauty reveals another aspect of Plato’s view:
correct and beautiful in anything’ (R. 517c; beauty is a feature of the way things appear
cf. 452e; Ti. 30a). If this were true, it would or manifest themselves to a subject. In the
justify his claim that all beautiful things are Phdr. Socrates claims that the beautiful alone
good (Alcibiades. 1 115a–16c; Meno 77b; among the forms ‘shines out’ through the
Protagoras 358b; for the converse, that sensible objects which participate in it (Phdr.
all good things are beautiful: Lysis 216d; 250b–e). In the first instance, this means that
Smp. 201c, 204d–e). In the R., he is espe- it is a form whose images we can literally see.
cially concerned with the beauty of things But the ‘radiance’ of beauty seems also to
with a proper work or function. We can see refer to our mode of access to it. Although
why goodness in such things would cause we may work out later why something is
them to be kalon. For the goodness of such beautiful, that it is beautiful is something of
a thing is whatever it is that enables it to which we are immediately aware.
perform its proper function well, but that Beauty is therefore the power of appear-
is precisely what will determine what it is ing, that is, manifesting oneself as, perfect
for that thing to be well-proportioned and and internally harmonious. This does not
internally harmonious. And proportion imply that whenever we experience some-
and harmony are the hallmarks of beauty thing as beautiful, it is in fact beautiful. Our
(R. 601d, 452e; Ti. 87c). This functional own defective perspective (perceptual or eth-
account of beauty fits well with one of the ical) may cause a false appearance of beauty
definitions of the beautiful proposed in or ugliness (Sph. 235d–6a; cf. Hp. Ma.
Hippias Major: that it is the appropriate 294a–e; R. 602b). And as with other illusions
(Hp. Ma. 290c–1d). It also makes sense of of appearance, one can experience something
the intuition that the beautiful is beneficial as beautiful without believing as a matter of
(Grg. 474d; Hp. Ma. 296e–7a; Laches 192d; rational conviction that it is perfect. In this
cf. R. 364a). Though genuinely kala things case, a conflict would occur between the
may not suit the desires we happen to have, part of the soul to which the object appears
if they are human artefacts, actions or souls, beautiful and the part which believes that it
they will be useful from the point of view is not.
of the human function (R. 589c; Ti. 87e). Genuinely beautiful things are therefore
It is less clear how beautiful things without truthful in the sense of communicating to a

140

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 140 3/17/2001 9:20:59 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

spectator an accurate appearance of perfec- BEING AND BECOMING (ON, ONTA;


tion. This is especially important for Plato’s GIGNESTHAI)
discussions of kalos logos, beautiful speech,
a topic that covers rhetorical persuasion Sandra Peterson
(Hp. Ma.; Phdr.), poetry (Ion; R.) and, by Several passages in Plato contrast being, using
implication, philosophical discourse (Smp. the Greek infinitive ‘to be’ (einai) or partici-
198b–9b; Lg. 817b). Since speech conveys ple ‘being’ (on) and becoming (gignesthai).
an image both of the world it describes and The contrast, tailored in each dialogue to its
of the person describing it, beautiful speech particular interlocutors, resists tidy packag-
must be truthful both in the sense of being ing into a single stance of Plato’s.
authentic and in the sense of imprinting in I discuss passages from Timaeus, Theaetetus
the listener beliefs which are correct, or at and Republic. Other relevant passages are:
least likely in outline. Truly beautiful speech Phaedo 78c–9a, 102b–3c; Cratylus 439b–
is, therefore, either wise or philosophical. 40e; Symposium 207d–8b; Parmenides
The experience of beauty is pleasant. 152b–e, 163d; Sophist 248a–9d; Philebus
Pleasure, according to Plato, is a qualifica- 26d, 27b, 54a–d, 59a–d, 61d–e; and Laws
tion of awareness attendant upon ‘being 893b–4.
filled with what is appropriate to our nature’
(R. 585d; Phlb. 31d). In other words, pleas- (I) TIMAEUS
ant objects and activities seem good for us
(Lg. 657c). The implication, though Plato At Ti. 27d–8a Timaeus strongly contrasts
does not say so explicitly, is that the expe- (a) what always is and never becomes, and
rience of beauty is not only the experience (b) what always becomes and never is. What
of a thing’s manifest perfection but also the always is ‘is grasped by understanding, which
experience of the thing’s perfection as good involves a reasoned account. It is unchang-
for the subject. It is no wonder, then, that ing’. What becomes is ‘grasped by opinion,
the experience of beauty excites erôs, that which involves unreasoning sense percep-
passionate desire for ‘intercourse’ with the tion. It comes to be and passes away but
beautiful thing. never really is’. The latter apparently includes
Plato’s faith in the transformative power all perceptible items in our world. Accounts
of beauty may seem overly optimistic, but of being are more reliable than accounts
he does not think it is guaranteed. In the of becoming, which are merely likely (Ti.
Phdr. Socrates depicts all aspects of the soul 29b–c). ‘What being is to becoming truth is
as responsive to the kalon boy, but their to belief (pistis)’ (Ti. 29c).
responses conflict. The life of philosophi- According to Timaeus (Ti. 28a–9a), a
cal conversation is only one way the strug- craftsman who made the universe could use
gle may be resolved (Phdr. 256a–c). Thus, only an eternal (aidion) model because a
it would be unfair to accuse Plato of sen- beautiful work requires an eternal model.
timental blindness to the danger of beauty. As an example of what is grasped by
Beauty has a beneficial effect only on souls understanding alone and not perceived by the
innately capable of improvement and only senses Timaeus (Ti. 51b–e) gives ‘intelligible
if they have a ‘leader to lead them aright’ forms’ such as fire itself, of which the fiery
(Smp. 210a). stuff in space that we perceive is an image.

141

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 141 3/17/2001 9:20:59 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

Timaeus further explains at Ti. 37e–8b nothing is hard, hot, or anything, just by
that we should not apply future or past itself; . . . but in their intercourse with
tensed forms of the verb ‘to be’ to what is one another things get . . . qualified in all
everlasting. We cannot say that it was and ways, as a result of their change. (156e)
will be, but we can say that it is. We can use [T]hings are always getting generated for
‘was’ and ‘will be’ of what becomes, but can- someone. We should exclude ‘be’; from
not accurately say even that what becomes everywhere . . . Nor ought we to admit
is what becomes. Timaeus does not dwell on ‘something’, ‘someone’s’, ‘my’, ‘this’,
this linguistic point. ‘that’, or any other word that brings
things to a standstill. (157b)
To illustrate Plato’s contrast between what
becomes round and what is round, consider:
when a lump of dough gets round after con- Socrates introduced the view that things never
tinued rolling, a doughy sphere gets generated are, but always get generated or come to be,
or comes-to-be (gignetai). Sphere-shape, how- to bolster Theaetetus’ proposal that knowl-
ever, always is (esti) round: the shape, sphere, edge is perception. On this view when we
did not ever become round. What a sphere is, incorrectly say that something is, we should
the sphere itself, is, permanently, round. most properly say that it is getting generated
for someone. (Or we could less properly say
(II) THEAETETUS that it is for someone.) Socrates explains the
connection to Theaetetus’ proposal:
Socrates at Tht. 152d finds Theaetetus
receptive to a view that elides the contrast 160c: Since what acts on me is for me and
between being and becoming. This view, not someone else, it’s also the case that I
which Socrates calls ‘not a paltry account’ and not someone else, perceive it? . . . So
my perception is true for me – because
of Protagoras, Heracleitus and Empedocles,
it’s always of the being that’s mine and
declares that nothing ever is:
as Protagoras said, it’s for me to decide
. . . Well then . . . how could I fail to have
. . . nothing is one thing itself by itself,
knowledge of the things I’m a perceiver
and you would not correctly call some-
of? . . . So you were quite right to say that
thing some sort of thing, but if you label
knowledge is nothing but perception.
it great it shows itself small . . . – and
everything that way, nothing being one
At Tht. 183b, however, Socrates and
thing or of something nor any sort of
thing. But from movement, change, and Theaetetus agree that in our current language
mixture with one another, everything one cannot state the theory that everything
that we say is – not labeling it correctly – constantly changes, unless perhaps one sim-
gets generated. For nothing ever is but ply utters ‘not so’ endlessly – which, presum-
always gets generated. (152d2–e1) ably, reduces the theory to absurdity. Socrates
drops it from the ensuing conversation.
Socrates subsequently gives the example
(154a) that colour gets generated or comes to (III) REPUBLIC
be between an eye and an object when they
(each a complex of motions and changes) What purely is contrasts with what rolls
collide. He says: about or wanders between what purely is

142

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 142 3/17/2001 9:20:59 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

and what is not (R. 475c–80b). What purely down by an ‘account (or working out, logis-
is, including such items as the beautiful itself, mos) of the cause (aitia)’ (Meno 97e–8a).
is always the same in all respects and is an This is also suggested by Timaeus 27e–8a,
appropriate object of knowledge (477). It which makes two points: first, that belief
is the special interest of philosophers (480). is concerned with that which comes to be,
Certain items roll about in that if they may in distinction from knowledge which is
be called, for example, just or beautiful, they concerned with that which is, and, second,
may also be called unjust or ugly (in some that everything that comes to be comes to
respect). Only later at 485b does the word be through the agency of some cause (cf.
‘becoming’ occur: philosophers love the Philebus 26e).
learning that makes clear to them ‘the being In the Phaedo Plato makes Socrates inter-
that always is and does not wander around rupt his attempt to prove that the soul is
between becoming and decaying’. At 521–32 immortal by turning to an inquiry into ‘the
we read that study of mathematics draws us cause of generation and destruction’ (Phd.
from becoming to study being (521d). The 96a). Although earlier scientists speculated
study of being leads us to the final item of about the causes of a wide range of natural
study, good itself (532b). phenomena, Plato was the first to consider
The secondary literature disputes whether critically what it meant to speak of a cause
such passages suggest (a) every perceptible of something. According to Plato earlier sci-
change in every respect at all times (Cherniss entists took causes (e.g. of thinking) to be
1957:356 responding to Owen 1953a), or bodily processes involving stuffs like air or
suggest at most that there is (b) at each time fire or blood.
every perceptible change in some respect or Socrates says that he was intrigued by
other (Irwin 1977b:3 note 5). There is also Anaxagoras’ claim that intelligence (nous)
dispute whether Plato believed (a) at some is the cause of everything, but disappointed
time: Irwin (1977b:6) says no. Cherniss when he found that Anaxagoras actually
(1957:349–60) says yes. tried to explain things in terms of material
processes like other earlier scientists. It is as
if one were to say that Socrates’ actions are
due to his mind but then to explain why he
CAUSE (AITIA) was sitting in his prison cell in Athens rather
than escaping to another city as due to the
Fred D. Miller, Jr. position of his bones, sinews, flesh and skin.
Plato’s terms aitia (n.) and aitios or aition This indicates a failure ‘to distinguish the
(adj.) are traditionally translated as ‘cause’, real cause from that without which the cause
although ‘reason’ and ‘explanation’ are also would not be able to act as a cause’ (99b).
used. The correct translation is controversial, What Anaxagoras calls the cause is merely a
as will become clear. necessary condition of what he purports to
The concept of cause helps to distinguish explain. The cause of X should explain why
reliable from unreliable beliefs: although X in fact exists and not some contrary state
true opinions are valuable as long as they of affairs. Ideally it would explain ‘what was
remain, they tend to escape from our souls, the best way for it to be, or to be acted upon,
so that they are not worth much unless tied or to act’ (97c–d).

143

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 143 3/17/2001 9:21:00 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

The best causal explanation would explain theory of causality, for the soul is the special
how the universe is held together by the good bearer of life which cannot admit of death.
and what ought to be. After confessing that In the later dialogues perhaps Plato adum-
he has not found such a cause, he offers a sec- brates the causal explanation of the cosmos
ond best method of explanation based on the envisioned in the Phd. The Phlb. distinguishes
theory of forms, which involves the following four factors – the unlimited, limit, the mix-
claims: There exist forms such as the beauti- ture that comes to be from the foregoing and
ful itself, and particular things are beautiful the cause or productive agent that brings
only because they partake of the beautiful this mixture about (Phlb. 27b–c). Further,
itself. The forms typically have opposites it recognizes intelligence (nous) or soul as
which they cannot admit, for example, tall- the fundamental cause of the universe (Phlb.
ness cannot be short, and shortness cannot 30d; cf. Ti. 46d; and Lg. 10.891e). However,
be tall (102d). Moreover, there are two types the Ti. recognizes two kinds of causes: intel-
of forms – for example, tallness ‘in nature’ ligent and unintelligent (Ti. 46c–e, 68e). The
versus tallness ‘in us’ – which some commen- former is identified with intelligence, person-
tators call transcendent and immanent forms ified as the cosmic demiurge (29a), while the
(102d–3b). For example, the immanent latter is necessity, which is called ‘the stray-
form of shortness is itself short and cannot be ing cause’ (48a). The latter is evidently pos-
tall, and it also compels whatever it enters to tulated to explain the pervasive resistance to
share in shortness. Socrates is short because orderliness. Plato’s search for the first cause
he shares in the immanent form of shortness, of cosmic order, especially in Lg. bk 10, is
while Phaedo is tall because he is occupied a precursor of cosmological arguments for
by the immanent form of tallness. This use- the existence of god by Aristotle and later
ful distinction also explains the paradoxical theorists, though lower levels are dependent
fact that a particular can in a way partake of on higher in the Republic’s divided line (q.v.)
opposite forms: Simmias can have the imma- as well.
nent form of tallness in relation to Socrates Against the theory of the Phd. Aristotle
and the immanent form of shortness in rela- objects that Platonic forms cannot be causes
tion to Phaedo. Finally, in order to support because causes produce their effects intermit-
more sophisticated explanations, the theory tently, although the forms exist perpetually
recognizes a special bearer of a form, which and continuously. Again, health seems to be
is distinct from the form but brings the form produced by a doctor rather than by the form
with it whenever it occupies a particular and of health itself (Gen. & Corr. 2.9.335b17–24).
will not admit the opposite of the form that Aristotle assumes that Plato’s aitia is a rival
it brings. For example, an object becomes to his own theory of four causes: for exam-
hot when it is occupied by fire, the special ple, a particular statue has four causes, a par-
bearer of heat; and if the object is occupied ticular sculptor (efficient cause) imposes a
by snow, the special bearer of cold, the fire particular shape (formal cause) on particular
retreats or ceases to exist. Likewise three bronze (material cause) for a particular pur-
brings oddness with it and excludes evenness. pose (final cause). He complains that Plato
(It is noteworthy that Plato includes a math- recognizes the formal and material causes of
ematical example.) The Phd.’s final proof of things, but overlooks the efficient and final
the immortality of the soul presupposes this causes (Metaphysics 1.6.998a8–10).

144

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 144 3/17/2001 9:21:00 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

Recent commentators disagree over Plato’s the divided line (q.v.) is an image of education
understanding of aitia. Does he have in mind (Republic 514a; q.v. Education), which Plato
what many moderns would understand as a says elsewhere is the only acquisition one
causal explanation of a natural phenomenon, retains after death (Phaedo 108d). This clus-
or does he intend instead a logical or meta- ter of images serves to unpack in detail the
physical explanation of phenomena? The dense series of claims Socrates makes about
causal interpretation is suggested by Socrates’ the ‘greatest study’, which provides the meas-
statement in the Phd. that he is seeking an ure for all other studies, namely, the idea of
‘investigation of the cause of generation and the good (R. 505a–6a). The cluster occurs in
destruction’ (Phd. 96a) and that he is con- the middle of a discussion of the nature of
cerned with problems like those discussed philosophy and towards the end of the long
by the pre-Socratics such as why the earth interruption that occupies the central books
has the shape it does and why it is located of the R. (bks 5–7), and so falls between the
where it is (97d). If Plato is seeking a cause, ‘peak’ of the city as a kingship or aristocracy
what sort is it? Is it a formal cause (see Sedley (445c–d) and its decline into increasingly less
1998) or a final cause (see Taylor 1969)? Or perfect orders. It can be said to represent a
does the Phd. anticipate the sort of compre- paradigm outside of the whole discussion
hensive causal explanation found in the later that stands as the ultimate reference point
dialogues, which arguably accommodates for the city described within that discussion
all four Aristotelian causes (see Hankinson (cf., 472c–3a) just as the idea of the good
1998)? However, the causal interpretation explicated in these images represents the ulti-
has trouble with other examples in the Phd.: mate standard for all thought and deed. The
for example, Socrates is shorter than Simmias argument regarding the good and the soul’s
because he has smallness compared with relationship with it that comes to expression
Simmias’ tallness (Phd. 102b–3a), and three in these passages is, among other things, the
bringing oddness with it and excluding even- basic response to the challenges presented to
ness (104d). These examples suggest that Plato Socrates by Glaucon and Adeimantus at the
is concerned with a logical or metaphysical beginning of the main body of the dialogue.
explanation, such as a conceptual analysis of Socrates insists the allegory must be con-
essences (see Vlastos 1969) or an account of nected with ‘what was said before’ (517a–b),
truth-making conditions (see Sharma 2009). that is the images of the sun and the line. If
These interpretations would lead off into very the sun image introduced the epistemologi-
different directions, but, arguably, Plato’s cal and ontological significance of the good,
account of aitia shares features with both drawing a distinction between the realm of
causal and metaphysical explanation. the sensible, which is mixed with darkness,
and the realm of the intelligible illumined
by the light, the line image subdivides the
realms and articulates their relationships to
CAVE, THE ALLEGORY OF THE one another mathematically. The cave image
draws on the epistemological and ontologi-
D. C. Schindler cal role of the good illustrated in the sun and
The allegory of the cave that Socrates on the notion of levels of reality and stages
presents after the images of the sun (q.v.) and of the apprehension of truth illustrated in

145

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 145 3/17/2001 9:21:00 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

the line, bringing these together in what may sun. This last level unfolds gradually in five
be called a ‘moving image’, that is the mini- steps (shadows, reflections in water, things
drama of education as a liberation from the themselves, the heavens and heavenly bodies
slavery of ignorance. The various parts of at night and the sun). Socrates explains that
the cave image symbolize an order of life education is a ‘turning around of the whole
(ethics and politics) based on the nature of soul’ (518c) – that is, not the introduction
reality and the soul’s apprehension of it (met- of intelligence, but a directing of this already
aphysics and epistemology). Scholars have extant power along with our soul’s spirited
rejected any simple one-to-one correspond- nature and appetites (cf., the ‘parts’ of the
ence between the segments of the line and soul, 436a–b) towards the good. The edu-
the stages of education in the cave, but the cated and uneducated soul prove to be polar
inference that the cave allegory ought there- opposites: the latter measures everything
fore to be read independently of the previous it encounters against its ‘truth’, namely, the
images, and in some cases independently of ‘shadows of artificial things’ (515c) and so
the dialogue as a whole, is unwarranted. experiences confusion in relation to reality;
The sun in the cave image represents the former measures everything by the good,
the idea of the good, which Socrates calls the most complete standard (cf., 504c) and
the ‘cause of all that is right and beautiful’ so finds itself at a loss when it faces, once
(517c), both of the sun and its light in the again, the darkness of the cave.
visible realm and of truth and understanding Because education involves a fundamental
in the intelligible realm. The things outside of reordering of desire (q.v.), the prisoners must
the cave are intelligible objects – presumably be released by someone outside of them-
the forms (q.v.) – and the artefacts inside selves and be forced out of the cave (since
the cave presumably represent visible, that they would be able to liberate themselves
is physical things. While Socrates does not only if their desires were already properly
explain the significance of the shadows cast ordered). This, however, entails an infinite
upon the cave wall, we may interpret them, regress problem that Plato does not explicitly
in light of Socrates’ general discussion of the address. Socrates suggests that the prisoners
problem of education in the R., as the ‘imita- would resist their liberator, and would in
tion’ of reality in the poets’ (and the sophists’) fact kill him if they had the chance (517a – a
speeches, and perhaps also as a reference to reference to Socrates?). When the prisoners
the ‘noble lie’ used to impose political order are first released, they become dazzled by the
on the ignorant (cf., 414b–c, 459c–d). firelight and so lose the ability to make out
The cave image presents three basic con- the shadows. What appears to be a state of
ditions of our nature in its education: first, confusion, however, is in reality an advance
we begin as bound at the bottom, so that the towards truth. The confusion intensifies
shadows and sounds reflected off the back when the prisoners enter out into the light
wall constitute the whole of our experi- of day, that is, the realm of the intelligible.
ence (514a–15c); second, we may be turned However, once their eyes grow accustomed
around while still in the cave so that we may to the light at its source, they in turn come to
see the fire light and the artefacts that cast pity those who are still inside the cave, and
their shadows; third, we may be dragged out would ‘prefer to undergo everything rather
of the cave into the world illuminated by the than live that way’ (516d–e). The reason

146

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 146 3/17/2001 9:21:01 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

for the philosopher’s return to the cave, ‘non-moral’, or irrelevant to assessing a per-
which Socrates insists is necessary (519c–d), son’s character. But in ancient Greek terms
remains controversial; the stated explanation all such features have potentially ethical
is that, in the city, private interest must ulti- implications, since they are viewed as consti-
mately be subordinated to the common good tuting, expressing and/or representing ethos.
(519e–20d). Thus, it is the universal truth of Characteristics that might now be seen as
the idea of the good that requires both an quirks of personality tend to be viewed as
ascent out of the cave and then a descent simultaneously formative and indicative of
back into the cave, in both cases against one’s both social identity and moral character. Yet,
apparent desire. the human ideal remains one of simplicity
and harmony. In literature, philosophy and
the visual arts, idiosyncrasy, whether physi-
cal or psychological, tends to denote not spe-
CHARACTER (TOPIC) cial beauty or appeal but a departure from
some ideal and more homogeneous ethical
Ruby Blondell and/or aesthetic standard.
The English word ‘character’ may denote – There is a close relationship in Greek cul-
among other things – both (moral) charac- ture generally, and Plato in particular, between
ter and a theatrical dramatis persona. In the character in both the above senses and educa-
former sense it approximates to the Greek tion. Almost all ancient Greek writers assume
ethos, which embraces both moral qualities that the representation of persons exerts on
and the social and personal features that help its consumers (actors, audience, readers or
to construct, embody and convey these quali- listeners) an emotional effect that tends to
ties (such as age, status, social relationships, assimilate them to the characters represented
gender, way of life, deportment, physiog- (on this ‘mimêtic pedagogy;’ see Blondell
nomy and manner of speaking). Ethos also 2002:80–112). Traditional educational mod-
covers intellectual traits, that is, the rational els, such as Homer’s heroes, may have certain
and rhetorical skills and attitudes that are positive traits, but in general, their impact is
used to reach and convey moral choices. For presented as overwhelmingly negative. Plato’s
character in the latter sense – the theatrical characters, especially Socrates, often criticize
or literary – Greek normally uses a differ- the educational use of such poetry; in addi-
ent word (prosopon); yet the two concepts tion, Plato as author defuses the threat of
remain intimately linked. Literary charac- traditional character models both by co-opt-
ters are conceived of, and represented, in the ing them for his own purposes and by sup-
first place as embodiments of moral quali- planting them in his own works. In Hippias
ties, while philosophers show a strong con- Minor, for example, he uses Socrates to chal-
cern with character types and their external lenge the educational value of Achilles and
expression both in actual people and in the Odysseus, but also appropriates these heroes
arts, especially theatre. for his own use (Blondell 2002:113–64). The
In English, ‘character’ often refers to moral most important positive character model in
character as detached from physical circum- Plato’s works is Socrates, who is marked,
stances, or as opposed to individual quirks paradoxically, by an unparalleled degree of
of ‘personality’, which are often viewed as physical and intellectual idiosyncrasy.

147

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 147 3/17/2001 9:21:01 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

Plato’s pervasive concern with human plurality and change. The philosopher-rulers
character, its formation and representation, is are defined by their ability to see beyond
central to the Republic, which provides a fully the distracting multiplicity of the phenom-
developed picture of the character required enal world to the homogeneous unity of the
for the philosopher-rulers of Callipolis. This forms (474b–6d). The same vision informs
ideal incorporates a long list of admirable their characters. Like the statue of the per-
qualities, which may be summarised as vig- fectly just man (361d), the undifferentiated
our and gentleness in mind and body. It is model of the philosopher-ruler lacks distract-
to be achieved through three stages of char- ing personal detail, providing an abstract,
acter formation. First, the young guardians impersonal ideal of philosophical perfection.
must have the right natural inclinations and Only their level of progress on a linear scale
capacities. Second, these traits must be fos- differentiates the guardians.
tered from infancy by cultural education, This ideal is developed still further in the
including poetry and the visual arts as well Theaetetus, where ‘likeness to god’ (176b) –
as physical training; at this stage the young an idealized state of epistemic, ethical and
guardians’ characters are to be ‘molded’ by personal self-consistency and stability – is
the right kind of poetry and storytelling, presented by Socrates as the ultimate human
which will use appropriate literary role mod- ideal. Ironically, however, this ideal remains
els to ‘dye’ their souls indelibly with right unattainable as long as we are, in fact,
opinion (429c–30b). Finally the guardians embodied human beings. Plato seems well
are subjected to many years of higher educa- aware of this. The ideal philosopher in the
tion (519c), largely mathematical in nature; Theaetetus is paired with his anti-ideal, the
this culminates in dialectic, which eventually orator, who is fully engaged in the messy
allows the truly superior soul to reach the business of Athenian social and political life.
vision of the forms. We are left to infer that the best any real
The resulting ideal character is uniform human being can do is to negotiate between
and homogenous since, as Socrates puts it, these two poles, striving for ‘likeness to god’
‘there is one form of virtue, but the forms while acknowledging her inescapable embed-
of vice are unlimited’ (445c). This means not dedness in the material and social world that
only that there are many more ways of being makes such a goal ultimately unattainable.
bad than being good, but also that within The ever-paradoxical Socrates models this
each individual complexity and variation of mediating role for us.
character are to be frowned upon in contrast
to the simple and homogeneous. The belief
that the virtuous ethos is simple the complex
inferior (604e) is one important reason for CITY (POLIS)
Socrates’ famous disapproval of imitation
(q.v.), since sympathetic identification with a Richard Stalley
range of characters is expected to fragment In his political and moral philosophy, Plato
the guardians’ own ethos. This quest for a sin- takes it for granted that he is dealing with
gle perfect character-type is a central aspect life in the Greek polis (plural poleis), a
of the dialogue’s pervasive concern with sta- small independent city state. His two long-
bility, homogeneity and unity, and hostility to est works, the Republic and the Laws, both

148

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 148 3/17/2001 9:21:01 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

describe imaginary cities. While they are in practical city of the Lg. the confusion of roles
many respects different from each other, they is avoided by different means. Citizens will
arguably embody very similar conceptions be forbidden to engage in trade and manu-
of the nature and purpose of the polis. The facture – those tasks will be left to resident
underlying principles are brought out most aliens (Lg. 846d1–7b6, 918a6–20a4). All
clearly in the R., which describes an ideal citizens will serve in the army and take some
that is unlikely ever to exist. The Lg. shows part in government but the latter is still con-
how they might be embodied in a more prac- ceived as a work of reason. The city is there-
tical form. fore controlled by a strict code of law (q.v.)
The city comes into being because indi- established by a wise legislator and the most
viduals in isolation cannot provide all they important positions are assigned to the oldest
need for survival (R. 369b7–73d). But its and wisest citizens.
main function is certainly not to accumu- Plato believes that the good of the city
late wealth. The ideal location for a city is requires that its citizens possess the virtues of
one that will provide all the necessities of wisdom, courage, temperance and justice. A
human life without producing a surplus central concern of the city is therefore to pro-
to permit trade and luxurious living (Lg. vide an education (q.v.), which will develop
704a1–5c7). There are, in fact, three main the right kind of character in its citizens. In
kinds of functions which must be fulfilled the R. there is a long account of the train-
effectively if a city is to survive and prosper. ing in poetry, music and gymnastics that will
The first is to provide for the production inculcate the virtues and a similar education
of food and manufactured articles and for is prescribed in the Lg.
the buying and selling of these. The second Plato also assumes that whatever makes
is to wage war and the third is to govern for the unity of the city is good, while any-
itself wisely. A distinctively Platonic idea is thing that pulls it apart is bad (see Schofield
that each of these roles should be performed 2006:212–33). Unity requires shared feel-
exclusively by people with the appropriate ings and friendship (q.v.) among the citi-
training and aptitudes and that confusing zens. One major obstacle is the pursuit of
them can undermine and even destroy the wealth. In existing cities rulers use their
city (R. 412b9–15d3). power to pursue their own economic inter-
To avoid this confusion of roles, the ideal ests and to exploit their fellow citizens (R.
city of the R. would be based on a division 416d–17b). Differences in wealth also cre-
of the citizens into three classes: (a) those ate conflict between the rich and the poor
involved in farming, manufacture and trade; (R. 421d–3b). To avoid these outcomes sol-
(b) the soldiers or guardians (phulakes); and diers and rulers in the ideal city of the R.
(c) the rulers (R. 373d–4e). Those destined to would have no homes or property of their
be soldiers would be selected in early child- own but would live together like soldiers in
hood and undergo a long training. The rulers a camp. In the Lg., a different, and presum-
would be chosen from the best and wisest ably more practical, solution is suggested.
of the guardians to undergo a philosophical Each citizen family will have its own farm,
training that would ultimately enable them which will be inalienable. The farms will be
to achieve a rational understanding of the of equal size and the amount of wealth that
good and the just (R. 502c–41b). In the more can be accumulated in addition to the farm

149

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 149 3/17/2001 9:21:01 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

will be limited (Lg. 737b5–d8, 739e7–41a5, CONVENTION (see Law)


744d2–5b2). The disruptive effect of differ-
ences in wealth will thus be kept to a mini-
mum (see Morrow 1960:95–152; Stalley COSMOS (KOSMOS)
1983:97–111).
Another threat to the unity of the city is Gretchen Reydams-Schils
that citizens may feel loyalty to their family The Timaeus is the principal dialogue for
rather than to the city as a whole. In the ideal studying Plato’s view of the cosmos, though
city of the R., this danger would be avoided relevant comments are also found in several
by the abolition of the family. Mating among other dialogues.
the guardians would be arranged by the rul- The cosmology of the Ti. (26c) draws on
ers and the children resulting from this would the fundamental distinction between ‘being’,
be brought up in common. No one would be or intelligible reality, grasped by understand-
able to identify their biological parents or off- ing and the object of truth, that is, unchang-
spring (R. 457b7–66d7). This would ensure ing versus ‘becoming’, or sensible reality,
that citizens share feelings of pleasure and grasped by sense-perception and the object
pain. There is no such proposal for the city of opinion that is always in flux (Brisson
of the Lg. Indeed, its citizens would be legally 1994; Johansen 2004; Zeyl 2000). That
required to marry (Lg. 772c5–4d2). The point which ‘comes to be’ presupposes a cause of
seems to be that, in practise, the unity of the its coming to be. In the case of the universe –
city will be preserved by the careful regulation which falls under the heading of becoming
of the family and by institutions such as com- because it is visible, tangible and corporeal –
mon meals and shared religious rites. the cause is a good god, or divine artisan and
In the R. Plato uses the tripartite structure demiurge who knows no envy, and makes the
of his ideal city to elucidate the structure world as good as possible, introducing order
of the human soul. This, together with the in a state of disorder (Ti. 30a), by using being
emphasis on the unity of the city and aboli- as his model, not becoming. The demiurge’s
tion of property and families for the guard- model for the universe is also referred to as
ians, has led some commentators to suppose the ‘living thing’ that contains all different
that Plato is concerned for the good of the kinds of intelligible living things. Given that
city as opposed to that of its citizens. The things that have intelligence are superior to
latter are seen merely as parts of a larger those that do not, the world soul, which gives
whole, having no independent value. Other life to the entire universe, is endowed with a
commentators have argued that, when Plato mind.
speaks of the good of the city, he really has Timaeus also stipulates two types of
in mind the happiness of all the citizens (see accounts that have the same characteristics
Taylor 1986). Plato would probably see as their respective objects. The account of
a false antithesis here. On his conception being shares as much as possible in being’s
a worthwhile life requires membership of a stability and truth-value. The account of
city. The good of the individual consists in becoming as an image, or likeness, of being,
possessing the very virtues that are needed can at best be only ‘likely’ and convincing.
for the survival of the city and cannot be Plato’s point here turns on the verbal pun in
acquired outside it. the connection between ‘likeness’/eikôn and

150

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 150 3/17/2001 9:21:02 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

‘likely’/eikôs. This is a first epistemological The ending of the Ti. has its own version
restriction applying to any account of the of the ‘becoming like god’ theme (90a–d;
universe: given what the universe is, it can- Sedley 1999). Whenever a human soul enters
not be an object of true knowledge. A second a human body, the rational component of its
epistemological restriction follows from the soul, modelled after and made of the same
limitations of human nature in its attempt to ingredients as the world soul, becomes dis-
speak of things divine and the origin of the rupted (42e–4c). This order, however, can
universe. be restored by realigning one’s soul with the
Mathematics plays a key role in the struc- world soul, both through thinking and the
ture of the universe, as a vehicle for the trans- contemplation of the revolutions of heav-
fer of order from being to becoming. Both enly bodies that follow the revolutions of the
the world body (Ti. 31b–2c) and the world world soul. Hence, the order of the cosmos
soul (35b–6d) are governed by proportional becomes directly relevant for an ordered and
ratios. The traces of the elements in the recep- happy human life.
tacle have different regular solids, made out The speech which the demiurge addresses
of triangles, assigned to them. These trian- to the younger gods (who will create the
gles and solids also account for the elements’ human body and the irrational parts of
transformations into each other and forma- the human soul), and the rules he gives the
tions into things. The fixed stars belong to rational human souls (41a–2e) have sev-
the circle of the same in the structure of the eral themes in common with the afterlife
world soul, and the planets to the circle of and soul myths of the Republic (the Myth
the other. of Er, 614b–end), the Phaedo (107c–15a),
Timaeus’ account has three main parts: the Gorgias (523a–7a) and the Phaedrus
(a) the works of intellect (29d–47e); (b) the (246a–57b). These accounts display a judge-
works of necessity (47e–69a); and (c) the ment of the soul’s first or previous life, with
combined works of intellect and necessity rewards and punishments, and reflections on
(69a–92c). The second part, on necessity the consequences of earlier choices for sub-
or the wandering cause, introduces a third sequent lives, in the process of reincarnation.
principle, in addition to being and becom- They also present a view of the cosmos, least
ing, namely the receptacle. Plato’s account of developed in the Grg. myth, that reflects this
this ‘third kind’ reveals fundamental tensions moral order, with clear distinctions between a
(Algra 1995; Sayre 2002). A first tension higher realm more or less close to intelligible
exists between the receptacle as some kind reality and lower realms for souls weighed
of space or medium or as a constituent com- down by corporeal and sensible reality.
ponent of sensible things. The most likely The myth of the origin and governance
hypothesis is that the receptacle constitutes of the world in the Politicus, as told by the
the condition for things in the phenomenal Stranger (Plt. 268d–74e), posits an ongoing
world appearing as corporeal and sensible. alternation between two phases of the uni-
A second tension occurs between the two verse: one governed by the supreme god, who
accounts of the receptacle as being, on the delegates the supervision of parts of the uni-
one hand, completely neutral, and as being verse to other gods and demons, and another
endowed with traces of the elements in dis- in which the world is left to itself. The gov-
orderly motion, on the other. ernance of god represents a blissful state,

151

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 151 3/17/2001 9:21:02 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

whereas the other phase leads to a gradual to great variation. Plato made a virtue of this
decline until the god eventually takes matters fluidity in two related ways. From his literary
in hand again. Corporeal entities such as the and philosophical predecessors he selected
world cannot remain in an immutable state, attributes of divinity that discounted or dis-
but inherently contain a factor of disorder. carded the anthropomorphic and often fear-
Based on the principle that self-motion pre- some features represented in mythology and
supposes soul, bk 10 of the Laws (896c–9d) civic cult. Second, and more significantly, he
posits the existence of a disorderly soul as emphasized the idea that divinity is always
a counterpart to the rational and beneficial providential and never responsible for any
world soul that governs the heavens and the harm to human beings or to the universe. In
universe a whole. The exposition emphasizes advancing this thesis, Plato chiefly employs
that the universe is ordered and governed by the singular or plural of the term theos,
providence, rather than chance. The Philebus which is the standard Greek word to apply
(23c–31b) assumes as the basic components to Zeus and other leading gods. But in his
of reality limit, the unlimited, a mixture of late work, Laws, he often combines theos or
these two, and a divine maker called Zeus theoi (plural) with the term daimôn (singu-
as cause; it restates key claims about the lar or plural) and sometimes adjoins to these
order of the universe, the world body and terms the word heros, producing the provi-
the rational nature of the world soul (Kahn dential triad ‘god(s), divine spirit (s), and
2010). Finally, the Epinomis, wrongly attrib- hero(es)’. The point of this complex expres-
uted to Plato and probably by Philip of sion was to be as comprehensive as possible
Opus, assigns all levels within the universe in reference to everything in Plato’s culture
their own kind of demons, according to a that could be deemed divine, ranging from
principle of plenitude. the most exalted divinities to those former
men worshipped after their deaths as deified
heroes. By this token a daimôn was a divine
CROSS EXAMINATION (see Elenchus) being of lesser status than a theos.
Although Plato generally marks that dif-
ference, he also employs ‘god or daimôn’
DAIMÔN or ‘god and daemon’ as a hendiadys (e.g.
Cratylus 438c6; Lg. 730a, 906a). Such flu-
A. A. Long idity in the use of these terms goes back to
Daimôn is one of the terms employed to the earliest Greek literature. Homer some-
designate supernatural beings by Plato, and times calls Olympian gods and goddesses
is used in a number of different, but related, individually or collectively daimons, but he
ways in the dialogues. chiefly uses daimôn to refer to divine power
The polytheistic religious beliefs of ancient impersonally – as we might say ‘the divine’ or
Greece were remarkably fluid (q.v. Religion). ‘divinity’. In an important extension of this
They conformed to subsequent Western usage, daimôn stands for the fate or lot allo-
notions in regarding divinity as exponen- cated to mortals, which they are powerless
tially more powerful than every human to withstand. ‘Oh daimôn’, cries Oedipus in
capacity or possibility, but beyond that, how Sophocles’ tragedy, when he learns that he has
one conceived of the divine was susceptible fulfilled his terrible fate; and the Persian King

152

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 152 3/17/2001 9:21:02 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

Xerxes uses the same expression in Aeschylus’ is a seminal text for the ways Plato uses the
Persians at the point of his total defeat by the term daimôn to signify a guardian spirit,
Greeks. Such pessimism was due to the belief, whether in life and/or after death.
widely reflected in early Greek literature, that He does this most elaborately in the escha-
the Greek gods, far from being providential, tological myths (q.v. Myth) that conclude the
were often ill-disposed to human beings. Phaedo and Republic. Common to both con-
Plato rarely uses daimôn in this impersonal texts is the allotment to souls of a daimôn
or negative way. His daimons are most typi- responsible for watching over persons during
cally guardian spirits attached to particular their embodied life. In the Phd. (107d–8a),
persons. As such, they may be compared the daimôn ‘allotted to each person’ conducts
with the function that Plato and Xenophon the post mortem souls to the underworld’s
applied to the divine sign or divine voice that place of judgement, but in the R. (617e,
Socrates experienced from time to time, and 620d) the story is more complex. There the
which these authors (and very likely Socrates narrative starts from souls that are awaiting
himself) called daimonion. However, that rebirth. After drawing lots, to determine who
was a special usage of this term, signifying goes first, the souls are required to choose
Socrates’ peculiar claim to be the object of an their next lives from a vast selection of lives
individual providential concern. (animal as well as human), and then, having
Hesiod, who was more or less contempo- made that choice, make the further choice of
rary with Homer, foreshadowed Plato’s prov- a daimôn ‘to watch over their life and fulfil
idential conception of daimons in his account the choices made’.
of the post mortem destiny of the blissful Guardian spirit is Plato’s exact expres-
people from the Golden Age: ‘Because of the sion, but in using it he does not anticipate the
plans of mighty Zeus they are good daimons, modern, entirely protective or kindly sense
earth-dwelling \ guardians of mortal men, of a guardian angel. What Plato’s daimons
who keep watch over court judgements and \ ‘guard’ or secure is the necessity that embod-
wrongful acts, clad in mist, roaming all over ied souls conform to the lives they have cho-
the earth, and givers of wealth’ (Works and sen. When the mythological trappings are
Days 122–6). Plato drew directly on this pas- removed, his guardian spirits are tantamount
sage in the Cra. (398b) where he has Socrates to personifications of each person’s inevita-
say: ble destiny as determined by their prenatal
choices. A hundred years earlier Heraclitus
Hesiod and the other poets are right, had expressed this idea in his lapidary state-
who say that, when a good man dies, he ment: ‘Character is a human being’s daimôn’.
has a great dispensation and honor, and As to the mythology, Plato was influenced by
becomes a daimôn, which is a name given
eschatological ideas associated with Orphic
to him because it accords with wisdom.
mystery cults, which are diffused in earlier lit-
Accordingly, I myself propose that every
good man is daimonios, whether dead or erature and thought, especially Empedocles,
alive, and rightly called a daimôn. Pindar and Euripides.
Does Plato’s conception of a guardian spirit
fit the notion that divinity is always provi-
In spite of its spoof etymology (deriving dential and never harmful to human beings?
daimôn from daëmon, meaning ‘wise’) this It is quite consistent with that idea, when

153

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 153 3/17/2001 9:21:02 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

qualified by the following Platonic assump- contexts remain to be discussed. According


tions – first, that human beings, not divinity, to Diotima in the Symposium (202d), Eros
are entirely responsible for the choices they (q.v. Love) is not a god (theos) because,
make and the outcomes of these, and sec- rather than having good and beautiful
ond, that divinity is always just. Accordingly, things, he is in need and desirous of them.
human beings are justly rewarded in the Is he then a mortal? The answer is nega-
afterlife for good conduct and punished for tive because Eros, being ‘in between mor-
the reverse. tal and immortal’, is a great daimôn, ‘for
Plato interprets the concept of a guard- everything daimonion’ has this intermedi-
ian daimôn most creatively in the context of ate status. Categorical though this sounds,
the Timaeus (90a–d) where he expounds the it should not be taken to be Plato’s theo-
anatomy of the soul: logical axiom. As already stated, he likes to
use phrases such as ‘theos and/or daimôn’.
As regards the most authoritative form But, though he generally treats daimons as
of soul present in us, we should think of lesser beings than that which he signifies
it thus: that God has given it to each per- by theos, his concept of the divine is suf-
son as a daimôn, that thing which we say
ficiently capacious to include daimons as
dwells at the top of our body and elevates
well as more exalted deities. This finding
us from earth to our celestial kinship.
is borne out by the passage in the Apology
(26c–8a) in which Socrates refutes his
Here Plato uses daimôn to refer to what he accuser Meletus’ charge that he does not
elsewhere calls the ‘rational’ part of the tri- believe in gods at all. Socrates’ argument,
partite soul. As the passage continues, Plato in summary, runs thus: Belief in divine mat-
describes the truly philosophical person as ters (daimonia pragmata) entails belief in
someone who, by always keeping his cohab- daimons. Socrates, by Meletus’ admission
iting daimôn well-tended, must be supremely (referring to the indictment of his intro-
prosperous (eudaimôn). Eudaimonia (often ducing ‘novel daimonia’), believes in divine
translated by ‘happiness’) is the standard word matters. Therefore, Socrates believes in dai-
for prosperity. In everyday Greek it connoted mons. Daimons are either gods or children
material well-being or good fortune, and was of gods, from which it follows that Socrates
thus taken to be subject to the arbitrary dis- believes in gods.
pensation of gods rather than under a person’s Did Socrates take his divine sign to be the
control. Plato, by contrast, makes eudaimo- voice of a daimôn? No firm answer to this
nia (q.v. Happiness) depend primarily on the question can be given, but the word daimo-
virtues of a rationally governed character. In nion (literally ‘divine thing’) is just as appro-
the Ti. passage he plays on the etymology of priate to a visitation from a fully fledged
eudaimonia (literally, ‘a god-favoured condi- god, in which case its most likely source for
tion’) by associating it with both the tradi- Socrates would be the god Apollo whose ora-
tional idea of a guardian deity and his entirely cle initiated his interpretation of his mission
nontraditional conception of reason as a to the citizens of Athens.
human being’s normative guardian. For further information on daimôn, see
Plato’s principal uses of daimôn have Burkert (1985), Greene (1944), Long (2004),
now been covered. Two further well known McPherran (1996) and Vernant (1980).

154

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 154 3/17/2001 9:21:03 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

DEATH is taken up in Plato’s fuller examination of


death in Phd.
E. E. Pender The crux of the Phaedo’s account of death
Plato understands that the fear of death is that it is ‘nothing other than the separa-
(thanatos) afflicts humankind in waking tion (apallagê) of soul from body’ (Phd.
hours and in the terrors of dreams (Republic 64c4–5). The state of being dead is therefore
330e; Laws 904d). He observes the abhor- where soul and body have come to be apart
rence of the underworld familiar in Greek (cf. Gorgias 524b). Socrates explains (Phd.
culture from Homeric poetry onwards 64a–7d) that since the body causes desire for
(R. 386c–387a) and captured in Achilles’ physical pleasure and hinders the gaining of
famous lament at the loss of life (Odyssey wisdom, the philosopher gladly welcomes
11:489). He also offers sensitive and mov- this ‘release’ (lusis) of his soul. Socrates
ing reflections on grief, where the advice then presents four individual arguments on
to those mourning the ‘calamity’ of death the immortality of soul, culminating in the
is to bear such sorrows as lightly as pos- conclusion that due to its essential nature
sible (Menexenus 247c–d; R. 603e–4d). as life force, the soul cannot admit death
Both Aspasia and Socrates refer to the need and so cannot die (Phd. 102a–7b). Socrates’
for ‘healing’ (Mx. 247d2; R. 604d1–2), but various arguments recall earlier views on
where Aspasia counsels gentle consola- the afterlife, including the poetic concep-
tion through social practise, Socrates’ pre- tion of Hades and the ‘ancient doctrine’ of
scription for grief is reasoning and proper reincarnation held by the mystery religions
training of the mind. While both of these and the followers of Pythagoras (q.v., Phd.).
responses to death speak in familiar cultural But Plato radically transforms earlier ideas
terms, Socrates’ articulation adumbrates in line with his own teleology and account
the greater achievement of the philosopher of abstract reality.
explored elsewhere: the realization that Plato’s thought on death is founded upon
death is to be welcomed. his arguments for immortality and his com-
Plato’s redefinition of death is accom- mitment to the forms as the basis of exist-
plished over various dialogues but key texts ence, knowledge and goodness. For while
are Apology, Phaedo and Timaeus. In Ap. all souls will necessarily exist after death,
Socrates’ judgement is that death is one of the incarnate and discarnate periods of their
two things: either it is ‘like being nothing’, eternal lives are revealed as determined by
with no perception of anything, or it is a their level of knowledge of the forms and
sort of migration (metoikêsis) of the soul their consequent virtue. When soul is fully
(Ap. 40c6–10). The former state, likened to rational it will be as separate as possible from
a dreamless sleep, would be a ‘marvellous the corrupting influence of the physical and
benefit’. And the latter experience, likened will achieve its true nature as an immaterial
to travelling abroad to a place of good com- entity. During human life degrees of separa-
pany, would also be a good thing. Indeed, if tion can be attained through contemplation
a person arriving in the other world is to find of abstracts (Pakaluk 2003) but full and
true judges and more blessed men, ‘as peo- permanent withdrawal requires death as the
ple say’, then Socrates is willing ‘to die many removal of the last obstacle to uninterrupted
times’ (Ap. 40c–1c). The idea of migration contact with the forms. This ability of soul in

155

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 155 3/17/2001 9:21:03 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

human life to withdraw into itself gives rise Phd.), nevertheless, they consistently support
to Plato’s striking claim that the life of phi- Plato’s insistence that the consequences of our
losophy is the practise of death (Phd. 64a). human behaviour are not to be escaped along
The Ti. shares with Phd. the view that with the body (e.g. Phd. 107c5; Lg. 959b).
death can allow the soul to return to its pri- For, each myth depicts how the event of
mary state, separated from physical matter, death initiates different experiences depend-
and provides a closer account of the proc- ing on the soul’s condition. The souls of phi-
ess of death itself. While the language of lib- losophers, who have spent their human lives
eration is dominant in Phd. (e.g. 67d, 82e), contemplating the forms, will be rewarded
there is also a more neutral presentation of by transport out of the physical realm alto-
soul as an object bound in the body (e.g. 81e, gether, to an eternity in blessed, divine regions
92a1), a dual perspective continued in Ti. where they will enjoy even greater access
The gods create the human being by bind- to truth (e.g. Phd. 114c; Phdr. 247b–e; Lg.
ing together the parts of the body (Ti. 43a), 904e; see also Ti. 42b). Less virtuous souls
and then binding the soul within it (69e, 70e, who are nevertheless ‘curable’, the majority
73c). Conversely, natural death is identi- (Phd. 90a), will pass through a series of bod-
fied (81d, 89b) as the breaking apart of the ies, experiencing not one but multiple deaths.
bonds of the body which in turn loosen the The death events of these souls cause the
bonds of the soul. The theme of liberation is afterlife periods during which they pay the
recalled as the unloosened soul is said to ‘fly penalty for misdeeds, periods which will be
away with pleasure’ (81e). On the inverted followed by new incarnations as opportuni-
perspective of the philosopher, death is to be ties for improvement. Therefore, while physi-
welcomed as the freeing of soul – the source cal death is the same for philosophical and
of the person’s identity. In contrast, the body other souls, their respective states of being
is to be disposed of as a mere ‘bulk of flesh’ ‘dead’ are very different. Plato’s accounts of
(Lg. 959a–c; Phd. 115d–16a) and funer- death necessarily stretch the normal life/death
als are to be conducted with modesty and polarity, a point particularly borne out in the
restraint (Lg. 959d–60a). case of evil people.
Plato’s account of death is extended In his famous image of the cave (q.v.),
through his various eschatological myths – Plato suggests, in a further striking inversion,
Phd., Grg., R., Phaedrus and Lg. bk 10 (see that the unenlightened life is itself a state
Stalley 2009:188–94) – which depict the of ‘death’ (Laird 2003; O’Connor 2007).
afterlife rewards and punishment of souls Incurably corrupt people in their Hades-on-
and support the convictions that the gods are earth will then find their souls, upon their
good and the universe just. Plato uses estab- actual death event, separating from their
lished terms and story patterns in his after- bodies and departing to an afterlife of pun-
life myths (Edmonds 2004) but each is subtly ishment, imaged in the myths as in Tartarus,
crafted to fit its specific dialogic context. the place of retribution (Phd. 113e; Grg.
Although the myths do not form a compos- 523b; R. 616a). These evil souls, beyond all
ite whole and individually continue to pose hope of reform, have experienced their final
significant hermeneutical challenges (Ferrari death in bodily form and will gain no fur-
2009; Halliwell 2007; Kingsley 1995 on ther incarnation. Tartarus is then to be seen

156

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 156 3/17/2001 9:21:03 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

as an end state: the souls here remain alive happiness, an indefinite desire for whatever is
but their death experience is more like a ces- the best means becomes the executive desire
sation of life, the ‘nothing’ envisaged at Phd. for the particular action which is judged
91b2. Thus, in their lack of any fulfilling to be the best option available. Executive
life, evil people suffer a more intensive set of desires so generated all have a means-ends
‘deaths’. Moreover, if their incurable vice is structure, aiming at a particular action that
recognized during their civic lives, their woes has the agent’s happiness as its ultimate end
may be compounded by the death penalty (Gorgias 467; Lysis 217). Since these execu-
(Lg. 735e, 957e). For execution will hasten tive desires are shaped jointly by the agent’s
their physical dissolution and the transition general desire for the good and the agent’s
of their soul to Tartarus. However, while it is judgment concerning which action in the
permissible for the journey to Tartarus to be given circumstances will maximize happi-
expedited by human judges, Plato is careful ness, they are all rational desires for the good
to point out that decisions on the timing of (Penner 2005). And given that every execu-
other people’s departures must be left to the tive desire is fashioned in this manner, it will
gods. Thus suicide – even for a philosopher – follow that all desire is for the good (Meno
is forbidden (Phd. 62a–c). 77b–c). Moreover, since it is the real objec-
tive good and not the apparent good which
we desire (78a), it will further follow that we
never desire bad things. Due to misjudgement
DESIRE (APPETITE) (EPITHUMIA) as to what is the best option in the given situ-
ation, the desire generated from this intel-
Antonio Chu lectual error may bring about an action that
There are two theories of how desires bring is in fact bad. This action, however, is not
about intended actions in Plato: one the intel- the action the agent really wants to do. This
lectualism (q.v.) of the Socratic dialogues, the explains why tyrants, despite their enormous
other a theory that makes room for irrational political power, only manage to do what
desires bringing about actions in the Republic seems best rather than what they want (Grg.
and other dialogues. 467a–b). In virtue of their political power,
The intellectualist account takes it as a tyrants undoubtedly can bring about what-
psychological fact that all humans desire ever action that seems best. Unfortunately,
the good (i.e. happiness) as our ultimate end by downplaying the relevance of the science
(Euthydemus 281c–e; Symposium 204d–5a). of the good in determining what is the best
This common desire of ours is egoistic: it option in a given circumstance, there is little
is our own happiness that we each seek to hope that they will ever do what they want,
realize in life. In a given situation, this fun- that is, do what will in fact maximize their
damental desire for the good will naturally true happiness (Penner 1991).
give rise to the general desire for whatever Given the egoistic nature of our desires, it
is the best means to the agent’s happiness in is no surprise that no one errs willingly (in
the given circumstances. Through the agent’s securing their own happiness) (Protagoras
judgement as to what specific action in the 357–8). This also rules out any straight-
given circumstances is the best means to forward akrasia (q.v.): acting intentionally

157

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 157 3/17/2001 9:21:04 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

contrary to what one judges to be the best of reason’s estimation of the good that will
option. It is impossible to form an executive result from their realization. In situations
desire for an action that the agent does not where an irrational desire is in conflict with
at the time judge to be the best. Insofar as the an opposing rational desire (e.g. the appe-
agent has an executive desire for the prob- titive desire to drink simpliciter opposed
lematic action, it will indicate a momentary by the rational desire not to drink given the
lapse in judgement or a desire that results belief that not drinking is best for the entire
from a temporary change of mind as to what soul), a clear-eyed akrasia will occur when-
is best (Prt. 356d–e; Men. 97–8). Failure ever the irrational desire is strong enough to
to maximize one’s happiness in one’s action overwhelm the rational desire. Consequently,
is due strictly to ignorance of what is best. intellectual training alone will not suffice to
Hence, an unexamined life is not worth liv- direct most individuals towards good actions.
ing (Apology 38a). For unless we regularly Nonrational trainings will be required
examine and reexamine the web of beliefs to tame irrational desires and bring their
we utilize in determining what is the best strength in line with the good expected from
option in a given situation, it is unlikely that their realization. See, for instance, the edu-
our rational desires will result in actions that cation programme in physical training and
actually maximize our happiness. It is there- music outlined in R. bks 2–3 where habitua-
fore important to engage regularly in the type tion replaces intellectual conversation as the
of intellectual conversation made famous by means for shaping our desires (at least as far
the Socrates of the Socratic dialogues. as our irrational desires are concerned).
The intellectualist account of desire is In the late dialogues, Plato’s sympathy is
both a form of psychological egoism and usually with the theory of desire developed
a form of intellectualism. It is the former in the R. (although Laws is an exception).
because it explains every intended action in Whether this is indeed a superior account of
terms of the agent’s fundamental desire for human desire will depend in part on whether
personal happiness. It is the latter because it it provides a plausible and coherent account
maintains that bad actions are not the result of our psychology of action. That this is so
of bad motives or the agent’s desire for bad has been challenged (see Penner 1990). And
things but the result of intellectual errors and given the richness of Plato’s language, there
ignorance of what is good. are alternative interpretations of his views
The theory of desire developed in the R. on desire (see Anagnostopoulos 2006; Annas
proceeds on the assumption that, in addi- 1981; Bobonich 2002; Cooper 1984; Irwin
tion to rational desires which reside in the 1995; Price 1995). These alternative inter-
rational part of the soul (q.v.), there are irra- pretations generally see Plato’s postulation of
tional desires (residing in the appetitive part irrational desire as providing (a) a more ade-
and the spirited part of the soul). In fact, it quate account of the complexity of human
is this assumption which enables Plato to psyche and (b) a more plausible psychology
divide the soul into parts without commit- of action. In addition, they generally take his
ting himself to there being indefinitely many argument for irrational desire in R. bk 2 to
parts (Penner 1971). Since irrational desires be compatible with the attribution of some
are blind to all considerations concerning limited form of means-ends reasoning to the
the good, their strength varies independently appetitive part of the soul.

158

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 158 3/17/2001 9:21:04 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

DIALECTIC (DIALEKTIKÊ) called early, as well as the middle or later dia-


logues (Robinson 1953). It is common now
Dirk Baltzly to call the method putatively employed by
As a method for discovering important Socrates in the early dialogues the elenchus
philosophical truths, Plato’s dialectic has a (q.v.). Perhaps the most influential character-
degree of fame that is inversely proportional ization of Socrates’ method has been Vlastos
to our evidence for what it actually amounts (1983) (see, however, Scott 2002). It has also
to. Heidegger confidently pronounced it a become customary to distinguish the ‘method
‘philosophical embarrassment’ in a tone that of hypothesis’ that is described or illustrated
suggests that he thought he knew just what in Men. 86e–7b and Phaedo 99e–100b
dialectic was. I think he was overconfident. (Benson 2003; Van Eck 1994). Currently,
Dialectic is hard to pin down. when scholars talk about Platonic dialec-
The noun ‘dialectic’ (dialektikê) is formed tic it is typically the philosophical method
from an adjective (dialektikos) whose described by Socrates in Republic 531d–9e
broader sense is ‘conversational’. The associ- that they have in mind. The relation of dia-
ated verb can mean ‘to converse’, as well as lectic as it is described in the R. to the method
‘to sort things’ – an etymological connection of division illustrated in dialogues such as the
noted in Xenophon’s account of Socrates Sophist and Statesman is unclear. Plato cer-
(Mem. IV.5.12). The term seemingly acquired tainly uses the term ‘dialectic’ in these con-
an association with philosophy early on. A texts (Sph. 253d–e; Plt. 285c–6b), yet it is not
fragment from Aristotle credits its discovery easy to see how the divisions illustrated in
to Zeno of Elea (f. 65). Yet we should be cau- these dialogues’ search for an account of the
tious in assuming that this means that there sophist or the statesman conform to what we
is a single philosophical method – dialectic – are told about dialectic in the R.
found in the works of both Zeno and Plato. The nature of the dialectician’s inquiry
Indeed, we should be cautious in assuming in the R. is contrasted with the manner in
that when Plato himself writes about dia- which mathematicians pursue the truth in
lectic, he always has in mind one and the the divided line (q.v.) at R. 511a–c. Not only
same thing. The give and take of argument are the methods different, but so too are the
was, and remains, characteristic of philoso- mental conditions that result from following
phy and that give and take can resemble a them. Let us examine the latter first.
conversation, even when written and there Exercise of the methods characteristic of
is but a single author who takes both parts mathematics results in a cognitive state called
(as in Aquinas’ Summa Theologica). So it is dianoia, while the practise of dialectic yields
unsurprising that the method that is peculiar a superior cognitive condition called noêsis.
to philosophy should be called dialectical or Translations of these terms vary across differ-
conversational. But this uniformity of termi- ent authors, for the contrast drawn between
nology may hide a diversity of opinion about them answers to no convenient distinction
what conversational activities are best suited in English. In the subsequent Platonist tra-
to reveal philosophical truth. dition (q.v. Neoplatonism), however, dian-
At one time scholars used the term ‘dialec- oia is associated with discursive reasoning
tic’ to describe the method of philosophizing which is secondary to noêsis. The latter is a
that one finds in all Plato’s dialogues – those kind of direct, intellectual insight that results

159

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 159 3/17/2001 9:21:04 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

from the exercise of the faculty of intellect that dialectic could turn the unquestioned
(nous). In keeping with the conversational hypotheses of mathematics into knowl-
sense of dialektikos, Socrates insists that the edge (533b6–c5). Consider also that in the
person who masters dialectic is able to give Parmenides, Parmenides appears to deduce
an account (logos) of the essence (ousia) of the existence of numbers and the kinds into
each thing, and especially of the good (R. which they fall from some abstract consid-
534b–c). erations about what follows if we take up the
The method of dialectic is contrasted with hypothesis ‘if one is’ (Prm. 143b–4a). One
that of mathematics on two grounds. First, suggestion is that an unhypothetical starting
mathematical reasoning allegedly makes point is a proposition that is established by
improper use of hypotheses. While dialec- showing that its denial is self-refuting in a
tic treats hypotheses as hypotheses, using certain sense (Baltzly 1996, 1999;. criticized
them as steps to ascend to an unhypotheti- in Bailey 2006).
cal starting point or first principle (archê), Roughly, the first strategy that identifies
mathematics proceeds from hypotheses to a dialectic’s unhypothetical first principle with
conclusion (510b4–9, 511b3–c2). Moreover, the good is ontological and equates the unhy-
we are told that dialectic ultimately ‘does pothetical aspect of the archê in dialectic
away with’ these hypotheses (533c8). Second, with the ontological supremacy of the form
mathematical reasoning involves the use of the good (R. 509b6–10). The second strat-
of images and things that are visible, while egy is epistemological and treats the unhypo-
dialectic does not (510d5–11a1, 511b8–c2). thetical character of the dialectician’s archê
It is for this reason that Socrates describes as a matter of the kind of argument used to
mathematical studies as merely a ‘prelude’ to establish it.
dialectic (531d7) and they are often referred The dialectician’s avoidance of images or
to as ‘propaedeutic’. visible things is perhaps easier to understand.
It is not easy to know what dialectic is given In the R., Socrates repeatedly contrasts forms
this very abstract description. The notion of with sensible things and we have seen that he
an unhypothetical first principle is particu- treats dialectic as part of the soul’s turning
larly vexed. Is the form of the good, which away from the realm of sense objects or the
clearly occupies a special role in the metaphys- ‘coping stone’ of such studies as lead the soul
ics of the R., the unhypothetical first principle upward (R. 534e).
(Adam 1902)? R. 532a–b describes dialectic Other puzzles about dialectic in the R.
as the soul’s journey from visible to invisible, include the relation of what is said there
intelligible reality – a journey that ends with to descriptions of dialectic given in other
the grasp of the good itself. This requires that works. One example is Sph. 253d–e. Here
we assume that dialectic’s end point is also its again dialectic is the distinctive method of
unhypothetical starting point. the philosopher. However, now the dialecti-
Another related question is whether cian is likened to the grammarian or musi-
the method that is described in the middle cian who knows which letters or notes are
books of the R. is practised in any of the which, and also which can combine with one
Platonic dialogues. Some interpreters think another (cf. Philebus 16c–17e). Similarly in
so. Consider, for example, that the R. implies Phaedrus 266d, Socrates describes the person

160

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 160 3/17/2001 9:21:04 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

who masters the art of collecting particulars DIVIDED LINE


into their proper kinds and dividing those
kinds ‘along nature’s joints’ as a dialectician. Nicholas D. Smith
Here, perhaps, the sense of the verb dialegein The divided line passage begins at Republic
that means ‘pick out’ is relevant. In neither 509d6 by comparing the relative ‘kind and
dialogue, however, do we find mention of an place’ (trans. Grube and Reeve) of the form
unhypothetical first principle. Moreover, the of the good and the sun to a divided line. All
kinds of dichotomous division practised in but one of the manuscripts say that the line is
dialogues such as the Sph. or the Plt. readily to be divided unequally. Contemporary edi-
lend themselves to forking diagrams, at least tions and translations prefer ‘unequal’, given
as an aid to memory. Finally, it is unclear the emphasis on proportions throughout the
how far the method of division concerns passage.
itself with forms (Trevaskis 1967). But scholars have disagreed about the ori-
In spite of these apparent differences, entation (vertical, horizontal or diagonal) of
there are also some important commonalities the line and also about which of the subsec-
between the description of dialectic in the tions described in more detail in the passage
R. and Plato’s remarks on dialectic and the should be supposed to be represented, and
illustration of the method of division in later by which lengths. The literature on the line
dialogues. First, there is the fact that dialec- is perhaps more extensive than on any other
tic deals with something intelligible and not passage in Plato’s works. Lafrance (1986)
with sensibles (R. 531e; Plt. 286a), though provides a 275-page annotated bibliography
it is disputed whether what is divided in the (in French) of everything published on this
later dialogues are the same things as mid- single passage from 1804 to 1984. Many
dle period forms. Second, the dialectician can new articles and sections of books have
give an accurate account that can be defended been added to this literature since then. For
in question and answer (R. 511c; Cra. 390e). detailed discussions with citations of all of
The latter point seems to militate against an the scholarly debates about this passage, see
understanding of dialectic as a state of men- Smith (1996). As for orientation, it seems
tal fitness that permits one to simply see a decisive that some subsections are said to be
philosophical truth without being able to higher than others (see R. 511a6 and 511d8),
communicate or defend it in argument (cf. which rules out a horizontal line, and since
Epistle 7, 341c). no right–left distinctions are made, most rep-
Here, then, are the threads that interpret- resentations depict the line as vertical, rather
ers attempt to weave together to arrive at than diagonal.
an account of Platonic dialectic. If there is The relative lengths of the different sec-
a uniform and explicit picture of Platonic tions are still debated. Plato first claims
philosophy’s distinctive method in the dia- that the lengths of the line represent differ-
logues, then it has remained well hidden for ent degrees of clarity and obscurity (saphê-
over two and half millennia. In my view, neia kai asapheia:509d9) and also truth and
students of Plato do well to treat authorita- untruth (alêtheia te kai mê:510a9), which
tive pronouncements such as Heidegger’s on is compatible with the longer sections rep-
‘Platonic dialectic’ with great caution. resenting more of the positives but also

161

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 161 3/17/2001 9:21:05 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

with representing more of the negatives of thing, Plato never explicitly mentions this
these comparisons. See the debate between consequence. But also recall that the propor-
Proclus and Plutarch, as reported in Denyer tions are supposed to represent differences in
(2007:293); Denyer himself thinks that the degrees of clarity and truth in the differ-
the choice is ‘arbitrary’. In Plato’s conclud- ent subsections of the line. Even if we grant
ing remarks (at 511e3), however, only the that the same objects belong at both of the
positives are mentioned, so the proportions middle segments, it is clearly not the case
appear to indicate degrees of clarity and that Plato thinks that what is represented at
truth represented by each section of the line. BC (assigned to thought (dianoia) at 511d8)
Immediately after the first division, Plato is no more clear than the segment (assigned
subdivides the original sections in the same to belief (pistis) at 511e1) immediately below
proportion as in the first division (509d6–7). it. Indeed, Plato later (at 533d5) explicitly
Let the line be AE (with A at the top), the says that dianoia is clearer than doxa which,
original division at C, and subdivisions at B according to 510a9, would appear to be
on the top section and D on the bottom sec- represented by either the higher only or else
tion; the overall proportions of the line will both of the lower two subsections.
now be (in algebraic notation) AC/CE = AB/ Still others have claimed that the sec-
BC = CD/DE, with AB the highest and long- ond highest level (BC) should be associated
est of the subsections, and DE as the shortest with images, but not sensible ones; instead,
at the bottom. some scholars claim that the ‘mathematical
A mathematical consequence of this con- intermediates’ of the sort Aristotle says (at
struction is that the two middle subsections Metaphysics 1.987b15–18) Plato included in
(BC, CD) are equal in length. Scholars debate his philosophy were intended for BC. Though
whether this equality is significant. On one still defended by many scholars, this view
hand, the same sorts of objects (particular has the defect of basing an interpretation on
sensibles) are mentioned in relation to both something that Plato himself fails to mention
of the relevant subsections: as the originals in the text itself. Complicating this debate
at CD of the images at DE (509e1–10a3) and further is the interpretive business of how
as the images at BC of the originals at AB exactly the image of the cave is supposed to
(510b4–5, 510b7–9, 510d5–6, 510e1–11a1, ‘map’ onto the distinctions made in the line
511a6–7, 511c1, 511c7–8). Moreover, given passage, and how many sets of objects are
Plato’s own proficiency in geometry, it would to be found in that subsequent simile, and in
be strange to see him perform an operation the theory of higher education that follows it
that (surely he knew) would require the mid- in bk VII. At any rate, the highest subsection
dle subsections to be equal – but this is pre- represents the practise of dialectic, which is
cisely what happens at 533e7–4a5, in which associated only with forms and reasoning up
Plato recalls the earlier proportion in such to a first principle and only then down to con-
a way as to switch the two middle terms clusions (511b3–c2); the second highest rep-
in the proportion (which would now be, in resents the mathematical disciplines, which
algebraic notation: AC/CE = AB/CD = BC/ use images and hypothesize forms, drawing
DE). However, there are also good reasons conclusions directly from these hypotheses,
for resisting making the equality a significant but failing to link them with an unhypotheti-
feature of the line’s construction. For one cal starting point (510c1–11a1, 511c3–d5).

162

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 162 3/17/2001 9:21:05 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

The second lowest subsection is associated throughout on the personal character of


with visible particulars (510a5–6), and the learning. ‘Answer as you think’, he demands
lowest subsection is associated with shadows (Gorgias, Meno, Euthydemus). Even a wrong
and reflections of the sensible particulars answer is preferable to an insincere one
(509e1–10a3). (Men.; Theaetetus.). Thrasymachus, Socrates’
In the closing sentences of the divided line bitter adversary in Republic bk 1, complains
simile, Plato arranges each of the subsections that Socrates always asks and never answers;
in the proportion and now associates each and when he does, he is always suspect of
one with a distinct ‘condition in the soul’ speaking ironically and dialectically.
(pathêma en tê psuchê – 511d7). Scholars Plato’s Socrates summarized his educa-
remain unresolved on the exact relation of tional aim in one sentence: ‘The unexam-
these to the cognitive powers (dunameis) dis- ined life is not worth living for a human
cussed at the end of bk 5. Of these powers, being’ (Apology 38a). This he called ‘the
ignorance seems not to be represented on the care of one’s soul’ (Ap.), cleansing the soul
line at all, whereas knowledge (epistêmê) is of contradictions in thought and deed (Grg.).
associated either with the highest subsection Socrates’ main educational tool was the elen-
(associated at 511d8 with understanding chus, the confrontation of his interlocutor
(noêsis)) or with both of the top two subsec- with the logical and, more often, emotional
tions, and opinion (doxa), as I have already consequences of his received opinions. The
said, with either the higher or both of the horror of contradiction is natural to the soul,
lower subsections. but is seldom immediately felt. Once the soul
is rid of its inner contradictions, the truth
will follow of itself, so Socrates believed.
(Objective) reality is in the soul, but in an
EDUCATION indistinct manner, distorted by false and
muddled opinions.
Samuel Scolnicov In Grg., the crucial distinction is explic-
Education, as a direct consequence of his itly made between pepisteukenai (having
ethics, is, implicitly or explicitly, the central been persuaded) and memathekenai (having
concern of Plato’s thought. Plato aimed at learned). To have learned is to be able to give
providing the epistemological and metaphysi- a proper account of the matter at hand; to be
cal basis for his Socrates’ educational convic- persuaded is to be convinced of it for reasons
tions, as he interpreted them. Traditionally, extraneous to the matter. In Men., the paral-
the aim of Greek education (q.v. Education lel distinction is drawn between doxa (opin-
as background) was aretê (human excellence, ion) and epistêmê (knowledge, in the strict
often somewhat misleadingly translated as sense). The ‘geometry lesson’ in Men. and the
‘virtue’), which the Sophists claimed to teach simile of the midwife in Tht. demonstrate this
as a technique. Socrates opposed this view, distinction. The interlocutor is enjoined to
since any technique is double-edged: the recollect what he somehow already knows in
best doctor is also the best poisoner and the an indistinct manner. In recollection (anam-
best guardian is also the best thief. But aretê nêsis, q.v.), the content arising in the mind is
cannot be misused and cannot be passed on not perceived as something new, but gradu-
from master to pupil. Plato’s Socrates insists ally recognized as if it had been in the mind

163

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 163 3/17/2001 9:21:05 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

beforehand, like remembering something (arithmetic, plane geometry, stereometry,


that has been forgotten and is recognized as kinematics (‘astronomy’) and acoustics (‘har-
such. Anamnêsis, however, is not in the pro- monics’)). Mathematics is the paradigmatic
posal of answers. These can, for example, be science, the science of structure. It leads to the
suggested by Socrates, quoted from poets, idea of the good, viz. the idea of the nontem-
presented as dreams. Anamnêsis involves poral, well ordered, self-contained teleologi-
working through the reasons for or against cal system of ideas, of necessity imperfectly
the view entertained, until it is abandoned or exhibited in this sensible, moving world.
else transformed from opinion into knowl- Plato sets himself in R. bk 2 the task of
edge. (Cf. Men. 82e12: ‘Mark how he will go showing that justice, as hierarchy under rea-
on remembering’, Tht. 160e3: ‘Shall we then son, is desirable for the soul and for the state
say this is your newborn?’) not only for its consequences but also, and
Education as a personal project is nec- foremost, for itself. Hence, eudaimonia is not
essarily a product of erôs (q.v., Love) in in the consequences of one’s actions, for these
all its manifestations. Aristophanes in the are beyond one’s control. But aretê itself has
Symposium introduces the theme of man’s no masters and the god is not to blame (R.
incompleteness, his awareness of it, and his bk 10 617e3–5). Aretê is in the êthos, one’s
longing for what he lacks. Socrates transfers moral character and the locus of one’s moral
Aristophanes’ insight from the natural to the responsibility, not in what happens but in
metaphysical plane: a person is not incom- one’s relation to what happens. The end of
plete, but imperfect. Education is the process education is the development of this êthos
of helping someone to reach the perfection informed by reason.
that is his, but not yet grasped. In the famous simile of the cave (q.v.),
The R. and the Laws see the state as pri- education is a long and arduous process. The
marily an educational institution, whose prisoner is taken out of the cave against his
function is the promotion of eudaimonia, will and complains that the shadows were
human flourishing (not quite the modern much clearer than what he is now shown.
concept of ‘happiness’, with its subjective Education is not ‘like putting sight into
connotations), as a result of aretê. Human unseeing eyes’. It is turning the eye of the
excellence or perfection is his rationality. But soul, together with the whole soul, from the
reason will arise only in those souls that are sensible to the intelligible, a Gestalt switch
already predisposed to it (R.). Early educa- from everyday, instrumental to ideal, norma-
tion is the nurturing of reason by irrational tive rationality.
means: gymnastics and music (including In the final myth of R. bk 10, the first
poetry). Much importance is given to the soul to choose its new life had lived a life of
educational role of myth and art. But Plato is demotic aretê, by custom, without philos-
also wary of the force of poetry, and of art in ophia. In matter of overt behaviour, demotic
general; hence the necessity of careful censor- aretê is not different from true aretê. But it
ship (R.; Lg.). has no true moral worth. No one in that myth
Higher education in the R. is for the future achieves true aretê. Perhaps only Socrates
guardians and philosophers, in the Lg. for could, in Plato’s eyes. Thus, in Lg., Plato
all, in the measure of their capacities. It is must satisfy himself with leaving a detailed
education in the five mathematical sciences prescription for the good life in the good

164

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 164 3/17/2001 9:21:06 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

city, like the itinerant doctor of the Politicus. is directed at both the moral views held by
These laws are introduced by preambles, so opponents and their moral integrity. In the
as to achieve obedience through understand- words of Plato’s Nicias at Laches 187e,
ing of their instrumental civic advantages, Lysimachus does not know that whoever
insofar as possible. Even the well intentioned joins in a close discussion with Socrates,
rulers will not be the philosophers of the R. regardless of the original topic of conver-
and will have had neither their vision of the sation, must necessarily ‘not cease to be
good nor their understanding of the norma- dragged around and around by him in argu-
tivity of reason. They will, at most, be able ment until he is drawn into giving an account
to imitate the good order of the heavens and of himself – both how he now lives and how
educate their citizens according to it. he has lived his past life’. Plato regularly
For further reading, see Jaeger (1939–44), shows Socrates manoeuvring an interlocu-
Nettleship (1935), Scolnicov (1988) and tor first into some kind of moral discussion,
Stenzel (1928). and then into revealing – and indeed seeing
problems with – the false moral assumptions
upon which his life is founded. The proce-
dure is founded on Socrates’ conviction that
ELENCHUS (CROSS-EXAMINATION, ‘the unexamined life is not worth living’
REFUTATION) (Apology 38a), and the falsehoods stand-
ardly relate to areas in which interlocutors
Harold Tarrant were highly regarded, whether a professional
Elenchus is a name now applied to the argu- area (e.g. rhetoric, sophistry, ‘musical’ per-
ments most characteristic of Socrates in the formance), or a socially prized quality such
so-called early dialogues. Indeed, its presence as one of the virtues. Though Socrates may
has been used as a developmentalist crite- deny that he can improve upon another’s
rion for a dialogue’s inclusion in this group account (e.g. Charmides 175e; La. 200e), he
(Vlastos 1994:29–37). The word derives from compares favourably not only because his
the Greek elenchos, meaning a ‘test’ to deter- own image does not rely on claims to moral
mine how sound something or somebody is, virtue or moral knowledge but also because
and is closely related to a verb for ‘refute’ it is obvious that he has long been scrutiniz-
exelenchein. The simple verb elenchein may ing the issues as they apply to him. Conceived
be found in this meaning, though more as I have described it so far, ‘elenchus’ does
often as ‘put to the test’. While it is unclear not apply to all Socratic questioning, only
whether Socrates preferred to characterize cases involving claims to social or intellec-
his philosophic activity as elenchus, Plato’s tual standing, so the slave in Meno or young
dialogues show that such terminology was in men in Lysis and Euthydemus are not seen
widespread use in his intellectual world for as targets of ‘the elenchus’. Once an inter-
a variety of verbal challenges to somebody locutor has been engaged in debate Socrates
considered to be an opponent in a debate. elicits a premise that he challenges. The chal-
Regardless of Plato’s use of the term, it lenge comes not by direct confrontation but
is clear that his Socrates adopts a distinc- by eliciting from the interlocutor unforced
tive approach to refutation that merits some admissions that serve as further premises, and
technical name to describe it. The approach which, taken together, can be shown to entail

165

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 165 3/17/2001 9:21:06 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

the contrary of the premise challenged. The have survived all attempts to refute them.
consequences are usually spelled out clearly Grg. has less to do with the irrefutable truth
and politely, so that the person being refuted or falsehood of moral propositions than with
is given no good reason to attack Socrates for which of them may be rationally adopted
hostile conduct and is more likely therefore as the foundations of our public lives.
to blame himself, as Socrates points out on Conversely, outside Grg. where philosophic
Protagoras’ behalf at Theaetetus 167e–8a. and rhetorical refutation compete for legiti-
As the Alcibiades I (112e–13e) fully argues, macy, Socrates gives little hint that he has
free and honest admissions leading to the reflected deeply on precisely what the elen-
refutation of an interlocutor reflect his own chus achieves or the conditions that enable
views, not those of Socrates. While it is not it to work (Vlastos 1994:34–6). The conse-
necessarily the challenged proposition that is quence of the paucity of what one might call
refuted, since any one of the premises might ‘meta-elenctic’ outside the Grg. means that
be faulty, all admissions are assumed to coin- articles on individual elenchi (several exam-
cide with the interlocutor’s beliefs, so that his ples in Scott 2002) are often more rewarding
total set of moral beliefs is found wanting than those offering an overall theory.
and any special claims to moral expertise are One constant, however, is the conviction
thereby undermined. that the truth is best approached in discus-
Since Vlastos’ seminal article (1983) much sions involving at least two good minds, as
of the discussion about the elenchus centres Protagoras 348c–e demonstrates. When two
on whether Socrates is committed to its use perspectives are brought to bear on an issue it
as a vehicle for the refutation or demonstra- is far less likely that conclusions reached will
tion of moral theses. Central to this question be fatally flawed by false admissions aris-
are the arguments with Polus in the Gorgias, ing from an individual’s personal viewpoint
where Socrates claims that (a) the truth (Tarrant 2006). That people view things dif-
is never refuted (Grg. 473b) and (b) it has ferently in the heat of the moment is argued
been demonstrated that his claim was correct at Prt. 352d–8e, where moral lapses are
(479e). The former would not in itself justify explained as temporary misjudgements. We
certainty that anything left unrefuted must know from Thucydides, History 3.82 (Price
be true, and for Socrates it justifies only the 2001) that pressures led to radical misuse
assumption that it is so (509a–b). The latter of moral vocabulary in Socrates’ time. Such
would be more meaningful if it were clear misuse is reflected in the extreme positions
that demonstration were used in its mod- adopted by some interlocutors, for exam-
ern philosophic sense, but Polus has already ple Euthyphro 4a and Grg. 482e–95d. The
used the verb at 470d2 for what history can temporary nature of moral mistakes (unlike
‘demonstrate’. Besides, the demonstration- moral knowledge) is underlined by such pas-
claim is followed by ‘So if this is true . . .’, a sages as Euthphr. 11b–c, Alc. I.116e–17a
conditional clause that would be redundant and Men. 95c–6b.
if the truth had indeed been demonstrated. Hence, Socrates sees himself as offering
Similarly, at 509b, the conditional clause the divine service of reawakening people to
‘so if it is so’ confirms that Socrates is not their moral selves through elenchos and close
making a knowledge claim, and that there examination (Ap. 29d–31a), as if restor-
remains scope for challenging positions that ing their minds to the natural condition.

166

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 166 3/17/2001 9:21:06 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

Vlastos (1983:52–5) accordingly saw not knowledge is a kind of ‘recollection’ (q.v.);


only Socrates as having access to the moral (c) The primary objects of knowledge are the
propositions required to negate an interlocu- forms (q.v.); (d) Knowledge ideally comes
tor’s mistake but also the interlocutor him- with an understanding of the full causes of
self. The systematic manner in which he built things, which would require a teleological
such requirements into his theory finds little explanation of why things came to be for
support today, but the naturalness of moral the best, or for some good; (e) Finally, some
knowledge is implied by the metaphors of scholars believe, Plato defines knowledge
recollection and giving birth that are applied as a state involving true judgement with an
to Socrates-induced discovery in dialogues explanatory account; others however think
that Vlastos placed later. If moral awareness that he reserves for knowledge of the forms
is the default position for human beings, and themselves a different, self-certifying kind of
ignorance an aberration, then one might knowledge.
indeed expect an interlocutor to recognize In the ‘Socratic’ or aporetic dialogues, very
some moral truths unsystematically, and little is said about methodological or episte-
the seasoned philosopher to recognize most mological matters; Plato’s character, Socrates,
of them, seeing them more as an organic does not explain what he is doing, or explain
whole. what is needed for success in the inquiries
about virtue and happiness he undertakes.
Nor does Socrates take any pains to spell out
what knowledge is, and how it differs from
EPISTEMOLOGY (KNOWLEDGE) true belief. What we get, instead, is Socrates’
keen interest in coming to have knowledge –
Mi-Kyoung Lee something he denies possessing – about how
Nowhere in Plato’s writings does he articu- one ought to live. He displays little interest in
late and unequivocally endorse a theory or asking, for its own sake, what knowledge is;
definition of knowledge. Admittedly, the rather, he is interested in finding out whether
Theaetetus is devoted to the question, what anyone has knowledge of what the good
is knowledge? Yet, because the dialogue is life is (Ap. 20e–4a, 29b–30b). As he makes
aporetic – that is, contains a rejection of all clear in dialogues like the Euthyphro, Men.
three conceptions of knowledge considered – and Laches, he expects that one should be
it is controversial what, if anything, Plato able to give an account of concepts like vir-
intended us to conclude from that dialogue. tue, piety, courage and justice, one that can
Even so, there are indications in the Tht. as survive scrutiny, that is, Socrates’ elenchus or
well as in earlier dialogues, especially the ‘testing’ of his interlocutors (q.v.). Typically,
Apology, Meno, Phaedo and the Republic, the dialogues end with the interlocutors
of Plato’s views about knowledge. The fol- giving up, and admitting puzzlement and
lowing theses about knowledge are found in confusion.
these dialogues: (a) knowledge is, above all, In the Men., however, Plato has Socrates
expert knowledge, which allows its posses- address the question whether coming to
sor to give an explanatory account of things, have knowledge is really possible: if we do
and which gives one the ability to withstand not know a thing, why should we think that
critical examination; (b) Coming to acquire we will be able to discover anything about

167

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 167 3/17/2001 9:21:06 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

it? The puzzle has the following form: if one requires a grasp of the forms, that is, mini-
does not know what one is looking for, how mally, of what all things of a kind have in
will one know what to look for? And how common, and what it is to be a thing of that
will one know it, if one should find it? The kind. Plato illustrates the contrast between
answer is that the inquiry is guided by one’s knowledge and reality in a series of famous
conception and understanding of what one analogies: the sun (R. bk 6.507a–9c; q.v.),
is looking for. These fall short of knowledge, the line (R. bk 6.509c–11e; q.v.) and the cave
but are sufficient to guide one nonetheless, (R. bk 7.514a–21b; q.v.). Scholars disagree
and help one to recognize the correct answer, about whether Plato endorses, in these analo-
when one finds it. To demonstrate how suc- gies, the idea that knowledge is foundational,
cessful inquiry occurs, Socrates offers a dem- that is, that there is a special kind of certain
onstration using a slave boy, who, asked or self-certifying knowledge (concerning the
questions by Socrates, is prompted to con- form of the good and other forms) upon
sider and reject two incorrect answers to a which all other knowledge is based. It is
geometry problem, and then arrives at and clear, however, that Plato retains Socrates’
recognizes as correct the true answer. Socrates idea that knowledge derives from the dia-
calls this ‘recollection’, by which he seems to lectic – an idea present already in the Men.,
mean that we possess innate knowledge or endorsed in the R. and more fully developed
true beliefs. in the rich conceptions of dialectic and divi-
The Men. also explores the distinction sion in the Sophist and Politicus.
between knowledge and true belief. Socrates Finally, in the Tht., Socrates and his inter-
compares true beliefs to the statues of locutors Theodorus and Theaetetus exam-
Daedalus, a famous sculptor: like Daedalus’ ine and ultimately reject three accounts
statues, true beliefs ‘are not willing to remain of knowledge: (a) perception, (b) true
long, and they escape from a man’s mind, so judgement and (c) true judgement with an
that they are not worth much until one ties account. Knowledge as perception is linked
them down by (giving) an account of the rea- with Protagorean relativism and a thesis
son why’, that is, why they are true (Men. of Heraclitean flux and variability, both of
97e–8a). Whether Plato means to endorse which Socrates proceeds to reject. Knowledge
Socrates’ claim that knowledge is true belief as true judgement is quickly dispatched by
‘tied down with a reckoning (or account, logis- means of the example of a jury that is cor-
mos) of the reason why’ is not clear – since in rectly persuaded of the truth by a good law-
the R., Socrates seems to think that knowledge yer, but still lacks knowledge of the truth
is not a species of true belief at all. since they are not eyewitnesses. Knowledge
In the central books of the R., Plato has as true judgement with an account appears
Socrates argue that knowledge is only pos- to some scholars identical with the thesis
sible if one has a grasp of the forms. With put forward in Men. (97e–98a); however,
this argument, Plato makes an attack on the Socrates and his interlocutors are here una-
‘sight-lovers’, who deny that anything uni- ble to find a kind of account which, when
versal can be said about what makes things added to true judgement, would transform
beautiful, just or good, and insist on the mul- it into knowledge, because one falls into the
tiplicity of beauty, justice or goodness. They problem whether this account is knowledge
cannot have knowledge, because knowledge or opinion, and hence into infinite regress.

168

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 168 3/17/2001 9:21:07 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

Thus, the Tht. presents an interpretive puz- (q.v., eudaimonia) or its Greek equiva-
zle about whether Plato thinks knowledge is lent, faring well (Meno 87c–8d; Republic
something besides these options, or whether 621c–d). He additionally believes that the
he has left clues for the astute reader about human virtues (or excellences, aretê; q.v.)
why Socrates rejects an option which should govern the attainment of happiness, and con-
continue to be taken seriously as a definition sequently much of his ethical and pedagogi-
of knowledge. Solving the puzzle most likely cal writing passionately advocates cultivating
requires, as Cornford suggested, that one take virtue. The precise relation between virtue
into account the ways that the Tht. looks for- and happiness is disputed (Brickhouse and
ward to the Sph. and other late dialogues. Smith 1994:103–36), although many take
Despite the lack of clearly endorsed doc- Plato to believe that the virtues are necessary
trines, Plato’s dialogues are full of rich and sufficient for happiness (Irwin 1977a;
and imaginative ideas about the nature of Vlastos 1991a). Plato’s further view on the
knowledge and are the source of the follow- relation between happiness and pleasure is
ing seminal ideas, whether endorsed by Plato more controversial. Plato does reject hedon-
or not: that knowledge might be innate, that ism if pleasure is identified with the satisfac-
knowledge can only be of universals (i.e. of tion of the appetites, but it is challenging to
forms), that knowledge is foundational, that harmonize his opposition to hedonism in the
mathematics and geometry offer a para- Gorgias (500d) with its endorsement in the
digm of what knowledge might look like, Protagoras (351b–4e). Irwin (1995:78–126)
that knowledge must be a science that offers offers an important discussion of this topic,
teleological explanations, and finally, that and advocates distinguishing two versions of
knowledge is true belief or judgement with hedonism.
an explanation or justification. Beyond this basic commitment to eudai-
For further readings, see Benson (2000), monism, Plato’s ethical theory frustrates
Fine (1990), Fine (1992), Lee (2005), Lee attempts at systematic, unified, compre-
(2008), Matthews (2008), Polansky (1992), hensive treatment. Scholars often divide his
Scott (2006), Sedley (2004), Taylor (2008) work into two distinct groups. This division
and Vlastos (1983). generally correlates both with the division of
Plato’s works into earlier and middle periods,
but also with the exegetical and theoretical
ERISTIC (see Antilogy and eristics) methodologies that are brought to bear on
the dialogues. It is also often cast, though
unproductively, as a distinction between the
ERÔS (see Love) historical Socrates (q.v.) and the mature,
emancipated Plato.
Plato’s early dialogues present his read-
ETHICS ers with some important challenges regard-
ing the reconstruction of his ethical theory.
Richard Foley These dialogues contain a welter of his-
Plato’s ethical theory is eudaimonist, for torical, biographical, dialogical and literary
he, like most ancient philosophers, holds details that substantially complicate their
that all good actions aim at happiness ethical message. Additionally vexing is that

169

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 169 3/17/2001 9:21:07 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

although many end aporetically, these con- practise from philosophical theory, but this is
versations are richly insightful and guided not to say that Plato is a moral sceptic (Kraut
with skill, which suggests that they may 1992c:3). Instead, he is an ethical reformer,
contain an implicit ethical doctrine. There is seeking to liberate normative terms from an
widespread speculation that one element of earlier aristocratic tradition that valorizes
Plato’s early ethical theory is ‘intellectualism’ wealth, strength and power, to something we
(q.v.), the doctrine that the virtues are a type would recognize as genuinely moral. Some of
of knowledge. The further assumption that the tenets of this new ethical theory are so
Plato thinks virtue is knowledge of the good surprising that they are often labelled para-
specifically leads some to argue that the vir- doxical: the virtues are unitary (Prt. 329b–d;
tues are not just necessarily coincident, but in La. 198d–9e), virtue is a type of knowledge
fact identical (Ferejohn 1982; Penner 1973). (La. 199c–e), akrasia (q.v.) is impossible
The ethical position of Plato’s early works (Grg. 459c–60b; Men. 77a–8b), it is better
is distinctive for advocating a method (q.v.) to suffer than to do injustice (Grg. 469c), it is
which it prioritizes above any specific moral never just to mistreat another, even in retalia-
tenets. Plato depicts philosophy as simulta- tion (Cri. 49c–d) and a worse person cannot
neously a process of critical self-examination harm a better (Ap. 30d).
and an investigation into the definitions of Progress in ethics can perhaps be made
central moral terms like ‘piety’, ‘courage’ and through Socratic inquiry into ordinary moral
‘temperance’. Socrates repeatedly contrives beliefs. Pursuing a strategy similar to one
to shift the conversation to an evaluation Rawls later named ‘the method of reflec-
of the life led by his interlocutors (Laches tive equilibrium’, Socratic dialogues seek to
187e–8c). The ensuing Socratic elenchus expose and diminish inconsistencies between
usually results not only in the refutation our general moral principles and our ethi-
of proposed definitions but also in the ero- cal convictions in specific cases (Rawls
sion of the putative expert’s original self- 1971). Many dialogues make progress in this
confidence. In contrast, Socrates appears as regard, since early definitions are improved
a paragon of virtue, perhaps because he has in compelling ways over the course of the
thought critically about his actions (Vlastos conversation. Yet puzzlingly, all end aporeti-
1983), though such direct self-examination cally, progressive trajectory notwithstand-
on Socrates’ part is rarely depicted by Plato. ing (Charmides; Euthyphro; Hippias Major;
Socrates asserts that this examination is La.). The reader should build on this prelimi-
necessary (Apology 38a) and sufficient (Ap. nary work by adopting the Socratic method,
41c–d) for happiness, which offers confirma- in which case the aporetic conclusion con-
tion for intellectualism: philosophical activ- ceals the hortatory aspect to Plato’s writing.
ity yields knowledge, which is identical to It should be noted, however, that Socrates
virtue, which is itself necessary and sufficient defends his ethical views more explicitly in
for happiness. some early dialogues (Ap.; Cri.).
It must be stressed, however, that the The ethical works of Plato’s middle and
emphasis for Plato is on Socrates’ method. late periods reveal a shift to a more assertive
Plato himself raises doubts about the desir- style, although Plato will sometimes employ
ability or even possibility of deriving moral contrasting speeches or intermittent use of

170

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 170 3/17/2001 9:21:07 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

the Socratic method (R. bk 1; Symposium; EUDAIMONIA (see Happiness)


Phaedrus). This transformation also cor-
relates with an alteration in the techniques
of exegesis and evaluation used by the EXCELLENCE (VIRTUE) (ARETÊ)
scholarly community. Theoretically minded
ethicists object that the Socratic method of Naomi Reshotko
striving for consistency is inappropriately ‘Excellence’ is one of the two most common
deferential to one’s starting point. Instead, English translations of the Greek word aretê.
normative questions require a philosophical In translating Plato’s dialogues, the English
account of the good (q.v.). This approach to word ‘virtue’ is also used. Translators tend
Platonic ethics emphasizes R. above other to use the two English words ‘excellence’
dialogues. Bks 6 and 7, specifically the and ‘virtue’ in distinctive, although not unre-
analogies of ship, sun, line and the allegory lated, contexts and their different uses can
of the cave (q.v.), explain the source from be understood to capture a primary and a
which ethical claims derive their authority. more derivative notion of aretê for Plato.
On this theory, the good is prior to virtue There is discussion of the excellence of a tool
(Santas 1985:223), which means that apo- or a craft in many dialogues. The excellence
retic discussions can be resolved through the of a tool or craft is that which enables it to
study of the good. Some argue that the prob- do what it alone is designed to do and also
lems encountered in the earlier dialogues that which it does best. This task of a tool or
led Plato to this new theory of the good craft is also distinguished as its proper func-
(Irwin 1977a:132–76; Kraut 1992c:10). tion (ergon): the excellence of a knife is the
However, any understanding of the good sharpness that enables it to cut (i.e. to per-
itself presupposes elaborate metaphysical form the function of cutting) and the excel-
and epistemological theories (Kraut 1992:6; lence of cobbling is its ability to make shoes.
Santas 1985:223). The allegation that this The rationale would seem to be that the tool
ethical theory is empty for failing to show or craft becomes excellent when it can excel
how to derive ethical maxims from abstruse at its proper function.
metaphysics spans the history of philoso- The proper function of a human being,
phy (Aristotle Metaphysics 1096b8–7a13; which can in turn be honed and perfected, is
Popper 1962:274–5n32). that person’s aretê – human excellence – and
Reconciling Plato’s diverse writings on which concerns the soul (q.v.). In Republic 1
ethics thus continues to pose challenges. (353a1–4a4), the function of the soul is rul-
Although developmentalism (q.v.) provides ing, deliberating and living. Justice (q.v.) is
one avenue for thinking about this issue, it that excellence of the soul by which it rules
is difficult to accept that the lively debates of well, and insofar as it does so, it lives well
the early works could have been supplanted and is happy. The word ‘virtue’, as the trans-
by the abstract and relatively uncritical theo- lation for aretê, would, in the case of the
rizing of the later works. Plato’s enigmatic human being, point to that aspect or part
shift from moral critic to dogmatic theoreti- of the human being – the soul – that can be
cian thus endures as one of the most compel- honed and by the improvement of which a
ling topics in Plato scholarship. human becomes excellent or virtuous. The

171

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 171 3/17/2001 9:21:07 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

good human being is the excellent one and says that aretê is wisdom (Men. 88c4–d3;
is the virtuous one – but the good human Ferejohn 1984:107). While it is argued that
being, we would also say, ‘has’ virtue. Plato intended to single out a particular
Some dialogues, as just seen, are marked kind of knowledge that might be associated
by the character Socrates’ preoccupation with consequent moral behaviour, there is
with the relationship between aretê and also support for the notion that, according
eudaimonia. Plato seems here to make an to Plato, all knowledge is equally important
effort to isolate the relationship between and equally a component of virtue.
virtue – understood as the excellence of the Plato discusses several human character
function that is particular to humans – and traits under the umbrella of arête. While he
human flourishing. There is, to his mind, a singles out five ‘virtues’ (sophia or wisdom,
very important connection between being sôphrosynê or temperance, andreia or brav-
virtuous and flourishing or, to state it more ery, dikaiosunê or justice, hosiotês or piety),
boldly, between being virtuous and being and addresses them individually in particular
happy. There has been extensive debate over dialogues, in the R., he narrows it down to
what exactly this relationship is. That virtue four ‘demotic’ virtues (omitting piety). One
is sufficient for happiness, that it is neces- central doctrine of the Socratic dialogues
sary for happiness, that virtue and happiness (particularly Protagoras and Laches) is
(q.v.) are identical, that, not virtue, but, vir- known alternatively as ‘the unity of virtue’
tuous behaviour is sufficient for happiness, or the ‘the unity of the virtues’, depending on
and that the pursuit of virtue, while it does one’s reading of the text. Those who adopt
not guarantee happiness, is the only way to the ‘unity of the virtues’ find Socrates claim-
purposefully pursue happiness are all claims ing that a person cannot have only one of
that have been attributed to Plato or to the the virtues, but each person is, for example,
historical Socrates via the exegesis of Plato’s if brave then also wise, etc. (Vlastos 1972).
texts. ‘The unity of virtue’ finds the claim to be that
Since ‘virtue’, a burdened and storied all of these are names for one and the same
Latinized term taken to be a moral term thing (Penner 1973). That thing is taken to
often stands in for the Greek aretê, it is evi- be the psychological state that causes virtu-
dent that aretê is understood by many to be a ous behaviour. These virtuous behaviours
moral term as well. But, it is not obvious that are then distinguished by context: bravery
Plato always (or, some would say, ever) uses is what virtuous behaviour looks like on
aretê with a moral tone. It is widely agreed the battlefield, temperance is what virtuous
that a subgroup of dialogues, often referred behaviour looks like at the banquet table,
to as ‘Socratic’ on the assumption that they etc. Thus, the unity of virtue thesis resonates
represent the views of either the historical with the notion that virtue is all knowledge
Socrates or Plato during a period in which and that virtuous behaviour is simply knowl-
he was under the influence of Socrates, use edgeable behaviour and wise people on the
the word aretê to refer only to knowledge. battlefield act bravely while wise people in
Socrates, who asserts that the only thing the courts act justly.
that ever benefits us is wisdom (Euthydemus It is widely recognized that Plato brings
281e2–5; Meno 87d4–8, 88c6–d1), says that the notion of aretê, here best understood as
aretê always benefits us (Men. 87e3) and even ‘excellence’, into his conception of justice

172

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 172 3/17/2001 9:21:08 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

and the structure of his republic. The kallipo- whether Plato’s thoughts about forms con-
lis – the fine city proposed in the R. – is just stituted an actual theory (Sayre 1995b). A
because in it each person does that to which consequence is that there is considerable dis-
he or she is best suited and that at which he agreement about the contents of the account
or she excels. The people are, in turn, placed in question. This article summarizes the
into three classes according to their interests account’s main features without attempting
and abilities and each of those classes as a to arbitrate disputed issues.
collective does that at which it excels. Here, Aristotle reports (Metaphysics
rather than there being some generic human 1078b12–15) that Plato was led to his theory
excellence that is the function of humans gen- of forms by being persuaded that knowledge
erally, Plato is looking upon the function and requires permanent objects and that sensible
excellence of individual people in the same things are always in flux. To meet this require-
way he looks at the function and excellence ment, Plato posited eternal and incomposite
of tools. Knives are made of certain materials forms as proper objects of thought. Forms
that promote their function and allow them thus are both immutable and entirely what
to be excellent at cutting. Likewise, retailers they are, without parts to admit opposing
have specific physical and mental abilities features. A plausible example is the form jus-
that make them suited to and allow them tice (q.v.), which (setting aside for now the
to excel as retailers whereas farmers have problem of self-predication) is wholly just
a different and complementary set. Those and in no respect otherwise.
who should become auxiliaries and guard- Another consequence is that forms can
ians are distinguished by their mental and be presented immediately to thought or
physical abilities as well. Thus, the republic intellect, whereas particular things are pre-
fails when its individual members do jobs to sented only in sense perception (q.v.). Thus
which they are not well suited but most of all forms can be known as they are, in and by
when the classes no longer interact accord- themselves, independently of their relation to
ing to their excellences. It is central to the sense particulars.
guardians’ excellence that they look out for Forms and sense particulars are related by
the interests of the republic as a whole, while participation (q.v.), whereby particulars take
it is central to the craftspeoples’ excellence on determinate properties. Thus, sense par-
that they concern themselves with their own ticulars (otherwise in constant flux) become
affairs and trust the guardians to deal with beautiful (just, large, etc.) by participating
larger issues. in the corresponding form (beauty, etc.).
Whereas forms are what they are independ-
ently of other things (are absolute), features
of particulars are caused by participation.
FORMS (EIDOS) (IDEA) As a result of this causal dependency, sen-
sible things also share names with forms in
Kenneth Sayre which they participate. In effect, forms serve
Perhaps the best known doctrine associated as paradigms for naming sense particu-
with Plato is his so-called theory of forms. lars that participate in them. Thus we find
Yet that theory is never fully articulated in his Socrates in the Euthphro saying he must
extant writings. It has even been questioned know what the form holiness is in order to

173

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 173 3/17/2001 9:21:08 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

tell whether a particular act should be called argument attacking the notion of participa-
holy (cf. Allen 1971). tion itself. Although entire books have been
These several tenets comprise what is often written about such issues (see Allen 1971;
described as a ‘two world ontology’. On one Cohen and Keyt 1991), the debates they raise
hand are forms which are absolute, wholly will probably continue indefinitely.
real (nowise other than they are) and knowa- Perhaps the biggest anomaly affecting the
ble by thought. On the other are sense partic- theory of the middle period, however, is that
ulars which are dependent on forms for their several of its key tenets are challenged in later
properties, are subject to opposing properties dialogues. Questioning the youthful Socrates
and can be apprehended by sensation but not in his namesake dialogue, Parmenides attacks
by intellect. Due to these differences, forms in rapid sequence the theses that forms are
are said to be ontologically separate from the incomposite, causes of sensible properties,
world of sense experience. knowable by thought, paradigms for naming
These are the main tenets of the account and separate in and by themselves. Although
associated with Plato’s so-called middle dia- commentators disagree on the seriousness of
logues, notably in the Phaedo, Republic and these attacks (for a classic disagreement, see
Symposium. As it stands, this theory raises Cherniss 1957; Owen 1953a), they clearly
various problems which have been subject call attention to aspects of the original theory
to extensive debate. One is the issue of what that require rethinking.
participation amounts to. This shows up in Apart from Parmenides’ problems, the
the question of what things have correspond- Sophist contains an account of forms (or
ing forms. kinds) that directly opposes certain tenets of
The theory maintains that things are the original theory. Forms here admit oppos-
called by the same name (or described by the ing characters, inasmuch as sameness is dif-
same predicate) by virtue of participating in ferent from difference and difference is the
the same forms. Conversely, a single form is same as itself. Forms in the Sph. also are no
involved whenever we assign the same name longer changeless, since a form’s status alters
to (R. 596a) or predicate the same property when it becomes known.
of (Parmenides 132a) many things. But we Another departure from the original the-
apply the same name in the case of dirt and ory appears in the Timaeus. Participation ini-
other such paltry things. Does this mean that tially was a two-term relation between forms
there are forms in which such objects partici- and sensible objects. In Ti., it is represented
pate? If so, this deviates from Plato’s practise instead as a three-term relation involving
in the dialogues of emphasizing preeminent forms (or paradigms), a characterless recep-
forms like goodness, beauty and justice. tacle and sensible copies (‘reflections’) of the
A related question pertains to self-pred- forms in the latter. Another innovation here
ication. At Protagoras 330e, for instance, is that forms take on geometrical features,
Socrates says that holiness is holy, and at enabling a mathematical description of the
Phd. 100c that beauty is beautiful. But is the makeup of physical properties.
form oddness (Phd. 104d) odd, or the form An even more radical departure appears
largeness (Prm. 132a) large? Not only do in the Philebus, where the forms and recep-
self-predications like these seem senseless, tacle of Ti. are replaced by the ontological
but they give rise to the notorious third man principles of limit and unlimited respectively.

174

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 174 3/17/2001 9:21:08 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

Forms here become limits in the sense of is accompanied by the definite article and
measures or numbers (terms used synony- thus nominalized (‘the dear one’), it usually
mously in Aristotle’s Physics 4.11). In this means ‘friend’, although in the plural it occa-
late dialogue a wide array of sensible things sionally includes kin (‘dear ones’). Rather
are said to derive from the imposition of limit than distinguishing sharply between friend-
on the unlimited, ranging from grammatical ship and other types of affection, such as
phonemes and musical scales to good health, familial, Greek employed a single inclusive
fair weather and an orderly universe. term. Philia was, however, clearly differen-
Recent scholarship has indicated that the tiated from erôs, ‘erotic love’, which a man
conception of forms at work in the Phlb. typically felt towards a woman (in amatory
may correspond to claims Aristotle makes rather than domestic contexts) or an adoles-
about Plato’s forms in the Metaphysics (see cent boy. Thus, to determine Plato’s views of
Sayre 2005, 2006). One claim is that forms friendship, one must distinguish it both from
are numbers. Another is that forms come erôs, which Plato discussed imaginatively,
from participation of the indefinite dyad in and love or philia in general.
unity. Equivalent claims, in the language of The second difficulty is specific to Plato:
the Phlb., are that forms are measures and for Plato was not much interested in ana-
that they arise from a mixture of unlimited lyzing friendship as such, though friend-
with limit. ships, like that between Socrates and Crito,
If this correspondence holds true, yet are illustrated in his dialogues. The dia-
another tenet of the original theory is logue commonly read as Plato’s treatment
rejected in the later dialogues. A key provi- of friendship, namely the Lysis (sometimes
sion originally is that forms are incomposite, subtitled ‘On Friendship’; cf. Bolotin 1979),
whereas in Phlb. they are composed of limit has as much to do with erôs and other kinds
and the unlimited. In other respects, however, of affection as with friendship. Plato was
the initial theory holds firm. Forms still are chiefly concerned with the nature of desire
knowable by intellect, paradigms for naming or attraction in general, of which friendship
and responsible for determinate properties of is one type. Erotic desire in particular seemed
sensible things. to him a better emblem of the philosophi-
cal aspiration to pass beyond the world of
changing appearances to the timeless realm
of ‘ideas’.
FRIENDSHIP (PHILIA) Although the Ly. does treat philia, it is
not a typical ‘dialogue of definition’ (Sedley
David Konstan 1989). It opens with Socrates advising a
A discussion of friendship in Plato encoun- young man named Hippothales on the right
ters two major problems. The first pertains way to court Lysis, the boy with whom he is
to Greek terminology: for philia, the word in love; indeed he claims that his only skill
normally translated as ‘friendship’, has a is detecting ‘who loves and who is loved’
far wider range, embracing almost all that (erônta te kai erômenon, 204B8–10). Note
English includes under ‘love’ (q.v.), and more that these are two roles, lover and beloved;
(e.g. social concord and foreign alliances). erôs is typically an asymmetrical relationship
When the adjective philos, ‘dear’ or ‘loving’, (the age difference between Hippothales and

175

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 175 3/17/2001 9:21:08 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

Lysis is relevant). Hippothales hopes Lysis thus, Socrates declares, ‘erôs and philia and
will feel affection for him (prosphilês, from epithumia [desire] are for one’s own’ (Ly.
philia), not erôs (cf. Plato Phaedrus 255d; 221E3–4; on the conflation of the three terms,
Aristotle Nicomachean Ethics 8.4,1157a6–9; cf. Cummins 1981; Robinson 1986:74–5).
Eudemian Ethics 7.3,1238b36–9; Dover But this too turns out to be a false lead, and
1993:197; Halperin 1993:418). By con- the dialogue ends in aporia. At all events,
trast, the relation between friends (philoi) friendship is clearly of interest only as one
was understood to be mutual. As Socrates species of affection (cf. Penner and Rowe
puts it, ‘unless both parties love, neither is a 2005; contrast Nichols 2009:169).
friend’ (Ly. 213A; cf. Aristotle Nicomachean Plato touches on philia again in the Laws,
Ethics 8.2, 1155b31–6a5; Hutter 1978:6). here too in association with erotic love and
The frame of the dialogue concerns erôs, not desire (Lg. 8.836E). He explains that we call
friendship. ‘dear’ (philon) what is similar in respect to
Engaging Lysis in conversation, Socrates virtue, and also what is dissimilar when one
asks whether his parents love him: the term party is in need of the other; in either case,
is philein (eran, the verb corresponding to when it is intense we dub it erôs (837A).
erôs, would be inappropriate, though ster- Plato’s attention is on erôs here, and more
gein, referring mainly to parental affection, particularly on pederasty (q.v., paiderasteia);
would have been possible). Socrates argues philia is incidental.
that they love him for what he knows and Like ancient Greeks generally, Plato often
is good at. Nothing prevents affection on contrasts friends and enemies (ekhthroi). But
this basis from being mutual, but Socrates is because the disjunction tends to be exhaus-
interested here in the cause of affection, not tive, the class of ‘friends’ may become so wide
in friendship per se. Socrates then inquires as to include (absent civil dissension) all fel-
what kinds of things are dear (philon, neu- low citizens (cf. 694–5, 708); indeed, taking to
ter), and proceeds to argue that friendship an extreme the adage that the possessions of
resides neither in one party loving another or friends are in common, Plato concludes that
being loved, nor again – and this is surpris- in an ideal state there will be no private prop-
ing – in both parties mutually loving each erty at all (Republic 424A, 449C). In Greek
other. Having overturned his own earlier one could speak of such solidarity as philia
description of friendship, Socrates consid- (cf. Aristotle’s politikê philia, Nicomachean
ers whether we love those who are similar or Ethics 8.11; Eudemian Ethics 1241a32–3),
different, and rejects both options; again, the but rendering the term as ‘friendship’ is mis-
focus is on the reasons for loving. In a series leading. In the R. (335), Socrates ventures
of subtle arguments, Socrates demonstrates the definition that a philos, properly speak-
that we love or desire something for the sake ing, is anyone who is good, an ekhthros one
of something else, for example, medicine for who is bad, but he goes on to affirm, against
the sake of health, but this leads to an infi- common wisdom, that it is not just to harm
nite regress – there must be some first or pri- anyone, since that is to make a person worse.
mary object of love (prôton philon). Socrates Plato is clearly undermining the conventional
finally suggests that we desire (epithumein) opposition of friend and enemy.
what we lack or have been deprived of, and Of course, the Greeks recognized more
this must somehow belong to us (oikeion); intimate degrees of friendship, and Aristotle

176

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 176 3/17/2001 9:21:09 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

denied that one could have many close on this idea under the title of the ‘exact itself’
friends (Nicomachean Ethics 9.10). But (284d; cf. Ferber 2002:190). But the idea of
unlike Aristotle, Plato did not investigate the good is treated explicitly only in the sixth
such friendship systematically, though he no and seventh book of the R. in the course of
doubt appreciated it: Socrates much admires, three similes, though caution is warranted:
for example, the bond between Lysis and his the Platonic Socrates gives in these similes
agemate Menexenus. When he visits Socrates only his ‘opinions without science’ (R. 506c)
in jail, Crito affirms that he will never again and even these opinions are incomplete
find such a companion (Crito 44B), and tries (506e1–3). First, he distances himself from
to convince Socrates to let him bribe the existing philosophical conceptions of the
jailer, since it is shameful to value money good, where the good consists in pleasure or in
more than friends. But for Socrates evad- knowledge (cf. 505b–c). Both conceptions are
ing the law is wrong, and so he refuses the refuted, one because there are also bad pleas-
aid proffered by his friends. So too, Phaedo ures (cf. Grg.499c6–7), the other because this
assures Echecrates that Socrates died in conception would be circular (cf. Euthyphro
the presence of many friends (Phd. 58C), 292e3): knowledge would be knowledge of
but he is amazed that Socrates conversed something, namely, the good. Second, the
with them unsentimentally, as on any other Platonic Socrates says positively three things
day (58E–9A). Though Socrates may have about the good: (a) it is not sought like ‘just
described himself, tongue in cheek, as an and beautiful things’ (505d), where we may
expert in ta erôtika, when it came to philia be satisfied also with the appearance, but as
what most interested him, and Plato, was the something which really is good. So we may
love of wisdom or philosophia. be conventionalists concerning the ‘just and
beautiful things’, but we are realists concern-
ing the good. We want not the apparent, but
the real good. (b) It is the final cause of all
GOODNESS (THE GOOD, AGATHON) that is good in desire and action (517b7–c4).
(c) The knowledge of the idea of the good is
Rafael Ferber the condition of the knowledge of just and
The good is for the Platonic Socrates that the beautiful things, that is, the ideas of jus-
for which everything is done (cf. Gorgias tice and beauty (506a). This means that if
468b). This is an ‘axiom’ to which Plato the ideas of justice and beauty were not also
seems to adhere during his whole writing good, they would not be ideas of real but
career (cf. Symposium 205e–6a, Republic only of apparent justice and beauty. Since
505d–e, Philebus. 65a). But the Socratic without knowledge of the idea of the good
good becomes for Plato in the R. the idea of no other knowledge is of any use to us (cf.
the good, which is also the ‘greatest thing to 505a2–3), knowledge of apparent justice and
be learned’ and the ‘greatest lesson’ (megis- apparent beauty would not be of any use to
ton mathêma, R. 505a, 519c). us. Therefore knowledge of the idea of the
We may find a first allusion to this idea in good is required to know the goodness and
the Lysis in ‘what we like in the first place’ usefulness of just and beautiful things.
(prôton philon, Ly. 219d), cf. Penner and These two negative and three positive (for-
Rowe (2005:278–9). The Politicus may touch mal) determinations are supplemented by the

177

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 177 3/17/2001 9:21:09 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

substantive description which the Platonic Socratic paradox that virtue is knowledge,
Socrates gives in the three similes. Common realize the good in the city (on all three simi-
to them is that the idea of the good figures as les cf. Ferber 1984:49–166, 1989:49–219;
cause (q.v.; aitia, 508e3.517b2) or principle Schindler 2008:139–75).
(archê, 510b7). In the simile of the sun (q.v.), The Phlb. starts with the search for a cer-
it functions as the cause of knowledge, truth tain state of the soul which can render the
and being, although it is itself not being (ouk life of all human beings happy (cf. Phlb.
ousias ontos tou agathou, 509b8–9), but 11d4–6). But it asks nevertheless the Socratic
‘surpasses the being in dignity and power’ question ‘. . . what in fact is the good . . .’
(epekeina tês ousias presbeia kai dynamei (13e5–6) and holds on to a ‘single form’ (mia
hyperechontos, 505b9–10). Thus Plato seems idea) of the good (65a1), which Socrates tries
to found his ontology and epistemology on to hold down with the conjunction of three
a supreme principle which – if the cause is qualities (poia): ‘beauty, symmetry and truth’
not the same as that which is caused – must (65a2; cf. Ferber 2010). In his old age, Plato
be ‘something else and more beautiful than seems to have held a public ‘lecture on the
knowledge and truth’ (508e5–6) and being good’, although this lecture may go back
(but cf. Baltes 1997; Ferber 2005; Seel 2007). to earlier ‘seminars’ or ‘synousiai’ ‘on the
We can see in this description of the good good’. (cf. Simplicius, in Aristotelis Physica
the inauguration of the problem of the third commentaria Phlb. 542.1012, 545.24). After
between and above being and thinking: As an anecdote reported by Aristoxenos about
light and its master, the sun, functions as Aristotle, the hearers of the lecture expected
a third item (R. 507d.e), so the idea of the to be told
good functions as a third item between and
above thinking and being. In the simile of the . . . something about one of the recog-
line (q.v.), the idea of the good, though not nized human goods, such as wealth,
mentioned there, functions as an unhypo- health or strength, or, in sum, some mar-
velous happiness. But when it appeared
thetical principle (anhypothetos archê) of the
that Plato was to talk on mathemat-
mathematical ‘presuppositions’ (hypotheseis,
ics and numbers and geometry and
510c6), that is, the four arts of the quadri- astronomy, leading up to the statement
vium (on the text of the simile cf. Lafrance that there the good is one (hoti tagaton
l994; on interpretations between l804 and estin hen), they were overwhelmed by
l984, Lafrance l987). the paradox of the whole matter. Some
The image of the cave (q.v.) shows us what then thought little of the thing and oth-
education means for Plato. It is ‘a leading of ers even reproved it. (Aristoxenus, The
the soul’ (psychês periagogê, 521c1) that is Elements of Harmony II)
also a return of the soul’s attention to the
really good. But the idea of the good func- In this lecture, Plato may have presented the
tions also as a principle of Plato’s politics so idea on the good in a dialectical way, where
that not only every soul in her private life, unity as we find it in the abstract structures
but ‘anyone who is to act sensibly in pri- of mathematics may have played a signifi-
vate or public must see it’ (510c). Because cant role (cf. Burnyeat 2000). From this lec-
the philosopher-kings and -queens know the ture, only fragments from notes taken by his
really good, they will also, in the sense of the hearers, especially from Aristotle, survive

178

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 178 3/17/2001 9:21:09 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

(cf. the collection of fragments in Gaiser we all do in fact desire the genuinely good
l963:441–557; Isnardi-Parente l997:406–84, things obtaining which will make us happy
l998:5–115; Krämer 1990:203–17). But we (Gorgias 468b; Men. 77b–8b; Republic
find in Aristotle’s Metaphysics a ‘short and 505d–e); evidence of this includes our pur-
principal’ summary (987a27, 988a17) of suit of what appears good, our loss of desire
the public lecture whose content Plato may for things once we learn they are not good,
have already communicated earlier to his and our efforts to determine what really is
advanced students (cf. Ferber 1989:211–16). good.
What are the genuinely good things the
possession and correct use of which make
us happy? In the Philebus, Socrates argues
HAPPINESS (EUDAIMONIA) that the good or happy human life con-
tains a mixture of knowledge and pleasure
Rachana Kamtekar (Phlb. 20d–2a). In the Grg. (470e) and R.
In contemporary usage, ‘happiness’ is some- bk 1 (354a), Socrates says that our happi-
times taken to be a feeling, as temporary or ness depends entirely on whether or not we
permanent as feelings are. In ancient Greek are virtuous, but at other times he makes the
usage, in contrast, eudaimonia, the term weaker claim that having virtue makes one
translated ‘happiness’, characterizes a whole happier than any of those who lack virtue,
life and not just a moment of feeling, and has no matter what else they have and one lacks
an objective dimension: the happy life not (R. 360e–2c, 387d, 392cd, 580b). The com-
only feels good to the one who lives it, but is parative claim allows nonmoral goods, such
good. Sometimes translators use ‘flourishing’ as health and wealth, to contribute to the vir-
instead; one ground for this is that not only tuous person’s happiness. (The case that the
humans, but other species as well, are said to R. makes only this ‘comparative’ claim about
flourish when they are in a good condition happiness’ relationship to virtue is made in
relative to their capacities, but it was for the Irwin 1995:191–3 and contested in Annas
ancients a philosophical issue whether eudai- 1999:84–7; the alternatives for relating hap-
monia ought to be conceived this way, and piness and virtue are canvassed in Vlastos
indeed whether a life of pleasure not only 1999.) To explain how virtue contributes to
feels good to the one who lives it but also happiness, the R. (443d–4e) describes justice
is the best life; the same philosophical issue as a harmonious condition of soul, analo-
arises today about happiness, and it cannot gous to health for the body and wisdom as
be settled by a translation (see Kraut 1979). the perfection of our best capacity, reason, in
Plato takes it as uncontroversial that all knowledge of the forms and especially of the
of us wish to be happy, that is, to live well form of the good (R. 518c–d, 504e–5a). In
(Euthydemus 278e; Meno 78a–b; Symposium both cases, the happiness described involves
205a). He does not mean by this that we both the satisfaction of desires and the pos-
wish that our desires, whatever they are, session of some genuinely good thing(s).
be satisfied; rather, happiness requires pos- On the grounds that happiness consists in
sessing, and correctly using, genuinely good contemplation of the forms, an activity which
things (Euthd. 280d). But happiness is not is interrupted by our bodily condition, Plato
divorced from desire-satisfaction either, for sometimes (e.g. Phaedo, Phaedrus) seems to

179

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 179 3/17/2001 9:21:10 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

restrict true happiness to life after death for justification consists in showing that the
philosophers. government is competent to make citizens
The universal desire for happiness serves as good or happy (Politicus 293a–e). (Kamtekar
the cornerstone of a number of arguments in (2006) and Reeve (1988) offer alternative
Plato: in the R., the (presumed) desire of his accounts of how happiness figures in politi-
interlocutors for happiness enables Socrates cal justification)
to justify being just on the grounds that being
just is (at least) necessary for our happiness;
in the Euthd., Socrates wins Clinias over to IDEA (see Forms)
philosophy on the grounds that wisdom is
the condition for benefiting from any other
goods (Euthd. 278e–82d); in the Protagoras, IMAGE (EIKÔN)
Socrates convinces a hypothetical major-
ity that what we call being overwhelmed by Richard Patterson
pleasure is actually ignorance on the grounds Images (eikônes) are of great importance
that no one knowingly goes for anything to Plato for several reasons. For one, the
other than what they judge best, viz., most traditional Homeric and tragic images of
pleasant (Prt. 352a–8d). Many scholars take gods, heroes, humans and the afterlife had
the desire for happiness to be a foundation for many generations exercised a corrupt-
that structures Plato’s ethics, committing him ing influence on all of Greek society, and the
to ‘ethical eudaimonism’, according to which reform of these images was of fundamental
to be rational, action must aim at one’s own importance for Plato’s vision of proper reli-
happiness (e.g. Irwin 1995). Some also take gious, civic and moral education (see esp.
Plato to be committed to ‘psychological Republic bks 2–3; cf. bk 10 for further criti-
eudaimonism’, the descriptive thesis that cisms of epic and tragic imagery). Second,
our actions in fact aim at our own happiness in that same general spirit of harnessing the
(e.g. Penner 1991). Yet Plato does seem to power of images to positive effect, Plato
consider some noneudaimonistic reasons for casts his own philosophical writings as ver-
action: the desire to reproduce, and thereby bal images of encounters among philosophi-
approximate, the immortality one desires cal ideas and theories, and of diverse choices
(Smp. 207a–9e); the love of beauty (Phdr. concerning how one ought to live, all fash-
249d–56e); the debt philosophers owe to the ioned so as to reveal to the receptive reader
city that educated them (R. 520a–e; White their true nature and value. Third, the rela-
2002 discusses this and other noneudai- tion of images to the ‘real things’ of which
monistic passages in Plato). they are likenesses furnishes Plato’s principle
Happiness is important to Plato’s political illustration of his radically counterintuitive
thought as well as his ethical thought. Thus, views about reality, understanding and value.
legislation should aim at the happiness of This brief article will focus on the second and
the citizens (Laws 743c; the R. uses the lan- third of these points.
guage of aiming at the happiness of the city Although the Platonic Socrates appears in
in order not to beg the question of whether different roles – refutational gadfly, barren
the citizens, who are virtuous, will thereby midwife of ideas, planner of the just city – he
be happy, see Kamtekar 2010), and political remains a philosophical counterweight to the

180

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 180 3/17/2001 9:21:10 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

great Homeric images of heroism and excel- whole. In all three spheres goodness lies in
lence: in philosophy lies the greatest agôn correct imitation or enactment (mimêsis) of
(struggle, contest) – that to discover and lead standards that obtain whether or not anyone
the best life. This requires not only wisdom or anything ever discovers or lives up to them.
and self-control, but also the traditional A philosopher can shape her own life in the
heroic quality of andreia (‘courage’, ‘stout image of wisdom, can fashion an image of a
heartedness’). For the philosopher must just city in words, and might, if put in charge
take on powerful advocates of false concep- as philosopher-king, create an actual city
tions of excellence and happiness (Homer, in the image of justice itself (R. 472, 540a,
Thrasymachus, Callicles, Protagoras), defend 592a–b). Analogously, the divine craftsman-
the truth even if his views meet with scorn creator of the world makes the best possi-
and ridicule (R. bk 5), persevere in the most ble likeness (eikôn) of his good, intelligible,
protracted and difficult of investigations and, model (paradeigma, Timaeus 29b), bring-
if need be, choose death rather than abandon ing rational order into an initial disorderly
philosophy (Apology; Phaedo). motion in the ‘receptacle’ (hypodoche; some-
The philosophic hero does not cease to thing like ‘place’, chora Ti. 49a–52c).
become an image of justice itself or wisdom; If a truly good life requires apprehen-
rather she becomes a true and accurate enact- sion and mimêsis (imitation, enactment)
ment or imitation (mimêsis; q.v. Imitation) of of eternal, immutable, world-independent
wisdom and justice. By contrast, the reput- standards of goodness, this requires in turn
edly wise Homer, along with the legendary that Plato’s new and radical metaphysics of
fifth-century sophists (literally, ‘wise men’) forms and worldly imitations be itself coher-
are not only distorted but deceptive imita- ent. But this has been in dispute since Plato’s
tions of wisdom. As the Sophist suggests, the own day. Putting aside a host of thorny sub-
latter appear wise only to the unwise, who ordinate issues, the central question is this:
are in no position to judge – just as colos- did Plato think of forms as perfect or com-
sal sculptures have their proportions clev- plete exemplars of various kinds of things,
erly altered so as to look right to those who and their worldly images as imperfect or
must view them from an inferior perspective incomplete examples? Or are forms abstract
(Sph. 235d, ff.). The philosophic mimêsis of entities that are not in general instances of
wisdom is a genuine likeness (eikôn) rather themselves – something like properties them-
than a semblance (phantasma), and so can selves (e.g. equality, justice, humanity) – with
help convey, to those adequately equipped to worldly images being things that embody or
respond appropriately, the true nature of wis- possess those properties? Both approaches
dom. Indeed, the philosophic life becomes an have advocates dating back to antiquity.
‘imitation of god’ (Theaetetus 176b), where (For two modern influential versions of the
divinity is invested not in scandal-ridden first interpretation, see Vlastos and Owen
Olympians, but in eternal, purely intelligible in Allen 1967; for defence of the second, see
standards of goodness. Allen and Cherniss in Allen l967; Patterson
These imperceptible but intelligible ‘forms’ 1985; Prior l985).
(q.v.) provide standards of excellence not On a ‘perfect/complete exemplar’ read-
only for individual lives but also for human ing of forms, worldly imitations are imper-
communities, and even for the cosmos as a fect copies or duplicates of forms. But this

181

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 181 3/17/2001 9:21:10 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

makes most forms into impossible objects. that Plato emphasizes repeatedly by use of
For example, humanity itself is both the per- the image analogy. On this second sort of
fect human being and a bodiless, impercepti- interpretation, then, the problems discussed
ble, purely intelligible thing. Or (on another above for the ‘image/model’ theory of the
version of this first type of reading) equal- relation between forms and worldly things
ity itself becomes a thing whose equality is do not arise. And one may safely and quite
‘complete’ in and of itself; equality is equal sensibly say that being a just person is not
without being equal to anything. Either way, a matter of trying to be, or almost being,
the theory is plainly incoherent. It also gives another form of justice, but of exemplifying
rise to an infinite regress of forms rather than or enacting in one’s life the eternal and objec-
a single form for a given property, as first tive nature of justice.
explained by Plato himself via the epony-
mous protagonist of his Parmenides (132a–b;
132d–3a). IMITATION (see Mimêsis)
But the image analogy in fact strongly sup-
ports a reading on which forms are abstract
natures and worldly imitations are embodi- INCONTINENCE (see Akrasia)
ments or enactments of those abstract
natures. The form of human itself, for exam-
ple, and its worldly images are related in the INSPIRATION
way that paintings, reflections, dreams and
verbal images of a human being are related Kathryn A. Morgan
to a living human being. Although the paint- Plato uses the concept of inspiration flex-
ing or reflection is rightly labelled ‘human’ ibly, although it plays a major role only in
(rather than ‘ox’) it is not a second human Ion and Phaedrus. The vocabulary of what
being at all, perfect or imperfect. Similarly, we call ‘inspiration’ was expressed in Greek
the flesh-and-blood human being is not a in various ways, as being ‘held’ by a divine
more-or-less imperfect copy of the intelligi- force, ‘breathed upon’ or (mostly) as hav-
ble form of human; on the contrary, it is not ing a god inside you, being entheos. As had
an intelligible (or eternal, immutable, bodi- been recognized for centuries, this was the
less) thing at all. Rather, it is an enactment force that motivated prophets and poets, and
or embodiment of the intelligible nature made their gifts ‘divine’. There does not seem,
common to all earthly humans. Both are however, to have been a consistent or sys-
rightly called ‘human’, but they are very dif- tematic theorization of inspiration prior to
ferent kinds of ‘human’ (R. 597b) – one the Plato. Even within his corpus we still find the
unique, nonspatial, immutable, intelligible vocabulary of inspiration being used loosely.
form of human, the other a spatial, chang- Phaedrus in the Symposium can speak of
ing and perceptible embodiment of the form. being ‘inspired’ by love to acts of courage
It is precisely this combination of a critical (Smp. 179a7–8). Socrates in the Philebus
kinship between image and model on the says that one who has been seduced by the
one hand, with the absence of garden-variety pleasures of discourse is also ‘inspired’ (Phlb.
resemblance between the two on the other, 15d4–e2) and in the Cratylus he has himself

182

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 182 3/17/2001 9:21:10 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

been ‘inspired’ to etymologize by Euthyphro discovery about politicians: they are reputed
of Prospalta (Cra. 396d2–5). By this assertion to be experts but speak without knowledge
he attempts to disclaim responsibility for the (21b9–c7, 22a8–9). This connection is made
material he presents. This strategy is central explicit in the Meno, where he concludes
to more developed treatments of inspiration that politicians succeed not through knowl-
elsewhere in the corpus. edge but by a kind of right opinion and in
As Murray (1981) has shown, early Greek this respect are just like prophets:
literature drew no dichotomy between divine
empowerment and individual skill; inspira- We could say that politicians, no less
tion was thus not irrational. Plato, how- than these, are divine and have a god in
ever, bases his entire theory of inspiration them; they have been breathed upon and
are possessed by a god when they speak
as ecstatic possession on this dichotomy and
successfully about many great matters
develops it in the Ion. There Socrates sug-
although they do not know what they
gests that poets are moved by a ‘divine force’ are talking about. (99d1–5)
(Ion 533d3) and that the Muse makes them
‘inspired’ and ‘divinely possessed’ (533e3–8),
but then expands the notion, suggesting that The focus in these passages is not so much on
a poet cannot compose until ‘his mind is no divine encroachment on an individual but on
longer in him’ and that god does this so that success achieved despite lack of knowledge.
mortals will know that it is not the poet (or The notion of inspiration thus gives Plato a
prophet) who is speaking, but the god himself way of critiquing poetic and political accom-
(534b3–d4). Socrates here deploys the strong plishment. It can even be deployed in an
contrast between human skill and divine force attack on Heraclitean philosophers, among
as a way of explaining the Ion’s inability to whom there are no teachers and pupils, but
provide any rational basis for his talents in who ‘arise spontaneously wherever each of
reciting and explicating Homeric poetry. As them happens to catch his inspiration, and
many commentators have seen, however, this none of them thinks the others know any-
view of inspiration, while couched as a com- thing’ (Theaetetus 180b8–c3).
pliment, is intended to disqualify poets from Plato was an important figure in the devel-
intellectual pretensions and discredit them opment of an abstract vocabulary of inspi-
as cultural authorities. Far from transpar- ration. The noun enthousiasmos appears
ently reflecting his society’s beliefs, Plato has first in Plato and Democritus (‘DK’ 68B18),
pushed them to a tendentious extreme. while the adjective enthousiastikos, the noun
The significance of this contrast stretches enthousiasis, and verb enthousiazô are first
beyond poetry and has political and philo- preserved in the Platonic corpus (q.v.). This
sophical implications. In the Apology reflects a general concern with the technical
Socrates again contrasts poetic inspiration analysis and criticism of poets in the second
with knowledge, and (as he did in the Ion) half of the fifth century, but also reveals how
connects poetry with prophecy (Ap. 22b8–c4). suggestive Plato found the concept.
Here, crucially, his comment that poets com- Phdr. marks the culmination of this inter-
pose not by knowledge but by inspira- est, where the model of inspiration found
tion is closely juxtaposed to his similar in the Ion recurs and is superseded by a

183

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 183 3/17/2001 9:21:11 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

philosophical counterpart. Inspiration is INTELLECTUALISM


prominent in the first part of the dialogue.
Socrates’ two speeches on love are presented William Prior
as inspired by various powers: the Muses, Intellectualism is a view attributed to Socrates
the Nymphs, Pan (among others). Moreover, in several of Plato’s Socratic dialogues that
the content of Socrates’ great palinode is treats certain mental states, in particular vir-
concerned with inspiration, insofar as the tue and vice, as states of the intellect alone,
speech starts with the observation that cer- and which, as a result, denies the existence of
tain traditional manifestations of madness moral weakness (akrasia; q.v.). Intellectualism
(q.v.) may be connected with the divine is especially prominent in the Laches, Gorgias,
realm and are beneficial. Among these are Euthydemus, Protagoras and Meno.
prophetic, ritual (‘telestic’), poetic and erotic
madness. Poetic madness, in particular, is (I) VIRTUE IS KNOWLEDGE
said to come from the Muses and be a form
of possession (Phdr. 244a6–5a5). So far, Perhaps the most prominent mental state
the model is the one familiar from the Ion, that receives an intellectualist treatment at
but once Socrates describes the fate of the the hands of Plato is virtue. In the La., while
soul before and after embodiment, things attempting to define courage, Laches comes
begin to change. Now we learn that the phi- up with a definition of what Socrates calls
losopher, when recollecting the forms seen ‘virtue entire’: knowledge of all goods and
while disincarnate, is often thought to be evils (La. 199c–d). Why is virtue knowledge?
out of his senses because the many do not The Men. provides the following argument:
see that he is ‘inspired’. Similarly the lover virtue is good, makes us good and is thus ben-
is ‘inspired’ to recollect the form of beauty eficial. Other goods, such as health, strength,
by seeing earthly beauty, and this is the best beauty and wealth, or the psychological qual-
of all types of ‘inspiration’ (or ‘enthusiasm’) ities moderation, justice, courage, intelligence,
(249c4–e4). Enthusiasm or inspiration is memory and munificence, are sometimes ben-
now seen as a psychic reaction to a like- eficial and sometimes harmful. What renders
ness of a form that carries one to the divine them beneficial is right use; what produces
realm. We thus move from a notion of inspi- right use is knowledge (understanding, wis-
ration as possession and incursion, where dom). Thus knowledge, as the only intrinsi-
the poet is a passive instrument of the god, cally beneficial quality a person can possess,
to a philosophical mode where inspiration is virtue (Men. 87b–9a). A similar argument
is associated with recollection (q.v.). In the occurs in the Euthd. (278e–82d).
best-case scenario of the Phdr. philosophi- The Prt. offers a detailed account of what
cal inspiration is married to reason and the is meant by happiness and wisdom, one
philosopher uses contact with the divine to that is unique to the Socratic dialogues. In
engage in systematic reflection. In the Phdr., an argument with the many, Socrates leads
then, Plato has returned to the coexistence them to admit that they regard pleasure as
of reason and divine experience that charac- good and pain as bad (Prt. 354c). Given this
terized earlier notions of inspiration, but this account of happiness, Socrates argues that
idealized combination exists not in the poet, wisdom is an art of measurement of pleasure
but in the philosophical lover. and pain (358a–b).

184

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 184 3/17/2001 9:21:11 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

(II) VICE IS IGNORANCE knowledge ‘as being utterly dragged around


. . . as if it were a slave’ (352c). The position
If virtue is knowledge, it is easy to understand shared by Socrates and Protagoras, in con-
vice as ignorance. In the passage of the Men. trast, is that:
discussed above Socrates states, ‘all that the
soul undertakes and endures, if directed by knowledge is a fine thing, capable of
wisdom, ends in happiness, but if directed ruling a person, and if someone were
by ignorance, it ends in the opposite’ (Men. to know what is good and bad, then he
would not be forced by anything to act
88c). The Euthd., in the same vein states,
other than as knowledge dictates, and
‘with respect to all the things we called good
intelligence would be sufficient to save a
in the beginning, the correct account is not person. (352c)
that in themselves are they good by nature,
but rather as follows: if ignorance controls
them, they are greater evils than their oppo- The most elaborate Socratic argument
sites’ (Euthd. 281d). The analysis of vice in against akrasia, of which the above claim is
the Prt. yields the following account of igno- a part, occurs in the Prt. and relies on the
rance as vice: assumption of hedonism (354b–d). The many
believe in akrasia because they believe that a
If, then, I said, the pleasant is good, no person knowing full well that a given action
one who either knows or believes other is more beneficial than another, will none-
things are better than the things he is theless perform that other action because of
doing, and possible, then does those
being overcome by pleasure (352d–e). On
things if he is capable of the better; nor is
the assumption that pleasure is the good,
the ‘being worse than oneself’ anything
other than ignorance and ‘being stronger Socrates shows that this view of the many
than oneself’ anything other than wis- does not make sense by substituting ‘good’
dom. (Prt. 358c. Tr. Prior) for ‘pleasant’ in their position. The difficulty
with this argument is that it only works on
This ignorance is identified as false belief; the the assumption of hedonism, and the Prt. is
belief in question is a miscalculation of the the only dialogue in which Plato advocates
magnitude of pleasure and pain involved in hedonism, even for the sake of argument.
a particular course of action, an error in per-
spective (356c–e). (IV) LATER DEVELOPMENTS

(III) NO ONE DOES WRONG WILLINGLY The intellectualist position described above is
prominent in the ‘Socratic’ dialogues, though
Perhaps the most paradoxical claim in the it is also present in Laws. The Republic
intellectualist position is the denial of akra- offers a different moral psychology and a
sia (q.v.), moral weakness. The phenomenon new theory of virtue. For some scholars (e.g.
of moral weakness is alleged to occur when Penner 2002) this change marks a transition
one, in full possession of knowledge of the between the view of the historical Socrates
best course of action, nevertheless chooses and the view of Plato. The major develop-
an inferior course, under the influence of ment in the R. that gives rise to the modifica-
some other mental state. ‘The many’ think of tion or abandonment of intellectualism is the

185

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 185 3/17/2001 9:21:11 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

introduction, in bk 4, of the tripartite concep- However, in bk 2 of the R., Glaucon presents


tion of the soul. The soul is divided into three the common opinion that humans have a
distinct parts: reason, spirit and appetite. strong motivation to take more than their
Whereas the intellectualist picture identified equitable share. Since all are equally vul-
as virtue as a whole with knowledge, the new nerable to suffering if each acted on such
theory allocates the virtues to different parts motivation, a community adopts rules to
of the soul. Closest to the intellectual concep- assure respect for persons and property (R.
tion of the soul is reason, to which is assigned 358e–9a). However, there is a problem with
the virtue of wisdom. The spirited part of the this account of justice. After all, if some-
soul is assigned the virtue of courage, while one – because of, for example, intelligence
the virtues of temperance and justice are allo- or strength – can act unjustly without being
cated to the three parts in combination (R. bk caught, he enjoys a significant advantage
4.442c–d). The Prt. had described wisdom as over the just person, who follows the rules.
a powerful force, capable of ruling a person; So, why should anyone want to be just who
the R., in contrast, describes reason, the seat is intelligent or strong enough to act unjustly
of wisdom, as requiring the aid of spirit if it is with impunity?
to prevail over the appetites (441e). Further, To answer the question, Socrates under-
whereas the Socratic dialogues had insisted takes to show that justice is beneficial to the
that every desire was for the good (cf., e.g. just person himself (357b). In developing his
Grg. 468b; also Kahn 2008:4 and Penner argument, Socrates’ goal is to show that jus-
2002:195), the R. defines thirst in terms of tice is beneficial for one’s soul. This signifi-
drink and warns against adding ‘good’ to the cant move relies on an idea, known in other
object of desire (R. bk 4.437d–8b). Despite moral systems, that the true value of justice
this new theory of the R., aspects of intel- is psychological; it affords an internal good
lectualism reappear in the dialogues gener- that outweighs whatever external advantage
ally considered late, in particular in the Lg. one can obtain by acting unjustly.
(5.731c; 9.860d) and Timaeus (86d; cf. Kahn In order to make this kind of argument,
1996:72n). This renders doubtful the claim Socrates needs an account of the soul (q.v.),
that Plato ever abandoned the central tenets which up until this point in Greek thought
of intellectualism. has been conceived of as simply the princi-
See also: Brickhouse and Smith (2009), ple of life. Socrates does something unprec-
Irwin (1977a), Nehamas (1999), Segvic (2002) edented by analyzing the soul as a structured
and Shorey (1903). whole of differing parts. In order to make
such an account accessible, he compares the
soul to the city, with its organization of differ-
ing parts (368e). Nevertheless, when Socrates
JUSTICE (DIKAION, DIKAIOSYNÊ) begins we realize that he is talking about an
ideal city, profoundly unlike Athens. In the
Richard D. Parry organization of this city there are three chief
Justice is the overarching theme in the functions; providing for the material life of
Republic. If people are to live in a political the city, ruling and war-making. The first
community, they must share equitably in compromises such crafts as farming, weav-
such goods as wealth and personal security. ing, cobbling, house building, animal herding

186

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 186 3/17/2001 9:21:11 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

and commercial trading, undertaken by those its particular function and not interfering
naturally suited to such work (369b–71a). with that of another. The function of reason
Ruling is carried out by people with a philo- is to rule in the soul, exercising forethought
sophical nature; war-making by those with for the whole soul. The function of the spir-
an aggressive and honour-focused nature but ited part is to be the ally of reason. Together
gentle to those they know (374e–6c; 412c–e). they keep guard over the appetitive part
Justice in the city consists in each class stick- so it does not try to rule (441e–2a). Justice
ing to the function for which its members are also respects the various functions. Guided
suited by nature and not interfering with that by wisdom, reason is a benevolent dicta-
of another (433b–d). tor, looking out for the welfare of the other
This account of civic justice may seem parts (442c). Thus, if reason tried to enforce
strange in that it entails not a distribution a policy of asceticism on the appetites or of
of goods but a distribution of functions. passivity on the spirited part, it would not
Further, the distribution does not depend be treating them justly because it would be
on a value like equality but rather on one’s frustrating their respective functions.
natural ability to fulfil the function. In this Justice in the soul, then, entails a healthy
account, justice is rendered to an individual integration of various interests or tenden-
when he is given the function for which he is cies – reason, spirited part and appetite.
suited by nature; justice is rendered to others While a soul so well organized enjoys a great
when he fulfils that function. It is clear that, psychological good, there still needs to be an
in this account, justice does not recognize or argument linking justice among the parts of
guarantee individual rights in the modern the soul to the common notion of justice as
sense. For starters, no one has the right to respect for persons and property. Socrates
decide for himself about his natural function. argues that injustice committed by an indi-
For Plato, however, individual rights are not vidual against another arises from injustice
so much suppressed as unknown. among the parts of his soul. Unjust acts (for-
After this account of justice in the city, bidden by law or custom) such as embez-
Socrates turns to justice in the soul. He zlement, betrayal of the city or of friends,
argues that the soul also has a tripartite struc- breaking oaths and adultery are impossible
ture with analogous functions for the parts for someone whose soul is justly ordered
(436a–41c). Reason (q.v.) is the part suited (442e–3e).
by nature to rule in the soul. The part cor- Not only does justice in the soul beget
responding to the producers is appetite (q.v.), lawfulness, the law of the city should have
primarily bodily appetites for food, drink and a role in establishing virtue. In the Gorgias,
sex. The part corresponding to the military is Socrates argues that lawmaking and judging
called the spirited part (thumos or thumoei- aim at what is best for the soul (Grg. 464b–d,
des). While contemporary readers will rec- 501a–c). Indeed, the good orator seeks to
ognize reason and appetite, the spirited part establish virtuous order and harmony in
is not so familiar. While it is the source of it; when the soul is disordered by undisci-
anger against others, it also becomes angry plined desires, his speech must curb them
against appetites when they urge wrongful (503d–5c). Finally, judicial punishment can
action. Finally, justice in the soul, like justice relieve the vicious soul of its injustice (478a–
in the city, is constituted by each part doing 80b). The novel idea that punishment has a

187

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 187 3/17/2001 9:21:12 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

function other than retribution is developed and Socrates notice language in defending
in the Laws. The Athenian Stranger argues views of nature and thriving, Plato is the first
that punishment for serious crimes should to devote sustained, systematic attention to it.
aim to cure the soul of the criminal. However, Many deem familiar linguistic usage mislead-
if the judges determine that a cure is not pos- ing, but only Parmenides repudiates it alto-
sible they should pass a sentence of death, gether. Stopping short of his Eleatic forebear,
which will rid the city of an evil doer and Plato’s metaphysical discovery of forms and
deter others (854d–5a, 862c–3a). their spatiotemporal participants leads him
The R. begins with the common idea to acknowledge a pronounced gap between
that justice is a relation among individuals, optimal and commonplace deployments of
defined by rules and the actions prescribed by terms, particularly those corresponding to
those rules. However, by making this kind of mathematical concepts and values.
justice the effect of what justice is really, that Through recollection (q.v.; anamnêsis)
is, a hierarchical structure among parts of the philosophers attain a grasp of reality wholly
soul, Plato has shifted the focus from justice independent of language, thereby returning
understood as kinds of right action to justice as fully as possible to the clarity attending
as a psychological disposition, that is, the forms’ initial discernment by souls alone.
way the parts habitually interact, from which Plato’s treatments of ontological, epistemo-
appropriate actions flow. Finally, by making logical and linguistic issues are deeply inter-
justice primarily a psychological disposition, twined: the fact that reality is comprised of
Plato is then able to make another argument, natural, stable unities enables understanding,
that is, that it is a more valuable disposition and this insight in turn powers philosophers’
to have than any of its rivals. A soul with the deployment of language.
disposition that results in its acting justly is Plato’s own theorizing on this topic
simply finer as a soul than one with the dispo- emerges with force in Cra. (q.v.), the first
sition that results in its acting unjustly. work of Western philosophy devoted to lan-
For further reading on justice, see Cooper guage, which investigates the claim that the
(2004), Irwin (1995), Kosman (2007), Kraut descriptive content of words or names (ono-
(1992b) and Vlastos (1971b). mata) reveals their referents’ natures (phu-
seis). While controversy persists over what
view of terms’ correctness Cra. envisions,
KNOWLEDGE (see Epistemology) many conclude that it rejects naturalism
based on descriptive content as an adequate
determinant of whether onomata are fittingly
LANGUAGE assigned. One requires a prior, independent
grasp of reality to assess terms’ semantic (or
Susan B. Levin phonetic) constitution since otherwise one
Plato’s reflections on language engage sub- can interpret even the most salient terms –
stantially with predecessors in philosophical, for example, epistêmê (‘knowledge’, Cra.
sophistic, and literary traditions. When revis- 412a, 437a) – through antithetical, ontologi-
ing existing views in more promising direc- cal prisms. Precisely that awareness, how-
tions, his concern is ever with the merit of ever, renders otiose the quest to grasp natures
ideas, not their source. While pre-Socratics through such linguistic study.

188

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 188 3/17/2001 9:21:12 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

While Cra. targets an etymological to forms’ explanatory power stems from the
approach to orthotês onomatôn (the cor- fact that F-ness, too, is F (e.g. Beauty is beau-
rectness of words or names), Phaedo debuts tiful, Phd. 100c), with some claiming that the
a revamped version of eponymy, prominent theory of forms emerges unscathed only if
in Greek literature, to provide the seman- their onomata do not carry unique descrip-
tics of the form-participant tie (see Levin tive force, serving instead as proper names or
2001:101–18). The primary referents of indications of identity. At this juncture, how-
terms for mathematical concepts and values ever, it is individual forms’ being what and
(e.g. triangular, beautiful) are transcendent, as they are that warrants the relevant terms’
separately existing forms (eidê). Their sec- application to them, and it is only because
ondary referents are forms’ participants, for forms’ onomata do so apply that partici-
example, Helen of Troy and Phidias’ statue pants’ appellations may derive therefrom.
of Athena, possessing a measure of beauty While Plato’s linguistic focus thus far is
through participation in the correspond- onomata, the late writings evince a fasci-
ing form (q.v. Participation, Forms), and are nation with logoi. As before, his pursuit of
thus properly named ‘beautiful’ (Phd. 102b, linguistic concerns takes its compass from
103b). The limits on participants’ beauty ontology. Whether or not Plato now sees a
(they are such in one regard but not another, problem with the metaphysics and accom-
at one time but not others, etc.) ground the panying semantics of earlier dialogues, his
restricted application of ‘beautiful’ to them. late writings take the weight off self-predi-
The form’s unblemished standing, in contrast, cation to mark forms off from one another
ensures that the term ‘beautiful’ applies to it (see Moravcsik 1973). This transpires in part
eternally, without constraint (Phd. 103e). Far through the method of division (diairesis, q.v.
from being tied to the form, hence nature- Method) – debuted in Phaedrus (265e–6c)
disclosing, through descriptive content, on and elaborated in Sophist and Statesman –
the view of many the link to phusis is via the according to which the natures of eidê are
onoma’s unique descriptive force. Though disclosed through logoi, more than mere-
Plato is solidly committed to terms’ legitimate ological sums, whose component onomata
twofold application, Phd., Symposium and join to distinguish each explanandum (e.g.
Republic underscore just how far philosophi- sophistry) from the rest. Though descriptive
cal awareness and linguistic usage diverge content may be relevant, as in Cra.’s con-
from the ordinary. While some, holding forms clusion terms merit does not hinge on their
to be universals, assume that eponymy offers constitution’s illumining natures (see Levin
a general theory of predication, the fact that 2008). Again, philosophers’ reflectiveness
not all common nouns and adjectives have equips them alone to assess and deploy lan-
eidê corresponding to them (R. 523a–5a; guage reliably. Dialectic qua division may
Parmenides 130c–d) means that eponymy uncover what is wrongly thought to consti-
cannot function in this capacity. tute elements of reality; such parts (merê) that
How far, if at all, the third man argument are not also kinds (genê) are undeserving of
(q.v. Prm.) calls the metaphysics and accom- onomata, which must therefore be excluded
panying onoma-based semantics of these from a true, or philosophical, lexicon. The
dialogues into question remains hotly con- centrality of onoma-deletion and -construc-
tested. On one interpretation, the challenge tion to Plato’s late philosophical method is

189

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 189 3/17/2001 9:21:12 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

yet another indication of the distance sepa- way is’ (to mêdamôs on) are synonymous.
rating philosophical deployment of language Since the difference is key to his handling
from ordinary, nontheoretical usage. of false statement, much hinges on how
Plato’s handling of falsehood in Sph. has heteron is construed. Sph. 256a–b is often
received tremendous attention. The soph- taken to focus on to mê on qua nonidentity
ist eludes the charge of speaking falsely if (e.g. change is not the same). In contrast,
so doing involves speaking of ‘what is not’, Sph. 263a–b, citing ‘Theaetetus sits’ versus
construed as synonymous with ‘what in no ‘Theaetetus flies’, appears (with 257b–8c) to
way is’. Plato’s defence of false statement’s involve negative predication. Yet, notoriously,
possibility rests ontologically on a discussion this discussion purports to recur to the line of
of forms’ interweaving, particularly the role thought set forth in Sph. 256a–b. Persistent
of the different (heteron), and linguistically queries abound: (a) Does the earlier reference
on a stipulation of statements’ divergence, not involve nonidentity after all? (b) Does
qua bearers of meaning, from names. The nonidentity somehow remain Plato’s focus
referents of both onomata (here, ‘subjects’ or or (c) does subsequent discussion expand
‘agents’) and rhêmata (variously rendered by to include negative predication while taking
scholars as ‘verbs’, ‘actions’, ‘affections’ and nonidentity for granted? (d) If heteron sim-
‘predicates’) are assumed to exist outside the ply means separate things at the two junc-
mind (261d–2c); Plato’s account therefore tures (e.g. ‘other than’ versus ‘incompatible
excludes formulations taking unicorns or with’), is Plato’s account of false statement
Narcissus as subjects. unsuccessful? To those answering (d) in the
Interpreters diverge on key points, includ- affirmative Plato is confused, not realizing
ing whether Plato distinguishes two or more that he has made a switch; to those denying
uses of esti (existence, identity, predication). jeopardy, the difference is innocuous or even
To those who (a) deem the third man argu- philosophically apposite.
ment worrisome when forms’ onomata apply Despite divergent constructions and assess-
with descriptive force and (b) contend that ments, many acknowledge the importance of
Sph. disentangles identity and predication, Plato’s distinguishing onomata and rhêmata
this distinction is a welcome innovation. as functionally different and essential com-
Scholars who conclude that awareness of dif- ponents of statements. Plato’s move away
ferent uses of esti is lacking in Plato disagree from using onoma to encompass ‘nearly
on whether he confuses existence and predi- all categories of words’ (Smith 2008:148)
cation, or predication and identity. Certain allows him to distinguish meaningfulness
commentators (e.g. Kahn 1966) stress that from truth value and hence jettison decisively
Greek does not demarcate existential and a name based, either or model of statements’
predicative uses of ‘is’ and that the absence of correctness. Plato’s insistence that genuine
differentiation is a boon to Plato’s account. statements bear meaning even when false is
Scholars even diverge on suitable terminol- widely viewed as a salient innovation, as is
ogy for the conduct of discussions (cf. Owen his distinction of true and false logoi from
1971 and White 1993). positive and negative ones.
In Sph.’s framework, difference supplants Scholarly debate on right terminology for
not being, allowing Plato to refute the view discussions of esti in Sph. reflects in micro-
that ‘what is not’ (to mê on) and ‘what in no cosm, a worry voiced by some that we go

190

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 190 3/17/2001 9:21:12 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

awry in our grasp of Plato by taking as the by human beings (see Guthrie 1971a). Some
touchstone of interpretation modern dis- evidently took this to imply that law or
cussions of logic and language. Though not morality has no real claim on us and would
everyone would agree where historical faith- be ignored by wise individuals if they could
fulness left off and anachronism began, it is do so with impunity (Republic 343c1–4c9).
salutary to distinguish between what suffices Others argued for something like a modern
as a response to Plato’s critical targets and the social contract theory. In order to avoid a
merit his inquiries might or might not have situation in which people can injure each
from our perspective. As these orientations other at will, human beings have agreed
are not mutually exclusive, some maintain to establish laws. They call what accords
that Plato’s theorizing succeeds admirably on with the law ‘just’ and what contravenes it
both counts. Regardless of one’s stance on ‘unjust’ and punish those who transgress
its degree of proximity to modern concerns, (358e2–9b5). Plato rejects such views. He
the observation of Frede (1992a:423) is apt: argues that justice (q.v.) is a fundamen-
We must not forget that ‘in his day Plato tal value and is not simply the product of
was dealing with almost entirely unexplored human decisions.
issues for whose discussion even the most In the R. Plato argues at length that being
rudimentary concepts were missing’. Against just is worthwhile in itself and is in our
this backdrop, Plato’s investigation of false interests even if it brings us poverty, deri-
statement – along with other semantic mile- sion or death. He elucidates this conception
stones gracing his dialogues – is a ‘singular by describing an ideally just city. In doing so
achievement’, indeed. he does not emphasize law, and focuses more
attention on the education of the philosopher
rulers who will govern the city. He even sug-
gests that people who have been properly
LAW (CONVENTION) (NOMOS) educated will not need laws to govern the
minutiae of personal relations or the details
Richard Stalley of commercial transactions (R. 425a8–6a4).
The Greek word nomos (plural nomoi) is Some commentators take this to mean that
standardly translated as ‘law’, but has a wider an ideal city with truly wise rulers would
meaning than the English word. It may refer need no laws at all. But Plato uses the word
not only to what we would call a ‘law’ but nomos in referring to the ideal city and even
also to any kind of custom or convention. So, makes Socrates refer to himself and his com-
Greek authors, including Plato, do not dis- panions as legislating (nomothetein) for the
tinguish sharply between law and social cus- city they are constructing in words (e.g. R.
toms or between law and morality (Ostwald 417b8, 456c1). Plato’s position may be that
1962:20–54; Stalley 1983:23–4). citizens who have been thoroughly educated
In the fifth-century BCE some thinkers in the principles on which the city is founded
began to emphasize the contrast between will not need detailed directions as to how
human laws or conventions (nomoi) and they should lead their daily lives. Equally,
what happens by nature (phusis). They there may be little need for mechanisms of
argued that laws or conventions do not exist enforcement. But that does not mean that
by nature but result from agreements made there will be no laws.

191

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 191 3/17/2001 9:21:13 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

In the Laws Plato describes what seems the individual (Lg. 862b1–3a2). But his code
to be a more practical ideal city. It does not draws heavily on Athenian practise and pre-
depend on philosopher-rulers but is, rather, scribes punishments of a conventional kind
founded on the principle of the sovereignty with little apparent scope for variation (see
of law. Genuine law is seen as the work of Saunders 1991; Stalley 1995).
reason (Lg. 713a9–15d6). In the city of the Plato’s treatment of law in the Politicus has
Lg. it is embodied in a detailed code laid proved particularly controversial (e.g. Lane
down by a wise legislator. The constitution is 1998:146–63, 197–201; Rowe 1995:15–18).
designed to ensure that law, thus understood, In that dialogue the Eleatic stranger likens
is always supreme. In particular, a compli- law to instructions left behind by a doctor
cated system of checks and balances ensures who has gone away or is otherwise unable
that those who hold office always conform to give individual advice to his patients. On
to the law. The ultimate aim of legislation is one line of interpretation, Plato is arguing
the common good of the city, which is under- that ideally the expert politician should rule
stood as requiring citizens to possess the without constraint but, where such a person
virtues of wisdom, temperance, justice and is unavailable, rule by law is a second best.
courage. The wise legislator will ensure that Indeed, a city without an expert ruler should
all the city’s institutions and laws are directed stick rigidly to its laws, even if the proc-
towards this goal (631b2–2d7). This means esses by which those laws are chosen are not
that education is a central concern but it also particularly rational. The Plt. has thus been
applies to every other aspect of life. These regarded as marking a transition between
points are illustrated with a detailed law the R. (seen as demanding the untrammelled
code, covering matters such as marriage and rule of philosopher-kings) and the Lg. Recent
the family, property, agriculture and trade, scholarship has cast doubt on this view. A
religious belief and practise, and crimes such key point here is that the account of law in
as homicide and assault. A distinctive feature the Plt. seems to stand apart both from that
is that laws are accompanied by persuasive of the R. and from that of the Lg. It is pos-
‘preambles’. The idea here is that it is bet- sible, therefore, that Plato sees the views he
ter if people are persuaded to obey the law puts into the mouth of the Eleatic stranger as
voluntarily rather than coerced into doing so significantly defective. As he sees it, genuine
by fear of punishment (718a6–23d4). There law is not simply a substitute for the deci-
are many examples of such preambles, some sions of an expert ruler and should not be
quite elaborate. It is a matter of controversy applied mechanically. It requires the right
among scholars whether these should be seen institutions and a properly educated popu-
as appealing primarily to reason or to emo- lace to preserve and apply it.
tion (see Bobonich 1992; Stalley 1994).
Plato rejects retributive accounts of punish-
ment and sees it as serving primarily to cure
criminals of their wickedness (Protagoras LOGIC
323c3–4c5; Gorgias 472d6–80b5; R. 380a
6–c3; Lg. 933e6–4c6). He suggests, there- Charles M. Young
fore, that judges should pay close attention Logic (following Quine 1986) is the system-
to the state of mind and circumstances of atic study of logical truth (or, equivalently,

192

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 192 3/17/2001 9:21:13 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

valid argument). A logical truth is a sen- say). The divergence between Plato and Frege
tence that is true in virtue of its logical form. emerges sharply if we note that the sentence
Logical form is relative to a set of grammati- ‘If justice is a virtue, then injustice is a vice’ is
cal categories, and logical systems may be presumptively a logical truth in the logic of
classified by the categories assumed to matter contrariety, but not in modern sentential or
for logical form. Since Frege (1879) the set predicate logic.
of categories thought to matter begins with Plato wrote dialogues and not treatises,
sentence and sentential operator, definitive of and he does not engage in any systematic
sentential logic and goes on to include term, study of logical form and truth, in the man-
predicate and quantifying expression, defini- ner, say, of Aristotle’s Prior Analytics (or even
tive of predicate or quantificational logic. the Topics), and thus cannot be said to have a
From there one may go on, in various ways, logic in the sense specified above (and hence
to develop temporal, modal, conditional, rel- ‘logic’ does not appear in the index of Kraut
evantist and intuitionist systems of logic. (See 1992a). What we get instead is a congeries
Burgess 2009 for a helpful survey and sharp of insights and speculations about what
assessment of such developments.) might matter for logical form and logical
Plato has the ideas of logical form and truth, often expressed in difficult Greek, that
logical truth. Republic 4.436b9, for exam- may or may not be capable of systematiza-
ple, affirms: tion. To give a sense of what we have and the
problems we face, I take up three texts that
Exclusion: It is not possible for the same deal in abstract and in various ways with
thing to do or to suffer contraries in the predication.
same respect, in relation to the same Socrates says at Euthyphro 6e3–6 that if
thing, or at the same time. he learned what the idea of piety is, he would
be able to use that idea as a standard and say
This is a kissing cousin of our: that an action or person that is such as [it is]
is pious. Here such as [it is] is a stab at trans-
Non-Contradiction: It is not possible for lating the Greek toioutos, a combination of
both a sentence and its negation to be the indefinite pronoun toios (= of some sort)
true. and the demonstrative pronoun houtos (=
this); other tries include of that kind (Grube
But whereas Non-Contradiction appeals to 2002), resembles [it] (Cooper 1974), agrees
the grammatical category of sentences to [with it] (Fowler D. H. 1999). Whatever the
tell us, for example, that if ‘Helen is beauti- translation, the idea seems clear enough.
ful’ is true, then ‘It’s not the case that Helen Socrates thinks that if:
is beautiful’ is not. Exclusion appeals to the
grammatical category of contrary to tell (1) Piety is (say) doing what the god wants
us, for example, that if ‘Helen is beautiful’ done,
and ‘Helen is ugly’ are both true, then she
is beautiful and ugly in different respects and if Socrates is such as [it is] – that is, if
(appearance vs. character, say), in relation to
different things (Quasimodo vs. Aphrodite, (2) Socrates is doing what the god wants
say) or at different times (youth vs. old age, done,

193

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 193 3/17/2001 9:21:13 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

then it follows that grammatical category of a relative term to


support the thought that thirst as such is for
(3) Socrates is pious. drink as such, and not for good drink, even
though all desire is for the good. Shorey’s
If we note that ‘is’ marks identity in (1) and translation ‘But I need hardly remind you’ (of
predication in (2) and (3), and that ‘doing’ is the particles alla mentoi with which Socrates
a gerund in (1) and a participle in (2), then it introduces the principle) anticipates the
follows that: incomprehension that Glaucon immediately
expresses. The principle requires over forty
(4) If piety is doing what the god wants done, lines for its elucidation.
and Socrates is doing what the god wants Whether Plato’s various scattered remarks
done, then Socrates is pious. on contrariety, predication and relation can
be brought under control and organized into
This evidently expresses a logical truth con- a coherent logical system remains to be seen.
necting noun phrases that mention proper- Some worthwhile work has been done – for
ties with terms mentioning things that have example Robinson 1966, Lloyd 1992a and,
those properties. most recently and most systematically, Dancy
So far, so good. Consider Charmides 2007. But there is still much to do.
169e1–5, where Critias, with Socrates’
endorsement, states that ‘[one] is such as
what he has: he who has quickness is quick,
and he who has beauty is beautiful, he who LOGOS (ACCOUNT, ARGUMENT)
has knowledge will know, and he who has (DEFINITION, STATEMENT)
knowledge that is of itself will know himself’.
Here ‘[one] is such as what he has’ is very Kenneth Sayre
close to a generalization of the logical truth The term logos in Attic Greek carries dozens
of the Euthphr. But two points might give us of meanings, many of which occur routinely
pause. First, the inference from ‘[one] is such in Plato’s writings. There are several occur-
as what he has’ to ‘he who has quickness rences, however, in which the term conveys
is quick’ arguably presupposes ‘quickness meanings with particular philosophic signifi-
is quick’, not unlike this English exchange: cance. Sometimes the significance is relatively
‘You’ll have to be quick to do that’ – ‘Quick? transparent, while in other cases it poses
I’m quickness itself!’. Second, we might balk, substantive problems. We begin with a few
though again Socrates does not, at the infer- transparent cases.
ence to ‘he who has knowledge that is of One unproblematic sense of logos is that
itself will know himself’. of reasoned argument or account. When
Anyone still on the bus at this point Socrates asks Protagoras for an explanation
will surely get off faced with R. 438a7–b2: of how virtue can be taught, the latter decides
‘Regarding things that are such as to be of to respond not by a reasoned account (logô
something, those that are of certain sorts are Protagoras 329C) but by telling a story (the
of something of a certain sort, and those that myth of Prometheus). Yet Socrates eventually
are just themselves are of something that is wins the disputation with an elaborately con-
just itself’, a principle that appeals to the structed argument (logon 361A).

194

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 194 3/17/2001 9:21:13 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

Another philosophically significant sense plus logos) where the problem is explicitly
is statement or judgement. In the Sophist, stated. The problem is to specify a sense in
statement (logos 262A) is defined as a com- which logos might convert true opinion into
bination of names and verbs and said to knowledge. Senses examined and found
possess both reference and truth value. And wanting are (a) mere speech, (b) enumerative
in his conversation with Phaedrus, Socrates account and (c) distinguishing characteristic.
examines what a true statement (alêthês A striking feature of this list is that none of
logos Phaedrus 270C) would say about the these three is a serious contender for the role,
soul’s nature. whereas more promising candidates (expla-
There is also the standard mathematical nation, reason, ground) appear to be delib-
sense of ratio or proportion (Republic 509D, erately avoided.
511E) where Socrates describes the ratio Nonetheless, we find Socrates acknowl-
(logon) on which the divided line is based. edging at Tht. 202D that knowledge requires
A further straightforward meaning is that both logos and true opinion. Basically the
of definition. Thus at the beginning of the same requirement is stated in several other
Theaetetus, Socrates invites the young math- contexts including Meno 98A, Symposium
ematician to formulate a single logos that 202A and R. 533C (see also Timaeus 51D–E).
applies to the many varieties of knowledge. Although the sense in question remains elu-
In Theaetetus’ subsequent conversation with sive, Plato seems to treat logos as a necessary
the Eleatic stranger, likewise, the two embark ingredient of knowledge.
on the project of capturing the nature of the Another problem associated with the
sophist in a clear definition (Tht. logô 218C). final hypothesis is what to make of the
Other occurrences of logos in this sense can ‘dream theory’, which Socrates examines
be found in the Phdr., the Laws and the at length before taking up the three senses
Seventh Letter. of logos mentioned previously. The theory
Closely related is the sense at Phaedo in a nutshell is that every composite thing
99E–100A where Socrates is describing consists of elements that can be named but
his so-called second best method of logos. not described, and that a description (logos)
The method consists of hypothesizing what can be given of a composite object by com-
appears to be the soundest judgement (logon) bining the names of its elements. While this
on a topic and then testing other statements sense of logos is more sophisticated than the
for agreement with it (for detailed analy- other three, its relevance to the rest of the
sis, see Sayre 1995a:ch. 5). This use of the dialogue is not apparent. For one thing, it
term is comparable to that at Tht. 151E, is not obvious how true opinion about an
where Socrates expresses appreciation for object could be converted to knowledge
Theaetetus’ initial account equating knowl- by adding a description in terms of its ele-
edge with perception. In such contexts the ments. Other puzzles debated by commenta-
term logos can be understood to mean con- tors are the source of this ‘theory’ and why
jecture or hypothesis. Plato used so much space (four-and-a-half
We turn next to senses that are philo- Stephanus pages) at the end of the dialogue
sophically significant but more problem- in discussing it (for a detailed discussion,
atic. A noteworthy case comes with the final see Bluck 1956; Burnyeat 1970; Fine 1979;
hypothesis of Tht. (knowledge is true opinion Sayre 1969).

195

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 195 3/17/2001 9:21:13 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

Beyond these puzzling occurrences in ingrained’ logos has potential not only
Tht., appearances of the term logos in other of growing into fully fledged philosophic
writings pose problems of a seemingly more knowledge but also of spreading to other
basic nature. Following his discussion of souls through the medium of dialectical dis-
the mathematical curriculum in R. bk 7, course. Perhaps, the dialectical logos of R.
Socrates attributes to dialectic the power to coincides with the soul-bound logos of Phdr.,
grasp forms through the exercise of logos (R. in that both mature in a mental grasp of the
532A). Proceeding thus, Socrates continues, eternal forms.
the dialectician is able to reach the limit of One sense of logos not found in Plato (as
the intelligible world and to grasp the nature in Heraclitus and the Stoics), however, is that
of the good itself. This description of dialec- of ordering principle in a rational universe.
tic occurs against the background of three Plato’s closest approximation to such a prin-
famous images depicting various aspects of ciple is the world soul of Ti., which is not
the philosopher’s quest: (a) the sun (q.v.) as described as a kind of logos.
the visible analogue of the good which is the
ultimate source of being, (b) the divided line
(q.v.) representing the soul’s ascent to the
intelligible forms and (c) the cave (q.v.) dram- LOVE (ERÔS)
atizing the attainment of knowledge and the
philosopher’s responsibility to the state. This D. C. Schindler
background makes it clear that the philoso- Love (erôs) – one of the only things Socrates
pher’s quest is consummated with a grasp of claims to fall under his expertise (Symposium
the good through logos, which accordingly 177d–e; cf. Theages 128b; Lysis 204c) – rep-
might be designated the ‘logos of dialectic’. resents the primary theme in the two so-
Moving beyond the gorgeous rhetoric of called erotic dialogues, the Phaedrus and the
R., however, we find other texts that seem Smp., though it also plays a significant role
to deny logos this exalted power. One is the in the Republic.
Ep. 7, where the author explains why philo- Love appears as essentially ambiguous
sophic understanding cannot be conveyed in in the R. On the one hand, Plato calls it a
language (Ep. 7 logôn 343A). In this expla- ‘tyrant’, presenting it as the most intense
nation, the author states explicitly that logos of the soul’s base desires (R. 403a, 439d).
is inadequate to express the mind’s grasp of On the other hand, Socrates identifies love
the good (342D). Whatever the dialectical for knowledge of unchanging being as the
logos of R. might be, it cannot be communi- defining characteristic of the philosopher
cated verbally. (485a–b, 490b). In the one case, then, love is
Another Platonic writing disclaiming the what imprisons us in a lawless dream world
ability of language to convey philosophic (576b), while in the other case love is what
understanding is the Phdr. One legitimate draws us to the real. Plato typically uses the
use of written discourses (presumably includ- plural when speaking of the tyrant’s ‘loves’,
ing the dialogues) nonetheless, as Socrates and calls philosophical love, by contrast,
remarks, is to provide reminders of another ‘true erôs’ (490c), but he does not explicate
kind of logos (Phdr. 276E) inscribed in the the precise nature of the difference themati-
soul of the budding philosopher. This ‘soul- cally in this dialogue.

196

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 196 3/17/2001 9:21:14 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

Greater light is shed on this ambiguity in soul – which Socrates depicts as a winged
the Phdr., in which Socrates presents two chariot, with a charioteer (reason), an obe-
speeches on love as a response to Phaedrus’ dient horse (noble passions) and an unruly
reading of a speech by Lysias. In the first, one (base passions) – towards its proper
Socrates reformulates, with more order and end. Because it thus serves to ‘bridge’ the
clarity, the view of love presented in the prior difference between the transcendent and the
speech by Lysias, and in the second, a ‘pal- bodily, the notion of beauty and its correla-
inode’ or recantation, he corrects the first, tive love, that Plato presents in the Phdr. is
directly stating, ‘There is no truth to that seen by some as the hinge concept of his
account’ (Phdr. 244a). Socrates begins the philosophy in general.
first speech by defining love as a ‘desire for The most elaborate exposition of the
beautiful things’ (237d) – or, more specifi- nature of love in Plato’s work can be found
cally, the ‘beauty of bodies’ (238c) – and goes in the Smp. It contains six speeches on
on to associate it with a desire for pleasures love, followed by a speech by Alcibiades on
that runs counter to our ‘acquired opinion Socrates (who thus seems to personify erôs).
that strives for the best’ (237d–e). This love Scholars do not agree whether it is legitimate
is similar to the ‘tyrant’ that appeared in the to identify Plato’s own view of love with any
R., insofar as it is a force that seeks to domi- particular account, though a certain prior-
nate its object; it always leads to excess, and ity is generally accorded to Socrates’. The
it is essentially opposed, as a ‘madness’, to most famous speech is no doubt that given
the order and unity of reason. by Aristophanes, who expounds a myth to
The palinode, which is one of the liter- explain the origin of love: originally spheri-
ary gems in the Platonic corpus, begins with cal beings were divided by Zeus because of
the claim that madness can be beneficial if their haughtiness, and each fragment now
it is a ‘gift from the gods’ (244a) – that is, seeks his or her other half in order to recover
‘madness’ need not be sub or anti rational, the original unity. Socrates’ speech – in which
but may also be supra rational, and so in he recounts a conversation he had with the
principle able to include reason. This view prophetess Diotima and so sneaks in, as it
of love requires a revision of both its sub- were, the only woman ‘present’ in the group
ject and object: the soul is interpreted as (cf., Smp. 176e) – is nevertheless the most
having a transcendent origin and destina- comprehensive, insofar as it takes up ele-
tion, and the beauty that provokes erôs is ments from the other speeches, ordering and
no longer a merely physical object, but now correcting them as it proceeds. In contrast
an essentially transcendent reality that dis- to Agathon’s view of love as the supreme
tinguishes itself from all the other intelligi- beauty, Diotima begins by showing that, as
bles by being also accessible to bodily sight a desire, love is essentially constituted by a
(250d–e). Socrates memorably expresses need or lack (200a–b), though she distin-
love, thus understood, as the ‘wings’ that guishes this from complete absence. Instead,
carry the soul from its mundane state to in line with the account in the Phdr., love
the sphere ‘beyond the heavens’, the realm appears as a ‘spirit’ that mediates between
of ‘really real reality’ (247c). Love, in this the human and divine and so connects
case, is not simply one of the soul’s desires, them (202d–3a). It is identified with neither
but is in fact the movement of the whole complete fullness nor complete emptiness,

197

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 197 3/17/2001 9:21:14 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

but is the child of Penia and Poros (poverty Finally, one encounters beauty in its absolute
and plenty) (203b–c). existence, that is, not as relative to anything
Also like the account in the Phdr., the at all. This beauty in itself is presented as the
(efficient) cause of love is beauty, though cause of all the foregoing instances of beauty,
Diotima redescribes its object as goodness in and described as completely transcendent of
order to provide its final cause (204e). As a any beautiful thing, no matter how noble, as
desire for the good, love thus turns out to be beyond what appears to the senses and to
the truth of any desire whatsoever, since all reason, and as incapable of diminution or
desires aim at their objects insofar as they change (211a–b).
are good. Whereas Aristophanes explained Scholars have claimed that this description
erôs as a desire for completion, and thus as of beauty contradicts the beauty in the Phdr.,
essentially relative to the needy soul, Diotima which is an intelligible object that is also
shows that this need itself must be defined physically visible – but there is no reason in
in turn by the good in itself (205e–6a). But principle why it cannot both lie beyond the
the desire for the good in this complete sense mind and senses and be accessible to them
is in fact a desire for eternal goodness, so (for the transcendent form of beauty presents
that Diotima is able to specify the purpose itself in the Smp. at every level up the ‘lad-
of love further as ‘begetting in the beautiful, der’). Nevertheless, Plato does not himself
both in body and in soul’, for reproduction address this problem directly. Scholars also
is a mortal image of immortality (206b–7a). complain that Plato’s account in the Smp.
This allows her to explain a variety of phe- excludes the possibility of love for individu-
nomena in the animal and human worlds, als, though others have argued that Diotima’s
which had been alluded to in the previous speech can be read as describing an increas-
speeches, in relation to the single desire for ingly nonpossessive love, which can in prin-
immortality. ciple still be had for individuals.
Before elaborating what has come to be
known as the ‘ladder of love’, Diotima con-
fesses to Socrates that the ‘final and highest’
mystery of love is one that might exceed his MADNESS AND POSSESSION
capacity (210a). Some scholars have read this
as Plato’s indication of where his philosophy Silke-Maria Weineck
departs from that of his teacher. Diotima The theme of madness serves several distinct
presents an itinerary for the achievement of functions in Plato’s dialogues. When linked
love in its purest sense: one begins by loving to poetry, as in Ion and Phaedrus, madness as
beautiful bodies, first one and then all bod- divine inspiration or possession (theia mania,
ies insofar as they are beautiful; then, one enthousiasmos) allows Socrates to develop a
forgets bodies and learns to love souls and distinction between poetry and philosophy.
their deeds in noble actions and laws; and While poetry appears as a unique utterance
thirdly one comes to love knowledge of vari- the production of which is neither the result
ous sorts. In other words, there is a move- of specialized knowledge nor subject to the
ment from physical, to moral, and then to poet’s conscious control, philosophy emerges
intellectual beauty (which corresponds to the as the controlled, repeatable and teachable
three parts of the soul elaborated in the R.). labour of thought.

198

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 198 3/17/2001 9:21:14 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

At the same time, madness provides a cor- that is of interest. The madness that mat-
rective to overly rationalist thought. Thus, ters, then, is nearly always a form of divine
Socrates’ ‘inspired’ second speech in the interference or possession, an intervention
Phdr. refutes the cynical argument of the first into what we might call conventional human
one. In the Republic, the example of madness subjectivity, and Plato’s two most important
serves to undermine the definition of justice dialogues on madness, Ion and Phdr., take
as the habit of paying one’s debt and speak- considerable care to distinguish it both from
ing the truth: various forms of technê of speaking (e.g.
rhetoric, dialectics, psychagogia).
[I]f a man takes weapons from a friend Ion struggles to preserve an understand-
when the latter is of sound mind, and ing of rhapsody as a skill or craft (technê)
the friend demands them back when he that necessarily presupposes knowledge
is mad, one shouldn’t give back such
(epistêmê) of the poetic product he delivers.
things, and the man who gave them back
Socrates contends that the accomplishments
would not be just, and moreover, one
should not be willing to tell someone in of rhapsody rest on divine inspiration, and
this state the whole truth. (R. 331c–d, that the rhapsode performs in a state devoid
trans. Bloom) of knowledge, sovereign skill and reason
(epistêmê, technê, nous). He develops that
In the Ion, Socrates persuades the eponymous theory in the famous monologue about the
rhapsode to recant the mercenary account magnetic chain of divine inspiration linking
of his craft (‘if I set them to crying, I shall poet, rhapsode and audience. This speech
laugh myself because I am making money, contains the Ion’s most quoted lines: ‘For the
but if they laugh, then I shall cry because of poet is a light thing, winged and sacred, una-
the money I am losing’, Ion 535e) in favour ble to make poetry before he is enthused and
of a model of divine inspiration, for ‘to be out of his mind and intelligence is no longer
held to be divine is far finer’ (Ion 542b, trans. in him’ (Ion 534b). Though long neglected as
Bloom). a minor piece – Pangle (1987) calls it one of
Third, the question of divine – or quasi- the ‘forgotten dialogues’, and Goethe (1796)
divine – possession is at stake in Socrates’ called it a ‘persiflage’ of enthusiasm – the
daimonion (q.v.; Apology 31d, 40b–c; Phdr. Ion nonetheless presents interpretative chal-
242c, 242b), the enigmatic inner voice lenges worth exploring (Tigerstedt 1970),
that at times is said to negatively guide his particularly when read as a disquisition not
speech and actions and further complicates on poetry but on rhapsody. In this light, the
the notion of Socrates as the philosopher of central concern of the dialogue is not the
self-possessed reason (Burkert 1985:178–81; nature of poetry but the question of poetry’s
Destrée and Smith 2005; Gall 2009). guardianship. If the possessed poet is him-
In general, Plato shows little interest in self dispossessed of reason and knowledge,
madness as an illness; in the Phdr. he distin- the meaning of poetry needs to be mediated
guishes between ‘two kinds of madness, one by those who are not poets themselves. As
resulting from human ailments, the other Ion loses his argument, philosophy emerges
from a divine disturbance of our conventions as the first form of a practise that will even-
of conduct’ (Phdr. 265a, trans. Hackforth), tually become known as literary criticism
and as in Ion, it is only the nonsomatic kind (Weineck 2002:19–31).

199

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 199 3/17/2001 9:21:15 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

While Ion operates with a notion of poetic not only as compatible with philosophy (Phdr.
inspiration that may be an already well worn 278c–d) but perhaps as philosophy’s neces-
cliché, the Phdr. develops a far more com- sary precondition (Weineck 2002:32–44). In
plex account of various forms of madness: other words, the Phdr.’s philosophy of mad-
prophetic, ritual, erotic and poetic mania, ness solves, if ambivalently, the problem of
sent, respectively, by Apollo, Dionysus, Eros the origin of meaningful discourse.
and the Muses. The dialogue is notoriously Neither written nor spoken, the prohi-
complex, consisting of three speeches that bitions of the daimonion (q.v. Daimon)
weigh the benefits that lovers and nonlovers constitute a genre of its own that escapes
provide to boys or young men. In the third the various taxonomies of logoi Plato pro-
speech, Socrates revokes the praise of the poses. It is the daimonion that prevents
ostensibly rational nonlover and extols the Socrates from leaving after his first speech
virtue of erotic madness as a path to the rec- and prompts Socrates’ recantation or pal-
ollection (anamnêsis) of the forms – provided inode of cynical reason (if we can call it
that the mad lover can restrain his physical that): ‘This story is not true’ (Phdr. 243b).
desire and thus transform the relationship Truth, or more precisely the recantation of
into one of shared discourse. nontruth, then, depends in its origin on the
Socrates’ account of madness reverses the event of words without a speaker, an event as
steadiest assumptions of madness held in unforeseeable and incalculable as the event
modern times. As ritual it is a remedy instead of divine madness.
of an ailment; as prophecy it imparts the
most reliable intelligence instead of the most
unreliable; as erotic madness it leads to per-
fect attachment instead of perfect solitude. MATHEMATICS (MATHÊMATIKÊ)
Madness is neither excluded from nor an epi-
sode in or a footnote to history. In fact, mania Christine J. Thomas
seems to hold a central place within what we Plato’s ‘encounter with geometry was to
might call the different orders of history – the prove no passing infatuation, but a love
history of the individual, of the great families, match, a lifelong attachment as deep as it
of the state, of the nation, of the human soul. was intense’ (Vlastos 1991b:130). Plato’s
In the Phdr., all of them, in various ways, fascination extended to number theory, har-
depend on the interlude of madness – just as monics and astronomy. Though the degree
they depend on madness to be nothing but an to which Plato was himself an accomplished,
interlude. At the same time, mania interrupts practicing mathematician is disputed, he is
the usual progression of things and termi- credited in antiquity with facilitating math-
nates the course of causality: in the Oresteia, ematical progress and even directing major
clearly the backdrop of Socrates’ example of lines of research (Cherniss 1951; Fowler
Dionysian mania, only madness can stop the 1999; Proclus 1970; Simplicius in De Caelo
self-perpetuation of ancient pollution. 488.20–4). Famously, the entrance to Plato’s
This is not to say that the Phdr. breaks with Academy is said to have borne the inscrip-
the Ion’s tendency to privilege philosophy tion, ‘Let no one who is ungeometrical enter’.
over inspiration as intellectual and rhetorical The exact nature and details of Plato’s attach-
technê, but certain forms of madness emerge ment, however, are difficult to discern. The

200

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 200 3/17/2001 9:21:15 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

precision, methodical rigour and intellectual moves from given principles to conclusions.
authority of successful mathematical proofs Plato self-consciously mimics both geometri-
surely appeal to Plato; but it is not easy to cal analysis (Men. 86e3ff.) and geometrical
identify the features of particular mathe- synthesis (Phaedo 100a1–1e7) in philosophi-
matical strategies or results that impress him cal inquiries that proceed ‘from hypotheses’
most. Moreover, although mathematical edu- (Mueller 1992).
cation is regarded as propaedeutic to philoso- Of particular interest to Plato, however,
phy, any effort to determine exactly how or is the idea that an investigation might ulti-
why mathematics is assigned this role quickly mately light on something ‘unhypotheti-
becomes an attempt to solve a provocative cal’. For although rigorous investigations
mystery. At best, we can confidently say that from hypotheses might gain some epistemic
Plato deems mathematics a rich resource for entitlement to their results, those results
pursuing his first love: dialectic (q.v.). are nevertheless conditional. Even the most
Plato often looks to mathematics for inspi- successful mathematical proof fails to yield
ration. Philosophical attempts at definition the highest kind of understanding (noêsis)
are to emulate the account of ‘the even’ as ‘the so long as it begins from hypotheses which
part of number that is not scalene but isos- are not themselves sufficiently epistemically
celes’ (Euthyphro 12d8–10) or the definition secure (R. 533b6–c2). For Plato, a consist-
of ‘powers’ (i.e. incommensurable lengths) ent mathematical science is not guaranteed
as ‘the lines that square off oblong numbers’ to yield truth, and convincingness is not suf-
(Theaetetus 148a7–b2). Indeed, some of the ficient for genuine understanding (Cratylus
dramas played out in Plato’s dialogues con- 436c8–d8; R. 510c1–d3, 533b1–d1).
stitute historical evidence of developments Ultimately, a nonmathematical (or metama-
and struggles in the geometry of incommen- thematical), dialectical inquiry must discover
surability (Men. 82b–5c; Tht. 147c7–8b2), ‘the unhypothetical first principle (archê) of
stereometry (Tht. 148b2; Republic 509d6–8, everything’ thereby providing epistemic foun-
528a6–b5; Timaeus 53dff), and harmon- dations for mathematical and philosophical
ics and astronomy (R. 528e3–31c4; Ti. investigations at once (R. 511b5–7).
32c5–40d5; Laws 821b5–2c9). Though the What, then, is the relation of mathematics
full import of Plato’s appeals to mathemati- to philosophy? For dialectic discovers epis-
cal accomplishments is often difficult to temic grounds for mathematics, but math-
unpack, he clearly aims to illustrate the sorts ematical study appears to be an essential
of approaches and results he hopes for in phi- element of any educational curriculum that
losophy (Burnyeat 1978, 2000; Heath 1981; aims to produce dialectically capable indi-
Knorr 1989; Lloyd 1992; Netz 2003). viduals (R. 522c–31d, 533a8–10). Like the
As for mathematical method, Plato most most important philosophical objects and
explicitly calls on geometry. A successful truths, the objects and truths of mathemat-
geometric analysis either discovers premises ics are discovered, for Plato, not constructed.
required to complete a proof of a purported Mathematicians do not ‘make their figures,
conclusion or it identifies construction pro- they simply discover those which already are’
cedures to solve an articulated construction (Euthydemus 290c1–3). In the R., Socrates
problem (Menn 2002). Geometric synthesis comments on the absurd, though unavoid-
reverses the direction of investigation and able talk of practicing geometers who speak

201

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 201 3/17/2001 9:21:15 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

of ‘squaring’, ‘applying’ and ‘adding’ as if educational curriculum of the R. comes to


they are actually making and acting on their understand the governing principles of the
figures (R. 527a6–b6). In fact, mathematical richly mathematically constituted cosmos
arguments are for the sake of apprehend- described in Plato’s Ti. The truths of the pure
ing eternal, unchanging entities by means mathematical sciences are also the metaphys-
of thought alone. Number theory, geometry, ical truths grounding the unity, structure and
pure harmonics and pure astronomy facili- motions of the cosmic soul and body, and of
tate the soul’s cognitive contact with being every soul, body and ordered entity in the
or ‘what always is’. In the ideal case, then, cosmos (Burnyeat 2000). Grasping ultimate
mathematical study turns an inquiring philo- mathematical truths is, then, to grasp ulti-
sophical soul away from the changing percep- mate physical and metaphysical truths; it is
tible realm towards the realm of unchanging, to begin to understand how the cosmos has
imperceptible, eternal beings. Ultimately, the been mathematically structured by a divine,
R.’s mathematical curriculum prepares a soul intelligent craftsman. Moreover, where the
for cognition of the most important beings imposition of mathematical structure pro-
available to thought alone, Plato’s forms duces unity, order, concord, harmony and
(q.v.; e.g. justice, beauty and goodness). intelligibility, it also produces goodness (Ti.
On the one hand, Plato is not alone in 29d7–30a6, 53a7–c1, 68e1–6; Phlb. 64d9–
taking mathematics to supply paradigmatic 5a5). The study of organizing mathematical
examples of cognitions that are significantly principles is, in some sense then, the study of
independent of sense experience. Like many goodness (Burnyeat 2000; White 2006).
in the so-called rationalist tradition, Plato Finally, for Plato, any soul that is capa-
regards the mind or soul as having cogni- ble of understanding cosmic structure and
tive capacities through reason alone to grasp motion must be like the cosmos; it must
purely intelligible objects or truths, to recog- itself be mathematically structured. Insofar
nize that such objects or truths are eternal or as a soul’s motions can become assimilated
necessary and to see why eternal or necessary to cosmic psychic motions, it can become
truths are true (i.e. to recognize what a pri- intelligent. The flourishing human soul is the
ori justification or entitlement to such truths one that has (among other things) studied
might be available). On the other hand, for geometry, astronomy and harmonics, thereby
Plato, mathematical study has a particularly making possible the alignment of its motions
important and surprising role to play. For, the with the divine motions of the cosmic soul
ultimate aim of mathematical education is (Ti. 47b5–e2). To become so aligned is to
successful apprehension of a particular form, become like god, to become intelligent and
the form of the good (R. 526d8–e1). For happy (Ti. 90b6–d7).
Plato, the form of goodness (q.v.) itself plays
the role of the unhypothetical first principle
of everything; and mathematical study, along
with dialectic and practical political experi- MEDICINE (IATRIKÊ)
ence, somehow make cognition of this form
possible (R. 531c6–d4). Mark L. McPherran
Some of the surprise perhaps diminishes Plato’s attention to the craft of medicine,
in noting that the one who masters the which is conceived of as a paradigmatic

202

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 202 3/17/2001 9:21:15 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

instance of expert knowledge that lesser theory of the soul (q.v.) is fairly minimal: it
fields should imitate (Gorgias 464a–7c), is is that in us, separate from our bodies, that
evident throughout his work (e.g. Phaedrus is the subject or agent of moral judgement,
268a–70d; Republic 403d–10b; Politicus choice and action – that wherein vice and vir-
292d–300a; Timaeus 64a–92c; Laws tue reside (Cri. 47e–8a). It is the entire, real
889b–e). This is made particularly clear by self: the ‘I’ of consciousness and personality,
his various uses of the analogy of soul to and the part of us that engages in intellectual
body, of psychic health to somatic health (e.g. activity. It is also more important than the
Crito 47a–8b; Grg. 463e–5d; Phdr. 270a–e; body, and, like the body, can be harmed to
Sophist 223e, 226e–30e; Plt. 292e–3c) and so great an extent (by false moral beliefs or
the microcosmic and macrocosmic concep- wrong acts) that one might no longer have a
tion of human nature found in the Ti. – a life worth living (Cri. 47d–8a; Grg. 479b–c).
conception that parallels the similar one To care for this entity in the manner of a
found in the Hippocratic work On Regimen physician – that is, employing an analogous
(Jouanna 1998:70). Indeed, some take the expert knowledge (technê (q.v. Art)) – is to
frequency and force of the analogy to show endeavour to make it as good and happy as
that Socrates (s.v.) and Plato were the inven- possible by improving it in respect of virtue
tors of ‘scientific verbal psychotherapy’, and guarding it from the harm of vice, a task
beside whom ‘Gorgias and Antiphon are accomplished through correct philosophical
mere prehistory’ (Laín Entralgo 1970:137; training, elenctic testing and virtuous action
cf. 126; cf. Moes 2000). (Cri. 48a–8d; Grg. 467c–81b). Although
In Plato’s day medicine was just emerging medicine is an important technê in com-
as a science from its religious, magical roots. parison to the ‘knack’ of cookery, since the
Hippocrates started off as an Asclepiad – soul is more important than the body, phi-
born ten years after Socrates on Kos, the losophy is a more important field of knowl-
site of one of the four major healing temple- edge than medicine in the final analysis (Grg.
hospitals of Asclepius. The clinical work and 464a–6a).
success of the Hippocratic school, however, The medical analogy also shows up in
dates for the most part from the time sub- the Charmides, where Socrates is presented
sequent to Hippocrates’ departure from Kos to young, beautiful Charmides as a ‘physi-
and its temple (Jouanna 1998:27, 30–1). cian’ with a cure for his morning headaches.
Plato understands Hippocratic medicine Aroused by the youth, Socrates claims to
to hold that illnesses result from an imbal- know a medicinal leaf, a pharmakon, but
ance in the body of the four humours – flu- one that is only effective if accompanied by
ids that are equal in proportion in healthy the singing of the charm (epôidê) that goes
individuals (Timaeus 82a–6a). When these with it. Socrates then endorses the view of
humours (blood, black bile, yellow bile and those successful holistic Greek physicians
phlegm) are not in balance, sickness results. who do not attempt to cure eyes by them-
Hippocratic treatment focused on restoring a selves, but ‘. . . try to treat and heal the whole
proper balance (see further, and on medicine and the part together’ (Chrm. 156c). Socrates
in philosophy, Pellegrin 2009). next reports that he learned his charm while
Two prominent uses of a medical analogy with the army, from one of the physicians
are found in the Cri. and Grg. Here Socrates’ of the Thracian king Zalmoxis (156d–7c).

203

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 203 3/17/2001 9:21:15 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

He tells Socrates that Greek physicians are Diotima to insist that true physicians – unlike
acceptably knowledgeable, but that they Eryximachus – must be philosophers who are
often forget that just as one ought not to pious by accepting the primacy of a philo-
attempt to cure the eyes without the head, or sophical erôs that will lead them towards the
the head without the body, so neither ought Platonic project of ‘becoming like god’ (Tht.
one to attempt to cure the body without 176a–7c; see further McPherran 2006; q.v.
the soul . . . for the part can never be well Piety; Religion; Love). Socrates seems cast as
unless the whole is well. One should begin such a physician when he is likened to a mid-
by curing the soul, something done by using wife who helps deliver beautiful ideas in the
words that produce moderation in the soul Tht. (148e–51d).
(Chrm. 156d–7c; cf. Phdr. 269e–70e on this The Philebus also employs Hippocratic
and Hippocratic method). Some have identi- notions (emptying, repletion and homonoia)
fied these charming words as those spoken in its analysis of pleasure (Phlb. 31a–3c;
by Socrates during his subsequent elenctic 44b–9a) in order to address its central topic,
examination of Charmides and Critias; but namely, the search for that ‘state or condition
in any event, by the end of the dialogue, of the soul that can render the life of every
Socrates emerges as a subtle diagnostician man a happy life’ (11d). It has even been
of both men’s lack of moderation, charac- argued that if we follow this medical sugges-
ter defects so deep that neither of them can tion by construing the dialogue to offer a diag-
profit from further association with Socrates. nosis of the ‘disease’ of hedonism, followed
The dialogue has also communicated the by an account of the philosophical cure for
idea that philosophical ‘treatment’ is more it, we can understand how its puzzling transi-
central and more valuable than mere physi- tions and digressions actually contribute to a
cal treatment. coherent overall unity (Moes 2000:113–61).
It is natural to suppose that at least one of Whether or not that is so, it has also been
Plato’s purposes in employing the character of observed by scholars such as Dorothea Frede
the physician Eryximachus in the Symposium that the dualistic account of erôs as a physical,
is to convey the import of his own under- medical phenomenon we find outlined in the
standing of medicine insofar as it bears on the Smp. at 185e–9d makes a brief cameo appear-
central topic of that dialogue: erôs. Although ance towards the end of the Phlb. account of
some have taken Eryximachus to be a bombas- the fourfold division of all beings (23c–7c),
tic dogmatist who serves primarily as a target where there occurs what is arguably an allu-
of Platonic satire, others argue that his speech sion to the goddess Aphrodite (26b–c; Frede
‘is not a caricature but rather an historically 1993:23, n. 1; see further Dorothea Frede
correct picture of a [Hippocratic] medical 1992; McPherran 2010).
man of that time’, Edelstein 1945:91). He does Besides using medical analogies, Plato is
indeed give a Hippocratic medical account – interested in medicine per se in determining
but also a grand universalizing account of how the medical theories of his day might
erôs – one that takes in both the realm of be squared with his own theories of nature
nature and that of the gods. Moreover, it is a and the human constitution, and what role
theory supported by such stars of pre-Socratic physicians would play in the idealized states
science as Heraclitus (Smp. 187a–c). Here, it of the R. and Lg. In his R., for example,
has been argued that Plato subsequently uses Plato employs his health analogy once he has

204

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 204 3/17/2001 9:21:16 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

established that justice is good in itself, by If we look at both Plato’s depiction of


claiming that justice and injustice are ‘in the Socrates and Plato’s explicit description of
soul what the healthful and diseaseful are in his method, we notice three distinct phases
the body; there is no difference’ (R. 444c). of Plato’s account – the elenctic phase, the
But here Plato seems less willing than he hypothesis phase and the collection and divi-
was in, say, the Grg. to view medicine as a sion phase – each of which corresponds to a
standalone technê. By arguing for a tripartite common division of the dialogues into early,
soul of intellect, spirit and appetite in R. bk middle and late, whether or not these phases
4, Plato is led to see the ‘intertwining of soul indicate a development in Plato’s thinking on
and body in the cases of spirit and appetite’ method (q.v. Developmentalism).
(Levin 2007:147). The result is that the prac-
tise of medicine must come under the purview (I) THE ELENCTIC PHASE
of the philosophical rulers of his Kallipolis,
who will guide physicians in their treatments In dialogues like the Euthyphro, Laches,
so as to maximize the overall goodness of Charmides and Protagoras, Plato depicts
this ideal polis (Levin 2007). Here, as in the Socrates as engaging in a series of short ques-
Smp., the primacy of philosophical treat- tions and answers with various interlocu-
ment in comparison to medical treatment for tors. In every case, these interlocutors have
Plato is made clear. Meanwhile, Hippocrates some claim to knowledge of some relatively
laboured to free medicine ‘from the yoke of important matter. Euthphr., for example,
philosophy’ (Pellegrin 2009:667). claims to know both that prosecuting his
father is a pious action and what piety itself
is. Socrates’ questioning is aimed at testing
METAPHYSICS (see Ontology) the reputed knowledge of these interlocutors.
This questioning method (the elenchos) has
the following structure:
METHOD
(1) Socrates asks the interlocutor a ques-
Hugh H. Benson tion the answer to which, p, is meant to
For Plato, philosophy is the love of wisdom. exhibit the interlocutor’s wisdom, usually,
It is the search for and attempt to acquire but not always, concerning the definition
knowledge of the most important things. of some moral concept.
Following Plato, I will be using ‘wisdom’ and (2) The interlocutor provides answers, q, r and
‘knowledge’ interchangeably. To engage in s to a series of other Socratic questions.
such a search methodically is to systemati- (3) Socrates goes on to show that these answers
cally – purposively and repeatedly – attempt entail the negation of the original answer.
to acquire such knowledge. Clearly, Socrates (4) Thus, the conjunction (p & q & r & s) is
is not always engaging in this sort of behav- false.
iour. Sometimes, for example, he is sim-
ply attempting to persuade the jury of his The elenchos is not aimed at acquiring knowl-
innocence. Nevertheless, Plato often depicts edge, but at testing the reputed knowledge
Socrates as attempting to acquire knowledge of another. Moreover, its conclusion asserts
and to do so in a systematic way. only the falsity of a conjunction (i.e. that

205

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 205 3/17/2001 9:21:16 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

p, q, r and s are inconsistent) and not the (2) by examining the consequences of q to
falsity of one of the conjuncts. If Socrates is determine their coherence.
to come to know that one of these conjuncts
is false (and so that its negation is true) by In the R., Plato explains that the first part of
means of the elenchos, he must take the other the second stage, which is simply the applica-
conjuncts to have some special epistemic tion of the first stage on the ‘higher hypoth-
status. Unfortunately, Socrates’ descriptions esis’, q, is to be repeated on successively
of this method suggest that the conjuncts ‘higher hypotheses’ until one reaches the
all have the same epistemic status. The only ‘unhypothetical first principle’. This latter
property the conjuncts must have is that the appears to be the form of the good. In addi-
interlocutor believes them. As a method for tion, Plato describes the second part of the
acquiring the knowledge one lacks the elen- second stage in terms strongly reminiscent of
chos looks ineffective (perhaps confirmed the elenchos. Only when one pursues both of
by Socrates’ profession of ignorance near these confirmation procedures to their limit
the end of his life in the Apology, despite a can one genuinely be said to have acquired
lifetime of searching). (For a famously differ- the knowledge sought.
ent interpretation of the Socratic elenchos see
Vlastos 1981.) As a method for eliminating (III) THE COLLECTION AND DIVISION PHASE
one’s false conceit of knowledge, a neces-
sary first step in seeking the knowledge one In the Phaedrus and the Philebus, Plato
lacks, the elenchos plays an important role in describes a further method known as collec-
Plato’s philosophical method. tion and division, which he depicts at length
in the Sophist and the Politicus. It too con-
(II) THE HYPOTHESIS PHASE sists of two stages.

In the Meno, Socrates asks how it is possible to Stage 1: collect together a scattered plurality
acquire knowledge (Men.’s paradox, 80d–e). into a unity.
In various places in dialogues like the Men., Stage 2: divide the unity one has collected
Phaedo, Republic and Parmenides Plato also along its natural divisions.
depicts Socrates as describing and practicing
the hypothetical method as an answer. This In some dialogues, Plato appears to require
method consists of two stages in attempting to that the division that takes place in the sec-
come to know the answer, p, to some impor- ond stage be done dichotomously. In other
tant question (e.g. ‘Is virtue teachable?’). places, however, he appears to allow for a
more open-ended division.
Stage 1: find a second proposition, q, whose It has sometimes been thought that the
truth is necessary and sufficient for the method of collection and division was
truth of p, and show how q entails p. intended by Plato to replace the hypotheti-
Stage 2: confirm the truth of q: cal method of the so-called middle dia-
logues. But the appearance of the former
(1) by finding a third proposition r whose method in the Phdr. makes such a view dif-
truth is necessary and sufficient for the ficult to sustain. As a consequence, Plato’s
truth of q, and method of collection and division must be

206

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 206 3/17/2001 9:21:16 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

understood as an alternative method to In Cra. Socrates calls language itself


the hypothetical method or as an exten- mimêtic (Cra. 414b, 422e–7d): the ‘primary
sion of or an addendum to the hypothetical names’ of things were putatively based (by
method. the hypothetical name giver) on natural like-
nesses between individual sounds and aspects
(IV) DIALECTIC of reality. But mimêsis embedded in seman-
tics is differentiated from mimêsis in musical
Plato’s philosophical method is often referred (including poetic) and visual art: the latter is
to as dialectic (q.v.), a kind of working taken, not without simplification, to represent
through in words; but this should not be only the sensory properties of things, whereas
understood as indicating a distinct method the former captures their essence (ousia).
from those we have just described. Rather, Socrates allows visual images to be ‘correct’
Plato tends to call ‘dialectic’ whatever method or ‘incorrect’, but not, unlike discourse, true
he is recommending at the moment. It is bet- or false (430a–1d). Correctness here denotes
ter to take Plato’s philosophical method (his something like basic resemblance, a qualita-
dialectic) to be the combination of the three tive not a mathematically exact relationship
phases we have outlined, although how they to objects (432a–d). Philebus, by contrast,
are to be fitted together into a single method gives the idea of an image quasipropositional
for acquiring knowledge is a matter of con- force by characterizing thought itself as inner
tinued controversy. discourse (logos) accompanied by ‘paintings
in the soul’ (Phlb. 39b–40b), a sort of illus-
trated book (38e–9b). Here the terminology
of mimêsis is not used for mental images
MIMÊSIS (IMITATION) themselves, though it is used to describe the
‘false (i.e. ethically mistaken) pleasures’ asso-
Stephen Halliwell ciated with misconceived mental states (40c).
The vocabulary of mimêsis, conventionally Such pleasures are hardly ‘imitations’ of true
but often inadequately translated as ‘imita- pleasures, more like defective surrogates (cf.,
tion’, is found in numerous Platonic contexts, e.g. Politicus 293e, 297c for comparable
applied to matters ranging from everyday life usage).
to speculative metaphysics. Its most signifi- The Republic approaches questions
cant use occurs in a series of dialogues from of artistic mimêsis from shifting angles.
Cratylus to Laws in connection with two Socrates categorizes all visual, musical and
philosophical topics: first, questions relat- poetic arts in the ‘city of luxury’ as kinds of
ing to the representational and expressive mimêsis (R. 2.373b); they form a cultural
capacities of poetic, musical and visual art; fabric of image-making and dramatic pre-
second, the epistemologically problematic tence. Later, however, he temporarily restricts
relationship (construed in terms of image and poetic mimêsis to one particular mode of dis-
original) between representation in general course, that is, first person, direct speech, as
and reality. Mimêsis is a hallmark of certain opposed to third person narrative. He dwells
Platonic habits of thought. There is no such on the psychic assimilation (‘self-likening’)
thing, however, as a single Platonic theory of which this requires of performers of such
mimêsis. poetry (3.392d–8b), stressing the ethically

207

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 207 3/17/2001 9:21:16 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

destabilizing consequences of intense imagi- mimêsis to ontological emptiness. Yet the


native identification. The concept of mimêsis tragic poet, disparaged with other mimêsis
is applied (again) to music at R. 399a–400a, artists at 597e, is later said to produce works
where Socrates acknowledges a debt to which overcome the souls of ‘even the best
Damon in positing the expressive power of of us’ (605c–d): mimêsis remains psycho-
rhythms and melodies to convey equivalents logically powerful. Rather than diagnos-
to states of soul/character and even the ethi- ing a crude flaw in the argument, we can
cal qualities of ‘a life’ (399e–400a). read the rhetorically provocative critique
Although mimêsis is glossed at R. 393c by of mimêsis in bk 10 as exposing art’s own
appeal to vocal or bodily impersonation, the deeply paradoxical combination of imagina-
various stages of the argument entail more tive pretence with emotionally compelling
than a concept of imitation. Mimêsis involves seductiveness. Socrates admits nostalgia for
ways in which material media (shapes and the latter (607c–d); he leaves open the ques-
colours, musical sounds, speech, the body) tion whether it can be harnessed, as 3.401a–e
can communicate meaning through corre- suggested, to ethically beneficial ends.
spondence to, or simulation of, objects or In the Sophist, ‘the mimêsis’ is a large,
states of affairs (real or imagined). But the diverse class of activities (Sph. 234b). But
extension of the concept fluctuates; its con- in order to trap the sophist himself as an
ditions are never clearly defined. Moreover, impostor, the argument imprints mimêsis
the limitation of artistic mimêsis to purely in general with suspicions of the false and
sensory properties at Cra. 423c–d is ignored; fake: the production of ‘simulacra’ (eidôla,
music’s expression of emotions and charac- 265b). Visual mimêsis in particular is used
ter traits demonstrates that point; and there as an analogy with which to construct a
is a broader hint of mimêsis qua embodi- dichotomy between ‘original’ and ‘image’
ment of ethical values in artistic form at R. (q.v.). But Sph. complicates matters by dis-
399e–401a. tinguishing between ‘eicastic’ (objectively
Fluidity in the scope of mimêsis helps to accurate) and ‘phantastic’ (perspectivally
explain why in R. 10 Socrates returns to adjusted) mimêsis (235c–e); it even con-
the subject and now asks what ‘mimêsis as templates mimêsis informed by knowledge
a whole’ consists in (595c). But bk 10 adds (267b–e). While condemning the sophist as
new puzzles. Socrates develops an analogy a ‘counterfeiter of reality’ (235a), therefore,
between poetry and painting; the notorious the dialogue allows for superior and inferior
mirror analogy at 596d–e seems to restrict forms of mimêsis (cf., e.g. Plt. 300c–d).
mimêsis to mere replication of appear- Variation between positive and nega-
ances. The idea of mirroring clashes, how- tive paradigms of mimêsis occurs through-
ever, with depiction of gods and Hades at out Plato’s work. If the sophist consistently
596c, as well as with earlier references to marks the second pole, the status of mimêsis
idealized painting (e.g. 5.472d, 6.500e–1c). art wavers between mere ‘play’ (e.g. Plt. 288c,
Moreover, a tripartite scheme of unchang- R. 602b) and a power to change the soul. Lg.
ing reality (‘forms’, q.v.), material particulars (esp. 2.653c–71b, 6.764–7.817) contains
and mimêtic simulacra (596–7: influenced, intricate attempts to appraise artistic mimê-
though not precisely matching, the metaphys- sis with multiple criteria, including those of
ics of the middle books) apparently relegates artistic form, ‘correctness’ of depiction, and

208

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 208 3/17/2001 9:21:17 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

a mixed psychology of pleasure and ethical not work for concords smaller than the
judgement. Plato’s own writing has a mimêtic octave, so Plato divides the ratio of the fourth
dimension and can figure itself as a rival to (4:3) diatonically, that is, into two tones and
poetry (Lg. 817e; cf. Critias’ remark, Criti. a semitone: 9:8, 9:8, 256:243 (Ti. 36a8–b5;
107b–d). Some passages go further (provid- Wersinger 2008a:171–4). Harmonics takes
ing a cue for Neoplatonists like Plotinus; account of the ratios of intervals in scalar sys-
q.v. Neoplatonism) and gesture towards tems (Phlb. 17d1–4) corresponding to notes
the thought that all reality may be built on (phthongoi, R. 443d7–e1); in the conjunct
mimêtic correspondences: see the relation- system (sunêmmenon), two fourths are inter-
ship between bodily and transcendent beauty woven in the middle, producing a seventh
at Phdr. 251a, or the notion (influenced by (9 : 8, 9 : 8, 256 : 243, 9 : 8, 9 : 8, 9 : 8,
Pythagoreanism: cf. Aristotle Metaphysics 256 : 243). In the disjunct system (diêzeug-
987b11–12) of the entire cosmos as mimê- menon) the two fourths are separated by a
sis of a timeless model of being (e.g. Ti. 38a, disjunctive ratio (9:8) yielding a fifth within
39e, 50c). an octave (Wersinger 2008b:288–96). Such a
system (9 : 8, 9 : 8, 256 : 243, 9 : 8, 9 : 8,
9 : 8, 256 : 243) structures the world’s soul
(Ti. 36a).
MUSIC Harmoniai, or patterns of tuning (often
translated ‘modes’) attributed to Damon
A. Gabrièle Wersinger (West 1992:174) were initially irregular
Plato’s philosophy is concerned with music scales with ethnic names (R. 398d11–9c3).
not only as a metaphor (Phaedo 61a3; The notes and intervallic ratios of the Dorian
Republic 531d8–9) but as a model for phys- harmonia, for example, exceeds the octave:
ics, psychology, education, politics and
dialectics. re mi mi+ fa la si si+ do mi
Harmonics, as in the curriculum of the rul-
9/8 28/27 36/35 5/4 9/8 28/27 36/35 5/4
ers (R. 531a1), applies a mathematical method
(logistikê) to music based on numerical rela-
tions (logoi and analogiai). Musical concords (The + indicates a note raised by less than a
are epimoric (n+1:n) or double ratios (2n:n), semitone.) Theorists tried to reduce the har-
though not all epimoric ratios are concord- moniai to a system at the end of the fifth-
ant; discords are epimeric ratios (nm:n) (R. century BCE (Barker 1989:15), and Plato
531c3–4). These ratios play a central role in criticizes one such attempt (R. 531a4), per-
the generation of the cosmos in Timaeus. Plato haps that of Eratocles (described by Barker
knew from Archytas that one may supply a 1982:189).
missing geometrical mean, G, in the ratio of In Plato’s own system, his model for dia-
an octave (2:1) by using the fifth and fourth lectics (Phlb. 17c11–d4), four notes compris-
as arithmetic mean, A, and harmonic mean, ing a diatonic fourth delimit four harmoniai
H, that is, G2 = A · H (Ti. 31c5–2a7, 36a1–4). (Dorian, Phrygian, Lydian and Mixolydian)
He gives the world’s soul the structure of a that give rise to four others (R. 400a7),
‘musical proportion’ (Epinomis 991a5–b5; fourths to fourths: Dorian-Hypodorian,
Heath 1921:86–90). But this method does Hypophrygian-Phrygian, Hypolydian-Lydian

209

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 209 3/17/2001 9:21:17 PM


9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 210

TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES


Plato’s Systems of Harmoniai

Hypodorian Hypophrygian Hypolydian Dorian Phrygian Lydian Mixolydian Hypermixolydian

nêtê fa
9:8
paranêtê fa mib
9:8
paramesê fa mib reb
256 : 243
mesê fa mi re do
9:8
lichanos fa mib re do sib
9:8
parhypatê fa mib reb do sib lab
256 : 243
hypatê fa mi re do si la sol
210

9:8
nêtê fa mib re do sib la sol fa
9:8
paranêtê mib reb do sib lab sol fa
9:8
paramesê reb si sib lab solb fa
256 : 243
mesê do sib la sol fa
9:8
lichanos sib lab sol fa
9:8
parhypatê lab solb fa
256 : 243
hypatê sol fa
9:8
3/17/2001 9:21:17 PM

proslambanomenos fa

intervallic ratios 9:8 9:8 256 : 243 9:8 9:8 256:243 9:8
TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

and Hypermixolydian-Phrygian (Ptolemy among the harmoniai because they accustom


in Barker 1989:336). Those fourths build a the soul to all emotions, including harm-
diatonic conjunct octave (9 : 8, 9 : 8, 256 : ful ones (R. 395b9–7c6; Lg. 800d3). The
243, 9 : 8, 9 : 8, 256 : 243, 9 : 8) organizing so-called new music introduced by com-
eight systems of harmoniai from Hypodorian posers of dithyramb or tragic poets such as
to Hypermixolydian. In the illustration of Agathon, Euripides or Timotheus (Wersinger
Plato’s system below, notes and intervals are 2001:78–82; West 1992:356–66) leads to the
listed vertically, and tonoi are horizontal. The decay of the state (Lg. 700a3–1c5).
systems generate one another by cyclic reor- Although audible music is inferior to har-
dering of the intervals, moving up from the monics (Ti. 47c8–9; R. 522a), it helps to cor-
bottom. The highest pitch of the Hypodorian rect the disharmony inherent in sensation
octave coincides with the lowest pitch of the (Ti. 43a5–3d8, 47d5–6). In the choral city
Hypermixolydian octave so that in the nêtê of Lg. (664c4–d4, 665b5), expert musicians,
all pitches are similar (homotonon, Phlb. probably members of the nocturnal council,
17c4 and R. 617b7). are able, thanks to numbers, to adapt har-
When harmoniai are heard, they generate moniai and rhythms to rational forms of
emotions in the mortal soul, corresponding virtue (670b2–6, 963c7, 964d2, 967e2–3).
to the heart’s being stressed or relaxed (Ti. Elsewhere, however, if harmonics helps the
69c1, 70d5). The tuning of the strings of the soul in its conversion (periagôgê, R. 518d3)
lyre (Phd. 86c3–4; Wersinger 2010) influ- towards intelligible reality, dialectical knowl-
ences the ‘strings’ of the soul (R. 411b4). edge of the good (R. 534e2–5) remains inac-
Spiritedness (375b8) is softened by music cessible to harmonics.
(411b1; Protagoras 326b2–4), but too much
music excessively slackens it, producing cow-
ardliness (411a9–b5; Wersinger 2007:58–9).
To compose a melody (melopoiia) one has MYTH (MUTHOS)
to select the rhythms and harmoniai (Smp.
187d1–2) appropriate to the specific gen- Luc Brisson
res of song (Lg. 700b1–c1), for example, In ancient Greek, muthos first signified
the Syntonolydian for tragedies (R. 398e1). ‘thought that is expressed, opinion’. This
The aim of music is to show the image meaning was then modified in the course
(theama, R. 402d4) of the character (êthos, of the transformations affecting the verbs
R. 400d8–e3) of the soul, as in the verbal pic- expressing ‘saying’ and the nouns designating
tures of the virtuous man in war and peace ‘words’ or ‘speech’. This historical evolution
by which Socrates illustrates selected harmo- found its final development in Plato, who is
niai (399a5–c3). Only Dorian and Phrygian the first author to use the term muthos in the
harmoniai, with their corresponding rhythms sense that we still give it. By using muthos
(400b1–4), are suitable in education (R. in a nonmetaphorical way, Plato describes a
399a; cf. Smp. 187d3; Lg. 673a3) because certain type of discourse, fashioned by the
the city’s future guardians must imitate a poets of his society, with a view to substitut-
character whose moderation and courage are ing for it another one, the logos produced
prominent. Socrates disallows instruments by the philosophers. Yet although he shows
(R. 399d3–4) that modulate continuously himself to be highly critical with regard to

211

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 211 3/17/2001 9:21:18 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

myths, Plato must admit that philosophers Nevertheless, Plato distinguishes, frequently
cannot do without them. Thus, he takes his and fairly clearly, between the fashioning of
inspiration from the poets to develop certain a myth and its narration.
points of his doctrine, and he goes so far as Thus distinguished from its fabrication,
to fabricate myths, thereby recognizing their the narration of a myth becomes the task
efficacy in the fields of ethics and politics. either of such professionals as the poets
Plato presents myth as a message by (Republic 2.377d4–6) and their subordi-
means of which a given collectivity transmits nates (rhapsodes, actors and choreutes,
from generation to generation what it keeps R. 2.373b6–8), or of nonprofessionals.
in memory of its past, considering it as part Professionals recount myths primarily on
of its history. The past of which myth speaks the occasion of festivals, and particularly in
has the origin of the gods as its starting point, the context of contests (Ti. 21b1–7; Critias
and its lower chronological limit is a period 108b3–7; cf. 108d3–6). We recall that rhap-
distant enough for it to be impossible for the sody contests took place at Athens during
narrator to validate the discourse he holds, the Panathenaea, and tragedy contests dur-
whether through having been a witness to ing the urban Dionysia. Most of those who
the events he recounts, or by basing his story recounted myths, however, were necessarily
on the accounts of eye witnesses. nonprofessionals, who expressed themselves
In ancient Greece, this transmission of the in all circumstances, and outside of any com-
memorable initially took place exclusively petitive context. In Plato, these nonprofes-
from mouth to ear. And when, according to sionals feature two characteristics: advanced
what Plato recounts in the Timaeus, Solon age and feminine gender. Why is this?
went to Egypt to refresh the failing memory In a civilization of writing, the accumula-
of the Greeks, he was informed by a priest tion of messages is independent of individu-
of Sais who did not decipher the characters als: it is equivalent to the preservation of
engraved on the walls of the temple of Neith, traces on material support. In a civilization of
for he knew the contents of the message he orality, by contrast, the accumulation of mes-
was transmitting by heart. For Plato, writing sages can only be individual. Consequently,
can only play the part of a ‘counter-role’, in advanced age appears as a necessary, if not
the etymological sense of the term, with regard sufficient, corollary of the amplitude of
to muthos: ‘a double-entry register’. Yet this the reservoir of knowledge in a given indi-
function remains important, for in view of vidual: the more elderly the individual, the
the catastrophes that periodically fell upon more memories he must have. In addition,
ancient Greece, exclusive recourse to orality the narrator’s old age allows a reduction
(q.v.) naturally entailed a progressive impov- of the degradation that affects every mes-
erishment of the information transmitted. sage transmitted in an exclusively oral way
In an oral civilization, the fashioning of for a long period of time, a degradation that
a message is inseparable from its emission, results from the transformation every story
whereas in a written civilization, these two undergoes at each stage of its transmission.
spheres are clearly distinguished. The ambi- Between grandparents and grandchildren,
guity of the Platonic vocabulary on this one stage is skipped. The second feature is
point testifies to the gradual passage to the femininity of the narrators: mothers (R.
writing around this time in ancient Greece. 2.377c2–4, 381e1–6; Laws 10.887d2–3),

212

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 212 3/17/2001 9:21:18 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

nursemaids (R. 2.377c2–4; Lg. 10.887d2–3) NATURE (PHUSIS)


and old women (Gorgias, 527a5–6; R.
1.350e2–4). Thus, it is primarily women Thomas Johansen
who tell myths, and this is simply because of The Greek word ‘phusis’, like the English
their privileged relationships with those for ‘nature’, was used in a range of different
whom myths are primarily intended: chil- ways. Prominent among these in Greek phi-
dren. In sum, as far as the current description losophy is the notion of phusis as a prin-
is concerned, it is old women who obviously ciple of growth and change. Aristotle in
present the greatest interest, for in them our Physics bk 2 develops a theory of nature as
two characteristics, advanced age and female an inner principle or cause of change and
gender, are combined. rest (q.v. Causality). Aristotle saw many of
The reception of myth, which in an oral the pre-Socratic philosophers as concerned
civilization cannot be separated from its with phusis in this sense, referring to them
emission, and hence from its fabrication, (e.g. at Metaphysics 986b14) as ‘natural
is fundamentally a matter of listening for philosophers’ (phusiologoi). Plato, too,
the audience addressed by both profession- presents Socrates as concerned with a tradi-
als and nonprofessionals. For instance, in tion of studying nature in terms of causes of
the dramatic contests of the Dionysia, the change (see Naddaff 1995). So, in Phaedo
audience was made up of Athenians and Socrates says that as a young man he was
foreigners, rich and poor, accompanied by keen on ‘the wisdom which they call the
their wives and children; there may even inquiry into nature’ (phusis): ‘for it seemed
have been slaves attending. Those who told to me to be magnificent to know about the
myths occasionally, by contrast, had a much causes of each thing, why each thing comes
more limited audience, essentially consist- to be and why it is destroyed and why it is’
ing in children younger than seven years old (Phd. 96a). Socrates, however, raises a fun-
(Lg. 10.887d2–3; R. 2.377a6–7), the age at damental objection to the way this study has
which boys usually began to frequent the been pursued: Socrates thinks the real cause
gymnasium in ancient Greece. In both cases, of natural phenomena should be the good
however, the narrator’s need to capture his because of which they happen, just as the
audience’s attention and to maintain it con- real cause of Socrates’ continued imprison-
stituted a formidable instrument of cen- ment was the good he intended to achieve.
sorship. The narrator is always afraid of a In contrast, the causes that have been offered
hostile reaction from the audience. by earlier philosophers – material processes
In short, myth is a discourse by which all such as coolings and heatings – make no use
information concerning the distant past of a of the good and cannot be said to be real
community is communicated, and preserved causes, at best they are necessary conditions
in the collective memory. It transmits orally for the real cause. While Socrates in Apology
the story of this past from one generation to (19c) had indicated a general lack of inter-
another, whether this discourse was elabo- est in natural philosophy, Phd. thus suggests
rated by a technician of the collective com- a positive view of the study of nature, as a
munication of the memorable, such as the study of the causes of change and being, as
poet, or not (see further Brisson and Naddaf long as this inquiry focuses on the good (q.v.)
1999; Partenie 2009). as the cause. Plato pursues just such a project

213

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 213 3/17/2001 9:21:19 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

in the Timaeus. The aim of Timaeus’ speech has no spatial shape. Similarly, time, com-
is to offer an account of the nature of the uni- posed of past, present and future as its parts,
verse, from its creation down to the nature is created as a moving likeness of an eternal,
of man (Ti. 27a). He shows how a divine changeless paradigm without parts. To study
craftsman, the ‘demiurge’, created the world the world as a likeness of the forms, then,
for the best by imposing order on some cha- means to work out which analogous features
otically moving materials. As his model, the in the medium of change would best repre-
creator used the eternal forms (q.v.), in par- sent the eternal paradigm, a study that can-
ticular the form of a complete living being, not be reduced to reasoning about the forms,
comprising within it all the other kinds of but requires a different kind of practical or
living being. Using mathematical structures, productive reasoning.
he made the world as a perceptible likeness Another worry is that the world as an arte-
(q.v. Image, Imitation) of this model. While fact is not properly natural. The Greeks com-
subject to change and corruption, the natural monly distinguished between nature and the
world has, as a likeness of the eternal forms, products of human agency. Aristotle articu-
a degree of intelligibility and goodness. It lated this distinction by saying that nature
represents a paradigm of embodied order by is an inner principle of change, while craft
imitating which we can become more intel- makes and moves artefacts from without.
ligent and virtuous. This view of the cosmos So since the cosmos depends on an external
as an ethical paradigm is echoed elsewhere maker, we may object that it does not exem-
in Plato’s works: Gorgias 508a; Republic plify nature (see Lennox 1986). In Laws bk
9.592b; Philebus 28d–30c. 10 (889a), the Athenian argues against the
Does the Ti. account really amount to a view that nature and chance, not art, are
study of nature? First of all, since the world responsible for all the significant and fine
of change is only a likeness of eternal being, things in the cosmos. So the four elements
it might be objected that the natural world and the planets ‘moved at random, each
is not an object of study in its own right but impelled by virtue of its own inherent prop-
only a means of indirectly studying forms erties’ (Lg. 889b). The view of nature here
(see Rowe 2003:30). However, Timaeus is seems to involve the notion of what can move
clear that the study of the world as a like- itself. The Athenian counters by arguing that
ness is distinct from that of the forms (Ti. matter is not capable of moving itself, while
59c–d). To see why, it is important to dis- soul is (cf. Phdr. 245c8–9), so it is soul as the
tinguish between Plato’s notion of a likeness first moving cause that, properly speaking, is
and that of a mere copy: for Plato the world nature. A similarly view of the soul is present
has not been worked out so as to have the in Ti. (34b10–5a1, 36e2–4), which stresses
same properties as its original only in an the way in which the soul can transmit its
inferior way. Rather, the cosmos is a like- motions to the world body by being interwo-
ness in the sense that it has attributes that ven with it (Ti. 36d–e). Even if the soul was
are different from but analogous to those first created by god, it could be argued that
of the original. For example, the demiurge the cosmos now qualifies as natural by being
makes the cosmos (q.v. Cosmology) spheri- ensouled. By the same token, individual liv-
cal so as to make it complete like its para- ing beings within the cosmos might be natu-
digm (33a–b, cf., 30c–d), but the paradigm ral in having within them a soul similar to the

214

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 214 3/17/2001 9:21:19 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

world soul (41d–e). This leaves the question is long-lasting, or that another type is par-
in what way, if any, inanimate bodies such as ticularly supple. But no list of such proposi-
the four elements could be said to participate tions will completely capture what an expert
in nature. cobbler knows how to do. Again, someone
who knows Meno will again no doubt know
a variety of propositions, for example, that
NOMOS (see Law) he is handsome and that he is well born. But
one’s knowledge of all such propositions
will never amount to Socrates’ knowledge of
NON-PROPOSITIONAL KNOWLEDGE Meno, in virtue of Socrates’ actual acquaint-
ance with the man.
Hugh H. Benson This fundamental feature of non-proposi-
For Plato, knowledge at least sometimes tional knowledge is importantly connected
appears to be understood as a (cognitive) to its two other traditional features. Unlike
relation between a person and a proposition propositional knowledge, the object of non-
or set of propositions. For example, Socrates propositional knowledge does not admit
famously professes to know that it is wrong of propositional truth and falsity. For exam-
to disobey a superior (Apology 29b), that ple, the object of a cobbler’s knowledge, per-
knowledge is different from true belief haps the discipline of cobblery or shoes, is
(Meno 98b), and even (perhaps somewhat not something that can be true or false, nor is
paradoxically) that he knows nothing impor- the object of Socrates’ acquaintance knowl-
tant (Ap. 21b and 23b). Such knowledge is edge, that is, Meno. It must be conceded,
often referred to as propositional knowledge. however, that Plato is quite willing to treat
Nevertheless, Plato also appears to recognize alêtheia, which is often correctly translated
other kinds of knowledge that cannot readily as ‘truth’, as a property of objects. In these
be understood as a relation between a person circumstances alêtheia may be better trans-
and a proposition. For example, Plato some- lated as ‘reality’ and the adjective alêthê as
times characterizes knowledge as more like ‘real’. In addition, non-propositional knowl-
a relation between a person and an object edge admits of degrees, again allegedly unlike
(Republic 476d–80a), or as skill or expertise propositional knowledge. One can know
(Ap. 22c–e), or even as some kind of non-dis- cobblery to a better or worse degree, as any-
cursive self-awareness (Seventh Letter 344b). one who has taken shoes to an incompetent
Such characterizations indicate a commit- cobbler is well aware. Moreover, Socrates,
ment to non-propositional knowledge. while he knows Meno considerably better
Perhaps the most significant feature of than any of us, does not know him as well
nonpropositional knowledge is that know- perhaps, as Meno’s mother.
ing something nonpropositionally cannot be Given this rough characterization of the
completely described. Any attempt to describe nature of non-propositional knowledge, the
what it is to know something nonproposi- question arises whether Plato ever recognizes
tionally will be incomplete. For example, a knowledge of this sort. And here the answer
skilled cobbler will no doubt possess consid- would seem to be that he does. In the so-called
erable propositional knowledge. She/he will early dialogues, for example, Plato appears to
need to know that a specific type of leather take the paradigm of knowledge to be technê

215

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 215 3/17/2001 9:21:19 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

(craft or expertise). In the Ap., after exam- sort of thing whose content by its very nature
ining the professed knowledge of the politi- cannot be expressed in words. This ineffable
cians and poets and finding it wanting, he or indescribable experience might also be
discovers that the craftsmen did know many suggested by the failure in the definitional
fine things; although they also thought they dialogues of anyone managing to pass the
knew many things that they did not. Again, alleged Socratic test for knowledge, viz. pro-
in the Laches, the dialogue in which Socrates viding a verbal account of Socrates’ ‘What is
seeks to determine which of the two Athenian F-ness?’ question. Plato’s use of a geometri-
generals (if either) knows what courage is, the cal question whose answer is an irrational
inquiry is initially described as an examina- number in the Men. like that of powers or
tion of the expertise of the generals. But char- square roots in the Theaetetus has also been
acterizing knowledge as craft or expertise is thought to be suggestive of Plato’s willingness
apparently to view knowledge as the sort of to characterize knowledge as non-discursive
thing that cannot be completely describable, and so again incompletely describable.
as being directed towards an object that does It is, of course, one thing to see that Plato
not admit of truth or falsity, and as being the was tempted to characterize knowledge in
sort of thing that can admit of degrees. these two apparently distinct ways, and quite
Again, in the middle books of the R., Plato another to suppose that Plato took one of
is commonly thought to distinguish between these ways of characterizing knowledge as
knowledge and belief or opinion in virtue fundamental or even that he recognized the
of the fact that knowledge is in some way distinction between them. At least one rea-
restricted to forms, while belief is restricted son for wondering whether Plato saw much
to ordinary objects. These books indicate a moment to this distinction, if he recognized it
willingness on Plato’s part to characterize at all, is the following.
knowledge as a relation between a person and In dialogues like the Men., Phd. and R.
an object (pace Annas 1981 and Fine 1990). Plato appears to endorse a method of knowl-
Indeed, in dialogues like the Phaedo and the edge acquisition known as the hypotheti-
R. Plato often characterizes the knowledge of cal method. Whatever the precise details of
a form as analogous to a person seeing an this method turn out to be, the method itself
object (q.v. Vision). Other passages through- appears to resemble the axiomatic-deductive
out the dialogues indicate a similar propen- method of the geometers being explored in
sity. As a result, Plato is sometimes thought the fourth and third centuries BCE (even in
to think of knowledge as some sort of cogni- Plato’s Academy) and coming to expression
tive vision or knowledge by acquaintance – in works like Euclid’s Elements in about 300
a kind of direct and unmediated intuition BCE. Such an axiomatic deductive system
between a person and an object (like a form). presupposes a logic of propositions (whether
Again, this knowledge cannot be completely syllogistic (see Aristotle, Prior Analytics and
describable; its object does not admit of truth Posterior Analytics) or otherwise) in which the
and falsity, but does admit of degrees. premises of the deductions are propositions.
Finally, in a famous passage from Plato’s Nevertheless, in describing this method in R.
Ep. 7, knowledge appears to be character- bk 6, Plato characterizes the starting points
ized as a kind of non-discursive intuition that of this method non-propositionally, giving as
follows a lot of hard intellectual work – the examples of such starting points things like

216

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 216 3/17/2001 9:21:19 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

the odd and the even, the various figures, and There is no denying that Plato was inter-
the three kinds of angles. The reader is left ested in the problem of unity. The forms them-
to wonder whether Plato is being deliberately selves are introduced in order to account for
obscure, unaware of the distinction between the so-called one over many problem (hen
propositional knowledge of the premises and epi pollôn), viz. that many sensible things
nonpropositional knowledge of objects, or is can share one property (Euthphro 5c–6e;
simply unconcerned with the distinction. Meno 72c; Phaedrus 249b; etc., cf. Aristotle
Metaphysics 990b13–14, 1040b29–30,
1079a7–9, etc.), and the relation obtain-
ing between unity and plurality is central
THE ONE (TO HEN) to his discussions of collection and division
(q.v. Method). But of course positing the
James Wilberding one as a completely transcendent principle
In the Platonic tradition a systematic philoso- of forms is another matter entirely, and our
phy is ultimately developed in which the one primary evidence that Plato might have done
(to hen) comes to refer to the single, highest this comes from the so-called indirect tradi-
principle of all things both sensible and intel- tion, and in particular from Aristotle (e.g.
ligible. The Neoplatonist Plotinus (d. 270 CE) Metaphysics 987a28–8b16), who gives us
is the first in whom we find a clear and com- reports of Plato’s ‘so-called unwritten doc-
prehensive exposition of the one and its pro- trines’ (Physics 209b14–15) and who also
duction of other things. Briefly, the Plotinian composed a report of Plato’s oral lecture on
one qua the first principle of unity transcends the good, to which Alexander of Aphrodisias
all plurality and thus all predicates, includ- (fl. c. 205 CE) appears to have had direct
ing that of existence; since Plotinus identifies access but which was not accessible to earlier
true being (the forms; q.v.) and intellect, the Middle Platonists nor to later Neoplatonists
one is also beyond all understanding, though (Dörrie 1987:74– 90, 275–308; see Gaiser
some form of suprarational unification with 1968:441–557 for a collection of the testimo-
the one is possible; finally, the one timelessly nia and Erler 2007:406–16 for additions and
generates all things by a process of emana- a brief, more up-to-date and objective discus-
tion. This process may be said to consist of sion). Aristotle tells us that Plato posited two
two moments: from the one’s activity of, as principles as the ‘elements’ of the forms – the
it were, being itself, a secondary, indetermi- one as a determining principle and the indefi-
nate principle is produced, and this principle nite dyad (also called the great and the small)
is then given definition by the one. In this as a material principle, and identifies this one
way Plotinus accounts for the timeless gen- with the good (e.g. Metaphysics 1091b13–15;
eration of, first, intellect and the forms, then Aristoxenus Elementa harmonices 2.1–2).
soul, and ultimately the sensible world (see Additional support is found in the reports on
O’Meara 1993 for an accessible introduc- Plato’s immediate successors in the Academy,
tion). This raises the reasonable question of Speusippus and Xenocrates, who are also
just how much of this doctrine is already to described as advancing systems involving the
be found in Plato, which is effectively to ask one and the dyad (Dillon 2003b).
to what extent Neoplatonistm (q.v.) is in fact A central issue here is whether this material
just Platonism. can legitimately help us to better understand

217

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 217 3/17/2001 9:21:19 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

the dialogues and conversely whether the as belonging to the realm of being (518c9,
dialogues can help us unpack these indirect 526e3–4, 532c5–6), which strongly suggests
reports. There are wildly different responses that the good, if it is to be identified with
to this issue. At one extreme Harold Cherniss the one at all (Hager 1970:102–56), is not a
(1944 and 1945) attempted to explain away principle that transcends being and the forms
this material as Aristotle’s misunderstand- but is rather the highest member of that class
ing of Plato’s dialogues. At the other are the (Baltes 1999). Other aspects of the Plotinian
somewhat speculative efforts of the Tübingen one have been gathered from other passages,
school (q.v.; Gaiser 1968; Krämer 1959 and for example, emanation, the characteristic
1964; among Anglophone scholars, Sayre first moment of activity of the Plotinian One,
(1983) notably goes in the same direction). has been thought to be lurking behind Plato’s
They see the doctrine at work in the back- light imagery, especially R. 508b6–7, and the
ground of the middle and late dialogues and, interplay between the one and the dyad has
by invoking both the testimonia and critical likewise been thought to be at work in the
passages from the dialogues, claim to be able Philebus (esp. 14c–18d, 23c–7b) and the
to reconstruct the Platonic doctrine, which Sophist (esp. 242c–53e).
turns out to be remarkably Plotinian. The reconstructions of the Tübingen
Critical here is above all the interpreta- School have not been met with wide accept-
tion of the second part of Plato’s Prm.. In a ance, and not just for hermeneutic reasons.
classic paper E. R. Dodds (1928) showed the Philosophically, this approach to the dia-
striking parallels between the first hypothesis logues is seen by opponents to saddle Plato
(Prm. 137c–42a) of the Prm. and Plotinus’ with an unfashionably systematic philosophy
description of the one that transcends all at the cost of other interpretations that are
predication including existence (as well as not only exegetically possible (and in some
between the second hypothesis (142b–55e) case much more so) but also of more philo-
and Plotinus’ intellect), but whether Plato sophical relevance to us today. Yet, Cherniss’
intended such a metaphysical interpretation deflationary account of the testimonies has
(as defended most thoroughly by Halfwassen also failed to hold sway. The truth surely lies
1993:265–405; more briefly in 2004) was a somewhere in between these two extremes.
matter of contention even in antiquity(Proclus
On Plato’s Parmenides 630, 15–645, 8) and
is still more so today (see Erler 2007:227–9
for a brief overview of interpretations). The ONTOLOGY (METAPHYSICS)
transcendence of the one is also seen by some
(e.g. Halfwassen 1993:220–64) to be indi- Allan Silverman
cated in the Republic’s account of the good Of all the doctrines ascribed to Plato, per-
(q.v.). In the simile of the sun (R. 506e–9c; haps the most (in)famous is what we would
q.v.) the good is said to be ‘not being, but label a metaphysical thesis, namely that the
superior to it in rank and power’ (509b8–10). real, or most perfect beings, are forms (q.v.).
This might be taken to indicate transcend- Of course the various subdisciplines of phi-
ence, but it need not be. After all, the form losophy, for example, ethics, epistemology
of the good is repeatedly described as a and metaphysics, and arguably philosophy
form (505a2, 508e2–3, 517b8–c1, etc.) and itself, do not predate Plato and his student,

218

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 218 3/17/2001 9:21:20 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

Aristotle, from a later edition of whose writ- space and time – they are abstract entities.
ings the term ‘metaphysics’ actually comes. Particulars change, are material, and exist in
In thinking about Plato’s metaphysics, then, space and time. Forms are indivisibly simple
one should keep in mind that forms are the (or ones); particulars are divisibly complex
foundation of Plato’s whole synoptic vision. (have many properties). Forms are grasped
It is not unlikely that he comes to postulate by knowledge, particulars by perception or
forms (in the Phaedo) in order to support belief. Forms do not, whereas particulars
his teacher Socrates (q.v.) in countering chal- do, suffer from ‘the compresence’ of oppo-
lenges posed by ethical relativists such as site properties: whereas the form of equality
Protagoras, and it is almost certain that one is always equal and never unequal, particu-
fundamental purpose of forms is to serve as lar sticks or stones, say, are at once equal
the (objective, i.e. mind-independent) objects and unequal, perhaps because a given stick
of knowledge. is equal to a second stick but unequal to a
What then are forms? Forms are proper- third.
ties or universals. A universal property is, What precisely the perfection, simplic-
typically, common to many things. A form ity, separation and nature or being of forms
is a ‘one’ over many. The many things are, amounts to is controversial (Cherniss 1944;
typically, ordinary particulars. For instance, Silverman 2002). Relatedly, there is contro-
Shaquille O’Neal and Mt Everest are tall, a versy over the range of forms, at least in the
basketball and a penny are circular, Socrates Phd. and Republic (where scholars think
and Mother Teresa are pious, and Plato and Plato introduces it). Looking at (many of)
Aristotle are human. (It is disputed whether the forms mentioned in the arguments, schol-
there are, in addition to forms and particu- ars have argued that forms are limited to
lars, property instances or tropes, for exam- incomplete or relational properties, perhaps
ple, the tall-in-Shaq, as distinct from both with special provision for ethical properties
the tall-in-Everest and the form of tallness.) (Irwin 1977a; Owen 1957). So beauty (q.v.),
Plato, unlike Aristotle, is thought to have goodness (q.v.), largeness, equality and jus-
held that forms or properties exist regard- tice (q.v.) are forms, because anything that
less of whether there are any instances of is good, say, is good for a . . . diet, or a man,
them. Thus, even if there never has been, is or whatever ‘completes’ the thought that
not now, nor ever will be a truly wise person, X is good. Usually, the chief philosophical
nonetheless the form of wisdom is what it is, reason for positing forms of this sort is that
or exists. Plato’s forms are thus transcendent, particulars suffer compresence of opposites
as opposed to immanent or Aristotelian, uni- with respect to these properties; Socrates is
versals. They are ‘separate’ from their par- larger than Simmias but smaller than Cebes.
ticular instances. Since, or so it is argued, there must be entities
Plato characterizes the difference between that do not suffer such compresence, Plato
forms and particulars through several dis- posits forms that are simply and solely or
tinctions. Forms are perfect and independent perfectly and completely beautiful or large,
beings; particulars are imperfect and depend- and so on (Fine 1993). Other scholars think
ent participants, getting (some of) their prop- that the range of forms is not limited in this
erties by having a share of forms. Forms manner. Rather, there are forms for all the
are unchanging, immaterial and outside of natural joints, forms corresponding to all

219

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 219 3/17/2001 9:21:20 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

the properties actually had by particulars. properties essentially and others acciden-
(One can also maintain that there is a form tally (Frede 1967). Others think that Plato’s
corresponding to every linguistic predicate, account of forms is not subject to the Third
thus further expanding the range of forms.) Man regress because forms and particulars
How one understands the nature or being do not have properties in the same way, or
of forms varies, in part, with one’s view of that forms are self-explainers (Code 1986).
their range. The starting point for questions Finally, in the late dialogues Plato seems to
about the nature of forms is the self-predi- distinguish some forms, for example, being,
cation statements sprinkled throughout the sameness, difference, as greatest kinds. These
dialogues, for example, piety is pious, justice are what, in the tradition, are syncategore-
is just. Some think that justice is just in the matic or transcendental properties had by all
same way as Socrates is just – it is character- beings, as opposed to substantial forms such
ized by justice (Vlastos 1981). (Since forms as greenness, or cat.
are ‘causes’ (q.v.) of the way particulars are, While most of his efforts are devoted to
some think that forms transmit (via partici- forms, especially in the late Philebus and
pation; q.v.) the property they respectively Timaeus Plato develops a sophisticated,
have to the particulars.) Others, approxi- mathematical account of material particu-
mationists, think that forms are perfect lars, including the cosmos, and perhaps even
instances of the property whereas particulars of matter. The key elements are geometrical
are defective instances, say in the manner forms, ratios and the receptacle, an item very
in which no physical circle is perfectly cir- similar to space. In the Ti., particulars are,
cular (Malcolm 1991). Finally, others think at bottom, materially composed of triangles
that forms are different kind of beings from and are occupants of space and time.
particulars: forms are simply and solely what Finally, Plato’s metaphysics also includes
they are, whereas particulars get all of their immaterial souls. These are primitive beings
many properties via participation, a special that are essentially self-movers. As such, they
ontological relation (Silverman 2002). are ultimately responsible for all physical
In other dialogues, many of the metaphysi- and psychological motion.
cal issues involving forms and particulars are
given closer scrutiny. So, many, who think
that initially forms are limited, concede that
later works reveal a much broader range of PAIDERASTIA (PEDERASTY)
forms. In the Parmenides, Plato seems to call
into question the foundations of the theory in Luc Brisson
what is known as the Third Man argument. In the Symposium as a whole, which should
If forms have the property in the same way be associated with the Phaedrus, and par-
as particulars, and if forms cannot ‘explain’ ticularly in the speech Socrates places in the
why they have the property they have, then mouth of Diotima (Smp. 198a–212e), philos-
it seems a regress of forms threatens. Some ophia (q.v.) is opposed to paiderastia on
scholars think that Plato abandons forms the level of education (209e–12a, and espe-
(Ryle 1939a). Others think that he makes cially 211b–c). What does this mean? First
them immanent in particulars, and (thus) of all, paiderastia must not be confused with
allows that particulars can both have some what we now call ‘pederasty’. In order to

220

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 220 3/17/2001 9:21:20 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

understand the originality of what was called tenderness, an emotional and erotic
paiderastia in archaic and classical Greece, asymmetry subsists, which the Greeks
which had almost the status of an institution distinguish by speaking of the lover’s
among the wealthy circles of Athenian soci- erôs and the beloved’s philia. An older
ety, the following five particularities should man, inspired by love, pursued with
be mentioned. his advances a younger man who, if he
yielded, was led to do so by affection,
(1) Paiderastia implies a relationship not gratitude and admiration, feelings united
between two adult males, but between under the term philia; pleasure was not
an adult ‘lover’ (erastês) and his ‘beloved’ to be taken into account in his case (for a
(erômenos), a paîs. In this case, paîs des- contrary view, see Dover 1989:204).
ignates a boy in the age class that begins (5) The older male is qualified as an erastês,
around the time of puberty, until the whereas the younger one is called his erô-
appearance of the first beard, between menos (the passive participle of eran) or
approximately ages 12 and 18. his paidika (a neuter plural that literally
(2) The appearance of fuzz on a boy’s cheeks means ‘what concerns young boys’). The
represents the summit of his sexual attrac- amorous language found in Greek litera-
tiveness, which lasts until the growth of ture of a certain level and particularly
his first beard. In a transitional period, a in Plato always remains modest, but the
young boy may play both an active and a reader should not be fooled. Such terms
passive role in a sexual relationship, but as hupourgein ‘perform a service’ (Smp.
with different partners. 184d) or charizesthai ‘accord favour’
(3) Since it is limited to one period of life, (182a–b, 182d, 183d, 185b, 186b–c,
and is not associated with an inclina- 187d, 188c, 218c–d) must be interpreted
tion towards one individual in particu- in a strong sense: the service expected
lar, paiderastia is not exclusive. Adult or the favour requested by the older
males are expected to marry, after hav- male is ultimately equivalent to a sexual
ing played a passive role in the context relation.
of a homosexual relationship, and even
while still playing an active role in them. Outside of the desire for sexual satisfaction
Nevertheless, in the context of paideras- and the search for a certain affection or ten-
tia, the erastês was often a relatively derness, of what use might paiderastia have
young man between twenty and thirty, been in ancient Greece? Whereas marriage
who was not yet married or whose wife constituted the privileged institution that ena-
was very young. Moreover, in his speech bled an adult male to transmit his ‘genetic’,
(Smp. 189c–93d), Aristophanes insists on economic, social and political patrimony, the
the existence of very strong, long-lasting relations between an adult and an adolescent
bonds between individuals of the same can serve only to ensure the transmission of
sex. Agathon and Pausanias are a good an economic, social and political patrimony.
example, since they remained together Indeed, it seems that in classical Athens, the
for more than 30 years. goal of paiderastia was to facilitate the ado-
(4) Even when pederastic relationships lescent’s entry into the masculine society that
are characterized by mutual love and ran the city economically and politically.

221

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 221 3/17/2001 9:21:20 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

Paiderastia thus had a social and educational time of their adolescence. It does not always
role. This is the origin of all the remarks and correspond to the contrast between adoles-
developments on the utility (chreia) of homo- cent and adult, for there may be interference
sexual relations that we find in Plato, partic- between these terms. Finally, the couple het-
ularly in the Phdr. and the Smp. erosexuality/homosexuality, in so far as these
However, despite the institutionalized terms are used with a great deal of caution,
form assumed by paiderastia, and despite the is not identical with a clear division between
praise received by sexual relations among norm and deviance as it has been in other
men, which occupy the first place, particu- times and places, for homosexuality inspires
larly in the context of the banquet given both praise and blame. Indeed, the practise
at the home of Agathon (and described in of paiderastia, which has almost the status of
Plato’s Smp.), this type of relation inspired an institution in the upper classes of archaic
resistance and censure. It is worth noting and classical Athens never ceases to inspire a
that Socrates favours avoiding homosexual quiet mistrust that is sometimes transformed
coitus in Phdr. and the Athenian Stranger into hostility (see further Brisson 2006;
condemns it in Laws. Dover 1989; Halperin 1990).
In his speech (180c–5c), Pausanias is
obviously thinking of Agathon (who answers
him in his speech, 194e–5a), who was first his
‘beloved’ in the context of paiderastia, when PARTICIPATION
he underlines the quiet mistrust of Athenian
society with regard to this practise, and even Fiona Leigh
its open hostility. We find an example of this Participation (methexis) is the relation that
hostility in the Thesmophoriazusae (130–67), subsists between forms (q.v.) and things –
a comedy produced in 411 BCE, in which ‘participants’ – in virtue of which things
Aristophanes violently targets Agathon. The come to have as an attribute the property
scene in which a relative of Euripides debates the form is named after. Thus participa-
with Agathon constitutes a particularly vio- tion has a causal or at least an explanatory
lent condemnation of the homosexuality of role in Plato’s thought. Not being overly
the tragic poet, who must have been famous fond of technical language, Plato describes
at the time. the relation by way of various terms: shar-
By opposing paiderastia and philosophia ing, participating, communing and possibly
on the level of education, the Phdr., and espe- even mixing (metalambanein, epikoinônein,
cially the Smp., encourage broader reflection metekhô, koinônein, mixis). So, for example,
on sexuality. Relations between the sexes are if a person or a city is just, this is because
constructed as a function of social represen- of its participation in the form justice
tations that vary over time and space. At the (Republic 443e–4d, 472b, 479e–84d), if two
end of the fifth-century BCE, certain opposi- things are a duo they share in duality itself
tions manifest themselves in a context that (Phaedo 101c), if anything is beautiful it is
is very different from our own. The opposi- because of sharing or partaking in the beau-
tion (active/passive) does not coincide with tiful (Phd. 100d–e; Symposium 211a–b), the
the polarity (man/woman), for the latter many large things participate in the form
becomes confused for young men during the large (Parmenides 132a–b), and being a

222

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 222 3/17/2001 9:21:21 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

different thing involves a sharing in differ- approximating. Note that not all, perhaps
ence (Sophist 256b–e). In the Sph., at least a none, of these relations are necessarily iden-
select few forms share other forms: Motion tical. One way of copying something is to
is the same as itself through participation in be an image or visual representation of it,
the same in relation to itself, and is differ- another way is to imitate it by causing one-
ent from the same because of sharing in dif- self to come to share a feature in common
ference in respect of the same (256a–b). So with it (typically not all features), another is
what exactly is participation? to bear a likeness in a number of essential
What, according to Plato, the participa- features to it, another is to be a wholesale
tion relation consists in is a vexed question reproduction (fair or otherwise) of it, and
for the student of Plato’s metaphysics. No yet another is to roughly resemble it as one
character in the dialogues offers an adequate might resemble a pattern.
explanation of it, and in the Phd. (100d), Several key differences exist between forms
Plato makes Socrates deliberately vague on and nonforms. While forms are purely intel-
the details. Some have even doubted that ligible – accessible to the mind (soul) alone –
Plato himself understood it. nonforms are in space and time, and are
Broadly speaking, two interpretive trends enmattered or bodily (Ti. 30a–1b, 48e–9a;
are discernable in the secondary literature. R. 507b–c). Such stuff is impermanent, and
Some see participation as reflective of or is characterized by opposite properties. None
reducible to the apparent defect of sensible of the many physically beautiful things that
particulars as compared with forms; others the vulgar crowds adore is simply beautiful,
see it as playing a role in the causal connec- says Socrates, but each is such as to also to be
tion between forms and their participants. ugly (R. bk 5.479a–b). If the defect of sensi-
Sensibles are characterized in desultory terms bles lies in their matter, perhaps participation
as inferior, base and merely temporary (Phd.; is a relation of rough resemblance in which
Timaeus; Smp.; R.). The reader gets a strange the resemblance is limited in exactness by the
picture of sensibles, as ‘striving’ to be like the imperfection of the material. However, this
forms in which they participate, but always does little to explain possession of a property.
falling short (e.g. Phd. 74d–5d), suggesting For example, Helen of Troy is not beautiful,
that they are at best approximations of them but ugly, relative to the goddess Athena (cf.
(cf. Ti. 29b–c; R. 472b–3b). They are some- Hippias Major 289a–b; cf. Smp. 211a), and
times said to possess mere ‘becoming’, being so is both beautiful and not beautiful (com-
resemblances of the forms, which are more presence of opposite characters). Perhaps the
true (Ti. 50d–1c; Smp. 211a–2a), suggesting thought, on the approximation view, would
to some that they are like reflections in a be that humans are made of baser stuff than
mirror, or, alternatively, are copies or imita- gods, and so Helen does not approach the
tions (q.v.) of forms, as a chair may be said ideal of beauty (q.v.) as closely as Athena,
to imitate a craftsman’s blueprint, or a pat- who herself is not perfectly beautiful, but only
tern (paradigm) in nature (R. bk 10 596a–7e; approximates, however closely, the beauty of
Prm. 132d; Ti. 29a–b; cf. Ti. 48e–9a). Such the form beauty. But if beauty admits of a
images naturally give rise to suggestions that scale, as this view implies, then either Helen,
the participation relation is one of copy- Athena, or the rest have a precise measure of
ing, mirroring (or reflection), imitating or beauty, not an approximation, or else Plato

223

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 223 3/17/2001 9:21:21 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

thought that participation admits of degrees. the second form is like the original form and
On the first alternative, Plato appears to have the participant, the regress will be infinite.
confused being a precise measure with being If Plato’s forms are universals (cf.
a dim copy or approximation; while a prob- Ontology), as often thought, then the par-
lem for the second alternative is that degrees ticipation relation would be perhaps best
of participation do not figure prominently in thought of as an instantiation relation. The
the dialogues (but see R. 472b–c). Finally, if repeated characterization of sensibles as infe-
the form embodies the ideal standard, then rior could then be construed as an indication
we must ask in virtue of what it possesses of Plato’s fondness for his conceptual inno-
the property. If it is a further form, then vation of forms, as compared to the mun-
as Plato himself saw, the infamous ‘Third dane things of the sensible realm. But since
Man Argument’ threatens to undermine the this is hardly a philosophical reason to privi-
explanatory value of forms (Prm. 132a–b). lege forms, in the absence of solid textual
Perhaps, Plato characterizes participants evidence, it is an undesirable reading of Plato
as mere copies of forms because they belong (but see Harte 2008).
to a different ontological category. So, they Alternatively, one might attempt to under-
are not deficient as mere approximations of stand participation by focusing on the causal
forms made from inferior stuff, but because connection between forms and their par-
they are different sorts of things entirely. ticipants. A form of F is the cause of all the
Only forms really exist, whereas sensibles F-things being F, in the sense of being the
have a more tenuous reality, rolling about in thing responsible, by Plato’s lights, for them
the realm of ‘becoming’, not true being (R. being F. No cause of something’s being F can
479d). Consider the following analogy: a also be the cause of its being the opposite of F,
reflection of a red scarf in a mirror resembles and similarly, no cause of something’s being
the original, really existing scarf, of which F can be the opposite of F, which principles
it is a copy. But since it is merely a visual rule out other candidates for being the cause,
image of it, only an imitation, it is incapable such as material composition. Participation
of, say, keeping one warm in winter. Despite could, therefore, be construed as the causal
handling Socrates’ talk of sensibles as shad- relation that holds between forms and their
owy reflections well, however, it is not clear participants. If so, however, it seems it will
that the analogy is ultimately workable. For, have to be one of the small classes of causal
as the example makes clear, a reflection of relations that is at the same time the state of
a scarf is in an important sense not really a affairs identified as the effect brought about
scarf at all, whereas the tallness in Simmias by the cause. At least, participation seems
does seem to be a case of really being tall. to be temporally coextensive with the par-
Moreover, Plato himself apparently worried ticipant bearing the relevant property – it is
that an account of participation as similarity not conceived of in the dialogues as a dis-
or likeness was inadequate. For, if a partici- crete act or event that happens at some time,
pant is like the relevant form, then the form which then ceases, leaving the participant
is also like its participant, and it seems that as the property bearer at a later time. This
this common property, in virtue of which suggestion raises several questions: Is par-
they are alike, must in turn be explained in ticipation then identical with, and reducible
terms of a further form (Prm. 132d–3a). If to, having a property as an attribute? Is the

224

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 224 3/17/2001 9:21:21 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

suggested view compatible with thinking of distinguish sensation (the physical transac-
forms as universals, given that universals are tion) from perception (the conveying of infor-
not generally understood as causes of their mation by means of sensation). While Plato
instances? is keenly interested in both, and indeed has
separate theories for the two (for his theory
of sensation see Timaeus 45b–6c, 67c–8d;
cf. Meno 76c–d; Theaetetus 155c–7c), he is
PERCEPTION AND SENSATION undeniably hampered by having no terms to
(AISTHÊSIS, AISTHANOMAI) mark this and other key distinctions.
(SENSATION) In such famous passages as Phaedo
72e–7b, Republic 475e–80a and Ti. 51d–e
Timothy Chappell Plato develops a critique of aisthêsis which
tightens and sharpens not just his concept
One day at dawn, [Socrates] started of aisthêsis but also the accompanying and
thinking about some problem or other; contrasting concepts, especially knowledge
he just stood outside, trying to figure (gnôsis, epistêmê). By a simple piece of ‘ordi-
it out. He couldn’t resolve it, but he
nary language philosophy’ (see especially R.
wouldn’t give up. He simply stood there,
477a1 ff.) Plato argues that the content of
glued to the same spot. By midday, many
soldiers began to notice (êisthanonto) . . . knowledge is ‘what is’, whereas the content
(Plato, Symposium 220c) of aisthêsis (or rather doxa – see below) is
‘what is and is not’. By definition, whatever I
They say that when [Babylon] was cap- know is true (or real); so knowledge is about
tured, three days later much of the city sure, stable realities. By contrast, whatever
was still unaware of it (ouk aisthesthai).
aisthêsis is about is unstable, ambiguous and
(Aristotle, Politics 1276a)
uncertain.
Why is aisthêsis unstable, knowledge sta-
As these two quotations show, the classi- ble? Since aisthêsis constitutively depends
cal Greek words for perception, aisthêsis on changeable physical processes, whereas
and aisthanomai, normally have a straight- knowledge constitutively depends on expla-
forward nontechnical meaning: ‘be aware’, nations (logoi). For Plato, to know something
‘notice’, ‘detect’ (as in Edward Lear’s ‘I per- is actively to grasp a full (or approaching
ceive a large bird in this bush’). Furthermore full) understanding of it; such an understand-
they can have this nontechnical meaning ing will necessarily be stable if it is present at
even in the two Greek authors who, in their all. By contrast, to perceive something is to
different ways, do most to refine specialized be affected, passively, by the physical world;
philosophical concepts of aisthêsis. being so affected is what sensation is, and
It is a nice question how refined their there is no perception without sensation. But
concepts are, and how closely their concepts the physical world is itself unstable and unre-
align with any modern concept, given that, liable, and its effects on us are particular and
for example, Aristotle uses the same aisthêsis- perspectival. So an epistemic state of being
vocabulary to discuss both sense-perception affected by the physical world must be a state
(de Anima 2) and moral intuition (Nicoma- of becoming what the physical world is –
chean Ethics 6). Modern philosophers often unstable and unreliable – and of becoming

225

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 225 3/17/2001 9:21:21 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

this at a particular time and from a partic- This helps us see why, in Plato’s Tht., the
ular perspective. If knowledge exists at all, three would-be definitions of knowledge
knowledge will have to be an epistemic state rejected in turn are these: (a) knowledge is
which consists in being affected by ‘what aisthêsis, (b) knowledge is true doxa and (c)
is’ – by some reality that is not unstable in knowledge is true doxa with a logos. Plato
the way the physical world is. But knowledge is well aware of the apparent discontinuity
does exist. Therefore knowledge is not of the between (a), about aisthêsis, and (b) and (c),
physical world; it is a nonperspectival grasp about doxa. The Tht. does not skate over
of some realm of stable and unchanging this difference; it explores it. How can the
realities beyond it. (Our apparent knowledge surd, unstructured happenings of mere sen-
of mathematical truths is, perhaps, a clue to sation carry the sort of informational content
what such true knowledge might be like.) worth dignifying with the names perception
However, there is a twist of paradox in the or belief – let alone the name knowledge?
tale. The ultimate aim of the R.’s dialectical Can someone who thinks, as Heracleitus
education is itself a sort of direct, revelatory does according to the Tht., that there is
perception, acquaintance or intuition: ‘True nothing more to knowledge than the ebb and
Being . . . is visible (theatê) only to Nous’ flow of such separate sensations, give any
(Phaedrus 247c8; cp. theôrôn at Smp. 210d4). convincing account of the precondition of
Hence we find Plato apparently denouncing belief formation that we today call seman-
this-worldly perception in almost the same tic structure? These are the questions that
breath as he exalts the perception of the drive the argument of the Tht. The terrain
forms (R. 517b1–9). Knowledge, as the Tht. between bare-sensation aisthêsis and infor-
insists, is not perception in any ordinary or mationally loaded doxa is precisely what
mundane sense. And yet at the end of the phi- they are designed to explore. And though he
losopher’s laborious ascent, by way of rea- leaves his own positive doctrine implicit in
soning and hard thought and logical work, the Tht., it is possible to see how Plato would
what we find is that the ultimate knowledge answer these questions; without the kind of
is itself something so like perception in its structure for understanding that the forms
directness, immediacy and nondiscursive provide, he sees no route at all from aisthêsis
simplicity that Plato never finds a better or to knowledge. Perception on its own is – for
more illuminating image to describe it by. Plato as much as for his great contemporary
This line of thought is central to the R. But Democritus, whom throughout his life he
Plato never expresses it just thus. In particu- seems to have ignored – merely deception;
lar – as noted above – the R. speaks mostly where Plato and Democritus differ is on what
of doxa, not of aisthêsis. Usually the natural needs to be added to perception, in order for
translation for doxa is ‘belief’, which seems it to be something more than deception.
a very different thing from ‘perception’, still The Tht. is consistent with Plato’s fun-
more from ‘sensation’. However, the R.’s uses damental claim that the forms are the nec-
of doxa (see, e.g. R. 476b–d) show clearly essary precondition of all understanding.
that for Plato it is a technical term: doxa Nonetheless, the implicit lesson of the dia-
means, roughly, ‘sensation-based belief’, and logue’s explicit argument – that not just
that is not far at all from one possible sense knowledge, but belief and perception too,
of ‘perception’. are necessarily structured by the forms – is

226

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 226 3/17/2001 9:21:22 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

that there is a way for Plato to ‘liberalise’ his some men would devote themselves. Plato
view away from the hardline ‘two-worlds’ sometimes retains this meaning of philos-
Platonism that can be read into the R. ophia as opposed to physical and special-
Knowledge may be the ‘highest’ and purest ized activities, for instance in Hippias Minor
epistemic state, but that does not mean – (363a), Charmides (153e), Protagoras (335d)
Plato comes to think – that there is simply or when he describes ‘the democratic man’
no value in doxa or aisthêsis: these epistemic as able to engage in ‘philosophy’, at times
states, ‘lower’ though they may be, can help (Republic 561d).
us too (Philebus 58d–62d). Pace the R., the The departure from this loose meaning is
physical world is not such that the only epis- staged in Gorgias (481c–5e): the philosophy
temic states we can be in about it are igno- referred to by Callicles, when he says that it
rance and doxa: knowledge of it is possible is a fine thing, provided one applies oneself
too, if we come to see how the changing to it with moderation and in one’s youth, is
world approximates unchanging goodness. not the philosophy Socrates has just said he
To explain how this can be done is, of course, is in love with, which demands constant self-
the project of Plato’s greatest work of applied examination and rational self-justification:
physical science: the Timaeus. to love philosophy is to be a philosopher
For further reading on Plato on percep- through and through. Those who pursue
tion, see Burnyeat (2000), Chappell (2005), this kind of knowledge, or wisdom (sophia),
Frede M. (2000), Modrak (2006) and Sedley are neither wise nor ignorant (Lysis 218a;
(2006). Symposium 303e–4b; Phaedrus 278d), but
like Socrates they are wise enough to be
aware that they are ignorant (Apology 29b).
This negative wisdom is opposed to that of
PHILOSOPHY AND THE PHILOSOPHER the sophoi, the experts, able to master either
one particular material or a whole range of
Monique Dixsaut phenomena (cf. Aristotle, On Philosophy, f. 8
Plato did not create the word philosophia Ross), and whose sophia refers to a degree
(its coinage is ascribed by a later tradition to of excellence in performance which must be
Pythagoras; Burkert; Dixsaut 1985:43–83), fêted. The philosopher aspires to no sophia
but he completely changed its meaning. In of this sort. What he calls philosophy is the
the texts that have been preserved, the only quest for a universal knowledge that might
pre-Platonic occurrence of the word is to be give birth to flawless wisdom: but as such,
found in the Hippocratic treatise Of Ancient it seems that it can be a science belonging
Medicine, in the course of a polemic against to the god only, or no more than a purely
some doctors more desirous of cosmic spec- formal verbal passophia. According to Plato,
ulations than of true science and efficacy. the sophists are endowed with a wonderful
The adjective philosophos (Heraclitus f. 35; power of appearing to be ‘wise on all subjects’
D.K.; Antiphon 44a; Gorgias; Encomium (panta sophoi, Sophist 233a–c, cf. scholium
of Helen 11, 13), and the verb philosophein ad 251C), thanks to their art of controversy,
(Herodotus I.30 and Thucydides 2.40–1) but all imitators have this same ability to
refer to any form of intellectual curiosity or seem to know everything (to be passophoi,
exercise, not to a specific subject to which R. 598d): Prodicos (Prt. 315e), Protagoras

227

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 227 3/17/2001 9:21:22 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

(Theaetetus 152c), and also Homer (194e) Socrates begins by wondering if one must
and Hesiod (Ly. 216a), or Parmenides and say of the philosopher, as must be said of all
Melissos (Tht. 181b). Neither conception of those who love something (philein ti), that
sophia can be ascribed to Plato: for even if he loves not this or that particular aspect of
his Socrates sometimes seems to share the sophia, but loves the whole (R. 474b–80a):
view that calling oneself philosophos is a he would have a voracious appetite for all
token of humility, when summoning the learning. Glaucon objects that on the basis of
‘divine part’ of his soul, he claims that the this description, all the lovers of sights and
philosopher becomes akin to the realities to hearing would be considered philosophers,
which ‘the gods themselves owe their divine and mighty strange ones too, for undiscern-
nature’ (Phdr. 249c; cf. Tht. 176b). ing greed, particular to appetite, and indeter-
The Phaedo is the only dialogue belonging mination, particular to sophia, characterize
to the first period (before the R.) in which those who only resemble philosophers. The
the adjective philosophos is preceded by a philosopher proper is not one who likes
definite article and becomes a substantive, looking at everything new, but one who likes
this new substantive being defined in con- looking at the truth. He is not curious of
trast with other words based on philo-: the the many things that participate in one idea
philosopher is not obsessed with the care of (eidos), but he is always trying to get at what
his body (philosômatos), he does not crave each being truly is in itself, at the permanent
for money (philochrêmatos), honour (phi- and intelligible entity (ousia) these things par-
lotimos), power or glory (philarkhos, phi- ticipate in. Ideas are the justification of the
lonikos), and he is finally identified with a philosopher’s search, and the only science he
philomathes. The latter is not specified by its wants to acquire is dialectic (Philebus 58a–e).
object but by a kind of activity or learning, As Parmenides asks Socrates: if, owing to the
whose deep signification will be revealed by number of difficulties encountered, you give
the argument of reminiscence. In order to up assuming ideas, ‘what will you do with
gain what he claims he loves, ‘thought and philosophy?’ (Parmenides 135c).
truth’, the philosopher must ‘be dead’, that If the power to love the true prevails over
is, recall through the soul alone what is really every other kind of desire (in R. 581b–c, the
existent and fully intelligible, the invisible highest part of the soul is called philoso-
‘obscure to the eyes but to be seized by philo- phos), we are dealing with a philosophical
sophical thought’ (Phd. 81b7). Contrary to nature in which the love of truth, taken to
a commonly accepted etymology (but miss- its highest pitch, must not be called philia
ing in the Cratylus), Plato does not give as an but erôs. It takes very little for its violence to
object to the philosopher’s desire a sophia as be perverted: when he is not a philosopher,
impossible to obtain as it is ill defined. The erôs is a tyrant, and the same can be said of
meaning of the thing he calls ‘philosophy’ a philosophical nature. Plato scholars (e.g.
cannot amount to the sum of the two ele- Annas 1981) generally find little or noth-
ments making up its name. ing to say of its definition in bk 6 (485–90),
R. stresses the point: sticking to etymology since it seems to offer a colourless model of
leads to defining not the philosopher but the human perfection. In fact, far from aiming
philodox, the lover of opinion. To sustain his at endowing the philosopher with every pos-
proposal for the rule of philosopher-kings, sible virtue, it is meant to remind us that it is

228

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 228 3/17/2001 9:21:22 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

only in him that virtues truly are virtues (cf. region where they reside’ (Sph. 254a). That
Phd. 69a–b), just as it is only in him, because is why the sophist may claim that he is the
truth ‘leads the chorus’, that the unity of vir- philosopher, and the statesman hold that
tues is fulfilled. public affairs demand a realism the philos-
The philosophical nature is all the more opher is devoid of. When it comes to those
endangered as it is sturdy and exceptionally three ‘kinds’, the difference between them is
gifted. A philosophic education must turn not to be found in a definition (that may be
this nature towards its only fitting occupa- why Plato never wrote the dialogue of the
tion, which is philosophy – failing at which, Philosopher, alluded to in Sph. 254b), but
it will prove most dangerously harmful. ever again in Socrates, who is not a philoso-
From this passage (R. 491d ff.), we get a clear pher but the philosopher, a subject eluding
impression of the double-edged character of the predicate. He might have been no more
the force in human nature with which Plato than a disinterested, slightly eccentric sophist,
is dealing (Nettleship 1929:211). The prob- if his bite had not startled Plato awake and
lem of the selection, education and perver- opened the history of Western philosophy.
sion of these natures is the greatest political
problem, since the philosopher is an indis-
pensable agent when it comes to stamping a PHUSIS (see Nature)
right direction on the life of the soul and of
the state. His task is to recall that being a
man means being able to understand oneself PIETY (EUSEBEIA, HOSIOS)
in all one says and does, and to remind the
cities that they can only be saved if ruled by Mark L. McPherran
intelligence. One of the central concerns of Plato’s dia-
Making the existence of philosophy depend logues is the true nature of the cardinal vir-
on the birth and preservation of philosophi- tues, piety, justice (q.v.), wisdom, courage
cal natures is to make its extinction possible, and moderation (q.v. Excellence). Socrates
which is why one must diagnose the causes and Plato inherited the everyday Greek
for their perversion and expose the usurp- conception of piety, which designates those
ers. Since there can be no philosophy with- things that are in accord with the norms
out philosophers, since nothing can warrant governing proper relations between humans
that new philosophers will be born or that and gods. What marked a fifth-century BCE
‘the best natures’ will devote themselves to Greek city or person as pious, for example,
‘the best occupation’, it follows that nothing was not so much a matter of having a certain
can guarantee that philosophy will always set of beliefs as it was the correct observance
exist. Its essence is eternal, not its existence. of ancestral tradition, especially the correct
Philosophy is a rare plant, one which has performance of sacrifices and the celebration
flourished only in the West, and it is always of festivals in honour of deities, minor and
in danger and always in need of a defence major. No ancient text such as the Iliad had
(Bloom 1968:390). the status of a Bible or Koran, and there was
If sophists find refuge in the darkness of no organized church, trained clergy or sys-
not being, philosophers are difficult to see tematic set of doctrines enforced (although
because of ‘the dazzling brightness of the there were officially recognized priests and

229

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 229 3/17/2001 9:21:22 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

priestesses with clearly demarcated public 281d–e) makes it likely that the only or most
duties). important component of the gods’ chief
Plato’s most sustained and famous treat- product is virtue or wisdom. But then, since
ment of piety is found in the Euthyphro. piety as a virtue must be a craft-knowledge
There Socrates interrogates the self-professed (q.v. Art) of how to produce goodness, our
religious expert, Euthphr., from whom he primary service to the gods – the one we are
elicits five accounts of piety (‘piety’ naming best suited to perform – would appear to be
the one characteristic that makes all pious to help the gods produce goodness in the
actions and persons pious; Euthphr. 5c–d, universe via the protection and improvement
6d–e): (a) prosecuting whomever does injus- of the human mind/soul. Since philosophi-
tice (5d–6e), (b) what is loved by the gods cal examination of oneself and others is for
(6e–9d), (c) what is loved by all the gods Socrates the key activity that helps to achieve
(9e–11b), (d) the part of (generic) justice that this goal via the improvement of consistency
assists the gods to produce their most beauti- among our moral belief and the deflation of
ful product (pagkalon ergon; 11e–14b) and human presumptions to divine wisdom (e.g.
(e) the knowledge of prayer and sacrifice Ap. 22d–3b), Socratic philosophizing is a
(14b–15c). Subjected to the Socratic elenchos preeminently pious activity.
(q.v.), Euthyphro is forced to withdraw his This appropriation and reconception of
assent to all five proposals. However, many piety as demanding of us philosophical self-
scholars have argued that a positive and examination is not wholly at odds with tradi-
Socratically acceptable partial conception tion: Socrates’ antihubristic mission is very
of piety can be reconstructed on the basis of much in line with Delphic Apollo’s insistence
Socrates’ leading hints in the Euthphr. con- that humans obtain the self-knowledge that
cerning his fourth account, and his claims they and ‘human wisdom’ fall short of divin-
to be pursuing a god-ordered mission in the ity. Socrates also does not appear to reject
Apology as he defends himself again a charge conventional religious practises in general,
of impiety (Ap. 20e–3) (e.g. McPherran 1996; but only the narrowly self-interested motives
Taylor 1982; see Brickhouse and Smith 1989 underlying their common observance (cf.
on Socrates’ defence; McPherran 2003 has Xenophon, Memorabilia 1.2.64; Ap. 10–12).
argued that the fifth account can also be This activity can also be explained as being
interpreted in Socratically acceptable terms). compatible with the demands of piety recon-
This ‘Socratic piety’ would be defined as ceived as philosophizing (see McPherran
‘that part of justice that is a service of humans 2000).
to gods, assisting the gods in their primary In his later, more constructive and less apo-
task to produce their most beautiful product’ retic work, Plato moves beyond this defla-
(McPherran 1996:ch. 2). Socrates holds that tionary sense of philosophical piety when
we cannot have a precise or complete account he becomes more optimistic than his teacher
of this product, but since he also holds that regarding the capacity of human beings
the gods are wholly good and do not quarrel to cross the traditional gap separating the
like Homers’ gods, their chief project must human from the divine in respect of knowl-
be superlatively good. Next, the Socratic edge, wisdom and power. Plato’s philosophi-
view that the only or most important good is cal theology offered the unsocratic hope of
virtue/wisdom (e.g. Ap. 30a–b; Euthydemus an afterlife of intimate form contemplation

230

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 230 3/17/2001 9:21:23 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

by our souls in the realm of divinity (Phd. as a virtue is subsumed under the virtue of
79c–84b; R. 490a–b; Phdr. 247d–e). It was justice (and wisdom) as a whole, the phrase
influenced on the one hand by Socrates’ new ‘just and pious’ is assumed to refer to generic
intellectualist conception of piety as elenctic justice.
‘caring of the soul’ (Ap. 29d–30b) and the
success of the methods of the mathematicians
of his day that he took to overcome the limi-
tations of Socrates’ elenctic method (Vlastos PLEASURE (HÊDONÊ)
1991a:ch. 4) (q.v. Method), and on the other
by the aim at human-initiated divine status Dorothea Frede
(especially immortality) as expressed by some Plato treats pleasure (hêdonê) as the generic
of the newer, post-Hesiodic religious forms name of any kind of positive state of mind
that had entered into Greece. Self-knowledge (perception, emotion, experience or insight).
on Plato’s scheme leads not so much to an The same is true of its counterpart pain (lupê).
appreciation of limits, then, as to the realiza- Depending on the context, translations vary
tion that we are ourselves divinities: immortal between pleasure, delight, amusement or lust
intellects that already have within them – if (cf. Philebus 11b). From the early and middle
only we can but recollect it – all the knowl- to the late dialogues the conception of pleas-
edge there is to be had (Men. 81c–d; Phd. ure undergoes quite some development, with
72e–7e; Smp. 210a–11b) (q.v. Recollection). a significant differentiation of the evaluation
Platonic piety is now marked by its insistence of pleasure’s role in human life (Gosling and
that we engage in the intellectual project of Taylor 1984).
‘becoming like god’ (e.g. Tht. 176a–7c; In the so-called early Socratic dialogues
Smp. 209e–12b; Laws 715e–18a; see further pleasure is not addressed except in passing
McPherran 1996:ch. 5; Morgan 1990) (q.v. but in later Socratic dialogues especially the
Theology; Religion). Gorgias (493d–500d) it is associated with
In such a scheme, the central task of human desire (epithumia) and explained as the com-
existence becomes less a matter of assist- pensation of a lack. This leads to a funda-
ing gods and more a matter of becoming as mental critique of pleasure: desire as such
much like them as one can. This fact, plus is insatiable, pleasure is necessarily mixed
the more complex psychology Plato develops with pain and includes bad physical and psy-
in R. bk 4, may explain Plato’s decision to chological states of excitement. In addition,
no longer count piety as a cardinal virtue (R. pleasure is experienced by both good and evil
427e–8a). For, it seems that prior to this text persons alike so that criteria of differentiation
Plato had come to the view that there is little are needed if pleasure is to be regarded as a
internal difference between the knowledge of good at all. The Phaedo (especially 64c–6d)
how to do what is just towards gods (piety) associates pleasure and desire with the body
and the knowledge of how to do what is just and blames them for all evils to humankind
towards mortals (secular justice); as a result, such as sickness, discord and war, so that
piety as a form of psychic virtue seems to be true philosophers avoid such disturbances
nothing other than an aspect of generic psy- of the mind. The exception among the early
chic justice. So, although Plato continues to dialogues is the Protagoras where Socrates in
speak of pious actions in R., and after piety his final argument for the unity of the virtues

231

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 231 3/17/2001 9:21:23 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

forces the famous sophist to accept the defi- treatment of love (q.v.) for the beautiful as
nition of virtue as the ‘art of measuring pleas- an incentive to the higher and better shows
ure and pain’ (351b–7e). Whether or not that Plato no longer maintains a rigid sepa-
Plato is serious about this argument is still a ration of soul and body (cf. Smp. 210a–12b;
matter of debate, but ‘enlightened hedonism’ Phdr. 253d–6e).
of this type remains unique in his work. It is The R. gives some indications concerning
hard to see how Socrates could combine his the nature of pleasure as a filling or motion.
concern for the care for one’s soul (q.v.) with For example, in bk 9, the nature of the filling
the advocacy of an undifferentiated hedon- depends not only on the nature of the ‘filling’
ism where the size of pleasures and pains is (of soul vs. of body) but also on the nature
all that counts. of what each is being ‘filled’ with (forms vs.
The dialogues of Plato’s middle period sensible object); but this does not lead to a
from the Republic to the Phaedrus retain an proper definition (Frede 1985). This question
overall critical attitude towards pleasure as is finally addressed and settled in the Phlb., by
long as it is associated with the lowest part general consensus one of Plato’s last works.
of the soul. Education (q.v.) through music Pleasure is there presented once again as the
and gymnastics is to lead to better forms of rival of knowledge (q.v.) in a contest for the
pleasure (R. 3.403d–4d), and the members highest good in human life (Phlb. 11a–c). But
of the ruling class can reach a harmonious this time pleasure and its different kinds are
equilibrium with respect to pleasure and pain subject to a careful investigation that leads
(R. 6.462a–4d). While pleasure and knowl- to a definition of both pleasure and pain:
edge are at one point presented as unsatisfac- while pain is the disturbance or disruption
tory rivals for the title of the highest good of the natural equilibrium in an organism,
(R. 6.505c–d), in bk 9 Plato stages a competi- pleasure is its restoration (31b–6e). Such dis-
tion between different kinds of pleasure and turbances and restorations can affect both
finally assigns first prize to the philosopher’s body and soul, separately and in combina-
pleasures (R. 583c–5a). In that argument tion, and hence there is a host of different
Plato provides an explanation of the nature types of pleasures and pains. In addition,
of pleasure and of the difference between in his critique of pleasure Plato gives a sys-
‘real pleasures’ and ‘bastard pleasures:’ tematic treatment of the possibility of truth
Between pleasure and pain there is a neutral and falsity that had been left in a less than
state, free from either pleasure or pain; the satisfactory state in R. bk 9. The discussion
motion from pain to the neutral, middle state points out four quite different types of false-
is a mere semblance of pleasure, in contra- hood (Phlb. 36c–50e): (a) pleasures that have
distinction to the motion from the neutral a propositional content – enjoying something
state to that of true pleasure, which is at the that is not the case; (b) overrated pleasures;
same time explained as a ‘filling with what (c) the confusion of pleasure with freedom
is really real’ – that is, with what is true and from pain; and (d) pleasures inextricably
pure, uncontaminated by the body. The value mixed with pain. This distinction permits
of pleasure therefore depends on the quality Plato to pinpoint as true and pure all those
of the respective ‘filling’ (R. 585a–7c). The pleasures that are free from those flaws, and
Symposium and the Phdr. are not explicitly to justify the conclusion that the best human
concerned with pleasure, but their incisive state consists of a mixture of knowledge

232

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 232 3/17/2001 9:21:23 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

and pure pleasures (59d–64b). If the Phlb. Homer that has possessed me from child-
ends the long-standing tug-of-war between hood opposes my speaking’ (R. 10.595b–c).
knowledge and pleasure in Plato’s work, it Socrates later uses the stronger word erôs
does not justify the conclusion that he should to refer to his love of poetry (607e7). Plato’s
thereby be regarded as an enlightened hedon- own intense love for the poetry his Socrates
ist. Pleasure, in its best form, represents only condemns is evident throughout the dia-
a second-rate good, because even its true and logues, in which poetry is frequently quoted,
pure kinds are only the filling of an ‘unfelt and poetic language often used.
lack’, and is due to the necessarily deficient In the R., Socrates first condemns the use
status of human beings and its constant need of poetry like that of Homer and Hesiod to
of supplementation and replenishment in educate the young (bks 2 and 3), arguing
both soul and body (Harte 2004). that it misrepresents the gods as deceitful
This clarification of the nature of pleas- and harmful, and provides bad role models
ure and pain may be presupposed but is not in the form of heroes who lack courage and
explicitly addressed in Plato’s last work, the self-control. He then claims, in a context not
Laws, where pleasure and pain are assigned restricted to education (bk 10), that poetry
an important role in the education of the sec- and other forms of mimêsis (imitation, q.v.)
ond best city’s inhabitants (Lg. 1.631a–2b). misrepresent the truth, and appeals to an
The importance of handling pleasure and inferior part of the soul. Socrates’ ‘greatest
pain in the right way is symbolized by the accusation’ is that poetry corrupts even ‘the
comparison of the human soul with a pup- best of us’. According to Socrates, we think
pet that is controlled by pleasure and pain it right to endure our own sorrows as calmly
as if by iron strings, which in turn ought to as possible, but we do not believe that it is
be directed by the golden thread of reason shameful to enjoy poetry in which someone
and law (Lg. 1.644c–5d). Thus pleasure and acts in ways that we would condemn in real
pain remain important forces of motivation life. For this reason, we ‘let down our guard’
in Plato’s conception of human nature; they when we hear poetry, pitying and sympathiz-
stand in need of careful orchestration by the ing with someone who grieves excessively.
means of education and legislation. By thus feeding and strengthening the wail-
ing part of our soul, we make it harder to
restrain our own sorrows (605c–6d; Belfiore
1983). Socrates concludes that the only kinds
POETRY (POIÊSIS) of poetry that should be accepted into the city
are ‘hymns to the gods and encomia of good
Elizabeth Belfiore people’ (607a). In Laws bk 2, the Athenian
Socrates’ statements at the beginning of adopts this same rule when he states that the
Republic bk 10 sum up the ambivalent and lawgiver must persuade or compel the poet
complex attitudes towards poetry repre- to compose poems about ‘men who are self-
sented in Plato’s dialogues. After claiming controlled, courageous and good in all ways’
that mimêtic poetry is harmful to all who (Lg. 660a). Indeed, he says, tragic poets must
do not know the truth, Socrates says that he not be allowed to speak in opposition to their
must speak about this harm ‘even though a rivals, the lawgivers, whom he calls ‘poets of
certain affection (philia) and reverence for the best tragedy’, because they are creators of

233

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 233 3/17/2001 9:21:23 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

the polity that is a mimêsis of the best life (R. the dialogues, which contain, for example,
7.817a–d). In these dialogues, then, poetry 117 quotations from Homer and 13 from
is given a positive role within the city only Hesiod (Brandwood 1976). These quota-
when it conforms to rigorous ethical and reli- tions serve a variety of functions (Halliwell
gious standards. Little of traditional Greek 2000; Vicaire 1960:76–192). Some illustrate
poetry, especially that of Homer, Hesiod and ethical points (R. 3.390d, quoting Odyssey
the tragedians, is acceptable. 20.17–18, where Odysseus restrains his
The Ion has sometimes been thought anger against the maids); others demonstrate
to express a more positive view of poetry, Socrates’ superior knowledge of poetry
especially that of Homer. In this dialogue, (Protagoras 338e–47a, where Socrates
the rhapsode Ion, a professional reciter of quotes and interprets Simonides); some serve
Homer’s poems, claims that he has access to characterize interlocutors (e.g. the speak-
to more than human knowledge because he ers in the Symposium quote poetry in sup-
is possessed by the same divine inspiration port of their ideas (Belfiore, forthcoming)).
(q.v.) under whose influence the poets them- The dialogues also contain many poetical
selves compose. However, the way in which passages of Plato’s own invention, and even
Ion arrives at this claim gives us reason to some metrical phrases (e.g. Phdr. 241d1; and
doubt that Socrates himself is represented as Smp. 197d1–e5; Dover 1980:124). Most of
agreeing with it. Ion first claims that he has Plato’s own poetical passages are used, like
skill (technê, q.v.) concerning chariot racing, the quotations, for philosophical purposes.
generalship and other matters about which For example, at the end of his speech con-
Homer speaks. Socrates then questions Ion, taining the myth of the chariot, Socrates says
casting doubt on the truth of his claim, and that he spoke ‘in poetic words’ in order to
suggesting that Ion may be deceiving his audi- turn Phaedrus towards a philosophical life
ence about his skill and knowledge. Socrates (Phdr. 257a–b), and he states that the myth
finally forces Ion to choose between being of Er might persuade his interlocutors to pur-
considered an unjust deceiver or a ‘divine sue justice and wisdom (R. 621c).
man’. Only at this point does Ion say that Plato’s dialogues, then, invite us to con-
he prefers to be considered ‘divine’, that is, sider ways in which love for poetry can be
divinely inspired (Ion 542a–b). Indeed, the safely indulged, even leading to philosophi-
view of the inspired poet in this dialogue is cal insight. Not all of traditional poetry
just as negative as it is in Phaedrus 248d–e, is harmful, and Plato’s own myths (q.v.)
where the life of a poet is ranked only sixth present philosophical ideas in poetic lan-
in a hierarchy of nine, and in Apology 22a–c, guage. Moreover, by critically questioning,
where Socrates says that poets are ‘enthusi- even potentially harmful poetry, as Socrates
astic’, that is, divinely inspired, rather than does, we can acquire the countercharm that
wise, and that they not only know less about will allow us to listen to it without being
their own poems than anyone in their audi- deceived (R. 10.608a). Moreover, Socrates’
ence but also falsely believe that they are the treatment of one particular tragic poet,
wisest of all people in other respects as well. Agathon, suggests that it may also be pos-
Nevertheless, Plato’s own love for poetry, sible to reform the poets themselves. After
especially that of the poets his Socrates most Agathon gives an encomium of Eros filled
strongly condemns, is apparent throughout with poetic quotations, Socrates subjects him

234

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 234 3/17/2001 9:21:24 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

to an elenchus (q.v.) that demonstrates that Certainly Plato is the first ancient Athenian
Agathon, like Ion, does not know what he is author to make the politikos central to his
talking about (Smp. 199c–201c). Unlike Ion, account of politics. To appreciate the signifi-
however, who takes refuge in the unexamined cance of Plato’s formulation of this figure, we
claim that he is divinely inspired, Agathon must begin by observing how different it was
readily admits his ignorance (201b11–12). from prevailing figures in Athenian politics.
Socrates responds with a punning compli- Athenians at the time spoke of their political
ment, stating that Eros lacks (or needs) ‘the leaders primarily as the rhêtores kai stratê-
good’ (agathôn), and refers to Agathon as goi, ‘orators and generals’, so naming those
‘beloved’ (201c). That Agathon is willing to men who regularly swayed the Assembly
learn from Socrates is also apparent at the or were elected annually as military leaders
end of the dialogue, when he is eager to be (Hansen 1991:266). In the fifth century, these
praised by Socrates once again, even though two circles tended to overlap, with Pericles,
he thereby risks receiving a kind of ‘praise’ for example, owing his influence both to his
that Agathon called ‘hybris’ (insolence) in an prowess in swaying Assembly deliberations
earlier encounter (175e, 223a). Significantly, and to his regular reelection as a general. If
Agathon is the last of the symposiasts to Athenians wanted to speak of these men in
remain awake talking to Socrates (223d). another way, they called them dêmagôgoi,
The example of Agathon, then, suggests that which is best translated not by the modern
a poet may be able to acquire the kind of pejorative term ‘demagogues’ but simply as
wisdom that Socrates has, that of knowing ‘political leaders’ (see Finley 1985:69 for the
his own lack of wisdom, if he is willing to neutral use, though elsewhere he accepts a
question and examine his ideas rather than pejorative use). Notice that ‘orators and gen-
merely attempting to give pleasure to an igno- erals’ is a description of a plurality, a small
rant audience. His poems will then convey group. Political leadership in Athens was
this kind of wisdom, as well as giving pleas- understood as consisting in a small group of
ure by means of poetic language and meter. sometime rivals, sometime collaborators. If
Indeed, Plato’s dialogues show that if poetry the Athenians sought the image of a singu-
is used philosophically, that is, subjected to lar political leader elevated in kind above all
examination, it can contribute to the search others, they found this in the historical figure
for wisdom. of the lawgiver (nomothetês) Solon, who like
Lycurgus in Sparta had established funda-
mental laws for his city. Yet, having done so,
POLIS (see City) these lawgivers did not take part in its daily
political life: Solon voluntarily left Athens
for 10 years, while Lycurgus left Sparta never
POLITICS AND THE FIGURE OF to return.
THE POLITICUS With the legendary lawgiver on the one
hand, and the rivalling groups of orators and
Melissa Lane generals on the other, the Athenians would
Politicus, or ‘statesman’, is the Latinized form have found the conception of a ‘statesman’
of the Greek politikos, a term which ‘may well who was unique, yet who played a part in
. . . be a Platonic innovation’ (Rowe 1995:1). ordinary political affairs, to be alien. Yet

235

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 235 3/17/2001 9:21:24 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

this was the figure of the politikos whom A striking feature of the Grg. is Socrates’
Plato developed, in a direct challenge to the reference to himself within it. The proposed
norms of the Athenian democracy. Plato did account of the ‘true political art’ quoted
this in at least two ways. The first draws on above is actually embedded in a Socratic
his discussion in the Gorgias, which both self-diagnosis: ‘I believe that I’m one of a
criticizes the leading fifth-century orators few Athenians – so as not to say I’m the only
and generals and proposes Socrates as a rival one, but the only one among our contem-
to them; the second, on the Euthydemus and poraries – to take up (epicheirein) the true
the Plt., in which the notion of a politikê political craft and practise the true politics
technê (‘political art’ or ‘political craft’) and (prattein ta politika)’ (521c6–8). The verb
of the figure of the politikos defined by his epicheirein has the connotation of trying to
knowledge of that art or science (epistêmê) do something rather than necessarily suc-
are developed respectively. In refuting the ceeding at it. In other words, Socrates sees
aggressive and ambitious Callicles in the himself as alone among his contemporaries
Grg., Socrates undertakes an examination in adopting the correct orientation for poli-
of the admired fifth-century orators and tics, in aiming at the good rather than the
generals who had succeeded in winning the pleasant, but he does not here claim to have
power in the city which Callicles argues the knowledge or skill necessary to succeed
one should seek. In line with the amateur in doing so.
character of all Athenian political lead- The idea that the politikê technê must con-
ers, as democratic citizens who achieve a sist in full knowledge, rather than intention
temporary and mainly informal influence alone, is underlined in other dialogues, most
among their peers, he begins by considering notably the Euthd. There, between battles
simply whether Pericles, Cimon, Miltiades with a pair of shameless sophists, Socrates
and Themistocles were ‘good citizens’ (Grg. discusses with the young Clinias knowl-
515d). The argument against their being edge as the only art which can make a man
so hinges on their having failed to make happy and fortunate (Euthd. 277d–82e).
the Athenians virtuous, a failure demon- What kind of knowledge is that? Socrates
strated in the censures and rebukes which first dismisses the art of speechwriting (an
each of them suffered at least once at the identification which the Grg. reference to
hands of the people. Socrates then general- ‘speeches’ might unwisely suggest) or that
izes this point to propose by contrast a ‘true of generalship: in other words, with the
political craft’ (hôs alêthôs politikê technê; very arts exercised by the Athenian orators
521c7). Such an art would consist in mak- and generals. Instead, it is the ‘statesman’s
ing speeches aiming not at what is pleasant art’, also described as the ‘kingly art’ which
but at what is best (521d8–10). The stand- makes the citizens it governs ‘wise and good’
ard of the good (q.v.) as the aim of the true (292b4, 292c4–5).
statesman links the fundamental orienta- Although the Euthd. ends without resolv-
tion of this account to the standard of the ing exactly what ‘wise and good’ here means,
good as the aim of politics developed in the or how the statesman’s art can cultivate these
Republic, even though that dialogue does virtues in the citizens, the idea of a kingly art
not refer to its (plural) philosopher-rulers which defines the figure of the statesman is
by the singular term politikos. the central topic of the Plt. There, a stranger

236

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 236 3/17/2001 9:21:24 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

from Elea leads a discussion which eventu- function is extraconstitutional, in that he


ally distinguishes the statesman from his does not occupy any of the ordinary offices
closest rivals: identified as the orators, the or magistracies, but exercises his art at one
generals and the jurors (these last exercising remove, shaping the conditions in which
an office which any male Athenian citizen the citizens exercise the magistracies (and
could occupy). Statecraft – now articulated so connecting to the political structure of
as the distinctive knowledge of the poli- the Laws, another dialogue which does not
tikos, rather than simply a generic ‘political speak of the figure of the politikos). Plato’s
art’ – is not to be identified with the knowl- figure of the politikos embodies – in certain
edge of any of the practical arts, but rather dialogues – his fundamental claim which
as controlling the exercise of those forms of remains consistent across the dialogues as a
knowledge (Plt. 305d1–2). In particular, its whole: that politics must be based on the rule
role is to distinguish the ‘right time’ from the of knowledge, aiming at the good.
‘wrong time’ to ‘begin and set in motion the
most important things in cities’. The states-
man’s knowledge is essentially temporal (Plt. REALITY (see Appearance and Reality)
305d2–4; Lane 1998).
The Eleatic stranger goes on to define
statecraft even more broadly as the art ‘that REASON
controls all of these [the arts of oratory, gen-
eralship, and judging], and the laws, and Fred D. Miller, Jr.
cares for every aspect of things in the city, The idea of reason is fundamental through-
weaving everything together in the most out Plato’s philosophy. His terms logos, nous,
correct way’ (Plt. 305e2–6). Here, he draws dianoia, phronêsis and related words often
on his earlier use of weaving as a model for correspond to ‘reason’ as understood by
statecraft, and will go on to suggest that the modern philosophers.
statesman’s peculiar task is to weave together Socrates is depicted as the champion of
two rival groups of citizens, characterized by reason. Rather than accepting other people’s
opposing tendencies to misidentify the cor- opinions, Socrates professes to listen only to
rect time for initiating action. By binding the argument (logos) that seems best to him
together these two groups through appropri- on reflection (Crito 46b). He would rather
ate intermarriages and shared opinions, the disagree with the majority than to contradict
statesman can engender in them the ability himself, even though he is only one person.
to identify the right time for action and so Making no claim to wisdom he is grateful to
embody his political art in the polity as a anyone who can refute him because this will
whole (305e–11c). only bring him closer to the truth (Gorgias
It remains a question whether the states- 482c, 506a–c). In his quest for wisdom
man must remain present in the city and Socrates employs the method of elenchus
what his function in doing so would be. The (q.v.). In Meno and Phaedo he supplements
Eleatic stranger earlier compares the states- it with the hypothetical method and theory
man to an athletics trainer who issues writ- of recollection (q.v.). The main focus of the
ten instructions to his charges to cover his present article will be on the account of rea-
periodic absences. Certainly, the statesman’s son in Republic and later dialogues.

237

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 237 3/17/2001 9:21:24 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

Throughout Plato’s dialogues reason- forms and ultimately the form of the good,
ing (logismos) and thought (dianoia) are and discursive thought (dianoia in a narrow
ascribed to the soul (q.v.) as opposed to the sense). With discursive thought the soul uses
body. For example, in Phd. the soul reasons perceptible objects as images of the forms
(logizetai) best about true reality when it is and starts from unexamined hypotheses to
unimpeded by bodily perceptions and desires derive conclusions, as in the case of geom-
(Phd. 64c–7e). In R., however, reasoning etry or arithmetic. With intelligence the soul
belongs to the soul’s rational faculty (logis- eschews images and derives first principles
tikon), which is distinguished from the spir- from hypotheses using forms themselves.
ited and appetitive ‘parts’ of the soul (R. bk
4.435e–41c). This tripartite psychology is Reason (logos) itself grasps the intelligible
present in other dialogues: in Phaedrus 246a object by the power of dialectic, treating
reason is compared to a charioteer guiding a these hypotheses not as first principles
but really as hypotheses, in order to go
winged soul-chariot; in Timaeus 69c–71e the
up to what is non-hypothetical and reach
rational soul is located in the head while the
the principle of everything. After grasp-
spirited and appetitive souls are consigned to ing the principle, reason, reversing itself
the chest and abdomen; in Laws 1.644e–5a and holding on to what follows from
in the comparison of a human beings with it, in this way descends to a conclusion
a ‘puppet of the gods’ reasoning (logismos) making use of nothing visible at all, but,
is a ‘golden and holy’ cord which pulls us instead, of forms themselves, through
towards certain actions in opposition to them and into them, and it ends in forms.
other cords. (R. bk 6.511b; cf. R. bk 7.533c–d)
In Plato’s epistemology (q.v.) thought
(dianoia) involves two powers: knowledge Intelligence thus has two stages: ascent to a
(epistêmê) by which one knows a form such first principle through dialectic (q.v.), and
as the beautiful itself, and opinion (doxa) by descent from principle to conclusion. This
which one opines about perceptible objects leaves open important questions. For exam-
such as beautiful sights and sounds (R. bk ple, can Plato’s sharp distinction between
5.476d; Ti. 27d–8a). Knowledge has supe- knowledge and belief be defended without
rior epistemic status (i.e. infallibility) because positing a two world ontology? (for con-
its objects are more intelligible due to their trasting interpretations, see Cherniss 1936
higher ontological status: the objects of and Fine 1990) Can reason achieve genuine
knowledge are eternal and unvarying, while knowledge independently of perception? Is
objects of opinion are perishable and muta- the distinction between reason and percep-
ble. Light is also shed on the different modes tion all that clear since reason is required to
of reason by the metaphor of the divided line make judgements about perceptible objects
(q.v.) in R. bk 6.509d–11e. Opinion is sub- (Tht. 186c–d; see Burnyeat 1990:52–65 and
divided into belief (pistis) concerning visible Cooper 1970)? Further, even though logos
objects like animals and plants, and imagi- can be translated as ‘speech’ and ‘account’
nation (eikasia), which concerns images as well as ‘reason’, how closely are the three
(e.g. reflections) of these visible objects. notions connected for Plato? Does knowl-
Knowledge also has two subdivisions: intel- edge always require giving an account? Men.
ligence (noêsis), which is concerned with the 98a states that belief falls short of knowledge

238

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 238 3/17/2001 9:21:24 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

unless we can give an account, but Tht. 210a alone he will follow reason (logos) alone’ (Lg.
finds fault with the definition of knowledge as 8.835c). The rule of reason implies the rule of
true belief with an account (see Taylor 2008). law: ‘reason (logos), striving to become law’,
Again, Sph. 263e describes thought (dianoia) commands the citizens to avoid the desires
as silent discourse (dialogos), but Ep. 7.343a that drag them down (Lg. 8.835e). This dia-
complains of the weakness of words (logoi) logue notes the linguistic similarity between
and declares that nobody with intelligence nomos (law) and nous (intelligence). But this
(nous) will be so bold as to place his thoughts again raises questions (see Miller 2005). In
in them, especially unalterable written sym- particular, granting the need for rationality
bols. Must the deliverances of reason have in politics, is the rule of reason compatible
the form of propositional knowledge (q.v.)? with the practises of democracy?
In Plato’s psychology and normative the- Plato suggests that out of all the human
ory the rational faculty opposes the other faculties reason has the greatest claim to
psychic faculties, for example, when some- immortality. At R. bk 10.611b–2a, the pure
one wants to drink yet is unwilling to do so, state of the soul is compared to the sea god
because he reasons that it would be harmful Glaucus whose primary nature cannot be
(R. bk 4.436a–9d). It does not merely delib- easily made out because he is so mutilated by
erate about how to satisfy one’s appetites, waves and encrusted by shells, stones and so
but has its own desires for knowledge of the forth. The soul’s true nature is distinguished
truth and its own pleasures taken in learning by its love of philosophy, the hallmark of
(R. bk 9.580a–1c). The rational part ought the rational faculty (cf. R. bk 9.581b). More
to rule, ‘since it is really wise and exercises explicitly Ti. 69c–70b (cf. Ti. 42e) describes
foresight on behalf of the whole soul’ (441e). the rational soul alone as ‘immortal’, the
The rule of reason is the basis for the four other ‘mortal’ souls being created later.
cardinal virtues (442b–3e). Again, questions Plato also explores the role of reason
arise (see Annas 1981): Is the rational part a on the cosmic scale, in the myth of Ti. the
sort of agent or homunculus or is it merely god (demiurge) who created the perceptible
a nexus of capacities? And is reason in fact universe, wanting to make it as like himself
the ‘natural ruler’, or is Hume right to rejoin as possible, (Ti. 30b). If the cosmos (world
that ‘reason is, and ought to be, the slave of order) does not exhibit perfect order it is
the passions?’ because it resulted from ‘the conjunction of
The rule of reason also has political necessity and intelligence’ (48a). Similarly
import. Like the soul the city has a tripartite Lg. 10.893b–9b argues that the heavenly
structure, with guardian, auxiliary and ruling motions are due to immortal self-moving
classes. The guardians should be guided by souls, and the motions are orderly if the
reason; indeed, they should be philosopher- souls are intelligent. Orderly cosmic motion
rulers: ‘unless political power and philosophy involves continuous revolution around a
coincide, there will be no respite for cities central point, a physical motion which most
from evils’ (R. bk 5.473c–d). Conceding the closely resembles the cyclical motion of intel-
impracticality of philosopher-rule, in Politicus ligence (nous) or understanding (phronêsis)
and Lg. the linchpin of rational rule becomes itself (Lg. 10.898a; Ti. 34a).
the statesman or legislator: ‘opposing the Although Plato’s radical claims on behalf
greatest desires and having no human ally, all of reason were challenged by his successors,

239

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 239 3/17/2001 9:21:25 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

starting with Aristotle, they continued to in the sand that makes use of Pythagoras’ the-
have a profound influence, notably on early orem, to solve the problem of how to double
modern rationalism (q.v.). the area of a given square (82b–5b). As crit-
ics never tire of pointing out, the experiment
proves only that with the help of suggestive
questions and a drawing a layperson can be
RECOLLECTION (ANAMNÊSIS) made to recognize certain basic geometrical
truths (Scott 2006:99–112). In addition, it
Dorothea Frede presupposes a Socrates who not only pos-
Given the importance that is attributed in the sesses the art of questioning but also knows
secondary literature to the notion that Plato the problem’s solution beforehand. Against
explains learning as the recollection (anam- this it should be objected that Plato himself
nêsis) of prenatal knowledge that needs to be actually claims no more than that Socrates’
retrieved, because it has been covered up at questioning has stirred up opinions ‘like
the moment of the soul’s embodiment, new- in a dream’ that only with further practise
comers to Plato will be surprised to learn that will eventually turn into knowledge (Men.
explicit discussion of this doctrine is confined 85c–d). It is unclear whether Plato wants to
to two of Plato’s work, the Meno and the limit such ‘recollectable’ knowledge to math-
Phaedo (with a brief reminder in Phaedrus ematical truths. Nor is it clear to what extent
249c). When recollection is referred to else- he wants to support the myth of successive
where (mostly in verbal form, but occasion- births and deaths, for in his subsequent
ally as a noun, Philebus 34b–c), it means just distinction of true opinion and knowledge
what corresponding terms mean in English, (q.v.) he remarks that true opinions are elu-
that is, reminders of ordinary experience, sive goods ‘until one ties them down by an
most of all concerning previous agreements account of the reason why. And that is recol-
in the discussion. lection, as we previously agreed (98a)’ (Scott
In the Men. recollection is introduced as 2006:182–5). Plato may therefore limit
Socrates’ solution to Meno’s ‘paradox of recollection to the soul’s innate capacity to
learning:’ How one is to search for some- comprehend nonempirical truths, like those
thing one does not know at all, for even if of mathematics (q.v.), that will first emerge
one came across it, one would not recognize as true opinions and through further reflec-
it as the thing one did not know (Men. 80d). tion turn into knowledge proper. In addition,
Socrates does not directly challenge the para- mathematical geniuses can and do ‘find’ such
dox but resorts to the mythical explanation truths without outside help, so that the most
of ‘wise men and women, priests and priest- gifted among us seem to be ‘born’ with the
esses’ that the soul (q.v.) is immortal, has requisite knowledge.
undergone many deaths and rebirths and Whether or not Plato saw the limitation
has therefore ‘seen all things’ so that it needs of his account in the Men., the explanation
only to recollect what is has once known of recollection in Phd. (after a reference back
(81a–e). To illustrate how such recollection to the model in the Men.; Phd. 72e–3b) takes
works Socrates conducts an experiment. A a different turn. Instead of a recollection of
slave without training in geometry manages, mathematical theorems prompted by sugges-
thanks to careful questioning and a drawing tive questions, recollection is now triggered

240

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 240 3/17/2001 9:21:25 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

by sense-perceptions and concerns single catalogue of virtues (65d–e); thus, forms are
objects, the objects’ intelligible concepts or not confined to concepts of moral or mathe-
forms (q.v.). Their sensible reminders need matical perfection but include physical prop-
not be like them: just as in everyday life both erties, as well as relative terms.
things that are like and unlike can cause the In the Republic, the central work of Plato’s
recollection of something that is absent. The middle years, recollection is not resorted to,
point of such recollection is explained by and this is no accident; for the careful design
simple examples such as sticks and stones of higher education that takes 15 years to
and their seeming equality and inequality complete seems to replace the notion that
(74a–5c). The point, in a nutshell, is that humans are born with the requisite knowl-
merely looking at two sticks and stones does edge. The senses in the R. do not provoke rec-
not provide certainty that they are really ollection, but instead conflicting impressions
equal to one another; sometimes they appear act as incentives to the higher learning that
so, sometimes they do not. With the equal is ultimately crowned by dialectic (q.v.), the
itself there is no such ambiguity, it never enigmatic discipline that is the hallmark of
appears unequal, and hence it is not possi- the philosopher-kings and -queens. The only
ble that the knowledge of the equal itself is dialogue that mentions recollection in the
derived from experience of sensible objects in sense presupposed in the Men. and the Phd.
this life, but humans have an innate knowl- is the Phdr. (249c). But that reference serves
edge of the equal or equality. In contradistinc- as a mediator between the mythical depiction
tion to the form their earthly representatives of the soul’s travel to a ‘superheavenly’ place
‘are eager to be like it (the equal itself), but in the wake of the gods and the subsequent
are merely like it’ and always fall short of demythologized explanation of the dialecti-
it. If such knowledge cannot be caused by cal method of collection and division, the
experience of deficient objects it must have uncovering of the generic unity of the objects
been acquired before birth and exists in a of a given field and the subsequent division
latent form that is subsequently recalled by into its different species. If there is a place
an encounter with imperfect earthly speci- for recollection in Plato’s later work, it must
mens. This argument lets Plato conclude that consist in the ability to discover the relevant
the forms, as perfect beings, must really exist unities at the different levels of universality
and with ‘equal necessity’ that our souls must that is sometimes addressed as a ‘divine gift’
have existed before birth (75c–6e). There is (Phdr. 266b; Phlb. 16c).
no determination of the types of things that
have forms, but enumerations show that they
are of quite different sorts: there is the equal REFUTATION (see Elenchus)
as well as the greater and smaller, the beauti-
ful itself (q.v. Beauty), the good itself (q.v.),
the just (q.v. Justice), the pious (q.v. Piety) RHETORIC (RHETORIKÊ)
and ‘all those things which we mark with the
seal of ‘what it itself is’ (auto ho estin), both Marina McCoy
when we are putting questions and answer- Plato’s Gorgias succinctly defines rhetoric
ing them’ (75c–d). Earlier in the Phd. Socrates as the ‘art of persuasion’ (Grg. 452e), but
had added health, strength and tallness to his in several Platonic dialogues, the question

241

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 241 3/17/2001 9:21:25 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

as to rhetoric’s scope and value is a topic technê, but a mere ‘knack’ (Grg. 463b). Just
of considerable debate. To understand the as a cook might entice children with sweets,
nuances behind the Platonic understanding while a physician recommends healthy food,
of rhetoric, it is helpful to look at both the the rhetorician appeals to his audience with
cultural context for rhetoric’s practise and the aim of gratifying them, instead of speak-
the philosophical issues that Plato raises ing about what is best (464–5e). Socrates
regarding rhetoric’s definition and value. The describes rhetoric as the ‘counterpart of
Greek term for rhetoric, rhetorikê, is derived cookery in the soul’ (465e). Later parts of the
from the word rhetôr, or speaker. In demo- Grg. associate the practise of rhetoric in poli-
cratic Athens, the democracy consisted of an tics with the corruption of justice, as with the
assembly at which any Greek citizen could character of Callicles, who recommends the
both speak on matters of legislation and life of unbridled appetites as the best.
vote. Those who were known for speaking Plato’s Phaedrus, on the other hand,
regularly and with influence were known as presents the possibility of a philosophi-
‘rhetors’. Thus, the term from its inception cal rhetoric in contrast to that of sophistic
has a political as well as an oratorical signifi- oratory. After critiquing the orator Lysias’
cance. In his dialogues, Plato examines not paradoxical speech on love, Socrates offers a
only the relationship between rhetoric and myth in defence of love that surpasses Lysias’
philosophy but also between rhetoric and speech in style and content, suggesting the
politics, and whether rhetoric might have a legitimacy of a mythological mode of speak-
corrupting influence on politicians. ing as a way to present philosophical ideas.
Some commentators have suggested that Socrates then describes a positive form of
Plato may have coined the term rhetorikê, as rhetoric that uses a method of collection and
the word appears in no extant works prior division (q.v. Method) that draws together
to the Platonic dialogues (Schiappa 1994), what one wishes to explain into a common
with the exception of Alcidamas. Not only category, and then divides it again according
Plato, but also intellectuals such as the soph- to its ‘natural joints’ (Phdr. 265d–e). Ideally,
ists, Isocrates (q.v.) and Alcidamas wrote a speaker’s discourse should be well ordered,
about the value of speech in political, foren- like a ‘living being’ (264c). Later, the Phdr.
sic and private arenas. But the Platonic dia- takes on the question as to whether the spo-
logues most forcefully and directly undertake ken or written word is more rhetorically and
the examination of rhetoric’s value and its philosophically valuable. On the one hand,
relation to philosophy and sophistry. Socrates suggests that written speech cannot
In Plato’s Grg. Socrates sets out one of address its audience with attention to their
the strongest critiques of rhetoric in the dia- specific needs, and can easily be misunder-
logues, raising at least two important ques- stood when it is ‘orphaned’ with its ‘parent’
tions in talking to Gorgias: whether rhetoric unable to defend it. On the other hand, this
is a technê (art); and whether rhetoricians critique of writing takes place within the
teach justice as part of that art (Roochnik context of a written dialogue, leading some
1998). Socrates implies that Gorgias is care- commentators to suggest that Plato may have
less about whether his students are made understood the dialogue form as overcoming
more just or unjust by the course of his teach- some of the limitations of writing (Annas
ing. Socrates also argues that rhetoric is not a 2002; Gonzalez 1995b; Griswold 1998).

242

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 242 3/17/2001 9:21:25 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

Subsequently, some commentators have more deeply the question of how one ought
taken up the question of how dialogue itself to live one’s life.
functions as a rhetorical practise (Blondell
2002; Gordon 1999; Michelini 2003; Scott
2007). We also find that many Platonic dia-
logues feature Socrates using well known SELF-KNOWLEDGE
rhetorical techniques, often with the appar-
ent aim of upsetting his interlocutor’s Andrea Tschemplik
conventional views, or as an enticement Concern for self-knowledge recurs in Plato’s
to practise philosophy (Gonzalez 1995b; writings, although no single dialogue deals
McCoy 2007). Plato’s critique of rhetoric is exclusively with it and it is often introduced
also closely linked to his criticism of poetry indirectly (Annas 1985).
in works such as the Ion and Republic The ancient Delphic inscription ‘Know
(Griswold 2009). As with the rhetoricians, Thyself’ (gnôthi s’auton) was widely under-
the poets often represent and imitate reality stood as a reminder to know one’s limits as a
in ways that are opposed to a philosophi- human being; humans, after all, are not gods.
cal orientation to the world (Rosen 1988). It then comes as no surprise that Socrates
Again, this picture is complicated by Plato’s proclaims the limits of his own knowledge at
own practise of writing dialogues that the end of his life: ‘when I do not know, nei-
themselves frequently use myths, images ther do I think I know’ (Apology 21d). This
and diverse forms of argument that overlap awareness of one’s ignorance can be under-
with the practise of rhetoricians and poets. stood as a kind of self-knowledge, and the
Indeed, one might even suggest that the Ap. shows that such knowledge also informs
Platonic ‘voice’ of the dialogues is found not a way of living. Self-knowledge can be an
only in Socrates’ claims about rhetoric, but ethical as well as an epistemological quest.
also in the ideas of his opponents, who raise The Charmides illustrates the difficulties
important objections to Socrates’ practise, of seeing self-knowledge strictly as a prob-
such as whether it is politically expedient lem of knowledge, not involving the good.
(Grg. 486a–c). Alcibiades I on the other hand analyses self-
Perhaps one way to reconcile the difficulty knowledge as the activity of caring for the
is to suggest that Plato’s polemic is against soul. In the Phaedrus we see the most com-
those who use rhetoric to flatter and to plex formulation, where the erotic exchanges
manipulate, while the use of persuasive and between lover and beloved ultimately lead to
beautiful language to question, to arouse dis- recognition of the self in the other.
comfort about our own views and to entice If the knowledge of ignorance is our guide
us into further inquiry allows philosophy and to understanding self-knowledge, then all
rhetoric to go hand-in-hand. While sophistic the conversations that end in an impasse,
rhetoric seeks only to gratify its audience, the aporetic dialogues, can be viewed as
philosophical rhetoric seeks to lead the soul guideposts on the way. The interlocutor
to further inquiry and reflection, and to the does not always acknowledge his debt to
good itself. By including both advocates and Socrates, however, for guiding him to that
critics of rhetoric in the dialogues, Plato precipice; some respond to the experience
encourages his readers to seek to understand of aporia with an arrogant shrug (Meno)

243

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 243 3/17/2001 9:21:26 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

others by running away (Euthyphro). One of Charmides’ provenance, as if knowing


notable exception is Theaetetus, who is spe- one’s ancestors is a possible way of knowing
cifically told by Socrates, the midwife, that oneself. In other dialogues, too, Socrates intro-
his philosophical mission has been accom- duces parentage as an important indicator of
plished, once Theaetetus recognizes that he the nature of his interlocutor, for example, in
does not know what he previously thought the Tht. he recognizes Theaetetus through his
(Tschemplik 2008). The Theaetetus is doubly knowledge of his father; in addition, Socrates
puzzling because knowing that one does not reveals who he is with reference to his
know what knowledge is has paradoxical mother; and in the La., Laches says that he
implications. trusts Socrates because, among other reasons,
The Alc. 1 states most directly what to he knew his father (La. 181a–b); whereas the
make of the Delphic Oracle’s pronouncement character of the children of famous fathers is
(Alc. 1 129a, 132c). Throughout the dialogue precisely at issue in this dialogue. Socrates pro-
Socrates discusses the things which we should vides another way of gaining self-knowledge
care for and be concerned about (epime- through introspection (Chrm. 159a), when
leîsthai) before we enter the public realm he insists that Charmides should look within
and care for others. He guides Alcibiades himself to find out whether he possesses
(127–31) towards the understanding that care soundmindedness. But neither genealogy nor
for the soul, above all else, is a fundamental self-inspection lead to a satisfactory answer,
expression of self-knowledge (for an interest- and Charmides hands over the discussion to
ing interpretation of this point, see Foucault his cousin Critias, who equates soundmind-
1988:23–6). In addition, Socrates points to edness with self-knowledge (165a). What
the need for a mirror (Alc. 1 132c–3c) to be follows is a complex examination of various
able to inspect oneself, offering the analogy ways self-knowledge can be construed, work-
of the pupil of the eye, in which one can see a ing through to the formulation that it is the
reflection of the self. He applies the analogy knowledge of itself and of all other knowl-
to the soul, concluding that the soul must edges as well as the knowledge of ignorance
look to the most divine region of another (166e). Self-knowledge thus understood is the
soul, that is, knowledge and prudence (to ability to discern what one knows and does
eidenai te kai phrôneîn), to come to know not know and to be able to judge the same in
herself. Socrates identifies this construction others. Socrates calls into question the useful-
of self-knowledge as soundmindedness or ness of the knowledge of knowledge, since it
moderation (sôphrosynê). Alcibiades pledges appears that it has no content: In this case
to become Socrates’ attendant in pursuit of I know that the shoemaker knows how to
becoming virtuous. make shoes, but I myself do not know how
The Chrm. ostensibly focuses on learning to make shoes. The obvious question is why
the nature of soundmindedness; it provides Critias, who will later be a leader of the Thirty
another approach to self-knowledge. In the Tyrants, offers this particular construction of
first part of the dialogue Socrates converses self-knowledge as the definition of sound-
with Charmides and, after momentarily los- mindedness (Stern 1999). Clearly, the concern
ing himself (Chrm. 155d) when overcome for the care of the soul evident in the Alc. I
by Charmides’ beauty, offers a lengthy and has been left aside; instead we have an episte-
exhaustive genealogical account (157e–8b) mological account of self-knowledge.

244

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 244 3/17/2001 9:21:26 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

In the Phdr. Socrates raises the impor- discussion of writing and logos in the second
tance of self-knowledge and connects it with half of the dialogue can also be linked with
his need for the polis and the interlocutors the theme of self-knowledge, since we reveal
that a polis provides. Phaedrus seduced ourselves to another and come to know our-
Socrates to take a walk in the countryside by selves through dialogue (Griswold 1986).
promising him an account of Lysias’ speech. That at least is Socrates’ hope.
When Phaedrus wonders whether Socrates At the end of his life, as depicted in Plato’s
believes in the mythological or the scientific Ap., Socrates displays the same commitment
accounts of various natural phenomena, to the task of self-knowledge. He opens his
Socrates responds that until he has obeyed defence (Ap. 17a) with a caveat about the
the Delphic inscription (Phdr. 229e–30a) and power of speeches because his accusers had
comes to know himself, it makes no sense to spoken so eloquently that they almost caused
investigate these other matters. He makes him to forget himself (epelathomên). In
explicit that he cannot fulfil the injunction of response, he offers to tell the truth about him-
self-knowledge by communing with nature; self, including an appeal to Apollo, the god at
instead he requires other human beings to Delphi, who is responsible for Socrates’ con-
help him examine whether he is simple and clusion that human wisdom is worth little or
divine or monstrous and typhonic. As the nothing (23b), that it amounts to awareness
dialogue unfolds we are presented with dif- of his ignorance (21d). Socrates also took it
ferent accounts of erôs and in Socrates’ sec- upon himself to persuade his fellow citizens
ond speech, the palinode, self-knowledge is that care of the soul should be everyone’s pri-
addressed again. After having presented the mary concern (30a–b), so that they can live the
soul in the metaphor of the charioteer and best possible life. Because he has taken care of
two horses, Socrates characterizes the erotic his soul, as he tried to persuade Alcibiades to
encounter between the lover and the beloved do, Socrates faces death without any fear.
(255c–6c) in terms that had already been The greatest obstacle to self-knowledge
used in the Alc. I: and the most dangerous activity we can
engage in is lying to or deceiving ourselves
Then the boy is in love, but has no idea about who we are. Another way to approach
what he loves. He does not understand, the question of self-knowledge is by exam-
and cannot explain, what has happened ining Socrates’ discussion of self-deceit and
to him. It is as if he had caught an eye
self-ignorance in the Republic (382a) and
disease from someone else, but could not
Philebus (49a–50a).
identify the cause; he does not realize
that he is seeing himself in the lover as in
a mirror. (255d)
SENSATION (see Perception and Sensation)

The Phdr. offers an erotic encounter as a way


to self-knowledge: Once each of the lovers SOPHISTS
recognize himself in the other through the
recollection of the god they both followed, Marina McCoy
they can exchange philosophical speeches In the Platonic dialogues, the term ‘sophist’
and live a life of virtue and friendship. The refers to any number of intellectuals who

245

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 245 3/17/2001 9:21:26 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

travelled from city to city and offered to sophist primarily in terms of the difficulties
teach the youth of the city a variety of topics with persuasive rhetoric in democracy; there,
ranging from rhetoric (q.v.) to politics, lin- the ‘many’ are called the ‘biggest sophists’ (R.
guistics or even natural philosophy. 492a). However, a few brief themes recur in
‘Sophist’, or sophistês, had a broad range the dialogues.
of meanings in the Greek world. From the Plato’s dialogues frequently use the soph-
fifth century onwards, ‘sophist’ meant a ‘wise ists as a foil, or a contrast to philosophy
person’ as its root, sophia (wisdom), indi- (q.v.). Perhaps this distinction was significant
cates (Kerferd 1981:24). Wise men such as because Socrates seems to have been tried and
Thales or Solon, as well as many poets, were executed partly on suspicion of being a soph-
thought to be ‘sophists’ because they pos- ist; Aristophanes’ Clouds portrays Socrates
sessed political or moral wisdom. Gradually, as a sophist as well (though Dover 1968
however, the term came to be more ambigu- disputes its accuracy). Plato in his Apology
ous, and often meant someone who had (Defence) of Socrates, carefully distinguishes
pretensions to wisdom, rather than genuine Socrates from the sophists. While the soph-
wisdom. This transition took place around ists taught students for money, Socrates
the time of Plato’s writing. Not only Plato, claims that he never accepted money and had
but also other authors, such as Alcidamas not students, but only followers. While the
and Isocrates (q.v.), criticized those with a sophists claim to know, Socrates claims that
fundamentally different understanding of his greatest wisdom is not thinking he knows
the ‘good life’ by naming their opponents as what he does not know (Ap. 21d).
sophists. Isocrates (q.v.), for example, in his Plato’s Grg. begins with a conversation
‘Against the Sophists’, speaks of the soph- between Socrates and Gorgias, who claimed
ists as those who enjoy disputation for its that he could speak persuasively on any topic
own sake, and who waste their time proving (for a fee). Socrates questions Gorgias, ask-
themselves to be clever at argument in use- ing whether Gorgias cares for his students
less topics instead of applying themselves to if he does not teach them justice as part of
significant political problems (Mirhady and the study of rhetoric. He also suggests that
Too 2000). Alcidamas, in contrast, calls those Gorgias’ students might become unjust as a
who spend all their time writing, instead of result of studying with Gorgias, if their rhe-
learning how to speak well, by the term ‘so- torical skill is used for unjust purposes. Later,
called sophists’ (Alcidamas 1, in Muir 2000). the Grg. contrasts sophistry to a legitimate
The term ‘sophist’, we find, is often used to political art that seeks the good of the city.
contrast some better, different practise or Some of the sophists also seem to have writ-
person. ten about topics that today would be consid-
Plato’s criticism of the sophists is var- ered within the realm of philosophy (Kerferd
ied and complex. In some dialogues (e.g. 1981). For example, Protagoras wrote works
Gorgias; Protagoras), he confronts the views with titles such as Truth, Antilogic and On
of specific sophists. In others, such as the the Gods. While these works do not survive,
Sophist, the topic of the sophist’s identity is fragments passed down to authors such as
explored more abstractly and linked to phil- Sextus Empiricus indicate an interest in intel-
osophical problems of metaphysics and the lectual problems. Protagoras’ best known
nature of being. The Republic considers the statement is ‘Man is the measure of all

246

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 246 3/17/2001 9:21:26 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

things: of things that are, that they are, and of than his brother, a doctor, is. Such dialogues
things that are not, that they are not’. In the between sophists and Socrates raise questions
Theaetetus, Socrates uses this idea to explore about the value of rhetoric that are not fully
and to further define a view of knowledge as answered within the dialogue itself. Instead,
perceptual relativism. Although it is rejected the term ‘sophist’ is used both to criticize
as philosophically inadequate, Protagoras those intellectuals who stood in opposition
here is not merely a rhetorician, but rather to Socratic and Platonic goals, and to chal-
an intellectual concerned with articulating a lenge Plato’s audience to reflect on the value
particular intellectual doctrine. In the Prt. we of rhetoric and its relation to philosophy.
find a different view of the sophist, one that
pokes fun at an overly majestic self-presen-
tation and an intellectual understanding of
the good that does not seem coherent when SOUL (PSYCHÊ)
pressed. Hippias and Prodicus (though less)
are also mocked for their intellectual defi- T. M. Robinson
ciencies and lack of humility. In a well known lecture John Burnet called ‘the
Plato even uses the concept of sophistry as care of the soul’ the core of Socrates’ teaching
an entryway into difficult metaphysical issues. (Burnet 1916:235 ff.), and it was undoubt-
In the Sph., the Stranger begins by attempt- edly that of Plato as well. But what exactly
ing to define the sophist, whom Socrates says they meant by soul is less easy to describe (for
is not easy to separate from the philosopher bibliographies on soul in Plato, see Robinson
and the statesman (Sph. 216c–d). However, 1995:166–76 and Wagner 2001:363–9).
by the dialogue’s end, the main focus of the That it is distinct from the body is beyond
discussion is on the nature of non-being, a doubt, but its relationship to what we would
topic that arose in the course of understand- call the person is less clear. At Charmides
ing image-making and dissembling. Again, 156e7–8 the body is an integral part of per-
Plato features the sophist as much as an sonhood; at Phaedo 115c and elsewhere it is
entryway into understanding philosophy simply the soul which is the person. Sometimes
(and later in the Politicus, politics) as for the this is refined to suggest that the ‘person’ who
purposes of rejecting sophistic discourse. is the soul is such in two senses: the person
While it is tempting to seek a single cen- who exists for a while on earth, and is charac-
tral difference between sophists and philoso- terized by reason and impulse, and the person
phers, a deeper examination at times shows who survives physical death and lives on ever-
some overlap between them (Zuckert 2000). lastingly, who seems to consist simply of rea-
For example, Plato’s Ap. features Socrates son. The matter is complicated further by talk
using some methods of rhetorical argumen- in the various myths, where the person who
tation familiar in the courtroom by that survives death is spoken of in a way suggest-
time (McCoy 2007). Plato’s dialogues often ing that she/he continues to be characterized
raise important critical questions for phi- by both reason and impulse, and differs from
losophers, such as whether rhetoric might the person who once lived on earth only by
have a political value. For example, Gorgias having cast off materiality.
points out that he is more effective at get- If the soul is the person, how does it relate
ting medical patients to undergo treatment to the body? At times it is described as what

247

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 247 3/17/2001 9:21:27 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

one might call an ‘inner person’, like a body in In the Phd. significant efforts are made to
a tomb, or a prisoner in a prison (Phd. 82e3), prove that the soul survives our bodily death
or an oyster in a shell (Phaedrus 250c6). At and lives on everlastingly. But, disconcert-
other times, it is described more positively as ingly, several senses of the word soul that
the ‘possessor’ of a body, which it ‘uses’ and are not easily reconcilable are used in the
‘controls’ (Gorgias 465d1). Either way, the dialogue, and no attempt is made to recon-
doctrine seems to be one of numerical dual- cile them, rendering what are already a set
ism (in contrast with what one might call the of dubious proofs of immortality even more
‘mitigated monism’ of the Chrm.); soul and so. The most important sense is that of soul
body seem to be distinct substances (Grg. as being the whole person, the true or genu-
464b3), such that their numerical addition ine self (Phd. 115d8–e4, 469d6–9); as such
would apparently add up to two, though soul it effectively duplicates in its actions what
is clearly stated to be the more important and most people take a person (= a soul/mind and
valuable of the two (Protagoras 313a1–c3). body combined in some way) to be doing (see
They are also in a tense, if not actively inimi- especially 94b7 ff.). Though, even this notion
cal, relationship with each other, and oper- is not a little obfuscated by talk which appar-
ate almost as independent persons, with the ently distinguishes a soul and the person who
body possessing desires of its own that can possesses that soul (66b5–7, 67e6–8). But the
run counter to the good of the soul if allowed soul is also, for purposes of various attempts
free rein (Phd. 66b6 ff.). Each can also be at proving immortality, seen as a life-
‘sick’ or ‘healthy’; the appropriate food the principle or life-carrier (69e–72d, 102a ff.),
soul needs for health is mathêmata (‘pieces and, as we have seen, as reason too. In one
of knowledge’) (Prt. 313c7), which needs to passage it is furthermore clearly thought of
be implanted in it by reputable sources, not as being indestructible because it is immate-
by sophists. rial (80b1 ff.), whereas in another it is appar-
The reference to ‘pieces of knowledge’ ently quasi-physical in nature (81c4 ff.).
points, crucially, to the fact that soul is This somewhat confusing situation is
thought of as being in its most important clarified in important ways in the R. Moral
manifestation an intellectual principle. So conflict is now affirmed to be conflict within
much so that, as we have seen, it is on occa- the soul rather than between soul and body,
sion apparently equated with reason (see and the ‘bodily’ desires (for food, drink and
Phd. 67c2–3, dianoia). It is, however, that sex) are now affirmed to be part of the soul
whereby we are moral agents too, such that itself (the body being simply their instru-
we/our soul can be characterized by such ment), and fully acceptable to the degree that
terms as ‘righteous’ and ‘depraved’ (Grg. they are controlled by reason. Such reason is
313a3, a4). The ‘health’ of the soul will now described as the controlling element in
consist of a right balance between reason a soul which is not bipartite but tripartite.
and impulse within it. If reason is in con- The soul consists, like its analogue, the state
trol, the soul will manifest the virtues ‘tem- of a ruling part (reason), a soldier/police part
perance’ and ‘justice’; if folly is in control, (‘spiritedness’, thymos) and a desiderative
and impulse allowed free rein, the soul will part. The goodness of the soul like the jus-
be a sick one, ‘intemperate and unjust and tice of the state consists of a balance between
unholy’ (505b2–4, c7–d3). all three parts, such that each plays the role

248

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 248 3/17/2001 9:21:27 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

appropriate to it and only the role appropri- In the Laws, Plato repeats the Phdr. doc-
ate to it. trine that soul is the source of movement/
This view of soul as tripartite is repeated change and forever self-moving/self-chang-
in detail in the Timaeus, though now there ing, while still being of its nature contin-
is added to it the remarkable view that the gent, but (influenced possibly by the view of
universe itself, being a living thing, also pos- Aristotle) he seems to have come round to
sesses a soul. Differently from human soul, the view that the world we know is sempit-
however, this soul is simply rational; there are ernal, not everlasting, so that soul’s self-mov-
no two ‘lower’ parts to it. And a major clari- ing/self-changing nature will be such across
fication of the doctrine of immortality comes sempiternity (i.e. with neither temporal
with the affirmation that the universe’s soul beginning nor end) rather than being char-
and the (rational) human soul are everlasting acterized by everlastingness once it has been
(i.e. with a beginning in time but without an formed. Apart from this, the Lg. is a work
end), all of them having been formed by a in which he returns to the bipartite vision of
divine fashioner (the Demiurge) at a point in soul that was prominent in early dialogues;
time which was the beginning of time. In the only the disiecta membra (pace Saunders
same dialogue we are also introduced to the 1962:37–55) of the theory of tripartition
view that there is a difference between male seems now to remain. And till the end his
and female souls, the female having an inbuilt basic psycho-physical dualism remains a
tendency towards immoral conduct (kakia) problem for him; in this, his last work, he is
that the male lacks. This is little noticed by still unclear as to whether the soul of the sun,
commentators, and would be disconcerting for example, carries it from within, pushes it
if it reflected Plato’s own thinking. from without, or guides it along its path ‘by
In the Phdr., we find an apparent reference virtue of possessing some other prodigious
to a tripartite soul in the famous myth of the and wonderful powers’ (Lg. 898e8–9a4).
charioteer. The first statement in that same Two paths, however, towards a possible
dialogue, however, of soul’s being immortal mitigation of the problem posed by psycho-
because it is a ‘source of motion/change’ and physical dualism which are mentioned in other
itself everlastingly ‘self-moving/changing’ sug- dialogues, but ultimately not taken, are worth
gests that Plato may now be moving towards mentioning. Early on, in the Chrm., he had
a different vision of its nature; certainly its looked with interest if not, in the final analysis,
supposed tripartition never appears again conviction at the possibility that the body too,
with clarity in any dialogue after the Phdr. not just the soul, was integral to the concept
The Philebus repeats the notion (seen in of a person. And his view, in the Ti. (35a), that
detail in the Ti.) that soul depends for its the soul has in its very structure something of
existence upon an intelligence that performs both the form world and the world of mat-
the task of ‘fashioning’ and ‘making’ things ter suggests that, at one time at any rate in his
(Phlb. 27b1, 26e6), reaffirming that all soul lifetime of research into the nature of the soul,
is of its nature contingent, with the excep- he might have believed that the gap between
tion, perhaps, of the soul of the Demiurge soul and body might possibly be bridged if it
if the Demiurge is to be understood as a could be shown that the soul was not as close
reality and as something more than simply to being wholly immaterial as he had believed
intelligence. it to be when he wrote the Phd.

249

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 249 3/17/2001 9:21:27 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

THE SUN SIMILE that it is by sight (507c1–2). But unlike other


varieties of perception, Socrates continues,
Nicholas D. Smith sight requires some additional ‘third kind
At 504e4–6 in the Republic, Glaucon asks of thing’ in order to occur: light, without
Socrates to say what the ‘most important which even those with good eyesight can-
subject’ will be in the future ruler’s studies. not see (507d11–e2). The sun, they agree, is
This subject, declares Socrates, is the form the ‘cause and controller’ of light (508a4–8).
of the good (R. 505a2), for it is ‘by their These observations provide the groundwork
relation to it that just things and the others for the simile to the good, according to
become good and useful’ (505a3–4, trans. which, ‘What the good itself is in the intelli-
Grube and Reeve). But Socrates then goes gible realm, in relation to understanding and
on immediately to insist that ‘we have no intelligible things, the sun is in the visible
adequate knowledge of it’ (505a5–6). He realm, in relation to sight and visible things’
criticizes ‘the majority’ who identify the good (508c1–2).
with pleasure, on the ground that there are In brief, then, the details of the simile are
bad pleasures (505c7–8), and also the ‘more these:
sophisticated’ who claim that it is knowl-
edge, on the ground that when pressed to realm: Being becoming
say what sort of knowledge it might be, they
highest entity the good the sun
can only answer that it is ‘knowledge of the
and cause:
good’ (505b8–10). Glaucon then challenges
Socrates to state what he thinks the good is applicable knowledge vision
(506b2–4), and though Socrates first chas- power:
tises him for seeking just another opinion on medium truth light
the subject (506b5–d1), when Glaucon per- required for
sists in his request (506d2–5), Socrates care- power to
fully stipulates that he will not even attempt operate:
to articulate a theory of the good, but is will- objects forms visible
ing instead to ‘tell you about what is appar- effected: particulars
ently an offspring of the good and most like
it’ (506e3–4). organ by mind eye(s)
which power
So begins the first of what have been
operates:
called the great ‘similes of light’ – the sun
and divided line (in that order) at the end of defective relative relative
R. bk 6, and the cave at the beginning of R. condition: absence of absence of
bk 7. Simply put, the simile of the sun com- truth light
pares the relative positions and roles of the results of opinion poor
good, in its domain, to that of the sun, in the defective eyesight
sensible world. Socrates begins by remind- condition:
ing Glaucon of the distinction (introduced at
the end of R. bk 5) between forms and par- Several features of this simile have cre-
ticulars (507b2–10). Socrates then asks how ated interpretive discussion and contro-
we see visible things, and Glaucon answers versy. First, a vital element of the simile is

250

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 250 3/17/2001 9:21:27 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

the comparison of truth (alêtheia) to light Finally, there has been some discussion
(phôs). But this entails that truth cannot be of Plato’s startling claim that the good in
two-valued, as it is in sentential logic, but some way ‘transcends’ (Shorey 1937:107),
must come in degrees. Some translators (e.g. ‘exceeds’ (Bloom 1968:189), ‘surpasses’
Shorey 1935) have tried to remediate this (Ferrari 2000:216), or is ‘beyond’ (White
puzzling feature by translating ‘alêtheia’ as 1979:180) or ‘superior to’ (Grube and
‘truth and reality’, but modern readers may Reeve) being (at R. 509b9, translating Plato’s
find degrees of reality no less puzzling than ‘epekeina’). Some earlier interpretations held
degrees of truth. In a famous essay, Gregory that we cannot even attribute being to the
Vlastos (1981), noting that the application of form of the good, but now most scholars
‘alêtheia’ here is not to propositions, but to maintain that the language of transcendence
entities, proposed conceiving of alêtheia as here simply emphasizes the causal primacy
more or less like the conception of truth at of the good, relative to the rest of ‘what is’,
work in expressions such as ‘true friend’ or in the same way that the sun is claimed to
‘real friend’ where there are plainly also peo- be the ultimate source of causation in its
ple who qualify as friends in some lesser way. realm, while still being (very visibly!) a part
But as Vlastos carefully notes, this requires of that realm.
(but also facilitates) what has come to be
known as the ‘predicative’ reading of Plato’s
use of the verb ‘to be’ (einai), since neither
existence nor sentential truth (as the ‘existen- THEOLOGY
tial’ and ‘veridical’ interpretations of ‘einai’,
respectively, would have it; see Smith 2000) Harold Tarrant
can make sense of degrees of being. An entity, Later Platonism (q.v. Academy), from the
accordingly, may be said to be more or less F, time of Plutarch, seems to have regarded
and would thus have the appropriate degree Plato as a supreme theologian, who postu-
of alêtheia (as an F-thing). lated a limited number of distinct divine pow-
Also unfamiliar to modern readers is ers – a very small number of gods in authors
Plato’s comparison of knowledge to eyesight such as Alcinous (Didascalicus 10 etc.) and
as a ‘power’ (see R. 508b6), though this con- Numenius, but rather a large one in Proclus’
ception was also explicitly at work in the great Platonic Theology, which extended to
epistemology provided at the end of R. bk 5, six books. Proclus assembled this theology
by which the philosopher was distinguished primarily from the Parmenides and Timaeus,
from the nonphilosopher. Contemporary and secondarily from a range of passages,
epistemology conceives of knowledge not as many myths among them, from other works.
a cognitive power, but rather as the state that Theology was a huge issue in late antiq-
may – in the best cases, at any rate – be pro- uity, and in Platonism this was especially so
duced as a result of the successful or proper because ‘assimilation to god as far as possi-
use of our cognitive powers. Various interpre- ble’ had become entrenched as the very goal
tations have been offered for how we may of human life. Furthermore, the struggle for
compare Platonic to contemporary episte- or against Christianity necessarily involved
mology, but this subject continues to be con- matters of theology, and the protagonists vied
troversial among scholars (see Smith 2000). for the authority of Plato by offering rival

251

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 251 3/17/2001 9:21:28 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

interpretations, particularly of the demiurge At the end of Plato’s life there seems to
in the Ti. If Plato believed in a father figure have been a major step towards astral the-
creating the world at a given point, attended ology, where not only an intelligent cosmic
by a host of lesser supernatural beings who motive power, or soul, is postulated (as at Ti.
acted for him in the physical world, then it 35a and Laws 10.896d–7c) but also unerr-
was clearly easier for Christians to admire ingly intelligent souls of the heavenly bod-
him and to point to him as a predecessor. ies. Perfect intelligence that is not subject to
However, to consider Plato as a theolo- decay is not unnaturally held to be the sign of
gian may seem unnatural today. His lead- divinity. This kind of astral theology, which
ing speaker is frequently indifferent to the involves the earth too being treated as a god,
identity of the god of which he speaks, and is present at Ti. 38c–40d, but it reaches its
sometimes even to whether he uses the singu- climax only with the Epinomis, and it con-
lar (god) or plural (gods), regularly leading tinues in the work of later Platonists.
readers to wonder whether he is a polythe- As for the gods of mythology, Ti. 40d–1a
ist or monotheist. This is not unnatural. His seems very reluctant to say much about
‘Socrates’ is clearly attracted to the basic them, regarding the subject as difficult, and,
Anaxagorean idea of a controlling intel- like Phaedrus 229c–30a, an unnecessary dis-
ligent power, single but wide ranging in its traction. It is therefore best to go along with
operation (Phaedo 97b–8b; Cratylus 400a). tradition. Cra. 395e–410d gives etymologies
Intelligence was assumed to lead always in for very many gods and godlike entities, ety-
the same direction. Any Platonic god will mologies that also attempt to have the names
behave in accordance with intelligence, and explain their divine function. However, the
Plato seems to have considered that this whole passage, in which Socrates is said to
would eliminate fundamental disagreement have been inspired by the rather ambigu-
among the members of a pantheon. For this ous figure of Euthyphro (Euthphr. 396d–e),
reason Plato rejects the kind of god depicted and, while not to be dismissed as mere trivia,
in Hesiod and Homer in Republic bk 2. seems to undercut itself regularly enough to
Where intelligence rules, as most obviously make it unclear how seriously it is all meant.
perhaps at Philebus 28d–30e, no real divi- One should be similarly cautious of Plato’s
sions need be postulated – except perhaps a willingness to employ the traditional gods
division between intelligence itself and soul, in some of his myths (Gorgias 523a–4a;
both integral to the concept of ‘Zeus’ as Protagoras 320c–3a), since it was natural
cause at 30d. for him to compose them mainly from tradi-
It is therefore natural that Plato must tional materials.
reject any notion of a universe controlled by Much of the discussion relating to Plato’s
two gods of opposing intent (Politicus 270a). theology has concentrated on trying to rec-
The tendency of the world to slip backwards oncile the evidence of different dialogues,
at times must therefore be explained in terms particularly regarding the supreme divinity.
of the temporary relinquishing of divine con- Is it the demiurge of the Ti. for instance? Or
trol. In this dialogue the controlling god is the idea of the good from R. bk 6? Is the
therefore compared with a helmsman, who idea of the good closely related to the One
occasionally takes a rest from his duties at (q.v.) as discussed in Prm.? And if so, how
the rudder. are they related to the demiurge, assuming

252

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 252 3/17/2001 9:21:28 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

his portrait is to be taken seriously? The last decade have, in a sense, replayed debates
problem lies with those brought up under of the early twentieth century, when a hyper-
the influence of modern world religions that rationalizing neo-Kantian interpretation of
make salvation depend on worshipping the Plato gave way to a reaction, for example,
right god and believing in the right creed. For by the Platonists of the ‘George-Kreis’, as
Plato the most important thing in the politi- well as by Julius Stenzel (1883–1935), Bruno
cal context was belief in gods, and in gods Snell (1896–1986) and Martin Heidegger
who have some concern for matters of this (1889–1976). Today, scholars disagree about
world, as Lg. bk 10 demonstrates. At a more Platonic visuality: some believe that for Plato,
personal level, happiness depends on getting the most authentic cognition is dialectic
our inner selves in tune with the divine by (q.v.), and thus the cognition/vision compari-
raising our own souls to the highest level son is merely a figure of speech; others draw
of rationality that is attainable (Theaetetus various serious conclusions from Plato’s mul-
176a–c; R. 613a–b; Ti. 90a–d). This is the tiple and extensive use of visual motifs. Some
process of assimilation to god, central to (e.g. Press 1995) even use the term ‘vision’ to
later Platonism, but never explored at length define the polyphonic and dialogical charac-
or established by dialectical argument in ter of Plato’s philosophy as a whole.
Plato himself. Platonic visuality poses a number of
problems. Though historians of science con-
sider him an important and comprehensive
VIRTUE (see Excellence) source, physiological representations (e.g. of
vision as two opposite streams, one from an
object and one from the eye meeting half-
VISION way, Timaeus 45a–6c, 67d) merely attest that
Plato was well informed about the science of
Michail Maiatsky his time (Hippocrates of Chios, Democritus
Plato’s interest in vision and the visual is and even Empedocles). The study of optics,
multifaceted, and complex. Visual words and which drew on the fields of geometry, physics
images are frequent in the dialogues along or ophthalmology, actually developed later
with many direct and indirect discussions of on. Thus, Plato tended to treat it as the sub-
physiological, intellectual and social vision. ject of a ‘likely story’ (eikos logos) and part
The increased emphasis in recent scholarship of a wider ensemble, which could be called
on the importance of visuality in Plato is a scopics.
part of a ‘scopic turn’, the effect of which was Plato’s scopics involves optics, the psychol-
to ground interpretations of the history of ogy of visual perception, theories of light,
western European philosophy and metaphys- colour and optical illusions, theories of the
ics in its entirety in certain optical premises. image and of the sun (which in the Republic
On this view, the Ancient Greeks, as the is a metaphysical being), together with stud-
founders of the European thinking tradition, ies of mimêsis (imitation; q.v.) and sêmeiôsis
were said to be ocular people in contrast to (the relation between signs and things signi-
the verbal/acoustic Jews. A particular reading fied). Social visibility is also important for
of Plato played a key role – both positive and Plato as attested by comments on the psy-
negative – in this. Studies published in the chology of observation, testimony, ocular

253

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 253 3/17/2001 9:21:28 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

witnessing and judgement (Laches passim, (2) Plato expressed the distinction between
Symposium 194bc, 218d; R. 442bc, 537c), the sensible and the intelligible through
the problem of (in)visibility of virtue and the opposition of two types of vision (e.g.
justice (Meno 72cd; Phaedo 65d; Phaedrus the two visions of the soul, Phd. 65–79;
254bc; R. 577a, 368c–9a, 402de, 445bc, R. 523–4), although corporeal vision can
501b, 611bd), the aesthetics of theatre (ety- impede or on the contrary favour ‘real’
mologically linked to ‘theory’) and perform- vision (the intellect looking upwards, Tht.
ance in general (Laws 659b, 701a), as well 174a) by the invisible soul. This problem
as the theory of beauty (Phdr. 249d–50d). is connected with a Platonic imperative of
Statements related to this broad scopic inter- knowing the similar by the similar, since
est belong to different but closely related cat- the invisible object can be ‘seen’ only by
egories, among which one can distinguish: (a) an invisible ‘seer’, that is, soul.
visual situations: visual exchanges between (3) The relationship between cognition and
participants of the dialogues, condensation recognition (Philebus 38cd; R. 376ac,
of the visual lexicon and word games, mise- 484cd; Tht. 189b sq.) is both interest-
en-scènes implying observation, performance ing and important. One can attribute
and the visual aspect; (b) myths: of the cave to Plato a certain opsodicy (coined after
(R. bk. 7), of the Ring of Gyges (R. 359c sq., Leibniz’s theodicy; cf. its platonic ante-
612b), of the charioteer and his horses (Phdr. cedent in R. 617e), whereas vision is
246b sq.), of the Demiurg and his paradigm summoned to the trial that will reveal its
(Ti.); and (c) statements or doctrines that participation in the creation of illusions
raise various philosophical questions linked and distractions from what is true, and
to vision: justify it partially.
(4) The problem of illumination or sudden
(1) The main problem of interpretation lies knowledge (Epistles 7 341cd, 344b; Smp.
in the tension between what might be 210e), implying that the dialectical proc-
considered Plato’s ‘doctrine’ and his lan- ess climaxes in a vision-like revelation of
guage. In order to show the importance the truth.
of the dialectical grasp of the invisible, (5) The problem of the relation ‘being’ to
he frequently uses visual vocabulary and ‘seeming’ on the ethical and political
images; but the analogy between vision level (Apology 21c, 41b; Hippias Major
and knowledge often encountered in 294d; Lysis 217cd; R. 360e–1d, 362a,
his work seems at odds with the invis- 365c) as well as on the epistemological
ible character of objects of genuine sci- in terms of the opposition between truth
ence. This tension culminates in the and opinion (Tht. 188a and passim; R.
designation of invisible paradigms with 475d, 479e–80a, 527de).
words such as idea and eidos (q.v. forms) (6) Discussions of the participation of the eye
derived from the verb idein (the meaning in vision (Tht. 184c sq.) are inserted in
of which, however, was ‘to know’, before philosophical reflections on the soul, on
narrowing to ‘to see’). The traditional the role of mind (nous), on the question
expression ‘theory of ideas’ turns out to of its unity and its relation to sensation
be an oxymoron, meaning the contem- or perception (aisthêsis; q.v.). The mind
plation of the invisible. itself becomes a supervisor of all active

254

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 254 3/17/2001 9:21:28 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

sensation, taking on the function of the characters, both real and fictional, and the
inner eye, or the eye of the soul. use of imagery involving female functions
(7) The relationship of eyesight with the and traditional female activities.
other senses, for example, the competi- At Meno 73a–c Socrates counters Meno’s
tion between the senses (Ti. 45b–7b). traditional belief (Men. 71e) that a man’s vir-
Eyesight is sometimes considered as one tue is very different from that of a woman
of the senses (Tht. 163d), at others it is by arguing that all humans are good in the
representative of all the other senses, a same way. The spheres in which men and
model sense. Primarily, however (Phd. women operate, however, may still be dif-
79a; Ti. 30cd), it features in asymmetric ferent: Socrates does not commit himself.
oppositions such as the ‘sensible’ versus Republic bk 5 addresses this issue: at R.
‘invisible’, or the ‘thinkable’ versus ‘vis- 456b we are told that the nature (physis) of
ible’. Plato’s rational ethics (q.v.) and women is ‘akin’ or (somewhat confusingly)
moral epistemology (q.v.) suggest that ‘the same’ as the nature of men. The only dif-
one should prefer the invisible to the vis- ference is that the female bears and the male
ible, and that this preference is precisely begets (454e) and this difference is not rel-
what distinguishes the philosopher from evant when considering what jobs each can
any other person. Plato was the first to do. In consequence, the more able women
compare and clearly distinguish eyesight are capable of being trained to be guardians,
and thought. He created the vocabulary either as military auxiliaries or (540c) phi-
of visual metaphors, which he deployed losopher-queens. These guardian women are
as a pedagogical strategy for selecting to live in camp communes with their male
and educating people towards philoso- counterparts, and their eugenically bred chil-
phy and the pursuit of truth. Whereas for dren are to be taken away at birth and raised
those starting out on their ascent towards in nurseries, thus releasing them for military
philosophy, the visual operated as a met- and political duties.
aphorical tool enabling them to ‘see’ the These proposals have provoked heated
truth, for Academy initiates vested with debate. Is it really necessary to abolish
the eye of reason (e.g. R. 533de), the met- the family to allow women to take part in
aphor contained a different message: it is political and military life? Is Socrates only
not a ‘physiological’ vision at all. allowing women education and power on
condition that they become parodies of
men, hunting, wrestling and going to war?
WEAKNESS OF WILL (see Akrasia) Or does this view say more about the preju-
dices of the modern critic than of Socrates
(or Plato)? It is certainly true that Socrates is
WOMEN not interested in the ‘rights’ of women, qua
women, or in enabling individual women to
Angela Hobbs fulfil their potential; his concern, just as with
The significance of women in Plato can be the male citizens, is to harness their abilities
gleaned from four main sources: explicit and energies for the overall good of the state.
statements about the capabilities of women, For these reasons, and to avoid anachro-
casual remarks about women, female nism, it may be inappropriate to describe his

255

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 255 3/17/2001 9:21:29 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

agenda as ‘feminist’; we may also note that woman’s natural capacity for virtue is said
the possibility of female guardians depends to be inferior to a man’s, and at 781a women
on the domestic support of women from the are said to be ‘secretive and crafty’ owing to
producer class. their weakness. The Timaeus is even more
Elsewhere in the R., however, women are problematic. At Ti. 42a the male sex is said
casually disparaged, such as at 469d where to be superior (kreitton: this may just imply
plundering a corpse is said to be a mark of physical strength, but could also connote
‘feminine small-mindedness’. Some of the moral superiority), while at 90e–1a we hear
apparent anomalies can be dissolved if we that men who lived cowardly and unjust
consider that Plato distinguishes between lives were reincarnated as women. In 91c the
women as he currently perceives them womb is spoken of as an internal creature,
in Athens, ill-educated and confined and desirous of child-making; if this desire is
women as they could be if properly trained. thwarted it becomes ill and wanders through
But this distinction, though important, does the body, creating havoc. For those who want
not explain away the fact that Socrates some- to reconcile the Ti. with the more progressive
times appears to forget that there will be views expressed elsewhere, the best option is
female guardians too: at 395d, for instance, to emphasize that it is Timaeus, not Socrates,
trainee guardians are forbidden from taking who makes these claims.
the parts of women when acting or recit- In three dialogues Socrates claims to
ing ‘because they are men’. But who are to have received wise instruction from women,
be the role models for future philosopher- although they never appear in person and
queens? The Platonic corpus is notably short in each instance Socrates’ tone is difficult
of female ideals, although Alcestis is praised to gauge. The most notable is Diotima in
for sacrificing her life for her husband the Smp., a priestess who instructs Socrates
Admetus at Symposium 179b–c. Even in R. in erôs and to whom is given a key speech.
bk 5 women and children are said to be held Yet she is also called a ‘perfect sophist’ (Smp.
in common by the guardians (R. 461e), and 208c) – a highly ambivalent term in Plato’s
at 455d Socrates claims that in general the hands – and is credited only with delaying
class of men surpasses the class of women in the arrival of the plague in Athens; she could
everything. There are also a number of ref- not avert it altogether. Similar ambiguities
erences (e.g. 451e) to women being weaker apply to Aspasia, whom Socrates claims in
than men, and although Socrates probably the Menexenus to have trained him, Pericles
only has physical weakness in mind, it is just and many others in the art of rhetoric, and
possible that he intends intellectual inferior- to whom are attributed both Pericles’ funeral
ity as well. speech and another recounted by Socrates. It
Similar tensions apply to the Laws. On is difficult to assess the level of irony here:
one hand, at Lg. 805a the Athenian Stranger certainly Menexenus is sceptical that a mere
says it is foolish for men and women not to woman could have performed such feats
share a common education and thus enable (Mx. 249d), but this may say more about him
the state to double its achievements, and in than about Plato’s view of Aspasia. Finally,
consequence women in the Lg. take part in at Men. 81a Socrates says that he learnt of
military activities up to fifty and may hold reincarnation and the doctrine of recollec-
political office after forty. Yet, at 781b a tion from certain wise priests and priestesses,

256

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 256 3/17/2001 9:21:29 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

though he later (Men. 86b) expresses uncer- belief he supported (if Diogenes Laertius 3.4
tainty on these teachings. is to be believed) by allowing at least two
Actual women are sometimes present in women to attend the Academy (q.v.).
the dialogues, but none speaks apart from
Xanthippe, Socrates’ wife, who laments his
impending death at Phaedo 60a. However,
Socrates immediately banishes her; her cries WRITING (TOPIC)
would presumably disturb their enquiries
on the immortality of the soul. Similarly, at David Blank
Smp. 176e the aulos-girl is sent away so that Athens in the late fifth and fourth centuries
the men can discuss erôs without distraction; was home to a public enthusiastic for both
it is notable that when Alcibiades arrives oratory and instruction generally. Speech
escorted by an aulos-girl at Alc. 212c–d, writers (logographoi; q.v. Isocrates) com-
this is the point at which orderly discussion posed political and forensic orations for
disintegrates. others to give, and some of those who gave
But while women are largely absent, their own speeches or lectures also wrote
imagery drawn from female bodily func- manuals of arts such as rhetoric, as well as
tions and traditional female activities is not. books on scientific and philosophical sub-
Diotima claims at Smp. 206c that all humans jects. Plato’s Socrates, in contrast, insists that
are pregnant in both body and soul, and the way to do philosophy is through a dia-
that falling in love with a beautiful person lectical question-and-answer conversation
or object enables us to give birth; while at in a discourse (logos) ‘written with knowl-
Theaetetus 148e–51d Socrates refers to him- edge in the learner’s soul’ (Phaedrus 276a5)
self as a midwife to other men’s thoughts. and guided by one who can divide reality
In the Politicus, true statesmanship is said at the joints, a ‘dialectician’ (266c). While a
to be the expertise which correctly weaves rhetorical speech can be attractive, stimulat-
together opposing human characteristics ing, entertaining and persuasive, its author
and character types (Plt. 305e–11c). There is may not be truly knowledgeable and able
keen debate as to whether such imagery ele- to ‘aid’ (boêthein) his discourse by answer-
vates or denigrates actual women. Whatever ing questions and expanding upon it. The
the answer, the use of ‘female’ imagery same holds for written discourse, and one
needs to be considered together with Plato’s criticism of those who make speeches is that,
depiction of philosophy in terms of ‘male’ when questioned, they are as silent as books
imagery drawn from war, hunting and ath- or keep sounding the same note, like a bell
letics (though, as the female guardians show, (Protagoras 329a).
these activities need not be exclusively the The Phdr. expands on this critique (Phdr.
provenance of men). 275d4). Written words seem to be alive
If Plato’s views on women are complex, and to speak from understanding, yet when
this may partly be because he sees the ulti- questioned, only repeat the same thing. This
mate human goal as ascension to the realm dialogue contains Plato’s only extended dis-
of the nongendered forms. Nevertheless, it cussion of writing (274b–8b); in it he has
is clear that he thinks the state will benefit Socrates put some of writing’s disadvantages
if some women at any rate are educated – a in the mouth of Thamus, an ancient King of

257

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 257 3/17/2001 9:21:29 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

Upper Egypt: it induces forgetfulness; it gives Written discourses are subjected to inter-
the reader both the impression he has knowl- pretation and criticism in other Platonic
edge, and the boorishness that comes with dialogues too. Protagoras (Prt. 339a) cites
that impression. Socrates not only accepts an ode of Simonides in order to point out a
these strictures, he adds that it is folly to contradiction in it: Socrates defends it, but
believe that written instructions for an art – by a probably specious interpretation of its
rhetoric, say – can actually teach, and not language. In the Phaedo Socrates recounts
merely remind those who already know what (Phd. 97c–d) how, impressed by a reading
they say. One who actually knows what is from a book of Anaxagoras, he bought it,
just, fine and good, however, will instruct a but was disappointed when he learned that
pupil personally; he will take this kind of Anaxagoras did not actually explain how
instruction seriously; he will view writing as ‘mind’ made everything for the best.
an amusement, storing up reminders for his In addition to its portrayal of the unsuc-
old age and for his successors. Like writing, cessful defence of Protagoras’ book, the Tht.
lecturing does not permit genuine, productive is the only dialogue to call attention to the
instruction (didachê). Further, a written dis- process of recording a dialectical conversa-
course reaches those who do not understand tion in writing. Euclides has called on his
it and so have no business with it, and when memory of what Socrates told him and also
it is attacked it cannot defend itself without asked Socrates himself to fill in the gaps in
the aid of its father, who wrote it. his memory, in order to write down a con-
The helplessness of written discourse is versation Socrates had had with the young
prominent in the main body of the dialogue, Theaetetus. Decades later, when Terpsion
when Phaedrus reads aloud to Socrates a wants to hear the conversation, Euclides
speech he admires written by Lysias, a log- has his slave read it aloud (Tht. 143b–c).
ographos. Socrates conjectures that Phaedrus The book is therefore read in the presence
has secured the speech in a book roll, so of its author; but far from being its ‘father’,
that he could practise his own version of it; or even a participant in the original conver-
but instead he is pushed by Socrates to read sation, Euclides was merely an amanuensis
the original – whereupon Socrates gives his and, beyond his introductory statement, he
own, better speech on the same subject, and does not intervene in its telling in any way.
adds both a ‘palinode’ in which the oppo- The real authorship of the dialogue belongs
site point of view is maintained, and a cri- to others. This reading of the conversation
tique of Lysias’ speech (264b). Clearly, in from a book roll, then, is like Antiphon’s
the absence of its father Socrates is free to telling of what he heard from Pythodorus
handle the speech roughly, although Lysias about the conversation between Socrates,
would perhaps not have been able to aid Aristotle, Zeno and Parmenides (Parmenides
it, even had he been present. The same may 126a–7a) or Apollodorus’ narrative of the
hold of Protagoras’ book Truth, which in the symposium at Agathon’s house, which he
Theaetetus finds various defenders, including heard from Aristodemus, who was there,
even an imagined Protagoras redivivus, who and checked with Socrates (Symposium
briefly pops his head out of the earth, only to 172a–3e). The Phd., in contrast, is a first-
dash off again (Tht. 171d) – while in fact no person recollection of Socrates’ last hours
one comes successfully to its aid. by Phaedo, who also intervenes at a crucial

258

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 258 3/17/2001 9:21:29 PM


TOPICS AND THEMES TREATED IN THE DIALOGUES

moment, when his listener, Echecrates, has and in fact later it is Parmenides who comes
interrupted his narrative, dismayed like to the aid of his own thesis. In a model of
the participants themselves at the fate of the superiority of personal instruction over
some of Socrates’ arguments (Phd. 88c–9a). writing, he carefully takes Socrates through
Phaedo’s intervention, like Socrates’ inter- his challenges to the theory of forms, and
vention at this point in the conversation, then, by questioning the youngest person
respects the audience’s reactions, as recom- present, through a very challenging set of
mended for didactic conversation in the eight deductions, a process he qualifies as
Phdr. ‘training’ (135d7).
Zeno’s book, read at the beginning of the In the pseudo-Platonic Ep. 7 there is a
conversation reported in the Prm., is the critique, partially overlapping that in Phdr.,
only book defended in a Platonic dialogue of any attempt to write about the subjects
by its author: when Socrates begins to ques- that occupy Plato. The author argues (Ep.
tion Zeno about his motive for writing it, he 341b–5c) that writing can be of little use
explains he intended to support Parmenides’ about these serious matters, viz. the highest
famous argument (Prm. 128c6), but that it and first things of nature, which can only be
was written out of youthful ambition and grasped after a lengthy practise of the philo-
stolen by someone else before he could sophical life and once their names, definitions
decide whether or not to publish it – perhaps and qualities have been tested between teacher
an indication that he is disowning his work; and apt pupil in question and answer.

259

9780826435354_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 259 3/17/2001 9:21:30 PM


5
LATER RECEPTION,
INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE
OF PLATO AND THE DIALOGUES

Section A: The Interpretation and as a decipherer retrieving a meaning not


Influence of Plato in the Ancient World explicitly expressed by the divine. Along the
same lines, poets conceive of poetry as being
oblique. This conception rests ultimately on
ANCIENT HERMENEUTICS a gap between the literality of a speech and
its meaning, which is only accessible to wise
Catherine Collobert people (Bacchylides, Ep. 3.85).
Hermeneutics, the art of interpretation, Both the poets, because of their puz-
derives its name from Hermes, the messen- zling way of writing, and philosophers like
ger god. Ancient hermeneutical practises pro- Xenophanes and Heraclitus, because of their
vide the context in which Plato interprets the critique of Homeric poetry, giving rise to a
poets (q.v. Epic and Lyric Poets) and may also need for interpretation. There are basically
help in understanding how later ancient writ- four types of interpretation: (a) non-historic,
ers interpreted his dialogues (q.v. Academy). in which the historical context is ignored and
Hermeneutics originates from a specific the focus is on perennial questions, (b) his-
view on the relationship between the poet toric or exegetic, whose purpose is to retrieve
and his or her works. That the poet’s speech the authorial intention identified with the
is prophetic and oracular on account of its meaning, (c) pseudo-historic or allegorical,
connection with the divine is first claimed which is not necessarily defensive, that is,
by Pindar (Pythian 6.6, f. 94a5). The anal- meant to defend Homer from his detractors
ogy of the muse with the Pythia and, conse- and (d) intrinsic, in which the meaning is
quently, of the poet with the seer illustrates viewed as exceeding the authorial intention
the conception of poetry as an interpretation (Tate 1939).
of the Muses’ speeches. In fact, the oblique Allegorical interpretation (allêgorêsis)
quality of divine oracles expresses the idea rests on the idea that the poet purposively
of a hidden meaning in need of decipher- hides his intention. Hyponoia, which is usu-
ment (Odes 2.83–8). The poet thus appears ally translated into ‘hidden meaning’, that

260

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 260 3/8/2001 5:11:52 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

is, intentionally hidden, means literally a most practitioners of allêgorêsis claim. In


thought that lies under la lettre du texte. this regard, although Plato’s allêgorêsis does
Plutarch maintains that allêgoria substi- not appear much different in practise from
tuted for the obsolete hyponoia (Moralia that of the pre-Socratics (q.v.) and sophists
19E). However, although allêgoria entails (q.v.), there is a significant difference, which
hyponoia, the converse does not hold. Not is the absence of the idea of implicit philo-
all hyponoia consists in allêgoria according sophical truths purposively hidden by poets.
to which, for instance, the Trojan War com- The poet is definitely not a philosopher (q.v.
prises a physical or an astronomical theory. Philosophy and Philosopher) and therefore
Theagenes of Rhegium, Pherecydes of Syros not able to provide philosophical truths.
and Metrodorus of Lampsaca (‘DK’ 61A4) Belonging to the realm of opinion and belief
practise allêgorêsis by transposing the poetic (e.g. R. 331d5), poetry has no truth-value.
meaning into a philosophical framework, In consequence, interpreting poetry has
thus translating the poetic meaning into a four purposes. (a) The first is to emphasize
philosophical one. According to ancient testi- Plato’s apparent philosophical stances (Men.
monies, Anaxagoras and his school practised 81a–b). This allows Plato to give a philo-
physical and ethical allêgorêsis (‘DK’ 59A1). sophical truth the authority and the persua-
The practise of allêgorêsis by philosophers siveness of poetry. (b) A second purpose is to
often has the aim of validating their doctrines. undermine other philosophical theories, for
The Derveni Papyrus, which might have example, the flux theory (Tht. 152d–e). Plato
been written by a student of Anaxagoras or can thereby point to the errors of the poets’
Diogenes of Apollonia, is a case in point since sayings, which allegedly embody philosophi-
it is a translation of the Orphic theogony into cal doctrines. These two purposes are mostly
cosmology. On the other hand, the exegetic rhetorical. (c) A third purpose is to refute
interpretation is based on what is taken to doxa, opinion and ‘elenchic interpretation’,
be the necessarily ambiguous nature of lan- as in the case of Polemarchus’ interpretation
guage. This is why the exegetic interpretation of Simonides (R. bk 1). Interpreting poetry
as practised by Anaximander, Stesimbrotus is here tantamount to refuting doxa. (d) A
of Thasos (Xenophon, Symposium 3.6) and fourth purpose is to demonstrate that poetry
Protagoras includes grammar analysis (‘DK’ has no philosophical content, therefore, no
80A29) and ways of structuring a speech meaning to be retrieved. In this case, inter-
(‘DK’ 80A30), that is, also, stylistic analysis preting poetry for the sake of finding the truth
(Protagoras 344b1–2). is merely a vain and naïve undertaking. This
All interpretation is committed to the is the conclusion that Socrates reaches after
idea that as a vehicle for underlying truths, he tries to interpret Simonides’ poetry in Prt.
poetry has a double language. In fact, Plato Belonging to the nonhistoric, his interpreta-
seems to take for granted that poetry con- tion implies anticontextualism whereby sev-
veys hidden thoughts (Republic 378a–d) eral lines are interpreted with no relation to
and speaks through enigmas (ainittetai: the whole, and decontextualization whereby
Alcibiades II.147b). However, the examples a sentence is transposed into a philosophical
of physical allêgorêsis (e.g. Theaetetus 153c) framework, that is, translated to become an
are meant to be ironic insofar as for Plato assertion; hence the anti-intentionalism that
the poets are not hidden philosophers, as this interpretation entails (Phaedrus. 275c2).

261

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 261 3/8/2001 5:11:52 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

Before completing the process of translation, on the one hand, a text cannot defend itself
Socrates tests various interpretations that (275e5) and, on the other hand, the former
he rejects on the ground of their falsity, and implies understanding (276e). As a simula-
concludes by giving the only interpretation tion of a living dialogue, a written dialogue
possible on account of its truth (Prt. 345d). could have, however, the same effect on the
The exercise, whether or not a parody, dem- soul. Some interpreters suppose that Plato
onstrates a conflict of interpretations due to endorses the polysemic nature of a text. If
the impossibility of retrieving the authorial so, he may not have seen it as a handicap
intention and, consequently, the necessity for for the philosopher but rather as a trig-
reaching the truth through dialectic (Hippias ger for understanding, that is, interpreting.
Minor 364d; Prt. 347c). Poetry consists of The puzzles that Plato asks us to solve are
an open text in the hands of an interpreter philosophic and involve a philosophic con-
who manipulates it at will and who therefore frontation along the same lines staged in the
becomes, to some degree, the author of the dialogues. He therefore guides and compels,
text, as Socrates exemplifies. to a certain extent, the reception of his work.
One may ask how Plato avoids this pit- This may have been Plato’s goal: to help us
fall in the case of his own dialogues. In other become philosophers and improve our philo-
words, does Plato find a way of circumscrib- sophical capability by having us interpret his
ing the various ways of interpreting his own dialogues.
work, that is, of circumventing the inher-
ent weaknesses of writing, as expounded in
Phdr.? Let us first note that in the case of nar-
ratives such as myths (q.v.), Plato discourages ARISTOTLE
his reader from a literal interpretation (e.g.
Phd. 114d) by having Socrates give the lesson George Karamanolis
of the story and practise exegesis (R. 618c– Aristotle was born in 384 BCE at Stagira in
19b). Plato thus provides us with an inter- Chalcidike in northern Greece, as a son of
pretative framework on the basis of which he Nicomachus, court physician to Amyntas II,
invites us to further elucidate the myth, that king of Macedonia. In c. 367 Aristotle moved
is, to lend ourselves to the practise of herme- to Athens to study in Plato’s Academy, where
neutics. The difference between an open text he stayed for 20 years, until Plato’s death
such as poetry and a Platonic narrative such in 347. The evidence concerning Aristotle’s
as myth is that in the latter there is an under- study in the Academy is various anecdotes
lying philosophical truth (Phdr. 278c), which either aiming to illustrate Aristotle’s sup-
under the guidance of the narrator Socrates posed animosity towards Plato (Aelian
the interpreter retrieves. A complementary 3.18–19; Düring 1957:320–6) or Aristotle’s
means consists of a narrative’s arousing in the genius (Vita Marciana 6–7; Düring 1957:98,
reader the desire to understand her/his emo- 109). Some of Aristotle’s early works, such as
tional experience, such as the fear of being the dialogues and the Topics, must have been
mistaken about how we ought to live, in the written when Aristotle was a student of Plato
case of eschatological narratives. in the Academy. It is unclear why Aristotle
In Phdr., Socrates argues for the superior- left the Academy; it may have been the anti-
ity of a living dialogue over writing because, Macedonian sentiment in Athens after the

262

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 262 3/8/2001 5:11:52 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

victories of Philip II (Düring 1957:459), Aristotle further distinguishes within Plato’s


Aristotle’s disappointment at not being cho- dialogues between Socratic and Platonic
sen Plato’s successor in the Academy (Jaeger views. On the issue of virtue or excellence
1962:111; Lloyd 1968:4–5) or Aristotle’s (q.v.), for instance, Aristotle reports that
disagreement with the Academy’s new Socrates identified virtue with knowledge
head, Speusippus; but it may also be that and that he denied the possibility of incon-
Aristotle was mature enough to conduct his tinence (akrasia), implying that this was
own research and have a circle of students. not Plato’s position (Nicomachean Ethics.
Moving away from the Academy and initiat- 1116b3–26, 1144b17–30; Eudemian Ethics
ing one’s teaching circle does not necessarily 1229a14–16, 1230a6–8, 1246b32–7).
amount to a break with it. Academics such Aristotle takes a critical attitude towards
as Eudoxus (D. L. 8.87) and Heraclides of the reportedly Platonic doctrines, approv-
Pontus (Philodemus, Index Academicorum ing some and, more often, criticizing others.
col. VII Dorandi) held such circles. Aristotle Aristotle’s testimony has been considered
left Athens to go to Assos in Asia Minor to valuable by those ancient and modern
join the circle of Hermeias, consisting mainly Platonists who view Plato’s philosophy as a
of Academics, and then moved to the island system of doctrines. The scope of Aristotle’s
of Lesbos, where he carried out biological testimony regarding Plato’s philosophy
research. In 342, invited by Philip II to under- has been debated, however. Some narrow
take the education of Alexander, Aristotle it to Aristotle’s reports about Plato and
moved to Macedon, to return to Athens once the Old Academics, others extend it to the
again in 335, where he stayed until 323. This Aristotelian arguments and views which are
is the most prolific period of Aristotle’s life, ostensibly similar to those presented in Plato
and the time he established his own school, (e.g. the Nicomachean Ethics. vis-à-vis the
the Lyceum (D. L. 2–3). Being indicted for Republic), and yet others extend it to those
impiety (D. L. 5.5), Aristotle went to Chalcis Aristotelian views which can qualify as devel-
in 323, where he died a year later. opments of Platonic ideas (e.g. Aristotle’s
Aristotle’s acquaintance with Plato’s work logic; Karamanolis 2006:16–28).
and thought is manifested in numerous ref- Based on Aristotle’s evidence suggest-
erences to Plato and his dialogues. Aristotle ing that Plato had doctrines, Antiochus
commits Plato to specific doctrines, such as (first-century BCE) distinguishes between
on the forms (q.v.; Metaphysics 1.9, 13.4–5, Socratic/aporetic and Platonic/doctrinal
Nicomachean Ethics 1.4, 6), the first princi- dialogues (Cicero, Academica I.17–18) and
ples (Metaphysics 1.6), recollection (q.v.; Prior uses Aristotle, especially his ethics (De fini-
Analytics 2.21, Posterior Analytics 1.1), the bus V.12), and the Old Academics as guides
creation of the world (De caelo 1.12, 3.1–2, for the articulation of Plato’s presumed doc-
7, Physics 1.9, 4.2), matter (De Generatione trines. Aristotle’s report in Metaphysics 1 on
et Corruptione. 1.2, 8), the soul (q.v.; De Plato’s first principles and the forms attracted
anima 1.2–3), the happy life (Nicomachean much attention from the time of Eudorus
Ethics. 1.4, 2.3), the role of pleasure (q.v.; (end of the first-century BCE), who relies on
Nicomachean Ethics. 10.2), the political Metaphysics 1.988a7–17 for a reconstruc-
life (Politics 2.2–6, 5.12), let alone Plato’s tion of Plato’s doctrine of the first princi-
unwritten doctrines (q.v.; Physics 209b15). ples (Alexander, In Metaphysica 58.31–59).

263

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 263 3/8/2001 5:11:53 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

In this passage, Aristotle argues that Plato as 3, etc.). Some ancient Platonists adopted
accepts two causes, a formal one, accounting the latter interpretation, assuming Aristotle’s
for being, and matter, and he suggests that the access to Platonic doctrines (e.g. Xenocrates
former includes the forms and the One (q.v.). and Crantor, in Plutarch, On the generation
Eudorus corrects the passage to the effect of the soul in the Timaeus 1012E–13A).
that Plato admits only one cause, the One, Aristotle’s critical appreciation of Plato’s
thus crediting Plato with the metaphysical philosophy raises the question of how much
monism ascribed to Pythagoras (Metaphysics of a Platonist he is. Seminal in this regard
1.987b21–8a7), an interpretation adopted has been Jaeger’s (1962) view that Aristotle
later by Pythagorean Platonists, such as developed himself from a faithful Platonist
Moderatus (first-century CE) and Numenius in the Academy to progressively non-Pla-
(second-century CE). Regarding Plato’s tonic views, until he abandoned Platonism
Timaeus, Aristotle construes the dialogue to completely at the end of his career. Against
the effect that the world was created at a cer- this it may be replied that Aristotle was
tain point in time from the mixture of forms never a faithful Platonist in the sense of
and matter (De caelo 1.12, 3.1–2) and criti- not criticizing Plato, given the evidence of
cizes Plato for committing the logical fallacy early works such as the Categories (Lloyd
of maintaining that something generated can 1968:28–41). Besides, in a late work such
escape perishing. Platonists since Xenocrates as the Nicomachean Ethics., Aristotle both
set themselves in dialogue with Aristotle’s criticizes Plato (1.6) while he also approves
interpretation of the Ti., assuming much of of and develops views defended in the R.
it, while they set out to refute Aristotle’s criti- and the Philebus (cf. 2.3, 10.2). Nevertheless,
cisms. They adopt Aristotle’s terminology Aristotle arguably remains a Platonist in
that the world is genêtos (the term does not terms of his methods, standards, philosophi-
occur in the dialogue), while arguing for a cal concerns and aims in philosophy (Gerson
nonliteral interpretation of the dialogue; they 2005; Owen 1986).
assume Aristotle’s interpretation (Physics
1.9, 4.2) that the receptacle (chôra) is identi-
cal with matter (e.g. Alcinous, Didascalicos
8), which is far from clear from the dialogue ACADEMY OF ATHENS, ANCIENT
itself. Similarly important for the interpre- HISTORY OF
tation of Plato’s conception of the soul in
the Ti., is Aristotle’s De anima 1. Aristotle George Karamanolis
suggests that Plato considered the soul as The Academy was a grove in the outskirts
a spatial magnitude and criticizes this view of Athens, sacred to the hero Academos, 1.5
accordingly (De anima 407a2–19), while ear- km west of the Dipylon gate, in which there
lier on (De anima 404b16–30) he refers to the was also a gymnasium (Diogenes Laertius
work ‘On Philosophy’. It is unclear whether 3.7; Cicero; De finibus V.1). According to
this means his own or Plato’s lectures on phi- Diogenes Laertius, Plato acquired property
losophy, but he reports that Plato conceived in the Academy after his return from the
of soul as a mathematical magnitude with its first visit to Sicily in 387/6 (D. L. 3.20). The
powers being assimilated to numbers (intel- term used by our sources for this property
lect is identified as 1, knowledge as 2, opinion is ‘garden’ (kêpos; kêpidion), but, as John

264

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 264 3/8/2001 5:11:53 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

Dillon (2003:5) has rightly argued, there Opus and Eudoxus; the latter was appointed
was more than a garden. Plato may have acting head of the Academy while Plato
owned a house there (Aelian 3.19), and we was in his second trip to Sicily (367–5; Vita
also hear of a promenade (peripatos; Aelian Marciana 11).
3.19), and a hall (exedra; D. L. 4.19), pos- The case of Eudoxus is instructive.
sibly a lecture hall (Cicero; De finibus V.4; Aristotle testifies that Eudoxus maintained a
Philodemus; Index Academicorum col. 29, view on pleasure according to which pleas-
p. 100 Mekler), close to which the students ure is the highest good and man’s final end,
(hoi mathêtai) lived in little huts (D. L. 4.19). because all beings seek it and try to avoid
We do not know when Plato started using the opposite, pain (Nicomachean Ethics
the place for teaching, but a turning point in 1172b9–25). Aristotle contrasts Eudoxus’
the transformation of the place into a regular view with the allegedly Platonic view, namely
meeting point for Plato’s associates may have that pleasure is not the good (see Philebus
been the erection of a shrine of the Muses 20e–2b, 60a–c; q.v. Pleasure). On the same
(mouseion) in the Academy (D. L. 4.1). The issue, Speusippus is credited with an argu-
place soon became sufficiently well known, ment against the identification of pleasure
however, to attract students from far away, with the good (q.v.) and also with the view
such as Xenocrates from Chalcedon in the that pleasure is not good even accidentally,
Propontis around 374/5 and Aristotle from on the ground that it has a sensible nature
Stagira in 367. (aisthêtê physis), which is why he advised
Our information about the activities in avoiding any pleasure (Nicomachean Ethics.
Plato’s Academy is scarce. A number of testi- 1152b8–10, 1153b1–9).
monies from ancient comedy playwrights state This evidence suggests that there was no
that Plato and his pupils were walking and doctrinal uniformity but rather an ongoing
conversing about issues such as the good and debate in the Academy on the role of pleas-
the soul-body relationship (D. L. 3.26–32; ure. Evidence for this debate we have in
Riginos 1976:123–9). The most significant of Plato’s dialogues Protagoras, Phaedo, Phlb.
those testimonies is a fragment from Epicrates and in a series of writings on the same topic
(third-century BCE), who presents a bunch of by Speusippus (D. L. 4.4), Philip of Opus
Academics debating about the division of the (Suda s.v. philosophos), Xenocrates (D. L.
pumpkin (f. 10 Kassel-Austin). The fragment 4.12), Heraclides (ff. 55–61 Wehrli) and also
alludes to the method of division discussed in Aristotle (D. L. 5.24), which are no longer
Plato’s late dialogues (such as the Sophist and extant. The surviving evidence of the work
the Politicus; cf. D. L. 3.81–108), suggesting of Plato’s students and immediate successors
that some central features of Plato’s thought point to a similar lack of doctrinal uniformity
were sufficiently defused to become subjects within the Academy also with respect to other
of parody presented to nonphilosophers. topics, such as the first principles, the forms
Apparently membership in the Academy (q.v.), the status of the soul (q.v.), emotions
was free for anyone, including women (q.v.) and happiness (q.v.). Speusippus and
(D. L. 3.46, 4.2), but Speusippus allegedly Xenocrates, Plato’s loyal students and suc-
introduced a fee (D. L. 4.2–3). Plato’s circle cessors in the Academy are interesting in this
of students was considerable (D. L. 3.46), regard as they deal with the same issues but
including eminent scientists, such as Philip of their answers vary, sometimes considerably.

265

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 265 3/8/2001 5:11:53 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

Speusippus (ca. 410–338/9; scholarch (epistêmonikê aesthesis; Sextus, Adv. Math.


347–39), Plato’s nephew, son of his sister 7.145–6; f. 75 Tarán).
Potone, is credited with a theory of first prin- Xenocrates follows Speusippus in assum-
ciples, arguably preserved by Iamblichus, De ing a principle of unity, order and identity,
communi mathematica scientia ch. 4 (Dillon the One, and a principle of multiplicity, the
2003:40–2; Merlan 1960). According to Dyad (Aristotle, Metaphysics 1087b4–21).
this theory, which is largely inspired by the The One is identified with the intellect of
Timaeus and the Phlb., there are two princi- the highest god, while the Dyad with the
ples, the One (q.v.), which accounts for order receptacle of the Ti. The contact of the two
and identity, and a principle of multiplicity principles produces the world soul, which
and division (plêthos). The two principles pro- produces sensible reality (Plutarch, De ani-
duce both non-spatial and spatial multiplic- mae procreatione in Timaeo 1012D–E).
ity, that is, numbers and geometrical objects. Unlike Speusippus, however, Xenocrates
Speusippus’ attempt clearly was to have the identified the forms with mathematical enti-
two principles account for all kinds of being, ties, arguing that forms and numbers have
although it is not clear how exactly. Aristotle the same nature (Metaphysics 1028b24–7).
(Metaphysics 1085a31–b34, 1092a21–b8) Xenocrates characterized the forms as
gives an unclear and highly critical picture, ‘paradigmatic’ (Proclus, In Parmenidem
and he is actually confusing us when he sug- 888.13–15 Cousin; f. 94 Isnardi-Parente),
gests that Speusippus abandoned the forms which suggests that he maintained the eter-
and replaced them with mathematical enti- nal existence of the forms as models of the
ties (Metaphysics 1086a2–5). Speusippus immanent counterparts in sensible enti-
may have revised Plato’s theory of forms but ties (Alexander, In Metaphysica 819.37–41
with a view to strengthen it. The revision Hayduck; f. 116 I.–P). Xenocrates’ views,
may be caused by the difficulty of squaring especially on the forms, appear to have been
the theory with Plato’s method of division, crafted as a response to Aristotle’s objections,
since abstract entities, such as the form ‘liv- which reflects a tension in the Academy and
ing being’, resist division into species, for a tendency towards systematization. Such a
example, man or cat (Cherniss 1945:41–3). tendency is supported by Sextus Empiricus’
Speusippus probably maintained that the testimony (Against the Logicians I.16),
two principles produce mathematical and which credits Xenocrates with the division of
geometrical entities, including the world philosophy into three branches: logic, phys-
soul itself, which he defined as ‘the form of ics and ethics.
omni-dimensional extended’ (f. 54 Tarán). Our knowledge of Xenocrates’ successor
This soul serves as principle (Metaphysics in the Academy, Polemon (314/313–270/269)
1028b15–27) of souls and of the sensible is very limited. He focused on ethics, argu-
realm; it hosts the forms of sensible objects ing that virtue is sufficient for happiness and
and eventually produces sensible reality that the end (telos) must be a life according
(Dillon 2003:51–4). Given the role of intelli- to nature (Cicero; De finibus IV.4). His most
gible entities in producing reality, Speusippus notable pupil was Crantor, who worked
considers them essential for cognition. This in ethics and on the Ti., being the first to
can take the form of cognitive reason (epistê- write an exegetical work on it (Proclus,
monikos logos) or cognitive perception In Timaeum I.76.1–2). With the election

266

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 266 3/8/2001 5:11:53 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

of Arcesilaus as scholarch, the Academy his dialogues, which contain some long mon-
changed its philosophical point of view sig- ologues, but also his oral communications,
nificantly enough to mark a distinct phase in the so-called unwritten doctrines (Aristotle,
its history, the ‘Middle Academy’ (D. L. 1.14, Physics 209b15). The opposite scholarly pole
Sextus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism 1.220) or emphasizes Plato’s methodology, especially
‘New Academy’ (Cicero, Academica I.46). the dialogic form, as a means of avoiding
Arcesilaus was inspired by the Socratic prac- commitment and authority, and the revision
tise of examining a thesis without commit- in which Plato subjects his own theories.
ting himself to it; he rather withheld assent Several suggestions cover the middle ground
(epochê) as the only way of avoiding error, between the two poles. In this falls also the
and criticized the Stoic doctrine of cognition position of the anonymous author of a com-
(katalêpsis). The Stoic criticism that with- mentary on Theaetetus (first-century AD?),
holding assent leads to inaction was coun- who preserves two testimonies regarding
tered by Carneades (scholarch 156/5–137/6) Plato’s teaching in the Academy. According
who argued that plausible impression (pith- to one of them, ‘Plato was an Academic phi-
anon) suffices for deciding and acting. This losopher since he did not have any doctrines’
line of argument comes to an end with Philo (Anon. in Tht. 54.38–42), while according to
of Larissa (scholarch 110–c. 83), who rejected the other ‘Plato points to the view he likes to
withholding assent, arguing that knowl- those who are familiar with his method’ (Tht.
edge is possible but not of the Stoic kind. 59.8–17). The Epicurean Philodemus (first-
His pupil Antiochus abandoned scepticism century BCE) finally argues that ‘there was
altogether, advocating a return to the early much teaching activity at the time [of Plato],
Academy. Antiochus maintained that Plato with Plato being the architect who was pre-
had doctrines, from which early Academics senting problems’ (Index Academicorum,
and Aristotle were inspired, and set out to col. Y Dorandi).
reconstruct them, a project that was met with
criticism in antiquity (Academica I.46, II.15).
In one sense the Academy ceases to exist with
Antiochus; when Cicero visits it in 79 BCE, JEWISH PLATONISM (ANCIENT)
he witnesses no philosophical activity (De
finibus V.1–4; see Glucker 1978:242). In the David T. Runia
following centuries Platonists teach their cir- There is no mention of Judea or the Jewish
cles of students in their own schools. people in Plato and there is no reference to
The existing evidence about the Academy Greek philosophical ideas in the Hebrew
raises the question of the nature and the con- Bible. The history of Jewish Platonism begins
tent of Plato’s teaching. Apart from individual when contact was established between the
differences, the history of the Academy and expanding Hellenistic world and the Jews.
of Platonism in general hosts two opposing This process first occurred in a significant
interpretative strategies, the doctrinal and the way in the bastion of Hellenism founded by
sceptical (Tarrant 2000:10–19). These strat- Alexander the Great in Alexandria.
egies determine two poles in the scholarly A foundational event for Hellenistic
appreciation of Plato. The one assumes that Judaism was the translation of the Hebrew
Plato was teaching specific doctrines through scriptures into Greek. It has been argued that

267

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 267 3/8/2001 5:11:53 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

the Septuagint translation reflects the influ- of Moses, with the aid of the doctrines of
ence of Platonic terminology in some key Greek philosophy. He assumes that these
texts, for example, aoratos in Gen. 1.2, eikôn doctrines are present in scripture and that
in Gen. 1.26, paradeigma in Exod. 25.40 later philosophers derived them from the
(Rösel 1994). This remains controversial, but great Jewish sage (or perhaps reached them
the terminology certainly aided later think- independently). It enables him to demon-
ers in locating Platonic doctrines in scripture. strate the superiority of Jewish thought and
The Septuagint also contains some late books the reasonableness of the injunctions of the
originally written in Greek. The Wisdom Jewish law. It is not surprising, therefore,
of Solomon clearly shows the influence of that Philo only names Plato 13 times in all
Middle Platonism (Winston 1979:34), par- his writings, and almost all of these refer-
ticularly in its doctrine of creation and the ences are in his philosophical or apologetic
immortality of the soul. It was probably writings (seven in the treatise De aeternitate
written in Alexandria in c. 50 BCE. mundi alone). Plato’s name is never men-
But by far the most famous ancient Jewish tioned in his allegorical treatises. But Philo
‘Platonist’ was Philo of Alexandria (15 BCE–50 does twice quote passages from Theaetetus
CE). Indeed, the fourth-century Church father 176a–c in De fuga 63 and 82, introducing
Jerome in his brief biographical notice on Plato as ‘a person highly esteemed among
Philo mentions a saying in circulation among those admired for their wisdom’. In Quod
the Greeks that ‘either Plato philonizes or omnis probus 13 he appears to refer to ‘the
Philo platonizes, so great is the similarity in most holy Plato’, but the reading is contested
doctrines and style’ (De vir. ill. 11). and more likely should read ‘the most clear-
Philo lived all his life in Alexandria and voiced Plato’, that is, a reference to Phaedrus
was a member of a wealthy and highly influ- 237a7. A negative note is struck in De vita
ential family in the Jewish community. In a contemplativa 57–63, where Philo sharply
famous passage (De congressu 73–80) he criticizes the eroticism of Plato’s Symposium
states that he received an excellent education as compared with the sober feasts of the
in the subjects of the Greek paideia, enabling Therapeutae, a group of Jewish contempla-
him to place his knowledge of philosophy in tives living outside Alexandria.
the service of God. He wrote in Greek and Plato’s philosophy had a profound effect
about fifty of his treatises are extant. Most on Philo’s thought. The following doctrines
of these focus on the interpretation of scrip- are the most significant. (a) God is conceived
ture and the promotion of Jewish causes, as being and often called to on (based on the
but five treatises treat philosophical themes crucial biblical text Exod. 3.14). (b) Philo
and show an impressive knowledge of Greek accepts and frequently uses the division into
philosophy. It may be assumed that Philo the noetic and the sense-perceptible realms.
was acquainted with contemporary develop- (c) He regards the doctrine of the ideas as
ments in philosophy as they occurred in the indispensable and is the first author to speak
Alexandria of his day, but unfortunately he of the kosmos noêtos. (d) Negative theology
gives us no detailed information. It has to be is commonly used to express human knowl-
gleaned from his writings. edge of God as supreme Being. (e) He closely
Philo’s basic method is to interpret the follows the Timaeus in expounding the doc-
Greek Bible, and in particular the five books trine of creation, with particular emphasis

268

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 268 3/8/2001 5:11:53 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

on the role of the ideas and unformed matter in scripture. But the Rabbis in Palestine
(hulê). (f) The cosmos is created (taken liter- rejected his positive attitude to Hellenism
ally as the commencement of time), but will and were not interested in Platonic thought.
not be destroyed. (g) The Platonic doctrine Jewish Platonism does not recommence until
of soul is not used in cosmology, but has a the medieval period (q.v. Medieval Jewish
strong influence on Philo’s anthropology. The Platonism).
human being is a duality consisting of soul
and body. The soul is immortal and is often
described in binary and tripartite terms. (h)
In ethics Philo combines Stoic and Platonist NEOPLATONISM AND ITS DIASPORA
doctrines on the virtues and the passions.
He is greatly attracted to the formulation of Francesco Fronterotta
the telos as ‘becoming like God’ (homoiôsis
theôi). (I) PLOTINUS
The prominence of the above doctrines
shows that Philo’s appropriation of Plato’s Regarded as the founder of Neoplatonism
thought is strongly influenced by the inter- (Cleary 1997; Lloyd 1990; Wallis 1972),
pretative developments of Middle Platonism Plotinus (c. 205–70 CE) was born in Egypt
(Dillon 1996:139–81). This influence also and around the age of 27 became a disciple
explains his attraction to dialogues such as of Ammonius Saccas. He took part in the
the Ti., Phaedo, Phdr., Republic, Laws and Emperor Gordian III’s expedition to the East,
Tht., with less use made of the early Socratic but on the Emperor’s death (244), he took
dialogues and later works such as the Sophist refuge in Antioch and then in Rome. Plotinus
and Politicus. See further the detailed analy- lived in the capital of the Empire from 244 to
ses of Méasson (1986) and Runia (1986). The 269 among members of the Roman aristoc-
further influence of Eudorus of Alexandria racy linked to the Emperor Gallienus, upon
(q.v.) and early neo-pythagoreanism (q.v.) whose assassination in 269 he left Rome for
has been postulated (Bonazzi 2008) but can- Campania, where he died more or less in
not be proven in detail. solitude in 270. During his period in Rome
It would be wrong, however, to regard Plotinus united a large group of followers,
Philo himself as a Middle Platonist (Runia the most important of whom were Amelius
1993b). He is attracted to the doctrines of (from 246 to 269) and Porphyry (from 263
Platonism and they play a central role in his to 268), both of whom attended his lessons,
thought. His first loyalty, however, is to his which were mainly devoted to commenting
ancestral religion and its sacred writings. on the works of Plato. He began to set his
He uses Platonic doctrines (and also those teaching down in writing in 254, and from
of other philosophers) for his chief goal, to then to 263 produced 21 treatises; between
demonstrate the superiority of the philoso- 263 and 268 Plotinus composed 24 treatises,
phy of Moses. while in the last year of his life, in Campania,
Philo’s thought exerted a strong influ- he completed the last nine, sending them to
ence on early Christian writers, especially in Porphyry before he died. As well as writ-
Alexandria (Runia 1993a), and they took over ing a biography of his master (On the life
many of the Platonic themes that he located of Plotinus and the order of his treatises),

269

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 269 3/8/2001 5:11:53 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

Porphyry prepared an edition of his treatises matter, in the sensible world. Below the soul
in the form of Enneads (54 treatises divided remains the sensible world, which owes its
into six groups of nine (= ‘ninth’, ennead)) ontological substance to the form it receives
about 30 years after Plotinus’ death. He from the intelligible, by virtue of the action
arranged them thematically, although he of the soul, but possesses a material dimen-
also took pains to indicate the chronological sion that depends on the gradual exhaustion
order of composition. The first Ennead is on of the generating action of the one.
moral subjects; the second deals with phys- Plotinus introduces three main innova-
ics and the sensible world; the third exam- tory features into the Platonic tradition. (a)
ines cosmological questions; the fourth, fifth Previous commentary on Plato had treated
and sixth are on the soul, the intellect and the the Timaeus as the most important dia-
one respectively, that is, the three fundamen- logue, but Plotinus considered it alongside
tal principles – or ‘hypostases’ – of Plotinus’ the Parmenides, and the second part of this
doctrine. dialogue in particular, which contains a
Plotinus’ most characteristic doctrine series of deductions concerning the one that
(Gerson 1994; O’Meara 1993; Rist 1967) is he reads as an anticipation of his doctrine
that of the three ‘hypostases’ which articulate of the three hypostases. (b) In the first series
the whole of reality: the one, the intellect and of deductions, Plotinus identifies a principle
the soul. Unlike the Platonic tradition, which that is absolutely first, one and simple, partly
had identified the cause and principle of the drawing on the description of the idea of the
physical world in the intelligible world of good that Plato gives at the end of Republic
transcendent Platonic ideas, in various ways bk 6, and situates it completely beyond
associated with a demiurgic intelligence that being and reality. Being therefore unattain-
makes use of them to produce the sensible able by thought and discourse, it can only
cosmos, Plotinus identified the first principle be expressed in negative terms, by approxi-
of everything in a reality that is absolutely mations to it in terms of what it is not. (c)
simple and one to which we can attribute Plotinus elaborates an account of the real that
the conventional denomination of ‘one’ or is extremely unified and simplified, in that it
‘good’. Without exercising any voluntary, derives from an absolutely single and simple
intelligent or providential act, this emanates, principle, and he gives it a fully rational and
through its infinite power, ‘super-abundant’ necessary articulation, against any form of
portions of itself, thus giving rise to inferior religious influence connected with theurgy,
realities. The intellect (Emilsson 2007) is Gnostic doctrines or contemporary astrologi-
placed in the second degree of reality, con- cal currents of thought. In Plotinus’ original
sists of the totality of the intelligible world synthesis, as well as the Platonic doctrinal ele-
of ideas, and, according to Plato’s teaching, ments, there emerges a significant Stoic philo-
constitutes the model for the sensible world. sophical influence, but also a closely argued
The soul (Blumenthal 1971) is placed in the reflection on Aristotle’s work.
third degree of reality, and is a degradation
of the intellect and the intelligible on the spa- (II) NEOPLATONISM AFTER PLOTINUS
tial-temporal plane of extension and division.
It has the task of transposing ideal models, Plotinus’ most important disciple, Porphyry
in the form of rational principles acting on (c. 232–301 CE), composed an enormous

270

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 270 3/8/2001 5:11:53 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

body of work, which has been almost wholly identified as superior even to Plotinus’ first
lost and that partly questions Plotinus and principle, designated as an ‘Ineffable beyond
shows the influence of his previous mas- the One’ (Dillon 1987; Shaw 1995; Steel
ter, Longinus (Smith 1974). Significantly, 1978).
it emphasized the importance of Aristotle’s This position aroused wide-ranging
thought although its theoretical framework debate among the successive exponents of
was essentially Platonic. As well as his biogra- the School of Athens (Plato’s Academy),
phy of Plotinus and his edition of the Enneads, who were active between the end of the
on which he also wrote a commentary (frag- fourth century and the first decades of the
ments of which have survived with the title sixth-century CE. Plutarch of Athens (late
Sentences), he also wrote commentaries on fourth- early fifth-century CE) is regarded as
Plato’s and Aristotle’s works, an Introduction its founder. Of him we know very little and
to Aristotle’s Categories (Isagogê), a treatise in none of his works have come down to us.
which he claimed that Plato’s and Aristotle’s His successor, Syrianus (d. in 437), drew up
thinking converged (That the Schools of a scholastic teaching programme not unlike
Plato and Aristotle are one only), a History that of Iamblichus, and wrote commentaries
of Philosophy and a Life of Pythagoras, also on Beta, Gamma, Mu and Nu of Aristotle’s
taking an interest in theurgy and vegetarian- Metaphysics, on Plato’s Phdr., and above
ism, practicing allegory and writing a lengthy all on the Prm., of which, according to his
treatise Against the Christians. pupil Proclus, he suggested a particularly
Iamblichus (c. 240–325 CE) directed a detailed interpretation. Proclus (c. 412–85)
school of philosophy at Apamea in Syria, in is the best known exponent of the school, as
which he introduced a vast study programme we possess a good part of his works: com-
that involved the reading of the works of ments on Plato’s dialogues (on the Alc. I, Ti.,
Aristotle, an introduction to Pythagorean R., Cratylus and Prm.), school treatises, and
philosophy and the study of Plato’s dia- above all the Platonic Theology, in which
logues, culminating in the interpretation of Proclus provided a systematic exposition
the Ti. and the Prm. He wrote commentar- of the main Neoplatonic doctrines (Gersh
ies, most of them lost, on some of Plato’s dia- 1973), once again establishing the one as
logues (First Alcibiades; Phaedo; Phaedrus; first principle of everything, in conformity
Philebus; Prm.; Sophist.; Ti.) and on some with Plotinus’ doctrine and in opposition to
of Aristotle’s works (Prior Analytics; De Iamblichus. Damascius (462–>532), who led
interpretatione; De caelo); some fragments the School of Athens until it was closed by
remain of other treatises – On the Soul, On Justinian in 529 CE, took a different view:
the Chaldean Oracles, On the Gods; while for Damascius, who wrote a commentary on
four out of ten books have survived of a the Prm. and a treatise On First Principles,
treatise On the Pythagorean School (with the first of Plotinus’ hypostases – the one –
the titles Life of Pythagoras, Exhortation is preceded by another, absolutely ineffable,
to Philosophy, Common Mathematical principle, while the one is divided into infe-
Theory, On Nicomachus’ Introduction to rior principles that, by degeneration, lead to
Mathematics). Unlike Plotinus, Iamblichus the production of the whole of reality.
saw Plato’s philosophy as a theology related Of the Alexandrian School (Blumenthal
to Pythagoreanism, culminating in a level he and Lloyd 1982; Watts 2006) little has

271

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 271 3/8/2001 5:11:54 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

survived beyond a few names, although it philosophers stretching from Socrates (q.v.) to
must have had a certain intellectual influence Aristotle (q.v.): his portrait was not drawn as
in the fourth century some philosophers, vividly as Socrates’ in the wisdom literature,
such as Hermias, Hierocles, Isidorus, as well nor yet were his works studied as Aristotle’s
as Proclus and Damascius, who were born in were. Still, the spectre of Plato looms large
Alexandria, received their philosophical edu- over Islamic philosophy, to the extent that
cation in Athens; of Hypatia, the daughter of one may legitimately ask whether Arabic
the mathematician and astronomer Theon, philosophy in the classical period should
we know that she taught Synesius of Cyrene, be dubbed Platonizing Aristotelianism, as is
who later converted to Christianity, and that now common, or whether what we have is
her successor was Hierocles, the head of a rather a Neoplatonic (q.v.) tradition dressed
Platonic school around 430. Those who in Aristotelian garb. The Arabic philosophers
taught at Alexandria during the fifth and read almost nothing of Plato, and yet their
sixth centuries probably included Hermias, scholarly work over and over again returns
his son Ammonius, whose lessons were pub- to Platonic and Neoplatonic themes, whether
lished by Philoponus, a certain Eutocius and as an intellectual resource to be grasped (as
Olympiodorus, the last pagan head of the with the immortality of the soul) or a temp-
School and author of commentaries on some tation to be resisted (as was the case with the
of the works of Plato and Aristotle. theory of ideas).
Late Neoplatonism displayed a clear ten- It is in the school of Alexandria’s pervasive
dency to defend the substantial theoretical influence that an explanation is to be sought.
convergence between the doctrines of Plato The sixth-century Alexandrians had had to
and Aristotle, explaining why many of its justify their dwelling on Aristotle when it
exponents, philosophers with a Platonic was the divine Plato who held the key to
background, devoted themselves to com- true transcendent wisdom: their explanation
menting on the works of Aristotle: the most took the form of a teleologically interpreted
famous case is Simplicius, who was educated history of philosophy which helped to build
in Alexandria and active in Athens until the the case for Aristotle, not Plato, as the fore-
Academy was closed; he was the author of most Greek thinker in the minds of Syriac
commentaries on Aristotle’s works and can and Arabic scholars. This in turn appears to
be placed at the end of the long history of have led to Plato’s dialogues being largely
Neoplatonism. neglected in the translation movement that
took place from the eighth- to the tenth-cen-
tury CE. Certainly, there was no systematic
Section B: The Influence of Plato in the effort to render Plato into Arabic the way
Middle Ages and Renaissance there was for Aristotle or even, say, Galen or
Ptolemy.
At the same time, philosophizing in the
MEDIEVAL ISLAMIC PLATONISM Near East retained the broad soteriological
and cosmological orientation it had inher-
Taneli Kukkonen ited from the ancient Platonic schools.
In classical Arabic philosophy Plato features Neoplatonic texts such as the Theology of
as the least familiar member in a line of godly Aristotle and the Book on the Highest Good

272

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 272 3/8/2001 5:11:54 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

(in reality, adaptations from Enneads 4–6 counterweight to the harmonizing tendencies
and Proclus’ Elements of Theology) there- exemplified by al-Fârâbî’s (d. 950) Agreement
fore quickly found an audience, as they between the Opinions of the Two Sages. On
answered a perceived need for describing a personal level, a respectful and admiring
the great chain of being in broader terms attitude between Plato and Aristotle was con-
than anything found in the more scientific sistently maintained (in some more fabulous
Greek literature. The Theology of Aristotle stories Plato adopted the orphan Aristotle).
also provided materials for bridging the gap Fresh gnomological and doxographical com-
between the Platonic view of the soul present pilations were put together from older mate-
in Jewish, Christian and Muslim spiritual- rials and reached yet wider audiences.
ity – the tripartite division in moral psychol- What is missing from the Arabic scene is
ogy, the dualistic conception of the soul’s any deeper engagement with the intricacies
true nature and its destiny – with the more of actual Platonic dialogues. This may have
mundane musings of Aristotle’s De anima. In been due partly to the forbidding character
this way, the Peripatetic curriculum adopted of fifth-/sixth-century commentaries, exceed-
by Muslim falsafa could be situated in the ingly complex and replete with religious
larger framework of god, cosmos and soul, allusions, or it may have had more to do
and within the grand story of process and with the socioeconomic facts on the ground
return (al-mabda’ wa al-ma’âd). when it came to finding translating work.
What resulted was a general conception The renowned translator Hunayn Ibn Ishâq
of philosophy that would have appeared lists Proclus as the most dependable guide to
familiar to a sixth-century Platonist, with the Plato, but this may simply repeat received
important difference that all references to wisdom. Whatever the reason, no Platonic
traditional Greek religion had been carefully text has come to us in Arabic translation, and
excised and with it the notion of henads and there is reason to doubt that a single dialogue
other principles beyond the intellectual. The was ever translated in full in the first place.
First Principle might still be placed beyond Among the Peripatetics the record is
the reach of reason, limit or quiddity, though particularly scant. Bibliographical sources
not beyond being or existence (this is the attest to the Republic and Laws receiving
single most important transformation of some kind of comments from Hunayn, and
Plotinian Platonism effected by the Arabic according to the Christian Peripatetic Yahyâ
philosophers); the other supernal principles Ibn ‘Adî (d. 974) Hunayn’s son Ishâq trans-
were filled from the ranks of the Aristotelian lated the Sophist along with Olympiodorus’
separate intelligences, and the Agent Intellect commentary. These works seem to have had
made into a repository for the intelligibles. no impact: the abridgements of the Lg. and
As concerns doctrines commonly attrib- the R. produced by al-Fârâbî and Ibn Rushd
uted to Plato, doxographies such as Pseudo- (the Latin Averroes, 1126–98) are more likely
Plutarch’s Placita philosophorum sufficed in to have been written on the basis of Galen’s
introducing these. They would also serve to compendia. Still, lengthy citations of individ-
contrast Plato’s and the Academy’s teachings ual passages from the R. have at least been
with those of the other schools. The disagree- detected: certainly this work above all others
ments between Plato and Aristotle received interested the Peripatetics, due to the unavail-
much play, for instance, and acted as a useful ability of Aristotle’s Politics. Other citations

273

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 273 3/8/2001 5:11:54 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

and close paraphrases that were in circula- ideological construct rather than a substan-
tion come from predictable sources: Phaedo tial continuation of the Platonic tradition: it
on metempsychosis, Crito on Socrates’ death. is only Platonic to the extent that Avicenna
Finally, al-Fârâbî’s Philosophy of Plato attests (980–1037) and the Muslim Peripatetic tra-
to a working knowledge of some of the main dition in general can be regarded as Platonic.
positions advanced in Plato’s dialogues (all But this is problematic.
of the familiar works minus the Minos are
listed), though the dogmatic presentation –
likely derivative of some Middle Platonic
compendium – distorts Plato into the shape MEDIEVAL JEWISH PLATONISM
of an Aristotelian systematic philosopher.
None of this evidences a serious attempt to Oliver Leaman
advance beyond the popular imagination. Jewish philosophy in the middle ages operated
Plato exercised a wider influence in the largely within the context of Islamic culture,
medical tradition, principally due to Galen’s and worked with the philosophical curricu-
pronounced yet vague Platonic leanings. lum then current in that culture. Islamic phi-
The noted bibliophile Ibn al-Nadîm in his losophy grew out of Neoplatonism, which
Catalogue reports that he personally had had been the leading school of thought in
managed to get a hold of Galenic compendia the Greek world when philosophy started to
on the Cratylus, Sph., Statesman, Parmenides, be translated into Arabic, and moved sub-
Euthydemus, R., Timaeus and the Lg.: this sequently into the medieval Jewish world.
covers the first half of Galen’s Synopsis. It is Neoplatonism had involved the study of
probably because of his background in medi- both Platonic and Aristotelian texts, but this
cine that the notorious philosopher-physician did not, in medieval times, entail the com-
al-Râzî (the Latin Rhazes, d. 925) pledged mon Neoplatonist belief that Aristotle was in
allegiance to Plato above others: al-Râzî is harmony with Plato. Rather it led to a certain
said to have produced a treatise on the Ti., blurring of the distinctions between them. The
and certainly his cosmology bears a (pre-Plo- Islamic world particularly favoured Aristotle,
tinian) Platonic stamp, though again nothing and saw Plato as having been replaced by
we know concerning his teachings reflects an Aristotle on those issues where he was not in
actual knowledge of Plato beyond Plutarch’s agreement with him. This view was expressed
or Galen’s compendia, and in fact any detailed very clearly by the greatest Jewish philoso-
knowledge of the R. is explicitly ruled out. pher, Moses Maimonides (1138–1204).
That a putative Platonic identity could be What is often called Neoplatonism (q.v.) was
postulated on such a flimsy scholarly basis the leading school of thought in the Greek
shows the ultimate thinness of Platonism world when philosophy started to be trans-
under Islam. The same goes double for al- lated into Arabic and moved comfortably
Suhrawardî (d. 1191), the Illuminationist into the Islamic world, and subsequently into
philosopher who claimed that he was reinsti- the medieval Jewish world. This does not
tuting Platonic ideas when in fact the function mean that thinkers were incapable of distin-
served by his ideas was quite different. The guishing between Aristotle and Plato, but it
notion of a later Persian Platonism should did lead of course to a certain blurring of the
therefore be approached cautiously, as an distinctions between them.

274

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 274 3/8/2001 5:11:54 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

Before Maimonides three Jewish thinkers knowledge of philosophy but also on what
made considerable use of Plato. Saadya Gaon can be taken as its source, divine knowledge
(882–942), Solomon Ibn Gabirol (c. 1021–c. and ultimately on God and his representa-
1057) and Bahya ben Asher (mid-thirteenth tives (Melamed 1997). Plato was the basis
century; c. 1340) all accept Platonic philo- of political philosophy in the Islamic world
sophical psychology, where the soul and also, largely because of the availability of the
body are two substances conjoined tempo- R. and, perhaps, the absence of Aristotle’s
rarily during this life. In some ways it is rea- Politics. On the other hand, availability was
sonable to divide up the Jewish Middle Ages not the only issue, since what was trans-
as before and after Maimonides. The latter’s lated into Hebrew was selective (Leaman
influence, plus that of Ibn Rushd (Averroes), 2005). Maimonides suggested that Plato is
emphasized what they took to be the rigour not worth reading, the idea being that what-
of Aristotelianism, and this was to dominate ever he had to say that was valuable was
the philosophical curriculum of the Jewish also said by Aristotle, and much better said.
world until the Renaissance and the uses of This attitude was not to change much until
Plato, then to establish some form of human- the onset of the Renaissance, when Plato
ism. It is as always very difficult to distinguish was largely rediscovered in the Christian
between Platonism and Neoplatonism in the world; his thought then became very much
medieval period, not so much because the used by Jewish thinkers like Judah Abravanel
classical Neoplatonic themes are difficult to (c. 1465–c.1523), Yohanan Alemanno (c.
distinguish from Plato, because they are not, 1435–d. after 1534) and Judah Moscato (c.
but because there seems to have been very 1530–c. 1593; cf. Feldman 1997). But even
little reading of Plato without the accretions towards the end of the medieval period Isaac
of interpreters and commentators, and so Abravanel (1437–1508) took a decidedly
even where Platonic themes are evident, it is Platonic line on issues of significance such
not clear that these actually come from Plato as the existence of an individual soul, where
himself. Isaac Israeli, for instance, mentions he found Plato’s thought far more amenable
what became very much a theme of Jewish to the various Aristotelian approaches that
thought within this period, the idea of imi- emphasize the soul’s links with the body,
tatio Dei, through a purification of the soul. its relationship with the active intellect and
Plato was also often linked with a theory of the importance of intellectual perfection for
the creation of the world out of a pre-existing immortality. The Platonic idea of a separate
matter, where the heavenly bodies are both soul was far more amenable to the defence
everlasting and generated, as in the Timaeus of traditional religion that Isaac Abravanel
41a–b, a doctrine which Isaac Abravanel also had in mind, and this strategy should not be
refers to favourably (Feldman 2003). seen as a problematically eclectic approach
In the Jewish world Plato was used widely to philosophy, since the Neoplatonic nature
in moral and political philosophy, and also of most philosophy during this period makes
aesthetics. It is often argued that this was such an orientation towards Plato easy to
because it was so helpful to have a doctrine understand.
available that linked politics with religion, The disapproval that Maimonides had
and it was quite easy to see the Republic as for Plato could be expected to have had a
basing authority in the state not only on the considerable effect on subsequent Jewish

275

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 275 3/8/2001 5:11:54 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

medieval thinkers, given Maimonides’ high and when the need was felt to challenge an
status, even among many of those firmly overrational attitude to the world, Aristotle
opposed to him. On the other hand, it has in other words, Plato could often be recruited
often been pointed out that much of his as a more sympathetic intellectual source in
work is not that far from Plato (Frank 2009) both the Islamic and Jewish traditions.
and that it is quite easy to talk about a joint
approach to moral and political thought fol-
lowed by Plato and Aristotle (Jacobs 2010).
The idea that law must have a rationale and MEDIEVAL CHRISTIAN PLATONISM
not be based entirely on the will of god is
one that Maimonides uses a great deal in his Margaret Cameron
arguments about the basis of divine legisla- A thoroughgoing history of medieval
tion. Maimonides sees the great leaders of Christian Platonism remains to be writ-
the Jewish people as not just skilful politi- ten. The task will be difficult – not because
cians but also deep thinkers, whose inspira- the traces of Platonic thought are so few
tion comes from God of course, and yet who (although there are few direct points of
are able through their intellect to work out transmission), but because there are so many
much of how legislation should operate. (albeit indirect). According to a recent author,
Maimonides has nothing but contempt for ‘both Christian Greek and Latin writers were
those who follow the law without under- so affected by Neoplatonic thinking that one
standing something at least of its theoreti- would find it hard to disentangle even the
cal background, and it is not difficult to see doctrine of Christianity, as understood in the
Plato’s thought here being used to elucidate Middle Ages, from it’ (Marenbon 2007).
the links between Torah, Jewish religious law Direct access to Plato’s texts was limited
and nomos, rational law (Rosenthal 2010). and, for the most part, coextensive with
Much Jewish mystical work presents an the history of the influence of the Timaeus
account of the soul which resembles that of (Hankins 1987; Steel 1990). The Latin Ti. (up
the R., and if we are to find real evidence to 53C) was translated and extensively com-
of Plato’s thought in the medieval period it mented on by the fourth-century Calcidius,
is to the kabbalah, or Jewish mysticism, that many of whose ideas were often confused
we must turn. Ideas work their way through with Plato’s. It was introduced into the uni-
much of the kabbalah (Leaman 2010) and versity curriculum, only to be removed from
resonate with a good deal of Plato’s thought, the syllabus around 1255, presumably due to
especially as interpreted by the Neoplatonists its ‘replacement’ by other available texts by
(Idel 2002), including a sharp distinction Aristotle (Dutton 1997). The other dialogues
between love of the body and love of God, the available in Latin were: Phaedo and Meno,
latter attainable by abstracting our thinking translated in the twelfth century by Henricus
and concentrating and developing its form, Aristippus, and the Parmenides, translated
and an enthusiasm for asceticism, the notion in the thirteenth century by William of
of spiritual and intellectual growth, together Moerbeke. These dialogues, sometimes cir-
with a firm doctrine of the soul and its dis- culating with other ‘Platonic’ and ‘naturalist’
tinctiveness from the body. Socrates was seen material did not go unnoticed, but were not
in Islamic culture as a proto-Sufi and mystic, the subject of serious study.

276

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 276 3/8/2001 5:11:55 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

The high point of direct contact with St. Augustine and the fifth-century Roman
Plato’s work occurred during the twelfth cen- philosopher Boethius, both of whose
tury. Masters associated with the ‘school’ of Platonic views were filtered through the
Chartres (see most recently Jeauneau 2010) lens of Porphyry. This filter afforded medi-
commented directly on the available ver- eval thinkers insight into the ancient opin-
sion of Plato’s Ti. (along with other Platonic ion that the doctrines of Plato and Aristotle
materials, such as Boethius’ Consolation of are, ultimately, harmonious (see Ebbesen
Philosophy and Macrobius’ commentary 1990; Gerson 2005; Karamanolis 2006).
on the Dream of Scipio, a version of Plato’s Augustine’s writings were everywhere used
Myth of Er). There was among many mas- by medieval thinkers, although it is more
ters a keen interest in Platonic cosmology appropriate to talk about ‘Augustinianism’
and eschatology, especially the origin of the (rather than ‘Platonism’). Boethius’ aim to
world, the nature of time and eternity, provi- translate and provide commentaries on every
dence and fate, the world soul and the human work of Aristotle and Plato, and to show
soul. These masters were characterized as how their views are in agreement (Boethius,
Platonici, among whom Bernard of Chartres In peri hermeneias), was thwarted by early
was singled out as ‘the most perfect Platonist imprisonment and death. Nonetheless his
of our age’ (John of Salisbury, Metalogicon). extant commentaries were a rich source of
Not everything that Plato wrote, however, information on Neoplatonic interpretations
was easily compatible with Christian doc- of Aristotelian logic. Medieval thinkers there
trine, and so these masters – commenting on confronted Plato’s doctrine of the pre-exist-
every word of the Platonic texts available to ence and transmigration of souls, doctrines
them – had to devise a mechanism by which usually either explained away or sharply
to interpret the doctrines without raising dif- rejected as contrary to Christian faith. At the
ficulties with Church authorities. Plato’s true same time, the commentary tradition on just
meaning was often concealed, they thought, one of the Neoplatonic poems of Boethius’ is
under a veil, and the troublesome teach- massive (Nauta 2009).
ings were explained away as an involucrum Other sources included Isidore of Seville’s
or integumentum (Jeauneau 1957) whose Etymologiae, Martianus Capella’s The
proper interpretation could in the end be rec- Marriage of Mercury and Philology, and
onciled with Christian doctrine. For exam- the Christian fathers, including Jerome and
ple, that women ought to be held in common Ambrose who provided insight into Plato’s
(Republic bk 5) was given this reading: what views on the origins of the world. Especially
Socrates meant was that women should be important sources of Platonic (in fact
held in common affection (see Dutton 2005). Proclean) doctrine were the Liber de causis
This enabled some philosophers (Peter and the works from the ‘Dionysian’ corpus
Abelard and William of Conches) to interpret (On the celestial hierarchy, On the ecclesi-
Plato’s world soul as the Holy Spirit which, astical hierarchy, On the divine names, On
as defended by Abelard, had a beginning in mystical theology, along with several letters),
time (Peter Abelard, Theologia summi boni; thought to have been written by Dionysius
Gregory 1955; Marenbon 1997). the Areopagite and thus treated with extraor-
Two primary indirect sources for the dinary reverence. The understanding of Plato
views of Plato and the Neoplatonists were and Platonism changed in the late thirteenth

277

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 277 3/8/2001 5:11:55 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

century with the translation of Proclus’ proceeded from intelligible reasons, and
Elementatio theologica. Proclus’ commen- this was the particular characteristic of
taries on Ti. and Prm. were also translated. the Platonists. Some, however, have pro-
This allowed philosophers to begin to distin- ceeded from sensible things, and this was
the particular characteristic of the phi-
guish Plato’s thought from his systematizers’,
losophy of Aristotle, as Simplicius says
especially Proclus (q.v. Neoplatonism).
in his commentary On the Categories
It ought to be noted that, despite the fre- (De spiritualibus creaturis; tr. in Hankey
quent tendency by scholars to characterize 2002).
early medieval philosophy (i.e. before the
recovery of the bulk of Aristotle’s corpus
and the start of the universities) as ‘Platonic’, On the basis of Aristotle’s criticisms of Plato
there are in fact few references to Plato and in the first book of Metaphysics, medieval
his work, and fewer still that engage with philosophers could see Aristotle as a cor-
his thought in a systematic way. Plato was rector of Plato, although their views were
indeed praised, such as by the ninth-century taken to be essentially harmonious. Like the
John Scottus Eriugena who considered Plato twelfth-century effort to interpret Plato’s
‘the greatest of all those who philosophize views metaphorically or in a transferred
about the world’, not least because Plato sense, Aquinas too notes that ‘Plato had a
‘discovered the creator’. But ‘Plato’ was often bad way of teaching: for he says everything
simply cited as an authority for parts of the figuratively and teaches through symbols,
quadrivium. In these early years of the mid- intending something other through his words
dle ages, pithy Platonic sayings are most fre- than what they themselves say’ (Sententia
quent, usually learned at second hand (e.g. libri De Anima; cited in Hankey 2002).
that cities are fortunate to have philosophers For further information, see Bos and Meijer
as rulers, that the place of the soul is the (1992), Dobell (2009), Dutton (2003), Gersh
brain, not the heart and so on; see Marenbon (1986) and Klibansky (1939).
2002).
Scholars have remarked on the surprising
marginality of Plato’s thought, in direct trans-
mission, in the middle ages, wondering why RENAISSANCE PLATONISM
medieval thinkers did not seek out a complete
set of Plato’s texts, and why indeed those Sarah Hutton
that were translated lay nearly untouched. Renaissance Platonism is important for
Perhaps Aristotle’s texts were simply more two reasons: for the rediscovery of Plato’s
assimilable to a university curriculum, and dialogues and for developing a view of
his ideas more conducive to the development Platonism which values it for its moral
of natural science (Wieland 1985). Aquinas teachings and spiritual insight. Since late
recognized that Plato and Aristotle took dif- antiquity, thanks to Christian churchmen
ferent philosophical approaches (viae): like Augustine, Plato had a respectable
reputation as the pagan philosopher who
The diversity of these two positions stems came closest to Christian truth. But direct
from this, that some, in order to seek the knowledge of Plato’s works was fragmen-
truth about the nature of things, have tary in the Middle Ages (q.v. Christian

278

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 278 3/8/2001 5:11:56 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

Platonism, early; Christian Platonism, medi- editions of Plato’s complete works were pub-
eval). We owe our knowledge of the corpus lished in the sixteenth century: the Aldine
of Plato’s writings to the efforts of Italian editio princeps (1513) and the 1578 edi-
Renaissance editors and translators, who tion by the French scholar, Henri Estienne
acquired original manuscripts of Plato’s dia- (Stephanus), which established the referenc-
logues from Byzantine Greeks who were the ing system still in use today. Ficino’s trans-
heirs of a tradition of interpretation unbro- lation is remarkable for its accuracy, and
ken since classical times. Since that legacy it was not superseded by later Renaissance
was soon to be truncated, with the fall of translations of the complete dialogues by the
Constantinople in 1453, the preservation of German humanist, Janus Cornarius (Johann
Plato’s philosophy was one of the greatest Hainpol 1561), and by the French scholar,
services rendered by Renaissance Humanism Jean de Serres (published with the Stephanus
to European philosophy. The recovery of edition).
Plato’s dialogues established Plato as an The historical circumstances of the
important philosopher in the Renaissance recovery of Plato in the fifteenth century
setting the mould for interpreting Plato for account in large measure for the character of
the next 300 years. Renaissance Platonism. Plato was mediated by
The first fruits of the humanist study of the Byzantines, notably Manuel Chrysoloras
Plato were manuscript translations of indi- (1350–1414), George Gemisthius Pletho
vidual dialogues into Latin. One of the most (c. 1360–1452) and Cardinal Bessarion (c.
important early translators was Leonardo 1403–1472) who originally travelled to Italy
Bruni (1369–1444), who translated sev- in the hope of forming political and religious
eral dialogues, including the Phaedo and alliances with the beleaguered Byzantine
Republic. Another was George of Trebizond empire. Plato’s dialogues were read through
who translated the Laws and Epinomis in the prism of the philosophical, religious and
1451, followed in 1459 Parmenides dedicated social conditions of Early Modern Europe,
to Nicholas of Cusa (1401–64). Cusanus is where scholastic Aristotelianism prevailed
an example of a Renaissance philosopher in the universities. Unlike Aristotle’s philoso-
who was interested in Plato’s philosophy, but phy which had been subject to over a century
unable to read Greek. The most important of accommodation to Christian theology
Plato translator of the Renaissance was the within the institutions of higher learning,
Florentine, Marsilio Ficino (1433–99), who Platonism lacked a time-honoured tradition
translated into Latin all 36 dialogues of the of interpretation in the institutions of the
Thrasyllan canon, which were printed in Christian West. Platonism never succeeded in
1484. Ficino’s Plato translations were part of breaking the Aristotelian monopoly on uni-
a larger project, which involved translating versity study – notwithstanding the efforts
a substantial number of Neoplatonist texts of Francesco Patrizzi da Cherso (1529–97),
(q.v. Neoplatonism), including the Enneads who sought to replace Aristotelianism with
of Plotinus, Iamblichus’ De mysteriis Platonism, on the grounds that Aristotle’s
Aegyptiorum and the Corpus Hermeticum. philosophy contradicted Christian teaching
His plans for a Greek edition of Plato had (see his Discussionum peripateticorum libri
to be abandoned because of the death of his XV, 1571, and Nova de universis philos-
patron, Cosimo de’Medici. The first Greek ophia, 1591).

279

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 279 3/8/2001 5:11:56 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

To modern readers, unacquainted with calumniatorem Platonis (1469). Plato’s


historical Platonism, Renaissance Platonism admirers emphasized religious and philo-
might appear to be more properly a vari- sophical concordism. The most striking
ety of eclectic Neoplatonism. In fact, the instance of this is the concept of a prisca
modern habit of reading Plato separately sapientia which was developed by Ficino
from other philosophers of the Platonic (adapted from Iamblichus’ idea of peren-
tradition developed only recently. Through nial philosophy), which stressed the com-
most of its history, Platonism has been read monalities between Platonism, Christianity
in relation the so-called Neoplatonist phi- and the best of other philosophies (including
losophers. Renaissance Platonism was no Aristotelianism). The mytho-poetic aspects
exception. Ficino regarded Plotinus as the of Plato’s philosophy lent themselves to alle-
greatest interpreter and systematizer of gorical interpretation, which Ficino exploited
Plato. But Ficino was more than a translator chiefly to elucidate what he regarded as the
of Plato; he was a thinker who, by means veiled religious content. His allegorism is
of his commentaries, and his philosophical relatively restrained by comparison with the
writings, provided a framework for reading Neoplatonists of antiquity.
and interpreting Plato’s philosophy which In the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries
combined faithfulness to the text with a Platonism was taken up outside the acade-
Christian understanding of the wisdom to mies, and developed as a philosophy for lay-
which Plato aspired. Although he acknowl- men. The aspects of Plato’s philosophy which
edged the diversity of the themes of the gave it a secular and broadly cultural appeal
dialogues, he regarded Plato’s underlying included the Socratic conception of philoso-
philosophical outlook as unified. Ficino’s phy as the pursuit of wisdom, the dialogic,
Theologia Platonica de immortalitate ani- non academic format of Plato’s philosophy,
mae (1469–74) offers a systematic philos- and its potential for symbolic interpretation.
ophy of the soul, set out as a Neoplatonic The most striking instance of a Renaissance
hierarchy of being, and defended in terms of development of Platonic philosophy was the
scholastic arguments. adaptation of Plato’s philosophy of love in
Adapting Plato for Renaissance consump- the dialoghi d’amore (dialogues of love), such
tion meant tackling the culturally unaccept- as Pietro Bembo’s Gli Asolani (1505). These
able aspects of Plato’s dialogues. This was enjoyed wide currency as a genre through-
done in a variety of ways. Paedophilia (q.v. out the Renaissance, the most popular of all
Paederastia) and homoeroticism were rein- being, Baldessare Castiglione’s Il libro del
vented as Platonic love. On the religious side, cortegiano (1528). Another secular arena for
Platonism had been associated since early Plato’s philosophy in the Renaissance was
Christian times with theologically danger- political, especially the idea of the perfect
ous positions, especially Trinitarian heresies. government – the most creative and endur-
Old theological controversies were reignited ing Renaissance engagement with Plato’s R.
by the new influx of Plato’s texts, fuelling being Thomas More’s Utopia (1516).
the attack on Plato by George of Trebizond For more information, see Allen (1984),
(Comparatio Platonis et Aristotelis, 1458), Celenza (2007), Copenhaver (1992) and
which provoked Bessarion’s defence, In Hankins (1990).

280

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 280 3/8/2001 5:11:56 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

THE CAMBRIDGE PLATONISTS offers profound insights into the nature and
workings of the human soul. But they also
Sarah Hutton regarded Platonism as compatible with atom-
Cambridge Platonism is a modern term used ist natural philosophy, and looked to Plato to
to designate a form of English Platonism supply the metaphysics which they regarded
which flourished in the seventeenth century. as wanting in Cartesianism and other con-
The name Cambridge Platonism derives from temporary philosophy.
the fact that its chief proponents were all Contrary to views purveyed by schol-
associated with the University of Cambridge: ars like Cassirer (1963) and Koyré (1957)
Benjamin Whichcote (1609–83), Peter Sterry the Cambridge Platonists were not mys-
(1613–72), John Smith (1618–52), Nathaniel tics, but apologists for religion who sought
Culverwell (1619–51), Henry More to defend religious belief by philosophical
(1614–87) and Ralph Cudworth (1617–89). means. Platonism, with its combination of
Their wider circle included George Rust abstract reasoning and spiritual insight met
(d. 1670), Anne Conway (1630–79) and that aim well. They devoted their consider-
John Norris (1657–1711). Their interest in able philosophical learning to religious and
Plato’s philosophy may be accounted for moral issues, to defending the existence of
partly by their desire to find an alternative god and the immortality of the soul and to
to outdated scholastic Aristotelianism, and formulating a practical ethics for Christian
partly by their anti-Calvinist theological con- conduct. Their anti-determinism led them to
victions, which are characterized by a firm propose arguments for human liberty and
persuasion of the compatibility of reason and autonomy. The broadly Platonist features of
faith, an optimistic view of human nature their philosophy included their holding the
and belief in the freedom of the will. They eternal existence of both moral principles
studied Plato in relation to the full corpus of and of truth. Their epistemology and ethics
classical philosophy which had been made is underpinned by their view that the human
available by the editorial and translating mind is equipped with the principles of rea-
endeavours of Renaissance humanists. And son and morality. They were all dualists for
they studied ancient philosophy in relation whom mind is ontologically prior to matter,
to contemporary scientific and philosophical and for whom the truths of the mind are
developments – principally the philosophy of superior to sense-knowledge.
Descartes, Hobbes and Spinoza as well as the There are certainly aspects of their view
ideas of Bacon, Boyle and the Royal Society of Plato which we no longer share. Plato was
(Smith, Culverwell, Cudworth and More to them the ‘divine Plato’, the ‘Attic Moses’,
were among the first Englishmen to read the Greek philosopher who had achieved
Descartes). Plato was for them first among the greatest insight into the truth of the
philosophers, and they regarded Plotinus Bible. In his attempt to square Platonism
as his key interpreter. They viewed Plato’s with Christian doctrine, Cudworth, for
philosophy as the highest achievement of example, went to some lengths to argue
the human mind, unassisted by revelation. that Plato was not just a monotheist, but
Plato is the philosopher who exemplifies the a Trinitarian. Readings of this kind are
compatibility of reason and spirituality, and heavily dependent on accepting as genuine

281

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 281 3/8/2001 5:11:56 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

texts of controversial authenticity, notably invoking no authority but what was availa-
the second letter. However, their Platonism ble to everyone: common reason and the evi-
was not an antiquarian predilection, but dence of the senses. ‘Modern philosophy’ is
fully engaged with contemporary thought. often presented loosely in retrospect as divid-
Although they respected Ficino, and adopted ing into the rationalist tradition led by René
a similar model of perennial philosophy to Descartes (1596–1650), for which the math-
his, the sources of their Platonism were more ematical sciences provided the paradigm or
recent (they used the Stephanus edition) as at least the ideal; and the empiricist tradition,
was the philosophical prism through which begun by Francis Bacon (1561–1626) and
they interpreted it. They accepted post-Gali- re-shaped by John Locke (1632–1704), who
lean science, and subscribed to an atomistic took their inspiration from the burgeoning
theory of matter. But they repudiated the empirical sciences and sought to show how
mechanistic natural philosophies of Hobbes ideas all came from experience.
and Descartes, arguing that spirit is the fun- At the centre of the debates between phi-
damental causal principle in the operations losophers of the period are the interrelated
of nature. Both More’s hypothesis of the Platonic topics of innate ideas and eternal
‘spirit of Nature’ and Cudworth’s concept truths. Locke, consistently with his pro-
of ‘Plastic Nature’ are theories of intermedi- gramme of showing how all ideas come from
ate causality which owe something to Plato’s experience, denied the existence of innate
anima mundi. ideas. Truths that seem to be necessary and
The Cambridge Platonists continued and so appear to be eternal truths must, accord-
developed a strand of thought that was ing to him, be understood in some other
already present in early modern England – in way, as depending on definitions of terms.
John Colet (1467–1519) and Thomas Jackson In opposition to Locke, Gottfried Leibniz
(1578–1640). Their influence endured well (1646–1716) allied himself consciously
into the eighteenth century, notably through with the Platonic tradition. Leibniz not only
Lord Shaftesbury (1671–1713) and Richard defended innate ideas but took the same side
Price (1723–91). as the Cambridge Platonists in the debate as
to whether or not the eternal truths were sub-
ject to god’s will. He held that the standards
Section C: The Influence and Interpretation of goodness and justice would be ‘arbitrary’
of Plato in Modern and Contemporary if they were subject to the will of god. But
Philosophy in such controversies original philosophers
often took a different view from what might
be expected. Thus Descartes, though com-
EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY: mitted to innate ideas, denied that the truths
FROM DESCARTES TO BERKELEY of reason were independent of the will of
god. And on the other side, the Irish philoso-
Stuart Brown pher George Berkeley (1685–1753) though
Early modern philosophy was the new phi- he accepted the empiricist tenet that all ideas
losophy of the seventeenth and eighteenth come from experience, could still find much
centuries, modelled primarily on the math- in common with the Platonic tradition, find-
ematical or the experimental sciences and ing room for innate ‘notions’.

282

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 282 3/8/2001 5:11:56 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

One difficulty in assessing the reception Leibniz, though he would have disliked
and influence of Plato on the first genera- any (sectarian) label such as ‘Platonist’ being
tion of ‘modern’ philosophers is that they attached to him, regarded Plato as ‘the great-
set about doing philosophy in a radically est of the idealists’ (i.e. those who opposed
new way, and most made little mention of materialism). He told one correspondent that
their predecessors. The merits of the views if Plato’s philosophy were to be stated rig-
expressed by a philosopher were to be orously and systematically, it would ‘come
decided not by their pedigree but by the quite close’ to his own.
strength of the arguments given in support There is always some prospect of finding
of them. Benedict de Spinoza (1632–77) common ground between philosophers in
presented his Ethics as if he were writing the rationalist epistemological tradition and
a treatise on geometry, which provided an Plato. In the case of those labelled ‘empiri-
ideal of rational argument he and Descartes cists’, however, it might be expected that
shared, as did many other philosophers of looking for points in common with Plato
the period. would be particularly fruitless. But one of
Nicolas Malebranche (1638–1715) them, George Berkeley (1685–1753), wrote a
aimed to reconcile the Christian thought book (Siris) in later life in which he affirmed
of Augustine with the secular philosophy that the Platonists ‘had a notion of the true
of Descartes. Though Malebranche made System of the World’:
no acknowledgement of any debt to Plato
himself, he was sometimes referred to as They allowed of mechanical principles,
‘the French Plato’. His ‘Christianization’ but actuated by soul or mind . . . they
of Descartes allowed others to think of the saw that a mind, infinite in power, unex-
tended, invisible, immortal, governed,
‘father’ of modern philosophy as a reviver of
connected and contained all things: they
Plato. Thus, Leibniz credited Descartes with
saw that there was no such thing as real
having restored the study of Plato by leading absolute space: that mind, soul, or spirit
the mind away from the senses and by raising truly and really exists: that bodies exist
the doubts of the (Platonic) Academy. only in a secondary and dependent sense.
Leibniz was one of the first of the mod- (Sec. 266)
ern philosophers to be willing to place him-
self within a philosophical tradition. When It is a matter of controversy whether Berkeley
he was in Paris in the 1670s, he was part was being true, in this later work, to his
of a group keen to promote the revival of youthful Principles of Human Knowledge,
neglected philosophers of the past. He him- on which his reputation as one of the leading
self had written some Latin abridgements of philosophers of his age is based. Muirhead
the Phaedo and the Theaetetus, and encour- (1931), who provides a survey of the contin-
aged others to produce French translations uing tradition of Platonism in Anglo-Saxon
of Plato’s dialogues. One of Descartes’ many philosophy from the time of the Cambridge
critics, the ‘Academic’ sceptic Simon Foucher Platonists, treats Berkeley as a follower of
(1644–96), presented himself as a modern Locke’s way of ideas and his later sense of a
follower of the later Platonic Academy in connection with Plato as not relevant to an
ancient Athens, whose principles he pro- overall interpretation of his thought. (For
fessed to revive. a more recent assessment, see Hedley and

283

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 283 3/8/2001 5:11:57 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

Hutton 2008.) But even in the Principles Idealism in nineteenth-century Germany


there are obvious debts to Plato, as in his begins with the early romantic movement or
emphasis on spirits and his curiously ‘ration- Frühromantik (1797–1802), which has been
alistic’ argument for the immortality of the described as ‘the greatest revival of Platonism
soul. Like Descartes and Leibniz, Berkeley since the Renaissance’ (Walzel). Inspired by J.
held that souls, being indivisible, were not J. Winckelmann and the revival of Plato schol-
corruptible, and so were ‘naturally immor- arship in the eighteenth century, Friedrich
tal’, allowing as piety demanded that it was Schlegel (1772–1829), Friedrich Hölderlin
within the omnipotence of god to destroy (1770–1843), F. W. J. Schelling (1775–1845),
them. On this – to him – fundamental point F. D. Schleiermacher (1767–1834) and G. W.
Berkeley does not fit comfortably in the F. Hegel (1770–1831) all read Plato in the
space once allotted to him, between Locke original Greek in their youth and received
and Hume. He also belongs, as they did not, their philosophical education from him. Of
to the tradition of Christian Platonism. special importance for them were Phaedrus,
For more information, see Brown (1995), Symposium and Timaeus. The metaphys-
Brown (1997), Mercer (2001) and Muirhead ics of the early romantics was monistic,
(1931). organic and idealist. The monism came from
Spinoza’s single universal substance; but the
organicism and idealism came from Plato.
They saw the universe as a single living
NINETEENTH-CENTURY PLATO organism following Plato’s description of the
SCHOLARSHIP world in the Ti. as ‘a living being with soul
and intelligence’ (Ti. 30b). This organism was
Frederick Beiser governed by intelligence, and had unified a
In fundamental respects German idealism rational structure, according to ‘the idea of
of the nineteenth century was a revival of ideas’ (Schelling). There was also a profound
Platonism. The source of its idealism was aesthetic dimension to early romantic meta-
Plato’s theory of ideas; the inspiration for physics: the universal organism was a work
its Naturphilosophie was Plato’s cosmol- of art; and the rational structure of things,
ogy; and the basis for its epistemology was the ideas, were grasped only through aes-
Plato’s rationalism. In some idealists – Hegel thetic intuition. The chief source of this aes-
and Trendelenburg – Aristotelian motifs theticism was Plato’s Phdr. Romantic ethics
seem to overshadow Plato’s influence; but lays the greatest importance on love, whose
even in these cases Aristotle proves to be a source is as much Platonic as Christian. No
mediator of Platonic themes. Kant was also less than their eighteenth-century forbears,
a fundamental source of German idealism; the early romantics were Diotima’s children.
but his significance too lies in his transmis- Of all nineteenth-century German ideal-
sion of Platonic themes. German idealism ists, the most influential was Hegel. Although
of the nineteenth century was essentially his philosophy is usually interpreted as a
Platonized transcendental idealism, that modernized form of Aristotle, it is still, apart
is, Kant’s idealism minus the thing in itself, from its Aristotelian theory of universals,
regulative constraints and the transcenden- fundamentally Platonic. Having been nur-
tal subject. tured in a romantic nursery, Hegel upheld

284

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 284 3/8/2001 5:11:57 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

the same basic romantic doctrines – monism, influence on his age was immense; among
organicism and idealism – having the same his students were Frege, Brentano, Husserl,
Platonic roots. Even in his later years Hegel Windelband and Royce. Like Trendelenburg,
would pay handsome tribute to Plato, whom Lotze’s aim was to uphold the organic
he always regarded as the father of ideal- worldview against the growing naturalism
ism. After 1801 he broke with his roman- and materialism of the modern age. In his
tic friends and contemporaries, chiefly with Mikrokosmus (1856–64) he battled against
regard to the status of art and the powers of these forces by stressing the normative
aesthetic intuition in providing knowledge dimension of the universe, which he under-
of the absolute. But this was not a complete stood in essentially Platonic terms as the
renunciation of the Platonic legacy; it was realm of ideas. With Lotze, Plato becomes
rather playing off one Platonic motif (the a warrior against modern materialism and
dialectic of the Republic) against another naturalism. In his 1874 Logik, Lotze made
(the aestheticism of the Phdr.). an important distinction between the realm
The Platonic inspiration of nineteenth-cen- of truth or validity and that of existence and
tury idealism continues with Friedrich Adolf placed the Platonic ideas solely and squarely
Trendelenburg (1802–72). Trendelenburg, in the realm of truth or validity. The point
who was professor of philosophy in Berlin of Plato’s theory of ideas was to distinguish
for 40 years, was a seminal influence on between these realms, so that ideas must not
German philosophy from the 1840s to be understood as entities but as truths whose
1870s. Though he is most famous for his validity transcends the realm of existence.
critique of Hegel, he was also an important Lotze claimed that Aristotle had misunder-
teacher for the young Kierkegaard, Dilthey, stood Plato’s theory of ideas and that Plato’s
Cohen and Brentano. The chief source of theory, properly understood, gives a glimpse
his influence lay in his transmission of the into a completely new world, that of truth or
classical legacy. Very much a late roman- validity. Lotze’s interpretation of Plato, and
tic, Trendelenburg saw himself as a spokes- his distinction between truth and existence,
man for Plato and Aristotle’s philosophy in proved fundamental for phenomenology and
the modern world. The express aim of his neo-Kantianism.
philosophy, as expounded in his Logische Nineteenth-century idealism reaches its
Untersuchungen, was to defend ‘the organic culmination in the Marburg school of neo-
worldview’ of Plato’s Ti. against modern Kantianism, whose chief members were
naturalism and materialism. Trendelenburg Hermann Cohen (1842–1918), Paul Natorp
became famous for his Aristotle scholarship, (1854–1924) and Ernst Cassirer (1874–
especially his critical edition of De Anima, 1945). Cohen was the father of the Marburg
and has been seen as a major champion of school, and in him the Platonic influence is
modern Aristotelianism; yet he always saw most visible. With no exaggeration, Cassirer
Aristotle’s philosophy as fundamentally once described Cohen as ‘one of the most
Platonic. resolute Platonists in the history of philoso-
Another major idealist of the mid-nine- phy’. Though his philosophy grew out of his
teenth century, and transmitter of Platonism, interpretation of Kant, Cohen understood
was Hermann Lotze (1816–81). As professor Kant in Platonic terms. He regarded Plato as
in Göttingen for 35 years (1844–81), Lotze’s ‘the founder of idealism’, and he saw Kant

285

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 285 3/8/2001 5:11:57 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

as his modern interpreter and transmit- a novel programme announced in the intro-
ter. In some early essays – ‘Die Platonische duction to an opening volume of Friedrich
Ideenlehre’ (1866) and Platos Ideenlehre Schleiermacher’s translations of the dialogues
und die Mathematik (1878) – Cohen inter- into German (1804). Schleiermacher initiated
prets the theory of ideas in methodological a largely still regnant approach, according to
terms. The ideas are not things but stand which Plato is to be understood from his dia-
for ‘hypotheses’, that is, the first principles logues, which are in turn to be understood
of reasoning. In his later work, Die Logik in the light of an accurate reconstruction
des reinen Denkens (1902), the ideas have a of their original order. By the last, however,
more metaphysical status, because they are Schleiermacher understood a methodical
not only principles of thinking and reason- series deliberately designed as such by Plato
ing but also principles of being itself. In his from first to last. His approach was shortly
Platos Ideenlehre (published in 1902, written modified crucially by K. F. Hermann’s phil-
in 1887) Natorp applied Cohen’s approach ological thesis that the dialogues reflect the
to Plato’s intellectual development, interpret- unfolding of Plato’s thought according to
ing the ideas in terms of laws and scientific definite principles over which he himself
method. It was typical of the Platonic legacy did not have authorial control. Hermann
of the Marburg school that Natorp saw worked under the twin theoretical influences
Plato’s philosophy as the best introduction of Friedrich Schlegel’s romanticism and the
to idealism. ‘In Plato, idealism is primal, as it idealism of thinkers such as J. G. Fichte and
were native . . . Plato’s theory of ideas is the G. W. F. Hegel (Ausland 2002).
birth of idealism in the history of humanity.’ During the nineteenth century, vari-
Those lines from Natorp’s preface could be ous scholars were for a variety of reasons
taken as the fundamental conviction of all moved to athetize critically one or more of
nineteenth-century German idealism. a wide range of dialogues, culminating in
the extreme of A. Krohn’s conclusion that
the Republic alone was a genuine dialogue
of Plato, the general ordering assumed by
NINETEENTH-CENTURY PLATONIC Schleiermacher and Hermann alike, which
SCHOLARSHIP viewed the other dialogues as preliminary to
a ‘final’ exposition this dialogue would intro-
Hayden W. Ausland duce, has undergone but important modifi-
Modern Platonic scholarship began around cation since their day. This has resulted in the
the turn of the eighteenth to nineteenth significantly different view of Plato’s devel-
centuries, when a reconceived ‘critical’ phi- opment still often assumed, which has it that
lology emerged in Germany that soon sup- the R., together with several other character-
planted the older, humanistic style centred istically idealistic dialogues, is to be placed
in the Netherlands. W. G. Tennemann’s in a ‘middle’ period, with Plato’s ‘late’ period
attempt to cull the Platonic corpus of spuri- now occupied instead by a number of more
ous dialogues and to distil from a supposedly logically-oriented dialogues, which most
genuine remainder a systematic philosophy nineteenth-century developmentalists, fol-
arranged in accordance with Kantian prin- lowing Schleiermacher and Hermann’s lead,
ciples (1792–95) was promptly eclipsed by tended to associate with an immediately

286

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 286 3/8/2001 5:11:57 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

post-Socratic ‘Megarian’ phase in Plato’s 2000; Howland 1991), but the twentieth
thought. century nevertheless inherited and retained
The change in outlook responsible for this a scholarly consensus in favour of the reor-
shift arose first in Great Britain, but later dering proposed first by Campbell (1867; cf.
also more or less independently in Germany, 1889 and 1896). Moreover, despite an early
in either case prompted by what may be attempt to read the same newly ‘late’ dia-
broadly termed ‘stylistic’ considerations. logues in more metaphysical a vein (Jackson
For the first half of the nineteenth century, 1881:85), the scholarly mainstream has
efforts to order the dialogues relied mostly tended to assume that Plato later in life moved
on historical and doctrinal considerations away from thought of the kind informing the
of various kinds. (Friedrich Überweg 1855 R. The following syncopated orderings will
embodies the fullest such treatment of the illustrate the difference involved (for further
question. For a contemporary review of the comparisons, see the tables in Ritter 1910
status quaestionis, with extensive references and Ross 1951):
to previous scholarship, cf. Franz Susemihl
1855–57, updated in Eduard Zeller 1889.)
More empirically oriented scholarship in Hermann (1839) Ross (1951)
Britain was strongly sceptical of the entire Under Socratic Before Sicilian
approach (thus George Grote 1965), but in influence: visits: Chrm., La.,
his 1867 edition of the Sophist and Politicus, Charmides, Laches, Euthphr., Hp. Ma.
Lewis Campbell found affinities in the diction Euthyphro, Hippias
of the presumably late Laws with that found Major
in five other dialogues (Sph., Plt., Philebus, Under Megarian After first Sicilian
Timaeus and Critias). With this observation influence: Cratylus, visit: Cra.,
he paired a surmise that Plato had later in Theaetetus, Sph., Symposium,
life reconsidered both the political and the Plt., Parmenides Phaedo, R.,
metaphysical idealism of the R. in favour of Phaedrus, Prm., Tht.
a compromise with the real world in both During tenure as After second Sicilian
regards. Campbell’s study remained unno- director of the visit: Sph., Plt.
ticed for some time on the continent, where Academy: Phdr., After third Sicilian
around the same time an interest developed Smp., Phd., Phlb., visit: Ti., Criti.,
in reconstructing historically Plato’s compet- R., Ti., Criti., Lg. Phlb., Epistle 7, Lg.
itive interactions with contemporaries like
Isocrates, which led, in turn, to a series of
often minute examinations of Plato’s stylistic It is noteworthy that with neither general
devices. By the end of the century, these could ordering exemplified above could analo-
be gathered together as the putative data for gously ‘scientific’ criteria be found for iso-
a ‘stylometric science’ that promised to solve lating the common grouping of ‘Socratic’
once and for all the question of the order of dialogues, whose association in a hypotheti-
the dialogues (see Lutoslawski 1897). The cally early Platonic phase rests instead largely
sheer variety and inconsistency of the results on a particular interpretation of certain criti-
so obtained (cf. Brandwood 1990) has called cisms Aristotle directs against Plato, origi-
this entire approach into question (Ausland nally designed to rehabilitate Socrates as a

287

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 287 3/8/2001 5:11:57 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

philosopher in a sense adequate to nineteenth Brandwood 1992:90–120; Kahn 2002:93–


century demands (Ausland 2005). But the 112; Thesleff 2009:213–30). Stylometry was
conjectural three-period ordering and expla- unable to establish divisions within this latter
nation proposed by Campbell in 1867 still group (Kahn 1996:43–4)
remain those most often habitually assumed The existence of three groups of dialogues
by Platonic scholars today, if usually without does not in itself establish the truth of devel-
a sufficiently critical appreciation of their opmentalism, though it does provide a basis
historical genesis or scientific fragility. for it. It is possible to hold that the dialogues
were written in a certain order and to deny
that this chronology reflects any significant
changes in Plato’s view (Kahn 1996; Shorey
DEVELOPMENTALISM 1903:4). The most influential version of
developmentalism was motivated by a desire
William Prior to restrict the scope of Plato’s most famous
Developmentalism is a theory concerning the theory, the theory of forms (q.v.). Unitarians
order of composition and the interpretation since ancient times had regarded the theory
of Plato’s dialogues. It is a modern phenom- of forms as a distinctive and enduring fea-
enon; ancient interpreters of Plato were ‘uni- ture of Plato’s philosophy. In the middle dec-
tarians’ (Annas 1999:3–5; unitarians believe ades of the twentieth century, however, this
that there is a systematic unity of Platonic doctrine came under scrutiny. Some scholars
doctrine or belief among all the dialogues). took the critique of the theory in the Prm.
There are several varieties of developmental- to be either a refutation of the theory of
ism; what is common to them all is the idea forms (Ryle 1939a:134) or a call for signifi-
that the philosophical views contained in the cant changes in it (Owen 1953a; cf. Kraut
dialogues, which are taken to reflect Plato’s 1992c:14–19).
own views, changed significantly over time. This criticism required modification of the
In order for a developmentalist theory three stylometric groups of dialogues. The
of Plato’s philosophy to exist it is necessary strategy behind this grouping was to con-
to determine, at least in broad outlines, the fine the theory of forms, or at least objec-
order in which the dialogues were written. tionable versions of it, to the middle group
Until the advent of stylometry (the meas- of dialogues. On this interpretation the
urement of changes in Plato’s style, some of ‘middle dialogues’ become precisely ‘dia-
them unconscious) in the latter part of the logues containing the theory of (paradigm)
late nineteenth century there was no agree- Forms’. In order to accomplish this it was
ment on this order. The research of Campbell necessary to move three dialogues in the first
and other scholars led to the establish- stylometric group, the Cratylus, Phaedo and
ment of a late group of dialogues, includ- Symposium, into the middle group of dia-
ing the Timaeus, Critias, Philebus, Sophist, logues. The remaining dialogues in the first
Statesman and Laws, a penultimate group of group labelled ‘Socratic’ or ‘early’ were held
dialogues, including the Phaedrus, Republic, by some to represent the philosophy of the
Parmenides and Theaetetus, and an early historical Socrates (Vlastos 1991a). This
group consisting the remaining dialogues (for Socratic group was held to be purely ethical
thorough surveys of stylometric studies, see in content and not to contain any reference to

288

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 288 3/8/2001 5:11:57 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

the theory of forms. Two dialogues belonging of the R. This version of developmentalism
to the penultimate stylometric group, the Tht. does not involve modification of the first
and Prm., which were thought to be critical and second stylometric groups of dialogues,
of the doctrines of the middle period, were as does the version outlined above. Differing
placed by some scholars into a late, ‘critical’ conceptions of dialectic provide the basis for
group of dialogues. One scholar boldly pro- yet another conception of developmentalism:
posed moving the Timaeus, which contains the Socratic elenchus being succeeded by the
the paradigm version of the theory of forms, Platonic method of hypothesis and finally
from the late group of dialogues to the mid- by the method of collection and division
dle group (Owen 1953a). (Robinson 1953).
This version of developmentalism was As noted above, the chief opposing view
the dominant interpretation of Plato among to developmentalism is unitarianism, the
analytical scholars in the middle years of the view that Plato’s view altered little or not at
twentieth century. Questions about it arose, all over the course of his career. It is often
however. Some dialogues did not fit the early- assumed that one must be either a develop-
middle-late schema. The Meno, a dialogue mentalist or a unitarian. This, however, is not
of the first stylometric group of dialogues, necessarily the case. Unitarianism and devel-
seemed in some respects to be a Socratic dia- opmentalism are polar opposites: there is
logue, yet it contained the doctrine of recol- space, inhabited by many scholars, between
lection (q.v.), which was associated in the the options of radical change and little or no
Phd. (72e–7a) with the theory of forms. Some change in Plato’s view. It is also possible to
scholars regarded it as ‘transitional’ between reject the stylometric chronology on which
the early and middle dialogues. Some scholars developmentalism is based, or the idea that
(Allen 1970; Prior 2004) argued that some the dialogues represent (stages of) Plato’s
Socratic dialogues contain an early version of thought. Even if the stylometric chronol-
the theory of forms. The greatest impediment ogy is accepted, however, the most fruitful
to acceptance of this version of the develop- reading of the dialogues remains a matter of
mentalist picture, however, has been the Ti. interpretation.
Owen’s (1953a) attempt to re-date the dia-
logue to the middle period was criticized by
Cherniss (1957) and, despite vigorous and
prolonged scholarly debate, has not won the COMPOSITIONAL CHRONOLOGY
support of a majority of scholars (cf., e.g.
Brandwood 1992:112–14; Irwin 2008:80; Debra Nails
Silverman 2002:12). It was once hoped that determining the order
The presence or absence of the theory of in which Plato composed his dialogues would
forms is not the only criterion used to dis- permit the mapping of his philosophical
tinguish groups of Platonic dialogues. Penner development, but that approach, dominant
(1992) has argued that the relevant distinc- for some 150 years, now creaks unreliably.
tion is between a simple and a tripartite the- Two data from ancient times motivate infer-
ory of the soul, and that the breaking point ences about the order of composition of
between the early Socratic account of the Plato’s dialogues: Aristotle’s remark (Politics
soul and the Platonic theory comes in bk 4 1264b26) that Republic antedates Laws,

289

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 289 3/8/2001 5:11:58 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

and Diogenes Laertius’ statement that Lg., the criterion founders on the exceptions: for
‘in the wax’ at Plato’s death, was transcribed example, Laches and Ion would be post-Tht.;
by Philip of Opus (3.37). Glaring linguistic Ti. and Parmenides would be pre-Tht., defy-
mannerisms in Lg. (e.g. notable synchysis, ing considerations of content. To complicate
plummeting rate of hiatus, absence of cer- matters, several dialogues mix the dramatic
tain clausulae, etc., catalogued in Thesleff and narrative styles.
2009:63–81) are shared by Timaeus, Critias, (2) Stylometry, measuring aspects of Plato’s
Politicus, Sophist, Philebus and Epistles 7 conscious and unconscious style (e.g. partici-
and 8, marking all as late and edited with ple frequency, incidence of particles, formu-
the same stylistic principles in view, perhaps lae of reply) promised ‘scientific’ accuracy
those of Philip, whom Diogenes credits with in relative dating; and hundreds of studies
writing the non-Platonic Epinomis, stylomet- appeared after Campbell (1867) initiated the
rically indistinguishable from the bulk of the effort. Stylometry famously crossed swords
Lg. and the last half of Plt. Not unreasonably, with content when Owen (1953a) proposed
scholars sought definitive style markers of R. a ‘middle’ date for Ti. against the stylistic
that would permit the identification of a set evidence, though Cherniss (1957) trounced
of R.-like dialogues, leaving a third and ear- that bold suggestion. The advent of comput-
lier set, yet more remote from Lg. Although ers allowed measurement and correlation of
that effort has failed to distinguish the ‘early’ very large numbers of stylistic features and
and ‘middle’ groups reliably, the bulk of mod- heralded a new interest in stylometry, but the
ern scholarship has nevertheless followed problem of how to programme the computer
Campbell’s nineteenth century identification reiterated Campbell’s original problem: the
of three periods of productivity. Efforts to only invulnerable datum was the relation-
establish the order of composition once for ship between R. and Lg., insufficient for gen-
all on (a) literary, (b) stylometric, (c) thematic erating secure results. Ledger (1989) marked
and (d) historical foundations are yet alive. an advance with new programmes that did
(1) A common literary basis for composi- not require prior assumptions about what
tional order takes the predominance of Socratic to count as early style; but his preliminary
questioning as early, of constructive speeches results did not confirm scholars’ precon-
as middle. Despite the general uselessness of ceptions about the order of the dialogues
dramatic dates for determining composition (see Brandwood 1990; Young 1994), less
order, others have used the dramatic date of concerned about what he had to assume to
Theaetetus to claim that it was written just produce his results, delivered more palatable
before Sph. and Plt. Diogenes (3.38) reports fare, that is, confirming expectations. Again
an ancient story that Phaedrus, exhibiting complicating matters, both R. bk 1 and the
youthfulness (meirakiôdês), was Plato’s first first part of Prm. usually cluster with the
dialogue, a view defended by Tomin (1997). Socratic dialogues considered early. Kahn
Another effort takes literally the suggestion (2002) mounts a robust defence of stylom-
that such formulaic expressions as ‘I said’ and etry, in reply to which Griswold (2002) can-
‘he agreed’ should give way to direct speech vasses reasons to doubt its usefulness to our
(Tht. 143b–c; cf. R. 3.392c–8b). By this cri- understanding of Plato.
terion, dialogues with direct speech were (3) Thematic development was supposed
to be counted as later than Tht. However, (since Socher 1820) to demonstrate that

290

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 290 3/8/2001 5:11:58 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

Plato’s views evolved over time (e.g. about achieved by many of these scholars, their
forms, knowledge, political theory) and that results contradict one another within and
the order in which the dialogues were writ- across the methods used (Nails 1995:53–63).
ten could be determined by placing the least Moreover, a circularity problem confounds
evolved first. As evidence for such thematic (1)–(4): each suggested order depends on
development Aristotle’s various remarks on first positing a pre-R. exemplar for which
Socratic vs. Platonic positions are often cited, no independent confirmation has ever been
and often criticized (Kahn 1996:79–87). Two credible, though the Apology has been an
insurmountable difficulties arise: (a) the view unfortunate favourite – unfortunate because
considered most highly evolved depended court speeches are not reliably compared to
entirely on the existing views of the scholars dialogues.
who performed the investigations; and (b) (5) Further, there is textual evidence and
when dialogues addressing more than one testimony that Plato edited or rewrote dia-
subject were compared, a dialogue might be logues in his lifetime, confounding any single
‘highly developed’ on one subject and intro- date.
ductory on another, while another dialogue (6) Also, short dialogues may have been
would have the reverse configuration, leaving written during the periods when longer
no obvious way to determine which had been ones – Grg., R., Lg. – were being conceived
written earlier. Using criterion (3) with a dash and executed, resisting any linear chronol-
of (1), Vlastos (1991a:46–9) proposed that ogy. Evidence for 5) and 6) undermines all
the historical Socrates, depicted in dialogues purportedly discrete chronologies.
deemed ‘early’, and Plato, in ‘middle and late’ (7) Several dialogues show clear evi-
dialogues – though usually using the character dence of editing or rewriting: for example,
Socrates as his mouthpiece – addressed differ- Grg. (Tarrant 1982), Protagoras (Frede
ent subject matters and in different ways. For 1986), Cratylus (Sedley 2003:6–21) and
contrary views, see Press (2000). Tht. (Tarrant 2010). Inconsistencies in Lg.
(4) Less frequently than with the three prompted Morrow (1960) and Ryle (1966)
approaches above, relative dates of composi- to support the view that there was a proto-
tion have been derived from absolute dates Lg.; and Nails and Thesleff (2003) argue that
proffered for particular dialogues, usually by the Lg. exhibits the accretion of later mate-
linking their themes to historical events, for rial onto a Platonic stem, as allowed for in
example, Plato’s experiences (Grote 1865; the actual encouragement of change in the
Tennemann 1792); the death of Theaetetus law code. As for testimony, Dionysius of
(if in 392, Kirchner 1901; if in 369, Vogt Halicarnassus (de Compositione Verborum
1909–10); Theban politics (Dušanić 1979, 25.207–18), said Plato ‘combed and curled
1980); or to positions advocated by rivals in every direction’ the first line of R. bk 1.
whom Plato was said to be answering, for (8) R. presents an especially complex case;
example, Antisthenes or Isocrates (Rick and the extent to which it was revised dur-
1931; Ries 1959); or sometimes to nascent ing Plato’s lifetime casts further suspicion on
schools such as the Cynics or Cyrenaics. single dates of composition for any of the
Consensus about the order of composition longer dialogues while it also makes it more
has stayed firmly out of reach for several rea- plausible that short dialogues were com-
sons. Despite the wondrously exact results posed along the way. Although this remains

291

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 291 3/8/2001 5:11:58 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

controversial, it is likely that before the R. as 392 or 391 BCE could have included more
we know it was compiled, there was both (a) than a score of exact parallels to the lan-
a freestanding version of the first book, On guage and proposals of R. bks 2–3 and 5. It
Justice or Thrasymachus; and (b) a proto-R. explains why there is a dearth of contempo-
or Ideal State of two scrolls that comprised raneous references to other parts of R.; why
much of R. bk 2, most of R. bk 3 and the the explicit summary of the ideal state at the
beginning of R. bk 5 (for exact passages, see beginning of the Ti.–Criti. summarizes only
Thesleff 2009:521). those very same parts of R.; why a summary
Among the reasons cited for a discrete of the same material appears at the beginning
composition of R. bk 1, regardless of whether of R. bk 8; and why Aristotle summarizes the
it preceded or followed the proto-R., are the same material in Politics II.
natural break before the remainder of the dia- Ryle (1966:216–300) offers a compre-
logue; and R. bk 1’s featuring of several per- hensive, common sense discussion of the
sons whose active dates in Athens cannot be order of composition of the dialogues. In
reconciled with the lives of Adeimantus and shorter compass, but nevertheless taking a
Glaucon, who would then have been children number of approaches into account, Irwin
(Nails 1998). In addition, Socrates’ elenc- (2008:77–84) makes a case for the Anglo-
tic interaction with Cephalus, Polemarchus American ‘standard view’ of the order of
and Thrasymachus resembles that of other composition, distinguishing it from simple
Socratic dialogues; in R. bks 2–10, Socrates developmentalism, as criticized effectively by
takes a constructive role. Among those who Cooper (1997:xii–xviii).
have supported the view that R. bk 1 was
composed separately, deploying arguments
about content, are Vlastos (1991a:248–51)
and Kraut (1992a:xii); Kahn (1993) has ANALYTIC APPROACHES TO PLATO
opposed it. Stylometric analyses (Arnim 1914;
Ritter 1888:35–7, 1910:236–7) likewise sup- J. H. Lesher
ported separate composition (Brandwood’s During the past half-century a number of
1990:67–73 data is claimed by both sides; scholars have sought to apply the techniques
and Ledger (1989) did not test for variation of modern analytic philosophy to Plato’s
between R. bk 1 and R. bks 2–10). writings. This has involved recasting portions
There is abundant, though not conclusive, of the dialogues as concisely stated deduc-
evidence for a proto-R. or Ideal State – well tive arguments, exploring questions relating
known for some time before Plato composed to validity as well as to truth, exposing con-
R. – most of it provided by philologists tradictions and equivocations and making
(Hermann 1839; Hirmer 1897:592–8; Thesleff explicit all essential assumptions. The ration-
2009:519–39 with further references). Aulus ale behind this approach, as Gregory Vlastos
Gellius (Attic Nights 14.3.3) mentions the has explained, is that:
two scroll version that Xenophon opposed;
and Diogenes (5.22, 5.43) names a two By means of these techniques we may
scroll epitome of Plato’s R. from the librar- now better understand some of the prob-
ies of Aristotle and Theophrastus. A proto-R. lems Plato attempted to solve and we
explains how Aristophanes’ Ecclesiazusae of are, therefore, better equipped to assess

292

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 292 3/8/2001 5:11:58 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

the merits of his solutions. The result distinct senses of ‘know’ prompted others to
has been a more vivid sense of the rel- reflect on Socrates’ conception of knowledge
evance of his thought to the concerns of and its relation to virtue.
present-day ontologists, epistemologists, In his famous 1963 paper David Sachs
and moralists. (Vlastos 1971a:vii)
charged that the main argument of Plato’s
Republic traded on two different concep-
The classic example of the genre is Vlastos’ tions of justice and was therefore fallacious.
study of the Third Man Argument (TMA) in ‘Platonic justice’ consisted in the parts of the
Plato’s Parmenides (Vlastos 1954). Although soul working in harmony with one another
the name derives from Aristotle’s restatement while ‘vulgar justice’ consisted in refrain-
of the argument, the Prm. version holds that ing from behaviour normally counted as
positing the existence of a form such as large- unjust (acts of theft, sacrilege, etc.). Since
ness commits us to the existence of an infinite the challenge posed to Socrates by Glaucon
number of forms of largeness. Vlastos identi- and Adeimantus was to show, in effect, that
fied two assumptions essential to the valid- vulgar justice is profitable, Socrates’ expla-
ity of the TMA: (a) self-predication (that the nation of the benefits of Platonic justice was
form of F is itself F); and (b) nonidentity (that irrelevant. The many published ‘responses to
anything that has the character of F must be Sachs’ failed to yield a consensus, but most
nonidentical with that in virtue of which it found a greater degree of coherence in Plato’s
has that character). Vlastos maintained that account than Sachs had claimed.
while the two assumptions are inconsist- Analytic techniques have also been put to
ent (they imply among other things that the use in connection with epistemological and
form of F cannot be identical with itself), metaphysical aspects of the R. One example
Plato never clearly saw the inconsistency or of this approach, with a positive objective in
he would have stepped back from embrac- view, is Richard Ketchum’s inquiry into the
ing both principles. Vlastos concluded that grounds for Plato’s rejection of the knowabil-
the TMA reflected Plato’s ‘honest perplexity’, ity of things in the sensible world (Ketchum
but others have argued that Plato introduced 1987). As Ketchum explains the situation,
the TMA to call attention to inadequacies in Plato’s thesis that we can have no knowl-
earlier formulations of his theory of forms. edge of things in the sensible realm assumes
Three other studies by Vlastos focused a distinctive view of the nature of truth. To
attention on issues in Socratic philosophy. (a) assert the truth, as Plato sees it, is to assert
A 1974 account of Socrates’ attitude towards of a thing that is that it is (or of things that
civil disobedience prompted a series of discus- are that they are). But of any occupant of the
sions of how the apparently inconsistent posi- sensible world it can be said not only that it
tions Socrates embraces in the Apology and is (in some respect) but also that it is not (in
Crito might be reconciled. (b) A 1983 explo- some respect), and therefore one cannot say
ration of the Socratic method of elenchus or of it that it is tout court. And since knowledge
‘cross-examination’ sparked debate on the (both for us and for Plato) requires truth, it
assumptions underlying Socrates’ distinctive follows that, strictly speaking, no occupant
approach to philosophizing. (c) A 1985 anal- of the sensible world can be known. While
ysis of Socrates’ disavowal of knowledge as Ketchum leaves unanswered the question of
constituting ‘a complex irony’ exploiting two why Plato might have embraced this rather

293

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 293 3/8/2001 5:11:58 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

demanding view of the requirements for truth of knowledge as ‘true belief plus a logos or
(Prm. B2 seems a likely candidate here), his rational account’ a forerunner of the modern
explanation of the rationale behind Plato’s standard or tripartite analysis of knowledge.
denial of knowledge of things in the sensible These studies lend credence to the claim
realm has much to recommend it. that the use of modern techniques of analysis
Few passages in Plato’s writings have can help us to understand and assess Plato’s
attracted greater attention than Socrates’ achievements as a philosopher. But in focus-
refutation of Euthyphro’s third definition ing attention on texts that lend themselves to
of piety. When Euthyphro (unwisely) states logical analysis we run the risk of slighting
that the gods love what is pious because it other important if less logically structured
is pious (Euthphr. 10d) Socrates explains aspects of Plato’s thought. It would clearly
that if this were the case, and if ‘pious’ did be an error, for example, to develop an
mean ‘beloved by all the gods’, then the gods interpretation of a Platonic dialogue with-
would be loving what is beloved because it out attending to details relating to setting
is beloved – which contradicts the principle and characterization. Nor can the analysis
established at Euthphr. 10c that no one can of individual arguments, however expertly
love a thing because it is beloved. Socrates’ done, determine the larger significance of the
refutation of Euthyphro’s definition has been dialogues in which those arguments appear.
thought to pose problems for any attempt Thus we can profit from Vlastos’ analyses
to ground moral values in acts of will or of individual arguments without necessarily
approval, divine or otherwise. A second issue agreeing with his claim that the dialogues
posed by the Euthphr., memorialized in Peter give us an ‘early or elenctic Socrates’ as well
Geach’s charge of ‘fallacy’ (Geach 1966), is as a ‘mature’ one (see Beversluis 1993), or
whether Plato held that we can discover the that they divide into ‘early’, ‘middle’ and
essential nature from an inspection of indi- ‘late’ works (see Nails 1993). The relevance
vidual instances and that we must first know of Platonic thought to modern philosophy
the essential nature of a thing in order to has also sometimes been overstated. Plato’s
identify genuine instances of it. conception of knowledge, for example, may
Two dialogues generally regarded as bear a formal resemblance to the standard
works of Plato’s maturity have also been analysis of knowledge as justified true belief;
thought to anticipate issues of inter- but at Tht. 206c Socrates describes the logos
est to contemporary philosophers. In his as what we add to a belief we already have,
Philosophical Investigations (Secs. 48 ff.), not (as required by the standard analysis) as
Ludwig Wittgenstein identified the account some body of evidence or reasoning that led
of simples and complexes in ‘Socrates’ Dream us to adopt the belief we already have.
Theory’ in the Theaetetus as a forerunner of
the philosophy of logical atomism embraced
by Bertrand Russell, Wittgenstein himself
and others. Similarly, Gilbert Ryle claimed VLASTOSIAN APPROACHES
that the alphabet model of language intro-
duced in the Tht. and Sophist anticipates M. L. McPherran
aspects of Frege’s theory of meaning (Ryle Gregory Vlastos (1907–91) was one of the
1960), and many consider Plato’s conception most prolific, influential and well-regarded

294

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 294 3/8/2001 5:11:58 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

scholars of ancient Greek philosophy of the In his later life, Vlastos returned to his
twentieth century. His work ranged from earlier work on Socrates with a view to pub-
essays in pre-Socratic philosophy to Platonic lishing a book on the topic. After hosting
epistemology/metaphysics and Socratic moral a number of National Endowment for the
theory. He seems to have consistently assumed Humanities Summer Seminars on Socrates,
throughout his career that Plato’s dialogues where this ongoing work was exposed to
can be arranged into a tripartite order of the criticisms of many participants, he pub-
early, middle and late dates of composition, lished his results as Socrates: Ironist and
with the early, ‘aporetic’ dialogues offering Moral Philosopher (Vlastos 1991a). Chs 2
our best evidence – as opposed to, say, the and 3 make a sustained effort to solve the
testimony of Aristophanes (q.v. Aristophanes ‘Socratic Problem’, namely, the problem of
and ‘intellectuals’) or Xenophon (q.v. Other how to construct a Socratic philosophy that
Socratics) for the views and methods of the is distinct from that of Plato (or his other
historical Socrates (q.v.; q.v. Compositional followers), despite the fact that we have no
chronology). Vlastos thus offers a paradigm textual evidence by Socrates himself, and
case of the developmentalist approach (q.v. that the evidence we do have (such as Plato
Developmentalism) to the dialogues – as or Xenophon) appears not to be wholly
opposed to the Unitarian or Straussian (q.v. consistent.
Straussian approaches) interpretation. On Vlastos’ strategy, the primarily nondia-
According to Vlastos, Plato’s dialogues logical Ap. is regarded as capturing the tone
can be ordered into three groups: (a) The and essential substance of what Socrates
first group listed alphabetically as follows. actually said in the courtroom, and is thus
(i) Early Elenctic: Apology, Charmides, able to serve as a rough historical touch-
Crito, Euthyphro, Gorgias, Hippias Minor, stone (Vlastos 1991a:49–50, n. 15). The rest
Ion, Laches, Protagoras, Republic 1; (ii) of Plato’s early works are then understood
Transitional: Euthydemus, Hippias Major, to be imaginative recreations – and so not
Lysis, Menexenus, Meno. (b) The Middle necessarily reproductions – in dialogue form
Dialogues, listed in probable order of com- of the methods and doctrines of the his-
position: Cratylus, Phaedo, Symposium, torical Socrates. One then proceeds on the
Republic bks 2–10, Phaedrus, Parmenides, assumption that the early dialogues are the
Theaetetus. (c) The Late Dialogues, listed product of a Plato who, in the initial stages
in probable order of composition: Timaeus, of his philosophical career, was a convinced
Critias, Sophist, Politicus, Philebus, Laws Socratic and so philosophized after the man-
(Vlastos 1991a:46–7). In Vlastos’ account, ner of his teacher, pursuing through his writ-
Plato represents the views of his teacher in ing the Socratic insights he had made his own
the early dialogues, but then moves on in (an assumption justified by the independent
his middle dialogues to use Socrates as his testimony of Aristotle (and Xenophon to
mouthpiece to introduce his original and dis- some small extent) to the doctrines held by
tinctive theory of forms (q.v.) and associated the historical Socrates). On this view the
doctrines. Subsequently, and with the criti- early dialogues exhibit Socratic doctrine
cisms of that theory he put forward in the and method without necessarily or always
Prm. in mind, Plato then modified his views involving the conscious attempt to reproduce
in various ways in the late dialogues. an exact copy of them. This position in no

295

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 295 3/8/2001 5:11:59 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

way excludes the influence of Plato’s artistic On the basis of such evidence as this, Vlastos
craftsmanship and independent philosophi- finds ten key trait differences between SE and
cal intentions, and so does not hold that lit- SM; for example, SE is exclusively a practical
erally all the claims and positions in a text moral philosopher, disavowing knowledge
are ones Socrates (or Plato) was himself com- and possessing no theory of separated forms
mitted to (Vlastos 1991a:50–3, explains that or a complex account of the nature of the
he makes the fundamental assumption that soul or its immortality, whereas SM is a phi-
Plato’s dialogues record the development of losopher of wide-ranging theoretical inter-
Plato’s (not Socrates’) mind, with a sharp ests, confident that he has found knowledge,
change of direction in his way of thinking knowledge backed by a theory of separated
marked by the Men.’s introduction of the forms and of the tripartite structure of the
theory of recollection (q.v. Recollection) and immortal soul (Vlastos 1991a:47–9).
followed by the middle dialogues). An early Some commentators, however, are unim-
dialogue may appear to end in perplexity, pressed with Aristotle as a witness and as
but given this interpretation of their compo- a historian of philosophy, holding that his
sition, that surface perplexity need not mean testimony derives from his knowledge of
to a developmentalist that Plato himself had Plato’s dialogues and possibly other Socratic
no view on the issue at hand or on what the testimonia. On this view Aristotle is thus
position of the historical Socrates was. On but the first reader of a long line of readers
this approach, it is thus well within reason- (including Vlastos) taken in by the optical
able historiographic procedures to bring to illusion created by Plato’s masterful fictions
the interpretation of the early dialogues the (Kahn 1996:3; see further Beversluis 1993;
hypothesis that ‘authentic Socratic thought Nehamas 1992; Rowe 2006, who criticize
survives in Plato’s recreation of it’ (Vlastos Vlastos’ approach because of its reliance
1988:108). on the assumption that Aristotle is an inde-
Vlastos uses Aristotle’s testimony to nail pendent witness). Others focus their attack
down the distinction between the Socrates of on Vlastos’ attempt to impose a tripartite
the early dialogues (SE) and the Socrates of order on the dialogues and what they see as
the middle dialogues (SM) to make plausi- developmentalists’ unwarranted assumption
ble the working hypothesis that the ideas of that Ap. can be treated as historically accu-
the historical Socrates survive in Plato’s early rate in any useful sense (see, e.g. Morrison
dialogues. Vlastos (1991a:92) is particularly 2000; Nails 1993; Prior 2006; for a reply to
taken by Aristotle’s remark that: all these criticisms on behalf of the study of
Socrates based on a qualified developmental-
Socrates occupied himself with the excel- ism, see Brickhouse and Smith 2003).
lences of character, and in connection
with them became the first to raise the
problem of universal definitions . . . But
Socrates did not make the universals
CONTINENTAL APPROACHES
or the definitions exist apart; his suc-
cessors [viz. Plato], however, gave them
separate existence, and this was the kind Francisco Gonzalez
of thing they called ideas. (Metaphysics ‘Continental approaches’ to Plato are best
1078b7–32. Tr. after Jonathan Barnes) understood by tracing them back to their

296

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 296 3/8/2001 5:11:59 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

source, arguably Friedrich Nietzsche (1844– to the world of appearances, the rejection of
1900), because Nietzsche (1999, 2005) first becoming in favour of being, understood as
articulates the principal traits that charac- eternal static presence, the degrading of the
terize most readings of Plato in continental sensible in favour of the ‘supersensible’, the
philosophy despite the great diversity they disparagement of the body, the dismissal of
otherwise exhibit. poetry in favour of logic, the belief in Truth
(1) Nietzsche and his successors treat as opposed to truths.
Plato not as an object of philology and his- (5) Despite this critique, or rather because
tory, but rather as an interlocutor with whom of it, continental philosophers starting with
one can pursue a philosophical dialogue Nietzsche himself express a great indebted-
today, while at the same time assigning him ness to, and respect for, Plato. If the Greek
a definite place, and therefore a definite dis- philosopher is an adversary, he is a most
tance from us, in the history of philosophy. worthy one.
For continental philosophers starting with The next important name in the conti-
Nietzsche, doing philosophy today is insepa- nental approach to Plato, Martin Heidegger
rable from confronting and coming to terms (1889–1976), represents another turning
with the philosophical tradition; in such a point: Heidegger’s profound ambivalence
confrontation Plato becomes the privileged to Plato will come to characterize later con-
interlocutor. tinental readings and even produce a split
(2) In line with this, Nietzsche and his suc- among them. On the one hand, Heidegger is
cessors are most interested not in Plato’s spe- deeply influenced by Nietzsche’s critique and
cific conclusions or the arguments by which like him sees Plato as the representative of
he arrives at them, but rather in his funda- the metaphysical tradition that must be over-
mental assumptions, which usually go unsaid come. Specifically, Heidegger (2003) sees in
and must be discovered indirectly behind the Plato the inauguration of a naïve conception
texts. In Nietzsche this takes the form of an of being as static enduring presence arrived
emphasis on the ‘personalities’ of Plato and at from the perspective of a naïve conception
other Greek philosophers (1996), but in of time in terms of the present (with past and
later continental philosophers the general future understood as what is no longer or not
approach survives the abandonment of this yet present). Furthermore, Heidegger (1998,
‘psychologising’. 2004) sees in Plato the transformation of
(3) Given this emphasis on fundamental truth from an event of unconcealing taking
assumptions, Plato is seen not just as one place in beings themselves to mere correct-
philosopher among others, but rather as a ness in a speaking that corresponds to beings,
spokesman for the entire philosophical tradi- a transformation he identifies with Plato’s
tion he initiated. ‘unsaid’ teaching. Plato is thus seen as set-
(4) Thus, the confrontation with the philo- ting the West on its course towards a reduc-
sophical tradition takes the form of a radical tion of beings to a ‘standing reserve’ and a
critique of Plato. Plato is seen as represent- reduction of truth to ‘information’ in the age
ing all of those assumptions of the philo- of modern technology. Yet, at the same time,
sophical tradition from which continental Heidegger’s reading of Plato’s texts (a read-
philosophers seek to distance themselves: in ing much more sustained, nuanced and faith-
particular, the opposition of a ‘true’ world ful than Nietzsche’s) uncovers fundamental

297

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 297 3/8/2001 5:11:59 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

tendencies and characteristics that run coun- John Sallis (1996, 2004) and their pupils.
ter to the tradition with which he seeks to More and more philosophers trained within
identify Plato. He repeatedly encounters in the continental tradition are finding, when
Plato’s dialogues not the Platonism he seeks they turn to Plato’s dialogues, not the opposi-
to overcome but rather something much tion of philosophy to poetry and rhetoric but
more akin to his own task of thinking. A sim- their marriage, not a contemplation of the
ilar ambivalence can be seen in Emmanuel universal but a sensitivity to the particulari-
Levinas (1906–95), for whom Plato is both ties and contingencies of praxis, not a final
the representative of that ontological tradi- and absolute Truth but many approximate
tion that is to be surpassed and at least the truths, not the rejection of sensible appear-
first step towards surpassing it (see Benso ances but their validation as the resplendent
and Schroeder 2008). shining forth of the supersensible (beauty),
This ambivalence leads to a split among not the disparagement of the body and its
later continental philosophers in their rela- desires but a recognition of their indispen-
tion to Plato. Many, following in the foot- sability to the erotic pursuit of wisdom and
steps of Nietzsche and Heidegger, continue virtue. One could say that for this group of
to see themselves as anti-Platonist and anti- continental philosophers Plato has become
Plato (failing, as Nietzsche and Heidegger more of a ‘contemporary’ though still not ‘up
sometimes did before them, to make a dis- to date’. For, continental philosophers today
tinction here; q.v. Anti-Platonism). The believe they can critique the tradition, and
best known and most influential of these is therefore everything that has come to be ‘up
Jacques Derrida (1930–2004), who sees in to date’ on the basis of this tradition, with
Plato a representative of logocentrism and Plato rather than against him.
the metaphysics of presence, though his
nuanced readings of Plato, like Heidegger’s
before him, also uncover in the texts elements
at odds with this position (Derrida 1983). STRAUSSIAN READINGS OF PLATO
On the other hand, some of Heidegger’s
own students, for example, Leo Strauss Catherine Zuckert
(2003; q.v. Straussian readings) and H. G. Leo Strauss (1899–1973) developed a dis-
Gadamer (1983, 1991), were inspired by him tinctive way of reading Plato after study-
to pursue a much more sympathetic reading ing the Islamic philosopher Al-farabi’s
and positive appropriation of Plato, seeing account of The Philosophy of Plato (Mahdi
in Plato not a representative or father of the 1962:53–67). He described his way of read-
dominant philosophical tradition, but rather ing and the reasons for it at the beginning of
an alternative to it, a trace of something left his essay ‘On Plato’s Republic’ in The City
behind by it. and Man (Strauss 1964:50–62).
This tendency within contemporary In his dialogues, Strauss emphasized, Plato
continental philosophy towards a more presents exclusively the speeches and deeds
sympathetic reading of Plato has grown of others. The dialogues must, therefore, be
exponentially in recent years, as evidenced, read like dramas in which one never iden-
for example, by the works of Stanley Rosen tifies the views of the author with any par-
(1999, 2008), Drew Hyland (1995, 2004), ticular character. It may be tempting to take

298

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 298 3/8/2001 5:11:59 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

Socrates as Plato’s spokesman; but Socrates that Plato thought an individual could indeed
is not the only philosopher who appears in be just; that individual would be a philoso-
the dialogues, and Socrates is explicitly said pher who seeks the truth above and beyond
to be ironic. Socrates did not write, moreo- any other good. A city could not and never
ver, but his student Plato obviously did. Plato would be just, therefore, if it were not ruled
had to be aware of the essential defect of by a philosopher. However, precisely because
writing that Socrates stresses at the end of a philosopher seeks the truth rather than rec-
the Phaedrus – that writings say the same ognition or wealth, he will never want to rule
thing to all people. Plato’s dialogues thus and other people neither can and nor will try
show Socrates saying different things to dif- to force him to do so (Strauss 1964:112–38).
ferent people. Without philosophers to rule on the basis of
The different teachings presented in the knowledge, political associations will always
different dialogues do not merely reflect the be based on opinion. Indeed, they need to
different characters of the participants in formulate and enforce authoritative views
the conversation, however, nor are they sim- to hold them together. The best form of such
ply matters of rhetoric or persuasion. ‘Plato’s authoritative opinions is the kind of rational
work consists of many dialogues because it religion or ‘political theology’ put forward in
imitates the manyness, the variety, the het- Plato’s Laws (Strauss 1989).
erogeneity of being . . . There are many dia- Applying Strauss’ dramatic way of reading
logues because the whole consists of many the dialogues, his students and their many
parts’. Unlike numerical units, however, the students have emphasized a variety of dif-
parts cannot simply be added up to consti- ferent, though related themes. Allan Bloom
tute the whole. ‘Each dialogue . . . reveals the (1968:307–436, 1993) and his students
truth about that part. But the truth about a (Bruell 1999; Ludwig 2002; Pangle 1980;
part is a partial truth, a half-truth’ (Strauss and Bruell’s student, Stauffer 2001, 2006)
1964:61–2). In order to see the way in which show the way in which Socrates appeals
the truth presented in each dialogue is only to an erotic desire for justice in his young,
partial, readers have to pay particular atten- politically ambitious interlocutors, which he
tion to the dramatic elements. ‘The principle then moderates with a philosophical educa-
guiding the specific abstraction which char- tion. Seth Benardete (2000) and his students
acterizes [a] dialogue . . . is revealed primarily (Burger 1984 and Davis 2006) bring out the
by the setting . . . : its time, place, characters, way in which the action of a dialogue under-
and action’ (Strauss 1989:155). The setting is mines its apparent surface teaching or ‘argu-
what gives rise to and limits, that is, literally ment’. In the case of the R., for example,
defines, the conversation depicted. The task Benardete emphasizes the difference between
confronting the reader of a Platonic dialogue the ‘dialogic community’ Socrates forms with
is thus to see the way in which the drama, his interlocutors and the thumotically ordered
that is, the setting, characters and action, politeia they found in speech (Benardete
shape or distort the argument. Plato does not 1989). Although Plato shows that the world
tell us what he thinks; he shows us by pre- is not completely intelligible, Joseph Cropsey
senting the speeches and deeds of others. (1995) and his students (Nichols 1987, 2009;
Reading the Republic in light of the action Stern 1993, 2008; Zuckert 2009) argue, he
as well as the argument, Strauss concluded nevertheless shows in Socrates how a human

299

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 299 3/8/2001 5:11:59 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

being can not only live a fully satisfying life theory he mentions has been associated fur-
but also care for friends. Writing as profes- ther with the idea of a Platonic ‘Esotericism’
sional ‘philosophers’ rather than as political (q.v.), which will then have conditioned the
scientists or classicists, Stanley Rosen (1983, doctrines left unwritten. Aristoxenus reports
1986) and his students (Griswold 1986, a comment of Aristotle regarding a lecture
1998; Howland 1993, 1998; Hyland 1995, Plato gave publically on the good (on which,
2004; Roochnik 1998) have insisted on the see Gaiser 1980), and the Greek Aristotelian
advantages of dramatic readings of Plato in commentators, with other later writers,
opposition to deconstructive or purely analyt- speak in expansive terms of Plato’s unwrit-
ical approaches. In his last book-length inter- ten associations or lectures, of which writ-
pretation of Plato’s ‘Republic’, Rosen (2005) ten accounts were worked up by his pupils,
nevertheless explicitly breaks with Strauss including Aristotle. But sceptical arguments
with regard to the conclusion, although not have been vigorously urged against giving this
the mode of his reading. Although Rosen amplified tradition any credence, or even tak-
agrees that the R. reveals the insoluble prob- ing what Aristotle himself says at face value
lem of politics rather than its solution, he (Shorey 1903:82–5, anticipating Cherniss
contends that the philosopher wants to rule, 1944). Whence Aristotle has the materials for
but learns that he cannot. his account of a Platonic teaching on princi-
ples thus remains a real question. However
this may stand, his technique of referring to
the two basic principles with which he cred-
PLATO’S ‘UNWRITTEN DOCTRINES’ its Plato falls into two main kinds: the first
is regularly called ‘the one’, but in contexts
Hayden W. Ausland informed by physical conceptions, he pairs
The postulate of a body of unwritten doc- this with ‘the great and the small’, while in
trines of Plato originates in an enigmatically those focusing on mathematical conceptions,
unique mention in Aristotle, where he says he tends to substitute ‘the indefinite dyad’
that Plato identified ‘matter’ with ‘space’ (for a catalogue of these with other vari-
in the Timaeus but with ‘the great and the ants, see Ross 1924:lvii–lix). In both kinds of
small’ in ‘what are called the unwritten opin- context, however, Aristotle speaks further of
ions’ (Physics 209b11–17; for the transla- Plato’s having posited mathematical things
tion of ‘what are called’ rather than a still intermediate between ideas and sensibles, as
usual ‘so-called’, cf. Szlezák 1999). ‘The great well as having somehow identified the ideas
and the small’ is one of several designations themselves with numbers. (For translations
Aristotle employs in criticizing Plato in con- of the key Aristotelian passages as supported
texts where he speaks in his own idiom of by later writer’s contributions, see Appendix
certain basic ‘principles’ (or ‘elements’) Plato 1 in Findlay 1974.)
espoused in some way continuous with the Confronted with this evidence, modern
‘ideas’. In the wake of a later debate on the scholars have pursued two general paths.
status of universals, the idealism with which Some – and this originally with a view to dis-
Aristotle credits Plato seems easier to locate pelling any vestiges of the older attribution
in the dialogues than the Platonic principles of a mysterious esotericism to Plato – have
of which Aristotle speaks, so that the later undertaken to reconstruct a unified Platonic

300

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 300 3/8/2001 5:11:59 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

doctrine on the basis of Aristotle’s statements some intellectual experimentation late in


per se (so Trendelenburg 1826; cf. Gentile life (Thesleff 1999:91–107). And he will
1930 and Robin 1908). Others have sought doubtless have intended to spur his read-
to explain a variety of tantalizing passages ers’ autonomous philosophical impulses. But
in the dialogues as confirming a more cred- when an interpretive method – even with
itable esotericism once these are fleshed out due acknowledgement for varying degrees of
with the doctrinal content of what is denomi- speculative supplement – issues in the chari-
nated its complementary, ‘indirect tradition’ table allowance that further inferences from
(cf. Tübingen Approach and Merlan 1953). what is actually said in the dialogues may be
Special examinations of mathematical ‘inter- present in these without Plato having fully
mediates’ (Annas 1975; Wedberg 1955) and appreciated the fact (Miller 1995b), we may
‘idea-numbers’ (Dumoncel 1992; Scolnicov see exemplified the very Aristotelian method
1971) have tended to follow suit, either conditioning the historical-philosophical
eking out the evidence with Aristotelianizing dimension of the problem in the first place
or modernizing mathematico-metaphysical (Cherniss 1945).
speculation to yield a coherent theory of While scholarly agreement on the question
some kind (e.g. Cleary 2003, 2004; Taylor of Aristotle’s doxographical reliability will
1926–27), or searching for some way to likely remain elusive (for the fundamental dif-
integrate what Aristotle and later authors ference clearly depicted, cf. Shorey 1924 with
tell us with the idealism held to be present Taylor 1926), his critical remarks on Plato’s
in works like the Republic (Miller 2007), distinctions between radically different kinds
or with a supposedly less idealistic, ‘later’ of number (Metaphysics 13.6–8 passim;
phase of Platonic thought reflected in the cf. 1.6, 987b14–18 and 14.3, 1090b32–6)
Theaetetus-Sophist-Statesman trilogy, the Ti. suggest a fuller understanding of important
and the Philebus (see Sayre 1983 and Stenzel limits Plato may have placed on the powers
1924; cf. Miller 2003). The second general of rational expression as such (see Hopkins
approach falls subject to criticism for hold- 2009 on Klein 1934–36 and 1964; contra
ing to be present in Plato’s writings doc- Gadamer 1968).
trines ex hypothesi left unwritten by him (see
Cherniss 1945); from a less rigidly doctrinal
perspective, however, it usefully explores the
senses in which views conceivably held by ESOTERICISM
Plato may be meaningfully held to be present
in the dialogues at all (Miller 1995a). Hayden W. Ausland
Readings of either general kind have per- Reference to esoteric philosophical teach-
haps predictably yielded a wide variety of ing originates in antiquity, where it can sug-
hypotheses regarding Plato’s views or liter- gest a deliberate limitation on one’s outward
ary meaning, raising a question whether discourse, like that observed by the initiates
they may be anything more than occasions of various mystery cults or within certain
for supplanting the gaps in our evidence cults of personality. A prominent case of
with one’s own favoured mathematical the last is the reserve practised in the school
and metaphysical views – whether ancient of Pythagoras, whose initially exclusive
or modern. Plato may have engaged in mathematical speculation appears to have

301

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 301 3/8/2001 5:11:59 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

influenced Plato to some extent, according to for a now primarily American audience.
Aristotle even inspiring his metaphysical ide- Meanwhile, back in Germany, an alterna-
alism (Metaphysics 1.6). It may be doubted tive esoteric approach began to read the dia-
whether Aristotle’s own references to ‘exo- logues in the light of the foundational role it
teric discourses’ in his ethical works (Bonitz, accorded Plato in a European metaphysical
Ind. Arist. 104b44–5a48) are to be taken as tradition (Gaiser 1963; Krämer 1959). As a
complementary with such a practise, but at result, there came to exist side-by-side two
least subsequent ‘neopythagorean’ specula- interpretations of Plato both denominated
tion credited Platonism with a quasimysteri- ‘esoteric’, but of decidedly different inspira-
ous appreciation of such reserve, tracing this tions and orientations (Ausland 2002).
to Plato himself. Characters in the dialogues The esotericism integral to Straussian
will on occasion speak of such reserve as readings of Plato (q.v.) takes as its model a
becoming a thinker (e.g. Theaetetus 152c) or prudential hermeneutics acknowledging sev-
of themselves for various reasons having to eral levels of meaning, as developed in medi-
hold back something they might otherwise eval Jewish and Arabic philosophy for the
wish to say (e.g. Republic 506d–e), but any sake of pursuing speculation within a society
straightforward inferences from such literary governed by religious law (Strauss 1945), for
passages invite controversy. Indeed, in key which the analogue in Plato’s time will have
respects, the modern historical assessment of been the Athenian political conditions under
Plato’s philosophy is founded on a flat rejec- which the trial and execution of Socrates
tion of the notion of a Platonic esotericism of proved possible. Strauss revives an earlier
any such kind (Hegel 1840–43; cf. Tigerstedt understanding generally forgotten since the
1974). Yet it has from the outset retained at birth of nineteenth-century Platonic scholar-
least a latent strain of appreciation for the ship (q.v.), by acknowledging the real pros-
delicacy of the question (Schleiermacher pect of political persecution as a permanently
1804; cf. Strauss 1986). inescapable condition of the practise and
Pragmatic conditions of the twentieth writing, of philosophy. Where he avoided con-
century brought the question closer to the fronting metaphysical questions posed by the
surface. Paul Friedländer’s post World War I ideas, esotericism of the Tübingen approach
attentions to the existential dimensions (q.v.) postulates a founding role for Plato in
of the dialogues (Friedländer 1921, 1928, a European tradition of ‘Geistesmetaphysik’
1930) set the stage for some European schol- (Krämer 1964, 1990, on which see Sayre
ars working under the adverse political con- 1993) and so more broadly as a key player
ditions of the 1930s to consider whether in an ideal ‘History of Philosophy’ as devel-
the dramatic form of Plato’s writings might oped by Hegel (1840–43). Both approaches
well be owing to prudential considerations have prompted tangential efforts (e.g. Rosen
(Strauss 1986 – written in 1939). In the wake 1968 and Oehler 1965, respectively) and all
of World War II, Friedländer’s own work have encountered animated criticism, but
underwent important revisions and transla- where disparagement of Strauss and the
tion into English (Friedländer 1954, 1957, Straussians has – in seeming confirmation
1960), while other expatriates (Klein 1965; of his premises – assumed a politicized form
Strauss 1964) undertook to set out a more in the sphere of public intellectual discourse
curiously literary reading of Plato’s dialogues (e.g. Burnyeat 1985), a scholarly critique has

302

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 302 3/8/2001 5:12:00 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

lain bare several problems with methodical can be characterized in the following way.
assumptions of the ‘new scientific paradigm’ As to methodology, the so-called Tübingen
claimed by the Tübingen approach (Brisson School, which is now an international move-
1990 on Richard 1986; Brisson 1995; Fritz ment represented by scholars in well over a
1966; Fronterotta 1993; cf. Fritz 1967 con- dozen countries – though largely absent from
tra Oehler 1965; Ilting 1965; Isnardi Parente and unknown in the Anglo-Saxon world – (a)
1984, 1993, 1995; Vlastos 1963). takes seriously, unlike the common practise
Although the latter arose independently, since Schleiermacher (1804), clear indica-
some affinities emerged, as it at length spread tions in the dialogues that they are not meant
beyond Tübingen (where it also evolved by their author to be autarchic, self-sufficient
somewhat) resulting in two distinguishable and comprehensive accounts of his philoso-
styles. The more dogmatic of these is vis- phy. The fact that the dialogues point beyond
ible in the form adopted by an Italian school themselves not only casually and inciden-
centred at Milan, which elaborated an eccle- tally, but systematically and consistently
siastically oriented interpretation, as a com- (Szlezák 1985, 2004), is essential for their
panion of sorts to a similarly conditioned being understood. (b) The school does not set
reading of Aristotle’s Metaphysics (Reale aside or play down the importance of Plato’s
1986 with Reale 1967; cf. Rizzerio 1993). criticism of writing nor does it try to con-
Tübingen proper has meanwhile pursued vert its meaning into a recommendation of a
a path more compatible – but thereby also particular form of writing, viz. the dialogue
more competitive – with Strauss’ understand- form. (c) Its adherents are not convinced that
ing, by employing a rather greater sensitiv- the Seventh Letter was written by somebody
ity to the dialogues’ literary and dramatic other than Plato, pending discovery of the
nature (Szlezák 1985, 1993; with Krämer long sought proof of its inauthenticity. But
1988). Especially in the terms of the math- it is essential to note that the Tübingen posi-
ematical side of Plato’s thought, some unduly tion in no way depends on the assumption of
neglected writings by J. Klein (1965, 1966, the authenticity of the Letter. (d) Likewise, its
1977) have anticipated this approximation, adherents reject as methodologically ill-con-
but there remains much in this area still to ceived and wholly unconvincing the attempt
be done (cf. Unwritten Doctrines). The special (undertaken by Cherniss 1944) to discard the
approach of W. Wieland (1982, 1987) is anal- testimony of Aristotle and other sources con-
ogously intermediate, acknowledging a liter- cerning Plato’s agrapha dogmata or ‘unwrit-
ary reserve explained as conditioned by limits ten doctrines’ (q.v.). There are two sources
to communicability in propositional form. of our knowledge of Plato’s philosophy: the
direct tradition, that is, the dialogues, and
the indirect tradition, that is, the Testimonia
Platonica (as collected by Gaiser 1963 and
THE TÜBINGEN APPROACH Richard 1986). Neither of the two branches
of the transmission should be ignored.
Thomas Alexander Szlezák As to the contents, the picture of Plato
The new way of understanding Plato’s phi- resulting from the Tübingen School’s use of
losophy introduced half a century ago by the above methods can be sketched as fol-
H. J. Krämer (1959) and K. Gaiser (1963) lows. (a) In his search for the first principles

303

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 303 3/8/2001 5:12:00 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

of reality, Plato integrated and developed the The first products of the progressive limita-
Heraclitean theory of flux, the Pythagorean tion of the Unlimited by the One were the
(q.v.) philosophy of number, the Orphico- (ideal) numbers. The realm of the Ideas had
Pythagorean creed of the immortality of the a hierarchical order (hinted at in Republic
soul, and the Eleatic dialectic of the One and 485b6; cf. 500c2). Between the Ideas and
the Many. (b) By giving all these approaches the sensible things, the objects of mathemat-
a new and deeper interpretation and by com- ics, ta mathêmatika, occupied an intermedi-
bining them with the Socratic care for the ate (metaxy) position. The Soul, which itself
soul he created a synthesis of the whole of stands between the Ideas, which it receives,
Greek philosophy before him which amounts and the sensible things, which it orders, is
to no less than the second foundation of phi- akin to the realm of the mathêmatika. There
losophy (after its first foundation by the pre- is a structural kinship (oikeiotês) or com-
Socratics). Therefore, it is inadequate to see munion (koinônia) between the mathemati-
Plato exclusively or mainly as a ‘Socratic’ – cal disciplines among themselves and with
he was at the same time an unwavering the structure of reality as a whole, which is
Heraclitean, a committed Pythagorean and mentioned in the dialogues (R. 537c; Laws
a daring Eleatic dialectician. (c) With Plato 967e), but not explained in detail – the exact
begins the metaphysical epoch of Western elaboration of this theory being, like the der-
philosophy (Krämer 1982) which came to ivation of all reality from the One and the
an end by the late nineteenth and the early Indefinite Dyad, a topic for the oral theory
twentieth centuries in the philosophies of of the principles expounded in what Aristotle
Nietzsche and Heidegger (q.v. Continental called Plato’s agrapha dogmata.
approaches) on the one side, and by the ana- Contrary to a widespread opinion,
lytical approach (q.v. Analytic approaches) Aristotle’s reports on Plato’s philosophy of
and pragmatism on the other. (d) The struc- principles and numbers are neither inconsist-
ture of reality arrived at by Plato’s methodo- ent nor obscure (Richard 2005; Robin 1908).
logically multiple approach is reflected in the That the Testimonia Platonica are of great
dialogues, though not in its entirety. Taking use for the interpretation of the dialogues
into account both branches of the transmis- has been shown by Gaiser (1963, 2004) and
sion, we can see that Plato opted for a twofold Reale (1984). Aristotle’s own philosophy is
procedure (which is reflected in the way up clearly influenced by the ‘unwritten’ Plato in
and the way down in the simile of the cave): his theory of aretê as mesotês (Krämer 1959)
the analysis of the phenomena is meant to and in his use of the concept of matter (Happ
lead to the recognition of the first principles 1971). Likewise, Speusippus and Xenocrates
and elements (archai and stoicheia) of real- build not only on the written dialogues of
ity, starting from which the dialectician will their common master, but also on the philos-
show in a second, synthetic move how things ophy of the agrapha dogmata. In historical
are ‘derived’ from the principles or ‘gener- perspective, Plato’s oral philosophy proves
ated’ by their interaction. As highest princi- to be the highest point of Greek specula-
ples Plato posited the One and the Indefinite tion on the ultimate principles of reality,
Duality (hen and aoristos dyas). The One both resuming earlier attempts and enrich-
he equated with the Good (q.v.), while the ing later ones. Present-day meta-axiomatic
Dyad was for him the ultimate source of evil. theory has rediscovered the importance of

304

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 304 3/8/2001 5:12:00 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

Plato’s philosophy of mathematics (Surányi in Plato there has followed a proliferation


1999). of Platonisms (cf. Academy, Neoplatonism),
It is hard for our culture of literacy to that is, a multiplicity of constructions freely
understand is Plato’s decision not to commit elaborated by opponents or supporters at a
all of his philosophy to writing. Yet the dia- given time, answering a variety of strategies.
logues show his reasons: Socrates does not The histories of Platonism and anti-Platon-
tell his view on the essence of the megiston ism are constantly interacting, so that the
mathêma, nor does he give a sketch of dia- term ‘Platonism’ tends to become more and
lectics, because the interlocutors would not more devoid of content and is commonly
be able to grasp it (R. 506e, 533a). In his used to point to some great ‘error’ – tran-
criticism of writing, Plato recommends not scendental realism, idealism, elitism or totali-
addressing ‘those who have no business with tarianism. It refers little or not at all to what
it (sc. philosophy)’ (Phaedrus 275e3, 276a7). Plato wrote, but rather to the representation
The Epistle 7 (q.v. Letters) merely confirms one has of it. Yet, if Platonism is a variable,
this attitude. Thus the Letter is not needed what consistency could conceivably be found
as an independent witness for Plato’s views in the numerous anti-Platonisms?
on the worth of writing. Conversely, the anti-
esoteric position depends on the unproved (I) CRITIQUES OF PLATONSIM FROM
assumption of its inauthenticity, since it is OUTSIDE PHILOSOPHY
very clear about the fact that Plato favoured
an esotericist (q.v. Esoterism) use of his the- It might be useful to set out a first distinc-
ory of principles (Szlezák 1985:386–405, tion. ‘Platonism’ did not mainly provide
2004:54–8). philosophers with theories to refute: from
Antiquity to the first half of the eighteenth
century, two extra-philosophical forms of
anti-Platonism developed continuously, one
ANTI-PLATONISM, FROM ANCIENT devoted to the defence of rhetoric (and its
TO MODERN modern form, literature), and the other peri-
odically reasserting the subordination of
Monique Dixsaut philosophy to the true (Christian) faith. The
Opposition to Plato’s thought, sometimes counterattack of the supporters of rhetoric
called anti-Platonism, has existed since antiq- began with Isocrates (q.v.), proceeded with
uity; but it is a more complex phenomenon Aelius Aristides (117–81 CE) and the second
than the single name would suggest. sophistic, and was born again in the seven-
Quite obviously, to be an anti-Platonist is teenth century with the ‘Moderns’ whose
to oppose Platonism. But what is less obvi- spokesman in France is Charles Perrault
ous is how it is possible to oppose a philoso- (1688). The controversy was introduced into
phy which does not offer an articulated set England by Temple’s essay ‘Of Ancient and
of principles and consequences and is fre- Modern Learning’ (1692) and Swift, in his
quently objecting against its own theses, and Battle of the Books (1704), shows Duns Scot
why should one bother to refute a philoso- and his master Aristotle concerting to turn
pher who never asserts anything in his own out Plato ‘from his antient Station among
name? But from the absence of Platonism the Divines’. But in Diderot and d’Alembert’s

305

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 305 3/8/2001 5:12:00 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

Encyclopaedia (Jaucourt 1736) the word Aristoxenus of Tarentum (fourth-century


‘Platonism’ is endowed with a purely theo- BCE) and Antigonus of Carystus (third-
logical meaning and connected with the century BCE) are also often mentioned for
theory of the three hypostases. The twelfth their anti-Platonism.
and thirteenth centuries had been punctu- While disagreeing on a definition of
ated with quarrels between Roman and philosophy which oscillated between its
Greek Fathers, Trinitarians and anti-Trini- (Socratic) figure of an ever possible ques-
tarians, ‘philosophical’ theologians and theo- tioning, and its scientific (Aristotelian) figure
logians of the true faith (von Ivánka 1964). of a knowledge of first principles and first
‘Platonism’, which had been accused of hav- causes, they were all agreed on a rejection
ing perverted Origen, blamed for the outra- of Plato’s conception of forms as separate
geous claims of philosophy as expounded substances endowed with causal power over
in Boethius’ De consolatione Philosophiae sensible particulars. The various criticisms
(524) where no mention is made of Christ first aimed by Aristotle (q.v.) and more radi-
or of the Christian religion, is found to be cally formulated by Averroes, Aquinas and
responsible for Abelard’s scandalous theses: Duns Scot have made up a ‘Platonism’ which
Plato is ‘the purveyor of every single heresy’. is but the paradigm of a realistic theory of
What is at stake under the name Platonism is universals, under its purest and most nonsen-
merely symbolic, and its ‘subtlety’ is charged sical form: ‘Phantasticus Plato’, in the words
with corrupting the ‘simplicity’ either of fine of that trueborn anti-Platonist William of
language or of the Christian faith. Ockham. This medieval form of opposi-
tion dies out with scholasticism when Plato
(II) CRITIQUES OF PLATONISM FROM is at last allowed to speak again thanks to
WITHIN PHILOSOPHY. Marsilio Ficino (1433–99). Yet, this same
realism of universals is to be found at the
While they do not vanish entirely – cf. core of the mathematical anti-Platonism of
Nietzsche (1888) on Plato’s tedious prolixity those (Russell, the later Wittgenstein, Carnap
and ‘hybrid’ style – these debates no longer or Dummet) who stress that mathematical
are in the foreground and ‘Platonism’ is no objects are constructed, not objectively given,
more the word used by outside opponents and are conventions ruled by logical syntaxes
to expose the hubris of philosophy from the (Balaguer 1998).
moment Kant makes it a well defined theo- In the Kantian ‘History of pure reason’
retical object. The first philosophical objec- (in Kant 1787), Plato is also a prototype,
tions levelled at Plato came from the Socratic not of a ‘realist’ but of the ‘intellectualist’
Antisthenes, from some Cynics – mainly philosopher fought by Epicurus’ sensualism,
Diogenes: from the group of anecdotes and of the ‘noologist’ philosopher criticized
attributed to him in D. L. 4 there emerges by Aristotle’s empiricism. Kant’s ‘battlefield’
a Plato who is his antitype, a paradigmatic recalls the Battle of Giants between the Sons
metaphysician and plutocrat – and from of the Earth and the Friends of Ideas (Sph.
the sceptics, Timon of Phlius (c. 320–230 246aff), with this difference, that Plato, the
BCE) among others; but for Aristotle, on creator of a now dead and buried specula-
the contrary, Plato was too Socratic because tive metaphysic, is supposed to belong to the
of his immoderate trust in dialectical logos. latter. This paves the way for accusations

306

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 306 3/8/2001 5:12:00 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

of despising the body and the earth or dis- that same Sph. to which the ‘Conclusion’ of
carding the pleasures of the flesh, but ear- L’Etre et le Néant acknowledges its debt.
lier representations went directly counter And while Levinas (1972) feels the demand
to that ascetic pre-Christian figure: accord- for a fundamental meaning to be kept open
ing to Athenaeus, Plato keeps writing erotic beyond the world of established significa-
speeches, while George of Trebizond (1469) tions closed in by Plato, he finds it possible
judges Epicurus to be a second Plato who, to ‘return to Plato in a new way’. But it is
like the first one, decrees voluptas to be the certain that Plato is always accused of miss-
supreme good. What becomes at last patent ing (or ignoring) something, and that that
with Kant is that, if their answers may be ‘something’ is in the accuser’s mind reality
contradictory, the anti-Platonists share their itself. For Nietzsche, Bergson or Deleuze, it
problems and postulates with the Platonists; is the creative power of life; for those who
consequently, one must become aware that are called ‘existentialists’ it is the movement
being an anti-Platonist is just another way of negativity which preserves existence from
of being a Platonist. The most evident sign being submitted to essence (Sartre), or the
of this new awareness is a semantic muta- horizon which enables being and truth to
tion: from then on no philosopher attacks or unveil themselves while remaining veiled
refutes Platonism, he ‘reverses’ or ‘inverts’, (Heidegger). The charge is that Platonism not
‘surpasses’ or ‘overcomes’ it. The two dif- only ignores reality, it creates fictions more
ferent translations of the title of Carnap’s fictive than any of those it sought to expose.
paper, ‘Überwindung der Metaphysik durch It must therefore not be philosophically criti-
logische Analyse der Sprache’ (1932), plainly cized but discarded as an ideology, since it
show that what is meant by Überwindung is, if one may say so, ideology in itself. It is
is far from clear: is it ‘elimination’ or then easy to understand how Marxism man-
‘overcoming’? ages to find in the dualism of the two worlds,
one of which is a world of ideas governed by
(III) APPEALS TO PLATO AGAINST PLATONISM unchanging relations, an ‘ideological’ trans-
position of the ‘real’ division between the
Every attempt to go beyond Platonism seems working class and the idle one.
however to find its best ally in Plato (or his
Socrates). When Kant (1796; cf. Derrida (IV) CRITIQUES OF PLATO EMPHASIZING
1983) makes Platonism responsible for any POLITICS
form of mystical exaltation in philosophy,
he adds: ‘Platonism, not Plato’. Though the This brings us to the point which has always
Platonic ‘non-problem’ of the existence of excited the most brutal reaction, not against
Ideas is to Schlick (1937) the very example Platonism, but against Plato himself. The
of a confusion between question of mean- epithet used by Epicurus, dionysokolax, is
ing and question of fact, Socrates is said to aimed at the comedy under which Plato con-
be ‘the true father of our philosophy’ (logical ceals his desire for power (Nietzsche 1886) –
positivism). Heidegger calls upon Sartre to to put it more bluntly with Crossman or
come and ‘philosophize with him far beyond Popper, whoever flatters Denys may one day
all Platonism’, and chooses a sentence from flatter Hitler. Perrault (1688:58) draws on
the Sophist as an epigraph to Sein und Zeit, the diatribe by Athenaeus (Deipnosophists

307

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 307 3/8/2001 5:12:00 PM


LATER RECEPTION, INTERPRETATION AND INFLUENCE

XI.505–8) when he writes: ‘the nature felt as an act of violence: Plato’s negation of
over brimming with pride to be seen in any kind of equality among men, whether
Socrates [. . .] is quite insufferable to me’, it be natural or social, religiously revealed
and Crossman (1945:190) echoes George of or politically instituted, guaranteed by law
Trebizond, who ‘always detested Plato’: ‘the or acquired by means of a method. Plato
more I read the Republic, the more I hate it’; is surely not the only enemy of democracy
as for the idea of the philosopher-king, it is to among philosophers, but he is the only one
Popper (1945:I.137) ‘a monument of human to base on intelligence a hierarchical organi-
smallness’, and he contrasts ‘Socrates’ sim- zation of State and City, a fairly attractive
ple humanity with the hatred Plato is filled and dangerous proposition. The intensity
with’. It is not a matter of pleading for the of the repulsion is equal to the power of
democratic interplay of opinions and inter- his magic – ‘The Spell of Plato’ – as if Plato
ests, but of answering violently to what is could only be either divine or diabolical.

308

9780826435354_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 308 3/8/2001 5:12:00 PM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Adam, James. 1902. The Republic of Plato. Anderson, D. E. 1993. The Masks of
Cambridge. Dionysos: A Commentary on Plato’s
Adamson, Peter. 2002. The Arabic Plotinus. Symposium. Albany.
London. Annas, Julia. 1974. ‘On the
Albert, Karl. 1989. Über Platons Begriff der “Intermediates,”’Archiv für Geschichte
Philosophie. Sankt Augustin. der Philosophie. 57, 146–65.
Algra, Keimpe. 1995. Concepts of Space in — 1976. ‘Plato’s Republic and Feminism’,
Greek Thought. Leiden. Philosophy. 51, 307–21.
Allen, Michael. 1984. The Platonism of — 1977. ‘Plato and Aristotle on friendship
Marsilio Ficino. Berkeley and London. and altruism’, Mind. 86, 532–54.
Allen, R. E. (ed.). 1965a. Studies in Plato’s — 1981. An Introduction to Plato’s
Metaphysics. London and New York. Republic. Oxford.
— 1965b. ‘Participation and Predication in — 1985. ‘Self-Knowledge in Early
Plato’s Middle Dialogues’, in R. E. Allen Plato’, in D. J. O’Meara (ed.), Platonic
(ed.), 1965, pp. 43–60. Investigations. Washington, pp. 111–38.
— 1970. The Euthyphro and Plato’s Earlier — 1999. Platonic Ethics: Old and New.
Theory of Forms. London. Ithaca.
— 1971. ‘Plato’s Earlier Theory of Forms’, Annas, Julia and Christopher Rowe (eds).
in Gregory Vlastos (ed.), The Philosophy 2002a. New Perspectives on Plato,
of Socrates. Plato II: A Collection of Modern and Ancient. Harvard and
Critical Essays. Ethics, Politics and Cambridge.
Philosophy of Art and Religion. Garden — 2002b. ‘What are Plato’s Middle
City, pp. 319–34. Dialogues in the Middle of?’ in Julia
Alline, Henri. 1915. Histoire du Texte de Annas and Christopher Rowe (eds),
Platon. Paris. 2002b, pp. 1–25.
Anagnostopoulos, Mariana. 2006. ‘The Apelt, Otto. 1919. Platons Dialog
Divided Soul and the Desire for Good in ‘Parmenides’. Leipzig.
Plato’s Republic’, in Gerasimos Santas Ardley, Gavin. 1967. ‘The Role of Play in
(ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Plato’s the Philosophy of Plato’, Philosophy. 42,
Republic. Oxford, pp. 166–88. 226–44.

309

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 309 3/16/2012 9:47:58 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Arieti, James. 1993. ‘Plato’s Philosophical Baltes, Matthias. 1997. ‘Is the Idea of the
Antiope: the Gorgias’, in Gerald A. Press Good in Plato’s Republic Beyond Being?’
(ed.), Plato’s Dialogues: New Studies and in M. Yoal (ed.), Studies in Plato and the
Interpretations. Lanham. Platonic Tradition, Essays Presented to J.
Armstrong, David. 1973. Belief, Truth, and Whittaker. Hampshire, pp. 3–23.
Knowledge. Cambridge. — 1999. ‘Is the Idea of the Good in Plato’s
Arnim, Hans von. 1914. ‘Thrasymachos Republic beyond being?’ in Matthias
über die Gerechtigkeit’, in Hans von Baltes (ed.), Dianoémata. Kleine Schriften
Arnim (ed.), Platons Jugenddialoge zu Platon und zu Platonismus. Stuttgart
und die Entstehungszeit des Phaidros. and Leipzig, pp. 351–71.
Leipzig. Baltzly, Dirk. 1992. ‘Plato and the New
Aronadio, Francesco. 2008. Dialoghi spuri Rhapsody’, Ancient Philosophy. 12, 29–52.
di Platone. Torino. — 1996. ‘To an Unhypothetical First
Atwill, Janet. 2009. Rhetoric Reclaimed. Principle’, History of Philosophy
Ithaca. Quarterly. 13, 149–65.
Ausland, Hayden W. 2000. ‘The — 1999. ‘Aristotle and Platonic Dialectic
Euthydemus and the Dating of Plato’s in Metaphysics gamma 4’, Apeiron. 32,
Dialogues’, in Thomas M. Robinson and 171–202.
Luc Brisson (eds), On Plato: Euthydemus, Barker, Andrew. 1982. ‘Aristides
Lysis, Charmides. Selected Papers from Quintilianus and Constructions in Early
the Fifth Symposium Platonicum. Sankt Music Theory’, Classical Quarterly. 32,
Augustin, pp. 20–2. 184–97.
— 2002. ‘Plato’s Ideal Cosmopolitanism’, in — 1989. Greek Musical Writings.
K. J. Boudouris (ed.), Fourteenth Annual Cambridge.
Conference on Greek Philosophy. ‘Polis — 2000. ‘Timaeus on Music and the Liver’,
and Cosmopolis: Problems of a Global in M. R. Wright (ed.), Reason and
Era II’. Athens, pp. 33–50. Necessity: Essays on Plato’s Timaeus.
— 2005. ‘Socrates’ Definitional Inquiries London, pp. 85–99.
and the History of Philosophy’, in — 2007. The Science of Harmonics in
Rachana Kamtekar and Sara Ahbel- Ancient Greece. Cambridge.
Rappe (eds), The Backwell Companion to Barnes, Jonathan. 1979. The Presocratic
Socrates. Oxford, pp. 493–510. Philosophers, Vol. 1: Thales to Zeno.
— 2008. ‘Proëmial Prolepsis in Plato’s London.
Politeia’, Symbolae Osloenses. 83, 18–44. Barney, Rachel. 2001. Names and Nature in
Bailey, D. T. 2006. ‘Plato and Aristotle on Plato’s Cratylus. New York and London.
the Unhypothetical’, Oxford Studies in — 2010. ‘Notes on Plato on the Kalon and the
AncientPhilosophy. 30, 101–26. Good’, Classical Philology. 105, 363–77.
Bailly, Jacques. 2004. The Socratic Theages: Baxter, Timothy M. S. 1992. The Cratylus:
Introduction, English Translation, Greek Plato’s Critique of Naming. Leiden.
Text and Commentary. Hildesheim, Beiser, Frederick. 2002. German Idealism.
Zürich and New York. Cambridge.
Balaguer, Mark. 1998. Platonism and Anti- — 2003. The Romantic Imperative.
platonism in Mathematics. Oxford. Cambridge.

310

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 310 3/16/2012 9:47:58 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Belfiore, Elizabeth. 1983. ‘Plato’s Greatest Beversluis, John. 1993. ‘Vlastos’s Quest
Accusation against Poetry’, Canadian for the Historical Socrates’, Ancient
Journal of Philosophy. 9, 39–62. Philosophy. 13, 293–312.
— Forthcoming. ‘Poets at the Symposium’, Blank, David. 1993a. ‘The Arousal of
in Pierre Destrée and Fritz-Gregor Emotions in Plato’s Dialogues’, Classical
Herrmann (eds), Plato and the Poets. Quarterly. 43, 428–39.
Bélis, Annie. 2008. ‘Un Fragment de — 1993b. ‘Review article on: T. A. Szlezák,
Traité Musical sur Papyrus (P. Tebt. III, Platon und die Schriftlichkeit der
694)’, in J.-L. Périllié (ed.), Platon et les Philosophy, and M. Erler, Der Sinn
Pythagoriciens, Hierarchie des Savoirs der Aporien in den Dialogen Platons’,
et des Pratiques: Cahiers de Philosophie Ancient Philosophy. 13, 414–26.
Ancienne. 20, 225–36. Bloedow, Edmund F. 1975. ‘Aspasia and the
Benardete, Seth. 1989. Socrates’ Second “Mystery” of the Menexenos’, Wiener
Sailing: On Plato’s ‘Republic’. Chicago. Studien. 88, 32–48.
— 1991. The Rhetoric of Morality and Blondell, Ruby. 2002. The Play of Character
Philosophy: Plato’s ‘Gorgias’ and in Plato’s Dialogues. Cambridge.
‘Phaedrus’. Chicago and London. Bloom, Allan (trans.). 1968. The Republic of
— 2000. The Argument of the Action: Plato. New York.
Essays on Greek Poetry and Philosophy. — 1987. ‘An Interpretation of Plato’s Ion’,
Chicago. in Thomas L. Pangle (ed.), The Roots
Benitez, Eugenio. 2000. ‘Cowardice, Moral of Political Philosophy: Ten Forgotten
Philosophy, and Saying What You Think’, Socratic Dialogues. Ithaca, pp. 371–95.
in Gerald A. Press (ed.), Who Speaks for — 1991. ‘Interpretive Essay’, in The Republic
Plato? Savage, pp. 83–98. of Plato. New York, pp. 305–436.
— 2009. ‘Plato’s Music’, Special Issue of — 1993. Love and Friendship. New York.
Literature and Aesthetics. 19. Bluck, R. S. 1956. ‘Logos and Forms in
Benoit, William L. 1991. ‘Isocrates and Plato Plato’, Mind. 65, 522–9.
on Rhetoric and Rhetorical Education’, — 1961. Plato’s Meno. Cambridge.
Rhetoric Society Quarterly. 21, 60–71. — 1963. ‘Knowledge by Acquaintance in
Benso, Silvia and Brian Schroeder (eds). Plato’s Theaetetus’, Mind. 72, 259–63.
2008. Levinas and the Ancients. — 1965. Plato’s Meno. Cambridge.
Indianapolis. Bluestone, N. H. 1987. Women and the
Benson, Hugh H. 2000. Socratic Wisdom: Ideal Society: Plato’s Republic and
The Model of Knowledge in Plato’s Early Modern Myths of Gender. Amherst.
Dialogues. New York. Blumenthal, H. J. 1971. Plotinus’
— 2003. ‘The Method of Hypothesis in the Psychology. The Hague.
Meno’, Proceedings of the Boston Area Blumenthal, H. J. and A. C. Lloyd (eds).
Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy. 18, 1982. Soul and the Structure of Being in
95–126. Late Neoplatonism. Liverpool.
— 2006. A Companion to Plato. Oxford. Bobonich, Christopher. 1994. ‘Akrasia and
Betegh, G. 2004. The Derveni Papyrus, Agency in Plato’s Laws and Republic’,
Cosmology, Theology and Interpretation. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie.
Cambridge. 76, 3–36.

311

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 311 3/16/2012 9:47:58 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

— 2002. Plato’s Utopia Recast. Oxford. Cambridge Companion to Atheism.


Bolotin, David. 1979. Plato’s Dialogue Cambridge, pp. 149–65.
on Friendship: An Interpretation of the Brisson, Luc. 1987. Platon: Lettres. Paris.
Lysis. Ithaca. Brisson, Luc and Gerard Naddaf. 1994.
Bolton, Robert. 1975. ‘Plato’s Distinction Le Même et l’Autre dans la structure
between Being and Becoming’, Review of ontologique du Timée de Platon. Sankt
Metaphysics. 29, 66–95. Augustin.
Bonazzi, Mauro. 2008. ‘Towards — 1999. Plato: The Mythmaker. Chicago
Transcendence: Philo and the Renewal and London.
of Platonism in the Early Imperial — 2004. How Philosophers Saved Myths:
Age’, in Francesca Alesse (ed.), Philo Allegorical Interpretation and Classical
of Alexandria and Post Aristotelian Mythology. Chicago.
Philosophy. Leiden, pp. 233–52. — 2006. ‘Agathon, Pausanias, and Diotima
Bordt, Michael. 1998. Platon: Lysis. in Plato’s Symposium. Paiderastia and
Göttingen. Philosophia’, in James H. Lesher, Debra
Bos, E. P. and P. A. Meijer (eds). 1992. On Nails and Frisbee Sheffield (eds), Plato’s
Proclus and his Influence in Medieval Symposium: Issues, interpretation and
Philosophy. Leiden, Köln and New York. reception. Washington DC, 229–51.
Brancacci, Aldo. 2005. Antisthène: Le Brown, Eric. 2000. ‘Justice and Compulsion
discours propre. Paris. for Plato’s Philosopher-Rulers’, Ancient
Brandwood, Leonard. 1976. A Word Index Philosophy. 20, 1–17.
to Plato. ‘Index of Quotations’. Leeds, — 2004. ‘Minding the Gap in Plato’s
pp. 991–1003. Republic’, Philosophical Studies. 117,
— 1990. The Chronology of Plato’s 275–302.
Dialogues. Cambridge. Brown, Lesley. 1986. ‘Being in the Sophist:
— 1992. ‘Stylometry and Chronology’, in a syntactical enquiry’, Oxford Studies in
Richard Kraut (ed.), The Cambridge Ancient Philosophy. 4, 49–70.
Companion to Plato. Cambridge, — 2008. ‘The Sophist on statements,
pp. 90–120. predication, and falsehood’, in Gail Fine
Brickhouse, Thomas C. and Nicholas D. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Plato.
Smith. 1989. The Trial of Socrates. Oxford, pp. 437–62.
Oxford and Princeton. — 2010. ‘Definition and Division in Plato’s
— 1994. Plato’s Socrates. Oxford. Sophist’, in David Charles (ed.), Definition
— 2007. ‘Socrates on Akrasia, Knowledge, in Greek Philosophy. Oxford, pp. 151–71.
and the Power of Appearance’, in Brown, Stuart. 1995. ‘Leibniz and the
Christopher Bobonich and Pierre Destrée Classical Tradition’, International Journal
(eds), Akrasia in Greek Philosophy. of the Classical Tradition. 2, 68–89.
Leiden, pp. 1–17. — 1997. ‘Platonic Idealism in Modern
— 2009. ‘The Socratic Paradoxes’, in Hugh Philosophy from Malebranche to
Benson (ed.), A Companion to Plato. Berkeley’, in G. A. J. Rogers, J. M.
Oxford, pp. 263–77. Vienne, and Y. C. Zarka (eds), Cambridge
Brink, David. 2007. ‘The Autonomy Platonists in Philosophical Context.
of Ethics’, in M. Martin (ed.), The Dordrecht, pp. 197–214.

312

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 312 3/16/2012 9:47:58 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Bruell, Christopher. 1999. On the Socratic — 1999a. ‘Culture and Society in Plato’s
Education. Lanham. Republic’, The Tanner Lectures on
Brumbaugh, Robert S. 1961. Plato on the Human Values. 20, 217–324.
One: The hypotheses in the ‘Parmenides’. — 1999b. ‘Culture and Society in Plato’s
New Haven. Republic’, in Grethe B. Peterson (ed.),
Bruns, Ivo. 1896. Das literarische Porträt The Tanner Lectures on Human Values.
der Griechen. Berlin (repr. Darmstadt Salt Lake City, pp. 215–324.
1961). — 2000. ‘Plato on Why Mathematics is
Brunt, Peter A. 1993. Studies in Greek Good for the Soul’, in Timothy Smiley
History and Thought. Oxford. (ed), Mathematics and Necessity: Essays
Buchan, Morag. 1999. Women in Plato’s in the History of Philosophy. Oxford,
Political Theory. London and New York. pp. 1–81.
Burger, Ronna L. 1980. Plato’s ‘Phaedrus’: A — 2005. ‘ΕΙΚΩΣ ΜΥΘΟΣ’, Rhizai. 2, 143–66.
Defense of a Philosophic Art of Writing. Bury, R. G. (trans.). 1942. Plato. Laws.
Tuscaloosa. Harvard.
— 1984. The Phaedo: A Platonic Labyrinth. Byrd, Miriam. 2007. ‘Dialectic and Plato’s
New Haven. Method of Hypothesis’, Apeiron. 40,
Burgess, J. P. 2009. Philosophical Logic. 141–58.
Princeton. Caizzi, Fernanda D. 1966. Antisthenis
Burkert, Walter. 1960. ‘Platon oder Fragmenta. Varese and Milano.
Protagoras? Zum Ursprung des Wortes Campbell, Lewis. 1867. The ‘Sophistes’
“Philosophie”’, Hermes. 88, 159–77. and ‘Politicus’ of Plato. Oxford (repr. in
— 1972. Lore and Science in Ancient Salem, 1988).
Pythagoreanism. Cambridge. — 1889. ‘On the Position of the Sophistes,
— 1985. Greek Religion. Cambridge. Politicus, and Philebus in the Order of
— 1987. Ancient Mystery Cults. Cambridge. the Platonic Dialogues and on Some
Burnet, John. 1916. ‘The Socratic Doctrine Characteristics of Plato’s Latest Writings’,
of the Soul’, Proceedings of the British Transactions of the Oxford Philological
Academy. 7, 235 ff. Society. 25–42 (repr. in Oxford, 1894).
— 1920. Early Greek Philosophy (3rd ed.). — 1896. ‘On the Place of the Parmenides in
London. the Chronological Order of the Platonic
— 1924. Plato’s Euthyphro, Apology of Dialogues’, Classical Review.10, 129–36.
Socrates, and Crito. Oxford. Carey, C. 2000. ‘Old Comedy and the
Burnyeat, M. F. 1970. ‘The Material and Sophists’, in D. Harvey and J. Wilkins
Sources of Plato’s Dream’, Phronesis. 15, (eds), The Rivals of Aristophanes.
101–22. London, pp. 419–38.
— 1978. ‘The Philosophical Sense of Carlini, Armando. 1962. ‘Alcuni dialoghi
Theaetetus’ Mathematics’, ISIS. 69, pseudoplatonici e l’Accademia di
489–513. Arcesilao’, Annali della Scuola Normale
— 1990. The Theaetetus of Plato. Superiore di Pisa. 31, 33–63.
Indianapolis. Carnap, Rudolf. 1932. ‘Überwindung der
— 1997. ‘The Impiety of Socrates’, Ancient Metaphysik durch logische Analyse der
Philosophy. 17, 1–12. Sprache’, Erkenntnis. 2, 219–41.

313

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 313 3/16/2012 9:47:58 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Carone, Gabriela Roxana. 1998. ‘Socrates’ Clay, Diskin. 1994. ‘The Origins of the
Human Wisdom and Sophrosune in Socratic Dialogue’, in P. A. Vander Waerdt
Charmides 164c ff.’, Ancient Philosophy. (ed.), The Socratic Movement. Ithaca and
18, 267–76. London, pp. 23–47.
Carpenter, Rhys. 1933. ‘The Antiquity of — 2005. ‘The Comic Poet of Plato’s
the Greek Alphabet’, American Journal of Symposium’, Skepsis: A Journal for
Archaeology. 37, 8–29. Philosophy and Interdisciplinary
Cassirer, Ernst. 1963. The Individual and Research. 16, 73–81.
the Cosmos in Renaissance Philosophy Cleary, John J. (ed.). 1997. The Perennial
(trans. M. Domandi). Oxford (first Tradition of Neoplatonism. Leuven.
published in German, 1927). — 2003. ‘Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato’s
Celenza, Christopher S. 2007. ‘The Revival Theory of Form Numbers’, in G.
of Platonic Philosophy’, in James Hankins Damschen, R. Enskat and A. G. Vigo
(ed.), The Cambridge Companion to (eds), Platon und Aristoteles – Sub
Renaissance Philosophy. Cambridge. Ratione Veritatis. Festschrift für Wolfgang
Chappell, Timothy. 2004. ‘Alternative Wieland zum 70 Geburtstag. Göttingen,
Interpretations of the Theaetetus as a pp. 3–30.
Whole’, Reading Plato’s Theaetetus. — 2004. ‘Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato’s
Indianapolis, pp. 16–21. First Principles’, in J.-M. Narbonne and
Cherniss, Harold F. 1936. ‘The Philosophical A. Reckermann (eds), Pensées de L’un
Economy of the Theory of Ideas’, Dans L’histoire de la Philosophie: Êtudes
American Journal of Philology. 57, en Hommage au Professeur Werner
445–56. Beierwaltes. Paris and Québec, pp. 70–97.
— 1944. Aristotle´s Criticism of Plato and Code, Alan. 1986. ‘Aristotle: Essence and
the Academy. Vol. I. Baltimore and New Accident’, in Richard E. Grandy and
York. Richard Warner (eds), Philosophical
— 1945. The Riddle of the Early Academy. Grounds of Rationality. Oxford,
Berkeley and Los Angeles. pp. 411–39.
— 1951. ‘Plato as Mathematician’, The Cohen, Hermann. 1866. ‘Die platonische
Review of Metaphysics. 4, 395–425. Ideenlehre, psychologish entwickelt’, in
— 1957. ‘The Relation of the Timaeus Zeitschrift für Sprachwissenschaft und
to Plato’s Later Dialogues’, American Völkerpsychologie IV. 403–64.
Journal of Philology. 75, 225–66 (repr. as — 1876. Kants Theorie der Erfahrung (2nd
Studies in Plato’s Metaphysics, London edn). Berlin.
1965, pp. 1–12). — 1878. Platonsideenlehre und die
Chisholm, R. M. 1996. Theory of Mathematik. Marburg.
Knowledge. New York. — 1902. Logik des reinen Denkens. Berlin.
Chung-Hwa, Chen. 1978. ‘On Plato’s Cohen, Marc. 1971. ‘The Logic of the Third
Charmides 165c4–175d’, Apeiron. 12, Man’, Philosophical Review. 80, 448–75.
13–28. Cohen, S. Marc and David Keyt. 1992.
Clavaud, Robert. 1980. Le Ménexène de ‘Analysing Plato’s Arguments: Plato
Platon et la Rhétorique de son Temps. and Platonism’, in James C. Klagge and
Paris. Nicholas D. Smith (eds), Methods of

314

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 314 3/16/2012 9:47:58 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Interpreting Plato and His Dialogues. and Religion. Vol. II. Garden City,
Oxford, pp. 173–200. pp. 126–8.
Cole, Thomas. 1991. The Origins of Creese, David. 2010. The Monochord in
Rhetoric in Ancient Greece. Baltimore. Ancient Greek Science. Cambridge.
Conacher, Desmond. 1998. Euripides and Cropsey, Joseph. 1995. Plato’s World: Man’s
the Sophists. London. Place in the Cosmos. Chicago.
Cooper, John M. 1970. ‘Plato on Sense- Crossman, Richard. 1945. Plato to-day.
Perception and Knowledge (Theaetetus London.
184–6)’, Phronesis. 15, 123–46. Crotty, Kevin. 2009. The Philosopher’s
— 1974. Plato on the Trial and Death of Song: The Poets’ Influence on Plato.
Socrates. Ithaca. Lanham.
— 1977. ‘The Psychology of Justice in Csapo, Eric. 2004. ‘The Politics of New
Plato’, American Philosophical Quarterly. Music’, in Penelope Murray and Peter
14, 151–7. Wilson (eds), Music and the Muses:
— 1984. ‘Plato’s Theory of Human The Culture of Mousike in the Classical
Motivation’, History of Philosophy Athenian City. Oxford, pp. 207–48.
Quarterly. 1, 3–21. Cummins, Joseph W. 1981. ‘Eros,
— (ed). 1997a. Plato: Complete Works. Epithumia, and Philia in Plato’, Apeiron.
Indianapolis. 15, 10–18.
— 1997b. ‘Introduction’, in John. Dahl, Norman O. 1991. ‘Plato’s
M. Cooper (ed.), 1997, pp. vii–xxvi. Defense of Justice’, Philosophy and
— 1998. ‘Socrates’, in Edward Craig (ed.), Phenomenological Research. 51, 809–34.
Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Dancy, J. and E. Sosa. 1992. A Companion
London and New York, pp. 8–19. to Epistemology. Oxford.
— 2004. ‘Two Theories of Justice’, in John Dancy, R. M. 2007. Plato’s Introduction of
M. Cooper, Knowledge, Nature, and the Forms. Cambridge.
Good: Essays on Ancient Philosophy. Darwall, S. 1992. British Moralists and the
Princeton, pp. 247–69. Internal Ought. Cambridge.
Cooper, L. 1974. Plato on the Trial and Davidson, Donald 1985. ‘Plato’s
Death of Socrates. Ithaca. Philosopher’, The London Review of
Copenhaver, Brian. 1992. Renaissance Books. 7, 15–17.
Philosophy. Cambridge. Davies, J. K. 1971. Athenian Propertied
Cornford, Francis M. 1935. Plato’s Theory Families 600–300 BC. Oxford.
of Knowledge. London. Davis, Michael. 2006. Wonderlust. South
— 1937. Plato’s Cosmology. London. Bend.
— 1939. Plato and Parmenides. London. de Romilly, Jacqueline. 1975. Magic and
— 1964. Plato’s Theory of Knowledge: Rhetoric in Ancient Greece. Cambridge.
The Theaetetus and the Sophist of Plato. De Stryker E. and S. R. Slings. 1994.
London. Plato’s Apology of Socrates: A Literary
— 1971. ‘The Doctrine of Eros in Plato’s and Philosophical Study with Running
Symposium’, in Gregory Vlastos (ed.), Commentary. Leiden and New York.
Plato: A Collection of Critical Essays: De Vries, G. J. 1949. Spel bij Plato.
Ethics, Politics, and Philosophy of Art Amsterdam.

315

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 315 3/16/2012 9:47:58 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

— 1953. ‘Isocrates’ Reaction to the — 1996. The Middle Platonists: a Study of


Phaedrus’, Mnemosyne. 6, 39–45. Platonism 80 B.C. to A.D. 220 (2nd edn).
Denyer, Nicholas (ed.). 2001. Plato: London.
Alcibiades. Cambridge. — 2003a. ‘Philip of Opus and the Theology
— 2007. ‘Sun and Line: The Role of the of Plato’s Laws’, in Samuel Scolnicov and
Good’, in G. R. F. Ferrari (ed.), The Luc Brisson (eds), Plato’s Laws: From
Cambridge Companion to Plato’s Theory into Practice. Sankt Augustin,
Republic. Cambridge, pp. 284–309. pp. 304–11.
— 2008. Plato: Protagoras. Cambridge. — 2003b. The Heirs of Plato. A Study of
Derrida, Jacques. 1972a. ‘Plato’s pharmacy’, the Old Academy (247–274 BC). Oxford.
in Disseminations. (trans. Barbara Dillon, John and Luc Brisson (eds). 2010.
Johnson). Chicago (repr. of ‘La pharmacie Plato’s Philebus: Selected Papers from the
de Platon’, Quel Tel 32–3). Eighth Symposium Platonicum. Sankt
— 1972b. ‘La pharmacie de Platon’, in Augustin.
Jacques Derrida, La dissemination. Paris, Dillon, Matthew. 2000. ‘Dialogues with
pp. 71–197. Death: The Last Days of Socrates and the
— 1983. D’un ton Apocalyptique Adopté Buddha’, Philosophy East and West. 50,
Naguère en Philosophie. Paris (English 525–58.
trans. by P. D. Fenves in Raising the Tone Dimas, P. 2003. ‘Recollecting Forms in the
of Philosophy, 1993, Baltimore). Phaedo’, Phronesis. 48, 175–214.
Desjardins, Rosemary. 1988. ‘Why Dittmar, Heinrich. 1870. Aischines von
Dialogues? Plato’s Serious Play’, in Sphettos Studien zur Literaturgeschichte
Charles L. Griswold, Jr (ed.), Platonic der Sokratiker. Berlin.
Writings, Platonic Readings. New York, Dixsaut, Monique. 1985. Le Naturel
pp. 110–25. philosophe: Essai sur les dialogues de
Destrée, Pierre and Nicholas D. Smith. 2005. Platon. Paris.
‘Socrates’ Divine Sign: Religion, Practice, — 1986. ‘Isocrate contre des sophistes sans
and Value in Socratic Philosophy’, sophistique’, in B. Cassin (ed.), Le Plaisir
Apeiron 38, xii–180. de Parler. Paris, pp. 63–85.
Devereux, Daniel. 1995. ‘Socrates’ Kantian — ed. 1993.Contre Platon 1: Le Platonisme
Conception of Virtue’, Journal of the Dévoilé. Paris.
History of Philosophy. 33, 381–408. — ed. 1995. Contre Platon 2: Renverser le
Dillon, John M. 1987. ‘Iamblichus of Platonisme. Paris.
Chalcis’, in Wolfgang Haase and Dodds, Eric R. 1928. ‘The Parmenides of
Hildegard Temporini (eds), Aufstieg und Plato and the Origin of the Neoplatonic
Niedergang der Römischen Welt, Teil “One”’, The Classical Quarterly. 22,
II, Band 36.2. Berlin and New York, 129–42.
pp. 862–909. — 1951. The Greeks and the Irrational.
— 1989. ‘Tampering with the Timaeus: Berkeley.
Ideological Emendations in Plato, with — (ed.). 1959. Plato: Gorgias. A Revised
Special Reference to the Timaeus’, Text with Introduction and Commentary.
American Journal of Philology. 110, Oxford.
50–72. — 1985. Plato Gorgias. Oxford.

316

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 316 3/16/2012 9:47:58 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Dönt, Eugen. 1963. ‘Die Stellung der — 1980. ‘Plato’s Academy and Timotheus’
Exkurse in den pseudoplatonischen Policy, 365–359 B.C.’, Chiron. 10,
Dialogen’, Wiener Studien. 76, 27–51. 111–44.
Dorandi, T. (ed). 1991. Philodemi — 1990. Историја и Политика у
Academicorum Historia, in Storia dei Платоновим “Законима.” Beograd.
Filosofi, Platone e l’Academia. Naples. Dutton, Paul. 1997. ‘Material Remains of
Döring, Klaus. 1972. Die Megariker the Study of the Timaeus’, in C. Lafleur
Kommentierte Sammlung der and J. Carrier (eds), L’enseignement de
Testimonien. Amsterdam. la Philosophie au XIII Siècle: Autour
— 2004. [Platon], Theages. Übersetzung du ‘Guide de L’étudiant’ du ms. Ripoll
und Kommentar. Göttingen. 109: Actes du Colloque International.
Döring, Klaus, Michael Erler and Stefan Turnhout, pp. 208–19.
Schorn (eds). 2005. Pseudoplatonica. — 2003. ‘Medieval Approaches to
Stuttgart. Calcidius’, in G. Reydams-Schils (ed.),
Dörrie, Heinrich. 1987. Der Platonismus in Plato’s Timaeus as Cultural Icon. Notre
der Antike. Die geschichtlichen Wurzeln Dame, pp. 183–205.
des Platonismus. Vol. 1. Stuttgart and Bad — 2005. ‘Holding Women in Common.
Cannstatt. A Particular Problem in the Twelfth
Dorter, Kenneth. 2006. The Transformation Century’, in T. Leinkaut and C. Steel.
of Plato’s Republic. Lanham. (eds), Plato’s Timaeus and the foundations
Douglas, Mary. 2007. Thinking in Circles: of cosmology in Late Antiquity, the
An Essay on Ring Composition. New Middle Ages, and Renaissance. Louvain.
Haven and London. Easterling, Patricia (ed.). 1995. Greek
Dover, Kenneth J. (ed.). 1968. Aristophanes: Literature: The Cambridge History of
The Clouds. Oxford. Classical Literature. Vol. I. Cambridge.
— (ed.). 1980. Plato: Symposium. Cambridge. Ebbesen, Sten. 1990. ‘Porphyry’s Legacy to
— 1989. Greek Homosexuality. Cambridge. Logic: A Reconstruction’, in R. Sorabji
— (ed.). 1993. Aristophanes: Frogs. Oxford. (ed.), Aristotle Transformed: the Ancient
Du Bois, Page. 1988. Sowing the Commentators and their Influence.
Body: Psychoanalysis and Ancient London, pp. 141–71.
Representations of Women. Chicago. Ebert, Theodor. 1973. ‘Plato’s Theory
Duke, E. A., W. F. Hicken, W. S. M. Nicoll, D. of Recollection Reconsidered: An
B. Robinson and J. C. G. Strachan (eds). Interpretation of Meno 80a–86c’, Man
1995. Platonis Opera I. Oxford. and World. 6, 163–80.
Dumoncel, J. C. 1992. ‘La Théorie Edelstein, Ludwig. 1945. ‘The Role of
platonicienne des Idées-Nombres’, Revue Eryximachus in Plato’s Symposium’,
de Philosophie Ancienne. 10, 3–34. Transactions of the American Philological
Düring, Ingemar. 1957. Aristotle in the Association. 76, 85–103.
Ancient Biographical Tradition. Göteborg. — 1962. ‘Platonic Anonymity’, American
Dušanić, Slobodan. 1979. ‘L’académie de Journal of Philology. 83, 1–22.
Platon et la Paix Commune de 371 av. — 1966. Plato’s Seventh Letter. Leiden.
J.-C.’, Revue des Études Grecques. 92, Edmonds, J. M. 1957. Fragments of Attic
319–47. Comedy, Vol. 1. Leiden.

317

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 317 3/16/2012 9:47:58 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Edmonds III, R. G. 2004. Myths of the Pluralism of the “Good” in the Philebus
Underworld Journey: Plato, Aristophanes, (65a1–5)’, Elenchos. 41, 51–76.
and the ‘Orphic’ Gold Tablets. Cambridge. Ferejohn, Michael. 1982. ‘The Unity of
Emilsson, Eyjólfur K. 2007. Plotinus on Virtue and the Objects of Socratic
Intellect. Oxford. Inquiry’, Journal of the History of
Endress, Gerhard. 1973. Proclus Arabus: Philosophy. 20, 1–21.
Zwanzig Abschnitte aus der Institutio — 1984. ‘Socratic Thought Experiments and
Theologica in Arabischer Übersetzung. the Unity of Virtue Paradox’, Phronesis.
Beirut. 39, 105–22
Erler, Michael. 1987. Der Sinn der Aporien Ferguson, John. 1963. ‘Sun, Line, and Cave
in den Dialogen Platons. Berlin. Again’, Philosophical Quarterly. 13,
— 2007. Ueberwegs Grundriss der 188–93.
Geschichte der Philosophie. Antike 2/2. Ferrari, G. R. F. 1987. Listening to the Cicadas:
Platon. Basel. A Study of Plato’s Phaedrus. Cambridge.
Evans, Matthew. 2008. ‘Plato on the — 1989. ‘Plato and Poetry’, in George A.
Possibility of Hedonic Mistakes’, Oxford Kennedy (ed.), Cambridge History of
Studies in Ancient Philosophy. 35, 89–124. Classical Criticism, Vol. 1. Cambridge,
Feldman, Seymour. 2003. ‘The End pp. 92–148.
and Aftereffects of Medieval Jewish — 1992. ‘Platonic love’, in Richard Kraut
Philosophy’, in D. Frank and O. Leaman (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to
(eds), Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge, pp. 248–76.
Medieval Jewish philosophy. Cambridge, — (trans.). 2000. Plato: The Republic.
pp. 414–45. Cambridge.
Ferber, Rafael. 1984. Platos Idee des Guten. — 2005. City and Soul in Plato’s Republic.
Sankt Augustin. Chicago.
— 1989. Platos Idee des Guten. Sankt — 2007. The Cambridge Companion to
Augustin. Plato’s Republic. Cambridge.
— 2002. ‘The Absolute Good and the — 2009. ‘Glaucon’s Reward, Philosophy’s
Human Goods’, in Giovanni Reale and Debt: the Myth of Er’, in C. Partenie (ed),
Samuel Scolnicov (eds), New Images of Plato’s Myths. Cambridge, pp. 116–33.
Plato: Dialogues on the Idea of the Good. Ficino, Marsilio (trans.). 1484. Plato
Sankt Augustin, pp. 187–96. [Complete Works]. No t.p. Florence.
— 2005. ‘Ist die Idee des Guten Nicht Findlay, J. N. 1974. Plato: The Written and
Transzendent Oder ist sie es Doch? Unwritten Doctrines. London.
Nochmals Platons EPEKEINA Fine, Gail. 1979. ‘Knowledge and Logos in
TES OUSIAS’, in D. Barbaric (ed.), the Theaetetus’, Philosophical Review.
Platon über das Gute und die 88, 367–97.
Gerechtigkeit / Plato on Goodness and — 1990. ‘Knowledge and Belief in Republic
Justice/Platone sul Bene e sulla Giustizia. V–VII’, in Stephen Everson (ed.),
Würzburg, pp. 149–74. Epistemology. Cambridge, pp. 65–115.
— 2010. ‘Plato’s Side Suns: Beauty, — 1992. ‘Inquiry in the Meno’, in Richard
Symmetry and Truth. Comments Kraut (ed.), The Cambridge Companion
Concerning Semantic Monism and to Plato. Cambridge, pp. 200–26.

318

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 318 3/16/2012 9:47:58 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

— 1993. On Ideas: Aristotle’s Criticism of — 1992. ‘Disintegration and Restoration:


Plato’s Theory of Forms. Oxford. Pleasure and Pain in Plato’s Philebus’,
Finley, Moses I. 1985. ‘Athenian in Richard Kraut (ed.), The Cambridge
Demagogues’, in Moses I. Finley (ed.), Companion to Plato. Cambridge,
Democracy Ancient and Modern. (2nd pp. 425–63.
edn). London, pp. 38–75 (repr. of Past — 1993. Plato Philebus. Indianapolis.
and Present 21, 3–24). — 1997. Platon Philebos: Übersetzung und
Flashar, Hellmut. 1958. Der Dialog Ion Kommentar. Göttingen.
als Zeugnis platonischer Philosophie. Frede, Michael. 1967. Praedikation und
Berlin. Existnzaussage. Gottingen.
Ford, Andrew. 2002. The Origins of — 1987. ‘The Original Notion of Cause’,
Criticism: Literary Culture and Poetic in Michael Frede, Essays in Ancient
Theory in Classical Greece. Princeton and Philosophy. Minneapolis.
Oxford. — 1988. ‘Being and Becoming in Plato’
Foucault, Michel. 1988. Technologies Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy.
of the Self: A Seminar with Michel Supplementary volume. 53–60.
Foucault, Luther H. Martin, Huck — 1992a. ‘Plato’s Sophist on False
Gutman, and Patrick Hutton (eds). Statements’, in Richard Kraut (ed.), The
Amherst. Cambridge Companion to Plato. New
Fowler, David H. 1999. The Mathematics of York, pp. 397–424.
Plato’s Academy: A New Reconstruction — 1992b. ‘Plato’s Arguments and the
(2nd edn). Oxford. Dialogue Form’, in James C. Klagge and
Fowler, H. N. (trans.). 1999. Plato: Nicholas D. Smith (eds), Methods of
Euthyphro. Apology. Crito. Phaedo. Interpreting Plato and His Dialogues.
Phaedrus. Cambridge. Oxford, pp. 201–19.
Frank, Daniel. 2009. ‘Divine Law and — 1996. ‘The Literary Form of the Sophist’,
Human Practices’, in S. Nadler and T. in C. Gill and M. M. McCabe (eds), Form
Rudavsky (eds), Cambridge History and Argument in Late Plato. Oxford,
of Jewish Philosophy. Cambridge, pp. 135–51.
pp. 790–806. Frege, G. 1879. Begriffsschrift, eine
Franklin, L. 2005. ‘Recollection and der Arithmetischen Nachgebildete
Philosophical Reflection in Plato’s Formelsprache des Reinen Denkens. Halle.
Phaedo’, Phronesis. 50, 289–314. Freydberg, Bernard. 1997. The Play of the
Frede, Dorothea. 1985. ‘Rumpelstiltskin’s Platonic Dialogues. New York.
Pleasures: True and False Pleasures in Friedländer, Paul. 1958. Plato Vol. I,
Plato’s Philebus’, Phronesis. 30, 151–80 An Introduction (trans. H. Meyerhoff).
(repr. as Fine, Gail (ed.). 1999. Plato 2 London.
Ethics, Politics, Religion, and the Soul. — 1964. Plato II, The Dialogues, First
Oxford. (pp. 345–72)). Period. Princeton (pp. 179–95).
— 1986. ‘The Impossibility of Perfection: — 1965. Plato Vol. II (trans. H. Meyerhoff).
Socrates’ Criticism of Simonides’ Poem London.
in the Protagoras’, The Review of Fussi, Alessandra. 2006. ‘“As the Wolf Loves
Metaphysics. 39, 729–53. the Lamb.” Need, Desire, Envy, and

319

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 319 3/16/2012 9:47:58 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Generosity in Plato’s Phaedrus’, Epoché. Gentile, Marino. 1930. La Dottrina Platonica


11, 51–80. Delle Idee Numeri e Aristotele. Pisa.
Gabbey, Alan. 1982. ‘Philosophia Gersh, Stephen E. 1973. Kinesis Akinetos:
cartesiana triumphata: Henry More and A Study of Spiritual Motion in the
Descartes, 1646–71’, in T. M. Lennon, Philosophy of Proclus. Leiden.
J. M. Nicholas and J. W. Davis (eds), — 1986. Middle Platonism and
Problems in Cartesianism. Kingston, Neoplatonism: The Latin tradition. Notre
pp. 171–249. Dame.
Gadamer, H.-G. 1968. ‘Plato und die Gerson, Lloyd P. 1990. God and Greek
Dichter’, in Platos Dialektische Ethik Philosophy. Studies in the Early History of
und Andere Studien zur Platonischen Natural Theology. London and New York.
Philosophie. Hamburg. — 1994. Plotinus. London.
— 1980. ‘Plato’s Unwritten Dialectic’, in P. — 2003a. Knowing Persons: A Study in
C. Smith (trans.), Dialogue and Dialectic: Plato. Oxford.
Eight Hermeneutical Studies on Plato. — 2003b. ‘Akrasia and the Divided Soul in
New Haven, pp. 124–55. Plato’s Laws’, in Samuel Scolnicov and
— 1983. Dialogue and Dialectic: Eight Luc Brisson (eds), Plato’s Laws: From
Hermeneutical Studies on Plato (trans. P. Theory into Practice (Proceedings of
C. Smith). New Haven. the VI Symposium Platonicum). Sankt
— 1991. Plato’s Dialectical Ethics: Augustin, pp. 149–54.
Phenomenological Interpretations — 2005. Aristotle and Other Platonists.
Relating to the Philebus (trans. Robert Ithaca.
M. Wallace). New Haven. Giannantoni, Gabriele. 1983–5.
Gaiser, Konrad. 1959. Protreptik und Socraticorum Reliquiae. Naples.
Paränese. Stuttgart. Gill, Christopher. 1979. ‘Plato and Politics:
—1963. Platons Ungeschriebene Lehre (1st The Critias and the Politicus’, Phronesis.
edn). Stuttgart. 24, 148–67.
— 1968. Platons Ungeschriebene Lehre — 1985. ‘Plato and the Education of
(2nd edn). Stuttgart. Character’, Archiv für Geschichte der
Gaiser, Kurt. 1980. ‘Plato’s Enigmatic Lecture Philosophie. 67, 1–26.
on the Good’, Phronesis. 25, 8–37. — 1996. Personality in Greek Epic, Tragedy
— 2004. Gesammelte Schriften. Sankt and Philosophy: The Self in Dialogue.
Augustin. Oxford.
Gall, Robert S. 2009. ‘From Daimonion — 1998. ‘Is Plato Proleptic?’ Polis. 15,
to the “Last” God: Socrates, Heidegger, 113–21.
and the God of the Thinker’, Philosophy — 2002. ‘Dialectic and the dialogue form’,
Today. 53, 265–72. in J. Annas and C. Rowe (eds), New
Gallop, David. 1984. Parmenides of Elea, Perspectives on Plato, Modern and
Fragments: A Text, with an Introduction. Ancient. Cambridge, pp. 145–71.
Toronto. Gill, Mary Louise. 1996. Plato: Parmenides.
Geach, Peter. 1966. ‘Plato’s Euthyphro: An Indianapolis.
Analysis and Commentary’, The Monist. — 2010. ‘Division and Definition in Plato’s
50, 369–82. Sophist and Statesman’, in D. Charles

320

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 320 3/16/2012 9:47:58 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

(ed.), Definition in Greek Philosophy. Gosling, J. C. B (trans.). 1975. Plato


Oxford, pp. 172–99. Philebus. Oxford.
Glaser, Konrad. 1935. ‘Gang und Ergebnis Gosling, J. C. B. and C. C. W. Taylor. 1984.
des Platonischen Lysis’, Wiener Studien. The Greeks on Pleasure. Oxford.
53, 47–67. Gould, Thomas. 1991. The Ancient
Glucker, John. 1978. Antiochus and the Quarrel Between Poetry and Philosophy.
Late Academy. Göttingen. Princeton.
Goethe, Johann Wolfgang. 1796. ‘Plato Goulet-Cazé, M.-O. 1999. ‘L’ Ordre
als Mitgenosse Einer Christlichen Succession des Socratiques’, in Marie-
Offenbarung’, in Ion. Cambridge, pp. 42–6. Odile Goulet-Cazé (ed.), Diogène Laërce
Gomez-Lobo, Alfonso. 1999. The vie et Doctrine des Philosophes Illustres.
Foundations of Socratic Ethics. Paris, pp. 161–5.
Indianapolis and Cambridge. Greene, W. C. 1944. Moira. Fate, Good, and
Gonzalez, Francisco J. 1995a. ‘Plato’s Lysis: Evil in Greek Thought. Cambridge.
An Enactment of Philosophical Kinship’, Griswold, Charles L. 1986. Self-knowledge
Ancient Philosophy. 15, 69–90. in Plato’s Phaedrus. New Haven.
— (ed). 1995b. The Third Way: New — 1988a. Platonic Writings/Platonic
Directions in Platonic Studies. Lanham. Readings. New York.
— 1998a. Dialectic and Dialogue: Plato’s — 1988b. ‘Unifying Plato’, Journal of
Practice of Philosophical Inquiry. Philosophy. 85, 550–1.
Evanston. — 1999. ‘E Pluribus Unum? On the Platonic
— 1998b. ‘Nonpropositional Knowledge in “Corpus,”’ Ancient Philosophy. 19,
Plato’, Apeiron. 31, 235–84. 361–97.
— 2000. ‘Socrates on Loving One’s Own: — 2000. ‘E Pluribus Unum? On the Platonic
A Traditional Conception Radically “Corpus:” the Discussion Continued’,
Transformed’, Classical Philology. 95, Ancient Philosophy. 20, 195–7.
379–98. — 2001. Platonic Writings/Platonic
— 2002. ‘The Socratic Elenchus as Readings. University Park (repr. of New
Constructive Protreptic’, in Gary Alan York and London, 1988).
Scott (ed.), Does Socrates have a Method? — 2002. ‘Comments on Kahn’, in Julia
University Park, pp. 161–82. Annas and Christopher Rowe (eds),
— 2003. ‘How to Read a Platonic Prologue: New Perspectives on Plato, Modern and
Lysis 203a–207d’, in Ann N. Michelini Ancient. Cambridge, pp. 129–44.
(ed.), Plato as Author. Leiden, pp. 15–44. — 2009. ‘Plato on Rhetoric and Poetry’,
Goody, Jack. 1977. The Domestication of in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford
the Savage Mind. Cambridge. Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.
Gordon, Jill. 1999. Turning Toward stanford.edu/archives/fall2009/entries/
Philosophy: Literary Device and plato-rhetoric/ (accessed 1 March 2010).
Dramatic Structure in Plato’s Dialogues. Grote, George. 1865. Plato and the Other
University Park. Companions of Socrates. London.
Gorgias, 1972. ‘Encomium of Helen’, in Grube, G. M. A. 1926. ‘On the Authenticity
Rosamond Kent Sprague (ed.), The Older of the Hippias Major’, Classical
Sophists. Columbia, pp. 50–4. Quarterly. 20, 134–48.

321

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 321 3/16/2012 9:47:58 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

— 1929. ‘The Logic and Language of the Hall, Dale. 1980. ‘Interpreting Plato’s Cave
Hippias Major’, Classical Philology. 24, as an Allegory of the Human Condition’,
369–75. Apeiron. 14, 74–84.
— (trans.). 2002. Plato: Five Dialogues. Hall, Rupert. 1990. Henry More. Magic
Indianapolis. Religion and Experiment. Oxford.
Gulley, Norman. 1954. ‘Plato’s Theory of Halliwell, Stephen. 1990. ‘Traditional
Recollection’, Classical Quarterly. 4, Greek Conceptions of Character’,
194–213. in Christopher Pelling (ed.),
— 1968. The Philosophy of Socrates. London. Characterization and Individuality in
Gutas, Dimitri. 2000. Greek Philosophers in Greek Literature. Oxford, pp. 32–59.
the Arabic Tradition. Aldershot. — 2000. ‘The Subjection of Muthos to
— 2003. ‘Suhrawardî and Greek Logos: Plato’s Criticism of the Poets’,
Philosophy’, Arabic Sciences and Classical Quarterly. 50, 94–112.
Philosophy. 13, 303–9. — 2002. The Aesthetics of Mimesis:
Guthrie, W. K. C. 1969. A History Ancient Texts and Modern Problems.
of Greek Philosophy, Vol. 2: The Princeton.
Presocratic Tradition from Parmenides to — 2007. ‘The Life-and-Death Journey of
Democritus. Cambridge. the Soul: Interpreting the Myth of Er’,
— 1971a. The Sophists. Cambridge. in G. R. F. Ferrari (ed.), The Cambridge
— 1971b. Socrates. Cambridge. Companion to Plato’s Republic.
— 1975. A History of Greek Philosophy, Cambridge, pp. 445–73.
Vol. 4: Plato, The Man and His Halperin, David M. 1990. One Hundred
Dialogues, Earlier Period. Cambridge. Years of Homosexuality: And Other
— 1978. A History of Greek Philosophy, Essays on Greek Love. New York and
Vol. 5: The Later Plato and the Academy. London.
Cambridge. — 1993. ‘Is There a History of Sexuality?’ in
Hackforth, Reginald. 1972. Plato’s Henry Abelove, Michèle Aina Barale, and
Phaedrus. Cambridge. David M. Halperin (eds), The Lesbian
Haden, James. 1983. ‘Friendship in Plato’s and Gay Studies Reader. New York,
Lysis’, Review of Metaphysics. 37, pp. 416–31.
327–56. Hankey, Wayne. 2002. ‘Aquinas and the
Hager, Fritz-Peter. 1970. Der Geist Platonists’, in S. Gersh and Maarten J. F. M.
und das Eine: Untersuchungen zum Hoenen (eds), The Platonic Tradition in the
Problem der Wesensbestimmung des Middle Ages: A Doxographic Approach.
höchsten Prinzips als Geist oder als Berlin and New York, pp. 279–324.
Eines in der griechischen Philosophie. Hankins, James. 1987. ‘Plato in the middle
Bern. ages’, in J. Strayer (ed.), Dictionary of
Halfwassen, Jens. 1993. Der Aufstieg zum the Middle Ages. Vol. IX. New York,
Einen. Untersuchungen zu Platon und pp. 694–704.
Plotin. Stuttgart. — 1990. Plato in the Italian Renaissance.
— 2004. ‘Platons Metaphysik des Einen’, Leiden.
in Marcel van Ackeren (ed.), Platon Hankinson, R. J. 1998. Cause and Explanation
Verstehen. Darmstadt, pp. 263–78. in Ancient Greek Thought. Oxford.

322

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 322 3/16/2012 9:47:58 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Hansen, Mogens H. 1991. The Athenian Henry, Madeleine Mary. 1995. Prisoner
Democracy in the Age of Demosthenes. of History: Aspasia of Miletus and her
Oxford. Biographical Tradition. Oxford.
Happ, Heinz. 1971. Hyle: Studien zum Hermann, Karl Friedrich. 1839. Geschichte
Aristotelischen Materie-begriff. Berlin. und System der Platonischen Philosophie.
Harriott, Rosemary. 1969. Poetry and Heidelberg.
Criticism Before Plato. London. Hirmer, Joseph. 1897. ‘Entstehung und
Harris, William. 1989. Ancient Literacy. Komposition der Platonischen Politeia’,
Cambridge and New York. Jahrbücher für Classische Philologie
Harte, Verity. 2002. Plato on Parts and (Supplementband). 23, 579–678.
Wholes: The Metaphysics of Structure. Hobbs, Angela. 2000. Plato and the Hero:
Oxford. Courage, Manliness and the Impersonal
— 2003–4. ‘The Philebus on Pleasure: Good. Cambridge.
The Good, the Bad and the False’, — 2006. ‘Female Imagery in Plato’,
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. in J. H. Lesher, Debra Nails and
2, 111–28. Frisbee C. C. Sheffield (eds), Plato’s
— 2008. ‘Plato’s Metaphysics’, in Gail Fine Symposium: Issues in Interpretation
(ed.), The Oxford Handbook to Plato. and Reception. Cambridge and London,
Oxford, 191–216. pp. 252–70.
Havelock, Eric. 1963. Preface to Plato. Hoenen, Maarten J. F. M. and L. Nauta
Cambridge. (eds). 1997. Boethius in the Middle Ages:
Hawtrey R. S. W. 1981. Commentary on Latin and Vernacular Traditions of the
Plato’s Euthydemus. Philadelphia. Consolatio Philosophiae. Leiden.
Heath, Malcolm. 2002. Interpreting Hoerber, R. G. 1959. ‘Plato’s Lysis’,
Classical Texts. London. Phronesis. 4, 15–28.
Heath, S. Arthur. 1921. A History of Greek Hopkins, Burt. 2009. ‘Jacob Klein on the
Mathematics. Oxford. Myth of Learning’, The St. John’s Review.
Heath, Thomas. 1981. A History of Greek 51, 5–39.
Mathematics, Vol. I: From Thales to Howland, Jacob. 1991. ‘Re-Reading Plato:
Euclid. New York. The Problem of Platonic Chronology’,
Hedley, Douglas and Sarah Hutton (eds). Phoenix. 45, 189–214.
2008. Platonism at the Origins of — 1993. The Republic: The Odyssey of
Modernity: Studies on Platonism and Philosophy. New York.
Early Modern Philosophy. Dordrecht. — 1998. The Paradox of Political
Heidegger, Martin. 1998. ‘Plato’s Doctrine Philosophy. Lanham.
of Truth’, in William McNeill (ed.), — 2007. ‘Plato’s Dionysian Music? A
Pathmarks. Cambridge, pp. 155–82 Reading of the Symposium’, Epoche. 12,
— 2003. Plato’s Sophist (trans. Richard 17–47.
Rojcewicz and André Schuwer). Howland, R. L. 1937. ‘The Attack on
Indianapolis. Isocrates in the Phaedrus’, Classical
— 2004. Essence of Truth: On Plato’s Quarterly. 31, 151–9.
Parable of the Cave and Theaetetus (trans. Huby, Pamela M. 1957. ‘The Menexenus
Ted Sadler). London. Reconsidered’, Phronesis. 2, 104–14.

323

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 323 3/16/2012 9:47:59 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Huffman, Carl A. 1993. Philolaus of Hyland, Drew. 1968. ‘Why Plato Wrote
Croton: Pythagorean and Presocratic. Dialogues’, Philosophy and Rhetoric. 1,
Cambridge. 38–50.
— 1999. ‘Limite et Illimité chez les — 1981. The Virtue of Philosophy: An
Premiers Philosophes Grecs’, in Monique Interpretation of Plato’s Charmides.
Dixsaut (ed.), La Fêlure du Plaisir. Paris, Athens.
pp. 11–31. — 1995. Finitude and Transcendence in the
— 2005. Archytas of Tarentum. Cambridge. Platonic Dialogues. Albany.
— 2008. ‘Two Problems in Pythagoreanism’, — 2004. Questioning Platonism:
in Patricia Curd and Daniel W. Continental Interpretations of Plato.
Graham (eds), The Oxford Handbook Albany.
of Presocratic Philosophy. Oxford, — 2008. Plato and the Question of Beauty.
pp. 284–304. Bloomington.
— 2009. ‘The Pythagorean conception of Idel, Moshe. 2002. Absorbing Perfections:
the soul from Pythagoras to Philolaus’, in Kabbalah and Interpretation. New
Dorothea Frede and Burkhard Reis (eds), Haven.
Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy. Irwin, Terence H. 1977a. Plato’s Moral
Berlin, pp. 21–43. Theory: The Early and Middle Dialogues.
— 2010. ‘Reason and Myth in Early Oxford.
Pythagorean Cosmology’, in Joe McCoy — 1977b. ‘Plato’s Heracliteanism’, The
(ed.), Early Greek Philosophy: Reason at Philosophical Quarterly. 27, 1–13.
the Beginning of Philosophy. Washington, — (trans., comm.). 1979. Plato: Gorgias.
DC. Forthcoming. Oxford.
Hunter, Richard. 2004. Plato’s Symposium. — 1995. Plato’s Ethics. Oxford.
Oxford. — 2005. ‘Was Socrates Against Democracy?’
Hutchinson, D. S. 1997. ‘Alcibiades’, in J. in Rachana Kamtekar (ed.), Plato’s
M. Cooper (ed.), Plato: Complete Works. Euthyphro, Apology, and Crito: Critical
Indianapolis. Essays. London and Boulder, pp. 127–49.
Hutter, Horst. 1978. Politics as Friendship: — 2006. ‘Socrates and Euthyphro: The
The Origins of Classical Notions of Argument and Its Revival’, in L. Judson
Politics in the Theory and Practice of and V. Karasmanis (eds), Remembering
Friendship. Waterloo. Socrates. Oxford, pp. 58–71.
Hutton, Sarah (ed). 1990. Henry More Irwin, Terry. 2008. ‘The Platonic Corpus’, in
(1614–1687): Tercentenary Studies. Gail Fine (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of
Dordrecht. Plato. Oxford, pp. 63–87.
— 1992. ‘The Cambridge Platonists’, in Isnardi Parente, Margherita. 1969. ‘Sugli
S. Nadler (ed.), Blackwell Companion apocrifi platonici Demodoco e Sisifo’, La
to Early Modern Philosophy. Oxford. Parols del Passato. 9, 425–31.
— 2007. ‘The Cambridge Platonists’, in — 1980. Speusippo. Frammenti. Naples.
Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford — 1982. Senocrate-Ermodoro. Frammenti.
Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato. Naples.
stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/ — 1997 and 1998. Per una raccolta delle
plato/ (accessed 29 June 2010). principali testimonianze sul legomena

324

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 324 3/16/2012 9:47:59 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

agrapha dogmata di Platone in Atti della l’Ecole de Chartres, Amsterdam 1973,


Accademia Nazionale dei Lincei (2 vols.). pp. 127–92).
Rome. — 2010. Rethinking the School of Chartres
Ivánka, Endre von. 1964. Plato Christianus. (trans. Claude Paul Desmarais). Toronto.
Einsiedeln. Jenks, Rod. 2008. Plato on Moral Expertise.
Jackson, Henry. 1881–5. ‘Plato’s Later Lanham.
Theory of Ideas’, Journal of Philology. Johansen, Thomas K. 2004. Plato’s Natural
10, 253–98; 11, 287–331; 13, 1–40 and Philosophy: A Study of the Timaeus-
242–72; and 14, 173–230. Critias. Cambridge.
Jacobs, Jonathan. 2010. Law, Reason, and — 2008. ‘The Timaeus on the Principles of
Morality in Medieval Jewish Philosophy. Cosmology’, in Gail Fine (ed.), Oxford
Oxford. Handbook of Plato. Oxford, pp. 463–83.
Jaeger, Werner. 1939–44. Paideia, the ideals Johnson, D. M. 1999. ‘God as the True Self:
of Greek culture. (3 vols) (trans. Gilbert Plato’s Alcibiades I’, Ancient Philosophy.
Highet). New York and Oxford. 19, 1–19.
— 1962. Aristotle. Fundamentals of the Jouanna, Jacques. 1998. ‘The Birth of
History of his Development. Oxford. Western Medical Art’, in Mirko D.
Janaway, Christopher. 1995. Images of Grmek (ed.), Western Medical Thought
Excellence: Plato’s Critique of the Arts. from Antiquity to the Middle Ages (trans.
Oxford. Antony Shugaar). Cambridge, pp. 22–71.
Janko, Richard. 2009. ‘Socrates the Jouët-Pastré, Emmanuelle. 2006. Le jeu et
Freethinker’, in S. Ahbel-Rappe and le Sérieux dan les Lois de Platon. Sankt
R. Kamtekar (eds), A Companion to Augustin.
Socrates. Oxford, pp. 48–62. Joyal, Mark. 1995. ‘Tradition and
Jantzen, J. 1989. Hippias minor oder Der Innovation in the Transformation of
Falsche Wahre: über den Ursprung Socrates’ Divine Sign’, in L. Ayres (ed.),
der moralischen Bedeutung von ‘gutt’. The Passionate Intellect: Essays on the
Weinheim. Transformation of Classical Traditions
Jarratt, Susan. 1991. Rereading the Sophists. Presented to I.G. Kidd. New Brunswick,
Carbondale. pp. 39–56.
Jaucourt, Chevalier de. 1736. Art. — 2000. The Platonic Theages: An
‘Platonisme’ in Encyclopédie raisonnée Introduction, Commentary and Critical
des sciences, des arts et des métiers, Edition. Stuttgart.
Vol. 12. Paris. Justin, Gale. 2005. ‘Identification and
Jay, Martin. 1993. Downcast Eyes. The Definition in the Lysis’, Archiv für
Denigration of Vision in Twentieth- Geschichte der Philosophie. 87,
century French Thought. Berkeley. 75–104.
Jeauneau, Édouard. 1957. ‘L’usage de Kahn, Charles H. 1963. ‘Plato’s Funeral
la notion d’integumentum à travers Oration: The Motive of the Menexenus’,
les gloses de Guillaume de Conches’, Classical Philology. 58, 220–34.
Archives D’histoire Doctrinaire Littéraire — 1966. ‘The Greek Verb “To Be” and
du Moyen Age. 24, 35–100 (repr. in Id. the Concept of Being’, Foundations of
Lectio philosophorum: recherches sur Language. 2, 245–65.

325

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 325 3/16/2012 9:47:59 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

— 1968. ‘Review of G. Ryle, Plato’s Politics’, Oxford Studies in Ancient


Progress’, Journal of Philosophy. 65, Philosophy. 24, 131–72.
364–75. — 2010. ‘Ethics and politics in Socrates’
— 1981. ‘Did Plato Write Socratic Dialogues?’ defense of justice’, in Mark McPherran
Classical Quarterly. 31, 305–20. (ed.) The Cambridge Critical Guide to
— 1983. ‘Drama and Dialectic in Plato’s Plato’s Republic. Cambridge, pp. 65–82.
Gorgias’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Kant, Immanuel. 1787. Kritik der reinen
Philosophy. 1, 75–121. Vernunft. Riga (English trans. Smith N. K.
— 1988. ‘Plato’s Charmides and the (2nd ed.) (1933). Immanuel Kant’s
Proleptic Reading of Plato’s Dialogues’, Critique of Pure Reason. Edinburgh).
Journal of Philosophy. 69, 541–9. — 1796. Von Einem Neuerdings Erhobenen
— 1993. ‘Proleptic Composition in the Vornehmen Ton in der Philosophie, (Engl.
Republic, or Why Book I was Never a trans. Fenves, P. D. 1993. ‘On a Newly
Separate Dialogue’, Classical Quarterly. Arisen Superior Tone in Philosophy’, in
n.s. 43, 131–42. P. D. Fenves (ed.), Raising the Tone of
— 1994. ‘Aeschines on Socratic Eros’, Philosophy. Baltimore).
in P. A. Vander Waerdt (ed.), The Karamanolis, George. 2006. Plato and
Socratic Movement. Ithaca and London, Aristotle in Agreement? Platonists on
pp. 87–106. Aristotle from Antiochus to Porphyry.
— 1998. Plato and the Socratic Dialogue: Oxford.
The Philosophical Use of a Literary Keller, Evelyn and Christine Grontkowski.
Form. Cambridge. 1983. ‘The Mind’s Eye’, in Sandra
— 2000. ‘Response to Griswold’, Ancient Harding and Merill Hintikka (eds),
Philosophy. 20, 189–93. Discovering Realities. Dordrecht.
— 2001. Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans: Kelly, Eugene (ed.). 1984. New Essays on
A Brief History. Indianapolis. Socrates. Lanham.
— 2002. ‘On Platonic Chronology’, in Julia Kennedy, George A. 1963. The Art of
Annas and Christopher Rowe (eds), Persuasion in Ancient Greece. Princeton.
New Perspectives on Plato, Modern and — 1994. A New History of Classical
Ancient. Cambridge, pp. 93–127. Rhetoric. Princeton.
— 2007. ‘Why Is the Sophist a Sequel to the Kennedy, J. B. 2010. ‘Plato’s Forms,
Theaetetus?’ Phronesis 52, 33–57. Pythagorean Mathematics, and
— 2008. ‘Response to Christopher Rowe’, Stichometry’, Apeiron. 43, 1–31.
Plato 2. http://gramata.univer-paris1.fr/ — 2011. The Musical Structure of Plato’s
Plato/article31.html (accessed 15 June Dialogues. Durham.
2010). Kerferd, G. B. 1950. ‘The First Greek
— 2010. ‘The Place of Cosmology in Plato’s Sophists’, Classical Review. 64, 8–10.
Later Dialogues’, in Richard Mohr and — 1981. The Sophistic Movement.
Barbara Slater (eds), One Book, The Cambridge.
Whole Universe: Plato’s Timaeus Today. Ketchum, Richard. 1987. ‘Plato in the
Las Vegas, pp. 69–77. Unknowability of the Sensible World’,
Kamtekar, Rachana. 2004. ‘What’s the History of Philosophy Quarterly. 4,
Good of Agreeing? Homonoia in Platonic 291–305.

326

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 326 3/16/2012 9:47:59 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Kierkegaard, Søren. 1841. On the Concept M. W. Knox (eds), Greek Literature: The
of Irony with Continual Reference to Cambridge History of Classical Literature
Socrates (trans. L. M. Capel). New York. I. Cambridge, pp. 1–15.
Kimball, Bruce. 1986. Orators and Kosman, Aryeh. 2007. ‘Justice and Virtue:
Philosophers. New York. the Republic’s Inquiry into Proper
Kingsley, Peter. 1995. Ancient Philosophy, Difference’, in G. R. F. Ferrari (ed.),
Mystery and Magic. Oxford. The Cambridge Companion to Plato’s
Kirchner, Johannes. 1901. Prosopographia Republic. Cambridge, pp. 116–37.
Attica. Berlin. — 2010. ‘Beauty and the Good: situating to
Kirk, G. S. 1962. Heraclitus: The Cosmic kalon’, Classical Philology. 105, 341–57.
Fragments (2nd edn). Cambridge. Kosman, L. A. 1976. ‘Platonic Love’, in W.
Klagge, James C. and Nicholas D. Smith H. Werkmeister (ed.), Facets of Plato’s
(eds). 1992. Methods of Interpreting Philosophy. Amsterdam, pp. 53–69.
Plato and His Dialogues. Oxford. Koyré, Alexander. 1957. From the
Klein, Jacob. 1965. A Commentary on Closed World to the Infinite Universe.
Plato’s Meno. Chapel Hill. Baltimore.
— 1966. ‘A Note on Plato’s Parmenides’, Krämer, Hans J. 1959. Arete bei Platon und
in R. Williamson and E. Zuckerman Aristoteles (1st edn). Heidelberg.
(eds), Lectures and Essays. Annapolis, — 1964. Der Ursprung der
pp. 285–7. Geistmetaphysik. Untersuchungen zur
— 1992. Greek Mathematical Thought and Geschichte des Platonismus zwischen
the Origin of Algebra (trans. Eva Brann). Platon und Plotin (1st edn). Amsterdam.
New York. — 1982. Platone e i fondamenti della
Klein-Franke, Felix. 1973. ‘Zur metafisica. Milano.
Überlieferung der platonischen Schriften — 1990. Plato and the Foundations of
in Islam’, Israel Oriental Studies. 3, Metaphysics: A Work on the Theory of
120–39. the Principles and Unwritten Doctrines
Klibansky, Raymond. 1939. The Continuity of Plato with a Collection of the
of the Platonic tradition during the Fundamental Documents (trans. J. R.
Middle Ages: Outlines of a Corpus Catan). New York.
Platonicum Medii Aevi. London. Krauss, Heinrich. 1911. Aischinis Socratici
Klosko, George. 1984. ‘The Refutation reliquiae. Leipzig.
of Polus in Plato’s Gorgias’, Greece & Kraut, Richard. 1979. ‘Two Conceptions of
Rome. 31, 126–39. Happiness’, Philosophical Review. 88,
— 2006. The Development of Plato’s 167–97.
Political Theory (2nd edn). Oxford. — 1984. Socrates and the State. Princeton.
Kneale, William and Martha Kneale. 1964. — (ed.). 1992a. The Cambridge Companion
The Development of Logic. Oxford. to Plato. Cambridge.
Knorr, Wilbur. 1989. Textual Studies in — 1992b. ‘The Defense of Justice in
Ancient and Medieval Geometry. Boston. Plato’s Republic’, in Kraut (ed.), 1992a,
Knox, B. M. W. 1985. ‘Books and Readers pp. 311–37.
in the Greek World: From the Beginnings — 1992c. ‘Introduction to the Study of
to Alexandria’, in P. E. Easterling and B. Plato’, in Kraut (ed.), 1992a, pp. 1–50.

327

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 327 3/16/2012 9:47:59 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

— 1992d. ‘Chronology’, in Kraut (ed.), Traduzione Della Repubblica di Platone


1992a, pp. xii–xiii. tra Medioevo e Umanesimo. Naples,
Kretzmann, Norman. 1971. ‘Plato on pp. 13–30.
the Correctness of Names’, American — 2010. Judaism: An Introduction. London.
Philosophical Quarterly. 8, 126–38. Lear, G. R. 2007. ‘Permanent Beauty and
Krohn, August. 1876. Der Platonische Staat. Becoming Happy in Plato’s Symposium’,
Halle. in James Lesher, Debra Nails, and Frisbee
Lacey, A. R. 1971. ‘Our Knowledge of Sheffield (eds), Plato’s ‘Symposium’:
Socrates’, in Gregory Vlastos (ed.), Issues in Interpretation and Reception.
The Philosophy of Socrates. Plato II: Cambridge, pp. 96–123.
A Collection of Critical Essays. Ethics, Lear, J. 1992. ‘Inside and Outside the
Politics and Philosophy of Art and Republic’, Phronesis. 37, 184–215.
Religion. New York, pp. 22–49. Lebeck, Anne. 1971. The Oresteia. A Study
Lafrance, Yvon. 1986. Pour Interpréter in Language and Structure. Washington
Platon: La Ligne en République VI, D. C. and Cambridge.
509d–511e. Montréal and Paris. Ledger, Gerard R. 1989. Re-Counting Plato:
— 1987. Pour Interpréter Platon, I, La A Computer Analysis of Plato’s Style.
Ligne en République VI, 509d–511e. Oxford.
Bilan analytique des études (1804–1984). Lee, Mi-Kyoung. 2005. Epistemology after
Montréal and Paris. Protagoras: Responses to Relativism
— 1994. Pour Interpréter Platon, II, La in Plato, Aristotle and Democritus.
Ligne en République VI, 509d–511e. Le Oxford.
Texte et son Histoire. Montréal and Paris. — 2008. ‘The Theaetetus’, in Gail Fine (ed.),
Laín Entralgo, Pedro. 1970. The Therapy Oxford Handbook on Plato. Oxford,
of the Word in Classical Antiquity. New pp. 411–36.
Haven (trans. Lelland J. Rather and John Lesher, J. H. 1987. ‘Socrates’ Disavowal of
M. Sharp). Knowledge’, Journal of the History of
Laird, Andrew. 2003. ‘Death, Politics, Philosophy. 25, 275–88.
Vision and Fiction in Plato’s Cave (After — 1992. Xenophanes of Colophon. Toronto.
Saramago)’, Arion. 10, 1–30. Lesher, J. H., Debra Nails and Frisbee C.
Lamberton, Robert and John Keaney (eds). C. Sheffield. 2006. Plato’s Symposium:
1992. Homer’s Ancient Readers: The Issues in Interpretation and Reception.
Hermeneutics of Greek Epics Earliest Cambridge, Massachusetts and London.
Exegets. Princeton. Lesky, Albin. 1996. A History of Greek
Landy, Tucker. 1998. ‘Limitations of Literature. London.
Political Philosophy: An Interpretation Levin, Donald N. 1971. ‘Some Observations
of Plato’s Charmides’, Interpretation. 26, Concerning Plato’s Lysis’, in J. P. Anton
183–99. and G. L. Kustas (eds), Essays in Greek
Lane, Melissa S. 1998. Method and Politics Philosophy. Albany, pp. 236–58.
in Plato’s Statesman. Cambridge. Levin, Susan B. 2000. The Ancient Quarrel
Leaman, Oliver. 2005. ‘Plato’s Republic in Between Philosophy and Poetry Revisited:
Jewish philosophy’, in M. Vegetti and Plato and the Greek Literary Tradition.
M. P. Pissavino (eds), I Decembrio e la New York and Oxford.

328

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 328 3/16/2012 9:47:59 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

— 2007. ‘Is Medicine a Technê? Health and of the Boston Area Colloquium in
End-of-Life Care in Plato’s Republic’, Ancient Philosophy, Vol. XIX. Leiden and
Philosophical Inquiry. 29, 125–53. Boston, pp. 123–43.
— 2008. ‘Platonic Metaphysics and Long, Christopher P. 2003. ‘Dancing Naked
Semantics: The Cratylus’ Ties to the with Socrates: Pericles, Aspasia and
Sophist and Politicus’, in Dagfinn Socrates at Play with Politics, Rhetoric
Føllesdal and John Woods (eds), Logos and Philosophy’, Ancient Philosophy. 23,
and Language: Essays in Honour of 49–69.
Julius Moravcsik. London, pp. 73–98. Loraux, Nicole. 1986. The Invention of
Levinas, Emmanuel. 1972. Humanisme de Athens: The Funeral Oration in the
L’autre Homme. Montpellier. Classical City (trans. A. Sheridan).
Lewis, V. Bradley. 2000. ‘The Seventh Cambridge.
Letter and the Unity of Plato’s Political Lorenz, Hendrik. 2006. ‘The Analysis of the
Philosophy’, Southern Journal of Soul in Plato’s Republic’, in Gerasimos
Philosophy. 38, 231–50. Santas (ed.) Blackwell Guide to Plato’s
Lindberg, David. 1976. Theory of Vision Republic. Oxford, pp. 125–45.
from Al-Kindi to Kepler. Chicago. Lotze, Hermann. 1856–64. Mikrokosmus.
Livingstone, Niall. 2001. A Commentary on Leipzig.
Isocrates’ Busiris. Leiden. — 1874. System der Philosophie: Logik.
Lloyd, A. C. 1990. The Anatomy of Leipzig.
Neoplatonism. Oxford. Lovibond, Sabina. 1990. ‘True and False
Lloyd, G. E. R. 1968. Aristotle. The Growth Pleasures’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian
and Structure of his Thought. Cambridge. Society. 90, 213–30.
— 1979. Magic, Reason, and Experience. Ludwig, Paul. 2002. Eros and Polis.
Cambridge. Cambridge.
— 1992a. Polarity and Analogy: Two Lutoslawski, Wicenty. 1897. The Origin
Types of Argumentation in Early Greek and Growth of Plato’s Logic. With
Thought. Bristol. an Account of Plato’s Style and of the
— 1992b. ‘The Meno and the Mysteries of Chronology of his Writings. London.
Mathematics’, Phronesis. 37, 166–83. Luz, Menahem. 1994. ‘The Transmission
Lobel, Edgar. 1919. ‘Aeschines Socraticus, of Antisthenes’ Hercules in Hellenistic
Alicibiades’, in Papyri Oxyrhynchus. XII Philosophy and Literature’, in K. J.
n. 1608. Boudouris (ed.), Hellenistic Philosophy.
Long, A. A. 1996. ‘The Socratic Tradition: Athens, pp. 88–95.
Diogenes, Crates and Hellenistic Ethics’, — 1996. ‘Antisthenes’ Prometheus Myth’,
in R. Bracht Branham and Marie-Odile in John Glucker and André Laks (eds),
Goulet-Cazé (eds), The Cynics The Cynic Jacob Bernays: un Philologue Juif.
Movement in Antiquity and its Legacy. Villeneuve d’Ascq, pp. 89–103.
Berkeley, Los Angeles and London. — 2000. ‘Disgracefulness is Disgraceful:
— (ed). 1999. The Cambridge Companion Antisthenes’ Logic, Ethics and Sources’,
to Early Greek Philosophy. Cambridge. in Konstantine Boudouris (ed.), Greek
— 2004. ‘Eudaimonism, divinity, and Philosophy and the Fine Arts. Athens,
rationality in Greek ethics’, Proceedings pp. 88–95.

329

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 329 3/16/2012 9:47:59 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Lycos, Kimon. 1987. Plato on Justice — 2000. Plato and his Predecessors: the
and Power: Reading Book I of Plato’s Dramatisation of Reason. Cambridge.
Republic. Albany. — 2008. ‘Plato’s Ways of Writing’, in Gail
Mahdi, Muhsin (trans.). 1962. Alfarabi’s Fine (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of
Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle. Plato. Oxford, pp. 88–113.
Glencoe. McCoy, Marina. 2007. Plato on the
Mahoney, T. 1992. ‘Do Plato’s Philosopher- Rhetoric of Philosophers and Sophists.
Rulers Sacrifice Self-interest to Justice?’ Cambridge.
Phronesis. 38, 265–82. — 2009. ‘Alcidamas, Isocrates, and Plato
Maiatsky, Michail. 2005. Platon, Penseur du on Speech, Writing, and Philosophical
Visuel. Paris. Rhetoric’, Ancient Philosophy. 29,
Malcolm, John. 1981. ‘The Cave Revisited’, 45–66.
Classical Quarterly. 31, 60–8. McKim, Richard. 1985. ‘Socratic Self-
— 1991. Plato on the Self Predication of knowledge and Knowledge of Knowledge
Forms. Oxford. in Plato’s Charmides’, Transactions of the
Mannebach, Erich. 1961. Aristippi et American Philological Association. 115,
Cyrenaicorum Fragmenta. Leiden. 59–77.
Mansfeld, Jaap. 1994. Prolegomena: McKirahan, Voula Tsouna. 1994. ‘The
Questions to be Settled before the Study Socratic Origins of the Cynics and
of an Author, or a Text. Leiden. Cyrenaics’, in P. A. Vander Waerdt (ed.),
Manuwald, Bernd. 2005. ‘The Unity of Virtue The Socratic Movement. Ithaca, pp. 367–91.
in Plato’s Protagoras’, Oxford Studies in McPherran, Mark L. 1996. The Religion of
Ancient Philosophy. 29, 115–35. Socrates. University Park.
Marenbon, John. 1997. The philosophy of — 2000. ‘Does Piety Pay? Socrates and Plato
Peter Abelard. Cambridge. on Prayer and Sacrifice’, in Nicholas D.
— 2002. ‘Platonism–a Doxographic Smith and Paul Woodruff (eds), Reason
Approach: the Early Middle Ages’, in S. and Religion in Socratic Philosophy.
Gersh and Maarten J. F. M. Hoenen (eds), Oxford, pp. 89–114; also in Thomas
The Platonic Tradition in the Middle C. Brickhouse and Nicholas D. Smith
Ages: A Doxographic Approach. Berlin (eds). 2002. The Trial and Execution
and New York, pp. 67–89. of Socrates: Sources and Controversies.
— 2007. Medieval Philosophy: Oxford, pp. 162–89.
An Historical and Philosophical — 2002. ‘Elenctic Interpretation and the
Introduction. New York. Delphic Oracle’, in Gary A. Scott (ed.),
Marrou, Henri-Irénée. 1956. A History of Does Socrates Have a Method? University
Education in Antiquity (trans. George Park, pp. 114–44.
Lamb). New York. — 2003. ‘The Aporetic Interlude and
Matthews, Gareth. 2008. ‘The epistemology Fifth Elenchos of Plato’s Euthyphro’,
and metaphysics of Socrates’, in Gail Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy.
Fine (ed.), Oxford Handbook on Plato. 25, 1–37.
Oxford, pp. 114–38. — 2006a. ‘Platonic Religion’, in Hugh
McCabe, Mary Margaret. 1994. Plato’s Benson (ed.), A Companion to Plato.
Individuals. Princeton. Malden, pp. 244–60.

330

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 330 3/16/2012 9:47:59 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

— 2006b. ‘The Gods and Piety of Plato’s Michelini, A. N. 2003. Plato as Author: The
Republic’, in Gerasimos X. Santas (ed.), Rhetoric of Philosophy. Leiden and Boston.
The Blackwell Guide to Plato’s Republic. Migliori, Maurizio. 1990. Dialettica e
Malden, pp. 84–104. Verità: Commentario Filosofico al
— 2006c. ‘Medicine, Magic, and Religion ‘Parmenide’ di Platone. Milan.
in Plato’s Symposium’, in James H. Miles, Murray. 2001. ‘Plato on Suicide
Lesher, Debra Nails, and Frisbee Sheffield (Phaedo 60c–63c)’, Phoenix. 55, 244–58.
(eds), Plato’s Symposium: Issues in Miller, Fred D. 2005. ‘Plato on the Rule of
Interpretation and Reception. Cambridge, Reason’, Southern Journal of Philosophy.
pp. 71–95. 43, 50–83.
— 2010. ‘Love and Medicine in Plato’s Miller, Mitch Jr. 1985. ‘Platonic
Symposium and Philebus’, in Luc Provocations: Reflections on the Soul
Brisson and John Dillon (eds), Plato’s and the Good in the Republic’, in D. J.
Philebus: Selected Papers from the Eighth O’Meara (ed.), Platonic Investigations.
Symposium Platonicum. Sankt Augustin, Washington, pp. 165–93.
pp. 204–8. — 1986. Plato’s Parmenides: The
Méasson, Anita. 1986. Du char ailé de Zeus Conversation of the Soul. Princeton.
à l’Arche d’Alliance: Images et Mythes — 1995a. ‘The Choice between the
Platoniciens chez Philon d’Alexandrie. Dialogues and the Unwritten Teachings: A
Paris. Scylla and Charybdis for the Interpreter?’
Meinwald, Constance C. 1991. Plato’s in Francisco J. Gonzales (ed.), The Third
‘Parmenides’. Oxford. Way: New Directions in Platonic Studies.
— 1998. ‘Prometheus’s Bounds: Peras Lanham, pp. 25–44.
and Apeiron in Plato’s Philebus’, in — 1995b. ‘“Unwritten Teachings” in the
Jyl Gentzler (ed.), Method in Ancient Parmenides’, Review of Metaphysics. 48,
Philosophy. Oxford, pp. 165–80. 591–633.
Melamed, Abraham. 1997. ‘Medieval and — 2003. ‘The Timaeus and the Longer
Renaissance Jewish Political Philosophy’, Way’, in G. Greydam-Schils (ed.), Plato’s
in D. Frank and O. Leaman (eds). Timaeus as Cultural Icon. Notre Dame,
History of Jewish Philosophy. London, pp. 17–59.
pp. 415–49. — 2004. The Philosopher in Plato’s
Menn, Stephen. 2002. ‘Plato and the Method Statesman. Parmenides.
of Analysis’, Phronesis. 47, 193–223. — 2007. ‘Beginning the “Longer Way,”’in
Mercer, Christia. 2001. Leibniz’s G. R. F. Ferarri (ed.), The Cambridge
Metaphysics: Its Origins and Companion to Plato’s Republic.
Development. Cambridge. Cambridge, pp. 310–44.
Merker, Anne. 2003. La Vision chez Platon — 2008. ‘The Pleasures of the Comic and of
et Aristote. Sankt Augustin. Socratic Inquiry: Aporetic Reflections on
Merlan, Philip. 1947. ‘Form and Content Philebus 48a–50b’, Arethusa. 41, 263–89.
in Plato’s Philosophy’, Journal of the Mirhady, David C. 2001. ‘Dicaearchus
History of Ideas. 8, 406–30. of Messana: The Sources, Text and
— 1953. From Platonism to Neoplatonism. Translation’, in William W. Fortenbaugh
The Hague. and Eckart Schütrumpf (eds),

331

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 331 3/16/2012 9:47:59 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Dicaearchus of Messana. New Brunswick — 1960. ‘Aristotle’s Comments on Plato’s


and London, pp. 1–142. Laws’, in I. Düring and G. E. L. Owen
Mirhady, David C. and Yun L. Too. 2000. (eds), Plato and Aristotle in the Mid-
Isocrates I. Austin. fourth Century. Göteborg, pp. 145–62.
Moes, Mark. 2000. Plato’s Dialogue Form — 1993. Plato’s Cretan City. Princeton
and the Care of the Soul. New York. (repr. of Princeton 1960).
Moline, Jonathan. 1969. ‘Meno’s Paradox?’ Most, G. W. 1993. ‘A Cock for Asclepius’,
Phronesis. 14, 153–61. Classical Quarterly. N.S. 43 No. 1,
Monoson, Sara S. 1992. ‘Remembering 96–111.
Pericles: The Political and Theoretical Mourelatos, A. P. D. 1970. The Route of
Import of Plato’s Menexenus’, Political Parmenides: A Study of Word, Image,
Theory. 26, 489–513. and Argument in the Fragments. New
Moravcsik, Julius. 1970. ‘Learning as Haven.
Recollection’, in Gregory Vlastos (ed.), Mueller, Ian. 1992. ‘Mathematical Method
Plato: A Collection of Critical Essays. and Philosophical Truth’, in Richard
Vol. I. Garden City, pp. 53–69. Kraut (ed.), The Cambridge Companion
— 1973. ‘The Anatomy of Plato’s Divisions’, to Plato. New York, pp. 170–99.
in E. N. Lee, A. P. D. Mourelatos, and R. Mugler, Charles. 1964. Dictionnaire
M. Rorty (eds), Exegesis and Argument: Historique de la Terminologie Optique
Studies in Greek Philosophy Presented to des Grecs. Paris.
Gregory Vlastos. New York, pp. 324–48. Muir, J. V. 2001. Alcidamas: The Works and
— 1992. Plato and Platonism. Oxford. Fragments. London.
Moreau, Joseph. 1941. ‘La platonisme de Muirhead, John H. 1931. The Platonic
“L’Hippias Majeur,”’ Revue des Etudes Tradition in Anglo-Saxon Philosophy.
Grecques. 54, 19–42. London.
Morgan, Kathryn A. 2000. Myth and Mulhern, J. J. 1984. ‘Tropos and Polytropia
Philosophy from the Presocratics to in Plato’s Hippias minor’, Phoenix. 22,
Plato. Cambridge. 283–8.
— 2010. ‘Inspiration, Recollection, and Murdoch, Iris. 1977. The Fire and the
Mimêsis in Plato’s Phaedrus’, in David Sun: Why Plato Banished the Artists.
Sedley and Andrea Nightingale (eds), Oxford.
Ancient Models of Mind: Studies Murphy, David J. 2000. ‘Doctors of
in Human and Divine Rationality. Zalmoxis and Immortality in the
Cambridge, pp. 45–63. Charmides’, in Thomas M. Robinson
Morgan, Michael L. 1990. Platonic Piety: (ed.), Plato: Euthydemus, Lysis
Philosophy and Ritual in Fourth-Century Charmides: Proceedings of the
Athens. New Haven and London. V’Symposium Platonicum. Sankt
Morrison, Donald. 2000. ‘On the Alleged Augustin, pp. 287–95.
Historical Reliability of Plato’s Apology’, Murray, Oswyn. (ed.). 1990. Sympotica: A
Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie. symposium on the Symposium. Oxford.
82, 235–65. Murray, Penelope. 1981. ‘Poetic inspiration
Morrow, Glenn R. 1935. Studies in the in early Greece’, Journal of Hellenic
Platonic Epistles. Urbana. Studies. 101, 87–100.

332

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 332 3/16/2012 9:47:59 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

— 1993. ‘Inspiration and mimesis in Nauta, Lodi. 1996. ‘The preexistence of the
Plato’, in Andrew Barker and Martin soul in medieval thought’, Recherches
Warner (eds), The Language of the Cave. de Théologie Ancienne et Médiévale. 63,
Edmonton, pp. 27–46 (repr. in 2004, 93–135.
Apeiron 25, 4). — 2009. ‘The Consolation: the Latin
Nagy, Gregory. 1989. ‘Early Greek View of commentary tradition 800–1700’, in
poets and poetry’, in George Kennedy J. Marenbon (ed.), The Cambridge
(ed.), The Cambridge History of Classical Companion to Boethius. Cambridge.
Criticism. Vol. I. Cambridge. Navia, Luis E. 2001. Antisthenes of Athens:
Nails, Debra. 1993. ‘Problems with Vlastos’s Setting the World Aright. Westport.
Platonic Developmentalism’, Ancient Nehamas, Alexander. 1975. ‘Plato on the
Philosophy. 13, 273–91. Imperfection of the Sensible World’,
— 1994. ‘Plato’s Middle Cluster’, Phoenix. American Philosophical Quarterly.
48, 62–7. 12, 105–17 (reprinted in Fine, Gail
— 1995. Agora, Academy, and the Conduct (ed.). 1999. Plato I: Metaphysics and
of Philosophy. Dortrecht. Epistemology. Oxford, pp. 171–91;
— 1998. ‘The Dramatic Date of Plato’s also in Nehamas, A. 1999. Virtues of
Republic’, The Classical Journal. 93, Authenticity. Princeton, pp. 138–58).
383–96. — 1979. ‘Self-predication and Plato’s
— 2002. The People of Plato: A Theory of Forms’, American
Prosopography of Plato and Other Philosophical Quarterly. 16, 93–103.
Socratics. Indianapolis and Cambridge. — 1982a. ‘Participation and Predication
Nails, Debra and Holger Thesleff. 2003. in Plato’s Later Dialogues’, Review
‘Early Academic Editing: Plato’s Laws’, in of Metaphysics. 36, 343–74 (also
Samuel Scolnicov and Luc Brisson (eds), in Nehamas, A. 1999. Virtues of
Plato’s Laws: From Theory into Practice. Authenticity. Princeton, pp. 196–223).
Sankt Augustin, pp. 14–29. — 1982b. ‘Plato on Imitation and Poetry’, in
— 2006. ‘The Life of Plato of Athens’, in Julius Moravcsik and Philip Temko (eds),
Hugh Benson (ed.), A Companion to Plato on Beauty, Wisdom, and the Arts.
Plato. Oxford, pp. 1–12. Totowa: NJ, pp. 47–78.
— 2009. ‘Socrates’, The Stanford — 1992. ‘Voices of Silence: On Gregory
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward N. Vlastos’ Socrates’, Arion: A Journal of
Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ Humanities and the Classics. 2, 157–86.
socrates/ (accessed 19 February 2010). — 1999. Virtues of Authenticity: Essays on
Napolitano Valditara, Linda. 1994. Lo Plato and Aristotle. Princeton.
Sguardo nel Buio. Metafore Visive e Nettleship, Richard Lewis. 1929. Lectures
Forme Grecoantica Della Razionalità. on the Republic of Plato. London.
Roma-Bari. — 1935. The Theory of Education in Plato’s
Narcy, Michel. 1984. Le Philosophe et son Republic. Oxford.
Double: Un Commentaire de l’Euthydème Nichols, Mary P. 1987. Socrates and the
de Platon. Paris. Political Community. Albany.
Natorp, Paul. 1903. Platonsideenlehre. — 2009. Socrates on Friendship and
Leipzig. Community: Reflections on Plato’s

333

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 333 3/16/2012 9:47:59 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Symposium, Phaedrus, and Lysis. Women and the Family’, Philosophy and
Cambridge. Public Affairs. 6, 345–69.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1886. Jenseits von Gut — 1979. Women in Western Political
und Böse. 1888. Götzen-Dämmerung, oder Thought. Princeton.
Wie man mit dem Hammer philosophirt, Ong, Walter. 1982. Orality and Literacy:
‘Was ich den Alten verdanke’§2. The Technologizing of the Word.
— 1888. Twilight of the Idols, What I Owe London.
to the Ancients §2. Osborne, Catherine. 1994. Eros Unveiled:
Nightingale, Andrea W. 1995. Genres in Plato and the God of Love. Oxford.
Dialogue: Plato and the Construct of — 1995. ‘Perceiving Particulars and
Philosophy. Cambridge. Recollecting the Forms in the Phaedo’,
— 2004. Spectacles of Truth in Classical Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society.
Greek Philosophy: Theoria in its Cultural N.S. 95, 211–33.
Context. Cambridge. Oswiecimski, Stefan. 1978. ‘The Enigmatic
North, Helen. 1966. Sophrosyne: Self- Character of some of Plato’s Apocrypha’,
Knowledge and Self-Restraint in Greek Eos. 66, 31–40.
Literature. Ithaca. — 1979. ‘The Acephalous Dialogues’, Eos.
Notomi, Noburu. 1999. The Unity of 67, 55–67.
Plato’s Sophist: Between the Sophist and Owen, G. E. L. 1953a. ‘The Place of the
the Philosopher. Cambridge. Timaeus in Plato’s Dialogues’, Classical
— 2007. ‘Plato on what is not’, in D. Scott Quarterly. 3, 70–95 (repr. in R. E. Allen
(ed.), Maieusis. Oxford, pp. 254–75. (ed), Studies in Plato’s Metaphysics.
Nussbaum, Martha C. 1986. The Fragility London 1965, pp. 1–12 and repr. in G. E.
of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek L. Owen and Martha Nussbaum (eds),
Tragedy and Philosophy. Cambridge. Logic, Science, and Dialectic. Ithaca
— 1994. The Therapy of Desire. 1986, pp. 65–84).
Princeton. — 1953b. ‘The Place of the Timaeus in
O’Connor, David K. 2007. ‘Rewriting the Plato’s Dialogues’, Classical Quarterly.
Poets in Plato’s Characters’, in G. R. F. n.s. 3, 79–95.
Ferrari (ed.), The Cambridge Companion — 1957. ‘A Proof in the Peri Ideon’, Journal
to Plato’s Republic. Cambridge, of Hellenic Studies. 77, 103–11.
pp. 55–89. — 1965. ‘The Place of the Timaeus in Plato’s
O’Meara, Dominic J. 1993. Plotinus: An Dialogues’, in R. E. Allen (ed.), Studies in
Introduction to the Enneads. Oxford. Plato’s Metaphysics. London, pp. 313–38.
O’Sullivan, Neil. 1992. Alcidamas, — 1970. ‘Plato on Not-Being’, in Gregory
Aristophanes and the Beginnings of Vlastos (ed.), Plato I. New York,
Greek Stylistic Theory. Stuttgart. pp. 223–67.
Ober, Josiah. 1989. Mass and Elite in — 1971. ‘Plato on Not-Being’, in Gregory
Democratic Athens. Princeton. Vlastos (ed.), Plato: A Collection of
Ohly, Kurt. 1928. Stichometrische Critical Essays, Vol. 1. Notre Dame,
Untersuchungen. Leipzig. pp. 223–67 (repr. in Martha Nussbaum
Okin, Susan Moller. 1977. ‘Philosopher- (ed.), 1986. Logic, Science, and Dialectic.
Queens and Private Wives: Plato on Ithaca, pp. 104–37).

334

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 334 3/16/2012 9:47:59 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

— 1986. ‘The Platonism of Aristotle’, in Pellegrin, Pierre. 2009. ‘Ancient Medicine


Martha Nussbaum (ed.), Logic, Science and its Contribution to the Philosophical
and Dialectic. London and New York, Tradition’, in Mary L. Gill and Pierre
pp. 200–20. Pellegrin (eds), A Companion to Ancient
Pakaluk, M. 2003. ‘Degrees of Separation in Philosophy. Malden, pp. 664–85.
the Phaedo’, Phronesis. 48, 89–115. Pender, E. E. 1992. ‘Spiritual Pregnancy in
Palmer, John. 1999. Plato’s Reception of Plato’s Symposium’, Classical Quarterly.
Parmenides. Oxford and New York. 42, 72–86.
Pangle, Thomas L. 1980. ‘Interpretive — Forthcoming. ‘The Rivers of the
Essay’, in The Laws of Plato. Underworld: Plato’s Geography of
Thomas L. Pangle (trans.), Chicago, Dying and Coming-back-to-Life’, in
pp. 375–510. C. Collobert, P. Destrée, F. J. Gonzalez
Pappas, Nickolas. 2003. Routledge (eds), Platonic Myths: Uses and Statuses.
GuideBook to Plato and the Republic Leiden, ch. 11.
(2nd edn). London. Penner, Terry. 1971. ‘Thought and Desire in
Paquet, Léonce. 1973. Platon. La Médiation Plato’, in Gregory Vlastos (ed.), Plato II.
du Regard. Leiden. Garden City, pp. 96–118.
Parry, Richard. 1996. Plato’s Craft of — 1973. ‘The Unity of Virtue’, The
Justice. Albany. Philosophical Review. 82, 35–68.
— 2007. ‘The Unhappy Tyrant and the — 1990. ‘Plato and Davidson: Parts of the
Craft of Inner Rule’, in G. R. F. Ferrari Soul and Weakness of Will’, in David
(ed.), The Cambridge Companion Copp (ed.), Canadian Philosophers,
to Plato’s Republic. Cambridge, Supplementary Vol.16, Canadian Journal
pp. 386–414. of Philosophy. pp. 35–74.
Partenie, Catalin (ed.). 2009. Plato’s Myths. — 1991. ‘Desire and Power in Socrates: The
Cambridge. Argument of Gorgias 466a–468c that
Passmore, J. A. 1951. Ralph Cudworth, an Orators and Tyrants have no Power in
Interpretation. Cambridge. the City’, Apeiron. 24, 147–202.
Patrizzi da Cherso, Francesco. 1571. — 1992. ‘Socrates and the Early Dialogues’,
Discussionum Peripateticorum Libri XV. in Richard Kraut (ed.), The Cambridge
Basle. Companion to Plato. Cambridge,
— 1591. Nova de Universis Philosophiae. pp. 121–69.
Ferrara. — 2002. ‘The Historical Socrates
Patterson, Richard. 1985. Image and and Plato’s Early Dialogues: Some
Reality in Plato’s Metaphysics. Philosophical Questions’, in Julia Annas
Indianapolis. and Christopher Rowe (eds), New
— 1997. ‘Philosophos Agonistes: Imagery Perspectives on Plato, Modern and
and Moral Psychology in Plato’s Ancient. Cambridge, pp. 189–212.
Republic’, Journal of the History of — 2005. ‘Socratic Ethics, Ultra-realism,
Philosophy. 35, 327–54. Determinism, and Ethical truth’, in
— 2007. ‘Diagrams, Dialectic, and Christopher Gill (ed.), Virtue, Norms
Mathematical Foundations in Plato’, & Objectivity: Issues in Ancient and
Apeiron. 40, 1–33. Modern Ethics. Oxford, pp. 157–87.

335

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 335 3/16/2012 9:47:59 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Penner, Terry and Christopher Rowe. 2005. — 1995. Sophistical Rhetoric in Classical
Plato’s Lysis. Cambridge. Greece. Columbia.
Perl, Eric. 1995. ‘The Living Image: Pownall, Frances. 2004. Lessons from the
Forms and the Erotic Intellect in Plato’, Past: The Moral Use of History in Fourth-
American Catholic Philosophical Century Prose. Ann Arbor.
Quarterly. 69, 191–204. Pratt, Louise. 1993. Lying and Poetry
Perrault, Charles. 1688. Parallèle des Anciens from Homer to Pindar: Falsehood and
et des Modernes en ce qui Concerne les Deception in Archaic Greek Poetics. Ann
Arts et les Sciences (4 vol.). Paris. Arbor.
— 1996. Philosophy in the Tragic Age of Press, Gerald A. (ed.). 1993. Plato’s
the Greeks (trans. Mariane Cowan). Dialogues: New Studies &
Washington, D.C. Interpretations. Lanham.
— 1999. The Birth of Tragedy and Other — 1995a. ‘Knowledge as Vision in Plato’s
Writings (trans. Raymond Geuss and Dialogues’, Journal of Neoplatonic
Ronald Speirs). Cambridge. Studies. 3, 61–89.
— 2005. The Anti-Christ, Ecce Homo, — 1995b. ‘Plato’s Dialogues as Enactments’,
Twilight of the Idols and Other Writings in Francisco Gonzalez (ed.), The Third
(trans. Judith Norman). Cambridge. Way: New Directions in Platonic Studies.
Philip, J. A. 1970. ‘The Platonic Corpus’, Lanham, pp. 133–52.
Phoenix. 24, 296–308. — 2000. (ed.) Who Speaks for Plato?
Pieper, Josef. 1964. Enthusiasm and Divine Studies in Platonic Anonymity. Lanham.
Madness (trans. Richard Winston and — 2007. Plato: A Guide for the Perplexed.
Clara Winston). New York. New York.
Plass, Paul. 1964. ‘Philosophic Anonymity and Price, Anthony W. 1989. Love and
Irony in the Platonic Dialogues’, American Friendship in Plato and Aristotle. Oxford.
Journal of Philology. 85, 254–78. — 1995. Mental Conflict. London.
— 1967. ‘“Play” and Philosophical Price, Jonathan. 2001. Thucydides and
Detachment in Plato’, Transactions and Internal War. Cambridge.
Proceedings of the American Philological Prier, Raymond. 1989. Thauma Idesthai: The
Association. 98, 343–64. Phenomenology of Sight & Appearance in
Polansky, Ronald. 1992. Philosophy and Archaic Greek. Tallahassee.
Knowledge: A Commentary on Plato’s Prior, William J. 1985. Unity and
Theaetetus. Lewisburg. Development in Plato’s Metaphysics.
Popper, Karl. 1945. The Open Society and its Chicago and La Salle.
Enemies, Vol. I: The Spell of Plato. London. — 1996. Socrates: Critical Assessments.
— 1962. The Open Society and Its Enemies London and New York.
(4th edn, vol. 1). Princeton. — 2001. ‘The Historicity of Plato’s
Post, L. A. 1934. The Vatican Plato and its Apology’, Polis. 18, 41–57.
Relations. Middletown. — 2004. ‘Socrates Metaphysician’, Oxford
Pottenger, John R. 1995–6. ‘The sage and Studies in Ancient Philosophy. 27, 1–14.
the sophist: a commentary on Plato’s — 2006. ‘The Socratic Problem’, in Hugh
Lesser Hippias’, Interpretation. 23, Benson (ed.), A Blackwell Companion to
41–60. Plato. Malden, pp. 25–36.

336

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 336 3/16/2012 9:47:59 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Proclus. 1970. A Commentary on the First Rick, Hubert. 1931. Neue Untersuchungen
Book of Euclid’s Elements (trans. Glenn zu platonischen Dialogen. Bonn.
Morrow). Princeton. Rickless, Samuel. 2007. Plato’s Forms in
Quine, W. V. 1986. Philosophy of Logic Transition: A Reading of the Parmenides.
(2nd edn). Cambridge. Cambridge.
Rademaker, Adriaan. 2005. Sôphrosynê and Ries, Klaus. 1959. Isokrates und Platon im
the Rhetoric of Self-Restraint. Leiden. Ringen um die Philosophie (Dissertation).
Randall, John Herman. 1970. Plato: Munich.
Dramatist of the Life of Reason. New Riginos, Alice. 1976. Platonica. The
York. Anecdotes Concerning the Life and
Rankin, H. D. 1967. ‘Laughter, Humour Writings of Plato. Leiden.
and Related Topics in Plato’, Classica et Rist, John M. 1967. Plotinus: The Road to
Medievalia. 28, 186–213. Reality. Cambridge.
— 1986. Antisthenes Sokratikos. Ritter, Constantin. 1888. Untersuchungen
Amsterdam. über Platon. Stuttgart.
Ranta, Jerrald. 1967. ‘The Drama of Plato’s — 1910a. ‘Eidos, idea und verwandte
Ion’, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Wörter in den Schriften Platons’,
Criticism. 26, 219–29. in Ritter Constantin, Neue
Raven, J. E. 1953. ‘Sun, Divided Line, and Untersuchungen über Platon. München,
Cave’, Classical Quarterly. 3, 22–32. pp. 228–326.
Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. — 1910b. Platon: sein Leben, seine
Cambridge. Schriften, seine Lehre. Munich.
Reale, Giovanni. 1984. Per una Nuova — 1933. The Essence of Plato’s Philosophy.
Interpretazione di Platone. Milano. New York.
Reeve, C. D. C. 1988. Philosopher-Kings: Robb, Kevin. 1994. Literacy and Paideia in
The Argument of Plato’s Republic. Ancient Greece. Oxford.
Princeton. Robin, Léon. 1908. La Théorie
Reisman, David. 2004. ‘Plato’s Republic Platonicienne des Idées et des Nombres
in a Newly Discovered Passage’, Arabic D´après Aristote. Paris.
Sciences and Philosophy. 14, 263–300. — 1964. La Théorie Platonicienne de
Rexine, John E. 1985. ‘Daimon in classical L’amour (2nd edn). Paris.
Greek literature’, Platon. 37, 29–52. Robinson, David B. 1986. ‘Plato’s Lysis:
Richard, Marie-Dominique. 1986. The Structural Problem’, Illinois Classical
L´enseignement Orale de Platon (1st Studies. 11, 63–83.
edn). Paris. Robinson, Richard. 1953. Plato’s Earlier
Richardson, Henry S. 1990. ‘Measurement, Dialectic. Oxford.
Pleasure, and Practical Science in Plato’s — 1966. Plato’s Earlier Dialectic (2nd edn).
Protagoras’, Journal of the History of Oxford.
Philosophy. 28, 7–32. Robinson, Thomas. 1995. Plato’s
Richardson, Nicholas. 1975. ‘Homeric Psychology (2nd edn). Toronto.
Professors in the Age of the Sophists’, Rogers, G. A. J., J.-M. Vienne and Y.-C.
Proceedings of the Cambridge Zarka (eds). 1997. The Cambridge
Philological Society. 21, 65–81. Platonists in Philosophical Context:

337

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 337 3/16/2012 9:48:00 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Politics, Metaphysics and Religion. in the Lysis’, Archiv für Geschichte der
Dordrecht. Philosophie. 77, 1–20.
Roochnik, David. 1984. ‘The Riddle of Rowe, Christopher. 1986. ‘The argument
the Cleitophon’, Ancient Philosophy. 4, and structure of Plato’s Phaedrus’,
132–45. Proceedings of the Cambridge
— 1996. Of Art and Wisdom: Plato’s Philological Society. 32, 106–25.
Understanding of Techne. University Park. — 1990. ‘Philosophy, Love, and Madness’,
— 2003. Beautiful City: The Dialectical in Christopher Gill (ed.), The Person and
Character of Plato’s Republic. Ithaca and the Human Mind. Oxford, pp. 227–46.
London. — 1993. Plato Phaedo. Cambridge.
Rorty, Richard. 1979. Philosophy in the — 1995. ‘Introduction’, in Christopher J.
Mirror of Nature. Princeton. Rowe (ed.) Plato: Statesman. Warminster,
Rösel, Martin. 1994. Übersetzung als pp. 1–20.
Vollendung der Auslegung: Studien zur — 2006. ‘Interpreting Plato’, in Hugh
Genesis Septuaginta. Berlin. Benson (ed.), A Companion to Plato.
Rosen, Stanley. 1983. Plato’s Sophist: The Malden, pp. 13–24.
Drama of Original and Image. New Rudebusch, George. 1999. Socrates,
Haven (repr. in 1999, South Bend). Pleasure, and Value. Oxford.
— 1988. The Quarrel between Philosophy — 2002. ‘Dramatic Prefiguration in Plato’s
and Poetry. New York. Republic’, Philosophy and Literature. 26,
— 2005. Plato’s Republic: A Study. New 75–83.
Haven. — 2004. ‘True Love Requited: the Argument
Rosenstock, Bruce. 1994. ‘Socrates as of Lysis 221d–222a’, Ancient Philosophy.
Revenant: A Reading of the Menexenus’, 24, 1–14.
Phoenix. 48, 331–47. Runia, David T. 1986. Philo of Alexandria
Rosenthal, Erwin. 2010. ‘Torah and and the Timaeus of Plato. Leiden.
nomos in medieval Jewish philosophy’, — 1993a. Philo in Early
Judaism, Philosophy, Culture, Selected Christian Literature: A Survey.
Studies by E I J Rosenthal. London, Assen- Minneapolis.
pp. 309–24. — 1993b. ‘Was Philo a Middle Platonist? a
Rosenthal, Franz. 1940. ‘On the Knowledge Difficult Question Revisited’, The Studia
of Plato’s Philosophy in the Islamic Philonica Annual. 5, 112–40.
World’, Islamic Culture. 14, 387–422. Russell, Daniel C. 2005. Plato on Pleasure
— 1941. ‘Addenda’, Islamic Culture. 15, and the Good Life. Oxford.
396–8. Rutherford, Richard B. 1995. The Art
Ross, W. D. 1924. Aristotle’s Metaphysics: of Plato: Ten Essays in Platonic
A Revised Text with Introduction and Interpretation. London.
Commentary. Oxford. Ryle, Gilbert. 1939a. ‘Plato’s Parmenides’,
— 1951. Plato’s Theory of Ideas. Oxford. in R. E. Allen (ed.), Studies in Plato’s
— 1955. Aristotelis Fragmenta Selecta. Metaphysics. London, pp. 97–147.
Oxford. — 1939b. ‘Plato’s Parmenides’, Mind. 48,
Roth, Michael. 1995. ‘Did Plato Nod? Some 129–51 and 302–25.
Conjectures on Egoism and Friendship — 1949. The Concept of Mind. New York.

338

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 338 3/16/2012 9:48:00 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

— 1960. ‘Letters and Syllables in Plato’, Political Thought of Plato’, Political


Philosophical Review. 69, 431–51. Theory. 4, 195–212.
— 1966. Plato’s Progress. Cambridge. Sayre, Kenneth M. 1969. Plato’s Analytic
Sachs, David. 1963. ‘A Fallacy in Plato’s Method. Chicago.
Republic?’ Philosophical Review. 72, — 1983. Plato’s Late Ontology: A Riddle
141–58. Resolved. Princeton (expanded edition
Saffrey, H. D. 2007. ‘Retour sur le Las Vegas, 2005).
Parisinus Graecus 1807: le manuscrit — 1992. ‘A Maieutic View of Five Late
A de Platon’, in C. d’Ancona (ed.), The Dialogues’, in James C. Klagge and
Libraries of the Neoplatonists. Leiden, Nicholas D. Smith (eds), Methods of
pp. 3–28. Interpreting Plato and His Dialogues.
Salkever, Stephen G. 1993. ‘Socrates’ Oxford, pp. 221–43.
Aspasian Oration: The Play of Philosophy — 1995a. Plato’s Literary Garden: How to
and Politics in Plato’s Menexenus’, Read a Platonic Dialogue. Notre Dame.
American Political Science Review. 87, — 1995b. ‘Why Plato Never Had a Theory
133–43. of Forms’, in John J. Cleary and William
Sallis, John. 1996. Being and Logos: Wians (eds), Proceedings of the Boston
Reading the Platonic Dialogues. Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy,
Indianapolis. Vol. IX. Boston, pp. 167–99.
— 2004. Platonic Legacies. Albany. — 2002. ‘The Multilayered Incoherence
Santas, Gerasimos X. 1972. ‘The Socratic of Timaeus’ Receptacle’, in Gretchen
Fallacy’, Journal of the History of Reydams–Schils (ed.), Plato’s Timaeus as
Philosophy. 10, 127–41. Cultural Icon. Notre Dame, pp. 60–79.
— 1973. ‘Socrates at Work on Virtue — 2005. Plato’s Late Ontology: A Riddle
and Knowledge in Plato’s Charmides’, Resolved. Parmenides.
in Edward N. Lee, Alexander P. D. — 2006. Metaphysics and Method in Plato’s
Mourelatos, and Richard M. Rorty (eds), Statesman. Cambridge.
Exegesis and Argument. New York, Schaper, Eva. 1968. Prelude to Aesthetics.
pp. 105–32. London.
— 1985. ‘Two Theories of Good in Plato’s Schenke, Stefan. 1985. ‘Der Logik des
Republic’, Archiv für Geschichte der Rückstiegs’, Philosophisches Jahrbuch.
Philosophie, 67, 223–45. 92, 316–34.
— 1988. Plato and Freud: Two Theories of Schiappa, Edward. 1991. Protagoras and
Love. Oxford. Logos. Columbia.
Saunders, Trevor J. 1962. ‘The Structure of — 1994. ‘Plato and hê kaloumenê rhêtorikê:
State and Soul in Plato’s Laws’, Eranos. A Response to O’Sullivan’, Mnemosyne.
9, 37–55. 47, 512–14.
— 1994. Plato’s Penal Code. Oxford. — 2003. Protagoras and Logos: A Study
Saunders, Trevor J. and Luc Brisson. 2000. in Greek Philosophy and Rhetoric.
Bibliography on Plato’s Laws. Sankt Columbia.
Augustin. Schindler, D. C. 2008. Plato’s Critique of
Saxonhouse, Arlene. 1976. ‘The Impure Reason. On Goodness and Truth
Philosopher and the Female in the in the Republic. Washington DC.

339

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 339 3/16/2012 9:48:00 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Schleiermacher, Friedrich. 1828. Reimer – Sedley, David. 1989. ‘Is the Lysis a
The ‘Einleitung’, Platons Werke III. i Dialogue of Definition?’ Phronesis. 34,
Der Staat. Berlin (trans. Dobson, Berlin, 107–8.
pp. 350–415) — 1990. ‘The Dramatis Personae of Plato’s
— 1836. Schleiermacher’s Introductions Phaedo’, in T. Smiley (ed.), Philosophical
to the Dialogues of Plato (trans. Dialogues: Plato, Hume, Wittgenstein.
W. Dobson). Cambridge, pp. 1–47. Proceedings of the British Academy 85.
Schlick, Moritz. 1937. ‘L’École de Vienne Oxford, pp. 3–26.
et la philosophie traditionnelle’, in — 1997. ‘Becoming like God in the Timaeus
Travaux, du IXe congrès international de and Aristotle’, in Tomás Calvo and Luc
philosophie, IV. Paris, pp. 99–107. Brisson (eds), Interpreting the Timaeus-
Schmid, Walter T. 1992. On Manly Courage: Critias. Sankt Augustin.
A Study of Plato’s Laches. Carbondale. — 1998. ‘Platonic Causes’, Phronesis. 43,
— 1997. Plato’s Charmides and the Socratic 114–32.
Ideal of Rationality. Albany. — 1999. ‘The Ideal of Godlikeness’, in
Scolnicov, Samuel. 1971. ‘On the Gail Fine (ed.), Plato. Vol. II: Ethics,
Epistemological Significance of Plato’s Politics, Religion, and the Soul. Oxford,
Theory of Ideal Numbers’, Museum pp. 309–28.
Helveticum. 28, 72–97. — 2003. Plato’s Cratylus. Cambridge.
— 1976. ‘Three Aspects of Plato’s — 2004. The Midwife of Platonism: Text
Philosophy of Learning and Instruction’, and Subtext in Plato’s Theaetetus.
Paideia. 5, 50–62. Oxford.
— 1988. Plato’s Metaphysics of Education. — 2007a. Creationism and its Critics in
London and New York. Antiquity. Berkeley, Los Angeles and
— 1994. ‘Derrida’s drug and Plato’s London.
antidote: Socratic dialogue as moral — 2007b. ‘Philosophy, the Forms, and the
philosophy’, in L. Toker (ed.), Reflective Art of Ruling’, in G. R. F. Ferrari (ed.),
Commitment: Essays in Literature and The Cambridge Companion to Plato’s
Moral Philosophy. New York, pp. 3–23. Republic. Cambridge, pp. 256–83.
— 2003. Plato’s Parmenides. Berkeley. — 2008a. ‘The Ideal of Godlikeness’, in
— 2004. ‘Plato’s ethics of irony’, in M. Gail Fine (ed.), Plato. Oxford Readings in
Migliori (ed.), Plato Ethicus. Sankt Philosophy. Oxford, pp. 791–810.
Augustin. — 2008b. Creationism and its Critics in
Scott, Dominic. 1990. Recollection and Antiquity. Berkeley.
Explanation: Plato’s Theory of Learning — 2009a. ‘Myth, punishment, and politics
and its Successors. Cambridge. in the Gorgias’, in C. Partenie (ed.),
— 2006. Plato’s Meno. Cambridge. Plato’s Myths. Cambridge, pp. 51–76.
Scott, Gary A. 2002. Does Socrates have — 2009b. ‘A Thrasyllan Interpretation of
a Method?: Rethinking the Elenchus in Theaetetus’, Papyri Oxyrhynchus. LXXIII
Plato’s Dialogues and Beyond. University 4941, 65–71.
Park. Seel, Gerhard. 2006. ‘If you Know What is
— (ed.). 2007. Philosophy in Dialogue: Best, you Do it: Socratic Intellectualism
Plato’s Many Devices. Evanston. in Xenophon and Plato’, in L. Judson

340

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 340 3/16/2012 9:48:00 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

and V. Karasmanis (eds), Remembering Silverman, Allan. 2002. The Dialectic of


Socrates. Oxford, pp. 20–49. Essence: A Study of Plato’s Metaphysics.
— 2007. ‘Is Plato’s Conception of the Princeton.
Form of the Good Contradictory?’ Simon, Gérard. 1988. Le Regard, L’être
in Douglas Cairns, Fritz-Gregor et l’Apparence dans l’Optique de
Herrmann, and Terry Penner (eds), l’Antiquité. Paris.
Pursuing the Good, Ethics and Sinaiko, Herman L. 1965. Love, Knowledge,
Metaphysics in Plato’s Republic. and Discourse in Plato: Dialogue
Edinburgh, pp. 168–96. and Dialectic in Phaedrus, Republic,
Segal, Charles. 1962. ‘Gorgias and the Parmenides. Chicago.
Psychology of Logos’, Harvard Studies in Singpurwalla, Rachel. 2005. ‘Plato’s
Classical Philology. 66, 99–155. Defense of Justice’, in G. Santas (ed.),
Segvic, Heda. 2002. ‘No One Errs Willingly: The Blackwell Guide to Plato’s Republic.
The Meaning of Socratic Intellectualism’, Oxford, pp. 263–82.
Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy. Slings, Simon. R. 1975. ‘Some Remarks
19, 1–46. on Aeschines’ Miltiades’, in Zeitschrift
Sharma, Ravi. 2009. ‘Socrates’ New Aitia: für Papyrologie und Epigraphik 16.
Causal and Metaphysical Explanations pp. 301–8.
in Plato’s Phaedo’, Oxford Studies in — 1981. A Commentary on the Platonic
Ancient Philosophy. 36, 137–77. Clitophon. Amsterdam.
Sharples, R. W. (trans.). 1985. Plato: Meno. — 1999. Plato: Clitophon. Cambridge.
Chicago. Slings, Simon R., Gerard Boter and J. M.
Shaw, Gregory. 1995. Theurgy and the van Ophuijsen. 2005. Critical Notes on
Soul: The Neoplatonism of Iamblichus. Plato’s Politeia. Leiden.
University Park. Smith, Andrew. 1974. Porphyry’s Place in
Shorey, Paul. 1903. The Unity of Plato’s the Neoplatonic Tradition–A Study in
Thought. Chicago. Post-Plotinian Neoplatonism. The Hague.
— 1924. ‘Review of Stenzel 1924’, Classical Smith, Imogen. 2008. ‘False Names,
Philology. 19, 381–3. Demonstratives and the Refutation of
— (trans.). 1930. Plato: The Republic, Linguistic Naturalism in Plato’s Cratylus
Books 1–5. Cambridge. 427d1–431c3’, Phronesis. 53, 125–51.
— 1933. What Plato Said. Chicago. Smith, Nicholas D. 1979. ‘Knowledge by
— (trans.). 1937. Plato: The Republic. Acquaintance and Knowing What in
Cambridge. Plato’s Republic’, Dialogue. 18, 281–8.
Shortridge, Andrew. 2007. ‘Law and Nature — 1996. ‘Plato’s Divided Line’, Ancient
in Protagoras’ Great Speech’, Polis. 24, Philosophy. 16, 25–46.
12–25. — 2000. ‘Plato on Knowledge as a Power’,
Sickinger, James P. 1999. Public Records Journal of the History of Philosophy. 38,
& Archives in Classical Athens. Chapel 145–68.
Hill. — 2004. ‘Did Plato Write the Alcibiades I?’
Sider, David. 1977. ‘Plato’s Early Aesthetics: Apeiron. 37, 93–108.
The Hippias Major’, Journal of Aesthetics Socher, Joseph. 1820. Über Platons
and Art Criticism. 35, 465–70. Schriften. Munich.

341

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 341 3/16/2012 9:48:00 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Solmsen, Friedrich. 1975. Intellectual — (dir.). 2002. ‘Proclus: Fifteen Years of


Experiments of the Greek Enlightenment. Research (1990–2004). An Annotated
Princeton. Bibliography’, Lustrum. 44, 1–367.
— 1981. ‘The Academic and the Stefanini, Luigi. 1932. Platone. Padua (2nd
Alexandrian Editions of Plato’s Works’, edn, repr. Padua, 1991).
Illinois Classical Studies. 6, 102–11. Stenzel, Julius. 1924. Zahl und Gestalt
Sommerstein, A. H. (ed.). 1982. bei Platon und Aristoteles. Berlin and
Aristophanes: Clouds. Warminster. Leipzig.
— (ed.). 1987. Aristophanes: Birds. — 1928. Platon der Ezieher. Leipzig.
Warminster. — 1973. Plato’s Method of Dialectic (trans.
Sparshott, Francis E. 1966. ‘Socrates and D. J. Allen). New York.
Thrasymachus’, Monist. 50, 421–59. Stern, Paul. 1993. Socratic Rationalism and
Sprague, Rosamond Kent. 1962. Political Philosophy. Albany.
Plato’s Use of Fallacy: A Study of the — 1999. ‘Tyranny and Self-Knowledge:
Euthydemus and Some Other Dialogues. Critias and Socrates in Plato’s
London. Charmides’, American Political science
— (trans.). 1965. Plato: Euthydemus. New Review. 93, 399–412.
York. — 2008. Knowledge and Politics in Plato’s
— (ed). 1972. The Older Sophists. Theaetetus. Cambridge.
Columbia (repr. in Indianapolis, 2001). Stern-Gillet, Suzanne. 2004. ‘On (mis)
Stalley, R. F. 2000. ‘Sôphrosynê in interpreting Plato’s Ion’, Phronesis. 49,
the Charmides’, in Thomas M. 169–201.
Robinson (ed.), Plato: Euthydemus, Strauss, Leo. 1975. The Argument and the
Lysis Charmides: Proceedings of the Action of Plato’s Laws. Chicago.
V’Symposium Platonicum. Sankt — 1989. The Rebirth of Classical Political
Augustin, pp. 265–77. Rationalism. Chicago.
— 2009. ‘Myth and Eschatology in the — 2003. Leo Strauss on Plato’s Symposium.
Laws’, in C. Partenie (ed.), Plato’s Myths. Seth Bernadete (ed.). Chicago.
Cambridge, pp. 187–205. Striker, Gisela. 1970. Peras und Apeiron:
Stauffer, Devin. 2001. Plato’s Introduction Das Problem der Formen in Platons
to the Question of Justice. Albany. Philebos. Göttingen.
— 2006. The Unity of Plato’s Gorgias. Strohmaier, Gerhard. 2002. ‘Platon in
Cambridge. der arabischen Tradition’, Würzburger
Steel, Carlos G. 1978. The Changing Self. A Jahrbücher für die Altertumswissenschaft,
Study on the Soul in later Neoplatonism: Neue Folge. 26, 185–200.
Iamblichus, Damascius, and Priscianus. Struck, Peter. 2004. Birth of the Symbol:
Brussels. Ancient Readers at the Limits of their
— 1990. ‘Plato Latinus (1939–1989)’, Texts. Princeton.
in Rencontres de Cultures dans la Surányi, László. 1999. Metaaxiomatische
Philosophie Médiévale: Traductions Probleme. Frankfurt am Main.
et Traducteurs de l’Antiquité Tardive Susemihl, Franz. 1855–7. Die genetische
au XIVe Siècle. Louvain-la-Neuve, Entwicklung der Platonischen
pp. 301–16. Philosophie. Leipzig.

342

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 342 3/16/2012 9:48:00 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Szlezák, Thomas A. 1985. Platon und die Institute of Classical Studies Suppl.
Schriftlichkeit der Philosophie. Berlin and London, pp. 419–29.
New York. — 2008. ‘The Dramatic Setting of the
— 1993. ‘Zur üblichen Abneigung gegen die Arguments with Callicles, Euripides
Agrapha Dogmata’ Methexis. 6, 155–74. Antiope, and the Date of an Athenian
[English trans. 2001. ‘On the Standard Anti-Intellectual Argument’, Antichthon
Aversion to the Agrapha dogmata’, 4, 20–39.
Graduate faculty Philosophy Journal 22, — 2009. ‘The Object of Alcibiades’ Love’,
147–63.] Literature and Aesthetics 19, 74–87.
— 1999. Reading Plato. London and — 2010. ‘The Theaetetus as a Narrative
New York. Dialogue?’ Australasian Society for
— 2004. Das Bild des Dialektikers in Cognitive Science Proceedings. 31. http://
Platons späten Dialogen. Berlin and www.classics.uwa.edu.au/ascs31.
New York. Tate, Jonathan. 1929. ‘Plato and Allegorical
Taran, Leonardo. 1981. Speusippus of Interpretation’, Classical Quarterly. 23,
Athens. Leiden. 142–54.
Tarrant, Dorothy. 1928. The Hippias Major, — 1939. ‘On the History of Allegorism’,
Attributed to Plato. Cambridge. Classical Quarterly 28, 105–19.
— 1952. ‘Metaphors of Death in the Taylor, A. E. 1926. ‘Review of Stenzel 1924’,
Phaedo’, The Classical Review. n.s. 2, Gnomon. 2, 396–405.
64–6. — 1926–7. ‘Forms and Numbers: A Study in
— 1960. ‘Greek Metaphors of Light’, Platonic Metaphysics’, Mind. 35, 419–40
Classical Quarterly. 10, 181–7. and 36, 12–33.
Tarrant, Harold. 1982. ‘The Composition of — 1934. The ‘Parmenides’ of Plato.
Plato’s Gorgias’, Prudentia. 14, 3–22. Oxford.
— 1993. Thrasyllan Platonism. Ithaca and — 1960. Plato: The Man and his Work.
London. London.
— 2000. Plato’s First Interpreters. London. Taylor, C. C. W. 1969. ‘Forms as Causes in
— 2005. ‘Socratic Synousia: A Post- the Phaedo’, Mind. 78, 45–59.
Platonic Myth?’ Journal of the History of — 1976. Plato: Protagoras. Oxford.
Philosophy. 43, 131–55. — 1982. ‘The End of the Euthyphro’,
— 2006. ‘Socratic Method and Socratic Phronesis. 27, 109–18.
Truth’, in Sara Ahbel-Rappe and Rachana — 2008. ‘Plato’s Epistemology’, in Gail Fine
Kamtekar (eds), A Companion to (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Plato.
Socrates. Malden, pp. 254–72. Oxford, pp. 165–90.
— 2007a. ‘Olympiodorus and Proclus Tecuşan, Manuela. 1992. ‘Speaking about
on the Climax of the Alcibiades’, the Unspeakable: Plato’s Use of Imagery’,
International Journal of the Platonic in Andrew Barker and Martin Warner
Tradition 1, 3–29. (eds), The Language of the Cave.
— 2007b. ‘Moral Goal and Moral Virtues Edmonton.
in Middle Platonism’, in Robert Sharples Tejera, Victorino. 1984. Plato’s Dialogues
and Richard Sorabji (eds), Philosophy One by One. New York (repr. New York,
100 BC to AD 200. Bulletin of the 1998).

343

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 343 3/16/2012 9:48:00 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

— 1990. ‘On the Form and Authenticity — 1977. Interpreting Plato. Uppsala.
of the Lysis’, Ancient Philosophy. 10, Tomin, Julius. 1997. ‘Plato’s first dialogue’,
173–91. Ancient Philosophy. 17, 31–45.
Temko, Philipp and Julia Moravscsik (eds). Trendelenburg, Adolf. 1837. De Platonis
1982. Plato on Beauty, Wisdom and the Philibi Consilio. Berlin.
Arts. Totowa. — 1840. Logische Untersuchungen. Berlin.
Tennemann, Wilhelm Gottlieb. 1792–5. Trendelenburg, F. A. 1826. Platonis de
System der Platonischen Philosophie I. Ideis et Numeris Doctrina ex Aristotele
Leipzig. Illustrata. Leipzig.
Thayer, H. S. 1975. ‘Plato’s Quarrel with Trevaskis, J. R. 1967. ‘Division and its
Poetry: Simonides’, Journal of the History relation to dialectic and ontology in
of Ideas. 36, 3–26. Plato’, Phronesis. 12, 118–29.
Thesleff, Holger. 1967. Studies in the Styles Trivigno, Franco V. 2009. ‘The Rhetoric of
of Plato. Helsinki (repr. in Platonic Parody in Plato’s Menexenus’, Philosophy
Patterns. Las Vegas 2009, pp. 1–142). and Rhetoric. 42, 29–58.
— 1982. Studies in Platonic Chronology. Tschemplik, Andrea. 2008. Knowledge and
Helsinki (repr. in Platonic Patterns. Las Self-Knowledge in Plato’s Theaetetus.
Vegas 2009, pp. 143–382). Lanham.
— 1990. ‘Theaitetos and Theodoros’, Tsouna, Voula. 1997. ‘Socrates’ attack
Arctos. 24, 147–59 (repr. in Platonic on intellectualism in the Charmides’,
Patterns. Las Vegas 2009, pp. 509–18). Apeiron. 30, 63–78.
— 1993. ‘Looking for Clues: An Tuozzo, Thomas M. 2000. ‘Greetings from
Interpretation of Some Literary Aspects Apollo: Charmides 164c–165b, Epistle
of Plato’s “Two-Level Model,”’ in Gerald III and the Structure of the Charmides’,
A. Press (ed.), Plato’s Dialogues: New in Thomas M. Robinson (ed.), Plato:
Studies & Interpretations. Lanham, Euthydemus, Lysis, Charmides:
pp. 17–45. Proceedings of the V’Symposium
— 1997. ‘The Early Version of Plato’s Platonicum. Sankt Augustin, pp. 296–305.
Republic’, Arctos. 31, 149–74 (repr. — 2001. ‘What’s Wrong with These Cities?
as Platonic Patterns. Las Vegas 2009, The Social Dimension of Sophrosyne in
pp. 519–39). Plato’s Charmides’, Journal of the History
— 1999. Studies in Plato’s Two-Level of Philosophy. 39, 321–50.
Model. Helsinki (repr. in Platonic Überweg, Friedrich. 1861. Untersuchungen
Patterns. Las Vegas 2009, pp. 383–497). über die Echtheit und Zeitfolge
Thomas, Rosalind. 1992. Literacy and Platonischer Schriften und über die
Orality in Ancient Greece. Cambridge. Hauptmomente aus Plato’s Leben.
Thompson, E. S. 1901. The Meno of Plato. Vienna.
London. Untersteiner, Mario. 1954. The Sophists
Thompson, W. H. 1868. The Phaedrus of (trans. Kathleen Freeman). Oxford.
Plato. London. Usener, Sylvia. 1994. Isokrates, Platon
Tigerstedt, E. N. 1970. ‘Plato’s Idea of und ihr Publikum: Hörer und Leser
Poetical Inspiration’, Commentationes von Literatur im 4. Jahrhundert v. Chr.
Humanarum Litterarum. 44, 18–20. (ScriptOralia 63). Tübingen.

344

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 344 3/16/2012 9:48:00 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Van den Berg, Robbert M. 2008. Proclus’ — 1967. ‘Was Polus refuted?’ American
Commentary on the Cratylus in Context: Journal of Philology. 88, 454–60.
Ancient Theories of Language and — 1969. ‘Reasons and Causes in the Phaedo’,
Naming. Leiden. Philosophical Review. 78, 291–325.
Van Eck, Job. 1994. ‘Skopein en logois: on — 1971a. ‘Introduction’, in Gregory
Phaedo 99d–103c’, Ancient Philosophy. Vlastos (ed.), Plato II: Ethics, Politics and
14, 21–40. Philosophy of Art and Religion. Garden
Vander Waerdt, P. A. (ed.). 1994a. The City, pp. vii–xi.
Socratic Movement. Ithaca. — 1971b. ‘Justice and Happiness in the
— 1994b. ‘Socrates in the Clouds’, in P. Republic’, in Gregory Vlastos (ed.), Plato:
A. Vander Waerdt (ed.), The Socratic A Collection of Critical Essays. Vol. II.
Movement. Ithaca. Garden City, pp. 66–95.
Vasiliu, Anca. 1997. Du Diaphane. Image, — 1971c. ‘The Paradox of Socrates’, in
Milieu, Lumière dans la Pensée Antique et Gregory Vlastos (ed.), The Philosophy of
Médiévale. Paris. Socrates. New York, pp. 1–21.
Velardi, Roberto. 1989. Enthousiasmòs: — 1972. ‘The Unity of the Virtues in the
Possessione Rituale e Teoria Della Protagoras’, Review of Metaphysics. 25,
Comunicazione Poetica in Platone. Rome. 415–58
Verdenius, W. J. 1962. ‘Der Begriff der — 1974. ‘Socrates on Political Obedience
Mania in Platons Phaidros’, Archiv and Disobedience’, Yale Review. 63,
für Geschichte der Philosophie. 44, 517–34.
132–50. — (ed.). 1978a. Plato I, A Collection
— 1983. ‘The Principles of Greek Literary of Critical Essays: Metaphysics and
Criticism’, Mnemosyne. 36, 14–59. Epistemology. Notre Dame.
Vernant, J.-P. 1980. Myth and Society in — (ed.). 1978b. Plato II, A Collection of
Greek Thought. Atlantic Highlands. Critical Essays: Ethics, Politics, and
Vicaire, Paul. 1960. Platon: critique Philosophy of Art and Religion. Notre
littéraire. Paris. Dame.
Vidal-Naquet, Pierre. 1981. ‘Athènes et — 1981. ‘Degrees of Reality in Plato’, in
l’Atlantide’, in Pierre Vidal-Naquet, Le Gregory Vlastos, Platonic Studies (2nd
Chasseur Noir: Formes de Pensée et edn). Princeton, pp. 58–75.
Formes de Société dans le Monde Grec. — 1983. ‘The Socratic Elenchus’, Oxford
Paris, pp. 335–60. Studies in Ancient Philosophy. 1, 27–58
Vlastos, Gregory. 1954. ‘The Third (repr. in Fine, Gail (ed.). Plato I: Oxford
Man Argument in the Parmenides’, Readings in Philosophy. New York and
Philosophical Review. 63, 319–49 Oxford. 1999).
(repr. as Allen, R. E. (ed.). 1965. — 1985. ‘Socrates’ Disavowal of
Studies in Plato’s Metaphysics. London, Knowledge’, Philosophical Quarterly. 35,
pp. 231–63). 1–31.
— 1965. ‘Creation in the Timaeus: is it — 1987. ‘Socratic Irony’, Classical
a fiction?’ in Reginald E. Allen (ed.), Quarterly. 37, 79–80.
Studies in Plato’s Metaphysics. London — 1988. ‘Socrates’, Proceedings of the
and New York, pp. 401–19. British Academy. 74, 87–111.

345

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 345 3/16/2012 9:48:00 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

— 1991a. Socrates: Ironist and Moral Weiss, Roslyn. 1981. ‘Ho agathos as Ho
Philosopher. Ithaca. dunatos in the Hippias Minor’, Classical
— 1991b. ‘Elenchus and Mathematics’, Quarterly. 21, 287–304 (reprinted of
in Vlastos, Gregory. Socrates: Ironist New York, Essays on the Philosophy of
and Moral Philosopher. Cambridge, Socrates).
pp. 107–31 (repr. of American Journal of — 1998. Socrates Dissatisfied: An Analysis
Philology. 109, 362–96). of Plato’s Crito. Oxford.
— 1997. ‘Was Plato a Feminist?’ in Richard — 2001. Virtue in the Cave: Moral Inquiry
Kraut (ed.), Plato’s Republic: Critical in Plato’s Meno. New York.
Essays. Lanham. Welliver, Warman. 1977. Character, Plot
— 1999. ‘Happiness and virtue in Socrates’ and Thought in Plato’s Timaeus-Critias.
moral theory’, in G. Fine (ed.), Plato 2: Leiden.
Ethics, Politics, Religion and the Soul. Wender, Dorothea. 1973. ‘Plato: Misogenist,
Oxford, pp. 105–63. Paedophile and Feminist’, Arethusa. 6,
Vogt, Heinrich. 1909–10. ‘Die 75–80.
Entdeckungsgeschichte des Irrationalen Wersinger, A. Gabrièle. 2001. Platon et la
nach Plato und anderen Quellen des 4. Dysharmonie: Recherches sur la Forme
Jahrhunderts’, Bibliotheca Mathematica. musicale. Paris.
10, 97–155. — 2007. ‘Socrate, fais de la musique! Le destin
Wagner, Ellen (ed). 2001. Essays in Plato’s de la musique entre paideia et philosophie’,
Psychology. Lanham. in Florence Malhomme and A. Gabrièle
Walbridge, John. 2000. The Leaven of the Wersinger (eds), Mousikè et Aretè: La
Ancients: Suhrawardî and the Heritage of Musique et l’Ethique de l’Antiquité à l’Âge
the Greeks. Albany. moderne. Paris, pp. 45–62.
Walker, Paul. 1994. ‘Platonisms in Islamic — 2008a. ‘Pourquoi dans la République de
Philosophy’, Studia Islamica. 79, 5–25. Platon, l’Harmonique est-elle la Science
Wallis, R. T. 1972. Neoplatonism. London. Propédeutique la plus haute? Perspective
Walzel, Oskar. 1908. Deutsche Romantik. Nouvelle sur une Question Négligée’,
Leipzig. in Jean-Luc Périllié (ed.), ‘Platon et les
Watts, Edward J. 2006. City and School in Pythagoriciens, Hierarchie des savoirs et
Late Antiquity: Athens and Alexandria. des pratiques’, Cahiers de Philosophie
Berkeley. Ancienne. 20, 159–80 and 171–3.
Waugh, Joanne. 1995. ‘Neither Published — 2008b. La Sphère et l’Intervalle: Le Schème
nor Perished: The Dialogues as Speech, de l’Harmonie dans la Pensée des Anciens
Not Text’, in Francisco Gonzalez (ed.), Grecs d’Homère à Platon. Grenoble.
The Third Way: New Directions in — 2011. ‘De ‘l’Âme-Harmonie’ et
Platonic Studies. Lanham, pp. 61–77. du “Corps-Lyre” au paradoxe du
Wedberg, Anders. 1955. Plato’s Philosophy corps immortel: les aventures d’une
of Mathematics. Stockholm. métaphore, de Platon et Aristote à
Weineck, Silke-Maria. 2002. The Abyss Dicéarque de Messène’, in Florence
Above: Poetic and Philosophical Madness Malhomme and Elisabetta Villari (eds),
in Plato, Hoelderlin, and Nietzsche. Buffalo. Musica Corporis, Savoirs et Arts du

346

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 346 3/16/2012 9:48:00 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

corps, de l’Antiquité à l’âge Humaniste Wilkes, Kathleen. 1979. ‘Conclusions in


et Classique. Turnhout. the Meno’, Archiv für Geschichte der
West, M. L. 1992. Ancient Greek Music. Philosophie. 61, 143–53.
Oxford. Wilson, J. R. S. 1995. ‘Thrasymachus and
White, David A. 1993. Rhetoric and Reality the Thumos: A Further Case of Prolepsis
in Plato’s Phaedrus. Albany. in Republic 1’, Classical Quarterly. 45,
— 2007. Myth, Metaphysics and Dialectic 58–67.
in Plato’s Statesman. Farnham. Winston, David. 1979. The Wisdom of
White, F. C. 1989. ‘Love and Beauty in Solomon. New York.
Plato’s Symposium’, The Journal of Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1958. Philosophical
Hellenic Studies. 109, 149–57. Investigations (trans. G. E. M.
— 2006. ‘Socrates, Philosophers and Death: Anscombe). New York.
Two Contrasting Arguments in Plato’s Wolfsdorf, David. 2006. ‘The Ridiculousness
Phaedo’, The Classical Quarterly. 56, of Being Overcome by Pleasure:
445–58. Protagoras 352b1–358d4’, Oxford
White, Michael. 2006. ‘Plato and Studies in Ancient Philosophy. 31,
Mathematics’, in Hugh Benson (ed.), A 113–36.
Companion to Plato. Oxford, pp. 228–43. Woodbridge, Frederick J. E. 1929. The Son
White, Nicholas P. 1976. Plato on of Apollo. New York.
Knowledge and Reality. Indianapolis. Woodruff, Paul (trans.). 1982. Plato:
— 1979. A Companion to Plato’s Republic. Hippias Major. Indianapolis.
Indianapolis. — 1990. ‘Plato’s Early Theory of
— (trans.). 1993. Plato: Sophist. Indianapolis. Knowledge’ in Stephen Everson (ed.),
— 2002. Individual and Conflict in Greek Companions to Ancient Thought: 1
Ethics. Oxford. Epistemology. Cambridge, pp. 60–84.
Whitman, John. 1986. Allegory: The Woozley, A. D. 1971, 1980. ‘Socrates on
Dynamics of an Ancient and Medieval Disobeying the Law’, in G. Vlastos (ed.),
Technique. Oxford. The Philosophy of Socrates. Notre Dame,
Wieland, Georg. 1985. ‘Plato oder pp. 299–318.
Aristoteles? Überlegungen zur Aristoteles- Wundt, Max. 1935. Platons ‘Parmenides’.
Rezeption des lateinischen Mittelalters’, Berlin.
in Tijdschrift voor filosofie. 47, Young, Charles M. 1994. ‘Plato and
pp. 605–30. Computer Dating’, Oxford Studies in
Wilcox, Joel F. 1987. ‘Cross-Metamorphosis Ancient Philosophy. 12, 227–50.
in Plato’s Ion’, in Donald G. Marschall — 1997. ‘First Principles of Socratic Ethics’,
(ed.), Literature as Philosophy: Apeiron. 29, 13–23.
Philosophy as Literature. Iowa City, — 2006. ‘Plato’s Crito on the Obligation to
pp. 155–74. Obey the Law’, Philosophical Inquiry. 27,
Wildberg, Christian. 2006. ‘Socrates and 79–90.
Euripides’, in S. Ahbel-Rappe and Zaidman, Louise B. and Pauline S. Pantel.
R. Kamtekar (eds), A Companion to 1992. Religion in the Ancient Greek City
Socrates. Oxford, pp. 21–35. (trans. P. Cartledge). Cambridge.

347

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 347 3/16/2012 9:48:00 AM


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Zaslavsky, Robert. 1981. Platonic Myth and Zuckert, Catherine. 2000. ‘Who’s a
Platonic Writing. Washington, DC. Philosopher? Who’s a Sophist? The
Zeller, Eduard. 1888. Plato and the Stranger v. Socrates’, The Review of
Older Academy (4th edn) (trans. S. F. Metaphysics. 54, 65–97.
Alleyne and A. Goodwin). London, — 2009. Plato’s Philosophers: The
pp. 389–1049. Coherence of the Dialogues. Chicago.
Zeyl, Donald (trans.). 2000. Plato: Timaeus.
Indianapolis.

348

9780826435354_Ref_Final_txt_print.indd 348 3/16/2012 9:48:00 AM


INDEX

Numbers in bold (e.g. 129–30) indicate important discussions.

Abelard, Peter 277, 306, 330 al-Râzî 274


Abravanel, Isaac 275 Ambrose of Milan 277
Abravanel, Judah 275 Anaxagoras 10, 11, 23, 24, 78, 143, 258, 261
Academy 1, 4, 5, 9, 10, 13, 29, 37, 49, Anaximander 26, 261
50–2, 101–2, 200, 216–17, 251, 255, anthropology 1, 13, 269
257, 260, 262–3, 264–7, 271–3, 283, antilogy 133–5, 169
287, 305 Antisthenes 10, 30–3, 53, 107, 134, 291, 306
account 6, 19, 21–2, 25, 40, 42, 44, 52, 59, aporetic dialogues 125, 167, 243
62, 65–6, 69–71, 76–8, 80, 94–7, 99, aporia 31, 59, 69, 75, 176, 243
107, 109, 121, 136, 139–43, 145, 149, appetite 28, 79, 132, 146, 157–8, 169, 186,
150–1, 153, 155–61, 163, 165, 167–9, 187, 205, 228, 239, 242
171, 173–4, 184–7, 190, 192, 194–6, Arcesilaus 37, 102, 267
197–201, 204–5, 209, 214, 216–18, Archelaus 10, 57
220–1, 224, 226, 230, 235–40, 244–5, Archilochus 20, 21
260, 262, 266, 270, 276, 279, 289, Archytas 9, 10, 26, 67, 68, 209, 324
292–6, 298, 300, 304 aretê 12, 52, 61, 62, 64, 127, 137, 138, 163,
see also definition; logos 164, 169, 171, 172, 304
Aeschines 30, 31, 32, 107 see also excellence; virtue
Aeschylus 2, 125, 153 Aristippus 10, 30, 31, 33, 276
aesthetics 62, 87, 129–30, 139, 254, 275 aristocracy 8, 13, 89, 145
aisthêsis 96, 225, 226, 227, 254 Aristophanes 3, 9, 10–12, 29–30, 37, 50, 67,
aitia 143–5, 178 94–5, 105–6, 109–10, 114, 117–18, 126,
aition 143–5 134, 164, 197–8, 221–2, 246, 292, 295
akrasia 5, 85, 131, 132, 157, 158, 170, 184, Aristotle 1, 2, 9–11, 13–15, 24–5, 28–31,
185, 263 38, 44, 54, 62, 70–1, 76, 83–4, 93, 100,
Albinus 36, 50 112, 126, 131, 134–6, 144, 159, 162,
Alcidamas 17, 242, 246, 330, 332, 334 171, 173, 175–9, 193, 209, 213–14,
Alexandrian Library 50 216–19, 225, 227, 240, 249, 258,
al-Fârâbî 273, 274 262–4, 265–7, 270–9, 284–5, 287, 289,
allegory, allegorism 91, 106, 115, 119, 145, 291–3, 295–6, 300–6
146, 171, 260, 271, 280 Aristoxenus 10, 178, 217, 300, 306

349

9780826435354_Index_Final_txt_print.indd 349 3/16/2012 9:48:57 AM


INDEX

art 1, 13, 21, 27–8, 33–5, 52–3, 57, 64–5, Carnap, Rudolf 306, 307
80, 83–4, 86, 92–3, 120, 125, 129, 130, Cassirer, Ernst 281, 285
133–4, 137–9, 161, 164, 184, 207–8, Castiglione, Baldassare 280
214, 227, 232, 236–7, 240–2, 246, 256, cause 23, 27, 41, 56, 60, 64, 77, 82, 91,
258, 260, 284–5 99, 139, 140, 143–5, 146, 150–2, 156,
see also craft; technê 176–8, 198, 213–14, 224, 241, 245,
astronomy 24, 164, 178, 200, 201, 202 250, 252, 264, 270
Athenaeus 38, 307 character (topic) 4, 10–11, 14, 23, 32–4, 36,
Augustine 277, 278, 283 44, 46, 56, 62, 64, 67, 70, 72, 81–2, 93,
authenticity 38–9, 44, 49, 60, 67–8, 71, 98, 98, 100–5, 107, 110, 112–13, 117–18,
113, 123, 282, 303 120, 122, 127–8, 138, 147–8, 149, 154,
159, 160, 163–4, 167, 172, 193, 204,
Bacon, Francis 281, 282 208, 211, 216, 220, 223, 229, 236, 242,
beauty 41, 47, 54, 79–80, 95, 108–9, 117, 244, 254, 257, 273, 279, 286, 291, 293,
120, 127, 130, 139–41, 147, 168, 173–4, 296, 298
177–8, 180, 184, 189, 194, 197–8, 202, characters(dialogue feature) 3, 4, 21, 36,
209, 219, 223, 244, 254, 298 43, 52, 61, 62, 64–5, 76, 78–80, 84, 87,
see also kalon 90, 93, 101–2, 103–5, 106–8, 113–14,
becoming 123, 141–3, 150, 223, 224 118, 121, 124, 135, 139, 147–8, 174,
being 9, 14–16, 19, 21, 23, 26, 28, 35–6, 39, 212, 223, 255, 299
40, 42–4, 49, 51–4, 56, 58–9, 61, 63–4, city 1, 2, 8–9, 12, 21–2, 29, 35, 40, 42, 59,
69, 71, 73, 75–6, 79–80, 83, 86, 90–7, 66–7, 72, 87–91, 99–100, 105–6, 114,
100, 102, 105, 107, 109–11, 120–3, 119, 128, 136, 143, 145, 147, 148–50,
126, 130–1, 136, 139–40, 141–3, 165, 173, 178, 180–1, 186–8, 191–2,
148–56, 158, 161, 163, 166, 171–3, 207, 211, 221–2, 225, 229, 233–7, 239,
176, 178, 180–2, 185–6, 189–91, 196–7, 246, 299
202, 209, 211, 213–14, 216–20, 222–6, Cohen, Hermann 56, 174, 285, 286, 314
228–30, 232, 234, 236, 239, 242–3, collection 5, 37, 47, 50, 54, 80, 113, 179,
246–9, 251–6, 258, 260, 262–4, 266–70, 205, 206–7, 217, 241, 242, 289
272–3, 275–6, 280, 283–4, 286, 289, see also division
291, 297, 299–300, 303–4, 307 comedy 10, 12, 38, 60, 95, 105, 106, 109,
belief 2, 3, 14, 37, 47, 72, 90, 114–15, 110, 113, 115, 122, 222, 265, 307
118, 124–5, 131, 134–6, 141, 143, 148, constitution 60, 65, 66, 100, 188, 189, 192,
153–4, 158, 162, 167–9, 185, 204
192, 215–16, 219, 226, 230, 238–9, contemplation 31, 95, 151, 155, 156, 179,
253, 255, 257, 261, 274, 281, 288, 230, 298
294, 297 convention 5, 32, 34, 46, 191, 199, 306
Bembo, Pietro 280 cosmology 11, 14, 26, 65, 67, 99, 139, 150,
Bergson, Henri 307 261, 269, 274, 277
Berkeley, George 282, 283, 284 cosmos 14, 20, 22, 26, 99, 100, 116, 139,
Bernard of Chartres 277 144, 150–2, 181, 202, 209, 214, 220,
Boethius 277, 306 239, 269, 270, 273
Boyle, Robert 281 courage 16, 29, 43, 55, 60, 63, 64, 65, 71,
Brentano, Franz 285 86, 110, 149, 167, 170, 181, 182, 184,
186, 192, 211, 216, 229, 233
Campbell, Lewis 287, 288, 290 craft 3, 137–9, 1, 199, 202, 214, 216,
care of the soul 247 230, 236

350

9780826435354_Index_Final_txt_print.indd 350 3/16/2012 9:48:57 AM


INDEX

see also art; technê 134, 155, 170, 172–3, 212, 217–18,
Cudworth, Ralph 281, 282, 335 226, 229, 240, 247–9, 254, 256, 261,
Cynics 31, 32, 33, 291, 306 263–5, 267–73, 275–7, 281, 285,
287–9, 295, 300–1, 303
daimôn 152, 153, 154 doxa 17, 90, 135, 162, 163, 225, 226, 227,
definition 1, 22, 23, 31, 35, 37, 55, 56, 238, 261
57, 61, 73, 83, 84, 92–3, 134–5, 167, drama 1, 5, 8, 35, 90, 105–6, 121, 122,
169, 175, 176, 184, 195, 199, 201, 205, 146, 299
217, 225, 228, 229, 232, 239, 242, 244, dramatic date 43, 44, 64, 65, 66, 87, 290
294, 306 dramatic elements 3, 299
see also account; logos dualism 77, 249, 307
Deleuze, Gilles 307 dyad 24, 175, 217, 218, 266, 300, 304
demiurge 144, 150, 151, 214, 239, 249, 252
democracy 8, 13, 27, 28, 35, 72, 89, 100, education 5, 12–13, 18, 21, 28, 35, 51, 66,
106, 236, 239, 242, 246, 308 71, 87–91, 94, 100, 103–4, 130, 136,
Democritus 24, 183, 226, 253, 322, 328 145–6, 148–9, 162, 163–5, 178, 180,
Derrida, Jacques 6, 80, 298, 307, 316, 340 191–2, 202, 209, 211, 220, 222, 226,
Derveni Papyrus 11, 261 229, 232–3, 241, 255–6, 263, 268, 284
Descartes, René 281, 282, 283, 284, 320 eidos 46, 83, 136, 228, 254
desire 17, 35, 50, 58, 61, 69, 70, 79, 82, 89, see also forms
95, 98–100, 109, 130–2, 140–1, 146–7, eikôn 130, 150, 181, 268
155, 157–8, 175–80, 186–7, 194, see also image
196–8, 200, 221, 228, 231, 238–9, 248, elenchos 137, 165, 166, 205, 206, 230
256, 262, 281, 288, 298–9, 307 see also elenchus; refutation
destiny 118, 153, 273 elenchus 8, 152, 165–7, 241
developmentalist 2, 165, 288, 295, 296 emotion 28, 63, 105, 106, 208, 211, 231, 265
dialectic 15, 17, 22, 31–2, 43, 60, 78, 84, Empedocles 23, 25, 26, 34, 142, 153, 253
89, 91, 103–4, 123, 134, 137, 148, Epicurus 13, 306, 307
159–61, 162, 168, 196, 201–2, 207, epistêmê 5, 16, 17, 32, 42, 53, 63, 135, 163,
228, 238, 241, 253, 262, 285, 289, 304 188, 199, 225, 236, 238
dialectician 53, 83, 159, 160, 161, 196, epistemology 16, 17, 42, 119, 123, 139,
257, 304 146, 167–9, 178, 218, 238, 251, 255,
Dicaearchus 10, 25, 44, 331 281, 284, 295
Diderot, Denis 305 eristic 32, 35, 52, 54, 92, 133–5
Dilthey, Wilhelm 285 erôs 6, 32, 70, 78, 79, 80, 93, 94, 95, 109,
Diogenes of Apollonia 11, 261 114, 140, 141, 164, 175, 176, 196, 197,
Dionysius the Areopagite 277 198, 204, 221, 228, 233, 245, 256, 257
divine craftsman 99, 181, 214 see also love
divine sign 98, 99, 153, 154 esoterism 9, 102, 305
see also daimôn essence 55, 56, 92, 97, 102, 160, 207, 229,
division 2, 3, 13, 37, 51, 80–1, 84, 91–2, 305, 307
113, 149, 159, 161–2, 168–9, 189, Estiénne, Henri 279
204–5, 206–7, 217, 222, 241–2, 252, ethics 8, 13, 29, 30, 51, 52, 56, 61, 62, 64,
265–6, 268, 270, 273, 289 66, 70, 111, 118–19, 139, 146, 163,
doctrine 2, 4, 14, 19, 22–3, 25–6, 30, 32, 169–71, 180, 212, 218, 255, 263, 266,
37, 42–3, 47, 50, 61, 62, 87, 101–3, 269, 281, 284
111, 115–16, 120, 123, 125–6, 130, Euclides 8, 30, 32, 33, 96, 134, 258

351

9780826435354_Index_Final_txt_print.indd 351 3/16/2012 9:48:58 AM


INDEX

eudaimonia 13, 154, 164, 169, 172, 179–80 140, 144–7, 149, 150, 155, 157–8,
see also happiness 160–1, 164–5, 167–8, 170–9, 181,
Eudoxus 263, 265 185–7, 194, 196, 198, 202, 205, 206,
Eupolis 10, 12 211, 213–14, 217–19, 227, 230,
Euripides 11, 12, 32, 153, 211, 222, 315, 235–8, 241, 243, 246–8, 250–2, 265,
343, 347 270, 282, 300
excellence 12, 34–5, 39, 42, 52, 61–2, 64, Grote, George 44, 74, 287, 291, 322
107, 127, 137–8, 163–4, 171–3, 181, Gyges 119, 254
227, 263
see also aretê happiness 13, 20, 61, 66, 150, 154, 157–8,
164, 167, 169, 170, 172, 178, 179–80,
fallacy 134, 264, 294 181, 184–5, 253, 265, 266
family 8, 16, 17, 66, 81, 88, 104, 108, 149, see also eudaimonia
150, 192, 255, 268 harmonics 24, 202, 211
Fichte, J. G. 286 harmony 22, 26, 65, 94, 116, 117, 147,
Ficino, Marsilio 68, 279, 280, 282, 306, 187, 202, 274, 293
309, 318 health 248
forms 3, 5–6, 15–16, 22, 24, 26, 30, 46–7, hedonism 10, 81, 86, 169, 185, 204, 232
51, 54, 60, 63, 71, 73, 75, 77–80, 82–4, Hegel, G. W. F. 284, 285–6, 302
89–91, 93, 97, 99, 110, 113, 115–19, Heidegger, Martin 159, 161, 253, 297–8,
124, 134, 136, 140–2, 144, 146, 148, 304, 307
155–6, 160–2, 167–9, 173–5, 179, Helen 13, 16, 17, 27, 133, 189, 193, 223, 227
181–2, 184, 188–90, 196, 199, 200, Heraclides of Pontus 263
202, 208, 211, 214, 216, 217–20, Hermann, K. F. 126, 285–7, 292, 314, 323,
222–6, 231–3, 237–8, 241, 243, 250, 329
254, 257, 259, 263–6, 288–9, 291, 293, hermeneutics 262
295–6, 299, 305, 306 heroes 11, 19, 20, 31, 58, 90, 118, 147,
Frege, Gottlob 193, 285, 294, 319 152, 180, 233
Friedländer, Paul 8, 53, 55, 56, 70, 99, Hesiod 20, 21, 105, 106, 153, 228, 233,
302, 319 234, 252
friendship 23, 28, 34–5, 39, 55, 67, 69–70, history 1, 4, 5, 7, 19, 31, 37, 38, 45, 71, 72,
149, 175–7, 245 82, 89, 95, 100, 102, 107–8, 109, 166,
171, 200, 212, 229, 253, 267, 272, 276,
Gadamer, H. G. 298, 301 280, 285, 286, 297
Galen 37, 272, 273, 274 Hobbes, Thomas 281, 282
Gemisthius, George [Pletho] 279 Homer 12, 17, 19, 20, 21, 61, 63, 105, 106,
geometry 73, 103, 162–4, 168, 169, 178, 116, 136, 147, 152, 153, 181, 228, 233,
200–2, 240, 253, 283 234, 252, 260
George of Trebizond 279, 280, 307, 308 Hume, David 340
gods 10, 11, 19, 20, 22, 23, 25, 27, 29, 32, humour 3, 5, 86, 108–10, 123, 125
33, 40, 46, 50, 55, 56, 76, 90, 94, 95, Hunayn Ibn Ishâq 273
100, 109, 118, 128, 151–4, 156, 157, Husserl, Edmund 285
180, 197, 204, 208, 212, 223, 228,
229–31, 233, 238, 241, 243, 251–3, 294 Iamblichus 38, 266, 271, 279, 280, 316,
goodness, the good 9, 13, 31, 58, 60, 62, 341, 342
69, 70, 78, 81, 85, 89–91, 95, 99, Ibn Rushd 273, 275
109–11, 116, 120, 130–1, 133, 139, idealism 9, 284, 285, 286, 287, 300, 301, 305

352

9780826435354_Index_Final_txt_print.indd 352 3/16/2012 9:48:58 AM


INDEX

image 3, 58, 92, 110, 130, 140, 145–6, legislation 180, 192, 233, 242, 276
160, 162, 180–2, 196, 207–8, 223, Leibniz, G. W. 254, 282, 283, 284
238, 243, 253–4 Leucippus 24
see also eikôn Levinas, Emmanuel 298, 307, 311
imitation 21, 31, 90, 148, 181, 205–7, 208, likeness 47, 99, 130, 150, 181, 214, 223, 224
224, 233, 253 to god 148, 151, 202, 204
see also mimêsis literacy 12, 17–20, 305, 323, 334, 337, 344
immortality 76, 77, 78, 95, 123, 144, 155, Locke, John 282–4
180, 198, 231, 239, 247–9, 257, 268, logos 3, 72, 78, 93–4, 99, 107, 111, 113, 121,
272, 275, 281, 284, 296, 304 123, 133–4, 141, 160, 189–90, 194–6,
inspiration 20, 21, 62–3, 75, 101, 122, 200, 207, 209, 211, 225–6, 237–8, 239,
137, 182–4, 198, 199–200, 212, 234, 245, 253, 257, 266, 294, 306
284–5, 332 see also account
intellectualism 132, 170, 184–6 Lotze, Hermann 285, 329
intelligence 11, 21, 74, 99, 143–4, 146, 150, love 6, 27, 32, 38–9, 50, 55–6, 69, 70, 78,
184–5, 186, 199–200, 229, 238–9, 249, 80, 89–90, 93–5, 98, 105, 109, 120,
252, 270, 284, 308 128, 139–40, 143, 175–7, 180, 182,
irony 3, 5, 41, 86, 102, 110–11, 112–14, 184, 196–8, 200–1, 205, 221, 227–8,
119–21, 124–5, 127, 256, 293, 340 232–4, 239, 242, 245, 257, 276, 280,
Isocrates 9, 13, 16–17, 54, 119, 242, 246, 284, 294
257, 287, 291, 305, 311, 315, 323, 329, see also erôs
330, 332 Lyceum 13, 95, 263

Jerome 268, 277 madness (mania) 32, 184, 197, 198–200


John Scotus Eriugena 278 Maimonides, Moses 274, 275, 276
justice 16, 22, 26, 35, 39, 42, 44, 55, 57–8, Malebranche, Nicholas 283
66, 73, 85, 87–8, 108, 110, 149, 164, Manuel Chrysoloras 279
167–8, 172, 174, 177, 181–2, 184, Marxism 307
186–8, 191–3, 199, 202, 205, 220, 222, mathematics 1, 13, 25–6, 89, 136–7, 143,
229–31, 234, 242, 246, 248, 254, 282, 159, 160, 169, 178, 200–2, 240, 305
293, 299 measurement 82, 83, 84, 86, 184, 290
medicine 1, 43, 44, 176, 202–4, 205
kalon 42, 57, 58, 59, 60, 139, 140, 141, 327 Melissus 14, 15
see also beauty memory 20, 28, 53, 82, 118, 124, 161, 184,
Kant, Immanuel 284, 285, 306, 307 212, 213, 258
Kierkegaard, Søren 285 metaphysics 15, 23–4, 32, 71, 74, 78, 87, 91,
122, 135, 139, 171, 181, 189, 207, 220,
language 1, 3–4, 13, 18, 19, 22, 27, 28, 31, 223, 246, 271–9, 281, 295, 298, 330
38, 50–1, 69, 72, 110, 112–13, 120, 121, metempsychosis 25, 26, 274
124, 136, 142, 156, 158, 175, 188–91, methexis 222
196, 207, 221–2, 225, 233, 235, 243, see also participation
251, 258, 261, 294, 306 method 25, 33, 44, 47, 51, 63, 74–5, 77,
law 1, 9, 16, 18, 27, 41, 48, 51, 53–4, 66–7, 81–2, 92, 104, 113, 120–1, 124, 127,
95, 106, 119, 149, 165, 168, 177, 187, 134, 144, 159, 160–1, 170–1, 189,
191–2, 198, 233, 235, 237, 239, 268, 195, 201, 204, 205–7, 209, 216, 231,
276, 286, 291, 302 237, 241–2, 265–8, 286, 289, 293,
lawgiver 233, 235 295, 301, 308

353

9780826435354_Index_Final_txt_print.indd 353 3/16/2012 9:48:58 AM


INDEX

midwifery 96 nous 78, 135, 143–4, 160, 199,


mimêsis 90, 105, 129, 136, 181, 207–9, 237, 239, 254
233, 234, 253 Numenius 251, 264
see also imitation
moderation 43, 71, 110, 184, 204, 211, Olympiodorus 10, 36, 272, 273, 343
227, 229, 244 One, the 217–18, 264, 266, 304
Moderatus of Gades 264 ontology 76, 81, 84, 174, 178, 189,
monism 14, 15, 169, 248, 264, 284, 285 217–19, 238, 344
moral weakness 30, 184 opinion 14, 22, 73, 85, 90, 92, 111, 143,
see also akrasia 163, 177, 237, 240, 277, 299, 308
More, Henry 281 see also doxa
More, Thomas 3, 11, 16, 31, 47, 51, 74, 87, orality 17–20, 112
102, 122, 124, 239, 280, 287, 298 Orphics 25
mouthpiece 4, 20, 291, 295 ousia 56, 160, 207, 228
Muses 20, 21, 63, 184, 200, 260,
265, 315 Panaetius 10
music 1, 10–12, 26, 33, 90, 94, paradox 50, 73, 86, 103, 127, 128, 132,
116–17, 129–30, 149, 158, 164, 208, 134, 178, 206, 226, 240
209–11, 232 participation 54, 75, 76, 98, 173, 174, 175,
muthos 6, 99, 211, 212 189, 220, 222–5, 254
myth 1, 4, 23, 26, 28, 34, 57, 58, 71–3, 78, see also methexis
83, 85, 89, 95, 99, 102, 106, 109, 111, particulars 136, 161, 163, 173, 208, 219,
113–14, 118–19, 122–5, 136, 151, 153, 220, 223, 250, 306
156, 164, 194, 197, 211–13, 234, 239– Patrizzi, Francesco 279
40, 242–3, 247, 249, 251–2, 254, 262 perception 23, 77, 82, 96, 97, 136, 142,
150, 155, 168, 173, 195, 219, 225–7,
names, naming 6, 11, 18, 24, 46, 47, 53, 89, 231, 238, 250, 253, 254, 266
96, 97, 107, 172–5, 188–91, 189–90, Pericles 10, 32, 38, 39, 58, 71, 72, 85, 235,
195, 207, 209, 226, 230, 235, 246, 252, 236, 256
259, 268, 272, 277, 292 perplexity 59, 60, 125, 293, 296
Natorp, Paul 285, 286 persuasion 27, 34, 35, 119, 133, 134, 141,
naturalism 67, 188, 285 241, 281, 299
nature 7, 16, 21–2, 25, 27–8, 30, 32–4, 40–1, philia 70, 175, 176, 177, 221, 228, 233
46–7, 50–3, 55–7, 59, 64, 67, 69, 72, 77– see also friendship
82, 85, 93–4, 99, 100, 108–9, 117–18, Philip of Opus 65, 152, 290
121, 131–2, 134–6, 141, 144–6, 148–9, Philo of Larisa 102
151–2, 155, 157, 159, 161, 166, 169, Philodemus 10, 263, 265, 267
175, 180–2, 185, 187–9, 191, 195–7, Philolaus 22, 25, 26, 324
199–200, 203–4, 213–15, 216, 219, Philosopher-ruler 148, 192, 236
220, 223, 228–9, 232–3, 239, 244–9, philosophy 1, 3, 4, 8–10, 14, 16–17, 19,
255, 259, 261–2, 265–6, 267, 273, 275, 21, 23–4, 29, 33, 38, 40–1, 43–5, 50–1,
277–8, 281–2, 293–4, 296, 303 54, 60, 66–7, 71, 77, 83, 87, 89, 93,
Neoplatonism 1, 4, 74, 75, 101, 159, 209, 100, 102, 103–4, 106–9, 114, 116, 119,
269–72, 274–80, 305 120, 123–4, 126–7, 129–30, 132–4,
Nicholas of Cusa 279 145, 147–8, 159, 161–2, 170–1, 180–1,
Nietzsche, Friedrich 297–8, 304, 306, 307 188, 197–8, 199–201, 203, 205, 209,
noêsis 159, 163, 201, 238 213, 218, 225, 227–9, 237, 239, 242–3,

354

9780826435354_Index_Final_txt_print.indd 354 3/16/2012 9:48:58 AM


INDEX

246–7, 253, 255, 257, 263–4, 266, Pythagoras 22, 24–6, 116, 155, 227, 240,
268, 271–5, 278–9, 280–6, 288, 292–8, 264, 271, 301
302–7 Pythagoreanism 22, 24–6, 116, 209, 271
physician 203, 204, 205, 242, 262, 274 Pythagoreans 9, 21, 24–6, 76, 78, 116
Pindar 20, 21, 153, 260, 336
Platonism 2, 35, 116, 123, 217, 227, 251, ratio 116, 195, 209
253, 264, 267, 268, 269, 273–85, 298, reality 6, 14, 15, 23, 24, 46, 50, 91, 103,
302, 305, 306, 307 130, 135–7, 145–6, 150–2, 155, 160,
play 8–11, 29, 47, 66, 89, 98, 102, 106, 163, 168, 180, 188–9, 197, 207–8, 209,
110, 112–13, 120–1, 123–5, 202, 204, 211, 215, 224, 226, 237–8, 243, 249,
208–9, 212, 221, 269, 273, 303 251, 257, 266, 270–1, 273, 304, 307
pleasure 20, 25, 32–3, 57–9, 79, 81–3, reason 14, 21, 24, 26–8, 32, 43, 45–6, 49,
85–6, 131, 139, 140, 150, 155–6, 169, 52–3, 55–6, 59, 73, 79–82, 85–9, 91,
177, 179–80, 184–5, 204, 209, 221, 95, 99, 102, 131–2, 134, 137–9, 143,
231–3, 235, 250, 263, 265 146, 148–9, 154, 158, 160, 164–6, 168,
Plotinus 1, 209, 217, 218, 269, 270, 271, 179, 184, 186–7, 192, 195, 197–9, 200,
279, 280, 281, 309, 311, 318, 320, 334, 202, 219, 224, 233–4, 237–40, 247–8,
337 252, 255, 266, 273, 281–2, 286, 296,
Plutarch 36, 38, 162, 251, 261, 264, 266, 306
271, 273, 274 receptacle 99, 151, 181, 220, 264, 266
poetry 1, 3, 4, 8, 11–12, 18, 20–1, 28, 34, recollection 26, 73, 74, 77, 80, 121, 123,
62–3, 88, 90, 105–6, 112–14, 121, 125, 163, 167, 168, 184, 188, 237,
124–5, 129, 139, 141, 147–9, 155, 164, 240–1, 245, 258, 263, 296
183, 198–9, 207–9, 233–5, 243, 260–2, refutation 42, 53, 65, 92, 120, 134, 165–7,
297–8 170, 288, 294
polis 18, 148, 149, 205, 245 reincarnation 25, 77, 78, 89, 151, 155, 256
see also city relativism 11, 45, 96, 108, 168, 247
politics 1, 8–9, 40, 53–4, 67–8, 90, 118–19, rhetoric 1, 3, 4, 8, 13, 16, 27–8, 34–5, 57–8,
146, 178, 209, 212, 235–7, 239, 242, 71–2, 80, 108, 112, 124, 134, 165, 196,
246–7, 275, 291, 300 199, 241–3, 246–7, 256–8, 298–9, 305
politikos 235, 236, 237 Royce, Josiah 285
Popper, Karl 171, 307, 308 Russell, Bertrand 85, 86, 131, 294, 306,
Porphyry 269, 270, 277 338
possession 20, 23, 43, 62, 95, 179, 183–5, Ryle, Gilbert 8, 74, 220, 288, 291, 292, 294
198, 199, 223
Proclus 36, 37, 162, 200, 218, 251, 266, Saadya Gaon 275
271–3, 278 Sartre, Jean Paul 307
Prodicus 11, 31, 34, 35, 85, 86, 112, 247 scepticism 27, 30, 34, 96, 102, 267
prophecy 137, 183, 200 Schelling, F. C. J. 284
proportion 26, 82, 139, 140, 162, 163, 195, Schlegel, Friedrich 284, 286
203, 209 Schleiermacher, Friedrich 38, 125, 126, 284,
protreptic 44, 45, 53, 54, 74 286, 302, 303
psuchê 137, 138, 163 Schlick, Moritz 307
psychology 1, 13, 58, 66, 82, 83, 88, 90, self-knowledge, 32, 43, 50, 110, 128, 136,
158, 185, 209, 231, 238, 239, 275 230, 243–5
punishment 58, 66, 85, 100, 119, 156, 187, self-predication 173, 189, 220, 293
188, 192, 340 semantics 112, 113, 189

355

9780826435354_Index_Final_txt_print.indd 355 3/16/2012 9:48:58 AM


INDEX

sensation 14, 15, 174, 211, 225, 226, 245, unity 2, 17, 23, 42, 58, 80–1, 84–5, 88, 96,
254, 255 99, 115, 117, 132, 148–50, 172, 175,
see also perception 178, 197, 202, 204, 206, 217, 229, 231,
seriousness 71, 105, 108, 109, 123, 124, 241, 254, 266, 288
125, 174 unwritten doctrines 217, 300
Simonides 21, 86, 234, 258, 261, 319
Socratic Problem 295 virtue 21, 30–2, 34–5, 40, 44–5, 51–2,
Solomon Ibn Gabirol 275 54–6, 60–1, 66, 72–4, 85–7, 116, 135,
sophia 54, 62, 172, 227, 228, 246 137–9, 148, 152, 155, 157, 163, 165,
sophist 8, 11, 14, 17, 27, 30–1, 33, 40, 167, 169, 170, 171–3, 174, 176, 178–9,
51, 53, 58, 60–2, 64, 85–6, 92–3, 98, 184–7, 193–4, 200, 203, 206, 211,
103, 124, 133–4, 159, 195, 208, 229, 214–16, 222, 224, 228, 230, 231–2, 245,
232, 245–7, 256 249, 254, 256, 263, 266, 270, 293, 298
Sophocles 2, 152 see also excellence
Sparta 8, 12, 27, 59, 235 vision 58, 103, 117, 120, 125, 127, 148,
Speusippus 10, 51, 217, 263, 265, 266, 304 165, 180, 216, 219, 249, 250, 253–5
Spinoza, Benedict 281, 283, 284
spiritedness 79, 89, 248 war 8, 27, 28, 29, 41, 64, 66, 87,
statement 51, 53, 63, 93, 96, 101, 102, 120, 261, 302, 336
134, 145, 178, 190, 191, 195, 246, 249, wealth 52, 149, 150, 153, 170, 178, 179,
258, 290 184, 186, 299
statesman 235 William of Moerbeke 276
Strauss, Leo 114, 298, 299, 300, 302, 303 William of Ockham 306
stylometry 288, 290 Winckelmann, J. J. 284
Suhrawardî 274 wisdom 16, 25, 27, 34–5, 39, 40, 41, 52,
Susemihl, Franz 287 65, 69, 80, 85–6, 96, 97–8, 101, 103–4,
symmetry 130, 178 109, 127, 134, 137, 139, 149, 153, 155,
Syrianus 271 172, 176–7, 179, 181, 184–7, 192, 205,
213, 219, 227, 229–31, 234–5, 237,
technê 20, 63, 129, 133, 134, 137, 138, 139, 245–6, 268, 272–3, 280, 298
199, 200, 203, 205, 215, 234, 236, 242 Wittgenstein, Ludwig 294, 306
see also art; craft world soul 150, 151, 266
Tennemann, W. G. 286, 291, 343 writing 12, 16–19, 34, 42, 78, 80, 101–2,
Thales 22, 246, 310 110, 113–14, 118, 120, 124, 126,
Theognis 21 129, 136, 169, 170, 177, 196, 209,
Theon of Smyrna 37 212, 242–3, 245–6, 257–9, 260, 262,
theory of forms 266, 288, 289, 293 269, 271, 283, 290, 299, 302–3, 305,
Third Man argument 220, 293 307
Thrasyllus 10, 36, 37, 49, 50, 63, 67, 279,
340, 343 Xenocrates 49, 51, 217, 264, 265,
Timon 10, 306 266, 304
tragedy 88, 90, 95, 105, 106, 115, 122, Xenophanes 13, 22, 32, 114, 260
126, 152, 212, 233 Xenophon 3, 9, 10, 21, 29, 30, 31,
Trendelenburg, F. A. 284, 285, 301 32, 33, 72, 107, 126, 153, 159,
tyranny 41, 67, 89, 100, 134 230, 261, 292, 295

Überweg, Friedrich 287 Zeller, Eduard 287


unitarian 2, 3, 289 Zeno 14, 15, 32, 33, 37, 159, 258, 259

356

9780826435354_Index_Final_txt_print.indd 356 3/16/2012 9:48:58 AM

You might also like