You are on page 1of 16

Space-time, ‘science’ and the relationship

between physical geography and human


geography
Doreen Massey

This paper explores the possibility that there may be commonalities between
physical geography and human geography in emerging ways of conceptualizing
space, time and space-time. It argues that one of the things holding physical and
human geography apart for so long has been their relationship to physics as an
assumed model of ‘science’. It is proposed here that not only is this an inadequate
model of science but that it has led us astray in our inherited conceptualizations of
both time and space. The urge to think ‘historically’ is now evident in both physical
and human geography. The paper argues that this both forms the basis for a
possible conversation and also obliges us to rethink our notions of
space/space-time.

key words space-time/time-space complexity emergence physics envy

Faculty of Social Sciences, Open University, Walton Hall, Milton Keynes MK7 6AA

revised manuscript received 1 June 1999

Connections of course – one thinks of socialist environmental-


ism, for instance. Moreover, there is new work: that
This paper is a preliminary dip into deep waters. It of Whatmore (1999) and Murdoch (1997) among
will doubtless be taken to task on all sides. In a others springs to mind. This paper takes a particu-
sense (although I would rather not be proven too lar tack at the issue. It stems from the idea that
horribly wrong), that might in itself not be too there may be some questions that both physical
dismaying. For the argument presented here and human geographers are concerned with,
arises not only out of my theoretical interest in which we might, therefore, be able to debate
space(-time) but also out of another conviction. For together. There are, potentially, many such ques-
a whole variety of reasons, the carving-up of the tions (including those that branch off from the one
world and of scientific endeavour between disci- under consideration here – questions of realist
plines has been experienced recently as increas- philosophy, of the conceptualization of entities, of
ingly untenable. One of the most well-established reductionism, of path-dependence, of questions of
and best-fortified of these old divides within probability and indeterminacy, etc); this paper is a
knowledge has been that between the ‘physical’ tentative foray in one direction, but a direction that
and ‘human’ sciences. Yet even that ingrained is at the heart of our joint enterprise – the nature of
counterposition between so-called ‘natural’ and space, and therefore (I will argue) of space-time.
‘social’ is increasingly being questioned, and my The immediate stimuli for this paper were arti-
conviction is that if they are now up for reinspec- cles from geographers working in fields very dif-
tion and problematization, then geographers ferent (I had thought) from my own. They were
should be in a good position to make a leading Jonathan Raper and David Livingstone’s (1995)
contribution. In some areas they have long done so, ‘Development of a geomorphological spatial model
Trans Inst Br Geogr NS 24 261–276 1999
ISSN 0020-2754 © Royal Geographical Society (with The Institute of British Geographers) 1999
262 Doreen Massey
using object-oriented design’ and David Sugden’s In the object-oriented approach the environmental
(1996) ‘The East Antarctic ice sheet: unstable ice or scientist must declare the nature of the real-world
unstable ideas?’. The latter was David Sugden’s entities identified first: their characteristics and
vice-presidential address at the 1996 RGS-IBG behaviour structure the spatial representation. (360)
annual conference and in it he urged that his (The implication of this is, of course, that the GIS
reading of the controversy surrounding the history folk have to receive the spatio-temporal frame-
of the Antarctic ice sheet carried ‘further implica- work from the application domain, rather than, as
tions for geomorphology in particular and for heretofore, themselves being in a position to decide
physical geography and geography as a whole’ it.) Second, this approach to space-time enables the
(451). The present paper is in part an attempt conceptualization of entities themselves as a set of
to pick up that baton and to explore the connec- ‘worlds’ (365), where each world has its own
tions to and implications for my neck of the four-dimensional reference system. ‘Time’, they
geographical woods. write, ‘is a property of the objects’ (366). Third, and
Let me begin, however, with Raper and implicit in all of this, is that for the kind of work
Livingstone’s paper. This is an argument for the that Raper and Livingstone are addressing, it is
importance of a concept of relative space in the necessary to think not in terms of space and time
representation/modelling of environmental prob- separately, but in terms of a four-dimensional
lems. ‘[T]he way that spatio-temporal processes are space-time (364).
studied’, they argue, ‘is strongly influenced by the All of this was, for me, totally engrossing. It rang
model of space and time that is adopted’ (1995, many bells with my own work, and that of many
364). Traditionally, the authors argue, while envi- others, within human geography. We, too, have
ronmental representations have been somewhat been struggling to understand space (and space-
unthinking about the concepts of space and time time) as constituted through the social, rather than
that they imply and necessarily incorporate, they as dimensions defining an arena within which the
have in fact been dominated by ‘‘‘timeless’’ geo- social takes place. We too have tried to consider the
metric methods focused on two dimensional idea of local time-spaces, time-spaces specific
planes’ (363). Raper and Livingstone’s aim is to to the entities with which they are mutually con-
disrupt this unthought assumption and to argue for stitutive. Thrift’s (1996) explorations in rethinking
a more self-conscious and ‘relative’ understanding. theory and space together and Whatmore’s (1997)
In doing this, they turn to ‘theoretical develop- proposals for relational thinking are prominent
ments in physics’ (363) and in particular to Einstein examples, as is much of the work that draws on the
and Minkowski. This allows them to do a number writing of Bruno Latour. The new Open University
of things. First, it provides concepts that enable us course on Understanding cities tries to conceive of
to understand space and time as ‘dimensions that cities as open time-space intensities of social rela-
are defined by the entities that inhabit them and tions, themselves encompassing and interlocking a
not vice versa’: variety of sub-time-spaces of different groups and
activities. In brief, a number of human geographers
space and time must be considered relative concepts, ie,
they are determined by the nature and behaviour of the are now trying to rethink space as integrally space-
entities that ‘inhabit’ them (the concept of ‘relative time and to conceptualize space-time as relative
space’). This is the inverse of the situation where space (defined in terms of the entities ‘within’ it), rela-
and time themselves form a rigid framework which has tional (as constituted through the operation of
an existence independent of the entities (the concept of social relations, through which the ‘entities’ are
‘absolute space’). (363) also constituted) and integral to the constitution of
the entities themselves (the entities are local time-
Thus they distinguish between two approaches to spaces). Sometimes it can make your head hurt to
the spatial modelling of environmental problems: think in this way, but as Raper and Livingstone
the geometrically indexed (absolute space) and the argue (1995, 364), ‘the way that spatio-temporal
object-oriented (relative space). processes are studied is strongly influenced by the
Using the former approach makes the coordinate model of space and time that is adopted.’ In other
system . . . into the primary index of the spatial repre- words, it matters; it makes a difference.
sentation and dictates much of the representational Moreover, this way of conceiving of the world is
structure of the environmental problem of interest. coming onto the agenda in wider debates within
Space-time, ‘science’ and the relationship between physical geography and human geography 263
the philosophy of social sciences. Perhaps most up in such ideas as ‘quintessential Englishness’
evidently, there are resonances here of Deleuze and and more general forms of exclusivist nationalisms
Guattari’s (1984) ‘events’ and ‘becomings’ – see the and parochialisms.
definition of ‘entities’ above (although I would But to register these points is not at all to
argue that their formulation is a lot better on time attempt to distance myself/ourselves from what is
than it is on space). And, of course, the project of happening in Raper and Livingstone’s part of
reuniting space and time, and freeing ourselves geography. Rather it is to suggest that what we
from the debilitating separation of them that we have here is the potential for debate and discus-
have inherited, primarily (though not only) from sion, together. Maybe there are questions and
Kant, is one now being taken up by many writers debates, and even some tentative ‘answers’, that
(see, for instance, Massey 1992 and references different parts of geography have in common.
therein). Unwin (1993), in the resounding coda to
his book, argued for a reunification of geography
precisely around a reconceptualization of time-
‘Science’ and physics envy
space. Indeed, rather than arguing for a repriorit-
ization of space (in a kind of competition with There was, moreover, another aspect of Raper and
time), we should perhaps be arguing for a unified Livingstone’s paper that rang bells with me as a
understanding. As Larry Grossberg has written: human geographer. As I said, they turn to physics
‘The bifurcation of time and space, and the for stimulation in the development of their
privileging of time over space, was perhaps the approach. In this they are adopting a strategy – of
founding moment of modern philosophy’ (1996, referring to a ‘harder’ science – that is common
178); in a footnote, he adds, ‘the crucial issue is the across the subspecialisms within geography (and
separation of the two’ (187). indeed beyond). Cultural geographers may cite
Now, even at this level of generality, it was clear chaos theory, urban theorists turn to formulations
to me, on reading Raper and Livingstone, that from quantum mechanics, anyone arguing about
there were also differences of emphasis between the nature of knowledge might draw on the
their approach and mine. Thus, to give one exam- thinking of Heisenberg.
ple, they focus their conceptualization on ‘entities’, Two things in particular interest me about this
while it is perhaps more usual in the debates of phenomenon: on the one hand how we do it (that is,
which I am aware in human geography to focus on the terms on which we make the appeal) and on
the mutual constitution of relations and entities, the other hand the intellectual history of why we do
along with space itself. Their approach is explicitly it. It is my opinion that, at least in some cases, this
‘object-oriented’ and the objects come before the habit of referring to physics bears witness to an
space-times. For me it is easier and more helpful to implicit imagination both of a model of science and
understand entities and space-times as being con- of a particular relationship between the disciplines.
stituted in the same moment and as that in itself It is an imagination that physical and human
happening through the relational constitution of geographers share, even though in the latter case it
them both. This kind of relational understanding of is less explicitly held and would probably be
space and of entities/objects/identities is gaining denied if openly challenged (as I am challenging it
increasing currency within human geography. It is here). Moreover, I want to argue, it is an imagina-
now quite frequently argued that (social) spatiality tion which, while it may be shared by physical and
and entities such as ‘places’ are products of our human geographers, nonetheless serves to hold us
(social) interactions. The implications are numer- apart.
ous and range from a querying of the tendency to Raper and Livingstone are careful about the
see space as necessarily divided into closed and nature of their reference to physics. They are aware
bounded regions – a querying which would aug- of the need to define the limits to validity of the
ment this with a focus on interconnections – claims they are making, and remain consistent
through to the more general assertion that we have with the arguments of physics in accepting that
a responsibility for the spatialities through which concepts of absolute space may be suitable for
we live and construct our lives. It is an approach some spheres of geographical work (they cite land-
that opens up questions of the supposed ‘essences’ resource management as an example). This is not,
of places, along with notions of authenticity bound then, a general proposition about the applicability
264 Doreen Massey
of concepts of relative space. Their point is that There is a particular contradiction here: many of
‘there are arguments for the use of a ‘‘relative our appeals to physics these days are in fact to the
space’’ approach in the study of environmental new views of the world coming out of quantum
problems’ (1995, 363).1 Moreover, they turn to mechanics and more recent developments. This is
physics on defined terms: that it has ‘expanded the quite acceptable when the reference takes the form
range of concepts available’ (363). In other words, of pointing to a stimulating new idea or a potential
it is treated as a provocation, a stimulus to thought. analogy. But when it takes the form of a demon-
In this, however, they are quite different from some stration of proof simply through appeal to a higher
others, in both physical and human geography, authority, the irony is that that authority was
who turn to physics as a kind of higher authority, established in relation to, and in the days of, a
as a source of unimpugnable truth. It is what I call much older form of physics. We need, then, to be
the reverential reference: if ‘physics’ says so, who are circumspect about the nature and status of our
we to disagree? references.
Such an attitude is, of course, built upon implicit In human geography and related disciplines, for
understandings that lie deep within us, as both instance, what precisely is the status of appeals to
intellectuals and ‘ordinary citizens’. There has quantum mechanics or chaos theory? What, really,
developed over the last few centuries (building on are the grounds for evocations of fractal space?
even older foundations) an acceptance of a hier- As provocations to the imagination they may be
archy among the sciences, between the disciplines, wonderfully stimulating; as implicit assertions of a
and between forms of knowledge. It operates both single ontology they need justifying; as invocations
in general and with great precision. Within the of a higher, truer science they may be deeply
standard disciplines, physics is at one end and suspect.3
(say) cultural studies and the humanities at the There are, moreover, further reasons for caution.
other. Neoclassical economics has striven to distin- It is rare, for instance, that one can legitimately or
guish itself from other social sciences and to give unequivocally appeal to ‘recent developments in
itself as much as possible the appearance of a physics’ in proof or demonstration of an argument
physical (hard) science. Physical geographers on in another field, for such developments are often
occasions think they are ‘more scientific’ than themselves the subject of fierce debate. In my own
human geographers, where the term ‘scientific’ work on the reconceptualization of spatiality in
conjures up images of the status and worth of the ways adequate to face up to some of the problems
knowledge acquired. And yet, while the physical posed by modern times, I have also found myself
geographer might feel this way about the human, exploring debates about temporality. Indeed, not
the feelings are reversed when they turn to face the only would I argue that we need to think in terms
other way. Thus Frodeman writes of ‘the ‘‘physics of space-time/time-space, but also I would pro-
envy’’ that geology sometimes seems to suffer from pose that any conceptualization of space has a
(ie the sense of inferiority concerning the status (logically) necessary corollary in a particular
of geology as compared with other, ‘‘harder’’ ‘matching’ conceptualization of time. The fact that
sciences) . . .’ (1995, 961). And in a different people often work with ‘unmatched pairs’ is, I
discipline altogether, that of biology, Steven Rose maintain, the source of a number of the difficulties
deploys a very similar language to argue that his that scientists of all sorts have frequently faced in
discipline is often ‘said to suffer from a sense of this matter.
inferiority, of ‘‘physics envy’’ (which may perhaps The concept of space for which I want to argue is
be why these days many molecular biologists try to one that holds that space is open and dynamic.
behave as if they are physicists!)’ (1997, 9).2 This is That is (and given what was said above about
an envy that is deeply embedded, and it pro- space-time), ‘space’ cannot be a closed system: it is
vides an implicit grounding for references to the not stasis, it is not defined negatively as an absence
authority of physics in many a part of geography. of temporality, it is not the classic ‘slice through
There are many reasons to contest this assump- time’. Indeed, the closed-system/slice-through-
tion of authority. Most evidently, the established time imagination of space denies the possibility of
status of physics, of its methodology and its truth- a real temporality – for there is no mechanism for
claims, is based on an image of that discipline that moving from one slice to the next (Massey 1997).
is now out of date. Physics itself has moved on. Rather the spatiality that I envisage would be open,
Space-time, ‘science’ and the relationship between physical geography and human geography 265
would be constantly in the process of being made on the nature of geology as a science, argued the
(the relations yet to be established, or not) and following:
would have elements of both order and accident
Historical science . . . cuts across the traditional lines
(the latter deriving from the happenstance juxta-
between the various sciences: physics, chemistry,
positions and separations which – I argue – are astronomy, geology, biology, anthropology, psychology,
intrinsic to space). It would be integral to space- sociology, and the rest. Each of these has both historical
time. That kind of understanding of space, how- and nonhistorical aspects, although the proportions of
ever, ‘matches’ with a particular view of time: as the two differ greatly. Among the sciences named, the
irreversible and the vehicle of novelty. Now, I historical element plays the smallest role in physics,
could appeal to ‘physics’ for corroborating witness where it is frequently ignored, and the greatest in
to this argument; but I could also – being honest – sociology, where the existence of nonhistorical aspects
find a physics that proposed quite the opposite is sometimes denied – one of the reasons that sociology
has not always been ranked as a science. It is not a
point of view. And, within physics, I am not
coincidence that there is a correlation with complexity
competent to judge. We must not, then, resort to
and levels of integration, physics being the simplest
tactics that in reality amount to picking out for and sociology the most complex science in this partial
quotation – and as ‘proof’ – one’s favourite, or list. Unfortunately philosophers of science have tended
most compatible, ‘harder’ scientist. to concentrate on one end of this spectrum, and that the
I will not belabour any further all these argu- simplest, so much as to give a distorted, and in some
ments against the supposed scientific superiority of instances quite false, idea of the philosophy of science
physics, save to make two brief points and one as a whole.
more extended one. First that, however ‘hard’ a
science is, it is still the product of a process con- A whole host of issues clamour for attention in that
ducted within and influenced by a wider social quotation. To begin with, Simpson makes the very
context and the conditions and character of its own important point that the move along the spectrum
performance. The work of sociologists of knowl- from physics (nineteenth-century model) to sociol-
edge, actor-network theorists and others is now too ogy involves an increase in complexity. Physics’
well known for this point to need further elabora- focus on relatively simple systems, therefore, and
tion. Second that, wherever one finds oneself on especially the initial focus on the simple, timeless
this supposed ‘spectrum’ from physics to cultural systems of classical mechanics, has been problem-
studies, certain debates in which one is engaged atical for the development of other forms of knowl-
seem to be shared with at least some of those both edge. The assumption that non-simple aspects of
upstream and downstream. The work of Isabelle the world were in principle reducible to simple
Stengers and of Marilyn Strathern comes to mind: systems (or, in terms of knowledge-production,
neither of them geographers but both widely read would need to be if ‘scientific’ knowledge were to
by geographers. As a social scientist much preoc- be gained from them), that they were really simple
cupied with essentialism, I find the debates within systems with too much ‘noise’ in them, prevented
biology about the existence or not of ‘natural kinds’ them from being addressed in their own right as
(and, if they exist, debates about their conceptual- complex systems. As is now being ever more fre-
ization) to be both fascinating and unsettling quently argued in a range of fields, the move from
(see, for instance, Goodwin 1995; Rose 1997). an assumption of simplicity to a recognition of
Arguments in number theory about the status of complexity (with openness, feedback, non-linearity
‘natural numbers’ keep me equally riveted. Is there and a move away from simple equilibrium) can
here a return to a Platonism which I, in my part of change the picture entirely, to the point of
the forest, am struggling to be free from? thoroughly undermining many of the conclusions
The final and more extended point stems from arrived at through the analysis of simple systems
the fact that there is a considerable literature deny- alone. Prigogine and Stengers (1984) and Prigogine
ing the view of ‘physics’ (in classical mechanical (1997) argue this point at some length, expanding it
guise) as the one true method of doing science and to make the wider observation that an overconcen-
as the purest form of scientific knowledge. Both tration on simple systems might, at least on occa-
Frodeman and Rose argue this position, as do a sions, have led us thoroughly astray. With such
host of authors in both geology and geomorphol- arguments gaining an ever-wider hearing, it would
ogy. Thus Simpson (1963, 46), in a classic statement seem that, at least within academe if not in more
266 Doreen Massey
popular understandings, the higher status of In other words, it has ignored the emergent phe-
branches of science that restricted themselves to nomena: the landforms. And this in turn is related
simple systems might come in for further question- to time-span. Sugden’s paper demonstrates how an
ing. Perhaps disciplines that study ‘complex sys- understanding of the longer-term historical geo-
tems’ (from meteorology to sociology) can now morphology can lead to a different interpretation
lead the way. Certainly it is now increasingly of the history of the ice sheet.
argued that a number of different approaches Sugden’s aim (like that of Frodeman and
can be taken to the analysis of any individual Simpson for geology) is to argue that geomorphol-
object of study. Richards (1990; 1994, for example) ogy must be understood not as a discipline that is
makes a strong and detailed case for this in geo- an imperfect physics but rather as a complex and
morphology, enabling a move away from reduc- synthetic science that combines within itself atten-
tionism and a greater recognition of complex open tion to ‘timeless’ processes and understanding of
systems and feedback effects. And Spedding (1997) historical ones. Certainly what the argument as a
proposes a new kind of question for geomorphol- whole implies is that any comparisons between
ogy, one that gives priority to compositional physical and human geography on the basis of
relationships rather than to detailed process ‘scientific status’ need to be laid aside. Rather, we
studies. Crucial to this is another implication of should put in a claim for their both being sciences
complexity – emergence: of the complex and the historical, which are badly
served by looking to (an anyway now miscon-
The phenomenon of emergence enables us to describe
emergent forms sui generis. We don’t have to under- ceived notion of) physics as a model. This does not
stand brain chemistry to understand language, even mean that no assumptions of timeless processes
though the latter would not be possible without the may be made; even in the social field such assump-
former. (Sayer personal communication) tions may on occasions be innocuous. But both
physical and human geographers need to be
Similarly, in David Sugden’s analysis of the history cautious about their references to so-called harder
of the east Antarctic ice sheet, two approaches are sciences and a good deal more rigorous about the
presented: the biostratigraphical and the geomor- terms on which such references are made. Being
phological. The two approaches lead to very differ- self-critical in that way, by wrenching ourselves
ent understandings of the history of the ice sheet. away from all vestiges of that old imagination, we
The biostratigraphical approach appears to favour might find at least a few elements of a common
a history of dynamic change, while the geomor- ground: that both physical and human geography
phological points to a more stable past. It is a – at least in large measure – are complex sciences
difference in the analysis of history that has signifi- about complex systems.
cant contemporary implications: each view implies
a different prognostication of the potential results
of global warming.
Historical time
In recent years, the biostratigraphical approach
has had the wider currency. Sugden’s challenge is Simpson, in the quotation cited earlier, not only
that interpretation of its data has ignored the makes a distinction between simple and complex
broader geomorphological setting. This, he argues, systems and sciences, but also relates it to a further
is typical of a more general phenomenon: that distinction – between non-historical and historical.
geomorphology has, in recent decades ‘stressed This is a fundamental connection. One of the keys
short-term process studies and retreated from in this debate, certainly amongst geologists and
studies of landscape evolution’ (1996, 451). This, geomorphologists, is the distinction between pro-
in turn, he relates to the traditional view that cesses (and thus forms of explanation) that are
geology and geomorphology are a kind of physics timeless and those that are time-bound. (Different
manqué: terms are sometimes deployed in this distinction:
Viewed in this light and driven by the aspiration to be
Simpson (1963) uses immanent and configura-
scientific, it is perhaps understandable that geomor- tional, Bernal (1951) immanent and contingent.)
phology has stressed reductionism, short-term process There are also intermediate cases, such as equilib-
studies and experimentation as the optimum route to rium systems (see below). But the crucial point
knowledge. (451–2) here is that time-bound processes are historical in
Space-time, ‘science’ and the relationship between physical geography and human geography 267
the full sense that they develop a future that is this relationship of mutual admiration, Frodeman
open. argues, remained long undisturbed. It was little
Now, I want to argue that there are implications wonder that so many disciplines developed a form
here for the way in which we understand time of physics envy.
itself. Moreover, given my earlier proposition that Other philosophers and branches of philosophy
any conceptualization of the nature of time will have, however, long struggled against these formu-
have implications for the conceptualization of lations, largely developing in opposition to a
space, I want to propose that there are also, hidden reduction of ‘knowledge’ to a narrow interpreta-
within this debate, implications for how we think tion of science. The impulse for much of this latter
about space and spatiality. In other words, our investigation was the double argument that, on the
relationship to nineteenth-century physics has mis- one hand, ‘science’ was not the only – nor even
led us not only about simplicity/complexity but necessarily the best – way to gain knowledge of
also about our concepts of time. This has had reality and, on the other hand, that there is no one
effects in both natural and social sciences. It has best scientific method.
also had reverberations for how we conceptualize Frodeman wishes to inject more of this stream of
space. So, if we could overthrow some of our philosophy into geology: to abandon the search for
(shared, if different) fascinations with nineteenth- general timeless laws for everything (see also
century physics we might also be free to reimagine Simpson 1963) and to turn to the development of a
space/space-time. specifically historical approach.
Frodeman provides a good place from which to This issue of history is crucial. Frodeman points
begin. As David Sugden does for geomorphology, out that time has been absolutely central to the
Frodeman proposes for geology that it be accepted development of these critical strands of philoso-
as an historical science.4 Although he does not phy, but he does not develop the point further. In
spell this out, what is at issue here is the nature of fact, consideration of time was central to such
time: timeless processes do not generate a notion of philosophies precisely because the classical science
open historical time. In other words, behind the of the day evoked timelessness. This was the case
long-established status of ‘physics’ (largely in not only in the concept of fully timeless processes,
the guise of classical mechanics) as the scientific but also in closed equilibrium systems, where the
discipline par excellence has been an implicit future is given, contained within the initial condi-
assumption about time that deprives it of its tions – it is closed. This flew in the face of what
openness; reduces its possibility of being these critical philosophers knew of the world. A
historical. long history of the development of ideas about
This has been reflected in the complex relation- time was set in train. Prigogine and Stengers (1984)
ship between ‘science’ and philosophy. Frodeman analyse this history in detail. They point to a whole
argues that, in the case of geology, this relationship string of philosophers, from Hegel through
has been distant (geologists being impatient with Heidegger to Whitehead, struggling against what
philosophizing and philosophers not seeing any- they feared were the wider implications of the
thing of serious import within geology). However, epistemological and ontological claims of the then
he argues that this lack of dialogue has been set currently dominant forms of science. Diderot,
against a mutual commitment (and admiration) Kant, Hegel, Whitehead and Bergson all
between science-as-physics and philosophy-as- ‘attempted to analyse and limit the scope of
positivism.5 Such philosophy, especially in its early modern science as well as to open new perspec-
days and in the writings of people such as Carnap tives seen as radically alien to that science’
(1937), maintained that science was the only road (Prigogine and Stengers 1984, 79–80). Central to
to knowledge and that there was only one true their struggle was the argument that time must be
scientific method; it committed itself to (its under- fully open-futured. Bergson was crucial here: for
standings of) objectivity, the empirical method him, time was about the continuous emergence of
and epistemological monism (which essentially novelty, ‘To him the future is becoming in a way that
incorporated a reductionism-to-physics). Such an can never be a mere rearrangement of what has
approach can not admit ‘the fully historical’ into been’ (Adam 1990, 24).
the realm of the scientific. In spite of subsequent The ‘hard sciences’ were obdurate, however.
debates, and later writings such as those of Kuhn, Prigogine and Stengers (1984, 16) argue that this
268 Doreen Massey
difficulty of getting ‘science’ to recognize a fully of their day) and social (see Prigogine and Stengers
historical temporality ‘led to discouragement’. As 1984; see also a number of other accounts, such as
they put it, at that historical moment the choice Toulmin 1990).
seemed to be either to accept the pronouncements However, this troubled relationship also influ-
of classical science or to resort to a metaphysical enced the course that was taken by (some) philo-
philosophy. Bergson (along with Whitehead and sophical and social theorizing. One example is the
others) took the latter route. assumption mentioned above: that there is a rela-
One result of this, which I believe to have been tionship between space and representation. To
both utterly devastating and at the same time ‘represent’ was (and still often is) understood as
foundational for much subsequent philosophical being to ‘spatialize’. This assumption runs as a
and social thought, was that as a consequence of guiding thread through Laclau’s (1990) later work
these philosophers laying claim to the essential on the philosophy of radical democracy; it is
creativity of time, space – postulated as the intuitive asserted without further explanation by de Certeau
opposite – came to be seen as the realm of the dead. (1984); it reverberates throughout much of struc-
For Bergson, ‘space’ became associated with the turalism. Even one of the strongest protagonists
science with which he was embattled. If such within our own discipline of the importance of the
science ignored time (the open temporality that he spatial takes this view:
was struggling to assert) it must therefore be
Any system of representation, in fact, is a spatialization
‘space’ (a leap of ‘logic’ that I find totally unten- of sorts which automatically freezes the flow of
able, but you can see why it happens). Further, he experience and in so doing distorts what it strives to
interpreted the very process of scientific produc- represent . . . (Harvey 1989, 206)
tion as one of ‘spatialization’ (ie of taking ‘time’ out
of things). Indeed, representation as a generic There are two things going on here: first the
activity became associated with the spatial, an argument that representation necessarily fixes, and
association that lives on strongly to this day. For therefore deadens and detracts from, the flow of
Bergson, ‘the rational mind merely spatializes’; he life; and second that this process of deadening is
thought in terms of ‘the immobilizing (spatial) equivalent to ‘spatialization’. The first proposition I
categories of the intellect’ (Gross 1981–82, 62, 66): would not entirely dispute, though I shall go on to
modify the form in which it is customarily
For Bergson, the mind is by definition spatially ori-
couched. However, it seems to me that there is no
ented. But everything creative, expansive and teeming
with energy is not. Hence, the intellect can never help case at all for the second proposition: that there is
us reach what is essential because it kills and fragments an equivalence between space and representation.
all that it touches . . . We must, Bergson concluded, It is one of those accepted things that are by now
break out of the spatialization imposed by mind in so deeply embedded that they are rarely if ever
order to regain contact with the core of the truly living, questioned.
which subsists only in the time dimension . . .6 I would argue three things and pose one ques-
tion. First argument: that this now-hegemonic
I want to propose that this engagement between equation of space and representation in fact derives
‘science’ and different branches of philosophy (and from nineteenth-century and early twentieth-
thereby also social sciences) both has been genu- century battles over the meaning of time (as argued
inely two-sided and has had deep implications for above). This may be why, historically, representa-
how we think about space. In the era of classical tion has come to be equated with spatialization,
science – and on the issue of time – social science but in fact such terminology is both mistaken and
and philosophy were clearly reaching for questions actively harmful. Second argument: that represen-
that the dominant natural scientists of their day tation may indeed ‘fix’ and ‘stabilize’ (though see
simply did not grasp. These early so-called harder below), but that what it so stabilizes is not simply
scientists could with benefit have listened to and time but space-time. And third argument: that this
learned from philosophers and social scientists. historically significant way of imagining space/
Moreover, the reasons that they did not learn, or in spatialization not only derives from an assumption
some cases that they resisted so fiercely the ques- that space is to be defined simply as a lack of
tions and arguments of certain critical philoso- temporality (holding time still) but also has con-
phers, were both scientific (according to the lights tributed substantially to its continuing to be
Space-time, ‘science’ and the relationship between physical geography and human geography 269
thought of in that way. It is, however, a totally Moreover, there is a further point: that debates
inadequate conception of space. within physics itself are now challenging the
The question is this: given this association of arguments about temporality even there. What
space with representation, and the characterization Prigogine argued in much of his early work in
of space as immobility, what options are there for chemistry and physics, and now Prigogine and
representing space itself for cartography, for GIS, to Stengers argue more broadly, is that natural science
develop a form of mapping that – although repre- itself is changing (must now change) its own view
sentation – does not reduce space to a dead surface. of time – that the new reconceptualizations of
How can it be brought alive? This is an issue physics lead towards the recognition of an open
influenced both by the techniques available and by and fully historical notion of time. So natural
conceptual stance, and it is addressed by Raper science must change, and is indeed beginning
and Livingstone (1995, 362): the problem ‘concerns to do so:
the representation of a continuous reality using
The results of non-equilibrium thermodynamics are
discrete entities’; the issue, in other words and in close to the views expressed by Bergson and
my terms, is not the spatialization of the temporal Whitehead. Nature is indeed related to the creation of
(the dominant view of what representation is all unpredictable novelty, where the possible is richer than
about) but the representation of space-time. And the real. (Prigogine 1997, 72)
the representation of space-time is itself an emer- But what this in turn means, of course, is that the
gent product of the conceptualization of the space- science against which Bergson and others
time entities themselves. Deleuze and Guattari constructed their ideas no longer has to be
address this by challenging the notion of represen- combated . . .
tation. For them, a concept should express an event
rather than an essence. In Allen et al (1998), we the limitations Bergson criticized are beginning to be
were aiming to reconceptualize the region in this overcome, not by abandoning the scientific approach or
abstract thinking but by perceiving the limitations of
way – our object of study was ‘the-south-east-in-
the concepts of classical dynamics and by discovering
the-1980s’ – what Deleuze and Guattari might call
new formulations valid in more general situations.
an event, and what we would call a time-space. (Prigogine and Stengers 1984, 93)
Deleuze and Guattari (1984, 23) go further, how-
ever, and argue against any notion of a tripartite This must also mean that, insofar as it was influ-
division between reality, representation and subjec- enced – as it must have been – by the battle it was
tivity: ‘Rather, an assemblage establishes connec- waging at the time, Bergson’s own formulation can
tions between certain multiplicities drawn from now itself be reworked. In other words, we are not
each of these orders.’ Here representation is no obliged to follow his conclusions about space.
longer stasis, but an element in a continuous pro- Moreover and finally, and in case you were
duction; a part of it all, and constantly ‘becoming’. tempted to point to an inconsistency here, my
In geography, Thrift’s (1996) explorations in non- citing of Prigogine (Nobel Prize winner in a hard
representational theory are pushing in a similar science, etc) is not done in the manner of reference
direction. to the unimpugnable authority of ‘science’, for
But to return to the main argument: all this there are as many fierce debates among scientists
misreading of space, I would argue, came about about these matters as there are amongst philoso-
because of social scientists’ and philosophers’ phers and social scientists. Rather, it is simply to
reactions to natural science’s intransigence on the demonstrate that we no longer have to battle
matter of time. It was as a result of science’s against a ‘science’ that appears monolithically to
intransigence that some philosophers sought a way say the opposite.
around its propositions.
The argument here is that these lines of devel- Imagining ‘history’ in physical and human
opment can now be rethought. As I have argued,
geography
the culture of reverence for physics is being (or
needs to be) undermined. Not only is the (classical Some of this thinking is already well established
mechanics) image of physics an outdated one, within physical geography. Barbara Kennedy
but the validity of historical sciences, in their (1992), for instance, has reflected on the history of
own right, is being more properly recognized. geomorphology in this light. She argues that
270 Doreen Massey
the influence of Strahler’s (1952) and, more In other words, his aim is to draw on recent
particularly, Chorley’s (1962) advocacy of a developments in theories of dynamical systems
dynamic as opposed to a historical approach to that open up temporality in a more genuinely
geomorphology (that is, in the terms previously historical way. And, indeed, he draws on the work
used here, their emphasis on immanent processes, of, among others, Ilya Prigogine.
equilibrium and timelessness) has had a number of What Thornes is doing, in other words, is again
effects that should now be questioned. Thus, she drawing on a supposedly ‘harder’ science for
argues, it has encouraged the emergence of a insight into the complexities of his own. What we
history of the discipline as the gradual coming- have here is physics and maths (or, in general, a
to-dominance of that ‘scientific’ (as opposed to range of ‘harder’ sciences) as themselves historical.
historical) approach to analysis. She argues: As we have seen, there is nothing wrong with
drawing on such disciplines so long as the terms
All this has led, as is almost inevitable, to a ‘folk’ view
of the history of the subject emerging, in which the of the relationship (analogy? provocation/
triumph of the ‘dynamic’ approach is shown to be stimulation? direct translation? simple reverence?)
foreshadowed by the prescience of selected forerun- are made clear and adhered to. Taking up
ners: at its worst, this vision leads to a simple succes- Prigogine and others’ work on far-from-
sion of triumphant, dynamic ‘goodies’ and Hutton equilibrium systems, and the potential for the
begets Playfair, begets Lyell, and so forth. (Kennedy production of ‘order out of chaos’, Thornes can
1992, 232–3, emphasis in original) draw important conclusions about potential
instabilities and landscape sensitivity:
The first thing Kennedy does is question that
when a system is close to a stable equilibrium (such as
teleological interpretation of geomorphology’s his-
pediplain), random fluctuations in the environment
tory.7 Her second argument is even more central to may have little consequence, whereas if the system is at
the concerns of this paper. Chorley took the prin- or close to a bifurcation point, then small fluctuations
ciples of mechanics as the blueprint for the scien- can have dramatic effects. This is what is meant by
tific development of the discipline, opposed these landscape sensitivity. (231)
principles to those of historical analysis, and
neglected the latter. Kennedy’s argument (which However, the wider propositions about knowledge
draws on Prigogine and also more widely on chaos within which Thornes is working are also interest-
theory and the study of non-linear systems – ie ing. In the abstract to his paper, he writes that the
post-mechanical physics and chemistry) is that the renewed interest in the long-term behaviour of
separation between these approaches is, perhaps, landforms ‘should be soundly based in theory
more fluid than has often been supposed. rather than inferentially based on historical
The complexities – and indeed sometimes the studies’ (225). And later he writes of ‘the lack of
irony of the complexities – of this evolving debate any accepted theoretical (as opposed to historic-
are brought home by John Thornes’ proposals for inferential) model of long-term geomorphological
an evolutionary geomorphology (Thornes 1983). behaviour’ (225). Now, there are certainly particu-
He takes up the challenge of the ‘renewed interest lar issues of historical inference in geomorphology,
in the long-term behaviour of land forms’ (225) and given the very long-term nature of the processes it
argues that interest and emphasis in geomorphol- studies. Nonetheless, it needs to be acknowledged
ogy are shifting from the observation of equilib- that ‘theories’ also involve inference. Newton
rium states (that is, in the terminology of this ‘interpreted’, and in his interpretations was
paper, closed systems with no true historical time); influenced by the wider social movements and con-
his aim is to gain new insights into ‘historical ditions of his day. On the wider canvas, both
problems’ (234). The approach he adopts, however, ‘immanent’ and ‘configurational’ processes are
is rather different from that advocated by Sugden studied in historical contexts. Here, then, is a fur-
for geomorphology, or by Frodeman for geology; ther blurring of the distinction to add to that al-
his proposal is to shift, ready drawn out by Kennedy. Moreover, Thornes’
from the observation of equilibrium states per se to the notion of ‘theory’ seems to be confined to the
recognition of the existence of multiple stable and abstract/formal and mathematical. But ‘theories’
unstable equilibria, the bifurcations between them and can apply to the historical too. Finally, it must be
the trajectories connecting them. (234) noted that what we have here in Thornes’ work is
Space-time, ‘science’ and the relationship between physical geography and human geography 271
history as in non-linear dynamical systems. I shall sequence. All the stories of Progress, of Develop-
return to this point in a moment. ment, of Modernization (such as the movement
What is particularly interesting, however, about from traditional to modern), of the Marxist pro-
these developments in geomorphology is that in gression through modes of production (feudalism,
one way or another they are all rethinking the capitalism, socialism, communism) and of many
concept of time and their relationship to it. formulations of the story of ‘globalization’ (see
Whether it be through an emphasis on a more Massey 1999) share a geographical imagination
qualitative historical science, or via an analysis of that involves this manoeuvre: it rearranges spatial
the potential bifurcations in the paths of complex differences into temporal sequence.8 Such a move
dynamical systems, the implication is that time is has enormous implications: it implies that places
truly open-ended. are not genuinely different (I shall discuss below
One of the reasons I personally find this so what I mean by this) but simply ‘behind’ or
interesting is that I believe a similar shift has been ‘advanced’ within the same story; their ‘difference’
underway in the social/human sciences, or at least consists only of their place in the queue.
in parts of them. And this is in spite of the fact that This, then, is a powerful (in the sense of fre-
these sciences – or most of them – would have quently hegemonic) imaginary geography which –
planted themselves firmly in the camp of the ironically – serves to occlude the real significance
historical. For there is, of course, history and of geography. It obliterates, or at minimum in its
history. There are different ways of imagining muted forms reduces, the import and the full
history which imply distinct conceptualizations of measure of the real differences that are at issue. So
time and temporality (and, as I shall go on to what is ‘real difference’? I want to argue that a full
argue in the final section of this paper, space and recognition of difference would understand it as
spatiality). more than place in a sequence, for understanding
First of all, of course, it is necessary to note the difference as place-in-a-sequence is, after all, a kind
many attempts by human geographers to model of temporo-spatial version of that understanding of
themselves on Newtonian physics. Notions of difference that sees others as really only ‘a varia-
timeless processes were integral to much of the tion on myself’, where ‘myself’ is the one con-
modelling work of the 1970s. And the closed times structing the imagination. So the countries of, say,
of closed equilibrium systems have also figured the South of this planet (in these modernist imagi-
prominently. In the human sciences more widely, nations of progress emanating on the whole from
it has been the development of neoclassical eco- the North) are not really different – they are just
nomics from the 1870s to the 1900s (and still going slow versions of us. In contrast to this, a fuller
strong today) that has provided the iconic example recognition of difference would acknowledge that
of an explicit physics envy that referred (and the South might not just be following us; that it
refers) itself to the physics that was dominant in might, rather, have its own story to tell.9 A fuller
the nineteenth century. recognition of difference would grant the other, the
There have, however, been ways in which different, at least a degree of autonomy in that
‘history’ has been imagined in the social sciences, sense (where relative autonomy does not mean a
which have themselves been problematical. Thus, lack of interconnection – some stories are more
many of the great ‘modernist’ understandings of overarching than others, for example – but rather
the world implicitly drew upon, and thereby estab- the absence of a teleology of the single story). In
lished as unthought assumptions, a highly particu- other words, a fuller recognition of difference
lar conceptualization of time, of space, and of the would entertain the possibility of the existence of a
relationship between them. The aspect of this that multiplicity of trajectories.
is most significant for the present argument is their Now, to anticipate somewhat the argument of
habit of convening space in temporal terms. When, the final section, it is also the case that for there to
in economic geography for instance, we use terms be multiple trajectories – for there to be coexisting
such as ‘advanced’ and ‘backward’, ‘developed’ differences – there must be space, and for there to
and ‘developing’, we are effectively imagining be space there must be multiple trajectories. Thus,
spatial differences (differences between places, I want to argue, a more adequate understanding of
regions, countries, etc) as temporal. We are arrang- spatiality for our times would entail the recogni-
ing differences between places into historical tion that there is more than one story going on in
272 Doreen Massey
the world and that these stories have, at least, a conceptual and political. Imagining time as truly
relative autonomy. historical not only influences how we analyse the
The important point for the moment, however, past; it also implies, when we turn to look the other
is that not only do these modernist narratives way, that the future (though inevitably influenced
suppress the full import of the spatial but they by the histories that have led to today) is also
also have a very ambiguous relationship to time. radically open.
They are tales of progress and change, and of the But if an open historicity is once again on the
irreversibility of time; they are historical in that agenda in both physical and social sciences, there
sense. And yet they are also stories in which the are still questions as to quite what this means. John
future is already foretold (progress, development, Thornes’ non-linear dynamical systems open up to
modernization, socialism, globalization). This is history in a very different way from Frodeman and
what Ernesto Laclau has dubbed a grand closed Sugden’s stress on more narrative approaches. And
system where everything that happens can be – the big question – is the political openness of the
explained internally to it ‘and everything acquires future held up to us by radical democracy and
an absolute intelligibility within the grandiose queer theory (a societal level of ‘free will’, making
scheme’ (Laclau 1990, 75). This is not the ‘time as our own histories though not, of course, in circum-
the continuous emergence of novelty’ proposed by stances . . . ) . . . is this element of ‘free will’ in some
the likes of Bergson; the way of becoming that is way equivalent to (or ultimately subverted by?) the
never a mere rearrangement of what already is. ontological indeterminacy postulated by some
Now, what has been emerging in recent years in versions (eg Prigogine and Stengers’) of far-from-
some parts of political philosophy and the social equilibrium systems thinking?
sciences is an attempt to recapture that notion of There are two major questions here. The first
the genuine openness of temporality. In different concerns both the way we think about knowledge
ways, this attempt to think a radical openness is and questions of ontology. Some authors seem to
integral to the projects of Deleuze and Guattari be proposing that we can now all meet in a new,
(see, for example, 1984) – their imagination of single (and necessarily ‘mathematical’?) ontology
nomadism, for instance – to thinking around queer that has validity across inorganic, biological and
theory (see, for instance, Golding 1997) and to the sociocultural fields. Prigogine’s arguments, which I
reworkings of Marxism through a grounded have cited earlier, could be used to support such a
Gramscianism and through radical democracy (see naturalist position. Anti-naturalists would take a
Laclau 1990; Mouffe 1993). There are fascinating different view and assert most strongly that human
similarities here to what Barbara Kennedy is argu- and natural sciences are dealing with fundamen-
ing within geomorphology with her distinction tally different spheres: that the possibility of inten-
between ‘sequence’ and ‘progression’. The latter – tionality, meaningfulness and self-reflexivity is
the progressionists (Lyell, Dana, Horton) – she restricted to the human.
argues, studied the past not to see ‘how we got There is a more complex position, which would
here from there’ but to see how ‘we must get here argue that there may well at some level be onto-
from there’ (Kennedy 1992, 247, emphasis in origi- logical commonalities, but that these are articu-
nal). In contrast, Hutton, Darwin and Gilbert lated in distinctive manners in different spheres
viewed the present as merely one of all possible and, moreover, that this distinctiveness is a phe-
worlds. These latter, she argues, saw ‘history as nomenon of emergence. Thus, although humanly
sequence’ (247–8). There are connections here, if meaningful phenomena may not be reducible to
only distant and tentative, with some of the the phenomena studied by the natural sciences,
arguments of radical democracy. In heterodox eco- they may be emergent from them. There may be
nomics, the development of institutional and evo- real similarities in the abstract pattern of function-
lutionary approaches also entails a shift towards a ing of the inorganic, the biological and the socio-
historical concept of time. And in a different vein, cultural, but in each sphere it is necessary that
but in a direct parallel with the arguments of we specify the actual, particular, ‘mechanisms’
geomorphologists such as Thornes, economists through which this functioning occurs. This
such as Krugman and Lawson are drawing in part ‘qualified naturalism’ is, it seems to me, something
on the new theoretical mathematics and physics of like the position of Deleuze and Guattari with
complexity. Many of these projects are integrally their ‘bodies-without-organs’ and their ‘abstract
Space-time, ‘science’ and the relationship between physical geography and human geography 273
machines’, and of Manuel de Landa’s A thousand going on in other parts of geography: geology,
years of non-linear history (1997). geomorphology, GIS and so forth.
The issues are enormous and I make no attempt In contrast to the prominence of time and
to address them fully here (at the moment of historicity in the debates that I have explored so
writing this final draft I think I am a qualified far, space has had a very low profile. It is deni-
naturalist!), but the distinctions are important for a grated as a simple absence of history and/or not
major theme of this paper: our relationship to each accorded the same depth of intellectual treatment
other as physical and human geographers (and – as time. The arguments about opening up
what I have argued earlier has been one of the Newtonian-science models focus overwhelmingly
issues previously holding us apart – the relation- on historicity. Most of the developments docu-
ship of these two parts of our discipline to ‘harder’ mented above call for more explicitly historical
sciences such as physics). sciences. Yet ‘initial conditions’ are geographical as
Earlier in this paper, I argued that we must be well as historical. We must be spatial, as well as
both self-aware and precise about the terms by historical, sciences: indeed, this must be an implica-
which we refer to other sciences such as physics. tion of thinking in terms of space-time (see also
We may turn to them as a stimulation for new Spedding 1997). Yet the widespread development
ideas, or for a direct translation of their models into of evolutionary approaches in a number of fields
ours, or out of simple reverence. The anti-naturalist concentrates on thinking history, but not geogra-
might legitimately do the first; the full-blown natu- phy (see Martin’s (1999) very pertinent critique of
ralist is entirely justified in doing the second; the this in economics): ‘what economists have failed to
qualified naturalist must be careful to distinguish recognize is that the notion of ‘‘path-dependence’’
between the generalities and the specifics, and that they now emphasize is itself place-dependent’
must present an account of the latter.10 What none (Martin personal communication) (Sugden’s analy-
of these positions warrants, however, is a turning sis of the ice sheet seems to me to imply precisely
to ‘a harder science’ out of simple admiration for this point). And in philosophy, both Bergson and
its ‘hardness’ – the reverential reference. It would Laclau, while rigorously retheorizing time, relegate
be ironic if we were to escape from ritual obeisance space to a kind of residual category of stasis. They
to Newtonian mechanics as a model for all knowl- end up with an incompatible pairing of space and
edge, only to adopt precisely the same genuflecting time. What I want to argue is that all these re-
attitude towards the ‘new’ physics of the twentieth theorizations of time, and all this insistence on the
century. Rather, we should be pleased that physics openness of true historicity, in fact require (for
has in some of its parts become more like the philosophical compatibility) a parallel retheoriz-
complex and social sciences in other areas of ation of space. For history to be open, space must
knowledge.11 Ideas in philosophy can feed through be rethought too.
to physics as well as vice versa, insights from the Let us go back for a moment to Bergson, whose
social sciences can be helpful in biology . . . Per- position that temporality must embody open crea-
haps we should all have more confidence in our tivity has so much in common with many of the
own fields of endeavour, as well as in the links arguments being put forward today by philoso-
between them. phers and social scientists (and, as we have seen,
also natural scientists). Indeed, Bergson is an
important source for a number of these theorists –
see Ho (1993) and Deleuze and Guattari (1984). For
And so again to space
Bergson, as we have seen, temporality is essentially
What I want to argue finally, however, is that all open-ended: this is time as the continuous emer-
these movements towards a reconsideration of the gence of novelty; time as a way of becoming that is
nature of time/temporality/historicity necessarily never a mere rearrangement of what already is.
carry with them a requirement to reconsider how Without emergence, urges Bergson (and others),
we think about space. I can spell out the argument there is no time.
here in the abstract, but it is nonetheless an argu- Sensu lato, I would agree with this proposition. It
ment drawn from my thinking within my own does, however, in turn raise further questions. Why
field of human geography. My question is how this is there this ceaseless emergence? How does it
might relate to reconceptualizations of spatiality happen? One source that would seem not to be
274 Doreen Massey
compatible with notions of the openness of history mixed. A first implication, then, of this impetus to
would be that things somehow change in them- envisage temporality/history as genuinely open is
selves (through the immanent unfolding of some that spatiality must be integrated as an essential
unitary undifferentiated identity), for in that case part of that process of ‘the continuous creation of
the terms of change would already be specified in novelty’.
the initial conditions. The future would not be Such an effectively creative spatiality cannot,
open. Rather, in order to retain an openness of the however, be just any kind of (way of thinking of)
future, temporality/time has to be conceived (just space. This cannot be ‘space’ as a static cross-
as I am suggesting space should be) as the product section through time, for, as we have seen above,
of interaction, of interrelations. Adam (1990) con- this disables history itself. Nor can it be ‘space’ as
tains extended discussion of this way of thinking representation conceived of as stasis, for this pre-
about time, and of the many theorists who argue cisely immobilizes things. Nor can it be ‘space’ as a
for such an approach to its conceptualization. closed equilibrium system, for this would be a
Bergson once asked himself the following: spatiality that goes nowhere, that always returns to
the same. This cannot be ‘space’, either, as any kind
What is the role of time? . . . Time prevents everything
from being given at once . . . Is it not the vehicle of of comforting closure (the closures of bounded,
creativity and choice? Is not the existence of time the ‘authentic’ places), for these would also run down
proof of indeterminism in nature? into inertia. Nor can it be space convened as
temporal sequence, for here space is in fact
‘Indeterminism’, here, stands precisely for occluded and the future is closed.
creativity and the possibility of ‘free will’ and, in None of these ways of imagining space are
more recent parlance, politics. conformable with the desire to hold time open.
How are we to think of this statement? Well, it is Rather, for time genuinely to be held open, space
certainly possible to allow that time may be the could be imagined as the sphere of the existence of
vehicle of change. However, the fact that time multiplicity, of the possibility of the existence of
may be the medium within which change occurs difference. Such a space is the sphere in which
(or, more radically, that change-through-inter- distinct stories coexist, meet up, affect each other,
relationality is one of the mechanisms in the crea- come into conflict or cooperate. This space is not
tion of temporality) does not mean that it is its static, not a cross-section through time; it is dis-
cause. Time cannot somehow, unaided, bootstrap rupted, active and generative. It is not a closed
itself into existence. Nietzsche once mused that system; it is constantly, as space-time, being made.
‘only difference . . . can produce results that are Now, I can see what all this means in my neck of
also differences’. In other words, there must the woods. I have an idea of how it means we must
already be multiplicity – to enable the possibility of rethink globalization, reimagine regions/places/
interaction – for change to be produced as a result. nation states, reconceptualize cities. Those
And for there to be multiplicity there must be thoughts are emerging in other books and papers,
space. In other words, we must, as was indicated by myself but also by many others besides. But
earlier, rework Bergson’s logic, and rewrite him does it bear any relation to ways of thinking about
thus: for there to be difference, for there to be time space in other parts of the geographical forest? Do
. . . at least a few things must be given at once. To you have similar debates? Can we talk?
pick up an earlier argument of this paper, the leap
that Bergson seems to have made is to go from the
Acknowledgements
proposition that not everything is given all at once
to an assumption that therefore only one thing is The first person I would like to thank is Roger Lee,
given at once. Moreover, he would seem to have whose concern during his editorship to see this
done this in consequence of his engagement with a journal as a forum for debate in both human and
particular notion of ‘science’. physical geography provided an early encourage-
But the real result of this argument is that time ment to try my hand at developing an argument
needs space to get itself going; time and space are that might link them. I would also like to thank the
born together, along with the relations that pro- participants in a seminar at Birkbeck College,
duce them both. Time and space must be thought where I first presented some of these ideas.
together, therefore, for they are inextricably inter- Conversations with colleagues, and comments on
Space-time, ‘science’ and the relationship between physical geography and human geography 275
earlier drafts, have been extremely generous. I 6 Gross is here compressing the arguments of Bergson’s
should particularly like to thank David Sugden, Time and free will and Matter and memory.
Andrew Sayer, Keith Richards, Stephan Harrison, 7 As Kennedy remarks, such a process is ‘almost inevi-
John Allen, Steve Pile, Barbara Kennedy, Nick table’. This is not a process peculiar to geomorphol-
ogy or physical geography. The production of such
Spedding, Rob Inkpen and Ron Martin. Their
histories, the need to be aware of the tendency and to
positions did not by any means coincide, but it is –
question it, is again something that we all share.
perhaps – interesting to note that in all the many 8 It might be interesting to investigate whether there is
and multifarious comments made and opinions any relationship between this manoeuvre and
expressed there was no simple divide between Bergson’s (and others’) interpretation of difference as
those who might be thought of as human geogra- temporal change. Also, I have wondered a lot, though
phers and those who might be thought of as inconclusively, about whether there are any connec-
physical. tions between this temporalization of space in social
sciences and the ergodic hypothesis in geomorphol-
ogy, where an attempt is made to explain distribu-
Notes tions in time by recourse to distributions in space
(Thornes and Brunsden 1977, 23; Thorn 1982). My
1 Thus they write that: feeling is that there is probably no ‘connection’ in a
Whilst much of the work of mathematicians and historical or theoretical sense, though it is tempting to
physicists such as Minkowski and Einstein is rel- see one.
evant only at extreme scales or velocities, notions 9 The work of some post-colonial theorists, such as
such as relative concepts of space and time are Spivak and McClintock, has been important in
pertinent to environmental science. (364) establishing this argument.
I have to say that at least one of the geomorphologists 10 Deleuze (1995) was asked in interview about his own
with whom I have discussed the present paper quite use of concepts from contemporary physics. His reply
disagrees with this point! is too long to quote here, but is interesting for trying
2 Incidentally, but not coincidentally, the concern of to negotiate a relation of connection without a ‘spe-
Rose’s book is not only to deny this customary cious unity’ (30). Interestingly, too, he takes up the
subordination of complex sciences (or sciences of the cases of both Prigogine and Bergson. On the former
complex) such as biology, but also to understand he points out that the concept of bifurcation (used in
organisms and – crucially – their trajectories in and our field both in formal modelling and in more
constitution through time and space. Here is detect- philosophical and empirical enquiry) is ‘a good exam-
able the crucial link – picked up again later in this ple of a concept that’s irreducibly philosophical, sci-
paper – between complexity and emergence. entific, and artistic too’ (29–30). He also argues that
3 The book Intellectual imposters by Alan Sokal and Jean philosophers may create concepts that are useful in
Bricmont (1998) appeared while I was writing this science: ‘Bergson profoundly influenced psychiatry’.
paper. Although their own epistemological position is And, most importantly, ‘no special status should be
thoroughly naive, it has to be said that many of the assigned to any particular field, whether philosophy,
social scientists whom they quote (and mock) do science, art, or literature’ (30).
seem to have been not only flaunting a half- 11 And anyway – a point which gives me pleasure and
knowledge of natural science, but also indulging in illustrates the wider argument – some of chaos theory
an implicit ‘reverential referencing’ that stands in had its earliest beginnings in meteorology; physicists
total contradiction to their wider positions. were quite slow to take it up (Gleick 1987).
4 Frodeman’s most general aim, like David Sugden’s
and my own, is that intellectual communities should References
talk to each other. He says of his article,
Its overall goal is political, in the sense that I hope Adam B 1990 Time and social theory Polity Press, Oxford
it encourages conversation between intellectual Allen J Massey D and Sarre P eds 1998 Rethinking the
communities who have much to say to one another, region Routledge, London
but who too often are estranged. (1995, 961) Bernal J D 1951 The physical basis of life Routledge and
5 Frodeman actually uses the term ‘Analytical Philoso- Kegan Paul, London
phy’ here, and distinguishes it from a philosophy Carnap R 1937 The logical syntax of language Routledge
critical of this tradition that he calls ‘Continental and Kegan Paul, London
Philosophy’. I have dropped these terms because, as Chorley R J 1962 Geomorphology and general systems theory
was evident from a number of comments on an early Prof Paper 500B, US Geological Survey
draft of this paper, they generate more confusion than de Certeau M 1984 The practice of everyday life University
clarity. of California Press, Berkeley
276 Doreen Massey
de Landa M 1997 A thousand years of non-linear history Prigogine I 1997 The end of certainty: time, chaos and the new
Swerve Editions, New York laws of nature Free Press, London
Deleuze G 1995 Negotiations: interviews 1972–1990 Prigogine I and Stengers I 1984 Order out of chaos
Columbia University Press, New York (original Heinemann, London
interview published in Libération, 23 October 1980) Raper J and Livingstone D 1995 Development of a
Deleuze G and Guattari F 1984 A thousand plateaus geomorphological spatial model using object-oriented
(translated by B Massumi) Athlone Press, London design International Journal of Geographical Information
Frodeman R 1995 Geological reasoning: geology as an Systems 9 359–83
interpretive and historical science Bulletin of the Richards K 1990 ‘Real’ geomorphology Earth Surface
Geological Society of America 107 8 960–68 Processes and Landforms 15 195–7
Gleick J 1987 Chaos: making a new science Heinemann, — 1994 ‘Real’ geomorphology revisited Earth Surface
London Processes and Landforms 19 277–81
Golding S ed 1997 The eight technologies of otherness Rose S 1997 Lifelines: biology, freedom, determinism
Routledge, London Penguin, Harmondsworth
Goodwin B 1995 How the leopard changed its spots: the Simpson G G 1963 Historical science in Albritton C C ed
evoultion of complexity Phoenix Books, London The fabric of geology Addison-Wesley, Reading MA
Gross D 1981–82 Space, time and modern culture Telos 50 24–48
59–78 Sokal A and Bricmont J 1998 Intellectual imposters Profile
Grossberg L 1996 The space of culture, the power of Books, London
space in Chambers I and Curti L eds The post-colonial
Spedding N 1997 On growth and form in geomorphology
question Routledge, London 169–88
Earth Surface Processes and Landforms 22 261–5
Harvey D 1989 The condition of postmodernity Blackwell,
Strahler A N 1952 Dynamic basis of geomorphology
Oxford
Bulletin of the Geological Society of America 62 923–38
Ho M-W 1993 The rainbow and the worm: the physics of
Sugden D 1996 The East Antarctic ice sheet: unstable ice
organisms World Scientific, Singapore
or unstable ideas? Transactions of the Institute of British
Kennedy B A 1992 Hutton to Horton: views of sequence,
Geographers 21 443–54
progression and equilibrium in geomorphology Geo-
Thorn C E 1982 Space and time in geomorphology Interna-
morphology 5 231–50
tional Series 12, Binghampton Symposium in Geomor-
Laclau E 1990 Reflections on the revolution of our time Verso,
phology Allen and Unwin, London
London
Thornes J B 1983 Evolutionary geomorphology Geography
Martin R 1999 The new ‘geographical turn’ in economics:
68 225–35
some critical reflections Cambridge Journal of Economics
23 1 65–91 Thornes J B and Brunsden D 1977 Geomorphology and time
Massey D 1992 Politics and space-time New Left Review Methuen, London
196 65–84 Thrift N 1996 Spatial formations Sage, London
— 1997 Spatial disruptions in Golding S ed The eight Toulmin S 1990 Cosmopolis: the hidden agenda of modernity
technologies of otherness Routledge, London 218–25 Free Press, New York
— 1999 Imagining globalisation: power-geometries of Unwin T 1993 The place of geography Longman, Harlow
time-space in Brah A Hickmann M and MacanGhaill Whatmore S 1997 Dissecting the autonomous self: hybrid
M eds Future worlds: migration, environment and cartographies for a relational ethics Society and Space 15
globalization Macmillan, Basingstoke 27–44 1 37–53
Mouffe C 1993 The return of the political Verso, London — 1999 Hybrid geographies: rethinking the ‘human’ in
Murdoch J 1997 Towards a geography of heterogeneous human geography in Massey D Allen J and Sarre P
associations Progress in Human Geography 21 3 321–37 eds Human geography today Polity Press, London 22–39

You might also like