You are on page 1of 4

AJOB NEUROSCIENCE 25

ORCID Racine, E. 2010. Pragmatic neuroethics: Improving treatment


and understanding of the mind-brain. London: MIT
Walter Veit http://orcid.org/0000-0001-7701-8995 Press.
Heather Browning http://orcid.org/0000-0003-1554-7052 Veit, W. 2018a. Procreative beneficence and genetic
enhancement. KRITERION 32 (1):75–92. doi:10.13140/
RG.2.2.11026.89289.
REFERENCES Veit, W. 2018b. Enhancement technologies and inequality.
Birch, J., and H. Browning. 2021. Neural organoids and the In Proceedings of the IX Conference of the Spanish Society
precautionary principle. The American Journal of of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, ed. C.
Bioethics 21 (1):56–8. doi:10.1080/15265161.2020.1845858. Saborido, S. Oms, and J. Gonzalez de Prado, 471–476.
Dubljević, V., K. Trettenbach, and R. Ranisch. 2022. The doi:10.13140/RG.2.2.21932.08326.
socio-political roles of neuroethics and the case of klotho. Veit, W. 2018c. Cognitive enhancement and the threat of
AJOB Neuroscience 13 (1):10–22. doi:10.1080/21507740. inequality. Journal of Cognitive Enhancement 2 (4):
2021.1896597. 404–10. doi:10.1007/s41465-018-0108-x.
Farah, M. J. 2012. Neuroethics: The ethical, legal, and societal Veit, W., and H. Browning. 2020. Why socio-political
impact of neuroscience. Annual Review of Psychology 63: beliefs trump individual morality: An evolutionary per-
571–91. doi:10.1146/annurev.psych.093008.100438. spective. AJOB Neuroscience 11 (4):290–2. doi:10.1080/
Fitz, N. S., R. Nadler, P. Manogaran, E. W. Chong, and 21507740.2020.1830879.
P. B. Reiner. 2014. Public attitudes toward cognitive Veit, W., B. D. Earp, N. Faber, N. Bostrom, J. Caouette, A.
enhancement. Neuroethics 7 (2):173–88. doi:10.1007/ Mannino, L. Caviola, A. Sandberg, and J. Savulescu.
s12152-013-9190-z. 2020. Recognizing the diversity of cognitive enhance-
Levy, N. 2007. Neuroethics: Challenges for the 21st century. ments. AJOB Neuroscience 11 (4):250–3. doi:10.1080/
London, UK: Cambridge University Press. 21507740.2020.1830878.

AJOB NEUROSCIENCE
2021, VOL. 13, NO. 1, 25–28
https://doi.org/10.1080/21507740.2021.2001082

OPEN PEER COMMENTARIES

Continuums of Capacity, Binaries of Guilt: The Sociopolitical Role of


Neuroethics in Criminal Justice
Stacy S. Chena , Liam G. McCoya , Samuel Forsterb, Connor T. A. Brennaa , Nir Lipsmana, and Sunit
Dasa
a
University of Toronto; bIndependent Researcher

In 1966, Charles Whitman (the “Texas Tower If Whitman had been captured alive, and the mass
Sniper”) murdered his own wife and mother before discovered on an imaging study of his brain, would
mounting a University of Texas tower to shoot indis- this finding have affected determinations of his cap-
criminately at passersby until he was killed by police acity for criminal responsibility?
during the resulting shootout. It was, at the time, the As Dubljevic, Trettenbach, and Ranisch describe in
deadliest mass murder in the United States (Eagleman “The socio-political roles of Neuroethics and the case
2011). Whitman had previously sought help for inva- of Klotho,” the development of neuroethics calls for
sive, violent fantasies and impulsive violent behavior recognition of the discipline’s socio-political perspec-
and, in fact, even wrote a note requesting an autopsy tive owing to its capacity to offer insights on the intri-
be performed to search for anomalies in his brain cate relationship between the brain and human
(Eagleman 2011). The autopsy revealed a small tumor behavior (Dubljevic et al. 2022). This relationship
compressing his amygdala, a structure charged with inextricably implicates neuroscience in human agency
emotional and behavioral regulation (Eagleman 2011). and responsibility and entangles neuroscience with the

CONTACT Stacy S. Chen stacysi.chen@mail.utoronto.ca University of Toronto, 170 St George St, Toronto, ON M5R 2M8, Canada.
†co-first authorship.
ß 2021 Taylor & Francis Group, LLC
26 OPEN PEER COMMENTARIES

legal sphere of the socio-political arena. Drawing on THE POSSIBILITIES AND PITFALLS OF
the political philosophy of John Rawls, the authors NEUROTECHNOLOGIES
delineate a novel role for neuroethics in guiding
Modern neurotechnology has allowed for increasing
ongoing developments in neurotechnology (Dubljevic identification of minute structural and functional
et al. 2022). We extend this role to the emerging dis- changes in the brain, holding promise of providing
cipline of neurocriminology, in which determinations insight into the determinants of human behavior. The
of capacity for criminal responsibility have com- nascent field of neurocriminology seeks to turn these
pounding and consequential normative social technologies toward questions of crime and its neuro-
implications. biological determinants. As seminal research in the
field indicates, “rule-breaking behaviour common to
THE BINARISATION OF CAPACITY FOR antisocial, violent and psychopathic individuals is in
part due to impairments in some [neural] structures
CRIMINAL RESPONSIBILITY
(dorsal and ventral PFC, amygdala and angular
Within contemporary common law criminal justice gyrus)” (Raine and Yang 2006). Further studies have
structures, while sentencing demonstrates a consider- demonstrated the presence of a brain network for
able gradient of punishments, it is exercised only in moral decision-making, including regions involved in
response to a delimited, binary determination of guilt. empathy, value judgment, theory of mind, and deci-
This determination of guilt is, itself, dependent upon sion-making (Darby et al. 2018). Disruption to this
a binary assessment of capacity for criminal responsi- network through acquired lesions such as tumors or
bility, which is reflected in the language surrounding strokes is heavily associated with sociopathic, impul-
a major legal defense strategy that questions the cap- sive, and/or criminal behavior (Darby et al. 2018).
acity of the accused: one may only be found not guilty Some neuroscientists in the materialist tradition
by reason of insanity under the Texas Penal Code if, regard this increasing scientific clarity as reason to
“as a result of severe mental disease or defect, [he] question the doctrine of free will itself (Lavazza 2016).
did not know that his conduct was wrong” (General Others put forth a conception of agency informed by
Principles of Criminal Responsibility. Texas Penal complex interactions between brain and environment,
Code. § 8-8.01). There is no room to account for par- and regard capacity as existing on an imprecise multi-
tial moral knowledge or reasoning—one cannot be factorial continuum influenced by variance in neuro-
found, for example, to be 27% guilty, 99% insane, or chemistry and neural circuitry. Answers with respect
72% capable of criminal responsibility. to capacity for criminal responsibility seem clear at
This binary assessment of capacity demanded by the extremes of this continuum—for example some-
the criminal justice system exists in contrast to—and one striking a bystander while having a seizure could
not be considered capable of criminal responsibility
in tension with—the continuum of neurological func-
for such an action. Challenges arise, however, in
tion. Determinations of capacity often hinge upon the
attempting to assert clear binary thresholds between
diagnosis of a forensic psychiatrist—despite the field’s
capacity and incapacity.
clear professional consensus that psychiatric diagnoses
While neuroscience can provide increasingly
are imperfect and rely on generalized labels for condi-
robust, replicable descriptions of brain functions rele-
tions that are dynamic and spectral (Hengartner and
vant to criminal responsibility, it cannot “objectively”
Lehmann 2017). Further, the binary of insanity prescribe the location of the threshold between cap-
embedded in the law is rendered incomplete by the acity and incapacity. Neurotechnology may be able to
complexity of overlapping neurological processes effectively subcategorize an individual’s, such as
underlying human behavior. Consider, for example, Whitman’s, cognitive ability to comprehend, and
an individual (analogous to Whitman) who may be appropriately respond to, morally relevant informa-
neurobiologically incapable of inhibiting impulsive tion. Assessment of the level of functional deterior-
violent actions despite knowing that his conduct is ation at which one deems the individual incapable,
“wrong.” Such a case was documented in 2003, when however, fundamentally embeds values, and in doing
a 40-year-old man with a right orbitofrontal tumor so engages with domains beyond the realm of neuro-
developed adult-onset pedophilia and an inability to science. In other words, this assessment and determin-
“inhibit sexual urges despite preserved moral knowl- ation of a threshold level of “capability” takes what is
edge,” which resolved entirely following tumor resec- objective (the functional deterioration) and entails a
tion (Burns and Swerdlow 2003). subjective judgment of whether it is moral and just to
AJOB NEUROSCIENCE 27

deem an individual with such character- sociopolitical moral structures that take into account
istics incapable. the emerging insights of neuroscience into account.
Further, we must recognize the limitations inherent Neurocriminological determinations made by
in utilizing neurotechnological outputs as the primary forensic psychiatrist such as “capacity” are ultimately
determinant of capacity for criminal responsibility. value-laden because the very concept of “capacity for
While the perspective neurocriminology provides is of criminal responsibility” embeds values. At the individ-
relevance to the pursuit of criminal justice, it is funda- ual level, a forensic psychiatrist’s labeling of an
mentally insufficient without an understanding of the accused as “capable” embeds preconceived notions of
accused’s broader personal and sociopolitical context their responsibility and therefore their guilt, and thus,
(Fallin, Whooley, and Barker 2019). Returning to the these labels must be applied cautiously and with a
case of Whitman, we see that knowledge of the conscious recognition of their weight. At the broader
tumor’s presence and location can and must inform a societal level, decisions regarding the identity of these
full account of his criminal capacity, but it cannot thresholds would have significant implications for the
comprise the account in its entirety. Nor can it pro- proportion of accused deemed capable in ambiguous
vide conclusive answers with respect to his capacity cases. Moreover, establishing these thresholds may
for criminal responsibility, regardless of the granular- enhance the reliability and impartiality of penal praxis
ity with which its neurological consequences might by reducing human approximation from the sentenc-
be assessed. ing process. To inform such decisions with the most
advanced and best-validated neurotechnology is essen-
tial; yet to cede these decisions to such technology
NEUROETHICS AS A GUIDING FORCE
altogether would be to abdicate moral responsibility
The nature of the interconnection between the brain and hide beneath the obscurant veil of scien-
and human agency provides neuroethics with an tific complexity.
expansive scope interacting, alongside neuroscience, The ability of neuroethics to highlight these
with numerous domains of human activity (McCoy embedded value judgements is crucial to our naviga-
et al. 2020). As Dubljevic and colleagues describe, tion of the nebulous continuums of objective neuro-
neuroethics has a critical role to play in situating neu- criminological data analysis and the discrete realities
rotechnology in its social and political context, and in of practical penal decision-making. Neuroethics must
guiding the ways in which neurotechnology is both act to inform both the development and deployment
developed and deployed. In the context of neurocrimi- of these neurotechnologies in order to ensure that
nology, this role is clearly manifest in the task of iden- they are able to guide the moral process of judging
tifying the value judgments inherent in translating capacity for criminal responsibility without supersed-
between data and labels of capacity. Neuroethics must ing it.
act to ensure that neurotechnology does not mischar-
acterize such judgments as “objective,” and in doing
FUNDING
so reduce complex and subjective moral decisions to
mere data-driven thresholds. The author(s) reported there is no funding associated with
At the same time, neuroethics has a role to play in the work featured in this article.
explicating insights from neuroscience and highlight-
ing the ways in which they may challenge preexisting ORCID
moral intuitions and sociopolitical structures. There Stacy S. Chen http://orcid.org/0000-0003-0827-5175
would be an evident absurdity in, for example, Liam G. McCoy http://orcid.org/0000-0002-4468-2256
attempting to robustly deem individuals with 35% Connor T. A. Brenna http://orcid.org/0000-0002-
reduction in blood flow to moral circuitry incapable, 6126-3897
Sunit Das http://orcid.org/0000-0002-2146-4168
while those with a 34% reduction remain fully cap-
able. Increasing understanding of the continuums of
human neurological function exists in inherent ten- REFERENCES
sion with the binary determinations that the criminal Burns, J. M., and R. H. Swerdlow. 2003. Right orbitofrontal
justice system, as currently constructed, is called upon tumor with pedophilia symptom and constructional
to make. Neuroethics must act to identify these ten- apraxia sign. Archives of Neurology 60 (3):437–40. doi:10.
sions and their implications, and to advocate for 1001/archneur.60.3.437.
28 OPEN PEER COMMENTARIES

Darby, R. R., A. Horn, F. Cushman, and M. D. Fox. 2018. Hengartner, M. P., and S. N. Lehmann. 2017. Why psychi-
Lesion network localization of criminal behavior. atric research must abandon traditional diagnostic classi-
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the fication and adopt a fully dimensional scope: Two
United States of America 115 (3):601–6. doi:10.1073/pnas. solutions to a persistent problem. Frontiers in Psychiatry
1706587115. 8:101. doi:10.3389/fpsyt.2017.00101.
Dubljevic, V., K. Trettenbach, and R. Ranisch. 2022. The Lavazza, A. 2016. Free will and neuroscience: From explain-
socio-political roles of Neuroethics and the case of ing freedom away to new ways of operationalizing and
Klotho. AJOB Neuroscience 13 (1):10–22. measuring it. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 10:262.
Eagleman, D. 2011. The brain on trial. The Atlantic 7: doi:10.3389/fnhum.2016.00262.
112–123. McCoy, L. G., C. Brenna, F. Morgado, S. Chen, and S. Das.
Fallin, M., O. Whooley, and K. K. Barker. 2019. 2020. Neuroethics, neuroscience, and the project of
Criminalizing the brain: Neurocriminology and the pro- human self-understanding. AJOB Neuroscience 11 (3):
duction of strategic ignorance. BioSocieties 14 (3):438–62. 207–9. doi:10.1080/21507740.2020.1778127.
doi:10.1057/s41292-018-0135-y. Raine, A., and Y. Yang. 2006. Neural foundations to moral
General Principles of Criminal Responsibility. Texas Penal reasoning and antisocial behavior. Social Cognitive and
Code. § 8-8.01 1994. https://statutes.capitol.texas.gov/ Affective Neuroscience 1 (3):203–13. doi:10.1093/scan/
Docs/PE/htm/PE.8.htm nsl033.

AJOB NEUROSCIENCE
2021, VOL. 13, NO. 1, 28–30
https://doi.org/10.1080/21507740.2021.2001091

OPEN PEER COMMENTARIES

Eugenic Technologies Are Developed in Eugenic Eras: Why We Must Include


Historical Circumstances in Socio-Political Perspectives for Neuroethics
Sara M. Bergstressera
Columbia University

While I applaud this article’s (Dubljevic et al. 2022) com- sterilization, and sometimes death. This eugenic dis-
pelling arguments for the inclusion of a socio-political course had many profound implications for technological
perspective as central to neuroethics, I argue here that development; suppressive technologies were destined to
they have not gone far enough. The historical circum- control supposed undesirables, and other technologies
stances of neurological developments are also an essential were designed as a means to counter the violent politics
part of understanding this socio-political perspective. In of the day.
addition, to understand the full socio-political context of Dubljevic et al. (2022) use the example of neurosci-
new technologies, it is also important to realize that every entist Jose M. R. Delgado, who developed a radio-con-
technology emerges in a particular time and place, where trolled brain implant meant for “Physical Control of
basic assumptions about humanity, the ideal society, gen- the Mind” in the mid-twentieth century. They point
etics, heredity, and desirable human characteristics may out that Delgado was sensitive to ethical issues that
starkly contrast with the prevailing attitudes that exist could arise from the use of his “mind control” tech-
today. The eugenic era, for example, did have particular nology, and he knew that regulation might eventually
political neurodiscourses that were consistent with the be needed. While this shows a forward-thinking atti-
prevailing political discourses, emphasizing a hierarchy tude from Delgado, it does not mean that the design
among people. Certain types of people, with their corre- and proposed usage of his technology were not funda-
sponding genes and brains, were seen as superior, and mentally shaped by the socio-political contexts of the
those deemed inferior, with their inferior genes and day, potentially in some ways understood and others
inferior brains, were subject to discrimination, unrecognized by the researchers involved.

CONTACT Sara M. Bergstresser SB2715@columbia.edu Columbia University, Program in Bioethics, 2970 Broadway, 504 Lewisohn Hall, New York,
NY10027, USA
ß 2021 Taylor & Francis Group, LLC

You might also like