You are on page 1of 9

Philosophy and

Phenomenological Research
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
Vol. XC No. 3, May 2015
doi: 10.1111/phpr.12184
© 2015 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC

Essence, Necessity, and


Demonstration in Aristotle
DAVID BRONSTEIN
Georgetown University

Although the comments that follow are largely critical, I want to express at
the outset my great admiration for Marko Malink’s excellent book. It makes
a major contribution to our understanding of Aristotle’s logic and the
broader philosophical commitments that underlie it. It is also a model of ex-
egetical clarity and philosophical rigor the rest of us working in this field
should strive to emulate.
I want to explore some of the implications of Malink’s interpretation of the
modal syllogistic in the Prior Analytics for Aristotle’s theory of demonstration
in the Posterior Analytics. I’ll do so by focusing on Malink’s account of the
connection between essence and necessity. I’ll argue that if Malink’s account of
the modal syllogistic is correct, and in particular if his account of the connection
between essence and necessity is correct, then a broad range of demonstrations
Aristotle presents in the Posterior Analytics cannot be modal syllogisms. Ma-
link may happily accept this as a consequence of his view. Still, it seems worth
showing that this is a consequence of his view. I’ll also argue that Malink’s
account of the connection between essence and necessity risks committing
Aristotle to an unattractive form of essentialism.

1. Essence and Necessity


Malink1 endorses the following account of what in the Posterior Analytics
Aristotle calls a “per se accident” and Alexander of Aphrodisias calls an
“inseparable accident” and I’ll call a “necessary accident”2 :

1
Aristotle’s Modal Syllogistic (Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press,
2013), 125–6. All page references are to this book.
2
See Posterior Analytics 1.7, 75b1, 1.10, 76b6–7, b13–15, 1.22, 83b19–20, 2.13, 96b20,
b23–4. See also Alexander in Top. 50.6–51.5, cited and discussed by Malink (125).

724 DAVID BRONSTEIN


P is a necessary accident iff (i) P is not predicated essentially of S,
of a subject S (ii) there is an E such that E is predicated
essentially of S, and
(iii) P necessarily belongs to all S because
of E.

That is, a necessary accident is a necessary but non-essential property of a


subject that is explanatorily grounded in that subject’s essence.
Malink writes that the connection between essence and necessity in this
account of necessary accidents points to a central feature of Aristotle’s
modal syllogistic: “the necessity with which the predicate of an aN-predica-
tion3 is predicated of its subject derives from the essence of the subject”
(126). This is a familiar feature of Aristotle’s thinking: all essential proper-
ties of a subject S are necessary properties of S, but not all necessary prop-
erties of S are essential properties of S, and S’s necessary but non-essential
properties (its necessary accidents) belong to S because of S’s essence. Ma-
link summarizes part of this thought with the following statement:

S11: If there is an A such that AaNB, then there is a D such that D is


predicated essentially of B4 (126)

That is, if a term is the subject of aN predication, then it is the subject of


essential predication.

2. Barbara NXN
S11 plays an important role in a central part of Malink’s book: his account
of the validity of Barbara NXN (114–67).
A necessarily belongs to all B (AaNB)
B belongs to all C (BaXC)
A necessarily belongs to all C (AaNC)

Malink’s strategy is to argue that if A necessarily belongs to all B (AaNB)


and B belongs to all C (BaXC), then, given certain claims about essence
and necessity (including S11), it follows that B necessarily belongs to all
C (BaNC). Since Barbara NNN is valid, and since the premise pair of Bar-
bara NXN (together with the relevant claims about essence and necessity)
entails the premise pair of Barbara NNN, Barbara NXN is valid. Malink’s
account draws on the semantics of predicables in the Topics, from which
he derives not only S11 but another crucial claim as well, S9, according
to which “every subject of an essential predication is predicated essentially
of everything of which it is predicated” (124). Here is one way of present-

3
A is aN-predicated of B iff A necessarily belongs to all B.
4
To avoid confusion in what follows, I have used “D” in place of Malink’s “C.”

BOOK SYMPOSIUM 725


ing Malink’s argument that BaNC follows from AaNB and BaXC (and thus
that Barbara NXN is valid):
1. If there is an A such that A necessarily belongs to all B, then there
is a D such that D is predicated essentially of B. (S11, 126)

2. If D is predicated essentially of B, and B is predicated of C, then


B is predicated essentially of C. (S9, 124)

3. Therefore, if A necessarily belongs to all B, and B belongs to all


C, then B is predicated essentially of C. (From 1 and 2)

4. If B is predicated essentially of C, then B necessarily belongs to


all C. (S10, 125)

5. Therefore, if A necessarily belongs to all B, and B belongs to all


C, then B necessarily belongs to all C. (From 3 and 4)

Michael Pakaluk has objected that Malink “render[s] Barbara NXN valid by
reducing it to Barbara NNN” and that on Malink’s interpretation the second pre-
mise of Barbara NXN is or amounts to a necessary premise (what Pakaluk calls
“a kind of shadow N-premise”), which Pakaluk claims is false.5 However, Pak-
aluk’s objections are mistaken. As Jacob Rosen points out, “‘B necessarily
applies to all C’ is not a further assumption or ‘shadow premise’ in Malink’s
explanation.”6 Rather, it follows from “A necessarily belongs to all B” and “B
belongs to all C,” together with the relevant claims about essence and necessity
(S9–S11) to which Malink argues (with considerable textual evidence and
philosophical sophistication) Aristotle is committed. In the same way, Malink’s
interpretation does not “reduce” Barbara NXN to Barbara NNN. As I explained
above, his view is that the premise pair of Barabara NXN, together with the rel-
evant claims about essence and necessity (S9–S11), entails the premise pair of
Barbara NNN. To argue that p and q entail r is not to reduce p (or q) to r. And to
argue that p and q entail r is not to introduce r as a “shadow premise.”

3. The Modal Syllogistic and the Theory of Demonstration


For Aristotle, a demonstration is a syllogism in which the premises state the
explanation of the fact stated in the conclusion, and any syllogism with this
feature is a demonstration. In the Posterior Analytics Aristotle indicates that

5
Michael Pakaluk, review of Aristotle’s Modal Syllogistic by Marko Malink, Bryn Mawr
Classical Review (2014.03.04).
6
Jacob Rosen, review of Aristotle’s Modal Syllogistic by Marko Malink, Notre Dame
Philosophical Reviews (2014.08.33).

726 DAVID BRONSTEIN


the premises and conclusion of a demonstration must be necessary.7 This
has led some commentators to think that the theory of demonstration of the
Posterior Analytics forms part of the modal syllogistic of the Prior Analyt-
ics. Malink, however, denies this. In a footnote he says that:

unlike the modal syllogistic, the Posterior Analytics is not primarily con-
cerned with modally qualified propositions such as ‘A necessarily belongs
to all B’. Rather, it is concerned with assertoric propositions such as ‘A
belongs to all B’ which are true by necessity. (164–5, n24)

Let’s say that an apodeictic syllogism is a syllogism in which at least one


premise and the conclusion are propositions whose copula contains the
modal qualifier “necessarily.” Malink’s view, then, is that according to the
Posterior Analytics demonstrations are not apodeictic syllogisms.
Malink’s view is more complicated than this, however. For his account
of the modal syllogistic also commits him to saying that some demonstra-
tions are apodeictic syllogisms. Consider the account of necessary accident
above. It says that if P is a necessary accident of S, and E is predicated
essentially of S, then the following apodeictic syllogism is a demonstration:
P necessarily belongs to all E
E necessarily belongs to all S
P necessarily belongs to all S

On the other hand, in what follows I’ll argue that if Malink’s S11 is true, then a
broad range of demonstrations Aristotle presents in the Posterior Analytics can-
not be apodeictic syllogisms. So it turns out that on Malink’s view (i) the theory
of demonstration is not part of the modal syllogistic, and yet (ii) some demon-
strations must be apodeictic syllogisms, while (iii) others cannot be. These
claims are logically consistent with each other. However, there is something a
bit surprising about this picture. We might have thought that if some demonstra-
tions are apodeictic syllogisms, then demonstrations in general are and the the-
ory of demonstration is part of the modal syllogistic.
In what follows I’ll focus on (iii). I’ll suggest a different picture according to
which a broader range of demonstrations than Malink allows to be apodeictic syl-
logisms are such. I’ll conclude by discussing in more detail the account of the con-
nection between essence and necessity that emerges from Malink’s account.

4. Two Models of Demonstration


We saw above that S11 plays an important role in Malink’s account of the
validity of Barbara NXN. I want to suggest that Aristotle is committed not
to S11 but to a different claim:

7
See especially Posterior Analytics 1.6.

BOOK SYMPOSIUM 727


S11*: If there is an A such that A necessarily belongs to all B, then
there is a D such that (i) D is predicated essentially of B or (ii) B
necessarily belongs to all D and there is an E such that E is
predicated essentially of D.

S11 says that if B is the subject of aN-predication, then B is the subject of


essential predication. S11* says that if B is the subject of aN-predication,
then either B is the subject of essential predication or B is aN-predicated of
a term that is the subject of essential predication.
I argue elsewhere that in the Posterior Analytics Aristotle presents two main
models of demonstration.8 The key feature of a Model 1 demonstration is that
the middle term signifies the essence of the subject signified by the minor term.9
The key feature of a Model 2 demonstration is that the middle term signifies the
essence of the attribute signified by the major term.10 I now want to argue that
S11* is consistent with both models of demonstration, whereas S11 is not.
Here is an example of a Model 2 demonstration. I assume for the sake of
argument that the demonstration is an apodeictic syllogism. For what I wish to
show is that if it is an apodeictic syllogism, then S11 is false. Conversely, if
S11 is true, the following cannot be an apodeictic syllogism:11
2R12 necessarily belongs to all essence of 2R
Essence of 2R necessarily belongs to all triangle
2R necessarily belongs to all triangle13

8
Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: the Posterior Analytics (Oxford University Press,
forthcoming).
9
See Posterior Analytics 1.4, 73b31–2, 1.5, 74a30–4, 2.13, 96b15–25. See also the
account of necessary accidents above.
10
See Posterior Analytics 2.2 and 2.17 (99a21–2), where Aristotle says that “the middle
term is an account (logos) of the major term, which is why all the sciences come about
through definition (di’ horismou).” Later in the passage (at 99a27–9) it becomes clear
that by “logos” Aristotle means “definition.” He says that the middle term in the demon-
stration of “leaf-shedding” (the major term in the example demonstration he is consider-
ing in this part of the text) is what leaf-shedding is (ti esti), i.e., its essence.
11
Other Model 2 demonstrations in the Posterior Analytics include: “eclipse belongs to the
moon” through the middle term “screening of the sun by the earth,” “thunder belongs to
the clouds” through the middle term “fire extinguishing,” and “leaf-shedding belongs to
broad-leafed plants” through the middle term “coagulation of sap.”
12
2R = interior angles equal to two right angles.
13
In the Posterior Analytics, “2R” is both an example of an attribute that is demonstrated
to belong to its subject (triangle) through the subject’s essence (Model 1) (1.4, 73b31–2,
1.5, 74a30–4) (see below) and an example of an attribute that is demonstrated to belong
to its subject through the attribute’s (2R’s) essence (Model 2) (2.2, 90a33). I argue else-
where (see above n8) that Aristotle’s account is coherent. It’s not that there are two
independent causes of 2R, its essence and triangle’s essence. It’s rather that there is a
chain of explanation in which 2R’s essence and triangle’s essence both feature as causes.
The main difficulty with Aristotle’s account is that he does not indicate what the essence
of 2R is, nor does he explain how 2R follows from triangle’s essence.

728 DAVID BRONSTEIN


Malink argues that terms such as “2R” (or “having 2R”) do not have
essences and are not subjects of essential predication (136–8). However, in
the Posterior Analytics, Aristotle insists that terms such as “2R,” “eclipse,”
“thunder,” “leaf-shedding” have essences.14 (That is, he insists that the
demonstrable attributes signified by these terms have essences.) I’ll assume,
then, that (the demonstrable attributes signified by) terms such as “2R” have
essences. (In fact, it seems to me that in the Posterior Analytics Aristotle
thinks that (the demonstrable attributes signified by) these terms have
essences but are not subjects of essential predication, and that Malink is in
a good position to accept this claim, but I won’t argue that here.)
Consider the demonstration above in light of S11. Take the major premise.
According to S11, since “essence of 2R” is the subject of aN-predication, it is
the subject of essential predication. According to S9, if “essence of 2R” is the
subject of essential predication, then “essence of 2R” is predicated essentially
of whatever it is predicated. In the minor premise, “essence of 2R” is predicated
of “triangle.” So according to S9 and S11, “essence of 2R” is predicated essen-
tially of “triangle” in the minor premise. But this is wrong. “Essence of 2R” is
the essence of “2R,” not the essence of “triangle.” “2R” and “triangle” are dif-
ferent. The essence of one cannot be the essence of the other. So S11 is incon-
sistent with the demonstration above, if it is an apodeictic syllogism.
S11*, by contrast, is consistent with this demonstration. Take the major pre-
mise. S11* says that “essence of 2R” is either (i) the subject of essential predi-
cation or (ii) aN-predicated of a term that is the subject of essential predication.
In the minor premise, “essence of 2R” is aN-predicated of “triangle,” which is the
subject of essential predication. So the major premise satisfies the second of S11*’s
two disjuncts. Now take the minor premise. “Triangle” is the subject of essential
predication. So the minor premise satisfies the first of S11*’s two disjuncts.
Here is an example of a Model 1 demonstration:

2R necessarily belongs to all essence of triangle


Essence of triangle necessarily belongs to all triangle
2R necessarily belongs to all triangle

Take the major premise. According to S11, since “essence of triangle” is the
subject of aN-predication, it is the subject of essential predication. Malink
argues that some terms are essentially self-predicating (139–40). If this is true
of “essence of triangle,” then the major premise is consistent with S11. Now
take the minor premise. S11 says that “triangle” is the subject of essential predi-
cation, which, the minor premise tells us, is true. So S11 is consistent with

14
See the texts cited in n10 above.

BOOK SYMPOSIUM 729


Model 1 demonstrations, but only if we accept that terms such as “essence of
triangle” are essentially self-predicating.
Now consider this demonstration in light of S11*. Take the major premise.
According to S11*, “essence of triangle” is either (i) the subject of essential
predication or (ii) aN-predicated of a term that is the subject of essential predi-
cation. The minor premise tells us that “essence of triangle” is aN-predicated
of a term that is the subject of essential predication: “triangle.” So the major
premise satisfies the second of S11*’s two disjuncts. Now take the minor pre-
mise. It says that “triangle” is the subject of essential predication. So the minor
premise satisfies the first of S11*’s two disjuncts. So S11* is consistent with
Model 1 demonstrations, and we do not need to assume that terms such as
“essence of triangle” are essentially self-predicating.

5. Interim Conclusion
The question I am urging we ask is, are any Model 2 demonstrations apo-
deictic syllogisms? I’ve argued that if Malink’s account is right, and in par-
ticular if S11 is true, then the answer is “no.”
Perhaps this should incline us to S11*, which permits (without of course
requiring) Model 2 demonstrations to be apodeictic syllogisms. The problem
now is that if we substitute S11* for S11 in the argument for the validity of Bar-
bara NXN, the argument is spoiled. Suppose we follow the second of S11*’s
two disjuncts, according to which B, which is the subject of aN-predication, is
aN-predicated of a term that is the subject of essential predication. Now S9 is no
longer relevant. For S9 relies on the thought that B is the subject of essential
predication, which the second of S11*’s two disjuncts does not assert. And if
S9 is not relevant, then we cannot prove BaNC from AaNB and BaXC.

6. Aristotle’s Essentialism
I want to conclude by suggesting that Malink’s interpretation risks committing
Aristotle to an unattractive form of essentialism. In particular, it risks commit-
ting Aristotle to an unattractive account of necessary accidents, especially con-
dition (iii), according to which if P is a necessary accident of S, then P
necessarily belongs to all S because of S’s essence. My worry is that on Ma-
link’s account all the necessary accidents of a given subject are explained
(demonstrated) from the subject’s essence alone. For example, Malink quotes
approvingly David Charles’ claim that “‘the essence is the one cause of all the
kind’s derived necessary properties.’ (Charles 2000: 203)” (126; my empha-
sis) That is, Malink seems to commit Aristotle to:
Strong Essentialism: The essence of a subject is the sole (one and
only) cause of all of that subject’s necessary
accidents. (Cf. 126)

730 DAVID BRONSTEIN


However, Strong Essentialism, it seems to me, is an implausible view. An
Aristotelian essence is not sufficiently rich to serve as the sole cause of all
of the relevant subject’s necessary accidents. The subject’s essence may be
a cause of all of its necessary accidents, but other causes are also needed
(including, I submit, the essences of the necessary accidents themselves, as
in Model 2 demonstrations).

7. S11 and Strong Essentialism


I now want to argue that S11 together with two other claims central to Ma-
link’s interpretation (S9 and S10) entail Strong Essentialism.
Suppose A necessarily belongs to all B (AaNB). AaNB is either immediate
or demonstrable. If AaNB is immediate, then it seems that A is predicated
essentially of B, which is consistent with S11. Now suppose that AaNB is
demonstrable. According to S11, there is a D such that D is predicated essen-
tially of B. If D is predicated essentially of B, then D necessarily belongs to
all B (DaNB) (S10, 125). Now since AaNB is demonstrable, we need a middle
term that states the cause of the fact that AaNB. So far we have:
AaN?
DaNB
AaNB

There are two possibilities: either the middle term is D or it’s some other
term, E. Suppose it’s D:
AaND
DaNB
AaNB

I noted just above that according to S11, D is predicated essentially of B.


So, in this case, A necessarily belongs to all B because of B’s essence alone
(D) (Strong Essentialism).
Now suppose the middle term is E:
AaNE
...
DaNB
AaNB

The ellipsis “. . .” indicates that the argument needs to be filled in with addi-
tional premises. These additional premises must eventually yield AaND, for
this is required as the major premise in any demonstration whose minor
premise is DaNB and whose conclusion is AaNB. The most direct way to

BOOK SYMPOSIUM 731


get AaND from AaNE is to assume EaND. With this we can complete the
demonstration of AaNB:
AaNE
EaND
AaND
DaNB
AaNB

From S11 and AaNE it follows that E is the subject of essential predication.
From S9, AaNE, and EaND it follows that E is predicated essentially of D. From
EaND and DaNB, EaNB follows. Since E is the subject of essential predication
(S11) and is predicated essentially of whatever it is predicated (S9), E is predi-
cated essentially of B. Now D is also predicated essentially of B. So two terms
are predicated essentially of B: D and E. In addition, A necessarily belongs to
all B (AaNB) because of D and E alone. This is Strong Essentialism, which is
entailed by S11 together with S9 and S10: if A necessarily belongs to all B and
AaNB is demonstrable, then A necessarily belongs to all B because of B’s
essence alone (which in this case comprises two terms: D and E).
The same result can be obtained even if we don’t assume EaND straight
off but derive AaND from a longer series of aN-predications. The only dif-
ference is that more terms will be packed into B’s essence. And herein lies
the problem. The essence of a subject is the sole cause of all of that sub-
ject’s necessary accidents only if we pack a sufficient number of terms into
the subject’s essence to account for all the necessary accidents. This threat-
ens the unity of the essence. It also makes Strong Essentialism seem ad
hoc: it’s guaranteed to be true because the essence of B is just that set of
terms needed to explain all of B’s necessary accidents. But this gets things
the wrong way around: it’s not that D, E, etc. are B’s essence because they
explain all of B’s necessary accidents; it’s rather that D, E, etc. explain all
of B’s necessary accidents because they are B’s essence.
Now suppose that S11* is true. In that case, there is no guarantee that all of
B’s necessary accidents will follow from B’s essence alone. Rather, S11*
(unlike S11) is consistent with the view that B’s essence is a cause of all of its
necessary accidents, but not the only cause. For the essences of the necessary
accidents themselves are also needed to explain why they belong to B. I sug-
gest that it is this weaker form of essentialism that Aristotle is committed to.

732 DAVID BRONSTEIN

You might also like