You are on page 1of 13

SAGE Reference

Handbook of Social Theory


Functional, Conflict and Neofunctional Theories

Contributors: Author:Mark Abrahamson


Edited by: George Ritzer & Barry Smart
Book Title: Handbook of Social Theory
Chapter Title: "Functional, Conflict and Neofunctional Theories"
Pub. Date: 2001
Access Date: November 5, 2021
Publishing Company: SAGE Publications Ltd
City: London
Print ISBN: 9780761941873
Online ISBN: 9781848608351
DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.4135/9781848608351.n12
Print pages: 141-151
© 2001 SAGE Publications Ltd All Rights Reserved.
This PDF has been generated from SAGE Knowledge. Please note that the pagination of the online
version will vary from the pagination of the print book.
SAGE SAGE Reference
© George Ritzer and Barry Smart 2001

Functional, Conflict and Neofunctional Theories

Functional, conflict and neofunctional theories

Between roughly the mid 1940s and the late 1960s, structural functionalism was the dominant theoretical
perspective in sociology. Talcott Parsons was its major figure, and so great was his influence that even the
sharpest critics among his contemporaries conceded that they had to define their own intellectual positions
in relation to his (Alexander, 1983). The abstractness of Parsons' theorizing and his grandiloquent writing
style were, during his time of prominence, widely discussed and debated; but sociologists were generally
less reflective about many of the distinctive suppositions of Parsons' structural functionalism. Perhaps
the distinguishing features of the perspective remained in the background due to the relative absence of
competing paradigms (cf. Ritzer, 1980). In any case, Kingsley Davis' presidential address to the American
Sociological Association probably reflected the views of most of his contemporaries when he insisted that
functional and sociological analyses were, in fact, virtually identical (Davis, 1959). Anyone who thought
functionalism involved any special assumptions, Davis concluded, believed in a myth.

Current, multiple paradigm sociology has obviously changed very much in the latter decades of the twentieth
century. The place of functionalism and neofunctionalism in the contemporary theoretical mix is one of
the major topics to be assessed in this chapter. We will also examine the important historical interplays
between structural functional and (non-Marxian) conflict theories. Before turning to the changes that occurred
over the last one-third of the twentieth century, however, it will be instructive first to look back at how
diverse conceptual contributions converged to become the structural functional paradigm in the middle of the
twentieth century.

To state where any school of thought began necessarily requires arbitrary decisions, because no matter
where one chooses to begin it would almost always be possible to find some still earlier, relevant statement.
Therefore, let us simply say that one logical place to begin is with the writings of a group of eighteenth-century
Scottish scholars—including Adam Smith and David Hume, in particular—who later came to be collectively
referred to as the Scottish Moralists.

Scottish Moralists

Several theoretical notions shared by most of the Scots had particular impact upon the development of
functional theory in sociology (and anthropology). To begin, they all tended to emphasize a conceptual
distinction between levels of analysis in which collective units, such as the economy or society, were seen as
possessing qualities that were separate from the individuals that comprised them. Further, the Scots claimed,
a collectivity could not be entirely fashioned by the conscious volition of individual participants because they
only partly understood it, at best. In Adam Smith's view, genuine comprehension and explanation required
that the analyst be distanced from the routine workings of a society or economy (cf. Copley, 1995).

However, neither Smith nor the other Scots regarded social organization as adversely >affected by its
separation from human agency. Smith's discussion of how an ‘invisible hand’ anomolously promotes social
ends, despite people's selfish and hedonistic intents, may be the exemplar of this position. To illustrate, he
explained how the vanity of large land and factory owners combined with the eager entre – preneurship of
merchants to produce an industrial and commercial revolution that benefited everyone:

A revolution of the greatest importance to the public happiness was … brought about by two different orders
of people, who had not the least intention to serve the public … To gratify the most childish vanity was the
sole motive of the great proprietors. The merchants … acted merely from a … principle of turning a penny
whenever a penny was to be got. Neither of them had either knowledge or foresight of that great revolution
which the folly of the one, and the industry of the other, was gradually bringing about. (Smith, [1863] 1967:
199)

The Scots' separation of intent and consequence proved to have enormous analytical and methodological
Handbook of Social Theory
Page 2 of 13
SAGE SAGE Reference
© George Ritzer and Barry Smart 2001

implications. It meant that social practices could not necessarily be judged according to any intrinsic or
introspective standard that involved people's motives. Instead, a social analyst had (metaphorically at least)
to stand aside, and observe the actual collective consequences of individuals' behavior. An interesting
illustration is provided by David Hume's analysis of courtship and marriage patterns. After observing
differences among societies, he wondered what accounted for the variation in civil laws and moral sentiments.

Hume was able to answer this question, at least partially, by examining the consequences of particular
matings. For example, among royalty, what harm would come from a widow marrying her deceased husband's
brother? In the circle of great princes, he reasoned, marriage is more ceremonial and commercial than sexual,
so rules which prohibit such marriages among non-royalty need not apply to them. Furthermore, if the widow
and her brother-in-law come from different nations, then their marriage may help to cement an alliance, even
if it violates a conventional marital taboo. Therefore, Hume concluded, ‘there is less reason for extending
toward them the full rigour of the rule …’ (Hume, 1879: 95).1

In sum, the Scottish Moralists presented several inter-related points that were especially important with
respect to the development of structural functional theory in sociology: an emphasis upon an outsider's
examination of the consequences of people's behavior; a conceptual distinction between individuals and
collectivities as units which act and are acted upon; and the assumption that the parts of societies or
economies will generally be well integrated, despite their tendency to be removed from individual volition. All
of the above notions were elaborated by the French theorist, Emile Durkheim, and they became the early
cornerstones of his new science of sociology.

Emile Durkheim

The primary topic in Durkheim's first classic provided him with a great opportunity to polemicize against earlier
theories which viewed the collective division of labor as a product of individuals' calculations (cf. Luhmann
1982). Correspondingly, Durkheim began The Division of Labor in Society ([1893] 196; hereafter cited as DoL)
with an acknowledgement of Adam Smith's influence, especially Smith's insights into the advantages of the
division of labor. By contrast, elsewhere in DoL Durkheim went to some lengths to stress the uniqueness of
his own contributions, especially in relation to Comte and Spencer.

In a brief introductory passage, Durkheim states that the first problem is, ‘To determine the function of the
division of labor, that is to say, what social need it satisfies’ (DoL: 45). Then in Chapter One he turns to a
clarification of what the term ‘function’ implies, beginning with why some seemingly identical words can not
be used as synonyms. An ‘aim’, for example, would presuppose intent, and (like the Scots) he does not want
to go in that direction. ‘Effect’ is not an acceptable substitute either because it does not necessarily indicate a
correspondence between any particular result and the needs of the society; but function has this implication
for Durkheim. At the end of the first chapter he offers the book's major hypothesis: divisions of labor normally
function to provide the ‘order, harmony, and social solidarity’ that society needs {DoL: 63).

The rest of DoL provides insightful analyses of change across diverse institutions. Many, if not most,
of Durkheim's arguments and interpretations are functional, and he seems to take special pleasure in
pointing out what Merton ([1949a] 1968a) later termed latent functions; that is, how a social practice or
activity contributed to social integration in ways which people neither intended nor recognized. For example,
Durkheim argued that crime has the (latent) consequence of enhancing solidarity among the non-deviant,
and that the punishment of a criminal paradoxically reinvigorates the norm that the offender violated.
He completed this classical functional interpretation by arguing that crime and punishment meet such
fundamental social needs that it is difficult to image a society in which they are absent.

Durkheim's ([1895] 1964) most formal and elaborate presentation of functional methodology came later, in
The Rules of Sociological Method (hereafter cited as The Rules). In this book he explicitly places individual
needs and motives outside the proper realm of sociological enquiry and identifies the social order and the
‘things’ which comprise it—social facts—as the appropriate subject matters. Then he poses as the central
question, How are these social facts to be explained? No personal characteristic could logically explain a
religious belief, a rate of marriage, or the like because these social facts transcend individual lifetimes. Each
generation encounters an institutional arrangement it did not make. Therefore, he concludes, the explanation
Handbook of Social Theory
Page 3 of 13
SAGE SAGE Reference
© George Ritzer and Barry Smart 2001

of social facts must lie in previously established social facts.

In the first four chapters of The Rules, Durkheim presents canons for observing and classifying social
facts, building toward Chapter Five in which he outlines the protocol by which they are to be explained.
Unfortunately, this key chapter includes a number of statements that are, in my opinion, either confusing
or untenable, and the similarities or differences that Durkheim envisioned between functional and causal
analyses of social facts are at the heart of the problem.

Durkehim begins his description of the rules of explanation by offering the observation that some law or
pattern of behavior might retain essentially the same form or content over hundreds of years, but serve
different functions at different times. So, ‘the causes of its existence are, then, independent of the ends it
serves’ (The Rules: 91). On the one hand this statement may mean just what it appears to mean, namely,
that function and cause are two different things. On the other hand, he goes on to define ‘ends’ in this context
as referring to individual utilities. Function, by contrast, is again defined as entailing practices that satisfy the
general needs of the social organism. Thus, rather than being intended to separate function and cause, the
quotation in question may really be nothing more than a restatement of his non-reducibility dictum.

In later pages of The Rules Durkheim appears to oscillate, sometimes clearly separating function and cause,
sometimes fusing them. For example, to explain a social phenomenon, he states, ‘we must seek separately
the efficient cause which produces it and the function it fulfills’. That seems clear, but then he adds, ‘the
bond which united the cause to the effect is reciprocal … the … cause needs its effect’ (The Rules: 95.) To
illustrate, Durkheim proposes that the punishment of a crime ‘is due to’ (that is, caused by) the collective
sentiments that are offended by the crime. The punishment, he continues, is also functional for maintaining
those sentiments because unless they are periodically activated and expressed through punishments, the
sentiments, themselves, will diminish in intensity.

Durkheim's writings on causality and function leave more questions unanswered than we could hope to
address here. However, a few of the issues need to be at least noted. To begin, did Durkheim mean to say
that whenever a causal relationship is shown, one should expect to find that the dependent variable ‘needs’
the independent variable? To answer this question one would first have to clarify what Durkheim meant by
cause, and sometimes he confused causal inference with simple correlation. Other times he may be using
causal to mean that some behavior seems patterned, hence amenable to law-like descriptions in which the
causal connections among terms might remain implicit (Turner, 1990; see also Faia, 1986).

Perhaps the most consistent interpretation is that Durkheim conceptualized a highly integrated social system
in which simple correlations among social facts reflected both functional and causal interconnections.
Function and cause were to be kept conceptually separate, even if one could not readily tell them apart in
the analysis. Certainly he did regard society, in its normal state, as an organic whole in which the parts were
harmoniously integrated. He most clearly presented this view in his analysis of ‘survivals': practices which
once served a function, do not seem to do so now, but persist anyway. (Inferring survivals creates a quandary
for functionalists because an alternative interpretation is always possible, namely, that a latent function will
later surface.) In reflecting upon the prevalence of survivals, Durkheim states that to maintain non-functioning
social facts still cost effort. Because they do not benefit the society, though, such survivals are ‘parasitic’ to the
budget of the social organism. No society could afford to carry very many of them. Thus, Durkheim concludes,
it will typically be possible to show that social facts, ‘combine in such a way as to put society in harmony with
itself and with the environment external to it’ (The Rules: 97).

Durkheim had previously argued that it was normal for the parts of a society to fit together and to function
to maintain solidarity. For example, he identified the first abnormal, or pathological, type of division of labor
as ‘anomic’. He defined it as overly fragmented, entailing differentiation in which specialization does not lead
to solidarity because, ‘social functions are not adjusted to one another’ (DoL: 354). To illustrate, Durkheim
described the serious labor conflicts that can occur in large-scale industry when workers and employers
become too separate from each other. However, such instances were exceptional and temporary, in his view,
and tended to be self-correcting by a ‘spontaneous consensus of parts'. Further, if the parts of a society did
not fit, there was typically little anyone could do about the resultant problems until, in effect, the social system
re-equilibrated itself. ‘We cannot adjust these functions to one another and make them concur harmoniously

Handbook of Social Theory


Page 4 of 13
SAGE SAGE Reference
© George Ritzer and Barry Smart 2001

if they do not concur of themselves’ {DoL: 360).2

In sum, note that all the major parts of Durkheim's theory and method were in close accord with the main
assumptions of the Scottish Moralists. Specifically, they shared:

• 1
A preference for outsiders' inferences to insiders' understandings, or introspection. (They viewed
participants as likely to be overwhelmed by a multitude of detail.)
• 2
A strong conceptual distinction between the attributes of individuals and of collectivities. They also
insisted that variables related to individuals cannot be causal with regard to larger social units, but
characteristics of collectivities were often assigned causal status with regard to individual behavior.
• 3
An assumption of social integration, in which the parts of a society (that is, the social facts) fit with
each other and fulfill the needs of the collectivity, without the tinkering of would-be social engineers.

Talcott Parsons3

Parsons consistently acknowledged that he was strongly indebted to four theorists: Durkheim, Pareto, Weber
and Freud. He not only fused their insights, but his early book (Parsons, 1937) also brought their work to the
attention of many American sociologists. We have discussed Durkheim at length because of his continued
importance as a social theorist, quite apart from Parsons. Following that logic, our treatment of Pareto will be
brief because, although he greatly influenced Parsons, he is no longer among the more widely read theorists
in sociology. Weber and Freud will not be examined at all due to their limited contributions to structural
functionalism. Although Freud's incipient system perspective influenced Parsons, his primary interest in Freud
and Weber was probably more substantive, for their insights into the role of the non-rational. Sciulli (1991:
281) claims that all of Parsons' work can be summarized by saying, ‘he was a theorist preoccupied with non-
rational social action’.

Pareto's influence upon Parsons' structural functionalism was great primarily because of the former's efforts
to view society in system terms. (And a system conception, or its equivalent, is probably essential for any
analysis that focuses upon the patterned consequences of action in an integrated structure.) Like Durkheim,
Pareto ([1916] 1963) emphasized the distinction between function and cause, but he had less interest in
causal inference than Durkheim because he felt that, for sociologists, it required erroneous assumptions.
Many social variables tend to be so strongly interrelated, in Pareto's view, that it is not fruitful to try to isolate
specific relationships and explain them in causal terms. He proposed instead that sociologists examine the
interrelated parts of government, religion and the like in order to deduce their common functions.

In the Preface to The Social System, Parsons (1951: vii) wrote that his book's title was the most indebted
to ‘Pareto's great work’.4 As sociologists, Parsons stated, we are primarily interested in the social system,
but cultural and personality systems were seen as impinging so directly on the social system that their
influences could be partitioned out only in arbitrary conceptualizations. Furthermore, the way these three
systems (or subsystems) interpenetrated was the key to Parsons' theory of social integration—and he saw
integration as the foremost function of the social system. Specifically, he conceptualized an ideal type society
in which cultural values were institutionalized in the social system and norms were, in turn, internalized in the
personality system. Individuals will then comply with social expectations, in this view, because they regard
the rules as legitimate (given their source) and because the rules are consistent with their own internalized
values. In addition, because norms are derived from common value orientations, they possess a ‘harmonious
character’, so competing expectations will not often lead people to face internal conflicts.

While Parsons did not expect the ideal type condition of perfect congruence among the three systems
to be attained by any actual society, a substantial degree of accord was considered both necessary and
inevitable—or the society could not persist. Correspondingly, Parsons and several of his contemporaries
(cf. Aberle et al., [1950 1967; Parsons and Smelser, 1956) deduced functional prerequisites, or necessary
conditions, of society. Included at the top of everyone's list were social control mechanisms designed to
safeguard the socialization process in order to ensure that each cohort of youngsters internalized the norms
Handbook of Social Theory
Page 5 of 13
SAGE SAGE Reference
© George Ritzer and Barry Smart 2001

and was motivated to play conventional roles.

The ‘danger’ to the stable equilibrium among the three subsystems in the ideal type society that Parsons
conceptualized early in his career was social change. In the final chapter of The Social System, Parsons
(1951) claims to have deliberately exaggerated system stability in order to devise a base line from which
to examine transformations. However, he assumed that each subsystem normally had the means to resist
alterations, and most of his core theoretical writings regarded change as worrisome because it could
compromise system imperatives. Further, Parsons (like Durkheim and the Scottish Moralists) was concerned
that the consequences of even a seemingly minor change might be more far reaching (and worse) than
anyone reckoned.

When, later in his career, Parsons (1966) explicitly analysed change, it was from an orderly, evolutionary
perspective. Societal complexity, in this view, entailed the greater differentiation of subsystems, and
transformations occurred as a result of system tensions which increased because of malintegration among
the components. Thus, societies were described as moving through stages of temporary equilibrium, but
change followed an orderly sequence and continued to be patterned in accordance with self-regulating
system needs.

Viewing change apprehensively, especially if it was deliberately enacted, was one quality that gave structural
functionalism a conservative tilt. A second involved a tendency not to consider the possibility that traditional
practices differentially benefit some parts of a society. For Durkheim, it will be recalled, the ‘beneficiary’ of
functional practices was the society, which he conceptualized as a thing apart (and which therefore could not
be equated with any specific segment or group). In Parsons' view, internalization of a common value system
led to a situation in which virtually everyone in a society shared a strong affectual commitment to seeing
institutionalized practices continue. Robert K. Merton, a student and colleague of Parsons, suggested that
sociologists explicitly consider the possibility that what is functional for some segments of a society might not
be functional for others. However, Merton's own case studies usually wound up showing how diverse groups,
in fact, benefited from the same practice (Abrahamson, 1978; Merton, [1949a] 1968a).

The third pillar on which the conservativeness of Parsons' structural functionalism rested was a disinclination
to accord an important place to conflict, opposition or power. The closest Durkheim came to dealing with these
phenomena was in his description of how society behaved coercively, prodding people to a moral way of life.
However, when he saw a clash between the wishes of individuals and the needs of the collectivity, he did not
consider the differential interests of divergent groups, so power remained a neglected variable (cf. Giddens,
1993). Even this limited type of power and opposition was largely absent from Parsons' conceptions, though.
Despite his abiding interest in Freud, Parsons regarded internalization as likely to correct any potential
individual ‘versus’ society antagonism.

In addition, because of the interpénétration of the subsystems, people in Parsons' theory did not have to force
each other to comply with legitimate expectations. They wanted to obey. Even the tendency of most of the
functionalists not to allow much room for survivals was part of their blindness to conflict, in Gouldner's (1970)
view. Had they really examined survivals, he wrote, they would have had to confront the existence of unequal
exchanges, and then they could not have avoided the role of force and opposition in maintaining exploitative
relationships.

In order to show the ways and degrees to which Parsons' writing continued in a functionalist tradition, let us
examine his positions on the three main assumptions previously used to summarize the continuity between
Durkheim and the Scottish Moralists.

• 1
The preference for outsider's inferences. Because Parsons contended that individuals internalized
the same core values, their reflections might provide valid social indicators. Hence, participants'
views might be taken more seriously by Parsons than Durkheim or Adam Smith; but the terms
in Parsons' scheme were so abstract that the potential relevance of insiders' observations was
extremely limited.
• 2

Handbook of Social Theory


Page 6 of 13
SAGE SAGE Reference
© George Ritzer and Barry Smart 2001

A distinction between individuals and collectivities. Parsons certainly emphasized their separation,
and the irreducibility of the social system, and he also saw the social system impinging upon, or
penetrating, the personality system.
• 3
Social integration, without ‘tinkering’, was a very central supposition in Parsons' scheme. The parts
fit, in his view, and once equilibrium was attained, its continuation did not require the stipulation of
any special mechanisms.

The previously described criticisms—from Merton and others working within structural functionalism—did not
lead to any substantial changes in structural functionalism. The perspective retained Parsons' imprint well into
the 1960s, and then it was slowly ‘overwhelmed’ by the criticisms of theorists working within other paradigms
that were then evolving. Functionalism left center stage, and nearly left the stage entirely. Nearly two decades
later, however, neofunctionalism appeared, and Parsons was again viewed as its major spokesperson. Before
examining these more recent changes, however, it is important to note most of the paradigms whose insights
were utilized to criticize structural functionalism were developed in large part as polemics against Parsonian
structural functionalism. Among the most important of these paradigms were:

• Exchange: George Homans (1958), who had been part of the Pareto Circle with Parsons, made
seminal contributions to this perspective, largely because he thought the macro-Durkheimian
emphasis in Parsons paid insufficient attention to the psychological underpinnings of social
structures.
• Ethnomethodology: Harold Garfinkel (1964), a former student of Parsons', made significant
contributions to this paradigm in part to rectify what he regarded as Parsons' view of people as
oversocialized dopes.
• Feminist-gender: The functionalists' very traditional views of women and women's roles was an
important impetus to new theories about gender differences and the sexual division of labor (cf.
Johnson, 1989).

Still other sociologists polemicized against the tendency—shared by most functionalists from Durkheim to
Parsons—to downplay the role of conflict in society. They developed a conflict school that probably depended
more upon a polemic against structural functionalism for its inception than any of the other theoretical
paradigms. Before Parsons' emphasis upon order and stability, Alexander (1998: 95) comments, ‘there was
no such beast as “conflict theory”’.

Conflict Theory

To keep the record straight, we should note that some conflict theories pre-dated Parsons. Marx, discussed
elsewhere in this volume, is the obvious example. Simmel may also be a good example, depending upon
how his writings are interpreted. His essays (1908; in Levine, 1971) examined such issues as superordination
and subordination, conflicts and contradictions. However, Simmel was interested in the form of solidarity,
friendship and other forms of relationship in addition to conflict; hence, Simmel can be interpreted as having
offered a theory of conflict rather than a conflict theory (Collins, 1990).

It is also important to note that the major structural functionalists did not entirely ignore power and conflict
(cf. Lockwood, 1992). For example, Durkheim ([1893] 1964) described class conflicts in modern society,
with a reference to Marx no less! And Parsons' (1951) analysis of need dispositions included a discussion
of dominance and submission. However, their attention to such matters was generally brief and they de-
emphasized conflict and differential power by placing them into ‘special’ (i.e. out-of-the-ordinary) categories.
Thus, Durkheim discussed class conflict under the heading, ‘abnormal forms’ of the division of labor, and
Parsons discussed domination under the rubric, ‘deviant orientation’. In reaction, some mid-twentieth-century
theorists urged a more prominent treatment of conflict, and one that regarded it as a more normal part of any
society.

The advocates of conflict theory quickly found themselves caught between theoretical behemoths. On one
side was structural functionalism, with Parsons' emphasis upon normative and value consensus, and a
harmonious relationship among the parts. There was, of course, a readily available rendition of conflict theory:
Handbook of Social Theory
Page 7 of 13
SAGE SAGE Reference
© George Ritzer and Barry Smart 2001

Marxian. However, it entailed a number of suppositions these proponents found little better than the structural
functionalism they were criticizing. Specifically, all the versions of Marxian theory tended to emphasize intense
struggles that had a material basis and could not be resolved without fundamentally changing the society that
engendered them. The conflict theorists were not comfortable embracing Marxism because they contended
that: the roots of social conflicts were as often normative as material, the intensity and tractability of these
conflicts were explicitly variable, and the competing interests of different groups might be reconciled without
necessarily altering fundamental properties of the society.

Two of the most influential early advocates of conflict theory were Ralf Dahrendorf and Lewis Coser. The
degree of convergence between their views declined over time, however, and their positions essentially
came largely to define the two poles within which conflict theories developed. Dahrendorf initially tried to
present an outline of a theory of social conflict that examined the intensity of conflict as variable, influenced
by such considerations as: the number of dimensions on which people were deprived, how organized they
were, the relations between a group's leaders and followers, and so on (Dahrendorf, 1959). Although he
was very critical of Parsons' emphasis upon consensus, he was primarily interested in trying to strike a
balance that would equalize the treatment of consensus and conflict. Coser (1956) professed a similar
objective, namely, balancing consensus and stability, on the one hand, with conflict and change, on the other.
Correspondingly, he argued that some of Marx's ideas should be incorporated into structural functionalism in
order to compensate for that paradigm's neglect of power and conflict.

Claiming to steer a middle ground, Coser criticized both Marx and Durkheim; but the latter fared a lot better
than the former in Coser's hands. For example, he claimed that Marx was ‘historically obsolete’, but Coser
thought it appropriate to forgive him because it was not Marx's fault he was born in the wrong century (Coser,
1967: 150). He also wrote that while Marx's analysis was analytically powerful, it was too narrow in its focus
upon the economic realm, and that it could and should be recast in functionalist terms. Coser's criticisms
of Durkheim were much milder; for example, he claimed that Durkheim's theories were too conservative.
However, even these gentle rebukes were usually offset by what followed, in which Coser either stated that he
really meant only to praise Durkheim or that Durkheim's influence upon his thinking remained unsurpassed.

In the end, Coser tried to add just a little conflict to a functionalist perspective more than he tried to add a
little consensus to a conflict theory. Thus, his analyses focused upon functions of social conflict and tried to
show its positive consequences; for example, reducing tension which thereby permitted systems to continue.
Perhaps in response, Dahrendorf's (1968) later writing became more critical of functionalism, Parsons in
particular, and described society as more characterized by conflict than consensus.

There continues to be some sociological writing that one can identify as falling within a non-Marxian conflict
perspective. One of the distinguishing features of much of this work is that, at least implicitly, Parsons'
ghost seems to hover in its background. For example, James Hunter's (1991, 1996) influential writing on
America's cultural wars sees conflict as endemic, and based upon competing values and beliefs that are
explicitly not class-based, in a Marxian sense. The only resolution Hunter sees will require the development
of a new normative consensus. To illustrate further, Beteille's analysis of contemporary India makes explicit
use of Parsons' paradigm, and shows how the tension between consensus and conflict has continued
to characterize conflict theory. After reviewing the ways in which institutionalized values in India seem
incompatible with each other, he concluded that a society's normative structure ‘is designed to regulate
conflicts of interest between … its constituent parts. But what is to regulate the conflicts that inhere in the
normative structure itself?’ (Beteille, 1998: 286).

In recent years, conflict theory has been nibbled at from two sides by the convergence of neo-Marxian and
neofunctional theories. Its always tenuous boundaries, between Marx and Parsons, have become still more
vague and its attempt to provide a balanced picture of conflict and order—the distinctive thrust of mid-century
conflict theory—has lost much of its distinctiveness. Within the larger discipline it may continue to inform
efforts at micro-macro synthesis, and provide a framework for empirical research (cf. Collins, 1990). However,
the more neofunctional and neo-Marxian paradigms converge, the more difficult it is for me to envision the
conflict perspective occupying an important place in sociological theory.

Collins (1990) presents a very different prognosis, however. He contends that after conflict theory's mid-

Handbook of Social Theory


Page 8 of 13
SAGE SAGE Reference
© George Ritzer and Barry Smart 2001

century theoretical debates with functionalism, conflict theory developed in relation to empirical, macro-
historical research, and such major substantive areas as social movements, organizations and stratification.
The theory's emphasis upon domination, power and change has, in Collins' view, permeated enquiry,
though not in a theoretically self-conscious manner. Thus, as research in these diverse areas continues to
accumulate, the development of conflict theory may quietly and simultaneously proceed.

Neofunctionalism

During the 1970s, the criticism and defense of Parsons and of structural functionalism declined. The burial
of the man (in 1979) could easily have been viewed as symbolizing the end of his influence as well. It
turned out to be only a brief hiatus, however, because during the 1980s there was a revival of interest in
Parsons' writing. Some of the renewed attention had little to do with structural functionalism. Rather, it was
the result of sociologists again recognizing his importance in synthesizing the work of classical theorists and
using it to advance such disparate areas as family sociology (cf. Smith, 1993) and economy and society
(cf. Holton and Turner, 1986). Of more direct relevance to the concerns of this chapter, there was also a
resurgence of interest in Parsonian structural functionalism, first in Germany and then in the United States
(Alexander, 1983). Almost all of the efforts, on both sides of the Atlantic, sought to merge aspects of structural
functionalism with other paradigms that had better developed critical and behavioral perspectives. The
objective was to create a ‘hybrid’ that built upon the conceptual strengths of each of the merged perspectives
in order to provide more balanced treatments of such (potentially) disparate tendencies as: equilibrium and
change, cohesion and conflict, social structure and agency (Alexander and Colomy, 1990).

Two of the leading figures in the German revival were Niklas Luhmann and Jiirgen Habermas. The two
collaborated in 1971 on a theory of social engineering in modern society, then subsequently worked
separately, though along some parallel tracks, and with frequent reference to each other's work. Luhmann
had been formally trained in law, but read sociology and spent a year studying with Parsons at Harvard (in
1960). At the time of his collaboration with Habermas, much of Luhmann's work followed a framework that
was sympathetic to Parsonian structural functionalism. In marked contrast, Habermas was a major figure in
the Frankfurt School, dominated by critical theorists for whom Marx's writings were central and for whom
Parsons was an anathema.

Luhmannn moved from Parsons: the title of one of his major theoretical books—Social Systems- clearly
reflects Parsons' influence; so did Luhmann's self-conscious use of ego and alter as referents. However,
Luhmann's book incorporated perspectives on systems from such diverse sources as linguistics and cognitive
sciences. He contended that relationships between systems and their environments were more complex
than Parsons' description implied, and he conceived of subsystems more as differentiated problem-solving
units (Luhmann, [1984] 1995). Perhaps his most explicit disagreement with Parsons concerned the options
normally available to ego and alter as concrete human beings. Parsons' emphases upon value consensus
and the social system's penetration of the personality system, according to Luhmann, limited the kinds of
social relationships and human behavior that a theorist could analyse outside of a deviant category. To open
more alternatives, he conceptually moved people out of the social system and into a ‘societal environment’
that he described both as more complex and less restrictive than the social system. It accords people more
freedom, Luhmann ([1984] 1995: 213) wrote, ‘especially freedom for irrational and immoral behavior’.

Habermas, on the other hand, moved toward Parsons. His early writings, like those of most critical theorists,
treated Parsons disparagingly. He was especially sharp in his criticisms of Parsons' proclivity for objectifying
and elevating system imperatives. In juxtaposition, he emphasized action and the ‘lifeworld’. However,
without attributing dominance to system properties or adopting Durkheimian notions about system integration,
Habermas did initially accord a place in his critical theory to cultural, social and personality systems;
and his conceptualization of their interrelationships was consistent with Parsons' view (Habermas, 1975).
Corresponding with these three systems, Habermas described the lifeworld as a parallel, intersubjective
realm for experiencing and communicating about culture, society and personality.

As societies become more complex, he later wrote, lifeworld and structural systems become increasingly
separated from each other because people find it more difficult to predict the consequences of their actions.
Therefore, Habermas (1987) concluded, to explain most contemporary societies may require the Parsonian
Handbook of Social Theory
Page 9 of 13
SAGE SAGE Reference
© George Ritzer and Barry Smart 2001

inference of self-regulating systems, though requirements of the lifeworld continue to set parameters within
which systems evolve. It is this assumption of (at least partly) self-regulating systems that is probably the
most unambiguously neofunctional feature in Habermas' intentionally eclectic theory. However, some critics
have been reluctant to let him hedge on this issue, and contend that any assumption of self-regulation is
fundamentally incompatible with Habermas' view that systems are dependent upon the conceptions and
actions of individual participants (cf. Schwinn, 1998).

Within the United States, most of the major contributions to neofunctionalism came from theorists who were
sympathetic to Parsonian structural functionalism. Especially notable was the writing of Jeffrey Alexander
whose volume on Parsons helped again to focus the attention of sociologists upon Parsons' framework
(Alexander, 1983; see also Camic, 1987). In that volume Alexander praised Parsons as a synthesizer of
grand theory without equal, and claimed that his influence continued to be enormous. At the same time,
Alexander was critical of Parsons' theory on several grounds, agreeing that it posed an overly deterministic
stance and lacked sufficient attention to conflict and strain. In his subsequent essays on neofunctionalism,
however, Alexander (1985; Alexander and Colomy, 1990) contended that the theory's deficiencies were not
irreversible. In other words, conflict and subjective meaning could be introduced; and system integration and
the interpénétration of subsystems could be regarded as tendencies, open to enquiry rather than assumed,
as givens.

The response to the efforts of Alexander and others to revive functionalist notions in the guise of
neofunctionalism has been markedly varied. Echoing the disapproval of Habermas' consolidations, some
critics felt there were limits to how far any theoretical perspective could go in accommodating incompatible
notions, and still retain its name and lineage. Noefunctionalism, to these critics, was eviscerated from its
heritage (Turner and Maryanski, 1988); but others saw clear continuity (Colomy, 1990). Coming from an
opposite direction, still other antagonists felt the recent changes were more cosmetic than real because
neofunctionalism remained imbued with the features that distinguished functionalism, from the Scottish
Moralists to Durkheim. Specifically, the ‘objective’ view of outsiders continued to predominate, people were
still regarded as reactors to systems more than actors, and conflict remained secondary. Blasi (1987: 187)
claimed the supporters of neofunctionalism failed to realize that they had not made substantive alterations
to functionalism because, ‘orthodoxies rest on presuppositions which are invisible to the orthodox adherents
themselves’.

An Empirical Referent?

If Alexander's predictions about the future of social theory are correct, the criticisms of neofunctionalism
(or functionalism) are merely final gasps from the past. In his most recent book (Alexander, 1998), he tried
to describe what the sociological landscape might look like ‘after neofunctionalism’. He concluded that the
polemics have run their course. There will be grand theory in the future, he foresees, it will be important and it
will be truly multidimensional with respect to macro-micro, conflict-order and the other polarities which divided
theorists in the past. Neofunctionalism, after further ‘hybridization’, will necessarily be a still less distinctive
paradigm if Alexander is correct.

If neofunctionalism, or some other descendent of functionalism, persists, will it be developed in relation to


empirical research? In other words, will theory and research be expected to bear upon each other in the
future? These questions introduce another potentially important polarity, namely, how much the referent for
any theory ought to be other theory rather than empirical research. These particular poles may have been
moved further apart even as other polarities were presumably diminishing.

The current emphasis upon synthesis accentuates the importance of conceptual analyses of how paradigms
and suppositions previously thought to be at variance with each other can now be combined. There may also
be some empirical referent in these efforts to construct or deconstruct theories, but it is of trivial importance
except insofar as one wants to include the theoretical writings of others as though they represented empirical
observations (cf. Parsons, 1949). When the culture of social theorists stresses synthesis it is likely to be
better for the advancement of metatheory than for extending the links between theory and research. As Ritzer
(1991) notes, there are diverse types of metatheory, different from each other in their ambitions. None of them
takes enhancement of the interplay between theory and research as a major objective, though.
Handbook of Social Theory
Page 10 of 13
SAGE SAGE Reference
© George Ritzer and Barry Smart 2001

Another major reason for the neofunctionalists' relative neglect of empirical linkages lies in the predilections
of its most influential figure, Jeffrey Alexander, and those who have worked most closely with him.5 While
not anti-empirical, Alexander (1998) is explicitly suspicious of empirically based inferences, arguing that
social science is fundamentally different from natural science because theoretical traditions always permeate
everything social scientists see and do. He further states, and this is the nub of the matter, that given the
differences in the nature of the two types of science, sociological theory can be scientifically significant
independently of its capacity to explain empirical observations (Alexander, 1998, esp. ch. 8).

Minimizing the importance of the interplay between theory and empirical research sounds, to me, more like
the past than the future. It will put the discipline at risk of experiencing what worried Merton ([1949b] 1968b)
half of a century ago, namely, that one group of theorists will absurdly contemplate each other's abstractions
while a totally separate group of researchers carry out mindless modeling and abstracted empiricism. Would
it not be ironic to characterize the division of labor in sociology as anomic?

Notes

1 His conclusions regarding marriage among royalty was one of several analyses in which Hume was
influenced by Mandeville's earlier contention that private vices can lead to public virtues (Baier, 1991).

2 In addition to describing a condition in which the parts did not fit, Durkheim also affixed anomie to situations
in which the norms did not regulate people's aspirations or desires. For further clarification of types of anomie,
see Abrahamson, 1980, and Merton, 1995. What ties these two types of anomie together is Durkheim's
contention that it is precisely when there is an imbalance among the parts that the social norms fail to regulate.

3 Sequeing from Durkheim to Parsons helps to illuminate their continuity, but it leaves out the way Durkheim
influenced social anthropologists, and how they, in turn, influenced subsequent sociologists. Especially
notable, to round out this picture, are Radcliffe-Brown, 1955, and Malinowski, 1927.

4 Along with Robert K. Merton, George C. Homans and others, Parsons belonged to a ‘Pareto Circle’ that
regularly met at Harvard during the 1930s (cf. Heyl, 1968).

5 There are exceptions, of course, and especially notable is the comparative analysis of educational
institutions by Parsons' former student and collaborator, Neil Smelser (1985).

MarkAbrahamson

References

Aberle, David F., Cohen, Albert K., Davis, Allison K., and Levy, Marion J., ([1950] 1967)‘The Functional
Prerequisites of a Society’, in NicholasDemerath, and RichardPeterson, (eds), System, Change and Conflict.
New York: The Free Press, pp. 317–31
Abrahamson, Mark, (1978)Functionalism. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
AbrahamsonMark‘Sudden Wealth, Gratification and Attainment: Durkheim's Anomie of Affluence
Reconsidered'’American Sociological Review45149–581980http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2095242
Alexander, Jeffrey C., (1983)The Modern Reconstruction of Classical Thought: Talcott Parsons. Berkeley, CA:
University of California Press.
Alexander, Jeffrey C., (1985)Neofunctionalism. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
Alexander, Jeffrey C., (1998)Neofunctionalism and After. Maiden, MA: Blackwell.
Alexander, Jeffrey C., and Colomy, Paul, (1990)‘Neofunctionalism Today’, in GeorgeRitzer (éd.), Frontiers of
Social Theory. New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 33–67
Baier, Annette C., (1991)A Progress of Sentiments. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Beteille, Andre, (1998)‘The Conflict of Norms and Values in Contemporary Indian Society’, in Peter L.Berger
(Ed.), The Limits of Social Cohesion. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, pp. 265–92
BlasiAnthony J.‘Review of Neofunctionalism’Sociological Analysis482186–71987http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/
3711208
Handbook of Social Theory
Page 11 of 13
SAGE SAGE Reference
© George Ritzer and Barry Smart 2001

CamicCharles‘The Making of a Method’American Sociological Review522421–391987


Collins, Randall, (1990)‘Conflict Theory and the Advance of Macro-Historical Sociology’, in GeorgeRitzer
(éd.), Frontiers of Social Theory. New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 68–87
Colomy, Paul, (1990)‘Introduction’, in PaulColomy (éd.), Neofunctionalist Sociology. Brookfield, VT: Elgar
Publishing, pp. xi–lxii
Copley, Stephen, (1995)‘Introduction’, in StephenCopley, and KathrynSutherland, (eds), Adam Smith's
Wealth of Nations. Manchester: Manchester University Press, pp. 1–22
Coser, Lewis, (1956)The Functions of Social Conflict. New York: The Free Press.
Coser, Lewis, (1967)Continuities in the Study of Social Conflict. New York: The Free Press.
Dahrendorf, Ralf, (1959)Class and Class Conflict in Industrial Society. Stanford, CA: Stanford University
Press.
Dahrendrof, Ralf, (1968)Essays in the Theory of Society. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
DavisKingsley‘The Myth of Functional Analysis as a Special Method in Sociology and Anthropology’American
Sociological Review243757–721959
Durkheim, Emile, ([1893] 1964)The Division of Labor in Society. New York: The Free Press.
Durkheim, Emile, ([1895] 1964)The Rules of Sociological Method. New York: The Free Press.
Faia, Michael A., (1986)Dynamic Functionalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1017/CBO9780511628078
GarfinkelHarold‘The Studies of the Routine Grounds of Everyday Activity’Social Problems112225–501964
Giddens, Anthony, (1993)New Rules of Sociological Method. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Gouldner, Alvin W., (1970)The Coming Crises in Western Sociology. New York: Basic Books.
Habermas, Jiirgen, (1975)Legitimation Crisis. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Habermas, Jiirgen, (1987)The Theory of Communicative Action. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
HeylBarbara S.‘The Harvard Pareto Circle’Journal of the History of the Behavioral
Sciences4316–341968http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/1520-6696%28196810%294:4%3C316::AID-
JHBS2300040403%3E3.0.CO;2-Z
Holton, Robert J., and Turner, Bryan S., (1986)Talcott Parsons on Economy and Society. London: Routledge
and Kegan Paul.
HomansGeorge C.‘Social Behavior as Exchange’American Journal of Sociology633597–6061958
Hume, David, (1879)The History of England. New York: Harper.
Hunter, James D.(1991)Culture Wars. New York: Basic Books.
HunterJames D.‘Response to Davis and Robinson: Remembering Durkheim’Journal for the Scientific Study
of Religion353246–81996http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/1386554
Johnson, Miriam, (1989)‘Feminism and the Theories of Talcott Parsons’, in Ruth A.Wallace (ed.), Feminism
and Sociological Theory. Newbury Park, CA: Sage. pp. 101–18
Levine, Donald, (ed.) (1971)Georg Simmel. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lockwood, David, (1992)Solidarity and Schism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Luhmannn, Niklas, (1982)The Differentiation of Society. New York: Columbia University Press.
Luhmannn, Niklas, ([1984] 1995)Social Systems. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Malinowski, Bronislaw, (1927)Sex and Repression in Savage Society. New York: Harcourt, Brace.
Merton, Robert K., ([1949a] 1968a)‘Manifest and Latent Functions’, in Robert K.Merton, Social Theory and
Social Structure. New York: The Free Press, pp. 73–138
Merton, Robert K., ([1949b] 1968b)‘The Bearing of Sociological Theory on Empirical Research’ and ‘The
Bearing of Empirical Research on Sociological Theory’, in Robert K.Merton, Social Theory and Social
Structure. New York: The Free Press, pp. 83–111
Merton, Robert K., (1995)‘Opportunity Structure’, in FredaAdler, and William S.Laufer, (eds), The Legacy of
Anomie Theory. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Books, pp. 3–78
Pareto, Vilfredo, ([1916] 1963)The Mind and Society. New York: Dover Publications.
Parsons, Talcott, (1937)The Structure of Social Action. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Parsons, Talcott, (1949)The Structure of Social Action,
2nd edn.
New York: McGraw-Hill.
Parsons, Talcott, (1951)The Social System. New York: The Free Press.
Parsons, Talcott, (1966)Societies. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Parsons, Talcott, and Smelser, Neil J., (1956)Economy and Society. New York: The Free Press.
Radcliffe-Brown, A. R., (1955)Structure andTunction in Primitive Society. New York: The Free Press.
Handbook of Social Theory
Page 12 of 13
SAGE SAGE Reference
© George Ritzer and Barry Smart 2001

Ritzer, George, (1980)Sociology: A Multiple Paradigm Science,


rev. edn.
Boston, MA: Allyn and Bacon.
Ritzer, George, (1991)Metatheorizing in Sociology. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books.
SchwinnThomas‘False Connections: Systems and Action Theories in Neofunctionalism and in Jiirgen
Habermas’Sociological Theory16175–951998http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/0735-2751.00043
Sciulli, David, (1991)Theory of Societal Constitutionalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511570933
Smelser, Neil J., (1985)‘Evaluating the Model of Structural Differentiation in Relation to Educational Change in
the Nineteenth Century’, in Jeffrey C.Alexander (ed.), Neofunctionalism. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage Publications,
pp. 113–29
SmithAdamThe Wealth of Nations. Edinburgh: Adam and Charles Black.
SmithDorothy E.‘The Standard North American Family’Journal of Tamily
Issues14150–65(1993)http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0192513X93014001005
TurnerJonathan H.‘Emile Durkheim's Theory of Social Organization’Social Torces6841089–1031990
TurnerJonathan H., and MaryanskiAlexandra Z.‘Is “Neofunctionalism” Really Functional?’Sociological
Theory61110–211988http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/201919

• structural functionalism
• functionalism
• conflict theory
• social facts
• division of labor
• social system
• lifeworld

http://dx.doi.org/10.4135/9781848608351.n12

Handbook of Social Theory


Page 13 of 13

You might also like