You are on page 1of 7

l

“Is” and “Ought” in Hume’s and Hume


Kant’s Philosophy
The issue of the mutual relation of “Is” and
Szymon Osmola and Wojciech Załuski “Ought” is tackled by Hume in the last paragraph
Department of Legal Philosophy and Legal of the first section of the Book 3 (“Of Morals”) of
Ethics, Jagiellonian University, Krakow, Poland his A Treatise of Human Nature. It comes as
follows:
I cannot forbear adding to these reasonings an
observation, which may, perhaps, be found of
Introduction some importance. In every system of morality,
which I have hitherto met with, I have always
The importance of Hume and Kant in the history remark’d, that the author proceeds for some time
of the discussion about relations between the in the ordinary way of reasoning, and establishes
the being of a God, or makes observations
sphere of facts (“Is”) and the sphere of duties
concerning human affairs; when of a sudden I am
(“Ought”) cannot be overestimated. In point of surpriz’d to find, that instead of the usual copula-
fact, it can be said that they initiated this discus- tions of propositions, is, and is not, I meet with no
sion by formulating the problem explicitly. They proposition that is not connected with an ought, or
an ought not. This change is imperceptible; but is,
also provided two “paradigmatic” answers to the
however, of the last consequence. For as this ought,
question of the relations between “Is” and or ought not, expresses some new relation or affir-
“Ought”, which determined the course of further mation, ‘tis necessary that it shou’d be observ’d and
discussions: generally speaking, both Hume and explain’d; and at the same time that a reason shou’d
be given, for what seems altogether inconceivable,
Kant agreed that there is no legitimate logical
how this new relation can be a deduction from
transition between “Is” an “Ought,” but while others, which are entirely different from it. But as
Hume (on one interpretation) believed that authors do not commonly use this precaution, I shall
“Ought” can be reduced to “Is,” Kant strongly presume to recommend it to the reader; and am
perswaded, that this small attention wou’d subvert
objected to this kind of reduction, stressing the
all the vulgar systems of morality, and let us see,
autonomy and irreducibility of the sphere of that the distinction of vice and virtue is not founded
“Ought.” But this general account of their views merely on the relations of objects, nor is perceiv’d
simplifies a lot. We shall try to highlight the com- by reason (Hume 2000: 302).
plexity of their investigations in the following The above paragraph, often referred to as the
sections. Is–Ought Paragraph (IsOP), is one of the most
frequently cited and, at the same time, the most
controversial passage from Treatise. There is a

# Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2017


M. Sellers, S. Kirste (eds.), Encyclopedia of the Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6730-0_225-1
2 “Is” and “Ought” in Hume’s and Kant’s Philosophy

great controversy between Hume’s interpreters, ‘Is’” (Black 1964: 169). Therefore, Hume’s argu-
concerning not only what Hume exactly has in mentation literally “subverts all the vulgar sys-
mind under vague notions of “is” or “is not” and tems of morality,” i.e., systems of morality that
“ought” or “ought not” but also what it means that try to bridge that unbridgeable gap. According to
his “attention wou’d subvert all the vulgar sys- the most radical readings, the conclusion of the
tems of morality” and what “systems of morality” IsOP is that it is entirely impossible to build any
he is concerned with at all. The significance of the ethical system at all. Readings like that often go
closing line of the IsOP (“the distinction of vice hand in hand with the noncognitivist view of
and virtue is not founded merely on the relations moral judgment – the view that moral judgments
of objects, nor is perceiv’d by reason”) is also not do not express any beliefs or state any facts but,
clear. rather, express speaker’s emotions, which means
One can distinguish two approaches to the that they cannot be truth-evaluable. Weak
interpretation of the IsOP – the textual one and textualists claim, on the other hand, that the
the contextual one. In general, the textual inter- above conclusions are too far-reaching. They
pretations are based on the literal reading of the agree that there is the “unbridgeable logical gap
cited passage, whereas the contextual ones tend to between ‘Ought’ and ‘Is’” – but they also stress
bear in mind the historical background of Hume’s that the gap is merely logical and that one can
work, as well as his overall epistemology and the actually get “moral conclusions from non-moral
psychology of morals. The textual interpretation, premises by logic plus [some] analytic bridge
sometimes referred to as the standard interpreta- principles” (Pidgen 2011) or by means of logic
tion, was the dominant interpretation of the IsOP plus some “constitutive rules of the institution” –
for the most part of the twentieth century, although which are the rules “that give the word ‘promise’
in recent years, as a result of an intensified interest its meaning” (Searle 1964: 57–58). This reading
in Hume’s overall moral theory, the contextual of the IsOP may be more proper but, as some
interpretation is often considered as the more scholars point out, also makes it quite trivial.
accurate one. The division between these two There is also a group of interpreters who claim
approaches should not be treated as the definitive that in the cited passage, Hume simply recom-
one – it should be considered as the typology mends a profound caution in the course of deriv-
instead. Each researcher may be classified as ing normative conclusions from factual premises.
textualist or contextualist due to features domi- Hume’s Guillotine, according to them, undercuts
nant in her reading of the IsOP. The distinctive these “vulgar systems of morality” whose authors
features of both approaches are introduced below. do not think and argue clearly enough.
According to the standard, textual interpreta- Other interpreters – the more contextual ones –
tion in its most popular variation, Hume in the try to read the IsOP against the background of
IsOP formulates some putative thesis of logic that Hume’s critique of the seventeenth- and
one cannot deduce (derive) nonfactual (e.g., nor- eighteenth-century ethical rationalism, which he
mative) conclusion from factual premises, the the- undertakes in the Book 3 of Treatise (first section
sis which relies on the rules of the valid syllogism. of which is entitled Moral Distinctions Not
That thesis is sometimes referred to as “Hume’s Deriv’d From Reason – section, which ends up
Law” or “Hume’s Guillotine.” There are two basic with the IsOP). Rationalists, like W. Wollaston,
versions of the textual interpretation of the IsOP – R. Cudworth, or S. Clarke, claimed that moral
the strong and the weak. The former is adopted by, laws exist objectively and can be recognized by
among others, R.M. Hare or P.H. Nowell Smith reasoning and their recognition intrinsically gives
and the latter by such scholars as Ch. Pidgen, us reason to act in accordance to them. Hume’s
J. Searle, or A.N. Prior. According to the strong moral theory, sentiment-based and anti-rationalist,
textual interpretation, Hume’s Law creates “an was in large part an attempt to rebut the rational-
unbridgeable logical gap between ‘Ought’ and ists’ doctrines. His argumentation, in broad
“Is” and “Ought” in Hume’s and Kant’s Philosophy 3

outline, was as follows. The function of reason is, (Haakonsen 1981: 4). Thus, Hume’s reasoning
generally speaking, discovering relations or the does not “subvert vulgar systems of morality.”
matters of fact (Hume 2000: 14–15). We can’t Quite the opposite – the Scottish philosopher
find the basis for our moral distinctions among tries to defend the common sense morality
relations or facts in the physical world (Hume (understood as the whole system of beliefs, not
2000: 301). Moreover, even if such basis were to as the set of particular moral beliefs) before he
be found, rationalist would have to demonstrate in attacks counterintuitive ethical theories. The com-
what way those relations or facts discoverable by monsense morality would be subverted if ethical
reasoning “wou’d be universally forcible and rationalists were right. Since they are wrong, and
obligatory” (Hume 2000: 300) or, using more we put the sentimentalist view in their place, we
contemporary language, how they could give us can still rely on common sense while building our
authoritative reasons for actions. That argumenta- moral systems. The contextual interpretation of
tion, additionally strengthened by the so-called the IsOP is often accompanied by more
Representation Argument (Hume 2000: 295) cognitivist views in metaethics (e.g., Cohon
(according to which passions or volitions cannot 2008: 96–125). But here there are also some
be contrary to reason because they are not repre- exceptions – J.L. Mackie, for example, interprets
sentations of any objects), entails that ethical Hume as ethical anti-realist (which is an non-
rationalists are wrong and that “the distinction of cognitivistic approach) and attributes to him the
vice and virtue is not founded merely on the view called “objectification theory,” which is
relations of objects, nor is perceiv’d by reason.” compatible with his own ethical doctrine, ethical
However, the thesis that Hume’s main target in the falsificationism (Mackie 1980: 144).
IsOP was ethical rationalists is not commonly Some people interpret the IsOP as the antici-
accepted. S. Botros, for example, claims that pation of the so-called naturalistic fallacy.
Hume in the cited passage attacks not only ratio- G.E. Moore famously claimed that naturalists
nalists but also other thinkers, such as his mentor, were guilty of what he called the “naturalistic
sentimentalist S. Hutcheson (cf. Botros 2006: fallacy,” viz., the attempt to define ethical predi-
72–95). Others, including A. MacIntyre, think cates (such as good or right) in nonmoral terms.
that Hume’s main antagonists are dominant reli- This is, according to Moore, a “fallacy” because
gious beliefs of his times and his main aim was to no such definition can pass the test of the “open
ground his naturalistic view of ethics (MacIntyre question argument,” i.e., we can always reason-
1959: 451–468). As was in the case of the textual ably ask whether what is supposed to be the defin-
interpretation, there are stronger and weaker con- iens of the predicate “good” is really “good”; the
clusions, which may be entailed by the contextual possibility of asking such a question attests, in
interpretation of the IsOP. The most radical inter- Moore’s view, that all definitions of “good” are
preters claim that Hume’s aim is the absolute mistaken (cf. Moore 1903: Chap. I). According to
“rejection of ‘Ought’ as a moral category” some views, Hume, in the IsOP, formulates a
(Capaldi 1966: 126–137). Less radical scholars, similar critique. Opponents of the view that
rejecting such far-reaching conclusions, claim that Hume’s intentions were similar to those of
Hume rejects only metaphysical, external Moore point out that Hume himself was a natu-
“Ought” and simultaneously establishes internal, ralist who analyzed moral terms by reference to
human-dependent “Ought” (cf. Darwall 1995: various natural properties (such as agreeable or
1–22; Korsgaard 1996: 49–89). Some others say useful to oneself or others, or eliciting approval in
that Hume, in the IsOP, does none of the above. the impartial spectator), and thereby it makes little
According to that view, “Hume’s task in his moral sense to connect him with the formulation of the
philosophy is completely analogous to his task in naturalistic fallacy. These opponents, however,
epistemology: to explain how a common world is omit the possibility that Hume’s view may be
created out of private and subjective elements” inconsistent: in the IsOP he may have anticipated
4 “Is” and “Ought” in Hume’s and Kant’s Philosophy

the “naturalistic fallacy” but, at the same time, by the meaning of its component terms – thus
may have also constructed normative ethic they can be known by reason; for Hume, by
which is based on precisely the same fallacy – of contrast, they are either factual truths (on the
identifying moral properties with some natural cognitivist interpretation of his theory) or have
properties. no truth value (on the noncognitivist interpre-
tation of his theory).

These two points of Kant’s moral theory – i.e.,


Kant
the strict separation of the realm of facts and the
realm of duties and the claim that it is thanks to
As was shown above, given Hume’s moral theory,
reason that we know the truths belonging to the
within which “Ought” appears to be defined in
sphere of duties – are, of course, strictly
factual terms, one may doubt whether he really
connected. Let us now analyze them in somewhat
makes a clear distinction between “Is” and
greater detail, starting from the basic epistemolog-
“Ought.” In Kant’s moral philosophy, by contrast,
ical point concerning the role of reason in moral
facts and duties are kept very strictly distinct. The
cognition. Then we will pass to some more
differences between Kant and Hume in this con-
detailed questions.
text can be stated more precisely in the following
Unlike Hume, who assigned a purely instru-
way:
mental role to reason in the sphere of action (the
role of finding appropriate means for realizing
1. As was mentioned in section “Hume,” com-
ends determined by “passions”), Kant’s central
mentators of Hume’s works are in disagree-
point, formulated in direct polemic with Hume,
ment as to whether he admitted “Ought” at
is that reason has also a practical (moral) dimen-
all. What can be said for sure is that if there is
sion: that is, its role consists in guiding the course
a place for “Ought” in his moral philosophy,
of human action in the fundamental sense of dis-
this can be only weak, internal “Ought.” Thus,
covering or constituting an unconditional rule of
if Hume introduces any normativity (“Ought”)
conduct, viz., the categorical imperative, which
at all, he locates it at the level of facts. Kant, by
human beings (or, more generally, all rational
contrast, unambiguously separates the sphere
agents) ought to follow. This belief is deeply
of facts from the sphere of duties, believing
embedded in his philosophy with its central
that they are to be situated at metaphysically
claim about the active role of reason in constitut-
different levels which are irreducible to each
ing our cognition, but, interestingly, Kant formu-
other. He therefore explicitly introduces
lates also a strictly empirical argument for it: he
“Ought” in the strong, external sense, believ-
asserts that the function of reason consists in pro-
ing that it can be defended only if the separate
ducing a goodwill in human beings (i.e., a will
sphere of normativity (as distinguished from
whose motive is the obedience to the categorical
the sphere of facts) is postulated.
imperative) rather than in securing their preserva-
2. Kant agrees with Hume (at least if we assume
tion, since “in a being which has reason and a will,
the standard, textual interpretation of the lat-
if the proper object of nature were its conserva-
ter’s views) that one cannot “deduce” any nor-
tion, its welfare, in a word its happiness, then
mative truth from the factual truths, but the
nature would have hit upon a very bad arrange-
way of apprehending normative truths is con-
ment in selecting the reason of a creature to carry
ceived by both philosophers in entirely differ-
out this purpose” (Kant 1964: 12). To return to the
ent ways: for Kant moral truths are synthetic a
categorical imperative, the imperative discovered
priori judgments, i.e., judgments which are
or constituted by reason is categorical in the sense
formulated without recourse to sense experi-
of being unconditioned by the previously existing
ence and whose truthfulness is not determined
“Is” and “Ought” in Hume’s and Kant’s Philosophy 5

ends or desires of the agent. In other words, it categorical imperatives. How this sphere is
formulates a duty which is binding for all rational exactly known and what ontological status it has
agents, irrespective of whether following this duty are controversial points of Kant’s moral philoso-
is in accordance with their preexisting desires or phy that we shall deal with in the remainder of this
ends. The exact content of this rule (in its basic section.
formula called “universal law”) is as follows: “Act From what has been said above, it follows that
only on that maxim through which you can at the Kant emphasized a strict relation between ratio-
same will that it should become a universal law” nality and morality. In fact, on his view, morality
(Kant 1964: 51) (it is usually assumed that Kant becomes a part of rationality: reason, acting in the
proposed five various formulations of the categor- practical sphere, points at the rules of moral
ical imperative, which he believed to be equiva- actions. However, the question arises (we have
lent. Arguably the most famous, apart from the left this question open in the initial description
Formula of the Universal Law, is the Formula of of Kant’s theory) how exactly reason “points at”
the End in Itself, according to which one ought to the rules of moral action: whether it discovers or
act in such a way as to treat humanity, whether in constitutes them. Kant does not decide this ques-
one’s own person or in any other person, always at tion with full clarity, but it can hardly be doubted
the same time as an end, never merely as a means). that the second alternative (“constituting”) is more
As mentioned before, Kant believes that the cate- consistent with his “transcendental” approach to
gorical imperative is an a priori synthetic judg- philosophical problems (within which the empha-
ment and, consequently, that the requirement that sis is laid upon the active role of reason in human
maxims (personal principles) of human conduct cognition), as well as with his insistence on the
must be such that agents can will them to become fact that rational agents are “self-legislators” who
a universal law is not part of the definition of the autonomously impose on themselves moral duties
concept of moral action (even though, in his view, (the claim that there are some binding moral
moral action does consist in fulfilling such a duties which exist in the sphere of “Ought” and
requirement). Kant also strongly emphasizes that which are to be discovered and obeyed by rational
one needs not engage in deep philosophical think- agents would be viewed by Kant as incompatible
ing in order to understand that the categorical with these agents’ autonomy and as an instance of
imperative is a cornerstone of (proper) morality; a “heteronomous” moral theory). Consequently,
he claims that this supreme principle of morality is one should say that, according to Kant, reason
presupposed or “encoded” in the common man’s does not discover the categorical imperative pur-
awareness of duty; the only merit of the philoso- portedly preexisting in some mysterious sphere of
pher (Kant himself) is to bring to light, i.e., for- moral “Ought” but rather, by virtue of its own
mulate explicitly, what is understood implicitly by activity, constitutes it (and thereby the sphere of
every common man. He also distinguishes moral “Ought”). It may be noted in this context
between the categorical imperative and that only on this interpretation Kant’s view of the
a categorical imperative (or categorical impera- sphere of moral normativity can be regarded as
tives). The categorical imperative (in its various truly original: if Kant just claimed that reason
formulations) is the supreme principle of morality “discovers” preexisting moral truths, his view
which enables testing various maxims of actions would be in essential points similar to the view
as to whether they are moral; a maxim that passes of the seventeenth- and eighteenth-century ethical
this test becomes a categorical imperative. One rationalists (which, as was mentioned, were
can therefore say that the sphere of “Ought” (or, strongly criticized by Hume).
more precisely, of “moral Ought”) consists of the Another interpretational problem of Kant’s
categorical imperative (in its various formula- moral theory (related, as we shall see, to the prob-
tions) and a broad (potentially infinite) set of lem of whether reason discovers or constitutes the
6 “Is” and “Ought” in Hume’s and Kant’s Philosophy

categorical imperative) is connected with an reality: soul, God, freedom) is indeed based on
ambiguity in Kant’s works regarding the question his ethics. But it should be noticed that his ethics is
of whether the categorical imperative can be jus- metaphysical in some weaker sense, especially if
tified in the sense of being derivable from some compared with an unambiguously naturalistic
more fundamental principle (cf. Paton 1946: ethics of Hume. Kant believes that reason (the
203–205). On the one hand, in Groundwork of distinguishing capacity of all rational agents) con-
the Metaphysics of Morals, he seems to suggest stitutes a sphere of moral “Ought” which is irre-
that the categorical imperative can be justified by ducible to the sphere of facts; and even if he does
an independently established presupposition of not confer a strongly metaphysical status on this
freedom. On the other hand, in Critique of Prac- sphere (as existing independently of rational
tical Reason, he conceives of the categorical agents), its status can nonetheless be regarded as
imperative as “a fact of pure reason” which we metaphysical, given the metaphysical status of the
know a priori as a certain truth; accordingly, it very reason (as imposing necessarily true laws in
need not (and cannot) be derived from anything moral and physical sphere). One more remark
else and, furthermore, is itself a basis for seems to be in order here. The fact that we regard
conducting a “deduction” of freedom as a neces- Kant’s ethics as metaphysical does not mean that
sary presupposition (postulate) of moral judg- we agree with G.E. Moore that Kant’s ethics is
ments, since in making a moral judgment of an based on the naturalistic fallacy (in its wider
agent’s action we assume, in Kant’s view, that the sense, embracing also the attempts to define ethi-
action was “freely chosen,” i.e., the agent could cal predicated in metaphysical, not only natural-
have acted otherwise (as is well known, according istic, terms). Moore (1903: Chap. IV) claimed that
to Kant, the other presupposition of practical rea- Kant identifies the predicate “good” with the pred-
son are the immortality of soul and the existence icate “required by the rational will” or “required
of God). Accordingly, in Kant’s view expressed in by reason” and thereby commits the naturalistic
Critique of Practical Reason, freedom is a pre- fallacy. But this interpretation of Kant’s moral
supposition of making moral judgments but not a theory cannot be defended, since Kant, though
principle from which the categorical imperative associating the categorical imperative with the
can be derived, whereas in Groundwork he seems capacities of reason, does not make any defini-
to assign to freedom both roles. As can be easily tional claim; he asserts that the categorical imper-
seen, Kant’s claim that the categorical imperative ative is known by reason (or, as we propose to
is a “pure fact of reason,” not derivable from interpret his theory, the categorical imperative is
anything else, provides another argument for constituted by reason in the sense that in the
such an interpretation of his ethical view which absence of reason, there would be no categorical
assumes that reason constitutes rather than dis- imperative); it is, as Kant strongly emphasizes, a
covers moral truths. It is worth invoking in this synthetic a priori judgment, whose truthfulness
context the opinion of H.J. Paton: “Kant’s ethics is cannot be derived from any other statements
not based on metaphysics: it would be truer to say (e.g., about reason or rational will).
that his metaphysics, so as we take this to be
concerned with supersensible reality, is based pri-
marily on ethics. Whatever confusion or error
Conclusion
there may be on this topic in the Groundwork is
to a great extent cleared always by the Critic of
As can be inferred from the above account of
Practical Reason” (Paton 1946: 203–205). This
Hume’s and Kant’s views on “Is” and “Ought,”
opinion is (generally) apt but it should be quali-
the interpretational problems they engender are of
fied. Truly, Kant’s metaphysics understood in this
a different kind – much more serious in the case of
strong sense (the existence of supersensible
Hume. Even though it is clear, at least for most of
“Is” and “Ought” in Hume’s and Kant’s Philosophy 7

his readers, that Hume did not believe that there Cross-References
exists some form of reasoning that can justifiably
lead us from “Is” (statements about facts) to ▶ Kans Kelsen (on Legal Science)
“Ought” (statements about duties), one can plau- ▶ Is and Ought Distinction in Legal Philosophy
sibly argue that Hume believed that reduction of ▶ Legal Rules and Deontic Logic
“Ought” to “Is” is feasible, i.e., that statements ▶ Legal Rules as Hypothetical Imperatives
about duties are in fact statements about facts
(about what is agreeable or useful to oneself or
other persons or what would be approved by the
References
impartial spectator). There seems to be an incon-
sistency in the claim that one cannot derive duties Black M (1964) The gap between ‘Is’ and ‘Should’. Philos
of facts and that duties are reducible to facts; Rev 73(2):165–181
however, this inconsistency could be eliminated Botros S (2006) Hume, reason and morality. A legacy of
if Hume’s purportedly normative moral theory contradiction. Routledge, Abingdon
Capaldi N (1966) Hume’s rejection of ‘ought’ as a moral
was interpreted as a descriptive moral theory category. J Philos 63:126–137
(saying how people do in fact make moral judg- Cohon R (2008) Hume’s morality. Feeling and fabrication.
ments). Perhaps this was Hume’s intention, but Oxford University Press, Oxford
this issue is hard to settle. The interpretational Darwall S (1995) The British moralists and the internal
‘ought’. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
problems of Kant’s theory are of a much less Haakonsen K (1981) The science of a legislator: the natural
serious nature. There is no controversy as to the jurisprudence of David Hume and Adam Smith. Cam-
basic claims of Kant: he believes that “Ought” bridge University Press, Cambridge
cannot be either derived from “Is” or reduced to Hume D (2000) A treatise of human nature. Clarendon
Press, Oxford
it; that it constitutes a separate realm, radically Kant I (1964) Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals
different from the realm of facts; and that it may (trans: Paton HJ). Harper & Row, New York
be known by means of reason. The crucial inter- Korsgaard C (1996) The sources of normativity. Cam-
pretational problem of Kant’s moral theory con- bridge University Press, New York
MacIntyre A (1959) Hume on ‘is’ and ‘ought’. Philos Rev
cerns the very relation between the sphere of 68:451–468
“Ought” and reason: whether reason constitutes Mackie JL (1980) Hume’s moral theory. Routledge,
it or discovers it; and if reason constitutes it (what London
seems to us to be a more plausible interpretation), Moore GE (1903) Principia ethica. Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge
what specific implications this “constitution” has Paton HJ (1946) The categorical imperative. A study in
for the question about the ontological status of the Kant’s moral philosophy. Hutchinson University
sphere of “Ought” (it is clear that this account of Library, London
the sphere of “Ought” makes it metaphysical, but Pidgen C (2011) Hume on is and ought. Philos Now
83:18–20
it remains unclear what is the difference between Searle J (1964) How to derive ‘ought’ from ‘is’. Philos Rev
the strong, external “Ought” understood in the 73(1):43–58
Kantian way and the strong, external “Ought”
understood in the spirit of ethical rationalists).

You might also like