You are on page 1of 11

Am J Community Psychol (2017) 59:284–294

DOI 10.1002/ajcp.12141

ORIGINAL ARTICLE

On the Historical and Conceptual Foundations of a Community


Psychology of Social Transformation
Ravi Gokani,1 and Richard T. G. Walsh2

© Society for Community Research and Action 2017

Abstract We examine historical and conceptual literature Since the earliest decades of this subdiscipline of psychol-
in community psychology in order to understand the field’s ogy, community psychologists have differentiated between
potential to be the socially transformative subdiscipline of changes affecting individuals and changes affecting social
psychology to which it aspires. By reviewing papers from systems, as captured by the terms first-order and second-
two prominent journals and other literature, we conclude order change, and ameliorative and transformative change
that the claim that community psychology is well-suited to (Prilleltensky & Nelson, 1997). First-order and ameliora-
social transformation, because it is a product of Sixties’ tive change denote what we term “social reform,” while
radicalism and is theoretically equipped, is untenable. second-order and transformative change denote what we
Systematic accounts of the subdiscipline’s origins suggest term “social transformation.” A politically progressive
that the transformative aspirations of current community shift toward social transformation has occurred over the
psychologists do not correspond to the subdiscipline’s last decades in the oral and written discourse of commu-
reformist past. Furthermore, in analyzing three related nity psychology. This discursive shift seems to imply that
concepts currently employed in the field—social justice, our subdiscipline has broader political implications and
power, and praxis—we show that each suffers from that some form of this social transformation either was or
conceptual ambiguity and a restricted political scope. These is one of the field’s inherent features. These suggestions
conceptual flaws, coupled with community psychology’s are evident in various common expressions in the field,
historical inclination toward social reform, inhibit the such as the call for community psychologists to engage in
possibility of contributing to radical social transformation. systems-change (Foster-Fishman, Nowell, & Yang, 2007;
We conclude that neither questionable historical claims nor Peirson, Boydell, Ferguson & Ferris, 2011) or to promote
ambiguous and politically dubious concepts support a liberation from oppression (Nelson & Prilleltensky, 2010).
community psychology of social transformation. We offer In this paper, we evaluate these suggestions by examining
solutions for the historical and conceptual problems we the field’s historical and conceptual literature that explic-
identify and, as a broader solution to the problem of itly and implicitly serves to justify them. Our review
engaging in socially transformative work, propose that shows a contradiction between the aim of social transfor-
community psychologists should seek direct political mation and the field’s historical and conceptual founda-
engagement in solidarity with other citizens as fellow tions that, we conclude, better fit social reform than social
citizens not as psychologists. transformation.
In reviewing the historical literature concerning commu-
Keywords Community psychology theory Social 
nity psychology, we employed standard historiographical
reform Social transformation Social justice Power
   
methods in psychology (Walsh, Teo & Baydala, 2014).
Praxis Thus, we consulted: (a) the primary-source document pub-
lished about the founding Swampscott Conference of 1965
(Bennett et al., 1966), and (b) first-person accounts from
✉ Ravi Gokani those who participated in the subdiscipline’s founding in
rgokani@wlu.ca the USA and Canada or were leaders of the second gener-
Richard T. G. Walsh
ation of community psychologists; these accounts
rwalsh@wlu.ca appeared in historical studies of this period (Kelly, 1987;
Walsh, 1987a, 1987b). Our historical review indicates that
1
Wilfrid Laurier University, Kitchener, ON, Canada in their accounts of the field’s origins current community
2
Wilfrid Laurier University, Waterloo, ON, Canada psychologists have attributed a greater presence of social
Am J Community Psychol (2017) 59:284–294 285

transformation to it than the evidence can support. Regard- mythical Sixties. Many authors have claimed that an
ing our conceptual review, three concepts seem to capture intrinsic feature of community psychology’s origins was
the discursive shift in the field toward social transforma- the founders’ identification with the allegedly transforma-
tion: social justice, power, and praxis. We discuss two tive impetus of social movements during that era (e.g.,
major problems common to each: (a) their use, in differing Elias, 1987). Fondacaro and Weinberg (2002) asserted
ways, is conceptually ambiguous and (b) again in differing that community psychology was “critically energized by
ways, whatever discernible meaning these concepts have the call for civil rights, the War on Poverty, and notions
seems to be better suited to social reform because of their of distributive justice” (p. 479). Echoing the view that
apparent, restricted political scope. We conclude by dis- community psychology was founded in the context of
cussing possible solutions to these historical and concep- “major social movements,” Wolff and Swift (2008) stated
tual problems. that contemporaneous social issues “became, if not part of
the text, an important part of the subtext for the Swamp-
scott [Massachusetts] conference” (p. 610), and that “[r]
A Psychological Enterprise of Social Transforma- eal world community psychologists were among the lead-
tion or Social Reform? ers of the conference. . . advocating for action to address
the social justice issues of the day” (p. 610). Although
Historical Case for Social Transformation Prilleltensky and Nelson (1997) asserted that the field was
originally animated by “radical impulses” (p. 178), they
From a critical historical perspective on psychology (Walsh conceded that this purported inclination was more a
et al., 2014), a tendency to exaggerate aspects of its origins rhetorical expression than a lived political commitment.
can lead to flawed accounts of its past. In the practice of All told, problematic accounts claim that founding com-
historiography (i.e., systematic historical inquiry), this bias munity psychologists expected to “become allies with
is known as presentism (Harris, 2009), meaning current oppressed groups in the struggle for social justice” (Pril-
interests can affect scholars’ interpretations of past events, leltensky, 2001, p. 749). Community psychologists have
particularly if oral histories are privileged and evidence strayed from their original commitment to social justice,
from archival and documentary sources is neglected. For this general account goes, and they should reclaim it.
example, after World War Two, mass conversion to a However, in our view, this narrative is incorrect and mis-
methodological consensus of quantitative laboratory exper- leading.
imentation occurred across psychology (Walsh et al., When the US American subdiscipline emerged (see
2014). In this context, social psychologists described the Walsh, 1988, on its Canadian origins), the nation was
pre-war origins of their field as primarily experimental in beset by Black Americans demanding their civil and eco-
nature. However, scrutiny of published research showed nomic rights, the impact of poverty on a significant
that diverse methods actually were the norm during social minority of US Americans, escalation of the war in Viet-
psychology’s early decades (Danziger, 1990). In effect, a nam that many perceived as unjust, and increasing
presentist narrative served as an ahistorical “origin myth” assertiveness by women for gender equality (Zinn, 2005).
about social psychology (Samelson, 1974). Thus, Kelly (2002) identified the social context for com-
Many accounts of community psychology’s origins munity psychology’s emergence as “the turbulence of
also are presentist in that authors of these accounts attri- racism in the 1950s. . .the second wave of the women’s
bute to the field’s origins the present concern for political movement, and the Vietnam War” (p. 51). Weinstein
progressiveness, partly by using the terms we review. The (2006) noted that addressing “social problems, social set-
result is a misleading narrative in which authors cast tings, and social change” was part of the field’s “promis-
social transformation as central to the field from its incep- sory note” (p. 11). However, when the US field was
tion. By contrast, a documented account shows that social founded in 1965, these social issues as well as interna-
transformation is a more recent emphasis in the subdisci- tional struggles to overthrow colonial regimes barely pen-
pline’s literature. Below, we contrast presentist accounts etrated the discourse of psychology, community
with the historical record, which shows that community psychology’s parent discipline (Walsh et al., 2014). Aca-
psychology in the USA was rooted in the community demic psychologists at that time typically did not partici-
mental health movement. pate directly in social change, such as the civil rights
movement. Even members of the Society for the Psycho-
Problematic Historical Accounts logical Study of Social Issues (SPSSI), one of the few
groups of psychologists interested in social action, con-
At least since the Eighties community psychologists have centrated on research, not research and action (Walsh &
tended to characterize the subdiscipline as a child of the Gokani, 2014).
286 Am J Community Psychol (2017) 59:284–294

Although the founders of community psychology Rather, it was an agenda for reforming the status quo by
admired the social movements of the day, they were nei- means of community mental health. Founding community
ther affiliated with SPSSI nor practiced the Lewinian tra- psychologists avoided association with contemporary
dition of social-action research, partly because their Black American and White political activists, because
clinical training excluded applied social psychology they were concerned about losing their academic legiti-
(Walsh, 1987b). If the early community psychologists macy in the eyes of their more powerful peers during
joined social movements, they did so as citizens and did the field’s crucial formative years (Walsh, 1987a). To
not describe such engagement in the field’s literature. survive academically, the founders engaged in main-
Interest in social transformation, despite Rappaport’s stream research practices, which partially explain the
(1981) and Seidman’s (1988) exhortations, was rather individual-centered content and conventional research
modest until the Nineties, when other community psychol- relationships in the first decade of articles in the field’s
ogists began to advocate for it and social justice (e.g., journals (Walsh, 1987a). For example, the first editor of
Bond & Mulvey, 2000; Maton, 2000; Moane, 2003; Nel- this journal was Charles Spielberger whose stress
son, 2013; Prilleltensky & Nelson, 1997, 2002; Prillel- research was said to enhance the subdiscipline’s credibil-
tensky & Nelson 2009; Prilleltensky, 2001, 2008; ity (Walsh, 1987a). All told, the social climate of aca-
Prilleltensky 2012; Watts, Griffith & Abdul-Adil, 1999). demic psychology constrained actualizing socially
If the prominent social issues of the day were the main transformative aims that later have been attributed to the
subject of community psychologists’ research and action, early community psychologists, while the quest for aca-
the literature does not show it (Walsh, 1987a). For demic legitimacy shaped the new field’s community
instance, the predominantly male members of the new research and action.
field were disconnected from the revival of feminism, Some community psychologists have acknowledged the
which the marginalized status of women in early commu- founders’ ambivalence about the need for political rele-
nity psychology reflected (Mulvey, 1988). In fact, the new vance (e.g., Seidman, 1988). Perhaps this ambivalence,
field’s context was the community mental health move- which affected later generations of community psycholo-
ment. gists, prompted another founder, Reiff (1975), to criticize
the inclination he perceived among his peers to emulate
Origins in Community Mental Health “techni-pros” focused on technical skills. The new field’s
lack of social activism also might have inspired Rappaport
According to the primary-source document (Bennett et al., (1981) to arouse it to social action by christening it “a
1966), the explicit purpose of the Swampscott Conference social movement.” Seidman (1988) echoed this exhorta-
was to define the roles for clinical psychologists within a tion, advocating for an “action science” that challenged
new mission of community mental health. Two psychia- the status quo (p. 4). Nevertheless, such clarion calls are
trists, Erich Lindemann and Gerald Caplan, and funding incongruous historically unless there was an identifiable
from the National Institute of Mental Health helped shape gap between the social values that early community psy-
community psychology as a profession that could imple- chologists espoused and those they practiced in their aca-
ment the mandate of nation-wide, community mental demic work. The desire to connect with social movements
health services including prevention (Kelly, 1987). The that Rappaport (1981) expressed stood in contrast to the
conference participants, with one exception all men, dis- reformist work at the micro level of analysis that most
cussed how psychologists might serve as social change community psychologists had been doing to ensure their
agents and community developers. They debated whether academic survival (Walsh, 1987a).
community mental health should incorporate interventions Overall, then, although the early generations of North
to overcome “degrading social conditions” and become American community psychologists generally advocated
directly “involved in advocacy and public policy” or “to “social change,” they researched community mental health
promote prevention as the goal of social change” (Walsh, issues (Walsh, 1987b). The latter proved to be the main
1987b, p. 528). The eventual consensus was that “psy- impetus for establishing and maintaining the field.
chologists would serve as proponents of the concept of Accordingly, the evidence for the more recent claim that
community in community mental health work, advocates over the decades community psychologists have strayed
for the poor and minorities, and active participants in and from their allegedly original, progressive roots of social
contributors to social and political life” (Walsh, 1987b, p. transformation is weak. The documented, hence stronger,
528; see also Bennett et al., 1966). conclusion is that the field pursued social reform, not
Clearly, the consensus was not an agenda for enacting transformation, from its founding years (Kelly, 1987;
social transformation as practiced by the social move- Walsh, 1987a, 1987b). To be clear, we are not suggesting
ments of the Sixties typically cited in presentist accounts. that this earlier reformist work is of lesser value or
Am J Community Psychol (2017) 59:284–294 287

importance to the field or to the communities in which For instance, while Prilleltensky (2012) defines “justice”
community psychologists work; we aim only to point out as either distributive or procedural, adding intrapersonal,
this work was not transformative, contrary to presentist interpersonal, organizational, and community “subtypes,”
accounts of the subdiscipline’s origins. SCRA’s (2016) definition excludes Prilleltensky’s (2012)
categories but includes “prevention of violence” and “ac-
Conceptual Case for Social Transformation tive citizenry.” Watts et al. (2003) discuss justice in their
work on sociopolitical development, but their formulation
Community psychologists who discuss social transforma- relies more on the concept of oppression and excludes
tion often employ potentially radical concepts, such as distributive or procedural justice. While some scholars
social justice, power, and praxis. Complementing presen- have attempted to ground social justice empirically (e.g.,
tist accounts of the field’s founding years, these concepts Fondacaro & Weinberg, 2002), disparate varieties of
seem to provide authors with the political relevance of a social justice remain endemic in the field.
socially transformative enterprise. Consequently, under- In addition, the literature lacks consensus or even
standing the nature of community psychologists’ concepts debate about what type of social justice community psy-
is crucial to understanding the field’s potential for social chologists seek. The most common type of social justice
transformation. As Todd and Rufa (2013) put it with ref- discussed among the many inquiries is distributive justice.
erence to social justice, “how one defines [it] likely con- For instance, Prilleltensky and Nelson (1997) defined
tributes to how one pursues [it]” (p. 316). If any of social social justice as “The fair and equitable allocation of bar-
justice, power, and praxis is defined conservatively in the gaining power, resources, and obligations in society” (p.
political, economic, or social sense, it could provide com- 168) and “the fair distribution of societal resources” (p.
munity psychologists with a conceptual justification for 171). Similarly, when defining oppression as social jus-
reform but not transformation of the status quo. On the tice’s opposite, Watts et al. (2003) stated that “as a pro-
other hand, if any of them is defined progressively, it cess” oppression is “the unjust exercise of power by one
could provide a valuable conceptual tool in the struggle to socially salient group over another in a way that creates
realize social transformation. and sustains inequity in the distribution of coveted
Based on our review of the literature, community psy- resources” (p. 186, emphasis added). Society for Commu-
chologists’ use of the three concepts generally suffers nity, Research, and Action (2016) and other authors have
from two major flaws, discussed below, which undermine taken an identical or similar position, resulting in a strong
each concept’s rhetorical power and transformative utility. push to adopt distributive justice as key to social justice
The first flaw is conceptual ambiguity, which stems from (e.g., Baffour & Chonody, 2009; Dalton, Elias & Wander-
the presence of multiple, at times contradictory, formula- sman, 2007; Evans et al., 2014; Fondacaro & Weinberg,
tions, usually without authors noting conflict or debate 2002; Kloos et al., 2012; Prilleltensky & Fox, 2007; Seid-
among competing formulations. The second flaw is a man, 1988; Speer, 2008; Torres-Harding, Siers & Olson,
restricted political scope, meaning formulations of a con- 2012).
cept are too narrowly defined, often blunting its sociopo- Although distributive justice serves as a thread woven
litical implications, which is an inclination that suits through the subdiscipline’s multiple formulations of social
social reform, not transformation. justice, that thread, in our opinion, is quite thin. As with
social justice, conceptualizations of distributive justice are
Problems with the Concept of Social Justice punctuated by the gaps that could be filled by engagement
with academic works from outside of community psychol-
The concept that has come to enjoy pride of place in the ogy (see Lamont & Favor, 2013; for a summary on dis-
oral and written discourse of North American community tributive justice); minor exceptions to this observation
psychology is social justice. It is discussed in several texts include passing references to theorists such as Sandel
(e.g., Kloos et al., 2012; Nelson & Prilleltensky, 2010); (Prilleltensky, 2012) and Rawls (Fondacaro & Weinberg,
it is the topic of numerous publications (e.g., Evans, 2002) and work from within social psychology (Drew,
Rosen & Nelson, 2014; Fondacaro & Weinberg, 2002; Bishop & Syme, 2002). But generally, community psy-
Prilleltensky, 2012; Prilleltensky & Fox, 2007; Watts, chologists have not properly contextualized either distribu-
Williams & Jagers, 2003); and the Society for Community tive justice or social justice to reflect the often
Research and Action (SCRA) (2016) explicitly has incor- heterogeneous perspectives from other disciplines that con-
porated it as a core value and goal. But social justice is vey the complexity of these concepts. As a result, commu-
plagued by conceptual ambiguity, a primary reason for nity psychology’s concepts of social justice appear more
which might be the presence of multiple existing defini- simplified, unchallenged, and ambiguous than they do in
tions (Evans et al., 2014; Fondacaro & Weinberg, 2002). other scholarly fields.
288 Am J Community Psychol (2017) 59:284–294

Moreover, community psychologists’ use of social jus- and Langhout (2010), noting the “relative infancy of a
tice is problematic because of the concept’s restricted power theory in community psychology,” introduced a
political scope. Although in theory, we agree with the theory of power from political science (p. 215). Angeli-
aims of distributive justice as conveyed in the field’s dis- que, Rodriguez, Culley, Brown and Binette (2013) found
course, concretely this formulation of social justice pre- the concepts of psychopolitical, social, and relational
sents some obstacles to social transformation. First, by power in their analysis, too, but also discerned several
failing to challenge social, cultural, institutional, and eco- other, small clusters of discussions on power within the
nomic systems that produce inequalities in the first place field. Elsewhere, Angelique (2008) stressed the impor-
distributive justice can naturalize social systems of tance of the Foucauldian perspective on power, which,
exploitation. Actualizing distributive justice, if achievable with the exception of a few passing citations (e.g., Chris-
in current North American societies, might simultaneously tens & Perkins, 2008; Prilleltensky, 2008), has received
leave exploitive social and ideological systems intact, ren- scant attention in the field. Alternatively, Davidson et al.
dering this conception of social justice essentially refor- (2006) affirmed the conceptualization of power present in
mist politically. In fact, the literature we reviewed the critical theory tradition (see also Angelique, 2008).
implicitly regarded political transformation of social insti- However, to our knowledge, Neal and Neal (2011) are
tutions as unnecessary in the few cases when it was perhaps the only community psychologists who have pub-
acknowledged. lished an attempt to connect the competing or overlapping
Second, one could argue that the “resources” being dis- formulations of power.
tributed might themselves be inherently oppressive, In addition to the multiple theoretical possibilities of
socially unjust or, in Marcuse’s (1964) language, instru- power, conceptual ambiguity is compounded by lack of
ments of social control. For instance, does distributing clarity concerning whether use of the noun power is theo-
micro-credit among impoverished third-world farmers con- retical or colloquial. Angelique (2008) noted that often
stitute resources adequate for the realization of social trans- multiple adjectives precede power without sufficient expo-
formation (Nelson & Prilleltensky, 2010)? Although the sition of their implications for the term. Moreover, when
acquisition of debt and money might grant access to basic usage seems more theoretical than colloquial, it is not
necessities that help to alleviate hunger and other biologi- always clear which particular formulation of power is
cal and social stressors, “such remedies,” to quote Oscar meant. By contrast, some scholars are clear about their
Wilde (2001), “do not cure the disease. . . indeed, [they] definitions, such as J. Neal (2014) on network power. But
are part of the disease” (para. 2, “The Soul of Man under overall, the existence of multiple meanings compromises
Socialism”). Marx detailed the embeddedness of money comprehensibility.
and debt in the social relations of inequality that produce Concerning community psychology’s marquee concept,
their value (Tucker, 1978). In the present neoliberal era, empowerment, Cattaneo, Calton and Brodsky (2014)
financial and economic sources of oppression are abundant asserted that “diffuse use of [the concept] has now ren-
(e.g., Piketty, 2014; Stiglitz, 2012). Accordingly, we would dered it more buzz word than call to action” (p. 434). In
argue that access to credit, particularly for those who are our view, the same conclusion pertains to the literature on
desperate, illiterate, or under economic pressure from power. Interestingly, the concept has had a murky rela-
multinationals, more likely constitutes amelioration and tionship with empowerment (Neal & Neal, 2014).
risks complicity with oppressive institutions (e.g., multina- Although some explanations of this relationship exist
tional banks). Access to credit per se cannot constitute (e.g., Prilleltensky, 2001), substantive elaboration is neces-
social transformation of financial and economic conditions. sary in order to overcome conceptual ambiguity. This task
is particularly important, because the subdiscipline’s con-
Problems with the Concept of Power ceptual identity has long depended on empowerment the-
ory, and many authors have either noted the obvious
Power also seems to be conceptually ambiguous in com- relationship between the two concepts or twinned power
munity psychology’s discourse. This ambiguity is partly with empowerment. Moreover, the failure to explain suffi-
due to a lack of consensus or even engagement among ciently the relationship between the two might lead com-
the multiple formulations circulating within the subdisci- munity psychologists to overlook the pitfalls of
pline. Neal and Neal (2011) identified three prominent empowerment theory when conceptualizing power. As
concepts of power: psychopolitical (e.g., Prilleltensky, Riger (1993) argued, empowerment relies on subjective
2003), social (e.g., Speer & Hughey, 1995), and relational criteria (e.g., perception of empowerment) in determining
power (e.g., Serrano-Garcıa, 1994). Neal and Neal (2011) objective empowerment. As it happens, this criticism
then proposed their own conceptualization of power, situ- might also apply to power. Prilleltensky (2008), for exam-
ating it in the “structure” of relationships. Dworski-Riggs ple, posited the crucial role of social relationships in his
Am J Community Psychol (2017) 59:284–294 289

concept of psychopolitical validity, but theorized power as transformative action; that is, such action always occurs in
a property of individuals’ “subjective manifestation of the dialectical relation to reflection (e.g., Freire, 1997). But in
societal distribution of power” (Fryer, 2008, p. 242). contrast to Freire’s (1997) lucid definition and acknowl-
Riger (1993) also claimed that empowerment is androcen- edgement of the term’s indebtedness to Hegel and Marx,
tric, which again applies to power in that several commu- many community psychologists tend to employ praxis
nity psychologists defined it in terms of masculine notions loosely, again leading to conceptual ambiguity. The net
of control, conflict, and mastery of the world to satisfy effect is the dilution of an otherwise radical concept, inti-
one’s needs (e.g., Brooker & Eakin, 2001; Prilleltensky, mately connected with social transformation, which ren-
2001; Serrano-Garcıa, 1994). ders praxis in a less potent form that is compatible with
As to the political scope of power, like social justice, it reform rather than transformation.
is limited by community psychologists’ reliance on One cause of the ambiguity of praxis is the tendency
notions of distributive justice. For example, Serrano- by some authors to ignore one or more crucial compo-
Garcıa (1994) defined power as a “social relationship nents (i.e., the dialectic, reflection, and transformative
characterized by the presence of two agents, within an action) or replace it with a concept devoid of theoretical
historically asymmetrical material base, which are in con- justification. Some have defined the dialectic, a concept
flict over a resource which one of them controls and the and intellectual practice with a long and specific history,
other covets” (p. 9, emphasis added). Other authors as a “knowledge-generating cycle” (Newbrough, 1992,
addressing power have considered the allocation of p. 20); a process of “willed action” in which reflection
resources and their asymmetric distribution, which Neal “becomes” action (Elias, 1994, p. 308); a “translation”
and Neal (2011) regarded as central to conceptions of (Prilleltensky, 2001, p. 749); a “linking” (Williams, 2008,
power. Prilleltensky (2001) defined the first component of p. 144); an “interplay” (Partridge, 2008, p. 162), “interac-
their formulation of power as “access to valued material tion” (p. 165), or “negotiation” (p. 166); and a “synergy”
and psychological resources” (p. 145). Although he did (Watts et al., 2003, p. 193).
not propose his own conception of power, McCubbin The second component of praxis, “reflection,” refers to
(2001) argued that resource allocation, “whether affective, individuals’ reflections on the concrete material conditions
material, or symbolic,” is the context for “power rela- of their oppressed state and/or to their reflection on the
tions” between individuals (p. 78). As in the case of social actions they have taken to overcome that state (Freire,
justice, we agree philosophically with the aim of distribu- 1997). But community psychologists have replaced reflec-
tive justice, but unreflective reliance on it yields the two tion with weaker political variants, such as “philosophy”
dubious characteristics already noted: distribution leaves (Elias, 1994, p. 301), “theory” and “ethical reflection”
oppressive systems intact, and resources might be forms (Prilleltensky, 2001, p. 749), and psychopolitical validity
of control from within those systems. (Williams, 2008).
Additional critiques of the restricted political scope of As to its action component, praxis denotes the acts of
power within community psychology’s discourse appear oppressed individuals or groups intending to transform
in a special issue of the Journal of Community Psychol- their oppressive conditions (Freire, 1997). Yet community
ogy on psychopolitical validity. The critiques include the psychologists have substituted action for “practice” (New-
view that power is political (Prilleltensky, 2008); that any brough, 1992, p. 20), described action as attempts to alter
conceptualization must recognize history (Reich, Pinkard the training and reward structure of a policing institution
& Davidson, 2008); that cultural assumptions within (Williams, 2008), or defined action as an “activity through
Bronfenbrenner’s macro-level limit the generalizability of which social life is lived” (Partridge, 2008, pp. 165-166).
formulations of power (Fisher & Sonn, 2008); and that Taken together, these changes to the essential features
power perhaps is not reducible to the individual nor is the of praxis not only alter its meaning, they sever it from its
“collective” reducible to multiple individuals (Fryer, critical philosophical tradition, thereby stripping the con-
2008). These criticisms, as well as those we have identi- cept of its original intention of emancipation from
fied ourselves, appear to validate Prilleltensky’s (2008) oppression (Freire, 1997). In fact, some community
somewhat ironic warning that “we sometimes use our psychologists simply equate praxis with “practice,” a col-
power to define power in such a way that we are not loquial use of the term (e.g., Bertram, Hall, Fine & Weis,
affected by it!” (p. 117). 2000; Bishop, Vicary, Browne & Guard, 2009; Townley,
Kloos, Green & Franco, 2011). We recognize praxis can
Problems with the Concept of Praxis be used this way in the term’s non-technical sense. The
same might be said of its components and of the concepts
Within the critical emancipatory tradition, praxis is of power and, to a lesser extent, social justice. To be
defined as the dialectical cycle of reflection and clear, we are not suggesting that none but the strictest use
290 Am J Community Psychol (2017) 59:284–294

of praxis, or any term, is the only valuable use; we recog- repudiate such faith. But in our view situating psychologi-
nize that concepts can develop over time and that this cal research as conventionally conceived and practiced in
development can be fruitful. However, we are asserting mainstream psychology into praxis neglects how psycho-
that the use of praxis within community psychology’s dis- logical research, even community psychology research,
course is ambiguous. Therefore, problems of meaning can be and has been a source and symptom of oppression
arise when the term with its rich philosophical (i.e., trans- (Walsh et al., 2014). Moreover, the insertion of research
formative) heritage is only given the semantic weight of into praxis masks a dynamic of unbalanced power that
colloquial (i.e., reformist) use. Confusion is compounded militates against liberation; the oppressed rarely plan, exe-
when such ambiguous use occurs against the discursive cute, analyze, and theorize psychological research. More-
backdrop of the field’s current rhetoric of social transfor- over, if emancipation is tied to conventional research
mation. relationships and sources of funding, then the oppressed
In contrast to the concept’s original meaning, commu- are bound to both for their liberation, which could impli-
nity psychologists’ discussions of praxis also seem to cate community psychologists as potential sources and
reflect a restricted political scope. This originally revolu- symptoms of oppression.
tionary concept apparently has become synonymous with
mere practical applications. Such a semantic alteration
suits social reform but not social transformation. Depoliti- Concluding Remarks
cizing of praxis in the community psychology literature
has occurred in at least two other ways. One is by failing Examining the community psychology literature to con-
to address liberation from oppression, perhaps the major sider the field’s potential to contribute to social transfor-
theme of Freire’s (1997) Pedagogy of the Oppressed. mation has revealed historical and conceptual problems.
Instead, for instance, Partridge (2008) fit praxis to “com- Below, we sketch possible solutions that hopefully can
munity research and action” (p. 168). Williams (2008) place the field on a firmer foundation.
applied it to the institution of policing in a particular
police station and reform of its training and reward struc- Historical Problems and Solutions
ture, but not to policing in general with its potential for
oppression of local communities, as has occurred in The current and popular notion that community psychol-
numerous North American locales. In another example ogy is a child of the allegedly radical Sixties from which
Prilleltensky and Nelson (2002) described praxis as “what it has strayed and to which it should return cannot be
lies between what is desirable and what is achievable” supported historically. Such a presentist interpretation of
(p. 158). This politically pragmatic interpretation of praxis the field’s actual history of social reform seems to serve
reminds us of the infamous 1867 definition of politics not as an origin myth that can be particularly misleading for
by an advocate of social transformation but by Otto von those, such as students, who might be disillusioned by
Bismarck, the first chancellor of the established German the field’s reformist practices. We hope that knowledge of
empire: “Politics is the art of the possible.” If praxis only this problem will help prevent future errors of the same
represents the interface between the desirable and the pos- nature. Our historical analysis relied on critical history,
sible, then praxis becomes the antithesis of social transfor- which can prevent creating and perpetuating misleading
mation, namely, social reform, and is likely to justify accounts of the past and foster clearer thinking about psy-
political maneuvers practiced by and for the establish- chologists’ current interests (Harris, 2009; Walsh et al.,
ment. 2014).
The second way in which community psychologists
narrow the political scope of praxis is by attributing to it Conceptual Problems and Solutions
a methodological or epistemological dimension (e.g.,
Newbrough, 1992; Partridge, 2008; Prilleltensky, 2001). Conceptually, the subdiscipline’s discourse on social jus-
Following Newbrough’s (1992) description of praxis as a tice, power, and praxis shows that typically authors
“knowledge-generating cycle,” (p. 20), Partridge (2008) ambiguously describe and depoliticize them. In addition,
defined praxis as “a way of learning that embodies ethical community psychologists tend to cast concepts like
and political theory and practice in the real world” (p. social justice as transformational, when the examples
165) and leads to ethical and political decision-making. they give typically illustrate social reform. By contrast,
The insertion of research-like concepts into praxis sug- scholars in other disciplines, fields, and professions tend
gests to us uncritical faith in the potential for psychologi- to have a more interdisciplinary focus, and therefore,
cal research to complement reflection in an emancipatory seem more fluent in the development of conceptual work
process. Perhaps few community psychologists would from across academic disciplines (e.g., critical race,
Am J Community Psychol (2017) 59:284–294 291

postcolonial, feminist, queer, and critical theories of constraints imposed by community psychologists’ privi-
political economy and society). Thus, an initial possible leged socioeconomic status are likely to compromise their
solution for the field’s conceptual problems is to expand capacity to help directly build a transformed society that
its scholarly purview, including curriculum, to reflect responds effectively to the urgent ecological-environmen-
increasing multidisciplinarity. We commend a recent tal, economic, social, and political problems of our time.
effort to move the field in this direction (see Munger, The field always has been primarily embedded in postsec-
MacLeod & Loomis, 2016). Moreover, as part of this ondary institutions that are currently governed by neolib-
broader purview North American community psycholo- eral policies and practices (e.g., Giroux, 2014), which
gists should take more seriously the international litera- arguably are responsible for much of the harm that society
ture in community psychology, because it can illuminate should redress. Relatedly, if community psychologists
diverse conceptual approaches to reform and transforma- attempt to be partisans for social transformation, they
tion (e.g., Reich, Riemer, Prilleltensky & Montero, might experience difficulty attaining tenure or receiving
2007). Perhaps such a broader purview would guard research grants from mainstream sources to fund their
against ambiguity and a restricted political scope, but an community work, a point that Sarason (1976) propheti-
attendant danger might be flooding the discipline with cally made. Thus, tension between community psycholo-
even more conceptualizations than exist presently. There- gists’ attempts to be engaged in communities, on the one
fore, engaging with the formulations that already exist in hand, and institutional and disciplinary constraints, on the
addition to expanding the scholarly purview is of para- other hand, seems inescapable. Consequently, the social
mount importance. transformation option for community psychology, even if
Although the above analysis of the historical and con- conceptually and politically improved, is likely to be unre-
ceptual work of the field suggests that it is presently alistic. In fact, this status is consistent with the history of
incongruent with the aim of social transformation, the other bodies of reputedly progressive psychologists
broader problem might be that this aim is unrealistic. Put (Walsh & Gokani, 2014) and prompts us to question what
differently, the historical and conceptual problems we dis- community psychologists should do about their genuine
cussed suggest that pursuit of social transformation from commitments to social transformation.
within the disciplinary constraints of community psychol- One recommendation we suggest is that community
ogy is likely to be a Sisyphean task. To understand why, psychologists engage directly in solidarity with oppressed
it is important to briefly identify institutional factors that groups in the struggle for social transformation, but as cit-
have shaped community psychology as a child of tradi- izens and not as academic community psychologists
tional psychology and that remain actively inhibitory. (Walsh & Gokani, 2014). Many important social justice
First, since its inception the parent discipline of psychol- movements today are better platforms for the social trans-
ogy allied itself with social reform (Walsh et al., 2014), formation that some community psychologists seek from
primarily through the assumption of self-contained indi- within academia and our subdiscipline. Participation as
viduals adapting to society, but it also has excluded social citizens in these movements would allow community psy-
structures, most notably social-class hierarchies under cap- chologists to express their commitment to social transfor-
italist societies, from its conceptual frameworks (Sarason, mation but avoid the limitations that inhere in the
1981). In fact, until the current century a virtual taboo disciplinary and institutional settings where they work.
existed in psychology against investigating social class One way perhaps to initiate this commitment is to
(Fine & Burns, 2003). Instead, the discipline long has embrace the international literature in community psychol-
functioned as an administrative science serving educa- ogy, because it suggests productive pathways for psychol-
tional, industrial, post-industrial, commercial, military, and ogists’ engagement in society (e.g., Reich et al., 2007).
criminal-justice institutions (Danziger, 1979; Herman, Postcolonial liberation psychology, which originated in El
1995). Salvador (Martın-Baro, 1994) and, as it happens, derives
Second, although community psychologists often have from Freire’s (1997) pedagogy for marginalized peoples,
criticized the broader discipline for its reformist inclina- also can exemplify transformative change. However, it
tions (e.g., Prilleltensky, 1989; Sarason, 1981), it appears would be mistaken to idealize international community
that they less frequently examine critically the subdisci- psychology and assume that it is, by definition, oriented
pline’s past and present reformist inclinations. to social transformation per se.
Third, Kelly (2002) candidly observed that community Although we remain skeptical about community psy-
psychologists “are part of the elite society of well-edu- chology’s ability to engage in social transformation for
cated professionals” (p. 48), placing them squarely on the the three reasons we discussed above, engaging in socially
opposite side of most, if not all, grassroots struggles from transformative work as citizens, with an eye to relevant
which transformative impulses often emerge. The international examples, could bear fruit for the
292 Am J Community Psychol (2017) 59:284–294

subdiscipline in untold ways. This, perhaps, is the best Drew, N.M., Bishop, B.J., & Syme, G. (2002). Justice and local
pathway to “reclaim social justice” for community psy- community change: Towards a substantive theory of justice.
Journal of Community Psychology, 30, 623–634.
chology by fulfilling a civic duty that we all share but that Dworski-Riggs, D., & Langhout, R.D. (2010). Elucidating the power
the field’s founders tended to avoid. in empowerment and the participation in participatory action
research: A story about research team and elementary school
change. American Journal of Community Psychology, 45,
Acknowledgments Ravi Gokani is a PhD student in Social Work 215–230.
at Wilfrid Laurier University. He completed an MA in community Elias, M.J. (1987). Establishing enduring prevention programs:
psychology with Richard T. G. Walsh who is Emeritus Professor of Advancing the legacy of Swampscott. American Journal of
Psychology at Laurier. The authors are grateful to Dr. Deena Man- Community Psychology, 15, 539–553.
dell, Dr. Robb Travers, and anonymous colleagues for comments on Elias, M.J. (1994). Capturing excellence in applied settings: A par-
previous drafts. ticipant conceptualizer and praxis explicator role for community
psychologists. American Journal of Community Psychology, 22,
293–318.
Evans, S.D., Rosen, A., & Nelson, G. (2014). Community psychol-
References ogy and social justice. In C. Johnson, J. Diaz, Z. Franco, H.
Friedman & B. Nastasi (Eds.), Praeger handbook of social jus-
Angelique, H.L. (2008). On power, psychopolitical validity, and play. tice (pp. 143–164). Westport, CN: Praeger.
American Journal of Community Psychology, 38, 246–253. Fine, M., & Burns, A. (2003). Class notes: Toward a critical psy-
Angelique, H.L., Rodriguez, R., Culley, M.R., Brown, R., & Bin- chology of class and schooling. Journal of Social Issues, 59,
ette, A.J. (2013). (Em-)powering community psychology 841–860.
through an examination of social power. Journal of Community Fisher, A.T., & Sonn, C.C. (2008). Psychopolitical validity: Power,
Psychology, 41, 725–742. culture, and wellness. Journal of Community Psychology, 36,
Baffour, T.G., & Chonody, J.M. (2009). African-American women’s 261–268.
conceptualizations of health disparities: A community-based Fondacaro, M.R., & Weinberg, D. (2002). Concepts of social justice
participatory research approach. American Journal of Commu- in community psychology: Toward a social ecological episte-
nity Psychology, 44, 374–381. mology. American Journal of Community Psychology, 30,
Bennett, C.C., Anderson, L., Cooper, S., Hassol, L., Klein, D.C., & 473–492.
Rosenblum, G. (1966). Community psychology: A report of the Foster-Fishman, P.G., Nowell, B. & Yang, H. (2007). Putting the
Boston Conference on the education of psychologists for com- system back into systems change: a framework for understand-
munity mental health. Boston: Boston University Press. ing and changing organizational and community systems.
Bertram, C., Hall, J., Fine, M., & Weis, L. (2000). Where the girls American Journal of Community Psychology, 39, 197–215.
(and women) are. American Journal of Community Psychology, Freire, P. (1997). Pedagogy of the oppressed (Rev. ed.) (M. Berg-
28, 731–755. man Ramos, Trans.). New York: Continuum.
Bishop, B.J., Vicary, D.A., Browne, A.L., & Guard, N. (2009). Pub- Fryer, D. (2008). Power from the people? Critical reflection on a
lic policy, participation and the third position: The implication conceptualization of power. Journal of Community Psychology,
of engaging communities on their own terms. American Journal 36, 238–245.
of Community Psychology, 43, 111–121. Giroux, H.A. (2014). Neoliberalism’s war on higher education. Chi-
Bond, M.A., & Mulvey, A. (2000). A history of women and femi- cago: Haymarket.
nist perspectives in Community Psychology. American Journal Harris, B. (2009). What critical psychologists should know about the
of Community Psychology, 28, 599–630. history of psychology. In D. Fox, I. Prilleltensky & S. Austin
Brooker, A., & Eakin, J.M. (2001). Gender, class, work-related (Eds.), Critical psychology: An introduction (pp. 20–35). Thou-
stress and health: Toward a power-centred approach. sand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Journal of Community and Applied Social Psychology, 11, Herman, E. (1995). The romance of American psychology: Political
97–109. culture in the age of experts. Berkeley, CA: University of Cali-
Cattaneo, L.B., Calton, J.M., & Brodsky, A.E. (2014). Status quo fornia Press.
versus status quake: Putting the power back in empowerment. Kelly, J.G. (1987). Some reflections on the Swampscott conference.
Journal of Community Psychology, 42, 433–446. American Journal of Community Psychology, 15, 515–517.
Christens, B., & Perkins, D.D. (2008). Transdisciplinary, multilevel Kelly, J.G. (2002). The spirit of community psychology. American
action research to enhance ecological and psychopolitical valid- Journal of Community Psychology, 30, 43–63.
ity. Journal of Community Psychology, 36, 214–231. Kloos, B., Hill, J., Thomas, E., Wandersman, A., Elias, M.J., & Dal-
Dalton, J.H., Elias, M.J., & Wandersman, A. (2007). Community ton, J.H. (2012). Community psychology: Linking individuals
psychology: Linking individuals and communities. Belmont, and communities. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Cengage.
CA: Thompson Wadsworth. Lamont, J., & Favor, C. (2013). Distributive justice. Stanford
Danziger, K. (1979). The social origins of modern psychology. In Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available from: http://plato.stanf
A.R. Buss (Ed.), Psychology in social context (pp. 27–45). ord.edu/entries/justice-distributive [last accessed April 17,
New York: Irvington. 2017].
Danziger, K. (1990). Constructing the subject. New York: Cam- Marcuse, H. (1964). One-dimensional man: Studies in the ideology
bridge University Press. of advanced industrial society. Boston: Beacon.
Davidson, H., Evans, S., Ganote, C., Henrickson, J., Jacobs-Priebe, Martın-Baro, I. (1994). Writings for a liberation psychology. A.
L., Jones, D.L., . . . & Riemer, M. (2006). Power and action in Aron & S. Corne (Eds.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
critical theory across disciplines: Implications for critical com- Press.
munity psychology. American Journal of Community Psychol- Maton, K.I. (2000). The social ecology of social transformation.
ogy, 38, 35–49. American Journal of Community Psychology, 28, 25–57.
Am J Community Psychol (2017) 59:284–294 293

McCubbin, M. (2001). Pathways to health, illness and well-being: Reich, S.M., Riemer, M., Prilleltensky, I., & Montero, M. (Eds.)
From the perspective of power and control. Journal of Commu- (2007). International community psychology: History and theo-
nity and Applied Social Psychology, 11, 75–81. ries. Berkley, CA: Springer.
Moane, G. (2003). Bridging the personal and the political: Practices Reiff, R. (1975). Of cabbages and kings. American Journal of Com-
for a liberation psychology. American Journal of Community munity Psychology, 3, 187–196.
Psychology, 31, 91–101. Riger, S. (1993). What’s wrong with empowerment. American Jour-
Mulvey, A. (1988). Community Psychology and feminism: Tensions nal of Community Psychology, 21, 279–292.
and commonalities. Journal of Community Psychology, 16, Samelson, F. (1974). History, origin myth and ideology: Discovery
70–83. of social psychology. Journal for the Theory of Social Behav-
Munger, F., MacLeod, T., & Loomis, C. (2016). Social change: ior, 4, 217–231.
Toward an informed and critical understanding of social justice Sarason, S.B. (1976). Community Psychology and the anarchist insight.
and the capabilities approach in community psychology. Ameri- American Journal of Community Psychology, 4, 243–261.
can Journal of Community Psychology, 57, 171–180. Sarason, S.B. (1981). Psychology misdirected. New York: Free.
Neal, J.W. (2014). Exploring empowerment in settings: Mapping Seidman, E. (1988). Back to the future, community psychology:
distributions of network power. American Journal of Commu- Unfolding a theory of social intervention. American Journal of
nity Psychology, 53, 394–406. Community Psychology, 16, 3–24.
Neal, J.W., & Neal, Z.P. (2011). Power as a structural phenomenon. Serrano-Garcıa, I. (1994). The ethics of the powerful and the power of
American Journal of Community Psychology, 48, 157–167. ethics. American Journal of Community Psychology, 22, 1–20.
Nelson, G. (2013). Community psychology and transformative pol- Society for Community, Research, and Action (2016). Who we are.
icy change in the neo-liberal era. American Journal of Commu- Available from: http://www.scra27.org/who-we-are [last acces-
nity Psychology, 52, 211–223. sed April 17, 2017].
Nelson, G., & Prilleltensky, I. (2010). Community psychology: In Speer, P.W. (2008). Social power and forms of change: Implications
pursuit of liberation and well-being. New York: Palgrave for psychopolitical validity. American Journal of Community
MacMillan. Psychology, 38, 199–213.
Newbrough, J.R. (1992). Community psychology in a postmodern Speer, P.W., & Hughey, J. (1995). Community organizing: An eco-
world. Journal of Community Psychology, 20, 10–25. logical route to empowerment and power. American Journal of
Partridge, W. (2008). Praxis and power. Journal of Community Psy- Community Psychology, 23, 729–748.
chology, 36, 161–172. Stiglitz, J.E. (2012). The price of inequality: The avoidable costs
Peirson, L.J., Boydell, K.M., Ferguson, H.B., & Ferris, L.E. (2011). and hidden costs of inequality. New York: W W Norton.
An ecological process model of systems change. American Todd, N.R., & Rufa, A.K. (2013). Social justice and religious
Journal of Community Psychology, 47, 307–321. participation: A qualitative investigation of Christian perspec-
Piketty, T. (2014). Capital in the twenty-first century. Cambridge, tives. American Journal of Community Psychology, 51, 315–
MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. 331.
Prilleltensky, I. (1989). Psychology and the status quo. American Torres-Harding, S.R., Siers, B., & Olson, B. (2012). Development
Psychologist, 44, 795–802. and Psychometric Evaluation of the Social Justice Scale (SJS).
Prilleltensky, I. (2001). Value-based praxis in community psychol- American Journal of Community Psychology, 59, 77–88.
ogy: Moving towards social justice and social action. American Townley, G., Kloos, B., Green, E.P., & Franco, M.M. (2011). Rec-
Journal of Community Psychology, 29, 747–778. oncilable differences? Human diversity, cultural relativity, and
Prilleltensky, I. (2003). Understanding, resisting, and overcoming sense of community. American Journal of Community Psychol-
oppression: Toward psychopolitical validity. American Journal ogy, 47, 69–85.
of Community Psychology, 31, 195–201. Tucker, R.B. (1978). The Marx-Engels Reader (2nd edn). New
Prilleltensky, I. (2008). The role of power in wellness, oppression, York: Norton.
and liberation: The promise of psychopolitical validity. Journal Walsh, R.T. (1987a). The evolution of the research relationship in
of Community Psychology, 36, 116–136. community psychology. American Journal of Community Psy-
Prilleltensky, I. (2012). Wellness as fairness. American Journal of chology, 15, 773–788.
Community Psychology, 49, 1–21. Walsh, R.T. (1987b). A social historical note on the formal emer-
Prilleltensky, I., & Fox, D. (2007). Psychopolitical literacy for gence of community psychology. American Journal of Commu-
wellness and justice. Journal of Community Psychology, 35, nity Psychology, 15, 523–529.
793–805. Walsh, R.T. (1988). Current developments in community psychology
Prilleltensky, I., & Nelson, G. (1997). Community psychology: in Canada. Journal of Community Psychology, 16, 296–305.
Reclaiming social justice. In D. Fox & I. Prilleltensky (Eds.), Walsh, R.T.G., & Gokani, R. (2014). The personal and political
Critical psychology: An introduction (pp. 166–184). London: economy of psychologists’ desires for social justice. Journal of
SAGE. Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, 34, 41–55.
Prilleltensky, I., & Nelson, G. (2002). Doing psychology critically: Walsh, R.T.G., Teo, T., & Baydala, A. (2014). A critical history
Making a difference in diverse settings. New York: Palgrave and philosophy of psychology: Diversity of context, thought,
Macmillan. and practice. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Prilleltensky, I., & Nelson, G. (2009). Community Psychology: Watts, R.J., Griffith, D.M., & Abdul-Adil, J. (1999). Sociopoliti-
Advancing social justice. In D. Fox, I. Prilleltensky & S. Austin cal development as an antidote for oppression-theory and
(Eds.), Critical psychology: An introduction (126–143). action. American Journal of Community Psychology, 27,
Washington, DC: Sage Publications. 255–271.
Rappaport, J. (1981). In praise of paradox: A social policy of Watts, R.J., Williams, N.C., & Jagers, R.J. (2003). Sociopolitical
empowerment over prevention. American Journal of Commu- development. American Journal of Community Psychology, 31,
nity Psychology, 9, 2–25. 185–194.
Reich, S.M., Pinkard, T., & Davidson, H. (2008). Including history Weinstein, R.S. (2006). Reaching higher in community psychology:
in the study of psychological and political power. Journal of Social problems, social settings, and social change. American
Community Psychology, 36, 173–186. Journal of Community Psychology, 37, 9–20.
294 Am J Community Psychol (2017) 59:284–294

Wilde, O. (2001). The soul of man under socialism and selected Wolff, T., & Swift, C. (2008). Reflections on “real-world” commu-
critical prose. Toronto, Canada: Penguin. nity psychology. Journal of Community Psychology, 36,
Williams, B.N. (2008). From the outside looking in: The praxis 609–625.
dilemma of linking psycho-political validity with community Zinn, H. (2005). A people’s history of the United States. New York:
policing. Journal of Community Psychology, 36, 137–147. Harper Perennial.

You might also like