You are on page 1of 11

B.J.Pol.S.

II, 309-329 310 MILLER


Printed in Great Britain 309
Socialists are sometimes inclined to challenge the historical assumptions that
bolster this libertarian argument. They claim that co-operatives are actively
Market Neutrality and the Failure of opposed by capitalists who see that successful co-operative production threatens
their own advantaged position. It is therefore in the capitalists' interests to harass
Co-operatives newly-formed co-operatives by, for instance, refusing to trade with them,
preventing them from obtaining credit, and in the last resort using the power of
DAVID MILLER*
the state to suppress them. The relative absence of co-operatives from the
historical record, therefore, testifies more to the power of the capitalist class than
Among the arguments that have featured in the recent revival of libertarian to the preferences of the working population for capitalist forms of organization.
thinking is one purporting to show that a free market economy, protected by A brief examination of British experience may throw some light on this
a minimal state1 - or even no state at all2 - is neutral as between capitalism and question. During the nineteenth century, several hundred small co-operatives
a certain form of socialism. The argument runs as follows. The market places were started by groups of working men, sometimes but not always with
no limits on the manner in which people may associate for purposes of economic middle-class sponsorship. Very few of these institutions survived for more than
activity. They may choose capitalist forms of organization, in which case those a few years, and indeed none managed to preserve the pure co-operative form
who become owners of capital assume a greater degree of risk and responsibility in which all and only workers have a share in the capital of the enterprise.4 There
and stand to gain correspondingly higher rewards, or they may choose is little evidence, however, of external hostility as the cause of disappearance.
co-operative forms, where groups of producers supply their own capital and If a corn-mill was established by subscription because a ring of millers
share the profits between them. If capitalist forms are overwhelmingly favoured, adulterated the flour and kept up prices, then naturally the millers would try
as the historical evidence shows, this reveals something about the preference to have the project stopped.5 But such cases were untypical, as we shall see in
structure of the population as a whole. Either the bulk of the population actively a moment. As far as the state is concerned, the law prior to 1852 was
wish to avoid the risks and anxieties of capital ownership, and so willingly unfavourable to co-operative associations, but Acts passed in that year and in
transfer these responsibilities to the few willing to bear them; or the efficiency 1862 gave co-operatives legal recognition as limited liability companies. Rather
of the capitalist firm is such that it can pay wages high enough to compensate than suppressing co-operatives, therefore, the state was willing to offer them its
the work force for their loss of autonomy in comparison with the co-operative
protection.
alternative.
Why, then, did the co-operatives fare so badly? The sources of decay were
Nozick, for example, argues that if workers' control of industry is considered almost entirely internal. There were three classic patterns of decline. The first
a sufficiently important goal by any group of people, they ought to be prepared occurred most commonly when the starting capital was supplied to the
to take lower wages in order to join a worker-controlled enterprise.3 The co-operative by a middle-class philanthropist. Here the co-operative simply went
financial sacrifice would be an accurate measure of the value they find in working
bankrupt, or made losses until the philanthropist decided to pull out what
in a democratic environment. So even if co-operatives are less efficient as remained of his investment. The cause was 'labour indiscipline': the workforce
economic units than capitalist firms, they will still be established by those with
refused to produce efficiently, or drew excessive amounts from the capital fund
the appropriate preference schedules. In this way the market responds to tastes as income, or both. Such behaviour is intelligible given that the producers had
for different modes of economic organization as accurately as it does to tastes no stake in the capital, and no assurance that the 'experiment' would be
for different varieties of ice-cream. If, by contrast, a particular pattern of continued indefinitely. The problem was no doubt amplified by the fact that these
association were to be made compulsory, as occurs in a socialist system which ventures typically opened their doors to all comers, and aspired to be more than
prohibits the private ownership of capital, the preferences of at least some merely productive units; they were intended to be reforming social communities
people would be ignored in the social calculus. This would not only be inefficient, as well.6 So, for instance, as one contemporary account puts it, 'failure was
but would discriminate between personal tastes in a way that the neutral market
mechanism avoids.
4 I therefore exclude the institution which bulks large in 'histories of co-operation', the
* Nuffield College, Oxford. An earlier version of this paper was searchingly criticized by lain Co-operative Wholesale Society, since this was an association of consumers employing workers
Hampsher-Monk, Anthony Heath, Brian Hindley and Kurt Klappholz at a meeting sponsored by rather than a co-operative in my sense.
the Acton Society. I am extremely grateful to them for their comments, and conscious that several 5 See Benjamin Jones, Co-operative Production (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894), Vol. I, Chap.
14.
of their objections remain unanswered. I should also like to thank the Journal's reviewers for a
number of helpful suggestions. 6 The classic examples were the communities at Orbiston, Ralahine and Queenswood. See Jones,
Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1974). Co-operative Production, Vol. I. Chap. 6; R. G. Garnett, Co-operation and the Owenite Socialist
2 David Friedman, The Machinery of Freedom (New York: Harper and Row, I973). Communities in Britain, 1825-i845 (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1972).
3 Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia, pp. 250-3.
Market Neutrality and the Failure of Co-operatives 31I 312 MILLER

accelerated by the sexes being thrown too much together, in consequence of the convert the original sponsors into small capitalists. Typical examples are the
want of separate rooms'.7 numerous boot and shoe societies which were set up initially by groups of
The second pattern of decline was manifested by co-operatives that were artisans supplying a few pounds each, but later took on non-members as
launched by share subscriptions, with the members taking up the bulk of the employees.10 Beatrice Webb, who for this and other reasons was implacably
shares. This is plainly an impure form of co-operative, but I think it deserves opposed to producers' co-operatives, denounced this particular development as
the title so long as it is differentiated from the standard joint-stock company 'the wolf in sheep's clothing, the brotherhood of workers sweating their fellow
men'.
by the fact that workers are majority shareholders. Here again there were often
'labour discipline' problems: workers who had appointed their manager The evidence therefore points overwhelmingly to the conclusion that co-
apparently found it difficult to accept disciplinary measures from him. However, operatives have disappeared for reasons internal to themselves. They have not
the fundamental source of decay came with financial success. As the enterprise's been crushed by outside pressure from capitalists, but undermined by the action
capital grew, shares passed increasingly to outside investors, who eventually of their own members, whether this led to financial failure or to degeneration.
Thus far it seems that the libertarian case stands. Individuals have followed their
came to have a majority shareholding. This was liable to happen through
workers retiring, or moving to new employment, or through share issues to raise preferences in the market, and their preferences have led them away from the
new capital. A good example is the Rochdale Co-operative Manufacturing co-operative form of organization.
Society, set up to run a cotton mill, which after a period of financial hardship A socialist critic might at this point fall back on the claim that the preferences
suddenly became profitable. One of the promoters described the result. expressed in market behaviour are corrupted by the market itself. The self-interest
displayed by the co-operators whose behaviour led to the downfall of their
The original promotors never lost confidence in the principle of profit-sharing. It was institutions reflects the influence of capitalist society on human motives, rather
the success of the society that attracted to it persons who only cared for the eternal 'divi'.
than any 'real' or 'true' human preferences. This familiar claim leads, however,
These persons brought into the society their money very rapidly for shares, thus raising
to grave difficulties concerning the identification of 'true' as opposed to 'false'
the number of shareholders from 200 or 300 to 1,400. It was the new shareholding element
preferences. I believe that a more economical case can be made out against the
that swamped the original promotors of what was then called 'Bounty to labour'.8
libertarian position. It may be possible to show that the market is an inefficient
These co-operatives were therefore transformed into joint-stock companies, with means of satisfying preferences of certain kinds, even when 'preferences' are
an increasing separation between capital and labour. In their transformed state taken to be those revealed in speech or behaviour rather than imputed 'real
they might of course prove commercially viable, and indeed some of the preferences'.
longest-lasting 'co-operatives' have been enterprises of this form - typically The case relies on the notion that the collective result of many separate
small and undynamic businesses where the new capital has come from sympathetic individual actions may be an outcome which is unintended and unwanted by
sources like trade unions which allow the workforce to retain a considerable say any of the persons involved. This possibility has often been explored using the
in the management of the enterprise.9 model of the Prisoner's Dilemma, in which two individuals acting self-interestedly
The third pattern of decay occurred in cases where the starting capital needed but independently arrive at a result that is worse for both of them than an
by the co-operative was fairly small, and could therefore be subscribed by the alternative which they could have reached by mutual agreement. In such a case
founders themselves. Here, too, success was fatal to the co-operative form. When it would pay both participants to employ an agent to compel them to reach the
expansion took place, it was more tempting to take on new workers as wage preferred alternative. The model has been thought to have particular reference
labour than to admit them as equal partners with claims to the profits from to the supply of public goods, where each person has an incentive to avoid
capital they had not subscribed. Sometimes this was done surreptitiously by making his contribution to their cost, whilst enjoying the results of everyone
raising the requirements of membership- for example, by demanding an else's contribution. If everyone follows this policy, no public goods are supplied,
unrealistically large capital subscription from new members. The effect was to even though everyone would be prepared to contribute on condition that all
others did likewise. In this case again, compulsion appears to be the only way
Jones, Co-operative Production, Vol. I, p. 70. of reaching the most efficient outcome.12
8 Jones, Co-operative Production, Vol. I, p. 262.
9 See Robert Oakeshott, The Case for Workers' Co-ops (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul,
10 Jones, Co-operative Production, Vol. I. Chap. 19.
1978), Chap. 5; Derek Jones, 'British Producer Co-operatives' in Ken Coates, ed., The New Worker
11 Beatrice Webb, The Co-operative Movement in Great Britain (London: Swann Sonnenschein,
Co-operatives (Nottingham: Spokesman Books, 1976). Jones stresses the longevity of these
I891), p. I44. For her general case against producers' co-operatives, see Chap. 5, passim.
enterprises and attacks the pessimistic views of the Webbs, but his figures reveal that the surviving
12 The Prisoner's Dilemma may also be avoided if the parties are assumed to have a sufficient
firms are really participatory joint-stock companies rather than genuine co-operatives, with the
degree of altruism. Fordiscussion of such escape routes, see Michael Taylor, Anarchy and Co-operation
employees very rarely being majority shareholders (although more often having a majority on the
(London: Wiley, 1976); A. K. Sen, 'Choice, Orderings and Morality' in S. Korner, ed., Practical
management committee).
Reason (Oxford: Blackwell, 1974); David Collard, Altruism and Economy (Oxford: Martin
Robertson, 1978), Chap. 4.
Market Neutrality and the Failure of Co-operatives 313
314 MILLER

I shall suggest that this analysis can be applied to co-operatives operating in


him, then of course there is potential conflict between the capitalist's goal of
a free market economy. In pursuing their preferences the members of such
wealth maximization and the manager's goal of maximizing his income.14 The
groups may be led inevitably to sub-optimal outcomes that involve the failure
firm's behaviour will depend on how successful the capitalist is in inducing the
or degeneration of the co-operative. If my suggestion can be validated, the
nineteenth-century examples will reflect the basic difficulties of any co-operative
manager to pursue the first goal, by threats, bonuses, offers of promotion or
operating in a capitalist society, not merely the mistakes of their members in whatever. I assume in what follows that we are comparing co-operatives with
particular. In a sense this would be reassuring, for although human error should
capitalist firms in which the capitalist either manages himself or succeeds in
getting the actual manager to make wealth maximization his aim.15
never be discounted in such cases, it seems unlikely that so many promising
The co-operative's goal is not wealth maximization but maximization of
beginnings would have come to grief if there were not some overriding defect
income per worker.l6 It is democratically run by its members, who have no
in the co-operative form when placed in capitalist surroundings.
interest in increasing the over-all wealth of the co-operative except in so far as
In the rudimentary economic analysis that follows, I assume that the goal of
this is reflected in increasing income for them. Now that does not mean that they
co-operative members is to maximize their personal incomes.13 This is certainly
will wish to maximize income in any one time period, say the current year. Their
a drastic over-simplification, but it is needed at this point to model the behaviour
interest is to maximize their total earnings from the co-operative. Like the
of co-operatives in the market. Later I shall ask what difference a more complex
capitalist they will need to include a time discount, to reflect the lesser value of
set of goals might make. It seems improbable that income maximization will not
a pound a year hence; unlike him, however, they will also need to consider how
feature among the goals of those entering a co-operative: in many actual cases
it seems to have been the dominant goal, in the sense that workers were driven
long they are likely to belong to the co-operative, and how much capital they
will be able to take out if they choose to leave. These factors will determine how
to seek this alternative by the predatory behaviour of their former employers.
calculations of potential income are made.
What difference does the co-operative's different maximand - income per
THE ECONOMICS OF CO-OPERATIVES worker - make to its behaviour? The effect can be seen easily if we compare a
capitalist firm and an otherwise identical co-operative deciding whether to take
At first sight it may seem that the economic behaviour of a co-operative will
on an additional worker, given a fixed quantity of capital and a fixed price for
replicate that of a technologically identical capitalist firm. The fact that in one
the product to be made. The capitalist, as we have seen, will hire whenever
case the assets are owned by the workforce as a whole and in the other by a
marginal return exceeds marginal cost. If the labourer can be hired for ?5o and
capitalist hiring labour will not affect decisions about production, employment
and investment, although it will of course affect the distribution of profits. A
makes ?5I profit for the enterprise, he will be taken on. In the case of the
co-operative, however, it will depend on the average income already being paid
co-operative is taken to be a productive unit owned and controlled by its
to members. Since the new hand can only be taken on as a full member (if the
members, with profits distributed according to a democratically-made decision.
co-operative is not to degenerate into a joint-stock company), he must be paid
Will such a unit follow the same profit-maximizing goal as a capitalist enterprise
in its external relations?
The capitalist's aim is wealth-maximization. He will hire labour and invest 14 For analysis of this conflict, see E. G. Furubotn and S. Pejovich, eds., The Economics of
PropertY Rights (Cambridge, Mass.: Ballinger, 1974), especially Chaps. 15, 22.
capital whenever marginal return exceeds marginal cost; that is, whenever an l'- One can see the possibility of developing a 'convergence thesis' here, if managers in both
extra labourer yields more in profit than he receives in wages, and whenever a capitalist enterprises and co-operatives are able to wrest control from the nominal owners.
pound invested yields more than a pound in return. This will have to be modified Moreover, if, instead of having a single owner, the capitalist firm is a joint-stock company, the
slightly to take account of time - a pound today being worth more in most problem of control is compounded, since the shareholders have to co-ordinate their efforts in order
to constrain the manager, which may prove a costly undertaking. For an analysis, see S. Pejovich,
circumstances than a pound in a year's time - but with this modification the
'The Capitalist Corporation and the Socialist Firm; a Study of Comparative Efficiency' in
assumption holds. The capitalist's wealth and the enterprise's value are one and K. Brunner, ed., Economics and Social Institutions (Boston: Martinus Nijhoff, 1979), who points
the same, so maximizing the latter means maximizing the former. If the capitalist out, however, that the threat of shareholders selling up and depressing the value of the firm's stock
chooses not to run his own business but hires a manager to make decisions for may act as an automatic constraint.
16 This is now a fairly standard assumption. See Benjamin Ward, 'The Firm in Illyria: Market
Syndicalism', American Economic Review, XLVIII (1958), 566-89; Vanek, The General Theory of
1: The analysis is presented informally and draws upon the rapidly growing body of literature
on the economics of co-operatives. Readers wishing for a more formal treatment should begin by Labour-Managed Market Economies; Meade, 'The Theory of Labour-Managed Firms and Profit
consulting the following: J. Vanek, The General Theory of Labour-Managed Market Economies Sharing'; P. Wiles, Economic Institutions Compared (Oxford: Blackwell, 1977), Chap. 4. It has,
however, been challenged by Furubotn who argues that a long-run analysis needs to take account
(Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1970); J. E. Meade, 'The Theory of Labour-Managed Firms and
of the possible effects of an income-maximizing policy on the size and composition of the co-
Profit Sharing', Economic Journal, LXXXII (I972), 402-28; A. Steinherr, 'The Labour-Managed
operative's membership. See E. G. Furubotn, 'The Long Run Analysis of the Labour Managed
Economy: A Survey of the Economics Literature', Annals of Public and Co-operative Economy, IL
Firm', American Economic Review, LXVI (1976), 104-23.
(1978), 129-48; A. Clayre, ed., The Political Economy of Co-operation and Participation (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, I980).
JPS 11
Market Neutrality and the Failure of Co-operatives 315 316 MILLER

according to the current income schedule. So the hiring decision depends on a yield of 23 per cent, a ten year horizon I3 per cent, a twenty year horizon 8
whether the profit he can create raises or lowers the existing average. Suppose per cent.17
for simplicity's sake that income is distributed equally, and that the rate Any actual co-operative will have members with different time horizons
currently paid is ?55, then the extra labourer will not be hired, since to do so depending on age, mobility and so forth. If investment decisions are made by
would reduce average income. One can see immediately the temptation to take majority vote, as has been assumed, the yield required will be determined by the
on this person as a non-member for ?50, which ex hypothesi he is willing to median voter (voters being arranged in order of ascending time horizon). If
accept. The basic logic of hiring is likely to create self-destructive pressures in everyone expects to remain within the co-operative for the whole of his working
the co-operative. life - say forty years - and there is a normal age distribution, the median time
We can infer from this that, ceterisparibus, co-operatives which remain as such horizon will be twenty years. But there is an unrealistically favourable assumption
will be smaller than capitalist firms. They will grow so long as there are from the co-operative's point of view, and I should guess that a median time
economies of scale such that adding extra workers increases the productivity of horizon of about ten years is the most one could expect. If so, we see that the
those already in the partnership; whereas capitalist firms will grow beyond this necessary rate of yield is considerably higher than that required for investment
point so long as the net marginal return remains positive. However, the biggest by a capitalist, from which it follows that the co-operative is likely to invest a
difference concerns not hiring but investment. This, I shall argue, is the Achilles' good deal less than its capitalist counterpart.
heel of co-operatives competing in the market with capitalist enterprises. Might this unfortunate result be avoided by having assets owned individually?
Consider a capitalist firm and a co-operative at the end of a time period when A share of the profit invested would be credited to each person's account, and
a net profit has been made after agreed wages have been paid out. Should the could be withdrawn when the person retired or left the co-operative. Under these
profit be consumed or reinvested? In the case of the capitalist I have postulated circumstances a member may be expected to approach investment decisions in
that investment will occur whenever the expected return is greater than the the same way as a capitalist, investing whenever the expected rate of return more
capitalist's discount for time. This postulate is over-simple, because the capitalist than covers his time discount. Against this, however, investment in a co-operative
will certainly want to pay himself a minimum income over any time period, and has two features which may make it less attractive to members than withdrawing
may not be indifferent as to the distribution between time periods (i.e. he may profits in the form of income and investing elsewhere. One is the inflexibility of
prefer ?5,ooo per annum to ?2,000 in year I and ?8,000 in year 2). But those the investment, which prevents money being drawn out to meet current needs,
complications aside, a pound invested is worth little less than a pound in the obviously an important consideration for most private savers.18 Although a
pocket, and so investment will take place whenever it promises to yield a capitalist may for the same reason wish to save some of his profit outside his
reasonable return.
enterprise, the amount in question will be much less than the combined total
How the co-operative will behave depends on the structure of ownership which required by the N members of a similarly sized co-operative. Furthermore the
it has established. At one extreme the capital may be held as a collective asset capitalist is aware that, should his liquid 'cushion' fail to shield him from some
with no individual having any claim to withdraw it; at the other, individual large financial misfortune, he can in the last resort sell up and realize his assets;
shares may be identified, with rules governing the crediting of accounts and the for the co-operator the existence of this option will depend on the rules of the
withdrawal of assets. There are infinitely many possibilities in between, but let co-operative, and therefore (in all likelihood) on finding a 'buyer' for his job
us consider the two extreme cases. with the right combination of working skills and capital. It will probably be
If assets are held collectively, than a pound invested in the co-operative is, difficult to do this quickly. The other feature which makes investment in a
from the point of view of any individual member, irrecoverable. Consequently co-operative relatively unattractive to its members is that such investment
he will only support the investment if he thinks that the income it will produce prevents the spreading of risk. If the co-operative should go bankrupt both
for him outweighs the immediate loss of revenue. As we have seen, he needs to income and capital would be lost, whereas a capitalist can disperse risk by
estimate how long he is likely to remain a member - a quantity sometimes investing some capital elsewhere and allowing others to invest in his own firm.
referred to as his 'time horizon' - to do this. It will always be true that the rate As Meade has said, 'while property owners can spread their risks by putting
of return needed to persuade such a member to invest is higher than that needed small bits of their property into a large number of concerns, a worker cannot
by a capitalist. To see the magnitude of the difference, suppose that everyone's easily put small bits of his effort into a large number of different jobs. This
time discount is covered by a rate of return on investment of 5 per cent, so that presumably is a main reason why we find risk-bearing capital hiring labour rather
a capitalist will invest whenever the promised yield is 5 per cent or greater. What
17 Calculated by Furubotn and Pejovich in Furubotn and Pejovich, The Economics of Property
is the minimum yield demanded by a co-operative member? If his time horizon
Rights, p. 240.
were one year, he would require a yield of I05 per cent before investing his 18 Might banks be willing to lend to co-operative members, using their investment accounts as
potential income. To take more realistic cases, a five year time horizon requires security? Only if bankers could be convinced that co-operatives were financially sound, on which
see below.
I 1-2
Market Neutrality and the Failure of Co-operatives 317 318 MILLER

than risk-bearing labour hiring capital.'19 One may conjecture whether this certainly invest a good deal more readily than if all assets were held collectively.
second feature explains the observed fact that when nineteenth-century co- At the same time they will not deplete the co-operative's capital unduly when
operators began to hire labour, they often preferred to take paid employment they cash in their assets on retirement. Now this is plainly not the behaviour
outside the co-operative themselves.20 of rational income-maximizers, and a priori there is no reason to expect
The main difficulty, however, with individualized assets is that once the departures from rationality to go in this direction rather than its opposite (i.e.
co-operative begins to lose members through retirement or transfer, it has to towards regarding all assets in the mixed scheme as collective assets). If none
require newcomers to supply capital equivalent in amount to the withdrawals. the less it is empirically true that mixed solutions have the desired result (as
If this requirement were not imposed, the co-operative would be steadily drained Oakeshott and others claim), the best ownership structure for any co-operative
of capital, and moreover, the newcomers would benefit unfairly from the assets will be that for which the 'investment effect' of individualized assets most
accumulated by the founding generation, creating pressure for them to be taken exceeds their 'withdrawal effect'. This may be visualized diagrammatically.
on as employees rather than as equal members of the co-operative. But the
requirement would quickly become a daunting hurdle as the capital per worker Net rate of capital gain Rate of capital gain through investment
increased; even if the money could be borrowed privately, it would make the A\ 45? F
co-operative a less attractive employment prospect than a capitalist enterprise Rate of Fully \
paying similar wages.21 So although individualized assets may reduce the capital collectivized
loss assets
co-operative's investment problem in the short term, in the longer run the effect
through B4
will either be to deter incoming members or to cause the co-operative to with- tI C \- Optimum
degenerate into a joint-stock company owned by the founding generation but drawals Mixed -- , solution
solutions
employing newcomers as wage labourers.22
Some partisans of the co-operative form favour a mixed solution, with Fully D
individualized
assets being held partly individually and partly collectively.23 Profits which were
assets
being reinvested would then be divided between the individual accounts of
members and the collective account in a fixed proportion (or perhaps on a sliding Fig. i.

scale). The argument behind this proposal is that workers need to have some
visible 'stake' in their enterprise to ensure that they make decisions responsibly, The curve AD shows levels of investment and withdrawal for all possible
while on the other hand the co-operative becomes vulnerable to withdrawals if structures of ownership running from fully collectivized to fully individualized
all its assets are held individually. But as far as the investment problem is assets. In drawing it as shown I assume:
concerned, the mixed solution can only succeed if workers are induced by the (i) that between A and B individual stakes are too small to produce much
ownership structure to behave irrationally. Suppose, to take the extreme case, 'investment effect', so that workers continue to perceive invested capital as
that they make their investment decisions as though all reinvested profit was to largely irrecoverable;
be credited to individual accounts. Then, although they will not invest quite as (2) That between B and C an increase in the proportion of individualized assets
readily as their capitalist counterpart (for reasons given above), they will quickly 'triggers' a perceptual change, and workers begin to think of
invested capital as accruing to them personally;
19 Meade, 'The Theory of Labour-Managed Firms and Profit Sharing', p. 426.
(3) that between C and D perceptions and therefore investments hardly alter,
20( Cole observed that 'workers who invested money in cotton mills preferred not to invest it in while withdrawals steadily increase as the ownership structure becomes
the mills in which they were employed; for if they did this they ran a big risk of losing both their further individualized.
wages and their dividends if their particular mill fell on bad times, whereas there was more chance All that this analysis shows is that, on certain psychological assumptions,
of avoiding the double loss by placing their savings elsewhere'. G. D. H. Cole, A Century of a mixed system of ownership may produce the highest level of net investment.
Co-operation (Manchester: Co-operative Union, 1945).
It does not show that this level of investment can match that achieved by the
'" Nowadays professional partnerships such as those formed by solicitors may loan incoming
members the purchase price of a share, to be repaid out of income over a set period. But these are co-operative's capitalist rivals who ought, according to the foregoing argument,
low capital-high income enterprises, and it is difficult to envisage such an arrangement being adopted to be willing to invest at least as much as the co-operative does at D without
throughout industry generally. the accompanying withdrawal effect, and therefore have a net investment of at
22 For evidence of the latter effect, see D. C. Jones, 'The Economic and Industrial Relations of least OF, compared with the co-operative's maximum of OE (when it has its
American Producer Co-operatives, 1791-1939', Economic Analysis and Workers' Management, xi
optimum structure of ownership at C). No system of ownership which does not
(1977), 295-317.
2: E.g. Oakeshott, The Case /6r Workers' Co-ops, pp. 32-4, 82-4, 190-4; 'Piecemeal' in Clayre,
involve the co-operative degenerating into a joint-stock company can avoid this
ed., The Political Economy of Co-operation and Participation. result.
Market Neutrality and the Failure of Co-operatives 319 320 MILLER

A third possible way of dealing with the investment problem is to have the any bank, not influenced by ideological considerations but pursuing a wealth-
co-operative financed externally. The co-operative would borrow all of its maximizing goal itself, lend to a co-operative when it can lend instead to
capital from a bank, say, and pay interest on its borrowings. At first sight this capitalist firms? The bank's agents can see that the co-operators have no
seems to solve the difficulties we have been considering, for the co-operative incentive to repay their borrowings; they can predict that the co-operative will
would invest whenever the expected return exceeded the rate of interest, and either have to borrow ever-increasing sums, or else be outperformed by the
there would be no problem created by members withdrawing their assets. This competition and go bankrupt. Neither prospect is attractive; the bankruptcy of
solution may indeed be the best where it can be achieved: the question is whether a firm collectively or jointly owned by a large number of individuals would be
it is a viable solution in an environment dominated by capitalist enterprises.24 a banker's nightmare. Indeed, a rational banker would only lend to a co-operative
The question can be examined from two points of view: that of the co-operative if he could impose conditions on the loan such that the co-operative was forced
and that of the lending agency. From the co-operative's point of view, repaying to behave in a way analogous to a capitalist firm. (This kind of solution to the
the loan will be equivalent to investing in capital, in the sense that once the loan problems of co-operatives is considered in general terms later.) But why go to
is repaid assets of a certain value will be held collectively. In the light of the this trouble if he can lend to a capitalist without it? Let me reiterate that this
argument so far, it will be seen that members will resist any such repayment consequence follows directly from the bank's attending to its own self-interest,
unless the yield from their investment is unusually large. The likely outcome is not from any wish on the part of bankers to suppress co-operatives or 'preserve
that the co-operative will borrow as much as it can from the bank and repay the capitalist system'. Co-operatives are simply a bad investment from the bank's
as little as possible.25 It therefore faces two problems. One is that it becomes point of view.
particularly vulnerable to year-by-year fluctuations in profit, having no reserves We have seen that there is no really satisfactory solution to the co-operatives'
to draw on in lean years, on the reasonable assumption that bank credit has an investment problem. Each possibility we have examined - collectivized assets,
upper limit.26 On the same assumption, secondly, investment ceases (in normal individualized assets, external financing - has serious drawbacks. The likely
cases) when the ceiling is reached. So finite credit really only masks the basic result is that co-operatives will be unwilling to invest as heavily as capitalist
weakness of the co-operative structure, namely the reluctance of income- enterprises, and will therefore be unable to compete in an open market whenever
maximizing co-operators to invest in collective assets. Of course the masking investment is needed to maintain technological advance. It does not of course
might be effective for a considerable time, depending on the size of the follow that every co-operative will fail immediately. For one thing, competition
credit. is never perfect, and for another a co-operative may be able to achieve higher
Consider now the question from the point of view of the bank. Why should levels of productivity than its capitalist rivals, given its members' more direct
interest in profit maximization.27 Our analysis shows that, other things being
equal, the chances of a co-operative's surviving in competition with capitalists
24 See Jaroslav Vanek, 'The Basic Theory of Financing of Participatory Firms' in Jaroslav
will increase to the extent that three conditions are fulfilled. First, it should
Vanek, ed., Self-management. Economic Liberation of Man (Harmondsworth, Middx.: Penguin,
1975). belong to an industry where small-scale production is technically efficient, since
2:5 Empirical support for this proposition comes from labour-managed enterprises in Yugoslavia, resistance to expansion will then be less important, and the motivational
which when not required by the government to re-invest a fixed percentage of their earnings have advantages of the co-operative form will be at their strongest. Secondly, it should
chosen to finance themselves almost entirely by bank credit. See E. G. Furubotn and S. Pejovich, belong to an industry requiring labour-intensive methods of production, so that
'Property Rights, Economic Decentralization and the Evolution of the Yugoslav Firm, 1965-72',
Journal of Law and Economics, xvI (1973), 275-302; and S. Pejovich, 'The Banking System and the
the capital-labour ratio is kept as low as possible. Thirdly, it should belong to
Investment Behaviour of the Yugoslav Firm', in M. Bornstein, ed., Plan and Market (New Haven: an industry where technological change is slow or non-existent, so that high
Yale University Press, 1973). levels of reinvestment are unnecessary. It is interesting in this connection to note
26 To avoid this difficulty it has been suggested that the co-operative should finance itself by that the longest-lasting British 'co-operatives' (as we have seen, their ownership
issuing equity, paying dividends that reflected profits in any year rather than a fixed interest charge. structure prevents them being regarded strictly as co-operatives) are firms in the
See Peter Jay,' The Workers' Co-operative Economy' reprinted in Clayre, ed., The Political Economy
printing, footwear and clothing industries which have managed to survive
of Co-operation and Participation. But since on this scheme shareholders would have no voting rights
in the co-operative, it is difficult to believe that it would seem an attractive channel for investment without growing and without much technological innovation. Research on the
if other channels were available. No dividend would be guaranteed, and indeed the only incentive footwear industry has shown that the 'co-operatives' in the industry are in
for the co-operative to pay one at all would be a wish to maintain the market value of its equity. general both smaller in size than the capitalist firms, employ less capital per
Meade has proposed that enterprises might instead take the form of' Capital-Labour Partnerships'
in which both suppliers of capital and workers have voting shares. See J. E. Meade, 'Labour
Co-operatives, Participation, and Value-Added Sharing' in Clayre, ed., The Political Economy of 27 In a co-operative of several hundred people, the link between any one individual's efforts and
Co-operation and Participation. This proposal clearly makes investment in the enterprise more the share of profits he receives is of course fairly slight. But at the same time each has an interest
attractive, but equally clearly does so at the cost of losing the co-operative form and moving half-way in seeing that others work hard and produce efficiently, so each will contribute to formal and
towards a joint-stock arrangement. informal methods of penalizing slackers and eliminating waste.
Market NeutralitY and the Failure of Co-operatives 32I 322 MILLER

worker, and have (over the post-war period) invested less capital per worker.28 If its members regard survival as their only goal,31 they will respond to their
Yet the nature of the industry is such that some of these enterprises have survived position in a capitalist market by following capitalist investment patterns, thus
for almost a century. One is said to specialize in 'good, stout walking shoes ensuring ceteris paribus that they remain in the competition. To dramatize this
for middle-aged and older women in which, apparently, fashions change but idea, imagine that they borrow the services of an entrepreneur and ask him how
slowly'.29 These cases aside, the pursuit of income-maximization by co-operators he would act in each contingency as it arises, supposing that he owned the firm's
leads to one of two unintended outcomes: competitive failure through under- capital. At the same time they bind themselves to accept his recommendations,
investment, or degeneration into a capitalist mode of organization. irrespective of the effect on their own incomes. In this way they can escape the
underinvestment trap which dogged them throughout the discussion in the
previous section of this paper.
CO-OPERATIVES WITH NON-ECONOMIC GOALS
This solution, however, quickly reveals its absurdity. Survival was valued for
The unpromising results we have so far obtained depend on the assumption that its non-monetary benefits, but the conditions we have just imposed exclude most
co-operators are interested solely in maximizing their personal incomes. This of those benefits. Decisions about investment cannot be isolated from decisions
may seem an excessive simplification. After all, the point of forming co-operatives about hiring and firing, methods of production and so forth, so that the only
is not only to avoid the depredations of capitalists but to enjoy certain issues left for the assembled co-operators to resolve are those that have no
non-monetary benefits: first and foremost control of the workplace by the bearing on the economics of the firm. Everything else is settled by the hired
producers themselves, but flowing from this a greater range of possibilities in entrepreneur. Participation is devalued because it is restricted to relatively trivial
organizing production. Among such secondary goods might be more varied questions that an enlightened capitalist would allow his workforce to decide in
work, greater individual responsibility for the results of work, and a new balance any case. This result does not of course depend on the actual presence of a
between work and leisure (more flexible hours, more holidays for those who want surrogate capitalist making recommendations accepted as binding; that is merely
them, etc.). Although some of these benefits might be provided by a progressive a dramatic device. It follows from the co-operative's decision to respond to the
entrepreneur or manager, their presence can only be guaranteed by democratic constraints of a capitalist market by behaving as a capitalist itself. Even if the
control of the workplace, and so industrial democracy takes on a twofold value. self-binding took the impersonal form of a set of constitutional rules requiring
It is valued intrinsically, since active involvement in making decisions is the co-operators to invest, produce, etc. in a specified manner, the power of the
satisfying, and moreover develops qualities of character and intellect,30 and it co-operative to determine its own manner of operation has been seriously
is valued instrumentally, for the desirable outcomes it renders possible. eroded.32
Now if co-operators are interested in these non-financial aspects of industrial Besides being self-defeating in the sense just explained, the extreme solution
democracy, then of course they have an interest in the survival of their co-operative, also rests on an implausible premise, namely that survival is now the only goal
this being the condition for enjoying the non-monetary benefits in security. valued by the co-operators. A more realistic assumption is that survival is valued
Nozick relies on this idea when he argues that co-operatives should be able to alongside other benefits, both monetary and non-monetary, and that the
survive by their members taking lower money incomes, the loss being compensated co-operators will therefore adopt a strategy which aims at survival but not at
by the non-monetary rewards. This, however, only deals with the effects on the expense of everything else. So, for instance, they may reinvest rather more
productivity of workers' control and its results (e.g. the fact that more varied of their profits than would be required by a policy of maximizing income per
work might be less efficient in terms of output). It does not attack the dynamic worker, but less than would be required by a wealth-maximizing policy, giving
problems we have been examining, particularly that of investment. How would themselves some leeway (by comparison to a capitalist firm) for distributing extra
a co-operative which values survival over and above its monetary rewards benefits either in monetary or non-monetary form. In other words whereas a
approach the investment decision? capitalist will pursue an aggressive investment strategy (investing whenever the
One extreme possibility is that it might decide to simulate capitalist behaviour. return is positive), the co-operative will adopt a defensive strategy, investing
whenever it judges that not to do so would seriously reduce its chances of
2s D. C. Jones and D. K. Backus, 'British Producer Co-operatives in the Footwear Industry: An
Empirical Evaluation of the Theory of Financing', Economic Journal, LXXXVII (I977), 488-510.
Similar evidence of under-capitalization has been found in the case of French co-operatives (mainly 31 There are in fact two ways in which this goal might be interpreted: as survival per se, and as
in the building industry). See Eric Batstone, 'Some Aspects of the Economic Performance of French survival during the lifetimes of the members. The appropriate interpretation will depend on whether

Producer Co-operatives', unpublished paper delivered to the Walton Symposium, Glasgow, 1979. the co-operators' non-monetary desires are altruistic or egoistic in nature.
32 It is difficult to conceive how such a constitution might be formulated. A rigid set of rules
29 Oakeshott, The Case for Workers' Co-ops, p. 67.
30 As argued, for instance, by J. S. Mill in the second chapter of Considerations on Representative would hamper any co-operative operating in an uncertain and fluctuating market. If, for instance,
it were a requirement that the co-operators should reinvest a certain percentage of their profits each
Government in J. S. Mill, Utilitarianism; On Libert'y; Considerations on Representative Government
(London: Dent, I9IO). For the extension of this argument to industrial participation, see Carole year, this would disadvantage the co-operative in relation to a capitalist who was free to adjust his
rate of investment to his estimate of market trends.
Pateman, Participation and Democratic Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970).
Market Neutrality and the Failure of Co-operatives 323 324 MILLER

survival. Whether this strategy collapses into the former depends of course on system to a co-operative system, even though the latter is the system preferred
whether the co-operative is competing in the market with aggressive capitalist by all workers.
firms. The moral of the Prisoner's Dilemma is that both parties should seek a way
We are driven again to the conclusion that the survival of co-operatives of binding one another to reach the preferred outcome. In the present case, the
depends on contingent factors such as the existence of an enclave within which moral is that workers with preferences as described should use political means
competition is muted, and in which the mixed strategy I have outlined can to convert the capitalist market into a co-operative market. The state must be
therefore be followed successfully. It can, however, be said confidently that a used to transform the ownership structure of private firms into the co-operative
market containing both capitalist firms and co-operatives is not in stable form. Whether it need then continue to operate depends on whether we have a
equilibrium. In the long term the capitalists will always tend to drive out the strict Prisoner's Dilemma (i.e. whether workers will revert to the capitalist form
co-operators. It remains to consider the political implications of this result. once given the opportunity) or an assurance game. In the latter case the state
might wither away once the transformation was complete. It seems more
realistic, however, to suppose that at least some workers will be tempted to take
THE TRANSITION TO A CO-OPERATIVE ECONOMY
the capitalist road in a co-operative environment (i.e. have x > I), in which case
I suggested earlier that the problem of co-operatives producing in an open degeneration will set in. So the state must continue to enforce the co-operative
market might be illuminated by the Prisoner's Dilemma model. To see how this form, or in Nozick's words forbid capitalist acts between consenting adults.
model applies, suppose that the workers in a given population value both the My aim has been to show that the market is not necessarily an efficient means
increased income and the non-material benefits promised by the co-operative of satisfying preferences. Rather than being a neutral device, it discriminates
form of organization. Faced with a choice between working for a co-operative against certain preferences, such as those for co-operative modes of organization.
in competition with other co-operatives and working for a capitalist firm in Even if everyone has these preferences, they may still arrive at a sub-optimal
competition with other capitalist firms, all would choose the former option. On outcome by following market mechanisms. The argument about the economics
the other hand the option of working for a co-operative in competition with of co-operatives is designed to show this. The upshot is that enforced market
capitalists is less attractive than either of these, since the short-term benefits of socialism (enforced in the sense that capitalist relations are forbidden, not in the
co-operation are heavily outweighed by the insecurity of their employment - the sense that it is imposed upon an unwilling population) may be the system which
workers in question having grasped the argument that co-operatives are unlikely satisfies desires most efficiently.
to survive in a capitalist environment. For safety's sake they prefer to work for Suppose now that instead of all workers preferring co-operative production
a capitalist in such circumstances. These preferences may be expressed by the to capitalist production, only part of the workforce have such a preference.The
values in the following table. optimum arrangement will plainly be one in which those who prefer to work
Other firms in co-operatives can do so, and likewise those who prefer to work for capitalists.
Co-operative Capitalist We have seen that this arrangement cannot be achieved by market mechanisms
alone. We again require the state, but this time to perform the role of sheltering
Co-operative I -I the co-operative sector from its capitalist environment. It can do this, very
Our firm broadly, either by hindering the growth of capitalist firms (say by imposing a
Capitalist x o wealth tax upon them) or by encouraging the co-operatives (say by providing
investment capital on favourable terms). This rigging of the market would
We have still to give a value to x - the option of working for a capitalist in an depend upon a political decision that preferences for the co-operative form
environment of co-operative enterprises. Opportunistic workers will see that this should be respected, and one can imagine a consensus emerging on this issue
puts them in a strong long-term position, a consideration which may outweigh which included those who chose to work for capitalist firms themselves.
the benefits of co-operation. If so we have x > I and the game takes the form The possibilities here are illustrated by the Mondragon group of co-operatives
of an n-person Prisoner's Dilemma; in this case workers will opt for a capitalist recently discussed by Robert Oakeshott.33 The success of this group, in contrast
mode of organization whatever they expect other workers to do. If, on the other to the largely dismal record of co-operatives elsewhere, appears to depend on
hand, workers rate the benefits of co-operation more highly than the material several connected factors. First, the co-operatives are physically concentrated
chances offered to those who strike out first along the capitalist road, we have in one geographical area (in the Basque region of Spain). Secondly, the number
x < I and an 'assurance game'. In this case workers will opt for the co-operative of co-operatives is quite large (eighty-two at the last count) and each co-operative
system if and only if they expect other workers to do likewise. In the second supports the others by, in particular, providing a market for its products.
case but not the first, a market composed entirely of co-operatives will be a stable
33 Oakeshott, The Case for Workers' Co-ops, Chap. 1o.
system; but in neither case can there be a spontaneous transition from a capitalist
Market Neutrality and the Failure of Co-operatives 325 326 MILLER

equal, a discriminatory intervention such as that described will reduce the over-all
Thirdly, a 'people's bank' supplies both investment capital and expert advice
amount of satisfaction obtained: the net loss to the grape-lovers is likely to
about the setting up and running of each co-operative. This factor is perhaps
outweigh the net gain to the potato-lovers.
the most crucial, for the bank is not merely in business to make money, but is
It has often been observed that both claims fail when desires for public goods
ideologically committed to fostering co-operative enterprises. It can therefore
are in question. Because public goods are, by definition, goods which cannot
act as an external constraint on the behaviour of the co-operatives, requiring
be made available to one person without being made available to large numbers
them for instance to adopt a particular structure of ownership and to follow
of others, it will rarely be possible to produce and sell them through the market
approved financial practices.
mechanism.34 Even if private production is possible, no consumer will be willing
This particular 'sheltered' environment depends on regional solidarity, which
to pay the cost of production himself, since by refusing he may hope to enjoy
led to the establishment of the bank in the first place and which ensures a regular
the good at someone else's expense. Consequently under a pure market regime
flow of funds into its reserves. It could therefore not be reproduced generally.
public goods are underproduced, and those in whose desire-schedule such goods
One can see, however, roughly what ingredients are needed to make a co-operative
feature prominently are discriminated against. Libertarians have responded to
enclave successful. The Mondragon group depends partly on the people's bank
this charge by looking for ways in which ostensibly public goods can be
behaving non-capitalistically, and partly on its being able to induce the
converted into private goods and so provided through the market.35
co-operatives to behave more capitalistically than they otherwise might. These
The examples which figure in this debate are mainly goods which for physical
ingredients could be provided by a Co-operative Enterprise Board whose brief
reasons have the property of being public, although the satisfaction that they
was to encourage the founding of new co-operatives, supply them with funds
and offer financial guidance. The point to be stressed is that such a Board could provide is itself private. Clean air is a public good because it is impossible to
only be a political creation, reflecting a public consensus that those whose separate the air you breathe from the air I breathe, but on the other hand the
act of breathing itself and the enjoyment it brings have no essential connection
preference is to work in co-operatives should be given the opportunity to do so.
with what anyone else does. Equally a public park must be provided for everyone
Market mechanisms alone would not produce such an institution.
if it is provided for anyone, but the actual satisfaction to be gained from visiting
the park is a private matter (I ignore such problems as crowding). Because of
LIBERTARIANISM, MARKET NEUTRALITY AND THE SATISFACTION this feature, the goods in question are only contingently public, and the debate
OF DESIRES
about their possible privatization hinges on technical questions (Can air-polluters
The argument offered here to show that co-operatives are likely to fail in market be identified? Can park-users be charged?). But other goods are necessarily
competition unless given political protection has important practical implications public, because they meet desires which are interpersonal in nature. If I gain
for those committed to fostering co-operative production; but it also illuminates satisfaction from living in a society which has certain over-all features, this good
in a broader way the shortcomings of libertarianism as a political philosophy. necessarily cannot be provided for me without simultaneously being provided
The specific libertarian assumption which the argument challenges is that a free for everyone else. Here there is no question of'privatizing' the public good, and
market is a neutral and efficient mechanism for satisfying desires. A 'free market' if the market fails to provide such goods its failure is irremediable.
here means inter alia one whose ground rules permit capitalistic forms of To make this more exact, let me distinguish private desires, group-oriented
association. The claims made for the neutrality and efficiency of such a market desires and social desires. Private desires are desires for states of affairs which

are analytically distinct but none the less closely related. The market is neutral involve no essential reference to other persons, whether the desire to eat grapes
because it responds to desires of various kinds in an even-handed manner. The or to breathe clean air. Group-oriented desires are desires for states of affairs
extent to which any person is capable of satisfying one of his desires depends involving at least one other person (but excluding over-all social states).
only on his purchasing power and the (naturally-determined) cost of producing Examples include the desire to enjoy a more equal relationship with one's
the object of satisfaction. If, by contrast, there were to be political intervention partner, to participate in making collective decisions, or to live in a Christian
in the market, in the form (say) of a tax on some commodities whose proceeds community. Finally, and as a separate category, there are social desires, where
the desired state of affairs is an over-all social state. Included here are the desire
were used to subsidize the price of others, this would discriminate against those
whose optimum bundle of commodities under given purchasing-power to live in an egalitarian society, or to live in a society composed exclusively of
constraints included relatively more of the tax-liable items. If grapes are taxed orthodox Muslims. These categories are analytically distinct, although actual
to subsidize potatoes, grape-lovers suffer at the expense of potato-lovers. The desires may be composites, involving elements from more than one class - for
fairness at stake here is likely to be particularly important to libertarians, instance, the desire to drink a glass of beer with one's friends.
because they eschew substantive ideals of social justice (applying, for instance,
to the distribution of income). Moreover the claim about market neutrality is 34 For a recent general discussion, see M. Laver, 'Political Solutions to the Collective Action
Problem', Political Studies, xxvIII (1980), 195-209.
linked to a claim about efficiency by the observation that, other things being
35 See, for example, Friedman, The Machinery of Freedom, especially Chaps. 26, 34, 39.
Market Neutrality and the Failure of Co-operatives 327 328 MILLER

Social desires plainly pose the greatest difficulties for the libertarian. The increasing consumption at the expense of increasing leisure. The form of the
objects of these desires will often have the properties of public goods. I may wish argument in each case is that the market operates to reward those who conform
to live in an egalitarian society, but be unwilling to act in the way that such a to the favoured model while penalizing those who depart from it.
state would require (for example, abstaining from increasing my income above To show that this is a serious source of market inefficiency, two further theses
the mean) unless others are obliged to do likewise. Goods of this kind cannot must be defended. The first is that the group-oriented desires against which the
be' privatized': there is no conceivable way in which I can pay to have 'equality' free market discriminates are as a matter of fact important desires felt by a
supplied to me privately. Consequently libertarians tend to react to social desires considerable number of people. The truth of this thesis may seem obvious, but
in one of two ways: either they try to eliminate such desires from political in any case I shall not try to defend it here.38 The second thesis is that there exists
consideration by arguing that they are intrinsically impossible to satisfy, or they some more efficient means of satisfying those group-oriented desires which the
try to reduce them to group-oriented desires, and then claim that satisfaction market fails to satisfy. This deserves a brief examination.
may be obtained on a small scale, through the combination of a like-minded A large-scale change in the pattern of desire-satisfaction must of necessity be
group of people. Nozick, for example, dismisses the desire for equality on the brought about by political means. The new pattern is chosen by a decision-making
grounds that if men are made equal along any dimension which is currently procedure and then implemented. Libertarians tend to view this process in a
thought to give rise to objectionable inequalities (wealth, for instance), some stereotyped way: the decision procedure is (at best) simple majoritarianism, and
other dimension or dimensions on which men score differently will come to implementation takes the form of prohibiting certain activities which were
assume the importance the first dimension once had. Thus the quest for equality permitted under the previous set of market rules. Thus politics is seen as a
is doomed to perpetual frustration; by implication there is no point in process whereby the majority imposes its preferences on the unwilling minority.
undertaking the quest in the first place.36 On the other hand he responds to such Even on this view political methods may sometimes achieve desirable results
desires as those for fraternity and authority by arguing that in a libertarian which the market itself cannot. If the majority comes to prefer driving on the
society individuals are free to band together in communities whose internal right to driving on the left, there is everything to be said for a political edict
relations are fraternal, authoritarian or whatever they wish. The implication in which makes driving on the right compulsory. But the simple model of politics
this case is that social desires are reducible without loss to group-oriented ones. is less likely to be appropriate where group-oriented desires are involved. Either
Anyone who claims that he wants to live in a fraternal society, not merely a there will be no majority for the policy which allows these desires an adequate
fraternal group, is ruled out of court.37 chance of satisfaction, or the policy adopted will be oppressive to the minority
Neither of these moves seems to me particularly convincing. But even if we which does not share them. We need therefore to recall that political decisions
choose to ignore irreducible social desires, and accept that other social desires need not be mandatory in nature: they need not prohibit activities or modes of
are reducible to their group-oriented analogues, we may still ask whether the association. They may simply facilitate alternative modes of association, or
free market responds in a neutral fashion to group-oriented desires, a question change the financial terms on which different institutions compete in the market.
that now becomes doubly important. It may be true that a libertarian society In the discussion of co-operatives we saw that, in cases where the distribution
will not prohibit any particular pattern of association; in theory people can of preferences makes compulsory market socialism inappropriate, the state
arrange their micro-environment in any way that they see fit. There may none might act as the sponsor of a minority co-operative sector. We should also recall
the less be a systemic bias in favour of some types of association and against that political processes need not follow the logic of simple majoritarianism.
others. If that is so, the market mechanism cannot be regarded as a neutral Given communication between voters, intense minorities on several issues may
device, and its efficiency in satisfying desires will be called in question. agree to support one another against their respective majorities. In a society
The argument about co-operatives points strongly to this conclusion. Co- where many minorities have important group-oriented desires that can only be
operatives may be chosen partly to satisfy private desires (income-maximization) satisfied politically, a bargain may be struck whereby each group is awarded
and partly to satisfy group-oriented desires (such as equality at work and political backing for its own project. Of course, as libertarians will be quick to
participation). If a free market dominated by capitalist firms makes co-operative point out, the cost of such support must be met through taxation, and therefore
failure likely, group-oriented desires of this kind will remain unsatisfied. The through reducing each person's capacity to meet desires of other kinds. The
market discriminates in favour of those who prefer the authority structure of result may none the less be efficient (more desires being satisfied on balance) just
the capitalist firm, whether as givers or receivers of commands. Similar as taxation to provide public goods of the more familiar kind may be efficient
arguments might be developed to show that a capitalist market favours nuclear Faced with this challenge, libertarians may abandon the attempt to defend
families at the expense of other modes of domestic life, and that it favours an unfettered market in terms of efficiency and rely instead on the claim that

:i Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia, pp. 232-46. 38 For some evidence in the particular case of the desire for participation at work, see H. Ramsay,
:7 Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia, Chap. Io passim. 'Participation: The Shop Floor View', British Journal of Industrial Relations, xIv (I976), I28-41.
Market Neutrality and the Failure of Co-operatives 329

only a market order is compatible with individuals' property rights, or on the


claim that only such an order preserves personal freedom, or both. They might,
in other words, defend the market on the grounds of justice or liberty, while
conceding that the protection of these values may involve some sacrifice of
efficiency. In the particular case in question, a libertarian might concede that
preferences for co-operative production could not be satisfied in an open market,
but claim none the less that the only means available for satisfying them - state
sponsorship supported by (non-voluntary) taxation - necessarily abridged pro-
perty rights or diminished freedom. These defences rely on controversial
accounts of the values in question (justice and liberty) and seem no stronger than
the vindication of the market discussed here.39 In general, the enthusiasm with
which even natural rights libertarians such as Nozick press the argument for
the neutrality and efficiency of the market suggests that this defence is fairly
central to the libertarian case.

::' I have examined these two other pillars of libertarianism in 'Justice and Property', Ratio, XXII
(1980-I), I-I4, and 'Constraints on Freedom', Ethics (forthcoming).

You might also like