You are on page 1of 4

Does Philosophy Matter? (Part Two) - NYTimes.

com 8/17/11 6:47 PM

AUGUST 8, 2011, 8:45 PM

Does Philosophy Matter? (Part Two)


By STANLEY FISH

Stanley Fish on education, law and society.

Tags:

moral relativism, Philosopher’s Brief, Philosophy, religion, Supreme Court, Tea Party

Some of the readers who were not persuaded by my argument that abstract moral propositions
do not travel into practical contexts (see, “Does Philosophy Matter?”) offer what they take to be
obvious counterexamples. Joe (187) cites “the ‘Philosophers’ Brief’ on assisted suicide that was
submitted to the Supreme Court.” The example, however, counts for my side.

The brief was written by Ronald Dworkin, Thomas Nagel, Robert


Nozick, John Rawls, Thomas Scanlon and Judith Jarvis Thomson A belief in moral
absolutes, as an
(an all-star roster if there ever was one). It argues against a abstract position,
Washington state law prohibiting assisted suicide. The affirms no
particular moral
philosophers hope to persuade the Court to strike down the law by
absolute.
invoking a “liberty interest” all men and women have in making
their own “personal decisions” about the “most intimate … choices
a person may make in a lifetime” including the choice to die. “Death is, for each of us, among the
most significant events of life.”

The Court alludes to this argument in passing when it acknowledges that the “decision to
commit suicide with the assistance of another” may be “personal and profound.” The point,
however, is summarily dismissed in the same sentence: “but it has never enjoyed … legal
protection” (Washington v. Glucksberg, 1997). That is to say, while “abstract concepts of
personal autonomy” (the Court’s phrase) may be interesting, they are not currency here in the
world of legal deliberation. What is currency is the line of decisions preceding this one: “The
history of the law’s treatment of assisted suicide in this country has been and continues to be the
rejection of nearly all efforts to permit it.” Case closed. The editors of a leading jurisprudence
casebook observe that “The Philosophers’ Brief arguments about autonomy seem not to have
influenced the Supreme Court at all” (Jurisprudence Classic and Contemporary, 2002). Why
should it have? The Court isn’t doing philosophy, it is doing law. Grand philosophical

http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2011/08/08/does-philosophy-matter-part-two/?pagemode=print Página 1 de 4
Does Philosophy Matter? (Part Two) - NYTimes.com 8/17/11 6:47 PM

statements may turn up in a Supreme Court opinion, but they are not doing the real work.

But what if a lawyer or a judge was a devout Christian or a Hasidic Jew or a follower of the
Koran? Would that change things? It well might, for it is a feature of religious tenets (at least
with respect to some religions) that they demand fidelity to their commands not merely on
holidays or in houses of worship, but at all times and in all places. Believers, Marie Burns (1)
observes, do rely on their religion “to determine their views on a variety of subjects.” Many
people, An Ordinary American (140) reminds us, when asked why do you do this, would reply,
“This is what my religion teaches me to do.”

The question is whether religion should be considered philosophy. For a long time, of course,
philosophy was included under religion’s umbrella, not in the modern sense that leads to
courses like “The Philosophy of Religion,” but in the deeper sense in which religious doctrines
are accepted as foundational and philosophy proceeds within them. But for contemporary
philosophers religious doctrines are not part of the enterprise but a threat to it. The spirit is as
Andrew Tyler (38) describes it: “to be skeptical, critical and independent so that you’re not so
easily duped and frightened into submission by religious dogma.” Courses in the philosophy of
religion tacitly subordinate religion to philosophy by subjecting religion to philosophy’s
questions and standards. Strong religious believers will resist any such subordination because,
for them, religious, not philosophical, imperatives trump. The reason religion can and does
serve as a normative guide to behavior is that it is not a form of philosophy, but a system of
belief that binds the believer. (Philosophy is something you can do occasionally, religion is
not.)

But aren’t beliefs and philosophies the same things? No they’re not. Beliefs such as “I believe
that life should not be taken” or “I believe in giving the other fellow the benefit of the doubt” or
“I believe in the equality of men and women” or “I believe in turning the other cheek” are at
least the partial springs of our actions and are often regarded by those who hold them as moral
absolutes; no exceptions recognized. These, however, are particular beliefs which can be arrived
at for any number of reasons, including things your mother told you, the reading of a powerful
book, the authority of a respected teacher, an affecting experience that you have generalized
into a maxim (“From now on I’ll speak ill of no one.”).

A belief in moral absolutes, as an abstract position, is quite another thing. It affirms no


particular moral absolute (although it might lead down the road to naming some); rather, it
asserts that the category of moral absolutes is full; and it does so against the arguments of those
who assert that the category is empty, not with respect to any particular moral absolute, but
generally. Wherever one stands at the end of a such a philosophical argument one will be
committed not to any specific moral stance (like turning the other cheek) but either to the
thesis, again abstract, that moral stances are anchored in and justified by an underlying truth
about the nature of moral behavior or to the thesis that they are not.
http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2011/08/08/does-philosophy-matter-part-two/?pagemode=print Página 2 de 4
Does Philosophy Matter? (Part Two) - NYTimes.com 8/17/11 6:47 PM

“I believe in moral absolutes” and “I hold absolutely to the idea that men and women are equal”
are propositions of quite different orders. It is only the first proposition that doesn’t travel; it
doesn’t tell you anything or direct you to do anything, necessarily. The second proposition, if
you affirm it sincerely, has already committed you to particular choices and decisions. So when
Id (19) imagines a Joe Schmoe who might say “But my moral beliefs do matter to my decision
making,” my reply is of course, they do, but that in no way undermines my argument, which is
not about moral beliefs but about a belief in moral beliefs. Moral beliefs are not the kinds of
thing you believe in; they are the kinds of things you have, or, rather, they have you.

Several posters complain that I can mount my argument only by


rigging it, by excluding from the category of philosophy a whole lot Your mind
operates
of things most people would put into it — religion, moral independently of
commitments and a great deal else. Lindsey S (176) asks, “Am I to whether or not you
have a philosophy
understand that epistemology doesn’t matter. That philosophy of
of it.
mind doesn’t matter? That political philosophy doesn’t matter?”
Well, they certainly matter to those who do them, those who engage
in the debates and controversies that impel an academic discipline. But I don’t see how they
matter to people who are just living their everyday lives. Thinking is not directed or improved by
your having an account of thinking, that is, an epistemology; your mind operates independently
of whether or not you have a philosophy of it; politicians don’t have philosophical frameworks;
they have strategies attached to some idea of what they want to get done. But, Tom (143)
objects, “the entire field of applied ethics … rests on the premise that a moral philosophical
framework can guide moral decision making.” Then the entire field should shut down.

But what about the Tea Party? That question was raised by a large number of readers who made
two points : (1) the debt ceiling controversy would have come to a better end if the participants
had read and studied the right philosophical tracts, and (2) the trouble with the Tea Party is
that it is guided by a bad philosophy, one that dictates its members’ behavior. The first point is
clearly silly; it employs the same reasoning that leads some people to believe that if only
terrorists, tyrants, and jihadists would read our constitution, the Federalist papers, and a few
pages of John Rawls, they would come to their senses and become followers of democracy. As
for the second point, according to its Web sites the Tea Party believes in limited government and
free enterprise and opposes political schemes that assume the perfectibility of man and fail to
recognize that we are motivated largely by self interest. (The view is a variant of Mandeville’s in
“The Fable of the Bees,” that private vices make for public benefits.) These are certainly ideas
and they are cited as support for the positions Tea Party members take; but “big government is
bad” and “free enterprise is good” are slogans that speak to the discontent of those who feel
disenfranchised; they amount to philosophy after the fact; they didn’t produce the Tea Party
disaffection; they dress it up for public viewing.

http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2011/08/08/does-philosophy-matter-part-two/?pagemode=print Página 3 de 4
Does Philosophy Matter? (Part Two) - NYTimes.com 8/17/11 6:47 PM

Finally, let me reply to the charge that I am contradicting myself by doing philosophy while
trashing philosophy. “Interesting that Dr. Fish would use such a ‘finely’ tuned philosophical
argument to debunk philosophy” ( 43). But I’m not debunking philosophy or saying that people
shouldn’t do it. Philosophy is fun; it can be a good mental workout; its formulations sometimes
display an aesthetically pleasing elegance. I’m just denying to philosophy one of the claims made
for it —that its conclusions dictate or generate non-philosophical behavior — and there is no
reason that my denial of philosophy’s practical utility should not take a philosophical form.

Hugh McDonald (112) thinks he has me when he says that if philosophy doesn’t matter, “Then
your philosophy doesn’t matter.” That’s right; it doesn’t, if by “matter” is meant that reading me
will make a difference in the way you live. The only benefit one might derive from following my
argument is the removal of a confusion; you might no longer think that getting your
philosophical ducks in a row will lead to better and more moral decisions. But your new clarity
will do you no more positive good — it will not translate into superior forms of action — than
your former confusion did you positive harm.

If you have a problem to solve or a decision to make reading me won’t help you any more than
chanting “I believe in moral absolutes” or “I don’t.” What will help are the usual ingredients of
what Aristotle calls “practical reasoning”— an understanding of your goal, a survey of alternative
ways of reaching it, a calculation of likely consequences, an effort to identify the relevant
considerations, a recollection of what happened last time, and so on. Sabrina Jamil (83) has me
saying that because there is no universal agreement on moral absolutes, we should “just drop it
because it makes no difference … which interpretation one holds anyway.” On the contrary, it
makes a great deal of difference and it is our obligation to work through to the interpretation (or
judgment or decision) that seems right in the circumstances. In the course of our efforts many
things (and not always the same things) will be of use, but moral philosophy won’t be one of
them.

Copyright 2011 The New York Times Company Privacy Policy NYTimes.com 620 Eighth Avenue New York, NY 10018

http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2011/08/08/does-philosophy-matter-part-two/?pagemode=print Página 4 de 4

You might also like