You are on page 1of 9

Philosophy Compass 10/12 (2015): 884–892, 10.1111/phc3.

12265

Social Construction
Ásta Sveinsdóttir*
San Francisco State University

Abstract
What is social construction? This essay offers a survey of the various ways in which something could be
socially constructed and then addresses brief ly the questions whether social constructionism involves an
untenable anti-realism and what, if anything, unifies all social construction claims.

1. Introduction
While debates over the social construction of various things have raged on for decades in other
fields, it is only just now that social construction has became a respectable topic of conversation
in mainstream philosophy circles, even though a few prominent philosophers have been writing
about it for quite some time.1 Perhaps a reason for that is that philosophers working on social
construction have tended to draw on both the analytic and the continental tradition in their the-
orizing and that in itself is something that is slowly entering the mainstream. Even as late as
2006, inf luential philosophers such as Paul Boghossian (2006) were dismissing social construc-
tion claims as vacuous, incoherent, or confused, and a persistent charge has been that the social
constructionists confuse the metaphysical and the epistemic: when arguing that some X is so-
cially constructed, the charge goes, social constructionists marshal evidence for the claim that
the idea or conception of X is socially constructed but then want to draw the conclusion that
X itself, not just the idea of X, is so constructed. Then the idea that X itself could be socially
constructed is summarily dismissed as involving a radical anti-realism where everything is lan-
guage, or text. To be sure, the arguments offered in fields ranging from sociology and anthro-
pology to literature in support of social construction claims haven’t always supported the
conclusions drawn, and the positions and the arguments for them could have benefited from
more clarity. But, by now, there is a growing body of philosophical literature on social construc-
tion and clear that social construction claims don’t just rest on confusion. They do, however,
vary greatly in what is supposed to be constructed and how.
This essay is intended as an introduction to social construction. The main focus will be social
construction claims where X itself is to be socially constructed, and the strategy will be to survey
the various ways in which that could be. We will then address brief ly the question whether so-
cial constructionism involves an untenable anti-realism and conclude with a discussion of what,
if anything, unifies all social construction claims.

2. What is constructed? Is the claim epistemic or metaphysical?


There are many types of social construction (and hence, social construction claims). The first
distinction we need is that between the epistemic and the metaphysical: is it X itself that is
socially constructed, or is it our idea or conception or knowledge of X that is? If the latter,
then the claim that X is socially constructed is an epistemic claim in the sense that social prac-
tices are somehow implicated in our epistemic access to X. This is what Ian Hacking calls

© 2015 The Author(s)


Philosophy Compass © 2015 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Social Construction 885

‘idea construction’ and discusses at length in his The Social Construction of What? (1999). As my
focus in this essay is on the metaphysics of social construction, we will only discuss one type of
idea construction, which is such that the idea of X causes changes in X itself, and thus, al-
though it is a type of idea construction, there are metaphysical consequences. This is the im-
portant phenomenon of the looping effect, identified by Hacking and much discussed in the
subsequent literature.
The looping effect is the phenomenon where X is being described or conceptualized as F makes
it F. This phenomenon only applies to cases where X is a subject capable of reacting to being
thought of or conceptualized in some way. In those cases, Hacking suggests, the availability
of a self conception or a way of being has the effect that the people so conceptualized start to
behave more and more in a way that fits that conception. Hacking discusses examples that in-
volve the classification of people by authorities, including psychological diagnoses like that of
multiple personality disorder. When a person is diagnosed with multiple personality disorder,
they are offered a conception of themselves as explanatory of their experience. The availability
of the diagnosis results in people conforming more to the conception (exhibiting
more symptoms) than before they were diagnosed (1999). This is the key to Hacking’s own ac-
count of human kinds which he labels ‘dynamic nominalism’: the conception of the kind and
the kind come into being together. On Hacking’s account, there isn’t the human kind person
with multiple personality disorder before the availability of the diagnosis and the conception of a
person with multiple personality disorder. The kind or type2 of person comes into being hand
in hand with the availability of the conception of that type or kind of person.
How is this possible? Hacking’s idea comes from Hegel via Foucault. Very brief ly, on Hegel’s
account of the development of consciousness in the Phenomenology of Spirit (1807), Conscious-
ness forms a conception of itself and attempts to act out or actualize that conception. In acting as
if the conception is true, the conception comes to fit better and better, until an internal contra-
diction in the conception itself comes to the fore. In the face of that contradiction, Conscious-
ness then forms a new conception of itself that incorporates what it has learned from the
contradiction and, in turn, attempts to actualize that conception. This is Hegel’s dialectic.
But, Consciousness does not only form a conception of itself, it also forms conceptions of what
isn’t itself, whatever Other it encounters. When the Other is an inanimate object, it cannot resist
Consciousness’ conception of it, but when the Other is itself a consciousness, we have a dy-
namic relationship between two subjects who form conceptions of themselves and each other
and attempt to actualize those conceptions, act as if they are true. Hegel describes a struggle unto
death over whose conceptions are to prevail which results in one being the master, the other the
slave. It is the master’s conception of itself and the other that has prevailed, and the slave has cho-
sen to accept those conceptions for itself rather than death. There are nuances and complications
in Hegel’s account of subjectification and objectification, of course, but Hegel’s insight is still
with us. Whose conceptions – of people themselves and of others, but also of anything whatso-
ever, including general world-views – prevail may not be determined by comparing the con-
ceptions with something like an independently reality or the facts but in a power struggle
where the conceptions of the powerful prevail.
Hegel was an idealist, and there was no room for any epistemic check on the conception, ex-
cept an internal contradiction in the conception itself. But, we don’t have to take on board
Hegel’s idealism in order to benefit from his insight. We can acknowledge the immense forces
of power in determining which conceptions of things prevail, even if we want to leave room for
the role of epistemic reasons, including, but not limited to, reasons from internal contradiction.
That scholars disagree over whether Foucault himself allows for a role for epistemic reasons or
whether the development of institutions and cultural practices is determined by power relations
alone3 should not commit us to the view that the only force of human culture is power.

© 2015 The Author(s) Philosophy Compass 10/12 (2015): 884–892, 10.1111/phc3.12265


Philosophy Compass © 2015 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
886 Social Construction

How do we use Hegel’s insight to explain the looping effect? When an entity in power forms
a conception of people it has power over, the people have to respond to being conceived of in
that way. They can take on that conception as their own, or they can try to resist. The cases of
the looping effect are not confined to those where the authority is epistemic authority, as in the
case of multiple personality disorder, where the doctors’ epistemic authority plays a role.
Hacking discusses the interesting case of two different ways of thinking about what it is to be
an alcoholic: the alcoholic as someone who is failing morally, and the alcoholic who has a disease
that needs curing. He thinks of Alcoholics Anonymous as working with the conception of the
alcoholic as someone who has a moral failing, and AA members come to see themselves in terms
of the conception offered to them. Likewise, that the medicalization model of alcoholism offers
a conception of the alcoholic as someone who has a disease of the body and patients diagnosed
with that disease come to see themselves in those terms. People struggling with alcoholism are
here offered two different ways of thinking of themselves and their predicaments with different
results: either they can think of themselves as being morally culpable or they think of themselves
as physically ill. In each case, they act accordingly and come increasingly to exhibit features be-
longing to the two conceptions of an alcoholic in question.
We have lingered with this special type of idea construction because even though it is the
idea of X that is socially constructed in the sense that it is, of course, a product of social forces,
given certain conditions, X itself is affected, so we can classify this kind of case as a case of
social construction in the metaphysical sense. We will not dwell on other types of idea con-
struction. Instead, in what remains, we will focus exclusively on the case where the social
construction claim is understood as a metaphysical thesis and X itself is claimed to be socially
constructed.

3. Causal Construction
Even though we have now chopped off a huge branch of the tree that is social construction,
many branches remain. We will introduce them with a concrete example. Let’s consider the
claim disability is socially constructed. This will, actually, turn out to be a host of claims, with vary-
ing implications.
An individual has various physical features and, depending on the physical environment, can
be more or less mobile within that environment. Let’s say Sam can’t walk and is in a wheelchair
(S has feature W; S is W).
If the environment fits well the way the wheelchair works – there are smooth sidewalks with
inclining curbs and all buildings are without thresholds and one story high, there is never any
snow or f loods, and so on – then Sam can move around freely in their environment. If, on
the other hand, there are some buildings that are taller than one story, without an elevator, then
there are parts of the physical environment Sam does not have access to. We can call this physical
consequences of being in a wheelchair, given the physical environment (physical consequences of being
W, given the physical environment).
But suppose it so happens that all parties take place on second f loors of buildings. No one
intended it that way; it just happens. Perhaps it’s a fad to have party venues with gorgeous views.
The point is simply that no one intentionally picked second f loor venues because it would ex-
clude anyone; no one really thought about it very much. But, the consequences are that Sam
cannot go to parties anymore, and now, there are not only physical consequences of Sam’s being
in a wheelchair, but social consequences of a certain sort as well. We can call this unintentional
communal consequences of being in a wheelchair, given the physical and social environment.4 A meaner
version of this is when someone, Kim, has realized that if they throw a party on the second
f loor, Sam cannot attend, and Kim deliberately decides to do so, perhaps to block a fellow suitor

© 2015 The Author(s) Philosophy Compass 10/12 (2015): 884–892, 10.1111/phc3.12265


Philosophy Compass © 2015 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Social Construction 887

and have the luxury of an evening of courtship in the absence of their rival. That case would be
intentional communal consequences of being in a wheelchair, given the physical and social environment.
Suppose now that the voting booth is on the second f loor of a building without an elevator,
but no one had intended this. Again, no one had given it much thought; it just sort of happened
that way. While the voting commission is eager for as many voters as possible to take part in the
election, some, like Sam, cannot vote. This would be unintentional institutional consequences of be-
ing in a wheelchair, given the physical and social environment. And a meaner version of this is when
some election officials have realized that if they put the voting booth on the second f loor,
Sam and others cannot vote, and deliberately decide to place the voting booth on the second
f loor to prevent Sam from voting. That would be intentional institutional consequences of being in
a wheelchair, given the physical and social environment. We have, of course, many actual examples
of this phenomenon, such as when polling places are only open during hours a certain section
of the population cannot possibly make.
The types of consequences identified above can be lumped together under the heading social
consequences of having W, given the physical and social environment, and the type of social construction
in question we can call social construction as social consequences. This is a type of social construction
Susan Wendell discusses in her ‘The Social Construction of Disability’ in (Wendell 1990).
But, social constructionist claims do not only concern social consequences of features or phe-
nomena. Sometimes, the physical environment gets changed as a result of social forces. Suppose
that a certain kind of vehicle, The Hopper, gets to be very popular, and this type of vehicle re-
quires very high curbs for parking. Then, in the absence of legislation pertaining to such things,
curbs become increasingly higher in the area and formerly non-curbed sidewalks become not
only curbed, but acquire very high curbs. This is a case of the popularity of a vehicle causing
changes in the physical environment, and the type of social construction is social construction as so-
cial causal construction, much discussed by Hacking, as well as Haslanger and Mallon. In our ex-
ample, aspects of the physical environment itself, namely the curbs, are socially constructed in
that social forces contributed to the existence or change in the physical features of the curbs.
But since we are focusing on the example of the claim that disability is socially constructed, is
this a case where disability is socially constructed as well? Yes, because any loss of mobility
(and therefore increase in disability, given the physical environment) is a causal effect of the same
social forces. Areas Sam could traverse freely before are now off limits, all because of the pop-
ularity of The Hopper.
This example brings out that although the type of social construction identified before, social
construction as social consequences of a feature, is also a type of causal construction, it is helpful to dis-
tinguish types of causal construction by their focus: is the social phenomenon the cause or the
effect? The causal construction discussed by Hacking, Haslanger, Mallon, and others is a con-
struction where the social is the cause. In the first type discussed by Wendell, the focus is on
the social effects of a feature. As we see in the above example, though, social forces can effect
changes in the physical environment that can have physical and social consequences so these
types of construction interact in a variety of ways.
There is a special case of the social causing changes in the physical environment with debil-
itating consequences that is noted by Wendell. This is the type where social norms or ideals have
the effect that certain bodies are not only abnormal, but disabled. When society is organized
around what the normal or ideal is, that has a disproportionate effect on those who are defined
abnormal. For instance, if public transportation is designed with 4 feet tall people in mind, then
6-feet tall people will have a hard time fitting through the bus doors and into the seats on the
bus. Similarly, if the ideal of femininity involves being exceedingly thin and most clothes are de-
signed around that ideal, then women who are not exceedingly thin, which may even be most
of the population, have a hard time finding fitting clothes. There are two senses of ‘normal’ at

© 2015 The Author(s) Philosophy Compass 10/12 (2015): 884–892, 10.1111/phc3.12265


Philosophy Compass © 2015 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
888 Social Construction

work here: the statistically normal, and the ideal, and both can have the effect of marginalizing
or making abnormal whomever they don’t fit, with debilitating effects. This type of construc-
tion we can call social construction as norms causing changes in the physical environment in such a way that
having feature W is disabling.
Finally, it isn’t only the physical environment we interact with that can be changed as a result
of social forces. Social forces can also cause changes in the physical features of individuals, mak-
ing them physically impaired where they were not so before. We can have social forces (laws,
regulations, corporations, community practices, etc.) cause environmental pollution which in
turn cause debilitating diseases or restrict access to basic necessities causing debilitating condi-
tions in populations. In this case, social forces cause the very feature in question. We can call this
social construction as social forces causing feature W.
4. Constitutive Construction
So far, we have only considered causal construction. Not all types of social construction are of
the causal kind, however. As Haslanger has discussed (2012), an important type of social con-
struction is what she calls ‘constitutive construction’ and defines thus5:

Constitutive construction Something is constitutively constructed if in defining it we must make


reference to social factors.

Intuitively, X is constitutively constructed just in case social phenomena make up or consti-


tute X. The notion of constitution is the familiar one: just as a material object is constituted by the
materials that make it up, arranged in a certain way, so a social phenomenon is constituted by the
phenomena (physical and social) that make it up, again, arranged in a certain way.
Constitutive construction features prominently in debunking projects where the aim of the
social construction theorist is to debunk widely held beliefs about the phenomenon in question,
for example, when it is widely held that a phenomenon is natural, and the aim is to show that it
is in fact social. Examples of this are claims to the effect that sex or intelligence is socially con-
structed, when they are widely held to be a matter of biology. Another prominent example is
the status of race, where a social constructionist offers that race is a social, and not a biological,
phenomenon. And to continue with our example of the social construction of disability, a social
constructionist would claim that disability is socially constructed as part of a debunking project:
while it is widely held that disability is a matter of physical impairment, it really is a social phe-
nomenon. Ásta Sveinsdóttir offers a way to f lesh out this claim thus6: for disability to be socially
constructed is for a feature, physical impairment, to have social significance in a context such that
people taken to have the feature get conferred unto them extra social constraints and
enablements that are over and above the constraints and enablements that mere physical impair-
ment brings. In effect, people taken to have the feature in question (here physical impairment)
get conferred onto them a social status, which consists in constraints and enablements on their
behavior. For instance, there can be institutional constraints such as laws banning people with
physical impairments from driving even though the person in question could physically drive,
or communal constraints, where no one takes what you say seriously because of the difficulty
you have with articulating words clearly, even though you have epistemic authority on the mat-
ter at hand. There can also be enablements. People taken to have physical impairment can be
granted special privileges, such as being permitted to park in certain designated areas, or to pre-
side over religious rituals.
While the notion of constitutive construction is integral to debunking projects, it is also cen-
tral to accounts of social phenomena where the social status of the phenomenon was never in
question. This is, for example, the central notion of social construction for Haslanger even

© 2015 The Author(s) Philosophy Compass 10/12 (2015): 884–892, 10.1111/phc3.12265


Philosophy Compass © 2015 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Social Construction 889

though a paradigm case of social construction for her is gender (the other is race), and the social
status of gender is not at all in dispute.7 In this kind of case, the social constructionist intervention
does not merely lie in the claim that something is socially constructed constitutively, since ev-
eryone is expecting it to be, but how it is so constructed. Haslanger’s notion of social construc-
tion is to capture the type of social construction involved in the post-Beauvoirean feminist
slogan gender is the social significance of sex, and she holds gender to be constitutively constructed
by a system of hierarchical power relations.8
We can read Ásta Sveinsdóttir’s account of social construction9 as an alternative account of
constitutive construction to Haslanger’s. While for Haslanger, gender, for example, is consti-
tuted by a hierarchy of power relations, on Ásta’s account, gender is a social status constituted
by the constraints and enablements conferred on people taken to possess the feature that
grounds the conferral in each context.10 She thinks that in different contexts, different features
are being tracked in the conferral of gender: in some contexts, it may be sex assignment, in
others socio-economic role, and so on. Then, people taken to have the relevant target property
(e.g. sex assignment) get conferred onto them constraints and enablements in the context and
that is what gender in that context consists in. Hers is an account of social construction as social
significance which works like this: gender is the social significance of the target property in each
context; in context C1, it may be the social significance of sex assignment, in C2 the social sig-
nificance of socio-economic role, and so on. So, for a feature, such as sex assignment, to have
social significance is for extra constraints and enablements to be conferred onto people taken
to have the feature in question.
5. Social Construction and Realism
As mentioned in the beginning, it has been a persistent theme to lump social constructionism
together with an untenable anti-realism, where everything collapses into language, text, or dis-
course.11 It should be clear from the above discussion that the question of realism is only prop-
erly addressed when it comes to constitutive construction. If we say, e.g., that racial categories
are socially constructed, what are way saying about the status of those categories? There is
now a considerable literature on precisely that question12 and on the metaphysical status of var-
ious human kinds in general.13 What all social constructionists about races, genders, or other hu-
man kinds share are the following two claims:

(1) Human kind terms refer.


(2) What human kind terms refer to are social phenomena.
The first claim distinguishes social constructionists from eliminativists and error theorists; the
second distinguishes them from theorists that hold that the human kinds under consideration are
biological phenomena. However, whether the social constructionist is realist or nominalist or
how exactly to account for social phenomena depends on the particular theorist.14 Ian Hacking
and Sally Haslanger have both addressed that issue specifically, so we will sketch their
commitments.
Hacking’s account, as mentioned before, is a dynamic nominalism. It is a nominalism because
the type of person comes into being with being named and does not exist independently of the
name; it is dynamic in that there is an interplay between describing (naming) the type of person
and the type itself such that describing the type has an effect on the entities so described, and
they in turn can inf luence subsequent descriptions of themselves.
Haslanger’s critical realism about social construction has it that genders and races, while so-
cially constructed, are real, objective, natural, types. In this way, she distances herself from the
social constructionist theorists who embrace anti-realism of various stripes. For Haslanger, saying

© 2015 The Author(s) Philosophy Compass 10/12 (2015): 884–892, 10.1111/phc3.12265


Philosophy Compass © 2015 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
890 Social Construction

that a type is ‘real’ means that talk about that type is truth-apt (in contrast to the error-theorist or
the eliminativist). An objective type is a type that is a proper object of empirical enquiry. And a
natural type is one that is part of the causal order: either it itself can be a cause or an effect or it
supervenes on entities that do.
As we can glean from the brief sketch above, each of the theorists offers an account of the
social construction of human kinds or types that does not obviously involve a self-refuting
anti-realism. How tenable each of these accounts is is a substantial philosophical question and
won’t be answered here. The present point is simply that to say that human kinds are socially
constructed need not involve commitments to everything being text or language, as the carica-
ture charge would have it.
When is it, then, that a social constructionist is threatened with an untenable anti-realism?
It is when the type of social construction offered is such that everything becomes socially
constructed in the same way such that, for example, there is no way to draw a distinction be-
tween natural and social phenomena. As long as the social construction theorist can draw a
distinction among different types of social construction, even if everything turns out to be
socially constructed somehow, the threat of everything collapsing into language or text or
concept is staved off.15

6. Final Remarks
What has been given here is a catalog of sorts of types of social construction and associated
claims, and you can see that social construction claims vary considerably. But, can we say any-
thing about all social construction claims? Is there anything that unifies them?
Social construction claims are, first and foremost, offered as explanations of phenomena that
are socially important, often as alternative analyses of social problems or as part of raising con-
sciousness regarding something that should be regarded as a social problem. Social construction-
ist analyses are not unified by their content, but by their purpose, as crucial components of
various liberatory programs. Locating the role of social phenomena in the construction of the
reality we live in points the way to possible solutions to problems we face; it also shifts respon-
sibility onto us, the participants in the social practices and institutions implicated.16

Short Biography

Ásta Kristjana Sveinsdóttir is an associate professor of philosophy at San Francisco State Univer-
sity. She holds a BA in mathematics and philosophy from Brandeis, an AM in philosophy from
Harvard, and a PhD in philosophy from MIT. Recent papers include “The Social Construction
of Human Kinds” (Hypatia), “Knowledge of Essence” (Philosophical Studies), and “Who’s Afraid
of Feminist Metaphysics?” (APA Newsletter on Feminism and Philosophy). She is at work on a
monograph entitled Categories We Live By: the construction of gender, sex, race, and other social
categories, which is under contract with Oxford UP. Her website: http://online.sfsu.edu/asta
online.sfsu.edu/asta
Notes

* Correspondence: Department of Philosophy, San Francisco State University, 1600 Holloway Ave, San Francisco, CA
94132, USA. Email: asta@sfsu.edu

1
Hacking 1999, 2002; Haslanger 2012; Mallon 2003, 2004, 2006, 2008/2013.
2
‘Type’ and ‘kind’ are used interchangeably in this essay.
3
Cf. Habermas’ famous criticism in 1986.

© 2015 The Author(s) Philosophy Compass 10/12 (2015): 884–892, 10.1111/phc3.12265


Philosophy Compass © 2015 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Social Construction 891
4
We reserve the use of ‘communal’ for non-institutional social consequences following Ásta Sveinsdóttir in Categories We
Live By.
5
Haslanger 2012, p. 87. See also Mallon’s slightly different formulation in Mallon 2008/2013: X constitutively constructs Y
if and only if X’s conceptual or social activity regarding an individual y is metaphysically necessary for y to be a Y.
6
Ásta Sveinsdóttir 2012; see also her Categories We Live By.
7
Cf. Hacking 1999, p. 39.
8
Haslanger 2012, p. 234.
9
Ásta Sveinsdóttir 2012.
10
The ‘grounding’ or ‘target’ properties can be sex assignment, self presentation, role in biological reproduction, role in
preparation of food, etc. Cf. Ásta Sveinsdóttir 2011 and 2012.
11
Cf. Introduction to Butler 1993.
12
Apart from Haslanger and Mallon, see also, e.g., Gooding-Williams 1988, Mills 1998, Piper 1992, Root 2000, and
Young 1989.
13
Apart from other authors mentioned already, see also, e.g., Andreasen 2000, Appiah 1996, Alcoff 2006, Díaz-León 2013,
Glasgow 2008, Hardimon 2003, Mikkola 2006, 2011, Spencer 2012, Stoljar 2011, Sundstrom 2002, and Zack 1993.
14
Different theorists also use ‘realism’ and ‘nominalism’ in different ways. In particular, Mikkola 2008/2011 and Alcoff 2006
use them differently than they are used here.
15
This is why Judith Butler’s account does not collapse into radical linguistic constructivism. See Butler 1990, 1993; Ásta
Sveinsdóttir 2011.
16
Thanks are due to Rachel Cooper, Dana Harvey, and an anonymous reviewer for helpful comments on an earlier
version. All remaining errors are the author’s responsibility.

Bibliography
Andreasen, Robin. 2000. ‘Race: Biological Reality of Social Construct?’ Philosophy of Social Science 67 (Proceedings):
S653–S666.
Alcoff, Linda Martín. Visible Identities: Race, Gender, and the Self. New York: Oxford University Press, 2006.
Appiah, Kwame Anthony. 1996. ‘Race, Culture, Identity: Misunderstood Connections.’ In Color Conscious: The Political Mo-
rality of Race. Ed. K Anthony Appiah and Amy Gutmann. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Ásta Sveinsdóttir. 2011. ‘The Metaphysics of Sex and Gender.’ In Feminist metaphysics. Ed. Charlotte Witt. Dordrecht,
Heidelberg, London, and New York: Springer.
——. 2012. ‘The Social Construction of Human Kinds.’ Hypatia, Fall 2013, vol. 28(4).
——.N. D. Categories We Live By (ms. under contract with Oxford UP).
Boghossian, Paul. 2006. Fear of Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Butler, Judith. 1990. Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity. New York and London: Routledge.
——. 1993. Bodies that Matter. New York and London: Routledge.
Díaz-León, Esa. 2013. ‘What Is Social Construction?’. The European Journal of Philosophy. Early View. DOI: 10.1111/
ejop.12033.
Glasgow, Joshua. 2008. A Theory of Race. New York: Routledge.
Gooding-Williams, Robert. 1988. ‘Race, Multiculturalism and Democracy.’ Constellations 5: 18–41.
Habermas, Jürgen. 1986. ‘Taking Aim at the Heart of the Present’ In Foucault: A Critical Reader. Ed. David Hoy. Oxford:
Basil Blackwell.
Hacking, Ian. 1999. The Social Construction of What? Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
——. 2002. Historical Ontology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hardimon, Michael O. 2003. ‘The Ordinary Concept of Race.’ The Journal of Philosophy 100(9): 437–55.
Haslanger, Sally. 2012. Resisting Reality: Social Construction and Social Critique. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hegel, G. W. F. 1807. Phänomenologie des Geistes. Bamberg and Würzburg: Joseph Anton Goebhardt.
Mallon, R. 2003. ‘Social Construction, Social Roles and Stability.’ In Socializing Metaphysics. Eds. F. Schmitt. Lanham, MD:
Rowman and Littlefield, 327–353.
—— 2004. ‘Passing, Traveling, and Reality: Social Construction and the Metaphysics of Race.’ Noûs 38(4): 644–673.
—— 2006. ‘A Field Guide to Social Construction.’ Philosophy Compass 2(1): 93–108.
—— 2008/2013. ‘Naturalistic Approaches to Social Construction.’ Naturalistic Approaches to Social Construction (2014),
Edward N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/social-construction-naturalistic.
Mikkola, Mari. 2006. ‘Elizabeth Spelman, Gender Realism, and Women.’ Hypatia 21(2006): 79–96.

© 2015 The Author(s) Philosophy Compass 10/12 (2015): 884–892, 10.1111/phc3.12265


Philosophy Compass © 2015 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
892 Social Construction

——. 2011. ‘Ontological Commitments, Sex and Gender.’ In Feminist Metaphysics. Ed. Charlotte Witt, Springer.
——. 2008/2011. ‘Feminist Perspectives on Sex and Gender.’ The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2012), Edward N.
Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2012/entries/feminism-gender.
Mills, C. 1998. Blackness Visible: Essays on Philosophy and Race. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Piper, Adrian. 1992. ‘Passing for White, Passing for Black.’ Transition 58: 4–32.
Root, Michael. 2000. ‘How We Divide the World.’ Philosophy of Social Science 67 (Proceedings). 628–639.
Quayshawn, Spencer. 2012. ‘What ‘Biological Racial Realism’ Should Mean.’ Philosophical Studies 159(2): 181–204.
Sundstrom, Ronald. 2002. ‘Racial Nominalism.’ Journal of Social Philosophy 33(2): 193–210.
Stoljar, Natalie. 2011. ‘Different Women. Gender and the Realism-Nominalism Debate.’ In Feminist Metaphysics. Ed.
Charlotte Witt. Dordrecht: Springer.
Wendell, Susan. 1990. The Rejected Body, Routledge.
Young, I. M. 1989. ‘Polity and Group Difference: A Critique of the Idea of Universal Citizenship.’ Ethics 99: 250–74.
Zack, N. 1993. Race and Mixed Race. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

© 2015 The Author(s) Philosophy Compass 10/12 (2015): 884–892, 10.1111/phc3.12265


Philosophy Compass © 2015 John Wiley & Sons Ltd

You might also like