You are on page 1of 13

Medieval Art after Duchamp: Hans Belting’s

Likeness and Presence at 25


R o l a n d B e ta n c ou rt   University of California, Irvine

Abstract proach postulated by Belting allowed scholars to venture into


areas of visual production outside the art historical canon or
In the early 1990s Hans Belting’s Likeness and Presence initi- strictures of “high” and “low” culture. At the time of its pub-
ated a consideration of the history of medieval art “in the era lication, this was met in the broader discipline with parallel
before art.” This book attempted to reconsider the binaries be-
moves, such as theories of reception and agency, and with the
tween the beautiful and the functional, the aesthetic and the
inception of visual culture studies, which had developed by
cult image. These investigations, however, relied on beauty and
the turn of the millennium into autonomous departments
neo-Kantian aesthetics to define art, circumventing the con-
temporary history of art and its discourses. While arguing for or interdisciplinary programs at various universities. Such
the validity of “non-art” as an object of investigation, I posit drives expanded the purview of a history of art by produc-
that this scholarship reified the very modernist myths from ing alternative critical spaces for images and their study. This
which it sought to distance itself by accepting such paradigms. is the established narrative as it is often passed down tacitly
In medieval studies, the years following—until now—have through schooling and conversations and which has made
seen research into sensual experience, moving from the focus Belting’s work such a heartening manifesto about the chang-
on visuality in the early 2000s to the present’s concern with the ing discipline and its hoped-for utopias of inclusion for so
soundscape. Parallel to this trend is a growing neoformalism, a many scholars and students of medieval art.
return to the alleged fundamentals of paleography, style, and Looking back at the past twenty-five years, however, I wish
iconography. While seeming to be wholly opposite projects, I
to consider how this very conception of “the image in the era
contend that these threads evidence a concerted return to mo-
before art” could likewise be said to have allowed for the his-
dernity’s bureaucratization of the senses and a faith in the tran-
tory of art to persist unchallenged and untouched, while rele-
scendental signifier.

T
gating the medieval image to new peripheries as business as
usual was allowed to continue in a newly fortified center for
he year 2015 marks the twenty-fifth anni- the art image. I wish provocatively to propose as well that, in
versary of Hans Belting’s landmark volume a parallel move, the discursive trajectory of the image in me-
Bild und Kult.1 When it was published, and dieval art history likewise came to accept its own alienation
particularly following its translation into from the history of art, no longer seeing its objects of study
English in 1994, this book invigorated medieval art history
2
as artistic works, indicated by a shift toward studies that focus
with the study of “the image in the era before art.”3 The ap- on theories of response, bodily experience, and the conditions

I wish to thank Charles Barber, Jacqueline Jung, Christopher Lakey, Robert S. Nelson, and Eric Ramírez-Weaver, whose invaluable com­
ments on this work in its various written and aural manifestations contributed to its present character. Additionally, Assaf Pinkus and an
anonymous reviewer generously provided invaluable feedback. Particular thanks must be extended to Aden Kumler, with whom long con­
versations on this topic not only helped formulate this argument in its present form but also demonstrated the ethical imperative of its publica-
tion. Finally, for their enthusiasm, ferocious friendship, and support of me, this project, and all things ontological, hearty thanks must be given
to Samuel Ray Jacobson, Luke Fidler, and Eileen A. Joy.

1. Hans Belting, Bild und Kult: eine Geschichte des Bildes vor dem Zeitalter der Kunst (Munich: Beck, 1990).
2. Hans Belting, Likeness and Presence: A History of the Image before the Era of Art, trans. Edmund Jephcott (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1994).
3. For a perspective on Bild und Kult’s influence and status at twenty years, see Jeffrey Hamburger, “Art History Reviewed XI: Hans Belting’s
‘Bild und Kult: eine Geschichte des Bildes vor dem Zeitalter der Kunst,’ 1990,” Burlington Magazine 153, no. 1294 (2011): 40–45.

Gesta v55n1 (Spring 2016).


0031-8248/2015/7703-0004 $10.00. Copyright 2016 by the International Center of Medieval Art. All rights reserved.

v55n1, Spring 2016    Belting’s Likeness and Presence at 25    5

This content downloaded from 128.252.067.066 on July 25, 2016 22:17:22 PM


All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).
and factors of production.4 The intent here is not to produce of  “art” in Likeness and Presence. In his foreword, for instance,
an intellectual biography of Belting’s thinking or a histo- Belting acknowledges the perplexing notion of an “era of art”
riographic analysis of his methods in the context of its time. and seeks to ameliorate the readers’ understandable confu-
Instead, the task at hand is to consider the by-products, effects, sion by defining the concept as follows:
and consequences of Belting’s intervention on the history of
medieval art through a close reading of his work’s emergent Art, as it is studied by the discipline of Art History
logics, implications, and unquestioned givens. By reading Belt­ today, existed in the Middle Ages no less than it did af-
ing closely, it may be argued that his unintended effects on terwards. After the Middle Ages, however, art took on
the field resulted because, philosophically, Art—proper and a different meaning and became acknowledged for its
with a capital A—was ultimately treated as a normative and own sake—art as invented by a famous artist and de-
fundamentally transcendental concept incapable of direct in- fined by a proper theory.7
tervention. This took form, ironically, not because of a poor
historiographic understanding of art but, rather, through an In this statement, Belting seizes the discursive space allowed
overhistoricization of the deep history of art. Contemporary by the disciplinarity of art history to argue that while the field
scholarship, echoing and following Belting, has attempted to may study a plurality of premodern artifacts under the ru-
see the rise of an ontologically defined concept of art in the brics of art, these objects cannot be considered artworks. Tac­
post-Renaissance world, albeit with interruptions and hic- itly, he asserts the possibility of the tautology that whatever
cups; yet, this concept was characterized as unmoved from its the discipline of art studies is art, but he eschews this course
basic tenets since then and fundamentally impossible before of action by critiquing this as a symptom of the discipline’s
then. In this established model, art (and particularly its art- myopic presentism. This would have been an important eman­­
ist) accrued power and definition over the centuries after the cipatory gesture that might have made Likeness and Presence
Renaissance, even if it still followed in the trajectory that the an unnecessary project, seizing in particular the equitable
latter set out.5 Thus, this model takes for granted the notion discursive field offered by Bildwissenschaft without the need
of the Renaissance as a radical break from tradition, as has to draw tenuous lines of separation between the art image
been eloquently challenged by Alexander Nagel, Christopher and the cult image, which would only come to reify the no-
Wood, and others before them, and it has also reified the no- tion that cognate fields, such as visual studies, are “everything
tion of art’s history as a mere fulfillment of archaic typologies that the narrowest definition of art history is not,” as Horst
within a Hegelian teleology of historical progress.6 Bredekamp aptly put it.8 Instead, Belting does quite the con-
trary: he forces an unnecessary divide that orients Art proper
around its own cultic practice of invention, the artist, and “a
The Cult Image as Double Bind
proper theory.” This was the tenuous definition of art adopted
The problem arises when one considers that Belting never by many medievalists in the past quarter century. Even Mi­
extensively develops precisely what he means when he speaks chael Camille, for example, stressed in his epilogue to The
Gothic Idol that art emerges when a discipline of formal study
builds up around the image and art becomes “art for art’s sake”;
4. Michael Camille insightfully predicted these shifts in the that is, when looking supplants using.9
field in his response and decisive re-performance of Meyer Scha­
piro’s “On the Aesthetic Attitude in Romanesque Art” (originally
published in Art and Thought: Issued in Honour of Dr. Ananda K. 7. Belting, Likeness and Presence, xxi. This is expanded in the
Coomaraswamy on the Occasion of His 70th Birthday, ed. K. Bhara- revised foreword to the book’s English translation, yet a similar
tha Iyer [London: Luzac, 1947], repr. in Schapiro, Romanesque Art articulation of this statement is evident in the original German vol-
[New York: Braziller, 1977], 1–27). Camille, “ ‘How New York Stole ume: “Die ‘Kunst’, wie sie der Autor hier verstehen möchte, setzt die
the Idea of Romanesque Art’: Medieval, Modern and Post­modern in Krise des alten Bildes und seine Neubewertung als Kunstwerk in
Meyer Schapiro,” Oxford Art Journal 17, no. 1 (1994): 65–75. der Renaissance voraus. Sie ist an eine Vorstellung vom autonomen
5. Andrew Martindale, The Rise of the Artist in the Middle Ages Künstler und an eine Diskussion über den Kunstcharakter seiner
and Early Renaissance (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1972). Erfindung gebunden. Während die Bilder alter Art von den Bilder-
6. Alexander Nagel, The Controversy of Renaissance Art (Chicago: stürmern zerstört werden, entstehen damals Bilder neuer Art für die
University of Chicago Press, 2011), 1–12; Christopher S. Wood, Kunstsammlung. Man kann nun von einer Ära der Kunst sprechen,
Forgery, Replica, Fiction: Temporalities of German Ren­aissance Art die bis heute andauert.” Belting, Bild und Kult, 9.
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2008), 61–108; Alexander 8. Horst Bredekamp, “A Neglected Tradition? Art History as Bild-
Nagel and Christopher S. Wood, Anachronic Renaissance (New York: wissenschaft,” Critical Inquiry 29, no. 3 (2003): 418–28, at 419.
Zone Books, 2010), 7–20; and John Monfasani, “The Renaissance 9. Michael Camille, “Epilogue: Idols as Art,” in The Gothic Idol:
as the Concluding Phase of the Middle Ages,” Bullettino dell’Istituto Ideology and Image-Making in Medieval Art (Cambridge: Cambridge
storico italiano per il Medio Evo 108 (2006): 165–85. University Press, 1989), 338–51, esp. 341.

6    Gesta  v55n1, Spring 2016

This content downloaded from 128.252.067.066 on July 25, 2016 22:17:22 PM


All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).
By these terms, one may summarize that art is that which Despite his recognition of mediation as a crucial concept
has lost its power and gained a medium. Belting, in fact, ex- for the image and its parsing into an art history, Belting’s focus
presses this notion precisely in the form of a retrieval of on the artist, innovation, and formal reflection under­pinned
artistic mediation. He describes the emergence of art follow- the trajectory of the image in his thinking and emerged as
ing the Protestant Reformation in the following terms: “The the dominant art-based narrative in medieval art’s history
image, henceforth produced according to the rules of art after Likeness and Presence.13 Studies on artists, patronage,
and deciphered in terms of them, pre­s­ents itself to the be- originality, visuality, and practices of artistic contemplation
holder as an object of reflection. Form and content renounce in the mid-1990s and early 2000s all consented to further-
their unmediated meaning in favor of the mediated mean- ing Belting’s investigation into the cultural contours of the
ing of aesthetic experience and concealed argumentation.”10 premodern artwork and its artist by attempting to analyze
Therefore, Belting’s premodern cult image is an image that re- critically medieval thoughts on such defining concepts, while
nounces the operative status of the medium as the structure of nevertheless sticking to this constellation of concepts as be­ing
mediation. Even in his Bild-Anthropologie, medium operates somehow definitive of what art is.14
for Belting as a mere site of mediation between presence and In his introduction to the Gesta volume in which Barber’s
absence, a binary that is allegedly absent from the paradigm essay appeared, Henry Maguire, the volume’s editor, stresses
of the Middle Age’s cult image. The cult image, for Belting, is that “art,” as has been noted by “many recent critics,” is for the
an image that is made fully manifest through re-presentation most part a nineteenth-century invention oriented around
rather than representation. individual achieve­ ment, monetary value, and detachment
In a special issue of Gesta in 1995 devoted implicitly to from everyday life. However, Maguire gives no footnotes for
a consideration of Belting’s thesis, Charles Barber argued these “many recent critics.”15 For Maguire, as for Belting, art
that Byzantium approximated a notion of art in the post- is not something that needs to be critically defined, since as
iconoclastic period. His article, tellingly titled “From Image a transhistorical or diachronic term it either remains ever
into Art: Art after Byzantine Iconoclasm,” faithfully follows the same as merely a disciplinary nomenclature or it is so
Belting in its reading of the iconophile writings of Patriarch infinitely di­visible in its successive evolution that it ends up
Nikephoros of Constantinople but uses Belting’s logic to argue meaning nothing in particular. In fact, Belting’s “image” in
the opposite: that the Middle Ages did indeed have “Art,” Likeness and Presence has been criticized for its narrow pur-
understood as a site for the formal and semiotic mediation view: staunchly against narrative images, as Camille pointed
of presence and absence, and, moreover, that such art could out in his review of the volume, and often limited to portrait
function as a cult-bearing image. Barber successfully demon­
strates that “in the era before art” there were pockets of resis­
tance that counter Belting’s monolithic and teleological nar- analysis of material and visual form. Barber’s use of the term here,
however, is not rooted in such art historical iterations of formalism
rative while adhering to what few tenets are provided for an but instead follows in the semiotic relations between the icon and
operative definition of art. Barber argues, then, that Nike­ its archetype. His use is in keeping with the semiotic definition of
phoros viewed the icon as a work of art because it was, in formalism that can be attributed to the so-called Russian Formalists
Barber’s words, “no longer an image that can be considered as of the Moscow Linguistic Circle.
the one it re-presents.”11 Over the course of Byzantine icono- 13. Arguably, it would not be until his publication of Bild-
Anthropologie in 2001 that Belting developed the importance of
clasm, ideas shifted so that notions of presence were rejected
the medium in the history of art. Hans Belting, Bild-Anthropologie:
in exchange for what Barber calls a “formalist reading,” one fo- Entwürfe für eine Bildwissenschaft (Munich: Fink, 2001), trans. by
cused on the relationship between the icon and its archetype.12 Thomas Dunlap as An Anthropology of Images: Picture, Medium,
Body (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2011).
14. E.g., see, respectively, “Artistic Identity in the Late Middle
10. Belting, Likeness and Presence, 16. “Das Bild, das nunmehr Ages,” ed. Sherry C. M. Lindquist and Stephen Perkinson, special
nach den Regeln der Kunst entsteht und sich nach ihnen auch issue, Gesta 41, no. 1 (2002); Colum Hourihane, ed., Patronage:
entziffern läßt, bietet sich dem Betrachter zur Reflexion an. Form Power and Agency in Medieval Art (Princeton: Index of Christian
und Inhalt treten ihren unmittelbaren Sinn an den vermittelten Sinn Art, Dept. of Art and Archaeology, Princeton University, in associa-
einer ästhetischen Erfahrung und eines verborgenen Arguments ab.” tion with Penn State University Press, 2013); A. R. Littlewood, ed.,
Belting, Bild und Kult, 26. Originality in Byzantine Literature, Art, and Music: A Collection of
11. Charles Barber, “From Image into Art: Art after Byzantine Essays (Oxford: Oxbow, 1995); Robert S. Nelson, ed., Visuality before
Iconoclasm,” in “The History of Medieval Art without ‘Art’?,” ed. and beyond the Renaissance: Seeing as Others Saw (Cambridge: Cam-
Henry Maguire, special issue, Gesta 34, no. 1 (1995): 5–10, at 7. bridge University Press, 2000); and Herbert L. Kessler, Seeing Medi-
12. Formalism and its precise definition have an errant trajectory eval Art (Peterborough, ON: Broadview Press, 2004).
in the discourse of medieval art, one that I am not able to treat in 15. Henry Maguire, “Medieval Art without ‘Art’?: Introduction,”
this article, seen in the context of art’s modern historiography as an Gesta 34, no. 1 (1995): 3–4, at 3.

Belting’s Likeness and Presence at 25    7

This content downloaded from 128.252.067.066 on July 25, 2016 22:17:22 PM


All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).
icons, which Arthur Danto noted in his response to Belting power, may exercise modern writers, but they usually
and which opened Danto’s landmark After the End of Art.16 did not apply in the Middle Ages, for in each of these
This contradiction, or double bind, seems likewise to have supposed oppositions one factor was a condition or a
affected Belting’s theorizations. While Belting’s work has had consequence of the other.17
important effects in art history at large, given its wide appeal
by virtue of its breadth and scope, it derived its force and ap- Maguire’s sentiment may be a sound reflection on the rela-
plicability primarily from a Foucauldian investigation of deep tionship between beauty and function, but these binaries and
history. As such, because Belting’s and cognate projects strive the paradigms that they enact have little if anything to do
to undertake an archaeology that in its depth forces present with the question of art in any capacity as it was being for­
myths and tautologies to buckle under the stress of their mulated in the mid-1990s. The distinction that Maguire was
own historiographic weight, the author never has to address thus purporting to address was not one of art versus image,
explicitly or criticize the present conditions of the matter but one of “fine” versus “applied” art, “quality versus social
at hand. The mere apocalyptic force of historical revelation function,” and “aesthetic beauty versus numinous power.”18
itself is seen as doing the critical conceptual work, thus al- Recalling that Belting was then first and foremost a Byzan­
lowing Belting to avoid resolute judgment and definition in tinist, and that the investigation that resulted in Bild und
the present. Consequently, the present fades from view in the Kult emerged from a long-term study on icons undertaken
archaeological approach, because in this model the present is for Dumbarton Oaks, the resonances between Maguire’s and
nothing more than a willing receptacle that masquerades as Belting’s perspectives are not surprising.19 In fact, it is telling
lacking inherent or relevant definition. As such, for Belting that Maguire’s special Gesta issue was titled “The History of
art need not be defined, nor do these recent critics merit Medieval Art without ‘Art’?” In summarizing the issue’s de-
enumeration. sire to reconsider such binaries, which “may exercise modern
In this overhistoricized purview of art, Maguire did not writers, but they usually did not apply in the Middle Ages,”
have to cite recent critics because the judgment of art as a Maguire only indicates the manner in which he himself con-
modern condition was treated as an unnecessary and self- ceived of the idea of art, colloquially and idiosyncratically,
evident universal. The tacit assumption by Maguire here is without critically questioning his sensibilities. The poignancy
that while we might not know what art was for past audiences, of  Maguire’s introduction comes from the absence of  Belting’s
we certainly know what art is for us today, yet the latter does name and the fact that the issue emerged from a session at
not necessitate critical definition or research, which, in this the 1993 College Art Association meeting in Seat­tle targeted
model, would only detract from the historical work. As such, at nonmedievalists. Note, in particular, that the issue result-
Maguire’s introduction goes on to address the distinction be- ing from this panel came out barely a year after Belting’s vol-
tween the cult image and the work of art in terms that qui- ume was translated into English, as evidenced by the fact that
etly played out the implications of Belting’s work and enacted Barber, the only author to engage with Belting directly by
their own archaeology. name, used only the original German publication and pro-
vided his own translations, noting the volume’s very recent
Is the present-day researcher, for example, to concen- English translation. Thus, it would seem that even as the Gesta
trate on the icons that are considered the most beau- issue attempted to grapple with Belting’s propositions at large,
tiful, or on those that have the largest cult following there was little desire on the part of the majority of scholars
(they are rarely the same)? Are the graffiti on medieval included in it to address critically and diligently the rubrics,
frescoes to be considered an impeding disfigurement language, and logics that Belting articulated in his text to dis-
or a valuable source of social history? Such opposi- tinguish the work of art from other forms of visual culture. It
tions as “fine” versus “applied” art, as quality versus so- is almost as if the proposition of “Medieval Art without ‘Art’ ”
cial function, or as aesthetic beauty versus numinous was sufficient description to conduct the investigation, since
again art itself did not need to be rigorously defined.

16. This tendency would likewise be repeated in Belting’s Anthro-


pology of Images (84–124), which places the death mask and images 17. Maguire, “Medieval Art without ‘Art’?,” 3.
of the dead in a central relation to the ontology of the image. See also 18. Ibid., 5.
the review of Belting, Bild und Kult, by Michael Camille in Art Bul- 19. Hans Belting with Alice-Mary Talbot and Gudrun Bühl,
letin 74, no. 3 (1992): 514–17, esp. 515; and Arthur C. Danto, After “Oral History Interview with Hans Belting,” Oral History Project,
the End of Art: Contemporary Art and the Pale of History (Princeton: http://www.doaks.org/library-archives/dumbarton-oaks-archives
Princeton University Press, 1997), esp. 3–4. /oral-history-project/hans-belting.

8    Gesta  v55n1, Spring 2016

This content downloaded from 128.252.067.066 on July 25, 2016 22:17:22 PM


All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).
The overall shorthand with which Belting’s volume treats goal is to consider tactics by which we might come to remedi-
the concept of art itself as a universal, without definition and ate the conflict of Belting’s double bind through a reparative
clarity as to what art precisely meant and for whom, cru- reading of the arguments in Likeness and Presence.21
cially cuts out the one true constituent in this whole discus-
sion: the medieval art historians doing the research. Rather
Belting after Duchamp
than seizing a grounded present of art historical discourse,
looking around to consider what art was for scholars in the The discourse on the cult image at large resulted, albeit
early 1990s, such projects overhistoricize the art concept in unintentionally, in a Kantian system, given its understand-
a manner that makes it either teleologically specific or fully ing of aesthetic judgment or, more precisely, the judgment of
transcendental. Few scholars in the period engaged with what art is. That is to say, such texts as Belting’s and Maguire’s
contemporary critical writings on art; instead, they took for came to imply, vaguely, that art is founded on aesthetics, or
granted that art is rooted in the artist’s cult, originality, qual- explicitly on beauty in the case of Maguire, as that which
ity, and aesthetic beauty—all notions that had little traction in is free from concepts and is a result of subjective taste that
the artistic and theoretical world of the mid-1990s, which fea- cannot be communicated at second hand but must be expe-
tured a rich and diverse landscape of thought about art in the rienced firsthand. As Kant writes, “The judgment of taste is
onslaught and wake of the decade’s culture wars. Fragments not based on concepts, for otherwise it would be possible to
of this trajectory of art may have started in the Renaissance or dispute about it (decide by means of proofs).”22 This comes
the nineteenth century, centered on the issues that Maguire into play in the idea of art for art’s sake, something that can
and Belting point out, but this was certainly not their status only be experienced in relation to itself through primary and
by the mid-1980s or 1990s. As such, this body of work has unmediated sensual experience. Maguire’s binaries, for in-
often failed to view its own writing of history as a present- stance, make it clear that while art objects may be subjected to
oriented practice and thus unintentionally transcendental- historical analysis, these analyses do not question their ontic
ized the very concepts that it was attempting to work past. status as art. Since, in these binaries, the notions of “fine” art,
The dissolution of a critical avenue in medieval art history in quality, and aesthetic beauty are opposed to concepts of appli-
the late 1990s is in large part due to the limiting imposition of cation, social function, or numinous power, the latter are left
such double binds in its academic discourse. out of art history because they do not pass—or, better said,
The double bind is a crucial concept here because it oper- cannot be subjected to—a judgment of taste. All these latter
ates as a linguistic anomaly in which two irreconcilable com- ideas direct one away from subjective experience; thus, they
mands or statements produce a contradictory situation that describe an object that cannot be rooted in the disinterested
makes it impossible to act.20 Here the double bind is mani- pleasure it produces (that is, art as that which is beautiful and/
fested as the contradictory impulse between the expansion of or a site of aesthetic reflection). Hence, these objects are only
the objects of study in art history via the inclusion of the non- of interest for their secondary signification, as scientific evi-
art/premodern image and the simultaneous problem of these dence of sociohistorical issues. Such a perspective stresses the
objects’ inability to be reconciled into the history of art, given self-evident autonomy of art, a concept that can likewise be
their alleged existence as something other than the artwork linked to Kant’s Critique of the Power of Judgment. The prolific
itself. While the German Bildwissenschaft inherently defies lack of a grounded and contemporary working definition of
these limitations, in the Anglo-American sphere the “era be- art is a telling gesture, since it follows in the conceit that the
fore art” solidified for medievalists the growing rift between experience of the beautiful is that which is universal. In other
art history and visual studies. This contradiction is united and words, this resolution implies that while art as a phenomenon
enacted not by these propositions and disciplinary conditions may have a history, what art is is not historically contingent.
alone but, rather, is exacerbated by the artwork’s lack of defi- Because aesthetic judgment is an act of judgment that
nition and articulation, given that this lack ends up allowing cannot be validated through concepts but only through that
only a negative definition of art whereby art itself becomes which is seen to inhere in the object and consequently is uni-
an other to the cult image but lacks any operative contours
beyond that. Belting’s project thus becomes a binary of nega-
tively defined terms: non-art/non–cult image. As such, my 21. On the method of reparative reading, see Eve Kosofsky Sedg-
wick, Touching Feeling: Affect, Pedagogy, Performativity (Durham,
NC: Duke University Press, 2003), 123–51.
22. Immanuel Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, trans. Paul
20. Gregory Bateson, Steps to an Ecology of Mind (Northvale, NJ: Guyer and Eric Matthews (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
Jason Aronson, 1972), 276–84. 2000), 215, sec. 56 (German ed., 5:338).

Belting’s Likeness and Presence at 25   9

This content downloaded from 128.252.067.066 on July 25, 2016 22:17:22 PM


All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).
versally perceptible, there would be no need for Maguire or title is founded on the present-oriented nature of historical
Belting to truly investigate what art is. Therefore, the catego- thought and writing. In this critical re-reading of Kant after
ries that Belting uses in his work to define a historicized no- the work of Marcel Duchamp, Duve engages with the judg-
tion of art are nothing more than the long-standing Kantian ment “this is beautiful” by replacing beauty with art.25 This
underpinnings of the discipline of art history, particularly in simple substitution is one of the landmark contributions of
the German-speaking world with such figures as Heinrich the text, which stresses the conditions of art in the late twenti-
Wölfflin and Erwin Panofsky.23 In the 1990s specifically, as eth century. Through this change, Duve is able to produce his
David Joselit has analyzed, these Kantian ideals were key to own reparative reading of Clement Greenberg’s modernism
art historians’ and curators’ defense in the obscenity trial of through Kant. The move initiated by Duchamp in the history
Dennis Barrie, director of the Contemporary Arts Center in of modernity, particularly via his 1917 Fountain, is the shift in
Cincinnati, in 1990, following the censorship of the Robert art from the specificity of painting, for example, to the generic
Mapplethorpe exhibition “The Perfect Moment” at the Cor­ statement “This is art.” As Duve writes:
coran Gallery of Art in Washington, DC, in 1989. Despite
being well intentioned, the “Beauty Defense,” as Joselit calls it, [Duchamp’s] Fountain spoke of art, or prompted people
played perfectly into the radical right’s attack on the show.24 to speak of art in connection with it. We have passed
After all, the Kantian structure of the beautiful was in no way from the specific to the generic, and this passage is a
different from Justice Potter Stewart’s “I know it when I see switch of names. Exit the painter, enter the artist, the
it” colloquialism to describe the threshold test for obscen- artist in general. His name was Richard Mutt, that is,
ity in 1964, an idea reiterated twenty-five years later by Jesse anybody, since anybody could be an artist at the Ind­e­
Helms. In the Mapplethorpe case in particular, the alleged gay pendents, even a manufacturer of bathroom fixtures.26
(that is, minority) taste could neither be seen as something
that might be universalized (for a majority) nor understood This nominal ontology of art as a proper name nevertheless
as free from concepts because of the homosexual (“special”) still ingrains in language the affect or feeling of quality emerg-
interest. This ingrained Enlightenment notion of the beau- ing from aesthetic judgment, as if such quality were a prop-
tiful in art history thus continued to demonstrate its effects erty of the object’s form. In Duve’s words,
in both the Mapplethorpe case and also in the discussion of
medieval art in the 1990s, as my reading of Belting shows. As In a way, art critics cannot write about “art as art”; they
such, it is necessary to ask how it is possible to move forward can write about painting, sculpture, poetry, or music,
and rehabilitate the scholarship that has been produced under that is, about the medium, and treat the medium as the
the conceptual aegis of “the image in the era before art.” only subject matter of art, even if the artist didn’t. In
A helpful guide through this medievalist minefield is this case, they are modernist even if the work is not.
Thierry de Duve’s Kant after Duchamp, a work whose very They are formalist if “art as art”—that is, their aesthetic
judgment, their feeling of quality—is what makes them
speak of a given work, whose form alone they can de-
23. Joan Hart, “Reinterpreting Wölfflin: Neo-Kantianism and scribe in language.27
Hermeneutics,” Art Journal 42, no. 4 (1982): 292–300; and Mark A.
Cheetham, Kant, Art, and Art History: Moments of Discipline (Cam-
The double bind of medieval art history in the early 1990s
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), esp. 67–100.
24. David Joselit, “Mapplethorpe’s Beauty” (keynote lecture, could be characterized as having emerged in an attempt to re-
symposium for the exhibition “Imperfect Moments: Mapplethorpe ject the Kantian roots of the judgment of art as dependent on
and Censorship Twenty Years Later,” University of Pennsylvania, the beautiful, in order to expand the purview of art historical
12 February 2009). For a brief discussion of Jesse Helms and the study. Yet it implicitly validated the same terms by transpos-
Mapplethorpe case in relation to medieval art, see Michael Camille, ing them on to a period already bereft of such strictures, from
“The Pose of the Queer: Dante’s Gaze, Brunetto Latini’s Body,” in
Queering the Middle Ages, ed. Glenn Burger and Steven F. Kruger
which new critical discourse could have emerged and offered
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2001), 57–86, esp. 59. its own theoretical frameworks to answer not what art is but,
The issues discussed in Camille’s 2001 essay have strong resonances rather, what it could be, for us, as its only extant public.
with Joselit’s essay on Mapplethorpe and the queer pose from 1988.
Joselit, “Robert Mapplethorpe’s Poses,” in Robert Mapplethorpe: The
Perfect Moment, ed. Janet Kardon (Philadelphia: Institute of Con-
temporary Art, University of Pennsylvania, 1988), 19–21. See also 25. Thierry de Duve, Kant after Duchamp (Cambridge, MA: MIT
Mark Jarzombek, “The Mapplethorpe Trial and the Paradox of Its Press, 1996), 283–323.
Formalist and Liberal Defense: Sights of Contention,” Appendx: Cul- 26. Ibid., 194.
ture, Theory, Praxis 2 (1994): 58–81. 27. Ibid., 214–15.

10    Gesta  v55n1, Spring 2016

This content downloaded from 128.252.067.066 on July 25, 2016 22:17:22 PM


All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).
On some level, it is possible to see Belting’s nondefini- heritage, such archaeologists as Alfredo González-Ruibal have
tion of art as relying on Duve’s substitution of beauty for art, demonstrated how such transcendental notions of art and
thus enabling the non-necessity of definition. The problem, heritage rooted in beauty and a fetishization of history emerge
however, emerges when one realizes that instead of seizing from globalism’s industrial complex, tied to neocolonial and
the nominal ontology of art itself as art’s definition—such as neoliberal agendas and epistemes.32
stating simply that medieval art is art because it is studied Not surprisingly, this gen­erative assessment of fundamen-
as art—lines were drawn in a failed attempt to use historical tal categories in archaeolog­ical research led to several meth-
distance and depth as an emancipatory tactic by attempting odological innovations in this cognate field in the early 1990s
to circumscribe art along the lines of the artist’s cult and a that would not occur in medieval art history until the mid-
proper theory, not understanding these to be the by-products dle of the first decade of the twenty-first century. Consider,
rather than the consequences of art. In other words, this his- for example, the proliferation of studies in materiality that
torical project fell victim to a failed archaeology because it have thrived in archaeological research since that time but
sought rubrics for liberation in an extinct past instead of in were only introduced into medieval art history through re-
its own present.28 As Duve notes in his introduction, “Even if cent work built directly on that research, even if not often ac-
you write on the Middle Ages, your writings bear a date and knowledged or properly credited.33 While “material culture”
what you will transmit will be the ‘modernity’ of the Middle studies may have been popular in these years in certain areas
Ages.”29 Even Duve’s substitution of beauty for art, a stereo- of medieval art history, particularly in research groups and
typically postmodern move, results in a modernist product. multiyear projects, the study of material culture has focused
After all, he was attempting to undertake an “archaeology” of more on the deep history or close study of everyday objects
modernism, not of his own late modernity or postmodernity. and their social life than on concern for the structures of mat-
Duve is conscious of this and uses this potential pitfall as a ter and what it signifies, which defines materiality and also
generative friction in his work, and not as a deterrent. If there places it closely in line with the recent ontological turn in the
is a moral to this story, it is that one cannot emancipate one’s humanities at large in the middle and end of the first decade of
own future through a distanced past, but only through a past the twenty-first century.34 I would argue that this differential
oriented toward a present with a proleptic eye on the future
one wishes to create.
Mediterranean and Middle East, ed. Lynn Meskell (London: Rout-
Such ethically motivated and present-oriented methods ledge, 1998), 124–39.
were shaping the discipline of archaeology at the same time 32. Alfredo González-Ruibal, “Vernacular Cosmopolitanism: An
that Belting’s arguments were taking form and proliferating Archaeological Critique of Universalistic Reason,” in Cosmopolitan
in art history. Similarly motivated by a desire to expand the Archaeologies, ed. Lynn Meskell (Durham, NC: Duke University
canon’s purview and include new and unique stakeholders, Press, 2009), 113–39, esp. 128.
33. See, e.g., Christopher Tilley, A Phenomenology of Landscape:
archaeologists advocated for archaeological writing that un- Places, Paths and Monuments (Oxford: Berg, 1997); idem, with
derstood contemporary subjects as the prime interlocutors Wayne Bennett, The Materiality of Stone: Explorations in Landscape
in the writing of history. This discourse was opened in 1989 Phenomenology (Oxford: Berg, 2004); Daniel Miller, ed., Materiality
by the British social archaeologist Christopher Tilley, who (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2005); Lynn Meskell, Object
convincingly argued that the production of archaeological Worlds in Ancient Egypt: Material Biographies Past and Present
(Oxford: Berg, 2004); and eadem, ed., Archaeologies of Materiality
scholarship is “a form of social and political action in the
(Oxford: Blackwell, 2005).
present with emancipatory potential.”30 Innovative figures in 34. For a recent survey of material culture studies in medieval
the field, such as the founder of postprocessual archaeology, art, its distinction from materiality, and common trends, see Beth
Ian Hodder, have even incorporated contemporary ethno- Williamson, “Material Culture and Medieval Christianity,” in The
graphic research into their studies of distant pasts.31 Through Oxford Handbook of Medieval Christianity, ed. John H. Arnold
a critique of the universalizing notions of art and cultural (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014), 60–75, esp. 67–68. For
precedents of medieval material culture studies, see Harry Küh-
nel, ed., Die Erforschung von Alltag und Sachkultur des Mittelalters:
28. Ibid., 82. Methode, Ziel, Verwicklung; internationales Round-Table-Gespräch,
29. Ibid. Krems an der Donau, 20. September 1982 (Vienna: Österreichi-
30. Christopher Tilley, “Archaeology as Socio-Political Action schen Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1984); and Andrzej Klonder,
in the Present,” in Reader in Archaeological Theory: Post-Processual “Geschichte der materiellen Kultur des Mittelalters und der Früh­
and Cognitive Approaches, ed. David S. Whitley (London: Routledge, neuzeit: Theorie, Methoden, Forschungsbilanz,” in Mensch und Objekt
1998), 305–31, at 307. im Mittelalter und in der frühen Neuzeit: Leben, Alltag, Kultur; inter-
31. Ian Hodder, “The Past as Passion and Play: Çatalhöyük as a nationaler Kongress, Krems an der Donau, 27. bis 30. September 1988,
Site of Conflict in the Construction of Multiple Pasts,” in Archae- ed. Gerhard Jaritz (Vienna: Österreichischen Aka­demie der Wissen-
ology under Fire: Nationalism, Politics and Heritage in the Eastern schaften, 1990), 23–36.

Belting’s Likeness and Presence at 25    11

This content downloaded from 128.252.067.066 on July 25, 2016 22:17:22 PM


All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).
time, characterized in terms of methodological interest, can oclasm might well ask whether it is a topic proper to the field
be correlated with medieval art historians’ relative disregard of art history.”36 Barber’s volume, in part a response to Belt­
for critically defining the ontological operation of the work of ing’s Like­­ness and Presence, was subversively titled Figure and
art itself and a concomitant disregard for innovatively seizing Likeness and sought to offer a “different approach” from that
the scholar’s lived presence as the primary avenue of approach of Belting.37 Such an opening disclaimer only a decade la­­ter
to the image, despite the fact that it was a radical change in evidences the litheness and fragility of Belting’s and Freed­­
these two interrelated avenues of approach that sparked the berg’s allegedly groundbreaking interventions in the field.
interest in materiality in medieval art and likewise pointed to While arguing for the validity of “non-art” and the methods
its origins in social archaeology. of external disciplines as objects and formats of investiga­­
To summarize my responses to Belting’s text twenty-five tion, their scholarship thus reified the very modernist myths
years later, it seems that in the early 1990s Likeness and Pres­ from which it sought to distance itself by accepting the para-
ence initiated a consideration of the history of medieval art digms of their broader epistemes as givens.
“in the era before art” that came to orbit around the binaries In medieval studies, the years following have seen research
between the beautiful and the functional, the aesthetic and into sensual experience, moving from the focus on visuality
the cult image. His and others’ goal was to bring into a history in the early 2000s up to the present concern with soundscape,
of art elements of visual culture previously ignored and left materiality, and affect. Parallel to these trends, however, is a
by the wayside. By relying on an unarticulated (perhaps even growing neoformalism, a return to the alleged fundamentals
unconscious) neo-Kantian logic to define art, however, Belting of paleography, style, and iconography. Although they seem to
and his contemporaries circumvented present realities and be wholly opposite projects, I would argue that these threads
conditions of the field and consequently left intact the op­ evidence both a faith in transcendental signifiers and a con-
pressive logics and systems that they were implicitly attempt- tinuation of double-bind logics alongside a return to moder-
ing to combat. This impetus was not limited to Belting’s work, nity’s “bureaucratization of the senses,” to borrow Caroline
and perhaps the phrase most emblematic of the period’s Jones’s concise words.38 This entwined development finds the
doubled logic is David Freedberg’s opening to The Power of roots of its trajectory in the conceptual frameworks estab-
Images, where he writes, “This book is not about the history lished by early 1990s scholarship oriented around the ques-
of art. It is about the relations between images and people in tion of art as an ontic category, which provided us with a series
history. It consciously takes within its purview all images, of double binds rather than with a synchronic and present-
not just those regarded as artistic ones.”35 There is perhaps no oriented reflection on the philosophical underpinnings of the
more perfect embodiment of a double bind than an art his- present-day work of art. This development has been fed by the
torian opening his book on the history of response with the ontological investigation of the picture, not of the epistemo-
statement, “This book is not about the history of art.” Like logical conditions of the image.
Belting’s, Freedberg’s contemporaneous text specifically at-
tempted to broaden the scope of the canon and understand
The Cult Image: Primitivism at the End of History
a history of images rooted in people’s interactions with them.
Neither author tried to define what art was for him in his own Returning, then, to the problem of the cult image as an im­
historically contingent experience and only then move on passable double bind, embroiled as it is in the methodo­
to ask whether forms of art could or could not be identified logical tides of the field over the past twenty-five years, it is
in the Middle Ages and beyond. While Freedberg aptly lo- necessary to consider the cult image of Likeness and Presence
cated his volume in the history of response and thus respon- within the concurrent discourses of Belting and others on the
sibly prevented ontologizing the relations between people “end” of art history. In a recent critique of the ontological turn
and images as defining a particular type of image, as Belting in the humanities, Jordana Rosenberg argues that the flour-
did, both volumes positioned themselves against a history ishing of object-oriented ontologies, new materialism, and
of art and against a working definition of art while claiming vitalism have manifested themselves as a “theoretical primi-
merely to investigate its postulated other. Even in 2002, Bar­
ber would deem it necessary to begin his study of Byzantine
image theory in the wake of iconoclasm with the statement, 36. Charles Barber, Figure and Likeness: On the Limits of Repre-
“Any art historian who turns to the subject of Byzantine icon­ sentation in Byzantine Iconoclasm (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 2002), 7.
37. Ibid., 141n3.
35. David Freedberg, The Power of Images: Studies in the His- 38. Caroline Jones, Eyesight Alone: Clement Greenberg’s Modern-
tory and Theory of Response (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, ism and the Bureaucratization of the Senses (Chicago: University of
1989), xix. Chicago Press, 2006).

12    Gesta  v55n1, Spring 2016

This content downloaded from 128.252.067.066 on July 25, 2016 22:17:22 PM


All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).
tivism that presents itself as a methodological avant-garde.”39 emerges from under the governance of the ra­tional, creative
Such methodologies postulate a realm of being outside the artist whose generative originality pushes  his­tory forward
scope of human action and knowledge, endowing matter, in from the Renaissance toward the utopic fulfillment of man in
its most molecular definition, with an agency and animacy late modernism.
of its own. Rosenberg observes, however, that in examining When described in such terms, Belting’s cult image reveals
this “ancestral” realm, which Quentin Meillassoux defines as itself as a construct analogous to a fetish object, with all the
a “reality anterior to the emergence of the human species,”40 mired baggage that this primitivist notion carries in anthro-
where the flux and being of matter exist parallel to human ac­­ pological historiography.43 The cult image enabled an unme-
tion, the ontological turn sees matter as the site for the play- diated experience with inanimate objects in the prehistory
ing out of a primitivist fantasy. That is to say, the ontological of the image, whereby the medieval viewer became akin to a
turn enables the radical break with social orders known to us noble savage. Seen in a vacuum, one might be able to ignore
and opens up a fetishized site of radical alterity that becomes these critiques of the cult image, but they are thrown into
nothing more than a crude remediation of neoliberal forms of relief when one understands them in dialogue with Belting’s
settler colonialism and financial capital accumulation on the “anthropology” of images that seeks out an ontology of art
level of molecules. through wide cultural analysis, that picks and chooses from
The intellectual legacy of the ontological turn is not unre- human history to produce a monolithic argument about the
lated to Belting’s own concern with the question “What is an image despite its call for cultural specificity through case
image?,” which marks his work’s development from Likeness studies. In his 1992 review of Bild und Kult, Camille noted
and Presence to An Anthropology of Images and investigates Belting’s uneasy primitivist tendencies when he critiqued the
the valences of the image across time and space. This has book’s interspersing of photographs of modern rituals and
paved the way for current medieval art historical discourse to their use as transparent examples of medieval cult practices,
be a site of lively discussion regarding the material presence which demonstrated Belting’s overall lack of “any ethno-
and endurance of objects, as championed by such research graphic sensibility”—a matter only exacerbated by Belting’s
groups as the Material Collective.41 While Ro­senberg’s cri- ex­plicit distancing from anthropological discourse because
tique is specific to the status of an ontological discourse that it is, according to him, too bound within the present’s own
has not yet fully penetrated medieval art history, although it is cul­tural concerns.44 Yet the belief that certain peoples living
certainly thriving in medieval literary studies, Rosenberg’s in- outside European and North American modernity have pre-
sights make one painfully aware that methods that ascribe an served ancestral traditions, which can in turn be used to study
innate animacy to matter in an ancestral realm (whether that historical rituals, is a hallmark of a primitivist outlook even
realm be chronologically anterior or parallel to human exis­ if those peoples are monks on Mount Athos. In doing so,
tence) also allow a space for the re-performance of a primitiv- Belting ignored the basic teachings of contemporary archae­
ist fantasy of a system not ruled by the civilized and rational olo­­gists and anthropologists, who were using their present
human, which scholarly analysis can now colonize and then and lived experiences as necessary avenues for entering and
combine with a consumerist-driven desire for matter. As approaching their work in order to undo this very legacy of
such, Rosenberg asks that one be particularly sus­picious of Western ethnocentrism, primitivism, and universalism.
a “lust for dehistoricization, for demediation, for a tempo- In Christian Materiality, Carolyn Walker Bynum attempts
rality outside of history.”42 This critique is ethically poignant to separate her work on materiality from the theories of
for my discussion because its problems with the ontological Bruno Latour, Alfred Gell, Daniel Miller, and others precisely
seem to echo the very function of Belting’s cult image: an because she sees them as often contributing to “universaliz-
animistic object of cult fascination, which lies in the anterior ing theories about the power of things.”45 Bynum goes on to
protoplasm of the image. In this model, the art image proper clarify:

Questions of how we talk about visual objects in the era


39. Jordana Rosenberg, “The Molecularization of Sexuality: On
Some Primitivisms of the Present,” Theory & Event 17, no. 2 (2014): before art, theories about the agency of ordinary objects
n.p. (from domestic aids to scientific equipment), and the
40. Quentin Meillassoux, After Finitude: An Essay on the Neces-
sity of Contingency, trans. Ray Brassier (London: Continuum, 2008),
10. 43. William Pietz, “The Problem of the Fetish, I,” RES: Anthropol-
41. Karen Eileen Overbey and Benjamin C. Tilghman, “Active ogy and Aesthetics 9 (1985): 5–17.
Objects: An Introduction,” Different Visions: A Journal of  New Perspec- 44. Camille, review of Belting, 517.
tives on Medieval Art 4 (2014): 1–9, http://thematerialcollective.org/. 45. Carolyn Walker Bynum, Christian Materiality: An Essay on
42. Rosenberg, “Molecularization of Sexuality.” Religion in Late Medieval Europe (New York: Zone Books, 2011), 31.

Belting’s Likeness and Presence at 25   13

This content downloaded from 128.252.067.066 on July 25, 2016 22:17:22 PM


All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).
somewhat reductive investigation into the physiology This is promulgated by the notion of an “end” of history
of seeing currently popular with some art historians in Belting’s work, which explicitly understood the all-present
have, of course, shaped the way I have pursued my topic. power of the unmediated cult image as existing before our
But my argument is a historical one. . . .46 [my emphasis] time in “the era before art.” For present scholars this historical
trajectory of the artwork had now been completed, and thus
By distinguishing her proposition from that of Belting as it would seem that one was left to repeat history in a utopic
being a “historical one,” Bynum opts to work past the univer- state of lofty fulfillment. This was certainly the narrative of
salizing and ethnocentric implications of such narratives to late-modern neoliberal thinkers, as in Francis Fukuyama’s
think in a grounded and specific manner about the problems 1989 essay “The End of History?,” in which the Hegelian prog­
of materiality. The breadth of topics that fall under her cri- ress of history was seen as having been completed in the
tique here likewise speaks to the proliferation of studies that “universalization of Western liberal democracy as the final
have cultivated a desire to see the medieval as a radical depar- form of human government.”49 After the universalization of
ture from our own social norms and as an ancestral realm of democracy and capitalism, a certain progress of history finds
estrangement and difference, notably including the “reductive its neat ends, not unlike the final project of art history in the
investigation into the physiology of seeing,” the aims of which late twentieth century. Given the strikingly similar narratives
could be understood to take part in the desire for a medieval of thinkers in radically different spaces, it is difficult to ignore
subject whose very bodily nature and perception were radi- Rosenberg’s critique of methodological forms of primitivism
cally different from our own. For instance, Robert Nelson’s ar- as adhering to neoliberal, colonial, and capitalist agendas.
gument that Byzantine visuality relied on haptic contact with While Danto would make a parallel proposition in After the
the work of art follows in this desire for alterity in which even End of Art, based on his 1995 A. W. Mellon Lectures, at the
perception succumbs to the tenets of unmediated and direct National Gallery of Art, Washington, DC, and earlier writ-
contact with the cult image.47 ings from the mid-1980s, his work is a model of an end to a
The cult image and its methods (as well as the cult image static art in exchange for a dialogic model of art and theory
as a method) thus seem all the more like some primitiviz- in which artists produce answers and counter-responses.50 As
ing myth about primal, agentic relations with images and an such, the end of art for Danto emerges less as an ontological
uncritical enchantment with their forms and strategies of shift in the being of art at the completion of its history, as is
representation. Even the volition of the artist in the modern the case with Belting, and instead manifests itself as a repo-
world becomes transposed on to a culture-wide will that has sitioning of its narrative amid changing stakeholders who are
been abstracted into a quasi-shamanistic force of creation, confronting the limitations of art’s dogmatic institutions and
and so Belting’s cult image starts to lead us to early narra- narratives. Danto’s end is one of radical pluralism.
tives of artistic form generated by a near-sentient, willful, In the context of Likeness and Presence, Belting sees the
and ultimately monolithic notion of culture, reminiscent of end of a history of art bookended by the present and the me-
Aloïs Riegl’s Kunstwollen.48 One is left with the sense that dieval past, in which a primitivist cult image now lies perhaps
“the era before art” is a period of image making driven by a at both ends of history but outside the temporality of a history
raw cultural force, producing re-presentations of unmediated proper and dehistoricized from Belting’s own lived present,
presence, existing in a realm anterior to our own epoch and as I have argued. Consequently, one is left with a proposi-
consequently outside history, all dehistoricized in a universal- tion for the cult image that is developed methodologically
izing notion of the cult image. through wholly traditional art historical forms of analysis,
looking at formalist narratives of stylistic development and
cross-referencing these with textual sociopolitical sources as
a means of validating a narrative of the cult image’s progress
46. Ibid., 31–32. toward art. The problem at hand is not so much in the details
47. Robert S. Nelson, “To Say and to See: Ekphrasis and Vision
in Byzantium,” in Nelson, Visuality before and beyond the Renais-
sance, 143–68; and Roland Betancourt, “Why Sight Is Not Touch: 49. Francis Fukuyama, “The End of History?,” National Interest
Reconsidering the Tactility of Sight in Byzantium,” Dumbarton Oaks 16 (1989): 3–18, at 4. See idem, The End of History and the Last Man
Papers 70 (forthcoming 2016). (New York: Free Press, 1992), xi.
48. Jaś Elsner, “From Empirical Evidence to the Big Picture: Some 50. Danto, After the End of Art, 3–20. See idem, “The Last Work
Reflections on Riegl’s Concept of Kunstwollen,” Critical Inquiry 32, of Art: Artworks and Real Things,” in Aesthetics: A Critical Anthol-
no. 4 (2006): 741–66; and Aloïs Riegl, “The Main Characteristics of ogy, ed. George Dickie and R. J. Sclafani (New York: St. Martin’s
the Late Roman Kunstwollen,” in The Vienna School Reader: Politics Press, 1977), 551–62. On the death of painting, see Douglas Crimp,
and Art Historical Method in the 1930s, ed. Christopher S. Wood “The End of Painting,” October 16 (1981): 69–86; and Noël Carroll,
(New York: Zone Books, 2000), 87–104, esp. 94–95. “The End of Art?,” History and Theory 37, no. 4 (1998): 17–29.

14    Gesta  v55n1, Spring 2016

This content downloaded from 128.252.067.066 on July 25, 2016 22:17:22 PM


All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).
of Belting’s argument and methodology as in the basic prem- Church and the Modern Museum.53 While Nagel seeks to put
ises, propositions, and unquestioned givens from which that “art out of time,” Powell’s method is one of forceful contempo-
project develops and takes shape. Likewise, rather than ever raneity driven by a desire to flatten and enfold temporal space
proposing a definition for art, or a model of an art history and allow for eloquent dialogues to emerge from the tectonics
after the end of art, Belting merely enacts a negative project of two previously distinct planes.
of defining not-art and not–art history. In this sense, Belting’s From the late nineteenth century to the turn of the millen-
inquiry took shape as nothing more than a breakdown of an nium, what one encounters in such structures of “touching
“Art” concept to blaze the way for a fantasy of the image built the past,”54 to borrow Carolyn Dinshaw’s evocative words, is
on the cult, whose image produces a double bind of simulta- a shift from doing history to colliding history together. From
neous inclusion and exclusion from the realm of art and its the photomontages of John Heartfield to the “flatbed picture
modern discipline. plane” of Robert Rauschenberg,55 there has been a coherent
and multifaceted artistic prehistory to methodologies that
sought to re-present history by taking the fragments of lost
Coda: On Contemporaneity, or, How to Outplay the
and displaced historical information and making them once
Double Bind
again physically present through forms of compilation, ag-
If this essay is premised on the notion that contemporary gregation, and accumulation that both enabled legibility and
visual culture and its theoretical frameworks can and must disturbed the usual flows and understandings of history, time,
inform the manner in which we, as scholars of the medieval, and culture. An earlier iteration of this phenomenon is what
conduct our investigations of the Middle Ages, then it remains Hal Foster described as “an archival impulse” in late modern
to be seen what one such method of approach could be. Such art, which in its retrieval allowed for the generation of  “alter-
work has often been motivated not by clear historical lineages native knowledge or counter-memory” and transformed the
or narratives but, rather, by the opportunities offered by the excavation site into a construction site.56 In Foster’s words,
potential to think of the medieval through the present and archival art has a utopian ambition, given “its desire to turn
the present through the medieval. Examples include Roger belatedness into becomingness, to recoup failed visions in
Fry’s coining of the term “Proto-Byzantines” to describe the art, literature, philosophy, and everyday life into possible sce-
Post-Impressionists in 1908,51 or, a couple of decades later, narios of alternative kinds of social relations, to transform
Alfred H. Barr Jr. describing Byzantine art and its iconic her- the no-place of the archive into the no-place of a utopia.”57
itage as fundamental to the development of modern art, des- This creative act of historical retrieval enacts a parallel dou-
ignating Byzantine art as one of the “Prototypes and Sources” ble bind in late modernist art, not unlike Belting’s own, be-
propelling his torpedo diagram for the Museum of Modern tween an amnesia of history and the presence of historically
Art into the future.52 Recently, Nagel’s Medieval Modern: Art distant objects and conceptual spaces.58 This archival impulse
Out of Time demonstrated how the medieval might be seen is a project that relies first and foremost on the act of making
to be an undercurrent in much of the art of the twentieth contemporary the fragment, of making a near or distant body
century, while other scholars have strived to understand how simultaneous with us in our present, and allowing for its out-
such cross-temporal thinking might offer a new understand-
ing of art in the present and in the past, such as Amy Knight
53. Alexander Nagel, Medieval Modern: Art Out of Time (Lon-
Powell’s exemplary Depositions: Scenes from the Late Medieval
don: Thames & Hudson, 2012); and Amy Knight Powell, Depositions:
Scenes from the Late Medieval Church and the Modern Museum
(New York: Zone Books, 2012).
51. Roger Fry, “Letter to the Burlington Magazine, March 1908,” 54. Carolyn Dinshaw, Getting Medieval: Sexualities and Commu-
in A Roger Fry Reader, ed. Christopher Reed (Chicago: University of nities, Pre- and Postmodern (Durham, NC: Duke University Press,
Chicago Press, 1996), 73. 1999), 1–54.
52. Alfred H. Barr Jr., “Russian Icons,” Arts 17, no. 5 (1931): 297– 55. Leo Steinberg, “Other Criteria,” in Other Criteria: Confron-
313, 355–62; and Richard Meyer, “Revolutionary Icons: Alfred Barr tations with Twentieth-Century Art (New York: Oxford University
and the Remaking of Russian Religious Art,” in Sensational Religion: Press, 1972), 55–91. See also Douglas Crimp, “On the Museum’s
Sensory Cultures in Material Practice, ed. Sally M. Promey (New Ruins,” in The Anti-Aesthetic: Essays on Postmodern Culture, ed. Hal
Haven: Yale University Press, 2014), 215–24. See also Russell Lynes, Foster (New York: New Press, 1998), 49–64.
Good Old Modern: An Intimate Portrait of the Museum of Modern 56. Hal Foster, “An Archival Impulse,” October 110 (2004): 3–22,
Art (New York: Atheneum, 1973), 27–30; Alice Goldfarb Marquis, esp. 4, 22.
Alfred H. Barr, Jr.: Missionary for the Modern (Chicago: Contem- 57. Ibid., 22.
porary Books, 1989), 53–54; and Sybil Gordon Kantor, Alfred H. 58. For a theorization of art historical amnesia in contemporary
Barr, Jr., and the Intellectual Origins of the Museum of Modern Art art, see Rosalind E. Krauss, Under Blue Cup (Cambridge, MA: MIT
(Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2002), 164–66. Press, 2010), 101–30.

Belting’s Likeness and Presence at 25   15

This content downloaded from 128.252.067.066 on July 25, 2016 22:17:22 PM


All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).
dated history to fade and become an active player in our world modern period is resolutely not postmodern but, rather, a re-
again. One might even say that Powell’s Depositions embod- mediation of modernist methods of historical engagement.62
ies the archival impulse in the opposite direction, throwing a This explains why the double bind of historical amnesia and
“vignette” of the present into the past’s archive. This is the age the archival impulse could exist alongside each other, since
of the work of art in syndication, the instantaneity and simul­ both attempted to remediate the same tenets of modernism’s
taneity of contact that globalism has enabled in our world. temporality through twinned structures that only reified this
Joselit understands the idea of the contemporary precisely very temporality by taking as a given what Elizabeth Freeman
in these terms, taking the forward motion of the avant-garde has described as modernity’s chrononormativity.63
and stripping it of its forward movement, leaving only mo- In a decisive reading of Friedrich Schiller’s On the Aes­
tion itself. The contemporary seeks not to be out of sync with thetic Education of Man, Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak utilizes
time but to exist fully and wholly within it. Investigation of Schiller’s notion of “play” (Spieltrieb) to allow the subject to
the contemporary in recent art is an approach that relies pre- shuttle between contradictory states of being, primarily those
cisely on moving past and beyond the mere archival impulse: of rational and emotional behavior.64 Spivak sees an aesthetic
rather than treating a past (or present, for that matter) as a education as enabling one to play between the binaries of the
distinct fragment of another world, the contemporary un- double binds inherent in contemporary systems of late capi-
derstands that past (and, in a sense, the entirety of history) talism and globalization. Not coincidentally, it is necessary
as one of many things that may be aggregated to be fully to note that Schiller’s own work is premised on the idea that
and wholly present in the present.59 This process of present- the experience of freedom emerges from an experience of
oriented aggregation is bred from the logic of the internet and beauty that results precisely from one’s aesthetic sensibilities.
the database, whereby the flow of information that can be il- Spivak’s goal, however, is to sabotage Schiller by modulating
legible in its mass and accumulation is composed, curated, the experience of beauty under the rubrics of aesthetic af-
and filtered through multiple aggregative sites for compre- fect and phenomenology, sites that in themselves cannot be
hensibility. As Joselit concludes, “In our current moment, it globalized. For Spivak, the aesthetic education shifts the ba-
is the aggregator that makes hyper-accumulation eloquent nalities of an ethical defense of beauty on to phenomenology,
by causing asynchronous objects to occupy a common space. which expands the horizon of play’s operative workings in
Aggregators filter a world saturated by commodified infor- and about the double bind. Consequently, she concludes that,
mation, making the unevenness of globalization plastic and in light of contemporary globalization, the inclusive view of
visible. Aggregators speak in tongues.”60 Thus, the logic of the cultural studies, postcolonial critiques of ethnocentrisms, and
aggregator transforms the locus of asynchronous encounter subsequent expansions of the canon are all valid methodolo-
that the archival impulse developed into the synchronicity of gies today. On their own they are not attuned to the needs of a
the collision, the event, the slash. In Rauschenberg’s flatbed, world driven by globalization’s instantaneity and contempora-
where images and objects accumulate and compound, these neity, however. The latter requires a level playing field where all
images remained as indexes of the world from which they things in a sense become modern. As such, Spivak’s concerns
came. The logic of the aggregator, however, thrives instead echo my own dissatisfaction with Belting’s methods of canon
on full presence and the wonderful complexities and associa- expansion and disciplinary critique, while also providing the
tions that the networking of sites and objects allows. While concept of play as an operative agent in the resolution and
the movement once described as “postmodernism” attempted rehabilitation of the work done by Belting and his followers.
to rely on a radical break with the modernist movement of A condition of contemporaneity—a flat temporality across
times and peoples in the capitalist assembly line of consump- which linear and lateral moves can be undertaken simulta­
tion and progress,61 the aggregator demonstrates that the late

of Cultural Change (Oxford: Blackwell, 1989), 3–120; and Fredric


59. On the contemporary and its precedents, see Richard Meyer, Jameson, Postmodernism, or, The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism
What Was Contemporary Art? (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2013); (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1991), 1–54.
and idem, “Questionnaire on ‘The Contemporary, ’ ” October 130 62. On the temporality of capital and modernism, see Dipesh
(2009): 3–124. See also Terry Smith, What Is Contemporary Art? Chakrabarty, Provincializing Europe: Postcolonial Thought and
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2009); and Julieta Aranda, Historical Difference, 2nd ed. (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
Brian Kuan Wood, and Anton Vidokle, eds., What Is Contemporary 2008), 47–71.
Art? (Berlin: Sternberg Press, 2010). 63. Elizabeth Freeman, Time Binds: Queer Temporalities, Queer
60. David Joselit, “On Aggregators,” October 146 (2013): 3–18, Histories (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2010), 1–19.
at 8. 64. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, An Aesthetic Education in the
61. On the crucial critiques of postmodernism, see David Har- Era of Globalization (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
vey, The Condition of Postmodernity: An Enquiry into the Origins 2012), 1–34.

16    Gesta  v55n1, Spring 2016

This content downloaded from 128.252.067.066 on July 25, 2016 22:17:22 PM


All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).
neously—therefore outplays the paradigm of amnesia/history of steam, in the hope of extending its life. To become an ag-
or Art/cult image. That is to say, contemporaneity subverts gregator it is necessary to be a conscientious observer of the
the temporal double bind of modernism’s and late modern- contemporary, filtering, compiling, and composing a present
ism’s strategies through the tactic of colliding time together with an eye on the future. The death of art history cannot be
in the event of synchronicity. I propose that in order to undo remedied through séances and resurrections.
Belting’s double binds, avoid their implicit bad faith, and In keeping with these goals, I wish to posit this article as
enact a self-possessed program that reflects contemporary being set in 1990, as an imagined encounter with Hans Belt­­
trends in the field and in our lives, all that is necessary is to ing twenty-five (or so) years ago, yet one happening in the
seize contemporaneity as method: to experiment with tempo- present today—a triangulation of a medieval object, a histo-
rally oriented methods derived from our own lived realities riographic past, and a discursive present. This methodology
and that seek to foster what Manuel De Landa has referred to of a setting in time is not a revivalist or revisionist gesture
as a “flat ontology,” where all forms of being exist as equals.65 but, rather, a reparative temporal tense for engaging with past
Exit the historian as accumulator, enter the historian as aggre- sources that still exert their weight on our present, yet also
gator: the producer of collisions, events, and slashes that con- bear within their logics incongruous and at times unethical
dense space-time into a dense singularity of peoples, times, projects that must be remediated before they can be respon-
and places in a present. sibly reintegrated into our present work. As such, this essay
Nevertheless, the aggregator function must be distanced picks up at a moment of radical change in the humanities at
from mere additive structures of methodological pastiche and large and of the validation of the alleged “era before art” in me-
revival that situate themselves as an avant-garde. There has dieval art history. Not surprisingly, the field has now returned
been a tendency in recent art historical discourse to claim re- to that time in its methods and investigations. By distancing
course to distant methodological sources and writers as a way itself from a history of art, Belting’s thesis unintentionally
of constructing seemingly new methodological spaces, from sep­arated medieval art from the discipline of the history of
the Vienna School to Heinrich Wölfflin. While my call for art with the goal of creating an emancipatory utopia. Here
spaces of encounter might seem to harken back to the work I have chosen, somewhat tongue-in-cheek, to return to this
of a figure such as Aby Warburg, it is not necessary to resort mythical point of origin as a way of forging another path
to such methodological primitivisms that seek to take an out- forward. To move past this impasse, I would urge us always to
dated source from a now distant and august past and then consider our present first and then—and only then—attempt
alchemically attempt to transform and elevate contemporary to provide answers and arguments for the artworks we study
work with its revival. Operating in the contemporary means (the artwork defined here as anything studied by an art his-
accepting the lineages of our thoughts and theories and re- torian, thus anything that can be tautologically defined as art,
sponsibly taking on the weight of their traditions and ethi- encompassing all forms of objects). The goal is to harness the
cal implications. If one were to accept the myth of an end to power of the encounter itself that initiates our scholarship
an art history, one would need to postulate a postapocalyptic as the driving methodological force, acknowledging that our
future that takes advantage of that end, not take a single or knowledge production is present-oriented and made for our
unique fragment from that past as a prosthetic and place it ad peers instead of for those lost, imagined communities that we
hoc as an appendage to a historical project that has run out study. Yet we must always remember that our methods are
monads. They bear, bundled up within themselves, the entire
logic of the episteme from which they came. Logics endure
65. Manuel De Landa, Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy and over time manifest themselves in the systems they oc-
(New York: Continuum, 2002), 41. See also Ian Bogost, Alien Phe-
cupy. If the episteme of our methods is contaminated, then
nomenology, Or, What It’s Like to Be a Thing (Minneapolis: Uni-
versity of Minnesota Press, 2012), 11–22; and Levi R. Bryant, The they too will quietly and insidiously enact the violence of the
Democracy of Objects (Ann Arbor, MI: Open Humanities Press, approaches from which they came, no matter how innocuous
2011). we might think their immediate implications to be.

Belting’s Likeness and Presence at 25   17

This content downloaded from 128.252.067.066 on July 25, 2016 22:17:22 PM


All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).

You might also like